ED Paradigm 09 - Consciousness
ED Paradigm 09 - Consciousness
In a Landscape of Suggestions
Richard Ostrofsky
copyright © Richard Ostrofsky, 2007
ISBN: 978-1-4357-1325-3
Talk #9 Consciousness1
Consciousness is not some extra glow or aura or “quale” caused
by the activities made possible by the functional organization of
the mature cortex; consciousness is those various activities. One
is conscious of those contents whose representations briefly
monopolize certain cortical resources, in competition with many
other representations. The losers – lacking “political clout” in
this competition – quickly fade leaving few if any traces, and
that’s the only difference between being a conscious content and
being an unconscious content.
– Daniel Dennett, interview with Chris Floyd
Guy: Well, I think we’re finally ready for the discussion we’ve kept
postponing – the one on consciousness I mean.
Guy: I’ll tell you the gist of what is known. I think most of the pieces
we needed are now in place.
Guy: Well, we’ve come quite a distance by now. We’ve seen how
patterns and relationships can organize themselves spontaneously, with no
need for input from an “intelligent designer.” We’ve discussed a notion of
suggestion that goes some distance toward bridging the conceptual gap
between the mental and the physical. We’ve seen how swarm effects,
Guy: Let me say once more that none of this will deprive you of your
precious subjectivity. What I’m presenting here is just a description, a way
of looking at things, that does not alter the phenomenon itself. Your
consciousness remains just what it was before we started these talks – or
this research, for that matter. Understanding how consciousness and
subjectivity are biologically constructed makes them more marvelous not
less so.
Perhaps the most difficult idea in the world today is that our beliefs
may or may not be intellectually honest, or consistent with one another, or
usefully descriptive and/or predictive of experience, but they are never
absolutely true in the classical, eye-of-God sense. Beliefs (including this
one) form and sustain themselves through an eD process, much as life-
forms do. For that reason, new modes of understanding never fully replace
old ones that are still useful and convenient. The sun still rises and sets;
and engineers still use Newtonian physics for most purposes. In a world as
complex and various as ours has become, epistemological sanity is
impossible until we grasp that divergent interpretations compete, but also
complement each other. Their relationship is politicious, not simply
adversarial. So you remain a conscious being, free to go on thinking of
yourself as such. But you can also understand your consciousness in
biological terms, when there is reason to do so.
Thea: Perhaps this new understanding will just confuse people yet
further – more than they are already confused?
Guy: More than likely, I admit. The price of knowledge has always been
a loss of innocence, with strange, new concepts, and difficult choices to
make. Please recognize, though: You or anyone can forego knowledge as a
personal choice. Willful ignorance is a feasible strategy and a highly
popular one; and there may indeed be things that it is better not to know.
That is why so much of our mental life is not conscious. But for humanity
as a whole, the choice was made long ago – when Eve bit into that apple,
in the poetic way of speaking. It’s too late to ask that we not learn how the
brain/mind system works. But you and I can end these talks right here, if
you wish.
Thea: No. It’s too late even for that. You’ve piqued my curiosity. I have
to hear the end of your story. I want to finish this tasty apple.
Guy: But that’s just the point. Functionalists argue that consciousness is
not some abstract property that a creature might or might not possess, but
rather the capability to function in all the ways that we expect of ourselves
and other conscious beings.2 To act like a conscious being is actually to be
one. Patterns of suggestion that reverberate sufficiently broadly and
persistently in the neural circuits are experienced as “consciousness,”
which is simply the feeling of what it like to undergo that neural
reverberation. Itself a part of that reverberation, of course.
Thea: Once again, you’ve ducked the question. Until you explain how
that feeling arises, and why we feel those neural reverberations rather than
merely have them, you haven’t explained anything at all.
Guy: We feel what we ourselves are doing – what the tissues of our
bodies are doing. What we experience as subjectivity is this process of
self-monitoring. To possess functioning neural circuits that warn you that
your body is being damaged, that cause you urgently to do something to
alleviate what is causing the damage, that leave an aversive memory trace
of the situation so it can be avoided in the future, is actually to feel pain.
Likewise, to have neural circuits currently in the spasms of a sneeze or an
orgasm or an epileptic fit is to feel the sneeze or the orgasm or the fit.
