Categorical Syllogisms
Categorical Syllogisms
2. Next, on this framework, draw the diagrams of both of the Now we add the minor premise to our drawing. The diagram
syllogism's premises. for "Some M are S" puts an inside the area where the M and S
o Always begin with a universal proposition, no circles overlap. But part of that area (the portion also inside the P
matter whether it is the major or the minor circle) has already been shaded, so our must be placed in the
premise. remaining portion.
o Remember that in each case you will be using
only two of the circles in each case; ignore the
third circle by making sure that your drawing
Third, we stop drawing and merely look at our result. Ignoring
(shading or ) straddles it.
the M circle entirely, we need only ask whether the drawing of the
conclusion "Some S are not P" has
already been drawn.
3. Finally, without drawing anything else, look for the Remember, that drawing would
drawing of the conclusion. If the syllogism is valid, then be like the one at left, in which there is
that drawing will already be done. an in the area inside the S circle but
outside the P circle. Does that already
Since it perfectly models the relationships between classes that appear in the diagram on the right above? Yes, if the premises have
are at work in categorical logic, this procedure always provides a been drawn, then the conclusion is already drawn.
demonstration of the validity or invalidity of any categorical
syllogism. But this models a significant logical feature of the syllogism
itself: if its premises are true, then its conclusion must also be true.
Consider, for example, how it could be applied, step by step, to Any categorical syllogism of this form is valid.
an evaluation of a syllogism of the EIO-3 mood and figure,
Page 2 of 18
the syllogism must be valid, and if it is not, the syllogism must be Categorical Syllogisms
invalid.
Categorical syllogisms are sets of three categorical propositions. The
AAA-1 (valid) first two are given and presumed to be true. These first two
All M are P. categorical propositions are called premises. The third categorical
All S are M. proposition is the conclusion. The third categorical proposition is in
Therefore, All S are P. the form _____ S is (___) P.
Mood
AAA-3 (invalid) There are four types of categorical proposition, the universal
All M are P. affirmative A, the universal negative E, the particular affirmative I,
All M are S. and the particular negative O.
Therefore, All S are P.
A: All rocks are hard things.
E: No rocks are hard things
I: Some rocks are hard things
OAO-3 (valid) O: Some rocks are not hard things [Not every rock is a hard thing]
Some M are not P.
All M are S.
Therefore, Some S are not P. Syllogisms consist of three of these, any three. The order in which the
three occur specifies the mood of the syllogism. Consider the
following EAO syllogism
EOO-2 (invalid) The above syllogism is term an EAO syllogism. Note the the middle
No P are M. term is the predicate of the major premise and the subject of the
Some S are not M. minor term. This could be abstracted in the following notation.
Therefore, Some S are not P.
Major premise: No P is M
IOO-1 (invalid) Minor premise: All M is S
Some M are P. Conclusion: Some S is not P
Some S are not M.
Therefore, Some S are not P. As long as there are women named Sepe, outer island women,
and gulfoy weavers, the above syllogism is indeed valid. In modern
logic, the particular proposition imply the existence of actual
members of the class, while the universal propositions do not imply
the existence of members of the class. In simplified terms, the issue is
what happens when no one knows how to make the gulfoy. When that
knowledge is lost, then there the conclusion, which demands existing
members, is false because there are no weavers.
Page 3 of 18
Figure PM
Categorical syllogism have four possible figures depending on the Diagramming the minor premise
position of the middle term. The "flying brick" is a good way to
remember the four figures. The flying brick refers to the possible The third circle added is the subject circle S. In the diagram below
positions of the middle term without regard to quantity. The the S circle has been temporarily laid "on top" to show the full circle.
following is a picture of the flying brick.
SPM
MM MMMM MM
"All S is M" is diagrammed by "erasing" or blacking out all areas of
Seen more abstractly: S that are not inside the M circle.
SPM
M MM M
\ /
MMMM Note that the areas of M blacked out by the major premise remain
blacked out. This results in a section of S also being blacked out - the
lower left "triangle" where S and M intersect outside of the P circle.
Now with the predicate and subject terms introduced.
Look at the Venn diagram and consider whether the diagram supports
the conclusion that All S is P. The only area of S that remains is the
M-P P-M M-P P-M center triangle of the three circles. And this triangle is wholly inside
\ / of P. All S is indeed P.
