Introduction To Philosophy PDF
Introduction To Philosophy PDF
AN INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY
Compiled by:
1
_____________________________________________________________________________
1. Mans Capacity for Knowledge and His Search for the Truth
Man seeks to know the truth of himself and of things around him. Thus, the fundamental
questions that concern his own nature, origin, purpose, meaning and destination are inevitably
sought; Who am I? What am I here for? Where do I come from? Where am I going? How will I
get there? His very experience of the realities around him also leads him to ask further questions
like: What is being? Why there is evil? etc. This innate hunger for truth forms the discipline of
philosophy, which is expressed in every culture and civilization since time immemorial.
These are the questions which we find in the sacred writings of Israel, as
also in the Veda and the Avesta; we find them in the writings of Confucius
and Lao-Tze, and in the preaching of Tirthankara and Buddha; they
appear in the poetry of Homer and in the tragedies of Euripides and
Sophocles, as they do in the philosophical writings of Plato and Aristotle.
They are questions, which have their common source in the quest for
meaning, which has always compelled the human heart. In fact, the answer
given to these questions decides the direction, which people seek to give to
their lives3.
1
Aristotle.
Ta
Meta
Ta
Pisika,
1.
2
Fulton
Sheen.
Lift
Up
Your
Heart,
69.
3
John
Paul
II.
Fides
et
Ratio,
http://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-
ii_enc_14091998_fides-et-ratio.html. , (14 September 1998) p.
2.
2
Men and women have at their disposal an array of resources for generating greater
knowledge of truth so that their lives may be ever more human. Among these is philosophy,
which is directly concerned with asking the question of life's meaning and sketching an answer
to it. Philosophy emerges, then, as one of noblest of human tasks. According to its Greek
etymology, the term philosophy means love of wisdom. Born and nurtured when the human
being first asked questions about the reason for things and their purpose, philosophy shows in
different modes and forms that the desire for truth is part of human nature itself. It is an innate
property of human reason to ask why things are as they are, even though the answers, which
gradually emerge are set within a horizon, which reveals how the different human cultures are
complementary.
Why does man need to know the truth about himself?
Socrates once advised us to venture into the quest of knowing ourselves as he said,
Know Thyself. Only he who knows the truth about an airplane is free to fly it. In the same
sense, only the person who knows the truth about himself can live his life well. It is meaning that
makes life happy and worth living. Socrates told us once again, an unexamined life is not worth
living.
It is undeniable that since time immemorial, man tirelessly searched for meaning. The
hunger for the truth is connatural to him. As food satiates his stomach and nourishes his health,
truth satiates his intellect and makes him fulfill his rational nature. St. John Paul II affirms mans
infinite desire for the truth. He says, the desire for knowledge is so great and it works in such a
way that the human heart despite its experience of insurmountable limitations, yearns for the
infinite riches, which lie beyond knowing that there is to be found a satisfying answer to every
question yet unanswered.4 He further contends, for within the visible creation, man is the only
creature who is not only capable of knowing but who knows that he knows and is therefore
interested of the real truth of what he perceives.5
The word for philosopher was wise man. Plato who lived in 5th century, explains in one
of his Dialogues how the term philosophy came into existence. He attributes it to Pythagoras,
another philosopher and he said that we can investigate wisdom, we can try to acquire wisdom,
but of course we can never achieve the complete wisdom or the totality of knowledge6. Greek
thinkers call themselves wise men, and that out of humility, Pythagoras wanted to call himself
simply a lover of wisdom or philosopher7. This is how the term philosophy originates.
St. Thomas explains the meaning of the word philosophy at the beginning of one of his
major works: the Summa Contra Gentiles. He explains in the first chapter of this book that
4
Fides
et
Ratio
no.
17
5
Ibid,
no.25.
6
Joseph
M.
de
Torre,
Christian
Philosophy,
39.
7
Mariano
Artigas,
Introduction
to
Philosophy,
3.
3
philosophy is the common ground for all mankind, so that through philosophy we can show the
gentiles that our faith is the true faith by showing its reasonableness. He then goes on to say that
philosophy means almost the same as wisdom. Philo and sophia are two Greek words which
means the love of wisdom.
We refer to the term philosophy we refer to the search of a profound knowledge about
reality that is a knowledge that goes beyond spontaneous knowledge attained by the arts, and
particular as well as technical sciences.8 It is the search of unaided reason for answers to the
ultimate questions of reality; this comprises exclusively that sort of knowledge which reason as
such can gain by itself, without the guidance of revelation.9
The material object refers to the subject matter with which it deals since it is the sum total
of what is studied. The material object of philosophy then is all things (reality), which makes it a
universal science. Unlike particular sciences, which study on some specific aspects of reality
leaving aside all the rest, philosophy studies all aspects of reality since one can seek their
ultimate and most profound causes.
The formal object is just an aspect of the material object. Thus the formal object of
philosophy then, is the study of reality through its ultimate causes, that is by seeking the
deepest explanations regarding the existence and nature of beings.
Philosophy begins with wonder. Once man becomes aware of the things around him, he
then begins to question. He starts to wonder the why, how and what of things. Wonder is the
feeling of a philosopher, and philosophy begins in wonder.10 For, it is owing to their wonder
that men both now begin and at the first began to philosophize.11 Such sense of wonder impels
men not just to take things for granted but to look for their causes and explanation. An honest
search for knowledge eventually ends up in the sense of mystery. Man comes to realize that he
cannot fully grasp the totality of reality itself. The answers to his questions will lead to further
enigmas and puzzles. Socrates himself affirms this fact as he realizes that the more we know, the
more we find out how little we know. In his honest search for truth, man learns to acknowledge
the limitation of the power of his reason. Paradoxically, his finite capacity for knowledge seems
to contradict his infinite longing for the truth. Socrates further contends that philosophy is like
the son of the god of plenty and the goddess of want: at once richest (the greatest aspiration of
man), and poorest in his inability to reach the heights. But man can always be a lover of
wisdom. 12 Thomas Aquinas acknowledges the sense of mystery before his death when he
8
Ibid,
4.
9
Joseph
Cardinal
Ratzinger,
The
Nature
and
Mission
of
Theology,
16.
4
exclaimed that he could not write anymore. It was said that he was able to have the vision of God
himself making him realize that all he had written seems straw compare to what he had seen.
We should bear in mind that the object of our philosophizing is to know the truth of things14
not to impose our truth on things. This aim leads us to arrive the certainty of truth15. A
certainty of truth is necessary and is given only by a sound philosophy, founded on the objective
reality of things.16
Benedict XVI argues that there are two essential tasks of a philosopher especially for us
Christians. The first essential task is to search for God. Second, the attitude of a true
philosopher is to live according to the Logos and in its company.17
One of the earliest answers to these questions can be traced back to Pythagoras, who held
that philosophy seeks knowledge simply for its own sake, apart from any question of gain or
usefulness. He compared the community of man to great crowds who used and come from all
parts of Greece to celebrate Olympic games. Some men come to compete for prizes and honors.
But others come simply as onlookers to see and enjoy the spectacle, seeking neither applause nor
profit. This is the role of the philosopher in the community of men. And as at games it is most
befitting a free man to be a spectator, seeking nothing for himself, so in life contemplation and
understanding far surpassed all other ambitions18. Philosophy concerns more on the purpose of
why man lives. Plato says that only philosophers are truly happy because they contemplate for
the truth. The truth perfects man and makes him more human.
Philosophy concerns how man sees the reality. His perception to the reality conditions his
actions, since man lives as he believes. His pattern of thinking greatly affects the quality of his
life. In this way, philosophy shapes mans worldview. Hence the orderly study of philosophy is
most recommendable, so as to attain a correct and well-founded view of reality19. Marcus
Aurelius once says, the happiness of your life depends on the quality of your thoughts. St. Paul
13
PDV,
52.
14
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
15
IVE
Constitutions
no.
220
16
Ibid.
5
himself encourages us to direct our thoughts to whatever is holy, decent, pleasing and perfect (cf.
Philippians 4:8).
As we found to be the case with the term philosophy itself, we can assign a broad
general meaning and a strict technical meaning to the expression common sense. In its wide
popular meaning, common sense is simply the conglomeration of generally held opinions and
beliefs, more or less well-founded, more or less mixed up with error and prejudice, which makes
up the voice of the community-----what everybody knows20. For the Romans, it means the
vulgar opinion of mankind and for St. Thomas it was a technical expression for the unifying
sense. For certain modern philosophers, it has meant a kind of instinct or special feeling for the
truth.21
Common sense refers to the spontaneous activity of the intellect, the way in which it
operates of its own native vigor before it has been given any special training. It implies mans
native capacity to know the most fundamental aspects of reality, in particular, the existence of
things (including my own existence), the first principles of being (the principle of identity, non-
contradiction and excluded middle), and secondary principles, which flow immediately from the
self-evident principles (the principles of sufficient reason, causality, etc.).
One of the points that links philosophy and common sense is that they both use these
principles. They differ however in the way they use them. Common sense uses them
unconsciously, unreflectively, and uncritically. They can be obscured or deformed for common
sense by faulty education, by cultural prejudices, by deceptive sense imagery. Philosophy on the
contrary uses these principles critically, consciously, and scientifically. It can get at things
demonstratively, through their causes. It can therefore defend and communicate its knowledge.
Philosophy therefore as contrasted to common sense is scientific knowledge; knowledge that is
through causes22.
The second point that links philosophy and common sense is that they take all reality for
their province-common sense blindly, in a kind of instinctive response of the individual to the
totality of experience; philosophy consciously, in the endeavor to give the aspect of the reality its
due. This claim philosophy to know the whole of reality does not mean that philosopher makes
pretense of knowing everything-the human intellect cannot exhaust the mystery of the smallest
being in the universe, let alone everything. It remains true nevertheless that all things are subject
matter of philosophy, in the sense that philosopher takes as his angle of vision or point of view
20
Daniel
J.
Sullivan,
An
Introduction
to
Philosophy,
261.
21
Ibid.,
262.
22
Ibid,
263.
6
the highest principles, the ultimate causes of all reality. Along with common sense, then,
philosophy seeks the comprehensive, all-inclusive view of reality; it is the knowledge of all
things.23
Philosophy is close to common sense because it shares the universality of common sense
and a common insight into the fundamental structure of reality. we might even say that
philosophy grows out of common sense, and common sense taken in its strict meaning is a kind
of foreshadowing, a dim silhouette, of philosophy proper. Any philosophy therefore, that strays
very far from common sense is suspect. If it goes so far as to contradict the basic certitudes of
common sense, then it is guilty of denying reality itself, and on this point, common sense can
pass judgment on it.24
2. Philosophy as Wisdom
Wisdom enables him to discover the meaning of life and to act in an upright way.
Ignorance, in contrast, is the source of disorder and errors in behavior, which prevent him from
attaining happiness.
One can attain true wisdom without studying philosophy. Spontaneous metaphysics of ordinary
knowledge suffices to make a person grasps the basic truths that govern human conduct.
Nevertheless, one needs a systematic study these truths to attain wisdom in all its extension and
depth. The term wise man is usually applied to a person who has a certain and well-founded
knowledge of the deepest truths, which enables him to guide and influence other people.
We can define wisdom in general terms as certain knowledge of the deepest cause of
everything25.
Commenting on Aristotles thought about this matter, St. Thomas Aquinas says: The
tern wisdom is applied to the most certain among the arts; knowing the first causes in a particular
type of arts, they serve as a guide for all the rest within a specific category, just as the architect
guides manual workers. In the same manner we regard some people as wisest among all that is
not only with regard to some type of beings but also with regard to all. Just as the wise man in
some kind of arts possesses the greatest certainty, wisdom in general (sapientia simpliciter) is
most certain among the sciences, since it reaches the first principles of beings.