When those reverberative processes are fully understood, there is nothing
left to explain.
Thea: I think that is completely wrong. Stories have been written about
the “undead” – about soulless “zombies” whose souls were somehow
stolen from them. You can imagine a zombie or robot that does everything
a man can do, that passes every possible test, but has no conscious feelings
at all.
Guy: Can you really? Perhaps you only think you can. Imagine some
horrible disease that turned its victims into zombies, but left them
unchanged in every other respect. Who would know? Certainly not the
zombies themselves. What I am saying is that life itself is such a “disease.”
The “zombies” you think you are imagining are just we ourselves.
Thea: If I think I can imagine something, then surely I have already done
so. To imagine that I am imagining zombies who lack a faculty of
consciousness that we ourselves possess is the same as to imagine them.
Guy: Not clear! It can be argued that only a conscious being could
produce conversation and behavior indistinguishable from those of a real
Thea: I can’t see why. You can program a computer to play chess at the
grandmaster level. It will not know that it is playing, and will have no real
understanding (no authentically cognized understanding) of the game. In
principle then, why could you not program a robot to produce human
conversation and behavior? I can certainly imagine doing so, whether it is
actually feasible or not. In fact, merely by talking about it, I have already
done so. As have you.
Guy: Hugh Noble has argued that to be convincing, the zombie would
have to have to believe in its own consciousness. 3 Within its neural
circuits, it would have to have convincing representations of a world and
of itself, including such concepts as belief, knowledge, intention, sincerity
and truth. For the zombie, truth will be a correspondence between its
representation of the environment, and its re-presentation of its own
beliefs. It will report to others that it is consciously experiencing its world
(since if it did otherwise, it would not be accepted as conscious); and it
will report to itself that it is truthful in this reporting (since the reporting
would pass its own internal criteria for sincerity and truth). In deceiving
others as to its consciousness, it would at the same time deceive itself. In
doing so, it would be as conscious as you or I; and would be convinced of
its own consciousness in the same way and for the same reasons that you
and I are convinced.
Thea: Ouch! So, if I understand, you’re saying there’s really nobody here
but us zombies, fooling ourselves that we conscious beings, and unaware
that we are doing so.
Thea: If it quacks like a duck, it’s a duck If it walks and talks like a
conscious subject, it is one.
Guy: Right. But it’s more than just a question of labels. It seems that
what we experience as consciousness is the “clout” of a given neural
pattern in its competition with other patterns – its “fame in the brain” as
Dennett puts it.4
Thea: I don’t see that connection. How are clout or fame analogous to
consciousness?
Thea: Neat! I don’t know that I can buy this story, but it certainly is
clever.
4 Dennett’s metaphor, making still more vivid the concept of “multiple drafts”
competing for influence. See Sweet Dreams (2005) or Dennett’s essay Are We
Explaining Consciousness Yet?
Guy: If the earthquake had not come along to swamp it, Jim’s novel
would have been the talk of the nation. Everyone would have heard of it,
gotten a copy, read it, talked about it, and been influenced by it in their
various ways. Similarly, a successful neural pattern reverberates in the
brain, and influences relevant specialist modules; to some extent, human
brains can monitor this reverberation – can track which patterns are
currently influential and take decisions based on this tracking. That self-
monitoring is our consciousness. If we understand the mind as a
suggestion ecology, then consciousness is a kind of user-friendly display
of the current state of that internal eco-system. How exactly that display
works, and what purposes it serves are questions we are just beginning to
answer.
Thea: Still, like the little man upon the stair, the mind-body problem
won’t go away so easily. You still owe some account of feeling itself: what
it is, where it comes from, how it is possible. Without a convincing answer
to that question – and you still haven’t given one – your whole program
cannot answer our most urgent question.
Guy: In the year 2000, Nicholas Humphrey wrote an essay called How
to Solve the Mind-Body Problem that seems to me fully worthy of its title.
I’ll try to summarize it for you, but the essay itself is brief, beautifully
written, and readily available.5 I cannot do justice to it here, and would
urge you to read it for yourself. In a nutshell, Humphrey’s solution is based
on a careful distinction between sensation and perception, and on an
argument that raw sensation may be considered “physical” and “mental” at
the same time – in the same manner I would say that suggestions are.