S-M S-M M-S M-S
S-P S-P S-P S-P
First Second Third Fourth EEE-1
Figure Figure Figure Figure
Venn diagrams Note that the three categorical syllogisms can be a mixture from any
of the four types. There are three categorical propositions in each
syllogism and four types or 43 = 64 possible combinations (moods).
AAA-1 With four figures possible for each of 64 moods there are 256 total
possible arrangements of mood and figure. For no particular reason
Mood is AAA, figure I. these examples first consider triplets of identical types of categorical
propositions in figure 1.
Page 4 of 18
Diagramming the minor proposition This sounds reasonable. Yet consider the III-1 syllogism:
Page 5 of 18
Then combine the two preceding Venn diagrams into a single Venn
diagram. that contains the major term, and the minor premise is the premise
that contains the minor term.
SPMwoodinthewaterrocksXX
For some wood to not be in the water there would have to be an X in The mood of a standard categorical syllogism is determined by the
the lower left triangle at the intersection of wood and rocks. The X on
the line at the bottom of the triangle, could be either in the wood types of categorical statements it contains. In the following example,
circle or outside the wood circle in the rocks circle. In the abstract the major premise is an E statement and the minor premise is
where Some M is not P and Some S is not M, there is no way to assure
validity. OOO-1 is not valid. an I statement. The conclusion is an O statement. So its mood is EIO.
Under Construction
The figure of a standard categorical syllogism is determined by the
SPMXXXXXXXXX positions of the two appearances of the middle term. In the above
2.4 Categorical Syllo gisms need to first change them into the standard form. This process may
involve two steps:
In this section, we study categorical syllogisms and learn how to
identify their argument forms. A syllogism is an argument with two 1. Paraphrase sentences into categorical sentences.
the minor and the middleterms. The major term is the predicate term
of the conclusion. The minor term is the subject term of the A few S are P. Some S are P
conclusion. The middle term is the term that appears twice in the
premises.
For example, the sentence
premise and the conclusion. Here the major premise is the premise
is paraphrased as
Page 6 of 18
Some soldiers are heroes. (Some S are H.)
not P. Not all apples are red. (Not all A are R.)
is rewritten as
The key point of the sentence Few tigers are white lies in the fact
that white tigers are rare. We need two categorical sentences to Some apples are not red things. (Some A are not R.)
Some tigers are white animals, but most tigers are not
white animals.
Not an S is a P. No S are P.
The sentence
For example,
Not every swan is white. (Not every S is W.)
is paraphrased as an A statement
Some swans are not white birds. (Some S are not W.)
Page 7 of 18
All drunk drivers are dangerous drivers. All the persons who can bear children are women.
(All D1 are D2.) (All B are W.)
Here D1 stands for drunk drivers and D2 stands for It would be a mistake to paraphrase the sentence as All W are B. It
dangerous drivers. Subscripts are used to distinguish the two terms. is not true that all women can bear children. So we can clearly see
that it is not logically equivalent to Only W are B.
Sometimes, the conditional sentences are written with if in the
middle of the sentence. None except S are P and None but S are P are just other ways of
saying Only S are P.
It is a P if it is an S. All S are P.
The sentence
is just a variation of
The sentence
If a driver is drunk, then he is dangerous.
None but club members can vote. (None but C are V.)
and hence is also rewritten as
is transformed as
All drunk drivers are dangerous drivers.
(All D1 are D2.) All the persons who can vote are club members.
(All V are C.)
Only , None except and None but
The only
Sentences begin with only are paraphrased using the following
formula. Some sentences start with the phrase the only. The only S are P
is another way of saying Only Pare S.
The sentence
Only women can bear children. (Only W are B.)
Page 8 of 18
says the same thing as
All kind people are considerate people.
we have five terms because both kind people and its complement
and is paraphrased as
unkind people appear in the syllogism. So do the terms
All the persons who can bear children are women. considerate people and inconsiderate people. When this happens,
(All B are W.) we need to use the three operations (conversion, obversion or
All K are C.
As discussed early, there can only be three terms in a categorical are prejudiced.
Page 9 of 18
The mood and figure of the argument form is OAO-4.
All S are non-P.
Afterwards, we apply obversion to the major premise to reduce the validity of a categorical syllogism.
All S are non-P. Obv. No S are P. In using Venn diagrams to determine the validity of a categorical
Some R are P. Some R are P. syllogism, we draw three overlapping circles to represent the minor,
middle and major terms. The three circles are divided into seven
Some R are not S. Some R are not S.
areas.