Thus wisdom has a judging and guiding role with regard to other forms of knowledge,
since perfect judgment about something can be obtained only by taking into account its ultimate
causes26.
23
Ibid,
24
All
the
passages
from
Philosophy
and
Common
Sense
are
taken
from
Daniel
Sullivan,
An
Introduction
to
7
Though the term wise man is usually applied to a person who has distinguished himself
in some particular specialty, it is applied in the proper sense to a person who has certain
knowledge of the most general causes of everything. It may happen that ordinary persons may be
wiser (in the strict sense) than a scientist who tackles issues outside his field of specialty with his
usual erudition, but in a superficial way.
In the natural level, the most perfect wisdom is attained through metaphysics. This is so
because metaphysics studies the deepest causes of reality, insofar as they can be known by
natural reason (with respect to all creation, the most profound cause is God; within a more
restricted scope, the human soul, which is spiritual). Metaphysics provides the foundation for a
proper perspective in particular sciences and for the adequate interpretation of their findings; it is
also the basis of natural ethics. Although metaphysics does not go into a detailed analysis of all
the sciences, it passes judgment on the ultimate value of the specific knowledge they attain. Thus
it makes the ordering of different types of knowledge and acts towards their true end possible.
In a general way, wisdom studies all things in the light of their ultimate causes. Above all
it considers them in relation to God, who is the origin and end of all creatures. In this way, it
allows us to carry out the task of passing judgment on them and of ordering them with regard to
their ultimate end, which is God.
Wisdom is also science, since science is the knowledge of truths attained by means of
demonstration, starting from some principles.
To understand this better, consider that most of us know through experience that not
everyone who is knowledgeable is wise. Some people have a great deal of learning, but very
little wisdom. Clearly there is a difference between knowledge and wisdom. What exactly is the
difference between the two?
Let us begin with knowledge of the scientific kind, since most of us are more familiar
with it; for even kids can possess it. The word "science" comes from the Latin verb scire, which
8
means "to know". Science, therefore, is about possessing a certain kind of knowledge. Some
people are under the impression that science is about knowing facts. But science is much more
than that; for everyone knows certain basic facts, such as "leaves are green", or "the sky is blue",
or that "people get cancer", etc, and that doesn't make them scientists. A person has science,
however, when he knows the reason for the fact, such as why leaves are green, or the reason for
cancer, etc. Science is about reasoned facts. In other words, one has science when one knows the
cause of the fact.
Now that which manifests a desire to possess "science" is the act of questioning. The
word question comes from the Latin querere, which means to quest, to journey, or to search. To
question is to go out on a quest in search of something, namely the cause of a fact, or the reason
for it. That is why science is fundamentally a knowledge of things through their proper causes.
Wisdom is a kind of science, and so it too is knowledge of things through causes. But,
more precisely, wisdom is knowledge of the highest causes. It is the intellectual virtue by which
a person judges in light of the highest or first causes. That is why we sometimes find wisdom in
older people, for they have had the years of experience to "see the larger picture", so to speak.
They have encountered many kinds of people throughout their lives, they have been deceived
before, lied to, have been pleasantly or unpleasantly surprised by things they weren't aware of,
they've made mistakes, have had time to reflect upon their mistakes and the mistakes of their
friends, associates, and family, and they have come to learn how to distinguish the genuine friend
from the false friend, they know something about what marriage really is as opposed to what
they thought it was when they first married, they understand what love really is and what it is
not, they understand that they knew very little when they thought they knew a lot, and so they
know something about human limitations, which they didn't quite appreciate when they were
younger. And so they understand something about human nature and human frailty, and they are
able to give us advice on whom we ought to be careful of, whom we can trust, what to expect in
the future, etc.
Such people are wise as a result of experience, honest reflection, and the ability to
reason. Not everyone over 50 is wise, because not everyone over 50 is honest, reflective, or
rational. And one has no need of a microscope in order to be wise. But one cannot do biology,
for example, without a microscope. And so philosophy, which is the love of wisdom, does not
require technology. The reason is that philosophy is the pursuit of first or ultimate causes; it is
the study of the ultimate nature of things. Empiriological science, unlike philosophy, seeks the
proximate causes of things, not their ultimate causes.
A few simple examples may help to clarify these points. Consider the growth of living
things. The biologist would like to know why things grow, that is, the cause of growth. Why do
cells multiply? How does cell division work? When he understands the cause of cell division, he
can be said to possess science. But if he claims to know the cause of cell division, he must be
able to demonstrate it. He can only do so definitively through empirical means (i.e., some sort of
experiment, or via the use of something that enhances the sense of sight, such as a microscope).
But sometimes people ask questions about causes of a different sort. Cells that are not
alive would not divide, and if they divide, they are alive. So, what is it that makes the cell living
in the first place? That question bears upon a first cause. Moreover, a cell is not living unless it
9
first exists. Thus, what is the cause of its very existence? That question too bears upon a first or
ultimate cause. Now every part of the living cell is alive, which is why we are not going to find
the cause of its life within some part of the cell. One cannot say, for instance, that the cause of its
life is the DNA, for the DNA is alive in so far as it is a part of the living cell. One only has to ask
what it is that causes the DNA to be living DNA? If it is a part of the cell, the cause will be the
same as the cause of the whole cell's life. Furthermore, existence is not a part of the cell; for the
whole cell exists. The cause of the cell's existence is not going to be something that you will be
able to see under a microscope. In other words, first causes cannot be investigated via the senses.
And so we have no choice but to reason our way to first or ultimate causes.
Metaphysics is both science and wisdom at the same time. There is no conflict in these
two aspects since metaphysics is precisely wisdom by being the science which studies ultimate
causes in the natural order.
St. Thomas Aquinas states that the science called wisdom is that which deals with first
causes and first principles27, he also asserts that wisdom is not just any other science; rather it is
the science of the most noble and divine realities, thus the head of all the sciences28. Indeed
wisdom is a science insofar as it shares what is common to all sciences, that is arriving at the
conclusions by demonstration, starting from some principles. But it has something proper to it
alone, which puts it above the other sciences, since it passes judgment on all things, not only
with regard to conclusions, but with regard to the first principles. Hence, it is a virtue (an
intellectual one) more perfect than science29.
Socrates is said to have equated virtue with knowledge. The period of Enlightenment
highlighted this relation of identity, affirming that science would suffice to make a person good.
Knowledge and moral virtue exert a mutual influence, since moral uprightness demands
prudence and prudence requires moral virtues. Knowledge itself does not suffice to make a
person morally good and happy; but ignorance regarding what is good makes upright living and
happiness difficult to attain. The study of particular sciences does not necessarily interfere with
the subjects moral dispositions, at least in matters which are not relates to ones personal
commitment, such as mathematical proofs, or demonstrations in the mathematical physics, or
many sociological or historical issues. But when particular sciences tackle issues that have
repercussions on attitudes towards life, the objectivity of the science concerned will also depend
on ones subjective dispositions. Thus, a person may exhibit an ignorance clothed in scientific
27
In
Metaphysics.,
I,
1
(35).
28
In
Ethic.,
VI,
6
(1184).
29
S.Th.,
I-II,
q.57.a.2,
ad1.
10
garb, and may take a stand that coincides with his personal preferences, in disregard of objective
considerations. This kind of pseudo-scientific ignorance is a serious hindrance in the quest for
objective view of reality and for true theoretical and moral wisdom.
For instance, an individual who accepts the historical laws Marxism upholds will tend to
interpret many historical events in the light of class struggle and the conflict of economic
interests although there may no facts supporting such interpretations, or even if the available data
may show the contrary. Something similar happens when a materialist studies psychology. He
will have the tendency to view human behavior in as determinist, in an arbitrary and anti-
scientific manner. One can easily see that in these and other similar cases, true wisdom gives rise
to an independent and objective attitude, and helps people discover the errors of various forms of
pseudo-scientific reductionism.
When a person comes face to face with wisdom, he finds himself confronted with truths
that have a deep bearing on his existence. Thus ignorance and error on these matters are closely
linked with moral uprightness of the subject. Knowledge concerning the deepest cause demands
an upright will that sincerely seek what is good without allowing itself to be carried away by
arbitrary preferences. Hence, the exercise of human freedom plays an important role in the
growth of sapiential knowledge, which deals with the ultimate causes and fulfills a judging and
ordering role with regard to other forms of knowledge.
Speaking about doctrine, St. Thomas Aquinas says to be efficacious, it must find a soul
possessing good morals, disposed to welcome the good joyfully and detests what is evil. The soil
must be well tilled in order to make the seed bear fruit. But a person who lives according to his
passions does not hear with good dispositions the words of the person who corrects him.
Obviously since freedom plays a main role in these matters, a persons dispositions may not
necessarily be constant; there is always room for change. But it is clear that the determining
factors in matters that fall within the term wisdom are not merely theoretical ones, no matter
how important they maybe.30
We can describe as the knowledge of things by their ultimate causes, as we have said. From
the word wisdom comes Wiseman, sage or savant: a scholar, an educated or learned man. A
savant is a person who has profound knowledge of reality, who knows the ultimate truths and
can give advice and guidance. Sometimes, he is replace by the fortune-teller, which is sign of an
impoverished culture.
What is the characteristic of wisdom? That it is concerned with the highest and most
ultimate causes, and that is why it leads to God. If we start looking for causes, eventually come
to God, the first and ultimate causes of everything. According to depth of these causes, we
Christians can distinguish to level of wisdom: the lower one is, that of reason alone, is Natural
wisdom; and the higher one, that of reason illumined by faith, is Supernatural wisdom.
30Artigas,
Mariano,
Introduction
to
Philosophy,
18-19.
11
St. Thomas says that the greatest wisdom is what he calls sacred doctrine: the doctrine
revealed by God to man and all the implications which man can withdraw from that doctrine.
This doctrine includes therefore both (i) what can be known about God through creatures, and
(ii) what only He knows but communicates to creatures through divine revelation. It includes (i)
revelation known through faith, and (ii) theology.
Example of truth or revelation: Though art the Christ, the Son of the Living God. Example
of a truth of theology: There is only one God in three persons: Father, Son and Holy Spirit:
here, there is already an elaboration of theology, although since it has been defined by Church, it
is also a truth of revelation, i.e. implicit in revelation.
Let us recall the revelation is received by man through faith, and faith is a gift from God:
hence the absolute dependence on God in order to acquire supernatural wisdom. Then, in
addition to the gift of faith, man receives also as perfection of the gift of faith, the gift of
wisdom, one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit. So, through this gift of wisdom man
understands the meaning of what he believes much better. Supernatural wisdom, then, is not just
the gift of wisdom from the Holy Spirit, but The wisdom acquired by man through faith,
theology and gift of wisdom of the Holy Spirit.
Now, we must remember that the gift of wisdom of the Holy Spirit is a gift of love because
the Holy Spirit is precisely the love of God. Therefore what matter is not to be a brilliant
thinker, but to love God very much (First Commandment). The depth of supernatural wisdom
depends on the intensity of loving God.
And then on a lower level we have a natural theology. What is wisdom on the natural level?
What we call metaphysics. And what is metaphysics? The study of the ultimate and most
universal causes through natural reason, and it reaches up to God and the spiritual beings. We
can say that the relationship between the two wisdoms is the same as between reason and faith,
philosophy and theology.