Thea: There! I’m suspicious right from the start. Why is this not just
another reductionist gambit to reduce feeling to function and sweep the
problem under a rug?
Guy: I don’t think that's a fair description of what he’s doing. Rather,
what Humphrey attempts, as I do, is a reduction of the conceptual distance
between the “physical”and the “mental” by showing that the most
primitive cell already has properties that partake of both, with no clear
distinction between them. He begins by discussing alternative approaches
to the known correlation between mind states and brain states: We can opt
Thea: It’s rather neat to distinguish between two logical types of news:
of what is happening directly to me, and of what is happening out there in
the world that might be causing happenings to me. But the amoeba’s
responsiveness is still just a matter of observable behavior. It’s not clear
that it feels anything at all.
Guy: For Humphrey, as for all the functionalists, the organism’s feeling
is an amplification and reverberation of raw sensation in its neural circuits
(if it’s complex enough to have circuits) but, it is first of all, a mere
“wriggle” (Humphrey’s word) in its very protoplasm. For one-celled
organisms that’s all there is: that “wriggle” at the boundary between the
creature and its world. Later, something like a reflex arc develops from the
site of local stimulation to a proto-brain and back again. Later still, the
neural feedback loops combine, prolong and amplify the raw sensations,
and provide the organism with “user-friendly” read-outs about the
happenings to itself. When further neural circuitry draws inferences about
the world beyond the organism, complex perceptions become possible –
grounded, and distinguished from dream and fantasy by their congruence
with sensation. As all this occurs, sensation is no longer “raw,” but
becomes more and more like what we willingly acknowledge as sentience
– as the rich core consciousness that humans enjoy.
Thea: All right. I’m not sure I’m ready to concede this argument, but I
can at least see where the functionalists are coming from. Suppose I grant
your case for the sake of argument. You still have a lot of work to do.
Guy: Indeed we do. There’s much we still don’t know, and I doubt these
arguments will convince anyone not already disposed to be convinced.
Mysterians can insist forever that the subjectivity of consciousness
remains to be explained even when all the functions of mind, including
feeling itself, have been accounted for. But I think the question they wish
to keep open is a purely metaphysical or religious one, beyond the
competence of science. Whereof we can’t say anything publicly
disconfirmable, we can go on talking as long as we like.
Guy: It’s pretty clear by now that the searchlight analogy is hopelessly
inadequate – not least because it makes it easy to fall into the error of
thinking that we have the light while other creatures don’t. We now must
say that infants and many animals are conscious in some senses, but not in
others, and that the quality of consciousness can vary greatly from one
occasion and person to another. The upshot, I think is that our word
“consciousness” is too vague to be useful for any purpose beyond the
everyday. At a minimum, we need a distinction between sentience
(Damasio’s “core consciousness”), the mindfulness of an animal or a
human baby, and what I think of as linguality – the symbolic, conceptual,
narrative consciousness that evolved along with language, perhaps as a
prerequisite for language. The upshot is that “consciousness,” as we begin
to understand it, is not even a single function (still less a single substance
or quality). “Fame in the brain” subserves a number of functions that
cannot be handled as local, background processes but require the
organism’s full resources.
Thea: What would those functions be? As you’ve pointed out, 7 nothing
like human consciousness is needed to get around in the world. The most
complex sensory-motor coordination is possible without it – actually
works better without it. In dance or martial arts, you train to move
“instinctively” – with fluid, unconscious skill. In creative work of any
kind, the role of consciousness is largely negative: to criticize, organize
7 In Talk #1.
and edit what the unconscious brings forth.
So why do we have consciousness? Surely there must be more to it
than the mere requirement to catch a meal or avoid becoming one.
Thea: Would such a brain really be worth the energy cost and the risks
that came with it?
Thea: I like that phrase: “remembered present.” It calls to mind the work
of anamnesis – “unforgetting” – in therapy: making significant, but highly
negative past experiences available to present consciousness. But then
what? On your model, how would my clients be helped by this recovery of
repressed memories?
Guy: Another feature of this model is to make clear why the kind of
therapy you do must be primarily a talking cure, whatever other forms it
takes. The key to our extraordinarily rich remembered present is the
linguality I mentioned earlier – which has been compared to a serial
information processor running on a massively parallel one.