When we try to reduce the number of terms by applying an operation conclusion. That is, if the two premises are true, then the conclusion
to a sentence, we need to choose an operation so that the resulting must be true. Visually in terms of Venn diagrams, this means that if
sentence is logically equivalent to the original sentence. This way, we we combine the basic diagrams of the two premises, we would get
make sure we do not change the argument and turn it into a different the basic diagram of the conclusion. To combine the basic diagrams
argument. The following operation is incorrect because of the premises, we place them on top of the three overlapping
place the Venn diagram of the major premise, the blue pair of circles,
Some H are B. Some H are B.
on top of the three circles. Next, we place the Venn diagram of the
No non-
Contrapos. No H are D. minor premise, the green pair, on top of the three circles. Click on the
D are non-H.
play button to view the illustration.
Some D are Some D are
not B. not B. The animation shows how the blue pair and the green pair are placed
on top of the three circles. Now click the above play button again to
We thus need to use different operations to reduce the number of see the resulting diagram in black and white.
terms. One way to do so is to apply conversion and then obversion to
both the premises. Next, we try to see if the Venn diagram of the conclusion, the red
Conv. & Some B are argument form is valid; if not, then it is invalid. Click on the play
Some H are B.
Obv. not non-H. button of the next illustration. You will see that a portion of the Venn
diagram gradually turns red to illustrate that the red pair is already
No non- Conv. &
All non-H are D. there in the diagram. This shows that we get the red pair from the
D are non-H. Obv.
blue and the green pairs. This in turn means that we have derived the
Some D are not B. Some D are not B.
conclusion from the two premises. As a result, the argument form
Page 10 of 18
AOO-2 is valid. Notice we did not superimpose the red pair on the the part of the diagram in the three circles that is highlighted in red
three circles. does not match the red pair. This means that the conclusion may not
be true given that the premises are true. Consequently, the form is
2.5.2 Rules for Venn Diagrams
invalid.
completed by shading Area 6 and Area 7, and placing an X in Area 5. The next few examples illustrate how to apply the two rules when
Superimposing the blue and the green pairs over the three circles is drawing the Venn Diagram.
an easy way to see which areas are shaded and where the X is placed.
But to draw Venn Diagrams accurately we need to follow the In the form OAO-3, we have a pair with a shaded area and another
following two important rules: pair with an X. According to Rule #1, we need to draw the shading
first. This is why we start with the green pair. We do the shading first
1. Shading always goes before placing an X. to find out which of the seven areas are empty. In this case, we know
2. If one of the two areas in which an X should be placed after the shading that Area 1 and Area 4 are empty. This tells us that
is shaded, place the X in the other area that is not we cannot place the blue X (that is, the X in the blue pair) in these
shaded. If none of the two areas are shaded, put two areas. To find out where to put the blue X, we first recognize that
the X on the line between the two areas. it is inside the area of the blue pair (from now on, we will call the
area Blue for short). In the three circles, Blue amounts to Area 1
A shaded area means that the area is empty, and no X can be in the and Area 2. But according to Rule #2, since Area 1 is shaded, X has
area. This is why shading is done first to determine which areas are to be placed in Area 2. This is why in the animation, the
empty. Placing an X on the line between two unshaded areas means blue X shows up in Area 2. As a result, the part highlighted in red
that all we know is that the X is in either of the two areas, but we do matches the red pair (that is, we have an X in Red ). So the form is
not know for sure which one. valid.
Use the following interactive illustration to become familiar with In the next example, to decide whether the form AII-1 is valid, we
these two rules. start with the blue pair because it is the pair with a shaded area.
You will also learn more about how to apply these two rules by going After the shading, we know that Area 1 and Area 2 are empty. The
over examples. Let us first look at the argument form EAE-1. green X is inside the area (that is, Green ). In the three circles,
highlighted in red. Since the diagram in red matches the red pair, the Now, compare AII-1 with the form AII-2.
form EAE-1 is valid.
Since neither Area 2 nor Area 3 is shaded, according to Rule
In the next form EAE-3, #2, X needs to be placed on the line between the two areas. The
Page 11 of 18
resulting drawing highlighted in red does not match the red pairwe The form AEO-3 also has two universal sentences as premises, but a
do not have an X in Red . This tells us that AII-2 is invalid. particular sentence as the conclusion. So we need to check to see if it
is conditionally valid.