St. Thomas says that it is proper to the sage, to the philosopher, to order all things in relation
to, and in the light of the ultimate cause, which is God. Order means arranging things in relation
to an end or design, relating means to ends, and it is proper to the mind to do this. So, this is what
the wise man does. When everything in our life is in its place, all related to one ultimate end,
everything related to God, and then everything is in order. On the other hand, the failure of man
to relate himself to God is what is called sin: the greatest of all disorders. And the work of
wisdom consists in putting things back in their place relating them all to God.
Wisdom considers ultimate causes, and above all the last end. We must remember that there
are four causes to account for the being or becoming of anything that comes to be. The present of
intelligence is revealed by those four questions, which announce the emergence of intelligence in
a person:
12
What is this?
What is it for?
What is it made of?
Who made it? (Who brought it into being?)
The first one is called the formal causes: it points to the essence of the thing, what thing is.
The second in the final Cause: the end for which it is made, the end or purpose. The third is
material cause. And the fourth is material cause. And the fourth is efficient cause: agent, maker,
producer. So, these are four: (i) essence or nature, (ii) purpose, (iii) stuff, and (iv) maker. And
these for question also indicate that this is field of metaphysics, that is, the study of being,
because the four of them point at being: what is the being of this? What is it? What is it for?
What is it made of? What brought it into being? This is metaphysics the field of the four causes
pointing to the being of things and it is also the approach of common sense.
Now, wisdom considers ultimate causes and above all the last end, the ultimate final causes
of everything that is or comes to be: it judges and orders all things in the most perfect way, that
is, related to the last end.
St. Thomas says also that taking into account the type of order, there are different types of
wisdom: there are as many types of wisdom as ways of relating things to an end. Accordingly, he
mentions four types of wisdom:
Metaphysics and science (what he calls speculative sciences) consider the order which exists in
reality-- the reality we perceive through our senses, and which man has not made, but only
found. The sciences look at reality and parcel it out among themselves. Each of them looks at in
one aspect of it: physics, chemistry, biology, etc. And metaphysics studies all these realities in
relation to the last end.
The second type is moral philosophy: the study of free action of man relation to the last
end, or how man ought to behave in relation to his last end.
The study of human reason makes in its own operations of acquiring knowledge and organizing
it: this is logic. This is most difficult study, since we have to make greatest effort of reflection: to
look at our own thinking. While in metaphysics and the sciences we look at reality directly, in
moral philosophy we have to make an effort of reflection to look at our own behavior, and in
logic even more so, as we look at our own thinking.
Lastly, we have the practical sciences, also called arts, the type of knowledge, which is
directly concern with making things. Art in Greek is techne, hence technique or technology. It is
also wisdom in so far as things are related to ends, made for some purpose.
This shows also that the mind has two functions: (a) reception, and (b) action. On the
other hand, it gathers information and knowledge, and on the other, it others things to practice.
But for practical action, knowledge is required. In order to acquire any technique or art, one has
to study. This means that speculative or wisdom the reception of knowledge is higher and more
important than practical wisdom, and prior to it.
Speculative comes from a Latin verb, which means mirroring (specullari, speculum): what the
mind that is mirror reality. But then, it also act in reality, it makes things, and that is practiced,
13
which comes from the Greek for action of making: praxis. On the other hand the Greek for
reception, looking at, is theorein; hence, theory and practice31.
Wisdom is also science, in fact it is the head of the body of sciences. It directs and judges
the other sciences, because the other sciences take for granted what metaphysics studies, namely
the fundamental truths about reality: What is being? What are the first principles of being and
reason? Any science, like physics or chemistry, takes for granted that a thing cannot be itself and
another in the same sense. What metaphysics does is precisely to look at this principle (called
the priniciple of non-contradiction). What is to be? What is to be itself? And to be another?
These are the questions asked by metaphysics (wisdom), and that is why its position is like the
head in relation to the body of all the sciences.
Metaphysics, however, is also a science, because it studies the cause of things, and this is
what science is, as we have seen: accurate knowledge through the causes. But it goes beyond all
the other sciences, since it is not satisfied wih knowing immediate or proximate causes, as other
sciences do, but looks for ultimate causes: this is what makes it wisdom (in the natural order).
St. Thomas explains the difference between philosophy and the other sciences by saying
that the degrees or types of science can be classified according to the various degrees elevation
above matter. It is very important to understand this point well.
Matter is the word we use to designate the world we perceive through our senses, the
sensible world or corporeal world (world of bodies). Now, the first characteristic of this sensible
world is that it is in continuous change. But science (episteme in Greek) is precisely a stable
knowledge, a knowledge that does not change. It is our understanding of things that changes, but
we aim at permanent knowledge, true, and valid always and everywhere. A scientific proposition
maybe expanded, modified, enriched or discarded, but to be scientific at any stage it has to be
stable and permanent, without stability, there is no accuracy, no necessity, no science, but since
matter is ground of change, in order to reach real scientific knowledge of reality we have to rise
above matter, so to speak.
This is what sciences do. First, they rise little above matter (which is always changing) in
order to discover general and stable patterns and laws in material bodies. This is the level of
sciences of nature. Nature in general means the sensible world. It comes from the Latin natura,
which means, what is born, what comes to be, anything that moves from being something to
being something else, from non-being to being. In Greek, the word for nature is physis, hence the
term physics and physical. The object of these physical or natural sciences is, therefore all
bodies or corporeal beings, i.e. those in whose definition sensible matter enters (men, animals,
31
See
Joseph
M.
De
Torre,
Christian
Philosophy
(from
Wisdom
as
knowledge
of
Ultimate
Causes
to
Philosophy
and
other
Sciences).
14
plants and inanimate bodies, whether solid, liquid or gaseous). This is the first degree of
elevation above matter. Here we no longer consider this or that sensible being, but sensible being
as such, i.e. abstracted from its individual and changing conditions: in its common (universal)
and permanent reality. These sciences are difficult because of the effort of abstraction or rising
above matter.
Then there is a second degree or level of elevation above matter, wherein we study beings
which although cannot exist without matter can be thought of or conceived without matter, with
a complete abstraction from matter. Sensible matter does not enter in their definition since they
can be conceived without it. These are abstract quantities or dimensions, whether continuous
(linear, surfaces, solids) or discrete (numbers). Quantity cannot exist alone, without matter, but it
can be conceived without matter, the science of abstract quantities is called mathematics, and its
greater difficulty lies in that it requires a greater effort of abstraction or elevation above matter,
but this makes it also more certain and accurate, and thus very useful for the physical sciences,
which, on the other hand, are more immersed in reality.
Lastly, we come to the third and highest level of elevation above matter, wherein we
consider beings which can both exist without matter and be conceived without matter. At this
level, we do not look at sensible being as such, or quantity as such, but at being as such. And to
be does not imply any matter at all or any change, to walk, to fall, to eat, to write, to cry or any
other such act does, but not to be or the act of being. To be is wider than any act we can think
of. To focus in being requires, therefore, the highest degree of elevation above, or separation
from matter. This separation is not a flight from, but a much more pervasive penetration into
reality, into reality as such, beyond all the differences of changes and quantities. It is the level of
meta-physics or trans-physics (meta- or trans- means beyond). At this level, all realities can be
looked at, both (i) those which exist and are conceived without matter, such as God and spiritual
beings, and (ii) those which may or may not exist without matter, such as substances and
accidents. Let us now take a first look at this highest of all sciences (wisdom) on the natural
level.
Philosophy is a science, and it is a science in an eminent way, that is, it is more sublime
than other sciences, as we ourselves can conclude after considering the two principal meanings
of the term science.
First, in so far as science is certain knowledge through causes, philosophy can be truly
considered as a science. Besides, since it studies the deepest causes of reality, it is the first and
most eminent among all the sciences; the other sciences deal only with the more immediate or
proximate causes of reality.
15
One has to note, moreover, that philosophy also studies the first or most basic principles of all
knowledge, which other sciences do not do. Hence, philosophy is truly a science, but it should be
considered not simply as one more among the other sciences, but as a science superior to all the
rest.
Thus, Descartes assumed as a model for philosophy the clarity and precision of
mathematics, and he wanted to deduce all knowledge from indubitable evidence.32 Kants model
was his own interpretation of Newtons physics, whose precision he regarded as a definitive
achievement; he concluded that the universality of knowledge comes form the necessary use of
some categories of thought common to all men.33 Other more recent attempts are those of
Husserl, whose phenomenological method exerted a great influence on 20th century philosophy34,
and of the neo-positivists of the Vienna Circle, who reduced all philosophy to the logical analysis
of language35
These approaches can only achieve a fictitious clarity, for they arbitrarily reduce
philosophical issues to some partial aspects36
True precision can only be attained by employing correct reasoning, starting from
experience, and avoiding all forms of unilateral reductionism. The lack of general agreement
should not be traced to philosophy itself, but to the shortcomings of those who do not study
issues with the required rigor or precision, and who try to explain reality by reducing it to some
of its partial aspects, and also to the difficulty entailed in the study of profound philosophical
issues.
Philosophy is really a science composed of different sciences. In spite of this fact, we can
still speak of a philosophical science, since the different parts of philosophy are closely linked
and are characterized by the same perspective. The nucleus of philosophy is metaphysics, which
studies the basic aspects of reality (its being) and its ultimate causes. The metaphysical
perspective, applied in the study if beings found in nature, gives rise to the philosophy of
inanimate nature, the philosophy of corporeal beings, and the philosophy of man.
32
Cf.
E.
GILSON,
La
unidad
de
la
experiencia
filosofica,
Rialp,
Madrid,
1973,
pp
147-176;
C.
CARDONA,
Rene
positivist.)
36
For
a
suitable
historical
and
thematic
discussion
of
this
topic,
see
E.
GILSON,
El
ser
y
los
filosofos,
EUNSA,
Pamplona, 1979.
16
Thus, when we speak of philosophy (in singular), we should not forget that the term
denotes several disciplines having the same basic perspective, which is metaphysical, that is, the
study of reality in the light of ultimate causes. That is why the differences between philosophy
and particular sciences are based mainly on the metaphysical perspective used by philosophy.
Even though not all philosophy is, strictly speaking, metaphysics, any philosophical study must
always be characterized by a metaphysical perspective.
Any specific aspect of reality can be the object of philosophical study, hence,
philosophy of nature, philosophy of man, philosophy of law, and so on, are branches of
philosophy even though these may be given other names. But a specific discipline cannot
rightfully be considered as a philosophical study simply because it has raised some general issues
about a specific matter; it must have the proper perspective, that is, it must gear its study towards
the being of the reality it tackles, and seek its ultimate causes.
The differences between philosophy and particular sciences are due mainly to a particular
point: philosophy studies reality in its deepest or most radical aspect, and seeks its ultimate
causes, while particular sciences study specific aspects of reality, and seek more immediate or
proximate causes. The proper scope of particular sciences (whether they are natural sciences like
physics and biology, or human sciences like sociology or history) is limited to some particular
aspects of reality; for instance, they can be physical properties or human behavior. Particular
sciences study these aspects, seeking causes, which do not go beyond that level for example, they
may try to find out how some physical properties affect other properties, or how some forms of
human behavior influence others. In contrast philosophy studies all reality, and tries to discover
the ultimate explanation of its very being.
In its search for the ultimate causes of reality, philosophy reaches the realm of spiritual
realities and it studies them as such. The knowledge of God, the knowledge of the human soul,
and the knowledge of the moral law are matters that properly and exclusively belong to
philosophy. Besides, philosophy deals with all aspects of reality in the light of ultimate
explanations, which are strictly metaphysical.