Thea: Yes. It all fits very neatly. Except for one thing, perhaps: Is there
anything left of the self, for those who accept your story?
the self
Guy: Your self is simply you – all of you, body and mind together, with
the mind experiencing and attempting to manage its body’s activities and
fate. In this respect nothing has changed. But now we see clearly that there
need be no extra, metaphysical “self” inside you, controlling your mind
and thinking your thoughts. Consciousness does not emanate from some
“corner office” in the brain, where high-level reports are tabled and
commands are issued. Rather, there are “modules,” “work groups” or
“agents” doing specialized jobs, and patterns competing for influence over
these modules. Among other things, there is competition to influence the
stories you tell about yourself; and so, from this perspective, the self is a
loosely stable ongoing story.
Thea: Then what story will we tell ourselves now? Or, more precisely,
how will the stories we tell about ourselves be altered when this novel
understanding of consciousness is taken on board?
Guy: Too soon to tell, I’d say. We’ll have to live with this new
psychology for awhile before its implications become clear.
Thea: Well, you’ve been living with it for awhile. What impact have
these ideas had on you? That’s a fair question, isn’t it.
Guy: It’s a fair question. But I’d like to postpone discussion of it till
almost the conclusion of these talks,11 after we’ve talked about this new
paradigm from a developmental and social perspective.
Thea: You might give me a hint. You obviously know where these talks
are going. What’s next?
Guy: We haven’t talked yet about individual personality – how the re-
suggestive structures that guide us as unique persons are themselves
evolved and stabilized through a socializing process which is itself
ecological in nature. That must be our next step. Only then will we gain a
just sense of individual men and women as ecological patterns rooted in
larger patterns – cultures and societies – which are themselves ecologies of
mind.
Thea: Patterns rooted in larger patterns? You make us sound like plants.
Guy: Yes, that image has occurred to me. We could do worse than see
ourselves as sentient, perambulating plants, each thriving as best it can in a
definite historical soil, making what it can of the cultural nutrients it finds,
and altering its cultural “soil” by having lived there. Of course, we are all
plants of the same species. Beyond that, no two of us grow in exactly the
same spot, make the same choices or develop in the same way.
Thea: But . . . what kind of choices can a sentient plant make? What are
the limits of its sentience? What kinds of thinking can it do?
11 To Talk #15.
Guy: All the thinking that we do. My point is that as a cognitive ecology
unto itself, the human organism is an open system that draws upon and
contributes to a native cultural environment, or “soil,” from which it is not
easily displaced. It’s important to be clear that human consciousness is not
a purely individual matter any more than just a matter of algorithmic
computation. Human beings are massively inter-connected suggestion
processors in dynamic equilibrium with each other and with their
environments. The individual will reflect that environment in many ways
and cannot be shifted without trauma and drastic re-organization – if it can
be shifted viably at all, as is not always the case.
Thea: I have to tell you: this notion of a “conscious plant” sounds like an
offensive oxymoron.
Guy: It shouldn’t. After all, it does no more than take seriously John
Bowlby’s notion of an attachment system – extended from the infant’s
primary caregivers to all the relationships and involvements, in childhood
and later, that nourish its life. An individual cut from his roots is not much
more viable than a flower in a vase. Apart from the broadly conceived
attachment system to other systems that satisfy a person’s material and
psychic needs, how long could that person live? How intelligible would he
be?
Thea: But we are not plants, after all. We roam around in the world,
today more than ever. You can buy a ticket, board a plane and be
transported half way round the globe in less than a day.
Thea: No argument from a therapist that our sense of self these days is
much shakier than most people are willing to recognize. My fear is that
this eco-Darwinian paradigm of yours will make it shakier still.
Perhaps this need to understand and explain everything is itself a kind
of pathology. Perhaps the mystery of life is better taken on faith. Perhaps
it’s the examined life – at least, the overly examined one – that’s not worth
living! Perhaps we need a measure of what Keats called “negative
capability” to be sane and happy in this world.
Guy: That may be so. For most people, lacking time or inclination to
look deeply into things, it may well be so. But there’s no way to unlearn
what we now know. There’s no way to stop learning more as we try to
cope with the situation that now exists.