If both of the premises of a categorical syllogism are particular
sentences (that is, either I or Ostatements), then there is no shading in If the set M is not empty, then Area 4 cannot be empty. However,
the Venn diagram. even after we place a brown X in Area 4, the resulting diagram
highlighted in red does not match the red pair. So the form is simply
The Blue is equivalent to Area 3 and Area 4 of the three circles. So invalid.
the blue X needs to be placed on the line between these two areas.
The Green is equivalent to Area 2 and Area 3, and the 2.5.4 Evaluating Categorical Syllogisms
2.5.3 Conditional Validity combining these two sections, we have a process that enables us to
are valid if a certain set is not empty. For example, the form AAI-1 Some voter-approved propositions are not
and EAO-3 are conditionally valid. constitutional. All laws that are unconstitutional
infer that Area 3 cannot be empty. Consequently, we can place First of all, we paraphrase the argument as
from the blue and the green pairs.) As a result, the part of the diagram All non-C are O.
in red matches the red pair, and the form AAI-1 is valid if the set S is
Some V are not C.
not empty (S ).
Some V are O.
circles we can see that in the circle Mthree areas (Area 1, 3 and 4) are
shaded. Now if the set M is not empty, then Area 2 cannot be empty. All non-C are O. All non-C are O.
We indicate this by placing a brown X in Area 2. The resulting Some V are not C. Obv. Some V are non-C.
diagram highlighted in red matches the red pair, and the form is valid
Some V are O. Some V are O.
if M .
Page 12 of 18
The resulting standard form is AII-1. To determine its validity, we
All S are non-T.
draw the Venn Diagram. Notice that the minor term is V, the major
Some P are not S.
term is O and the middle term is non-C.
Some P are S.
The diagram shows that AII-1 is valid. After completing the whole Some P are not T.
process, we find out that the written argument is valid.
Few politicians are not spin doctors. All spin doctors Some P are not S. and Some P are S.
are untrustworthy. Therefore, not all politicians are Some P are not T. Some P are not T.
trustworthy. (P: politicians, S: spin doctors, T: people
who are trustworthy) We then reduce the number of terms to three and get two standard
forms:
The sentence
EIO-1
After paraphrasing all the sentences we have the argument form:
Some P are not S and some P are S. But the next diagram shows that EIO-1 is valid.
EIO-1 from the original argument by simply tossing out the second
If we write Some P are not S and some P are S as two sentences,
premise.
the form would then looks like this:
Page 13 of 18
the Major Term and the Middle Term is called the Major
All S are non-T. Obv. No S are T. Premise and it is always stated as the first premise.
Some P are not S. In any Standard Form Categorical Syllogism, the premise
proposition that expresses the 'distribution of terms' between
the Minor Term and the Middle Term is called the Minor
Some P are S. Some P are S. Premise, and it is always stated as the second premise.
Some P are not T. Some P are not T. Using the example here are the major and minor premises with
the conclusion all Type A standard form categorical propositions
from the Aristotelian Square of Opposition.
Example:
All light bulbs are human. (MAJOR PREMISE = Type A)
The Formal Structure of Syllogistic Reasoning:
All Bostonians are light bulbs. (MINOR PREMISE = Type A)
Therefore, All Bostonians are human. (CONCLUSION = Type
In its most general meaning a 'syllogism' is a formal deductive
A)
argument consisting of just two premises, one called the 'major'
(NOTE THE POSITION OF THE MIDDLE TERM, SUBJECT
premise, and the other called the 'minor' premise, claiming that a
OF MAJOR PREMISE AND PREDICATE OF MINOR
'conclusion' follows if the premises are true. Since the 'form' of
PREMISE )
the four types of categorical propositions, A E I & O, express
either category inclusion or exclusion of members in one class
with members of another class, it is possible to harness this
4. Mood & Figure of Standard Form Categorical
power of 'distribution' to formulate a conclusion from only
Propositions:
two premises with absolutely certain validity.