Scientism claims that the method employed by experimental sciences is the only valid
one in order to know reality. This position is self-contradictory, since what it affirms cannot be
proven through the use of the scientific method.
Compared with the optimistic scientism of the 18th and 19th centuries, which considered
science as the solution to all human problems, contemporary scientism is usually pessimistic, it
acknowledges the limits of science, and even exaggerates them, extending them to all fields of
human knowledge, and asserts that we can never affirm any truth with certainty. This, for
instance is the case in the positions adopted by K.R. Popper and M. Bunge.
There is also a scientism that affects human sciences. For example, there is a
historicism that seeks the ultimate explanation of reality in historical factors governed by
17
necessary laws. Hence, its adherents arbitrarily deny the existence of other relevant factors, and,
at least theoretically, of human freedom.37
Particular sciences study reality using their respective methods and perspectives, which
are not philosophical. But they are founded on metaphysics, in varying degrees. Indeed, they
implicitly rely on certain notions regarding the reality they seek to study, and explicitly reflecting
on these ideas is a philosophical task. For instance, physics starts from some general notions and
principles regarding bodies, space and time, as well as physical causality, which are studied by
philosophy.
Marxism reduces human phenomena to economic factors and the necessary laws of
history. Hence, the partial truths it may contain are placed within a clearly erroneous context,
which does not acknowledge any spiritual dimension that characterizes man essentially.39
37
For
an
analysis
of
some
scientistic
doctrines,
see
J.A.
Riestra,
Condorcet:
Esbozo
de
un
cuadro
historico
de
los
progresos
del
espiritu
humano,
op.
cit.;
J.
J.
SANGUINETI
Augusto
Comte:
Curso
de
filosofia
positive,
Emesa,
Madrid,
1977;
M.
ARTIGAS,
Karl
Popper:
Busqueda
sin
termino,
op.
cit.
38
Cf.
S.L.
JAKI,
Brain,
Mind
and
Computers,
Gateway,
South
Bend
(Indiana),
1978.
This
work
offers
an
Contemporanea,
CSIC,
Madrid,
1962.
In
this
work,
the
author
shows
the
need
to
study
psychology
from
the
standpoint
of
man
in
his
totality.
18
These three positions are examples of reductionist doctrines, since they reduce the reality
they study to some aspects, and ignore the rest. They can attract minds because of their false
clarity, attained by arbitrarily simplifying objective data. In so far as they are usually presented
as scientific conclusions, they are pseudo-scientific doctrines, in which some partial scientific
truths are mixed with false statements. Since their errors are usually presented with partial truths
as forming just one single doctrine, it is difficult to isolate the partial truths from the errors they
contain.
The more sublime the object of a particular science is, the closer its link with philosophy
will be. Since biology studies living beings, it has more metaphysical implications than
chemistry. The sciences that deal directly with man (like psychology, sociology and history) will
necessarily make use of philosophical knowledge, and the truth of their conclusions will depend
greatly in their use of a correct metaphysical foundation.
For instance evolutionist theories in biology cannot rightfully deny the divine creation of
the universe, since they should limit their study only to the possible origin of some being from
some other pre-existing beings. Neither can they lawfully deny the spirituality of the human soul,
which, unlike material realities, cannot be the object of scientific experimentation. If one tries to
defend materialism though biology, he will be guilt of a false and scientifically unjustified
extrapolation.41
Particular sciences do not carry out metaphysical study. They make use of metaphysical
bases without adopting the perspective proper to philosophy, these sciences have their own
autonomy: their relations with philosophy do not prevent them from having their own methods of
obtaining and judging their own conclusions. With respect to them, philosophy has a guiding role
of a higher order, which does not interfere with their autonomy.
Philosophy judges and guides the rest of the sciences, because it has the function of
judging first the principles of all human knowledge and the value of scientific methods. Hence,
41
Cf.
for
example,
P.
JORDAN,
Creacion
y
misterio,
EUNSA,
Pamplona,
1978
19
its task includes determining the porper object of every science and classifying the sciences
according to a hierarchy, taking into account their specific nature.
This does not affect in any way the autonomy of the sciences. Philosophy dies not
interfere with them in their own respective fields, since its guiding role is exercised from a
higher lever. For instance, philosophy does not provide the means to judge the truth of a physical
or biological law, but it can issue a warning that some statements made in the name of physics or
biology are actually unjustified extrapolations which lie outside the scope of their respective
methods.
The conclusions of particular science are not deduced from philosophy, as Descartes in
some way tried to do. Nor are they totally independent from philosophy, as the positivists
affirmed. These conclusions are obtained through the methods proper to every science, but the
judgment on the validity of these methods requires philosophical considerations.42
From ancient times until the 18th century, philosophy was considered the sum total of all
knowledge, including the particular sciences. In many cases, the relative autonomy of the
particular sciences was not respected, In contrast, 19th century positivism reduced the task of
philosophy to a mere reflection of the findings of the positive sciences. A correct view of this
matter has to take into account the different perspectives of philosophy and the particular
sciences, and at the same time, their relationship, as previously explained.
In ancient times and in the Middle Ages, the scientific-experimental sciences were
grouped, together with the philosophical sciences, into natural philosophy. Even Newtons
principal work, a treatise on physics in the modern sense published in 1687, was titled
Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.
The progress of experimental sciences since the 17th century, achieved without a precise
understanding of their methods, provoked a reversal of attitudes: for some, experimental science
seemed to be the only valid knowledge about nature, and the cope of philosophy was limited to
methodological reflections or to the study of scientific conclusions geared towards arriving at a
synthesis. Alongside these positivist attitudes, bannered especially by Auguste Comte, opposite
exaggerated positions existed, which tried to relegate the sciences to a secondary role, far below
what their true advances dictated. Among these was the stand taken by the idealists. In general,
the relations between the sciences and philosophy until the 20th century have been characterized
by numerous irritants from either side, leading to misunderstanding and confusion.
42
Cf.
J.
MARITAIN,
Introduccion
general
a
la
filosofia,
Club
de
lectores,
Buenos
Aires,
1945,
pp89-100.
Maritain
rightly
concludes
that
to
advance
in
the
sciences,
one
does
not
have
to
be
a
philosopher,
and
that,
when
scientists
devote
themselves
to
their
sciences,
they
need
not
ask
for
advice
from
philosophy
or
strive
to
e
philosophers.
But
he
also
points
out
that
without
philosophy,
the
scientist
will
not
be
able
to
take
cognizance
of
the
place
or
the
scope
of
his
field
of
specialization
within
the
over-all
framework
of
human
knowledge,
nor
will
he
be
able
to
know
adequately
the
foundations
of
his
own
science.
Maritain
also
says
that
whenever
philosophy
does
not
adequately
exercise
its
guiding
role.
We
find
ourselves
faced
with
lethal
chaos
and
a
general
decline
of
the
intellect.
(Ibid.,
p
93).
20
Major revolutionary discoveries in the sciences in the 20th century have contributed to a
better understanding of the nature of the experimental method. Nevertheless, the widespread
influence of positivist prejudices and the inadequacy of some of the more popular philosophical
systems of the rationalist, existentialist, or materialist bent have given rise to considerable
imbalances and uncertainties. On one hand, philosophy of science had progressed greatly, and
has posted substantial achievements in some aspects, above all methodological matters; on the
other hand, there is still a great scarcity of adequately profound and rigorous philosophical
approaches with regard to these matters.43
Philosophy carries out its endeavor in continuity with ordinary human knowledge. It
makes use of the same means: it begins from sense experience, through which it obtains abstract
universal knowledge with the use of the intellect. It advances in knowledge by making use of
inferences whose significance is ultimately determined by sensible or intellectual evidence.
There is no faculty or power of knowing that gives rise to a type of knowledge that is distinctly
philosophical.
But this does not mean that philosophy should uncritically accept all opinions usually attributed
to common sense. These opinions can contain some error; philosophical reflection should thus
be applied to the study of their basis and validity.
Just as there is no infallible instinct for common sense, there is no intuition proper to
philosophy. In both instances, we use our intellect and we reason by means of it, relying on
knowledge supplied by the senses. There are no special faculties of human nature for certain
types of knowledge. Every human knowledge is attained through our senses and our intellect.
Hence it is not correct to say that philosophy is a task exclusively meant for people who
posses some special capacity for knowing. Philosophy makes use in a systematic way all the
means available to human knowledge.
These statements make us see the relationship affecting ordinary knowledge the science and
philosophy. In these three cases, the worth of knowledge is measured by the same standard the
correct use of sense knowledge and intellectual reasoning, according to the rules studied in logic.
Naturaleza
y
alcance
del
metodo
cientifico,
Gredos,
Nadrid,
1961,
and
J.J.
SANGUINETTI,
Logica,
EUNSA,
Pampliona,
1982
(cuarta
parte:
El
conocimiento
cientifico).
For
an
extensive
historical
and
critical
analysis,
accompanied
by
abundant
references,
see
S.L.
JAKI,
The
Road
of
Science
and
the
Ways
of
God,
University
of
Chicago
Press,
Chicago,
1978.
21
Particular sciences study in a greater details some specific aspect of reality, making used of
experimentation and diverse logical processes (such as the hypothetical-deductive method) in an
orderly and systematic manner. In doing so, they obtain conclusions that are beyond the reach of
ordinary knowledge.
Philosophy studies reality by seeking its ultimate cause. For this, it base itself on ordinary and
scientific knowledge, examining the decree of certainty that they attain in each particular case.
Besides, in its in references, it makes used the power of reason, in accordance with the rules of
logic valid for all types of human knowledge.
Philosophy studies reality by seeking its ultimate causes. For this, it bases itself on ordinary and
scientific knowledge, examining the degree of certainty that they attain in each particular case.
Besides, in its inferences, it makes use of the power of reason, in accordance with the rules of
logic valid for all types of human knowledge44.
44
(The
Method
of
Philosophy)
everything
is
taken
from
Mariano
Artigas,
An
Introduction
to
Philosophy.
22
PART II: DIVISIONS OF PHILOSOPHY
1. WHAT METAPHYSICS IS
23
For instance, philosophy of nature studies the being of bodies, and discovers in them a
composition of act and potency which metaphysics studies in a general way, since this
composition exists not only in corporeal beings, but also in spiritual substances.
The subject matter proper to metaphysics includes realities that do not depend on matter
for their being, either because they are spiritual-such as God, or the human soul-or because they
are aspects of reality that can be found in material as well spiritual beings-such as substance and
accidents, act and potency, and causality. When we speak of metaphysics as a philosophical
discipline distinct from other philosophical fields of study, we specifically refer to the study of
these matters.
The study of human soul as a spiritual being pertains to metaphysics, but it is included in
philosophy of nature in so far as the soul is form of the body.
Aspects of reality that are found both in material and spiritual beings are studied from a
specific point of view by philosophy of nature, and then in a general way and in depth by
metaphysics. Philosophy of natures studies them in so far as they are found in material beings.
This does not mean that the rest of the philosophical disciplines are a mere application of
metaphysics in the study of specific types of beings. Metaphysics, in its study in the being of
things in a general way, discovers law of being which are universally valid for all reality (the
so-called first principles), obtains conclusions applicable to all beings (although they apply to
them in varying ways and degrees), studies in a direct manner the spiritual beings which bear a
reference to being in all its aspects, due to their intellect and will, and ultimate reaches, God as
the First Cause of the beings of all things. The order philosophical disciplines coincide with
metaphysics in their search for ultimate cause of reality. However, they limit their study to some
type of being, for instance, bodies, as well as living things. Thus, they do not arrive at the
universal conclusions reached by metaphysics. Neither they do tackle strictly metaphysical
topics, even though they provide the foundation for many metaphysical considerations and
discover general laws applied to the scope of beings that they study.
24
3. METAPHYSICS, THE SCIENCE OF BEING AS SUCH
Particular sciences study different sectors of reality (such in the case of geology,
astronomy, botany, and other sciences), or certain aspects common to various sectors (such in the
case of mathematics, physics, and other related sciences). In contrast, metaphysics seeks the
ultimate and most radical component of reality. The most fundamental characteristic of all things
is the fact that they are, since without the perfection of being, they would not anything at all.
Now, what does being mean? What makes things to be? What the principal manners or ways
of being? These are some of the questions that, in one way or another, all philosophers have
asked through the centuries. They constitute the object of metaphysics.
Plato left behind metaphysical considerations, but it was his disciple, Aristotle, who
passed on to posterity a systematic and substantially valid study of the nature of metaphysics,
substance accidents, essence, act and potency, causes, and other metaphysical topics.
Aristotles fourteen books of First Philosophy are still required reference material in
metaphysics. St. Thomas Aquinas assimilated his idea in a superior synthesis, in the life of the
doctrine of the act of being (esse or actus essendi). According to this doctrine, the essence or
basic manner of being, limits the act of being of each thing. This act of being is received from
the Being that subsist by itself (God). Thus, the act of being, the ultimate component of every
thing, becomes the central point of metaphysics, since it is the principle that allows us to
understand all things in terms of their structure, their perfection, their activity, and their
finiteness and dependence on God as the First Cause of their being45.
The human beings cannot remain satisfied with an evermore detailed and complete
description of reality by the particular sciences, because they leave inevitable questions
unanswered. Why does the universe exist? What is it meaning and purpose? Is there a First
Cause? All these questions revolve around the nucleus, which is the being of things. For this
reason, metaphysics can be defined as the science, which studies not just any type of beings but
rather the being, as such, of all things.
Hence, metaphysics is the most universal science, since all reality is its object of study.
For everything is real in so far as it is, that is, in so far as it has being. Above all,
metaphysics is the most fundamental science, since it considers the most basic or most radical
45
Cf.
T.
ALVIRA,
L.
CLAVELL,
AND
T.
MELENDO,
Metafisica,
EUNSA,
Pamplona,
1982,
pp.
116-117.
25
perfection-being itself. In comparison to it, all other perfections are nothing else but particular
ways or manners of being.
For instance, the essence is the fundamental mode or manner of being of a thing (of a
man, or a plant, or iron). Any accident (like size, color, or being in a place) is a non-essential
mode of being. A thing has some specific actual perfections (such and such a thing is in act) and
it may also have other perfection in potency (it may become, that is, come to be what presently it
is not). That is why St. Thomas Aquinas affirms that the act of being is the most perfect of all,
since it play the roe in act with respect to all things. Indeed, a thing possesses a certain actuality
only in so far as it is. Hence, being is the actuality of all things and of all forms46.
If the term being (ens) is used to refer to everything that is, metaphysics is the
science of being as being, or of being as such. In contrast, particular sciences deal only with
some specific type of beings. Besides, they study their objects not in the light of their being, but
in so far as they possess some specific ways of being.
4. PARTS OF METAPHYSICS
Summing up what has been previously explained, we can say that metaphysics studies
reality in its deepest aspect, that is by looking at its being closely. This study leads to the
knowledge of the properties of being as such, the basic modes of being, the structure of limited
beings, the First Cause of being, and the relations of being with the powers of knowing or
possessing it.
In practice, the different aspects mentioned are usually the topics of various disciplines, which
are like parts of metaphysics.
a.) General Metaphysics. It deals with being as being and the modes and structure of being
of things.
For instance, metaphysics studies the basic aspects of the being of things, that is, the act of
being and the essence; the general modes of being, that is the substance and the
accidents; the composition of act and potency found in all limited beings; the structure of
corporeal substances, composed of matter and form; causality, that is, the influence exerted
by some things on the being of other things.
As we have earlier seen, some of these topics are studied in a particular way in philosophy of
nature, and then in a general way in metaphysics. Thus, a complete view of problems can only be
obtained by putting together both approaches that is by studying them in the light of
metaphysics. This is a consequence of the nature of philosophical knowledge, which considers
reality in a global manner-it studies its real being in an absolute manner, not only in its partial
aspects. That is why metaphysics is intertwined with the other branches of philosophy, which are
mutually dependent disciplines.
46ST.
THOMAS
AQUINAS,
S.Th.
I,
q.4,
a.1,
ad
3.
26
Metaphysics also studies being insofar as it relates to knowledge (truth), to the will
(goodness), and to the aesthetic sense (beauty).
Truth and goodness, together with unity and being something (aliquid), are properties of
being as such, and are therefore found in everything. By virtue of the being that everything has, it
is something; it has an internal unity; it is called true insofar as it can be the object of
knowledge; it has a certain specific perfections that make it desirable, hence good; and it is
beautiful insofar as considering it is pleasurable.
These perfections are called transcendental properties of being, precisely to indicate that they
are found in everything (though in different degrees, according to each things perfection). They
are thus distinguished from those perfections that are found only in such specific types of beings.
The name indicates that they transcend the specific ways of being, since they extend to all
beings.
These properties are found in God in an imminent way, since God is his own Being. God is
the Truth and the source of all created truth. He is Goodness itself, and is the cause of all
participated good. His Being is supremely One, since in him there is no composition whatsoever.
b.) Natural Theology. This branch of philosophy studies God as Subsistent being and First
cause of all things.
Starting from the being of limited beings, we arrive at the knowledge of God, the infinite
fullness of being, and the First Cause of the being of creatures.
Human reason can get to know Gods existence and his attributes (like infinity and
omnipotence), and acknowledge him as the ultimate purpose or end of man. This knowledge,
which can be attained by anyone, is rigorously examined by metaphysics. Starting from the being
of things as it is grasped through experience, the human reaches God as the being that subsist
itself, and the cause of the being of things. Hence, metaphysics is also called theology or study
of God. It is natural theology and thus different from supernatural theology which starts
from supernatural divine revelation.
c.) Gnoseology. It is a reflexive study of the scope of metaphysical knowledge itself and its
relation to being.
Thus, gnoseology studies how being arises in knowledge, focusing its attention on truth: it
evaluates sense and intellectual knowledge, the different degrees of certainty, and other matters.
For this, it has to rely on philosophical psychology, which deals with the knowing process.
27
In a way, gnoseology passes judgment of the validity of metaphysics, since it examines the
foundation of knowledge. Actually, metaphysics itself, as the primary and universal science,
passes judgment on its own foundations. That is why gnoseology is a part of metaphysics, not a
science distinct and previous to it. It cannot be otherwise, since metaphysics is the most basic
science and without it, all philosophy would lack the necessary foundation.
Since Descartes time, problems of gnoseology have hugged the limelight in modern
philosophy. This turn of events is usually accompanied by an erroneous attitude. Some
philosophers-Descartes in some way, Kant in a rather explicit manner, and many after them-
viewed the critique of knowledge as a study that has to be carried out before going to any
philosophical inquiry. But since that the study requires metaphysical considerations, leaving the
latter aside inevitably leads to distorting metaphysics or ruling out its possibility47.
Thomistic authors of our time have also been greatly preoccupied with these gnoseological
problems. Some of them think that the so-called critical problem (a term derived from the
critique of knowledge) is a solid feature of modern philosophy, and they have been trying to
make the metaphysics of being compatible with Cartesian or Kantian approaches 48 . This
endeavor has proven to be extremely problematic, since from the start, those philosophical
approaches are characterized by a perspective that is hardly compatible with the metaphysics of
being.
When we speak of philosophy of nature, the term nature can take on two meanings:
a) First, the term may refer to nature itself, that is, the sum of total corporeal beings. In this
sense, philosophy of nature is the philosophical study of corporeal or material beings.
b) Second, the term may refer to natural beings, as distinct from artificial ones. A natural
being is that which possesses an internal principle of its being and activity, while an artificial
being is one which is man-made structure, produced through the use of natural beings.
47
See
C.
CADORNA,
Metafisica
de
la
opcion
intellectual,
op.,
cit.
48
One
of
the
most
influential
attempts
was
launched
by
J.
MARECHAL
(cf.
El
punto
de
partida
de
la
Metafisica,
Gredos,
Madrid,
1957),
who
tried
to
make
Kantian
principles
compatible
with
the
metaphysics
of
being.
28
The human beings, as corporeal being, is an object of study of philosophy of nature,
notwithstanding the fact that the spiritual soul is an object of study of metaphysics and
philosophical psychology.
Other living beings are also the object of study of philosophy of nature, since they are also
corporeal beings. Nevertheless, because of their particular characteristics, they are oftentimes
study in philosophical psychology.
For the sake of order and clarity, the following criterion will be applied in this study: the
term philosophy of nature will refer to the study of material beings-hence, to inanimate beings,
and also to living beings, taking into account those aspects they have in common with inanimate
matter. In the next chapter, we shall take up the philosophy of living beings, which includes of
the study of the particular characteristics of living beings, and of human being.
The material object of philosophy of nature is the sum total of material natural beings.
These begins are also studied by the experimental sciences, but in the light of their proximate or
immediate causes, such as the laws that govern the movement or reaction of bodies, and the
chemical structure of material substances. Using a metaphysical perspective, philosophy of
nature studies their being, seeking their deepest causes. Thus, the formal object of philosophy of
nature is the being of corporeal things.
Following Aristotle, St. Thomas Aquinas affirmed that the object of philosophy of nature is
the changeable being. Indeed, the natural corporeal being is characterized by its capacity for
change: matter is always in potency to acquire new forms.
One might think that philosophy of nature, with the help of the experimental sciences,
seeks to come out with models of reality, such as theories about the structure of matter and the
universe, physical properties, and the like. Nevertheless, it is more correct to say that this task
properly belongs to the experimental sciences.
29
These types of studies require taking into account not only the results obtained from
science, but also the knowledge of methodology needed in order to interpret these results
properly. Philosophy of nature does not directly intervene in these matters; however, it is
extremely useful in detecting erroneous interpretations and in fitting scientific results within a
proper context.
For instance, if one seeks to know what the basic particles of physics are, philosophy
will allow him to realized that what is substantial does not necessarily have to be imaginable; it
will also provide him the adequate concepts of substance and accidents, which are needed in
order to come up with a reasonable answer. What is really important is to have a correct
interpretation of the results and methods of atomic physics.
At times, philosophy helps in the elaboration of scientific hypotheses and in the correct
interpretation of the results obtained by the experimental sciences. But it would be an error to
reduce philosophy of nature to these heuristic and methodological functions, since its principal
and direct objective is the metaphysical study of the characteristics of natural beings. In many
cases, this objective can be achieve with sufficient certainty by having recourse to ordinary
experience alone; however, in some more specialized questions, the results obtained by the
experimental sciences must be taken into account, and the degree of certainty attained will
depend on the validity of such findings.
In philosophy of nature, we can find three kinds of considerations, according to the degree
of certainty that can be attained.
a) First, there are certain philosophical conclusions, based on certain knowledge supplied
by ordinary experience or by the experimental sciences.
This is the case, for instance, of hylemorphism, which affirms that every material substance
is essentially composed of prime matter-a potential substratum capable of being actualized in
various ways-and substantial form-the actual element that determines the mode of being of the
substance. Other examples are many statements about the nature and properties of the accidents
of the corporeal substance, such as quantity and quality.
b) Second, there are hypothetical considerations, based on less certain findings of science,
they depend partly on the level of scientific knowledge during a specific period of time; hence,
they need to be revised once new findings become available.