Obviously, using just the three categorical terms in the example (
Thus, 'validity' is understood as a purely 'formal' deduction of a
'humans', 'Bostonians', & 'light bulbs') it is possible to formulate
new truth claim from the distribution of terms contained in two
literally hundreds of Standard Form Categorical Syllogisms using
other truth claims. Validity of deductive categorical arguments
all four types of standard form categorical propositions AND
does not rely on the factual truth of the premises from which the
MOVING THE MIDDLE TERM in four different permutations
conclusion is drawn. Validity of deductive categorical arguments
in the Major and Minor premises.
relies solely on the 'form' of the argument and not it's content. It
is absolutely essential to understand this in order to proceed in
mastering the power of syllogistic reasoning.
All professors of Philosophy are educated people. (Type A) Here are examples of single categorical propositions with two
All professors of Philosophy are respected members of society. overlapping circles graphing the distribution (or lack of
(Type A) distribution) between the categorical terms expressed in the
Therefore, all respected members of society are educated people. propositions.
(Type A)
Figure = 3 This is a Venn Diagram of any Type
A proposition: All S is P. The
Note that this particular form AAA-3 has the MIDDLE TERM as shaded blue area graphically
SUBJECT in both premises, Major and Minor. Note also that the indicates that; If something is a
MINOR TERM is NOT DISTRIBUTED in EITHER major or member of the category 'S'
minor premise. Yet the conclusion asserts that the MINOR (whatever 'S' might be) then that
TERM is distributed. Since the conclusion claims more something must also be a member
distribution than the premises assert, then the argument is invalid. of the category 'P' (whatever 'P'
And if this argument is invalid, then ANY ARGUMENT OF might be). Another way to say the logically equivalent thing
THIS FORM, AAA-3 will also be INVALID. Here's one that (by via negative) is; "It is not the case that something is a
refutes the original argument by logical analogy: member of the category 'S' without at the same time being a
Page 15 of 18
member of the category 'P'." Or, "There are no members of Step 2. Using the Venn technique
the category 'S' outside the category 'P'." Thus, S is above, graph each premise
distributed and P is not. proposition, starting with the
UNIVERSAL premise.
This is a Venn Diagram of any Type
I proposition: Some S is P. The 'X' in (Note: In any syllogism that has a
the overlapping area graphs the universal and a particular in the
lack of distribution for both S and premises, always graph the
P. The logical import of this graph UNIVERSAL FIRST. In syllogisms
is; There exists at least one with TWO UNIVERSAL
member of the category 'S' that is PREMISES, it does not matter which one you graph first.)
also a member of the category 'P'.
Or, (again using via negativa); It is not the case that there
exists at least one member of the category 'S' that is outside Since the major premise is a universal proposition, we may
the category 'P'. It also states the converse of the original begin with it. The diagram for "No M are P" must shade in the
Some S is P. There exists at least one member of the category entire area in which the M and P circles overlap.
'P' that is a member of the category 'S'.
(Note: Ignore the S circle by shading on both sides of it.)
Using the same Venn technique, here
is an example of any Type E Step 3: Using the Venn technique
categorical proposition No S is P above, graph the minor premise. The
diagram for "Some M are S" puts an
inside the area where the M and S
circles overlap.
All M are P.
All S are M.
Therefore, All S are P.
Page 16 of 18
If we get wet, we will get cold.
AAA-3 (invalid)
Therefore, if we go out we will get cold.
All M are P. Sorites
All M are S. A sorites is a specific kind of polysyllogism in
Therefore, All S are P. which the predicate of each proposition is the
subject of the next premise. Example:
With the purely formal nature of logical validity now understood, and
with the precise technology of Venn idagramming readily at hand in
both Essentials of Logic and Reason, Argue, Refute texts, we can
formulate yet another way to check the validity of any standard form
A polysyllogism (also called multi-premise categorical syllogism. This is done by making valid inferences after
syllogism, sorites, climax, or gradatio) is a string of any number Venn diagramming each of the 15 known valid syllogistic forms. By
of propositions forming together a sequence of syllogisms such that looking at the Venn diagrams of the 15 valid forms and comparing
the conclusion of each syllogism, together with the next proposition, them to the Venn diagrams of the remaining 241 INVALID forms of
is a premise for the next, and so on. Each constituent syllogism is syllogisms a set of six necessary conditions (The Six Rules) for all
called a prosyllogism except the very last, because the conclusion of the 15 valid forms is easily inferred.
the last syllogism is not a premise for another syllogism.