30
These considerations are oftentimes lumped together with some certain conclusions. Thus,
it is important to realize that their lack of permanent validity does not necessarily affect other
aspects of the philosophy of a necessarily affect other aspects of the philosophy of a specific
author. For instance, in the works of Aristotle of St, Thomas Aquinas, one finds some notions
dependent on theories about the world, which are now pass. Nevertheless, that does not in any
way invalidate their principal doctrines, based on certain data supplied by experience, or on
findings that science has later confirmed with even greater certainty.
c) There are also hypothesis about nature that can serve as guide for scientific inquiry. In
some cases, they may latter on be confirmed by science, and frequently prove to be useful for its
progress.
For example, the philosophical atomism of the ancient philosophers was a false doctrine,
which presupposed indivisible atoms and accepted mechanism. Nevertheless, it was helpful in
the nineteenth century in the formulation of the early atomic theories in chemistry, which in turn
to be greatly modified.
This auxiliary function in the service in the service of science is of little importance to
philosophy of nature itself.
Obviously, those considerations belonging to the first category are the most important for
philosophy of nature, even though it must also devote some attention to more hypothetical
matters, delimiting in each case its degree of certainty.
We have previously examined the relationship between philosophy and the particular
sciences. We shall now limit ourselves to some specific observations regarding philosophy of
nature.
a) In general, the experimental sciences need philosophy of nature so as not to reduce all
reality to those aspects that they perceive according to their method. Philosophy of nature
enables one to fit the results obtained by these sciences in context of the most profound
philosophical knowledge, thus avoiding the danger of various forms of reductionism.
Given the prestige enjoyed by science and the extensive coverage of the mass media,
reductionist doctrines, presented as scientific conclusions, or at least, as findings enjoying the
trustworthiness of the scientific method, reach a vast audience nowadays. This fact highlights the
31
importance of fitting scientific knowledge within a global context, for which philosophical
considerations are directly needed.
b) No matter how much the experimental sciences, using their own method, extend their
field of investigation, they cannot truly supplant philosophy of nature. Philosophy requires a
perspective different from that of the sciences.
c) In order to use scientific knowledge correctly, one needs an ethical foundation, which
cannot be derived from the experimental-scientific method, but from metaphysics, which relies
on philosophy of nature. Without this foundation, scientific knowledge can be used against the
real welfare of man. The experimental sciences provide us with knowledge and enable us to
produce instruments, but the ethical question regarding the purposes for which these should be
used falls beyond their scope.
The problems in these fields are getting to be more and more serious. One simply has to
think about atomic energy and forms of genetic manipulation, for instance, to realize the fact.
These problems require a proper perspective of science and of man, based in turn on philosophy
of nature. Science must be placed in the service of man, and used in accordance with ethical
norms.
In the world of natural beings, those beings endowed with life occupy a prominent place.
They are characterized by a distinctive power of self-motion: by their very nature, they can
assimilate external substances and transform them into their own substance; they experience
growth in various ways while maintaining their individual unity; they possess a diversified
32
capacity of self-regulation; and by their reproductive power, they give rise to other individuals of
the same species.
Because of these characteristics, as well as the fact that among living beings one can find
man in his rational and corporeal nature, the philosophy of living beings has always been a
specific object of study since ancient times.
The study of life in its varying degrees-vegetative, sensitive and rational-and of the soul as
the substantial form of living beings, gives rise to questions that require particular attention.
We can cite as examples, among many others, the following topics: the objective purpose
or end, which appears with special clarity in living beings, although it can already be perceived
even in inanimate nature1; the sense knowledge of animals, which are frequently used to promote
ideologies that distort scientific data and conclusions2.
As we have already seen, even though the philosophy of living beings forms part of the
philosophy of nature, it is highly preferable to make it the object of study of a specific discipline.
Hence, we will limit ourselves to saying that the observations and affirmations we have
considered in the section on philosophy of nature also apply to the philosophy of living beings.
The distinctive characteristic of the philosophy of living beings stems from the fact that living
beings comprise its material object.
Thus, it has usually been called psychology (or treatise on the soul as principle of life).
There is nothing wrong in the continued use of that term. The term philosophical psychology is
oftentimes used in order to distinguish it from experimental psychology. Psychology is also
used many times to designate the study of man, which is also called philosophical anthropology.
Obviously, the conclusions reached by the philosophy of inanimate nature will also be
applied to living beings, taking into account the particular characteristics derived from their
special condition.
1
Cf.
ST.
THOMAS
AQUINAS,
In
Phys.,
II,
13
(259).
2
This
happens
in
the
case
of
materialist
ideologies
which
have
nothing
to
do
with
true
science,
as
well
as
in
socio-biology
of
aristocratic
and
racist
tendencies.
33
Aside form those characteristics common to inanimate bodies, as well as those common to
living beings endowed with vegetative and sense life, man also possesses the traits of a rational
being, enabling him to rise beyond the level of purely corporeal beings.
The philosophy of man studies the strictly human operations of man, that is, act of
intellectual knowledge and free will. Through them, it demonstrates that the human soul is
spiritual, since it is the root of operations that transcends the scope and possibilities of matter.
The human soul is the substantial form of man, who in turn is a single substance in which
the spiritual material constitute a single being (nevertheless, since the human soul is spiritual, it
subsist even after death; besides, it has to be created directly by God). Hence, the study of man
requires taking to account what is proper to corporeal beings and to lower living beings.
Thus, the object of the philosophy of man is partly common to the philosophy of nature,
and partly common to metaphysics. It understandably provides a great deal of indispensible
knowledge for the study of ethics. Besides, it serves as basis to natural theology, since what we
are able to know about God through reason is necessarily dependent on our knowledge of the
human spirit-through analogy, we can know some characteristics of the divine Being which is
purely spiritual.
The experimental sciences study man in his material dimension, as a corporeal being. Even
though they cannot properly focus their attention on the human soul, as a consequence of their
methodology, they nonetheless provide significant facts that are extremely useful in obtaining a
deeper knowledge of some aspects of human activities.
For instance, recent advances in neurobiology are important in order to understand the
process involved in understanding, in human emotions, and in the field of human behavior.
Although the brain is not properly speaking the organ of the mind or of the will-which are
spiritual powers-it is one of the physiological bases of their operations.
Advances in human biology at times give rise to reductionist views with extrapolate
scientific findings beyond the real of possibility, and which ignore facts that lead to acknowledge
the spirituality of the human soul.
There have been many attempts to reduce man to something purely material. They
originated in ancient times, but they now want to find an ally in the sciences.
34
A seemingly more acceptable but still contradictory position is that taken by proponents of
emergent evolution. Advocates of this doctrine state that there are aspects in man that cannot be
explained by materialism. But since they deny the existence of the spirit, or at least want to
maintain a scientific neutrality with regard of the human soul, they affirm that is strictly human
has emerged from mater in the course of evolution. But this emergence is merely a name
used to designate some impossible change.
There have also been attempts to explain the nature of human intelligence through analogy
with artificial minds allegedly capable of performing some activities just as well as, or even
better than, any man. But again, we have to point out that what is proper to man cannot be reduce
to artifact. To grasp this point, it would be enough for us to realize that mans link with truth and
evidence, for instance, implies a capacity that goes beyond what is purely material.
The human science study man under different aspects through sociological, psychological,
or historical methods, which have their own validity and significance. But in order to have right
orientation, they need rarely a philosophy of man. They must have a correct metaphysical
foundation.
For instance, sociology and history have to accept, as a basic fact, the existence of human
freedom, which is studied by the philosophy of man. Otherwise, false conclusions will be
presented as scientific ones, since there are no really determinist sociological or historical laws.
Non-philosophical psychology must rely, too, on the metaphysical view of man. Of course,
this does not mean that its conclusions will simply be derived from philosophy. Similarly,
sociology needs a metaphysical foundation, and it has to rely on ethics (which, in turn,, is based
on metaphysics) so as to not to reduce human behavior to external factors which cannot account
for objective ethical norms.
The human sciences have particular characteristics that differentiate the from the
experimental sciences of nature, since in their object of study (man), freedom is found. Although
they can employ, in part, the experimental method (with respect to the more material aspects of
human behavior), they have to rely on the philosophy of man. When the sciences are presented
as ideologically neutral, people can be deceitfully led into accepting, as something scientific,
an implicit philosophy whose validity has not yet been clearly proven.
35
We have so far considered the branches of theoretical or speculative philosophy, which
seeks to know reality as such. In contrast, ethics is a practical science, since it studies how
human acts are directed towards mans purpose or end. It does not stop in contemplation of truth,
but applies that learning to human acts, providing the necessary knowledge so that man may act
in a morally upright way.
Ethics is a practical science, but not in the technical sense. Rather, it is a practical
science because it deals with human acts in so far as they are voluntary, and because it is part of
philosophy, which studies the ultimate explanation of the ends and means concerning human
existence.
Directing voluntary actions towards their end pertains to moral philosophy. The ordering
task carried out by reason with reference to external things produced through human reason,
pertains to mechanical arts. Hence, the study of human acts in so far as they are ordered among
themselves and towards the end is an activity proper to moral philosophy.
Ethics is the most important practical science, since it studies the last end of man, which
ensures his happiness, as well as the means to attain it.
Indeed, we hear people say that philosophy has no practical use. We should not forget,
however, that when things are considered in a comprehensive way, ethics appears as the most
useful rational knowledge for man, since it leads him towards his ultimate end, whose
possessions constitutes his happiness.
Ethics studies human acts from a moral perspective, that is in so far as they are morally
good or bad. This is known by taking into account the last end of man: whatever leads him to his
real end is good, and whatever deviates him from the end is bad. The study of the last end of
man, which is God, and of the morality of the human acts, is proper to ethics. Hence, it studies
the natural moral law, its application through the conscience, the factors that exert their influence
on the morality of human acts, the moral habits (virtues and vices), and the application of general
moral principles to specific problems, as well as to specific questions derived from mans social
nature.
Human acts comprise the material object of ethics. These are voluntary acts, which
proceed from the free will. Since they depend on man and do not arise in a necessary manner,
they entail moral responsibility.
36
The relation of human acts to mans last end is the formal object of ethics. Hence, ethics is
based on metaphysics; the latter studies God as First Cause and Ultimate End of all creation, and
particularly, of man.
Moral philosophy or ethics deals with human acts which proceed from
mans will according to the dictates of reason. Acts performed by an individual,
which are not subject to his will and reason, are not called strictly human acts but
rather natural acts. This is the case of the acts of the vegetative soul, which do not
fall within the scope of moral philosophy. As the object of study of the
philosophy of nature is change, or the changeable being, analogously, the object
of study of moral philosophy is the human act directed towards its end, or man in
so far as he acts willfully in view of an end.
3. PARTS OF ETHICS
Although ethics is one single science, for practical purposes, it is usually divided into two
parts.
a) One part is general ethics, which studies the basic principles regarding the morality of
human acts. It deals with the last end of man, the moral law, conscience, sin, and virtues
Hence, with regard to the last end, general ethics proves that it can only be
God, both in the objective sense (as that end whose possession one has to seek)
and in the subjective one (mans happiness). It establishes that the morality of
human acts refers to their conformity with the ultimate end, and that it is
determined by taking into account their object, their end, and their circumstances.