For writing argumentative essays and term papers in this course and
Example for your life of ideas mastery of the 15 valid forms of standard form
An example for a polysyllogism is: categorical syllogisms is indispensable. As already demonstrated, the
Venn diagram technique gives you a handy tool to quickly check
If we go out while it is raining we will get wet. ANY syllogism across the academic disciplines. But what if you
don't have paper and pen at the ready to evaluate any given
If we get wet, we will get cold. syllogism? By formulating the six rules for validity in any standard
Therefore, if we go out we will get cold. form syllogism both texts give you a purely mental process to
Examination of the structure of the argument reveals the demonstrate either validity or invalidity for any categorical syllogism
following sequence of constituent (pro)syllogisms: you may encounter. It all starts with establishing the list of necessary
conditions under which ANY standard form categorical syllogism is
If we go out while it is raining we will get wet. valid.
Therefore, if we go out we will get wet. In our list of 20 distinctions for Critical Thinkers it will be recalled:
Page 17 of 18
"Any list of required elements for something to take place is known
as a list of its necessary conditions." Example that violates Rule 3 (ILLICIT MINOR): All conservatives
are mean-spirited people. All mean-spirited people are Republicans /
As a direct result of finding the necessary conditions for all valid Therefore, all Republicans are conservatives.
syllogistic forms, it can also be inferred that any use of a syllogistic
form outside the 15 valid forms, will constitute a formal fallacy That (Note: In this AAA-4 syllogism the MINOR term, Republicans, IS
is, quite literally, a breech of the proper form of reasoning distributed in the CONCLUSION, yet it is not distributed in the
syllogistically. MINOR PREMISE. And since the premise does not tell us something
about ALL Republicans, then the conclusion cannot tell us something
The most common of these formal fallacies are: about ALL Republicans either. This violation of Rule 3 is called the
1. Fallacy of Four Terms (Quaeternio Terminorum) ILLICIT MINOR. For similar reasons the following IAO-3 syllogism
2. Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle Term is an example of the ILLICIT MAJOR violation of Rule 3, since it
3. Fallacy of the Illicit Major Term or Fallacy of the Illicit Minor applies to the MAJOR term and premise.)
Term
4. Fallacy of Exclusive Premises ( Two negative premises)
5. Fallacy of Affirming a positive conclusion from a negative Rule 4: No syllogism can have two negative premises.
premise
6. Fallacy of a Particular conclusion inferred from two Universal Example that violates Rule 4: No citizens are people that need to own
premises ( Existential Fallacy) a hand gun. Some women are not people that need to own a hand gun
/ Therefore, some women are not citizens.
For each of these formal fallacies there is corresponding necessary
condition for validity that has been violated. Copi, Cohen stipulate (Note: From the two negative premises of this EOO-2 syllogism, no
the six rules. ANY standard form categorical syllogism that meets NECESSARY conclusion can be inferred about 'some women' not
these necessary conditions is VALID, and ANY that violate any one being people that need to own a hand gun. If you try to Venn
of these necessary conditions is INVALID. Knowing the six rules Diagram this argument, then you will see that there is no clear
means that you can demonstrate validity or invalidity in your head UNAMBIGUOUS area to put the 'x' for the MINOR premise.)
without drawing any Venn Diagram.
Here are the six rules and examples of arguments that commit a Rule 5: If either premise is negative, the conclusion must be
FORMAL FALLACY by violating a given rule: negative.
Example that violates Rule 1: All rare things are expensive things. (Note: This EOI-1 violates Rule 5 in that it improperly infers a
All great novels are rare things / Therefore, all great novels are AFFIRMATIVE conclusion from two NEGATIVE premises, and it
expensive things. violates Rule 4 that stipulates that no valid syllogism can have two
negative premises.)
(Note: This syllogism SEEMS to be a valid AAA-1, Barbara, but
because the middle term is used in the major premise in one meaning
and then the meaning of the middle term is shifted in the minor Rule 6: No syllogism with a particular conclusion can have two
premise, you actually have FOUR terms and not THREE as required universal premises.
by the very definition of any standard form categorical syllogism.
THIS IS A COMMON MISTAKE FOR BEGINNING STUDENTS Example that violates Rule 6: All people who write about flowers are
IN LOGIC AND CRITICAL THINKING WHEN FORMULATING inhabited by fairies. All poets are people that write about flowers /
ESSAY AND TERM PAPER ARGUMENTS.) Therefore, some poets are inhabited by fairies.
Page 18 of 18