It considers the moral law as the objective norm of morality, and studies the kinds
of moral laws and their characteristics, such as the objective and universal nature
of the natural moral law. It analyzes the nature of conscience, its binding
character and the principles that must govern an upright moral conduct. It studies
the nature of moral habits (virtues and vices) and their relation with morality.
b) The second part is social ethics. It applies the preciously mentioned principles to the
life of man as member of society.
Among the various topics its studies are: the common good of society; the
relation between individuals and society; the role of social authority; the binding
character and morality of civil laws; the principle of subsidiarity, which obliges
authorities to respect and foster what individuals and intermediate groups are
capable of doing, and intervene in matters where its direct activity is required; the
nature, role and fundamental rights of the family as the basic cell of society; the
ends of purposes of marriage and the obstacles that hinder their fulfillment.
37
4. ETHICS AND METAPHYSICS
Ethics finds its foundation in metaphysics. In order to determine the conformity of human
acts to mans end, one has to consider basic truths about God, creation, the spiritual nature of
man and his freedom, and these are topics studied by metaphysics. Without this necessary
foundation, one cannot get to know the moral order that ought to be observed, and ethics would
be emptied of any real content.
Ethics begin its scientific study by acquiring a valid notion of the good, and this requires
a directly metaphysical perspective. If one does not perceive the good as an objective aspect of
reality, he will inevitably turn to subjective motives, which can never vouch for the objective
moral order that can and should be observed.
There have been modern attempts to construct ethical system on
inadequate foundations. Kant, for instance, tried to do so, In his work, Critique for
Pure Reason, he denied the possibility of knowing God through human reason,
and his Critique of Practical Reason, he drew up a moral system based on dictates
of conscience without any objective basis. Max Scheler affirmed the objective
reality of values and the spirituality of human person, but he places these valid
aspects within an inadequate metaphysical framework. Marxism rejected the
metaphysical foundation necessary to make ethics meaningful.
These and other varied attempts to elaborate an ethical system without
God may at times contain some partial truths. However, they will necessarily lack
an adequate foundation, for they cannot account for the genuine meaning of
human life.
Ethics has close links with psychology (understood as philosophy of man), which in turn,
as we have previously seen, pertains in some way to metaphysics.
Ethics is a science distinct from psychology. Although psychology also studies human
acts, it nonetheless considers them as such, specifying their nature and characteristics. Ethics, on
the other hand, considers them in the light of their morality, which is a different perspective. Of
course, in its study of numerous topics, ethics will make use of the knowledge supplied by
psychology as a starting point. From there, it will move on to questions of morality.
For instance, ethics has to rely on the studies of the philosophy of man
about the spirituality of the human soul, intellectual and sense knowledge, the will
and human freedom.
38
CHAPTER FIVE: LOGIC
1. WHAT LOGIC IS
Man gets to know reality in a partial, step-by-step manner. He proceeds from what is
sensible to what is intelligible, from some aspects of reality to others by way of reasoning. His
knowledge does not encompass reality all at once and in a complete way.
Reasoning would not be necessary if we had a perfect, once-and-for-all
knowledge of reality. However, the limits of our knowledge demand the use of
reasoning, so that with the use of our mind and starting from some previously
acquired knowledge, we can attain further knowledge.
Hence, through induction, we obtain universal knowledge by considering
some particular cases. For instance, from the repeated experience of seeing bodies
fall towards the ground, we induce that this is common to al bodies. Through
deduction we proceed from universal knowledge to individual cases. For
instances, if we know that all bodies tend to fall, we deduce that when we throw a
specific body upward, it will fall to the ground.
Logic studies the laws that apply to different types of reasoning, that is,
the conditions that must be met to make them valid.
Logic studies our mental processes, to make sure that they are correct and that they lead
to the truth. Logic is distinct from psychology. Psychology studies the acts of human reasons in
themselves, as characteristics of man, and seeks to define their nature. It considers human acts as
part of reality. In contrast, logic deals with intellectual processes in so far as they relate some
knowledge with others, or with the reality they signify.
For instance, psychology studies the nature of the intellect and its
operations: its immateriality, its capacity to know, and so on. Logic deals with the
products of intellectual activity, such as concepts, propositions, syllogisms, and
specifies the conditions that must be met so that they can be correctly used.
Obviously, logic relies on the knowledge supplied by psychology as well
as by gnoseology, regarding the nature of knowledge and of truth. However, it
adopts its own perspective, focusing its study on the conditions that must be met
for a valid reasoning process.
There is spontaneous logic which every human being possesses in varying degrees of
mastery, through which an individual reasons out correctly. But if we want to make sure that our
39
processes of knowing are correct, we need to study the science of logic or scientific logic, and
examine explicitly and systematically the norms of validity applicable to intellectual knowledge.
Logic deals with beings of reason, which exist only in the mind. Specifically, it studies
the relations the mind establishes among different products or contents of intellectual knowledge.
If we take the preceding observations into account, we will realize that logic is different
from metaphysics. The latter always deals with real beings that exist outside the knower; at the
same time, it is distinct from all the other sciences that deal with real beings. Nevertheless, logic
has its foundation in metaphysics, for the relations that mind establishes among the products of
intellectual knowledge ought to reflect the order existing in reality; otherwise, the mental
processes will be incorrect and will not lead to the truth. Logic is not an absolutely autonomous
science. It cannot be totally isolated from metaphysics.
Obviously, one can devise different logical rules and systems and in fact,
this is being done for there is a wide variety of possibilities that can exist in the
40
human mind. However, the basic principles of logic are not arbitrary. In so far as
knowledge is directed to reality, it is subject to metaphysical laws. Thus, for
instance, logic must abide by the principle of non-contradiction, which states that
something cannot be and not be at the same time and in the same respect;
otherwise, one falls into an absurd or meaningless chatter, as what happens with
Marxist-leaning philosophies based on the reality of contradiction.
Logic is applicable to all human knowledge, whether ordinary or scientific. The study of
logic is part of philosophy. Although logic does not study reality directly, it seeks to know the
conditions for valid knowledge; hence, it is an instrument that in a general way affects all
rational knowledge of reality.
Logic is philosophical because the very acts of reason, whose laws the
science seeks to establish, constitute its object of study. Hence, logic has a
directing role with regard to all other types of knowledge, and shows how the
mind has to proceed in an orderly and error-free manner. It has a universal scope,
just like metaphysics. Just as metaphysics deals with everything that is real, so
too, logic deals with everything in so far as it can be the object of rational inquiry.
In so far as it deals only with beings of reason, logic can be more
fittingly considered as an introductory and necessary science with respect to
philosophy and the other sciences (rather than a philosophical science itself).
Nevertheless, it is quite difficult to obtain all knowledge by explicitly observing the rules
of logic. It may not always be possible and recommendable, besides, to maintain this procedure.
In practice, in the case of both ordinary and scientific knowledge, we direct our attention first
towards reality, and only afterwards, at a later moment, do we turn to logical structures,
especially when we discover some errors or entertain some doubts.
Logical systematization is a means, not an end in itself. Creating artificial
languages: which explicitly show a strictly logical rigor gives rise to important
observations. Nevertheless, it will spawn tremendous complications when applied
to ordinary language, whether scientific or philosophical.
41
There have been attempts in the past to limit the role of philosophy exclusively or
principally to the study of logic. A relatively recent one is the so-called neo-positivism also
known as logical empiricism 0 of the Vienna Circle. Proponents of this error state that the sole
objective philosophy can have is to establish logical clarity in the meaning of language. Among
the many shortcomings of this doctrine is its self-contradictory position, since its principal thesis
about the role of philosophy does not arise from the logical analysis of language.
4. PARTS OF LOGIC
The object of study of logic is human knowledge in so far as it represents reality. We can
distinguish three basic operations in our process of knowing: 1) simple apprehension, which is
the first and most basic operation of the mind; its end result is the concept, such as the concept
man, or dog; 2) the operation of judging, through which we put concepts together its end
result is called judgment or proposition, such as Man laughs.; 3) the operation called
reasoning by which the mind combines several judgments or propositions in order to arrive at a
previously unknown judgment; its end result is called syllogism, such as He who breathes is
alive; Peter breathes; therefore he is alive. Hence, there are three general parts of logic: logic of
concepts, logic of judgment or of the proposition and logic of reasoning or of the syllogism.
There is another part usually considered as the fourth part of logic. It is called epistemology or
the philosophy of science, which deals with the process of knowing on the scientific level; it
focuses on methodology, principles of the sciences, the branches of scientific knowledge, and
other related themes.
42
CHAPTER SIX: HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
Histories of particular sciences usually occupy a place of least importance in the study of
these respective fields of knowledge. This is true, above all, in the experimental sciences, which
focus their attention on scientific results obtained. In the human sciences, the historical view of
the problems and solutions is of greater interest, since many doctrines and viewpoints are better
understood in the light of historical circumstances. The same thing is true, but to much greater
extent, in the field of philosophy.
The search for truth becomes a complex task when one confronts issues in depth, which
is the case in philosophy. That is why the study and discussion of viewpoints presented by other
philosophers in the past is a characteristic common to the most profound philosophers. It is a
guarantee, too, of great proximity to the truth.
Aristotle for instance, employed this method in trying to resolve philosophical issues, and
he would lament the lack of adequate treatment on some matters on the part of early
philosophers. St. Thomas Aquinas showed a striking example of love for truth, regardless of who
said it; thus he studied all kinds of opinions and tried to make use of them as much as possible.
History of philosophy is significant mainly because it facilitates our access to the truth; it
informs us about what others in the past have said regarding issues similar to contemporary ones
we now have to confront. The originality of some people seem to seek even if they may have to
resort to arbitrary simplifications, goes against a sincere quest for truth.
43
One of the greatest threats in our time is relativism, a philosophical doctrine, which
rejects the perennial significance of any human knowledge. Some people show their adherence
tot his doctrine at times by saying that even the doctrines considered as most certain in history
have finally been shown to be partial or erroneous. By alleging that philosophers affirmations
and philosophical doctrines contained some errors, they mistakenly do away with all certainty.
They adopt a supposedly objective stand, vainly seeking a basis of certainty, so that they could
keep on referring to objectivity and truth.
For a profound philosophical knowledge, they study of the great philosophers, who have
raised particularly profound issues, is of great importance. This should not simply be a quest for
erudite learning, or a purely historical knowledge; rather, it should be a help in order to attain
knowledge of truth. This study must be accompanied by a critical evaluation. Otherwise, one will
not be able to distinguish the valid contributions from the errors committed, and he will hardly
get away from skepticism as he considers the wide variety of views and solutions concerning
specific philosophical problems. It should therefore be a study that allows one to grasp and
evaluate the various ways philosophical issues have been drawn up, and the divergent ways of
resolving them, proposed throughout history.
They somehow transcend their respective historical eras, and they exert a
real influence on the development of human thought and therefore on the march
of history. Hence, familiarity with the more influential philosophers in the past is
always of current relevance. These are no necessary laws of history and the turn
of history greatly depends on the ideas of the most outstanding thinkers.
The study of history allows us to realize that different philosophical doctrines revolve
around some basic questions. Besides, the proposed solutions to such problems can ultimately be
reduced in turn to various basic lines of thought that have drawn up all throughout history, and
which are closely linked with all the possible attitudes before crucial problems of human
existence. We can also frequently trace the origin of some philosophical positions to reactions
against the excesses of opposed doctrines. All these enable us to counteract the perplexity that
44
may confront us as we survey the great variety of doctrines in the history of philosophy, and to
avoid relativist and skeptical conclusions.
3. PROGRESS IN PHILOSOPHY
The foregoing considerations allow us to finally give a reply to a question: Can there be
real progress in philosophy?
We cannot speak of progress in philosophy in the same way we acknowledge advances in
the sciences or technical studies that facilitate human dominion over nature. Progress in
philosophy does not depend on the appearance of new doctrines, but on achieving greater
proximity to the truth. This can happen in any historical period.
Philosophy will always confront new problems and data that did not
appear in the past. It will simply have to study them and take them into account.
With respect to basic issues, however, it could happen that the most valid
approach up to the present had been drawn up long ago, perhaps even centuries
ago, even though it may need updating in some minor details.
The study of the ancient Greek thinkers, for instance, has always been
greatly significant, for they were the ones who raised many of the important
philosophical issues, and came up with the main possible solutions.
45
Progress in philosophy is neither linear nor cumulative. There have been
advances, retrogressions and highly remarkable solutions that have not been
surpassed up to the present.
The study of history of philosophy is usually divided into four main periods:
A) Ancient philosophy, which covers the period starting from the early Greek philosophers,
and extending up to the Middle Ages. The ancient Greek thinks posed the main questions
in philosophy and also drew up the answers to them. These answers would later appear
and re-appear in many variant forms. Plato and Aristotle were the towering figures of this
period.
Aristotle worked out a remarkable synthesis of the questions studied by
his predecessors, such as the pre-Socratics, the sophists, Socrates, and Plato. He
systemized answers, which, in great part, enjoy perennial significance.
Undoubtedly, part of his works has been made obsolete by later scientific
discoveries. Nevertheless, even in those aspects, and especially in the strictly
philosophical ones, his works contain the seed completely formed and
endowed with unlimited possibilities of all human wisdom. We can say that up
to Aristotle, philosophy was in stage of embryonic formation. But once formed, it
would henceforth be capable of indefinite future development.
B) Medieval philosophy, which includes all the centuries of the Middle Ages. Outstanding
contributions were made during this period by the Arab philosophers and, above all, by
Christian scholasticism, which closely linked philosophy with theology. Its culminating
achievement lies in the doctrine of St. Thomas Aquinas, who gathered together in an
original synthesis the main contributions of classical philosophy and harmoniously
integrated them into Christian theology.
46
Middle Ages gave rise to philosophical and scientific ideas that some people are
using in order to suppress that period itself. The medieval age was the first to
employ a philosophy free from all authority, even human authority. Thus, that tale
about a renaissance of thought after centuries of slumber, darkness and error, has
to relegate to the realms of legends. Modern philosophy did not have to wage war
in order to acquire the rights of reason against the Middle Ages. The truth is that
the Middle Ages won them for modern philosophy.
C) Modern philosophy, which began with Descartes. Descartes was responsible for the sharp
turn in philosophy that would exert a decisive influence on all philosophers after him. He
was undoubtedly the father of modern philosophy. From his attempt to base all
knowledge on subjective evidence, and to develop it into a system, the rationalism
and empiricism of the 17th and 18th centuries would arise. The unanswered questions that
both systems of thought raised led to the Kantian approach, which in turn would strongly
influence the further development of philosophical thought.
47
The positivism of A. Comte represents a line of thought which, though
imbued with posts-Cartesian influence, concentrates especially on social reform,
based on allegedly scientific considerations. This scientific politics of the
utopian variety also throbs in Marxist philosophy, but it has been elaborated along
different lines. In more recent times, many related tendencies would simply be
varied forms of positivism and Marxism. They will prove prevalent not only in
the arena of contemporary philosophical thought, but also in political circles,
spawning many negative consequences.
-Marxist doctrine, divided into orthodox and heterodox positions, applied to political
reality;
-Analytic philosophy, prevalent in the Anglo-Saxon world, and focusing on linguistic
analysis;
-Philosophy of science, frequently linked with analytic philosophy and usually
conditioned by scientistic and positivist tendencies;
-Phenomenology, as expounded by E. Husserl and his disciples;
-Existentialism, in variant forms, such as those of of Heidegger, Sartre and Jaspers;
-Metaphysics of being, especially along Thomistic lines, viewed from varied perspectives
and expounded by many authors.
But with the increasingly urgent need to find more profound answers to vital
questions, there is also a presently strong current of interest in the study of the classical
philosophers, especially of Aristotle, and a renewal of metaphysical thought, cultivated
by what has been called perennial philosophy. Finding its most profound expression in
the philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, it seeks to defend the permanent and definitive
validity of basic metaphysical doctrines.
48
PART III. MODERN PHILOSOPHERS AND ERRONEOUS PHILOSOPHIES
A. Niccolo Machiavelli
B. Sigmund Freud
C. Karl Marx
D. Jean-Paul Sartre
E. Friedrich Nietzsche
F. Immanuel Kant
We need to talk about "enemies" of the faith because the life of faith is a real war. So say
all the prophets, Apostles, martyrs and our Lord Himself.
Yet, we try to avoid talking about enemies. Why?
Partly because of our fear of confusing spiritual with material enemies; of hating the
sinner along with the sin; of forgetting that "our struggle is not with flesh and blood but with the
principalities, with the powers, with the world rulers of this present darkness, with the evil spirits
in the heavens" (Eph. 6:12).
But that fear is more unfounded today than ever in the past. No age has been more
suspicious of militarism, more terrified of the horrors of physical war, than ours. And no age has
been more prone to confuse the sin with the sinner, not by hating the sinner along with the sin
49
but by loving the sin along with the sinner. We often use "compassion" as an equivalent for
moral relativism.
We're also soft. We don't like to fight because fighting means suffering and sacrifice.
War may not quite be hell, but it's damned uncomfortable. And anyway, we're not sure there's
anything worth fighting for. Perhaps we lack courage because we lack a reason for courage.
This is how we think as moderns, but not as Catholics. As Catholics we know life is
spiritual warfare and that there are spiritual enemies. Once we admit that, the next step follows
inevitably. It is essential in warfare to know your enemy. Otherwise, his spies pass by
undetected. So this series is devoted to knowing our spiritual enemies in the struggle for the
modern heart. We'll discuss six modern thinkers who've had an enormous impact on our
everyday life. They have also done great harm to the Christian mind.
Their names: Machiavelli, the inventor of "the new morality"; Kant, the subjectivizer of
Truth; Nietzsche, the self-proclaimed "Anti-Christ"; Freud, the founder of the "sexual
revolution"; Marx, the false Moses for the masses; and Sartre, the apostle of absurdity.
A. Niccolo Machiavelli
______________________________________________________________
Niccolo Machiavelli (1496-1527) was the founder of modern political and social
philosophy, and seldom in the history of thought has there been a more total revolution.
Machiavelli knew how radical he was. He compared his work to Columbus' as the discoverer of
a new world, and to Moses' as the leader of a new chosen people who would exit the slavery of
moral ideas into a new promised land of power and practicality.
Machiavelli's revolution can be summarized in six points. For all previous social thinkers,
the goal of political life was virtue. A good society was conceived as one in which people are
good. There was no "double standard" between individual and social goodness-until Machiavelli.
With him, politics became no longer the art of the good but the art of the possible. His influence
on this point was enormous. All major social and political philosophers (Hobbes, Locke,
Rousseau, Mill, Kant, Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Dewey) subsequently rejected the goal of virtue,
just as Machiavelli lowered the standard and nearly everyone began to salute the newly masted
flag.
Machiavelli's argument was that traditional morals were like the stars; beautiful but too distant to
cast any useful light on our earthly path. We need instead man-made lanterns; in other words,
attainable goals. We must take our bearings from the earth, not from the heavens; from what men
and societies actually do, not from what they ought to do.
The essence of Machiavelli's revolution was to judge the ideal by the actual rather than
the actual by the ideal. An ideal is good for him, only if it is practical; thus, Machiavelli is the
father of pragmatism. Not only does "the end justify the means"-any means that work-but the
means even justify the end, in the sense that an end is worth pursuing only if there are practical
means to attain it. In other words, the new summum bonum, or greatest good is success.
(Machiavelli sounds like not only the first pragmatist but the first American pragmatist!)
50
Machiavelli didn't just lower the moral standards; he abolished them. More than a
pragmatist, he was an anti-moralist. The only relevance he saw morality having to success was to
stand in its way. He taught that it was necessary for a successful prince "to learn how not to be
good" (The Prince, ch. 15), how to break promises, to lie and cheat and steal (ch. 18).
Because of such shameless views, some of Machiavelli's contemporaries saw "The
Prince" as a book literally inspired by the devil. But modern scholars usually see it as drawn
from science. They defend Machiavelli by claiming that he did not deny morality, but simply
wrote a book about another subject, about what is rather than about what ought to be. They even
praise him for his lack of hypocrisy, implying that moralism equals hypocrisy.
This is the common, modern misunderstanding of hypocrisy as not practicing what you
preach. In that sense all men are hypocrites unless they stop preaching. Matthew Arnold defined
hypocrisy as "the tribute vice pays to virtue." Machiavelli was the first to refuse to pay even that
tribute. He overcame hypocrisy not by raising practice to the level of preaching but of lowering
preaching to the level of practice, by conforming the ideal to the real rather than the real to the
ideal.
In fact, he really preaches: "Poppa, don't preach!"-like the recent rock song. Can you
imagine Moses saying, "Poppa, don't preach!" to God on Mount Sinai? Or Mary to the angel? Or
Christ in Gethsemane, instead of "Father, not my will but thine be done"? If you can, you are
imagining hell, because our hope of heaven depends on those people having said to God, "Poppa,
do preach!"
Actually, we have misdefined "hypocrisy." Hypocrisy is not the failure to practice what
you preach but the failure to believe it. Hypocrisy is propaganda.
By this definition Machiavelli was almost the inventor of hypocrisy, for he was almost the
inventor of propaganda. He was the first philosopher who hoped to convert the whole world
through propaganda.
He saw his life as a spiritual warfare against the Church and its propaganda. He believed
that every religion was a piece of propaganda whose influence lasted between 1,666 and 3,000
years. And he thought Christianity would end long before the world did, probably around the
year 1666, destroyed either by barbarian invasions from the East (what is now Russia) or by a
softening and weakening of the Christian West from within, or both. His allies were all
lukewarm Christians who loved their earthly fatherland more than heaven, Caesar more than
Christ, social success more than virtue. To them he addressed his propaganda. Total candor
about his ends would have been unworkable, and confessed atheism fatal, so he was careful to
avoid explicit heresy. But his was the destruction of "the Catholic fake" and his means was
aggressive secularist propaganda. (One might argue, perhaps peevishly, that he was the father of
the modern media establishment.)
He discovered that two tools were needed to command men's behavior and thus to control
human history: the pen and the sword, propaganda and arms. Thus both minds and bodies could
be dominated, and domination was his goal. He saw all of human life and history as determined
by only two forces: virtu (force) and fortuna (chance). The simple formula for success was the
maximization of virtu and the minimization of fortuna. He ends "The Prince" with this shocking
image: "Fortune is a woman, and if she is to be submissive it is necessary to beat and coerce
her"(ch. 25). In other words, the secret of success is a kind of rape.
For the goal of control, arms are needed as well as propaganda, and Machiavelli is a
hawk. He believed that "you cannot have good laws without good arms, and where there are
good arms, good laws inevitably follow" (ch. 12). In other words justice "comes out of a barrel
51
of a gun," to adapt Mao Tse-tung's phrase. Machiavelli believed that "all armed prophets have
conquered and unarmed prophets have come to grief" (ch. 6). Moses, then, must have used arms,
which the Bible failed to report; Jesus, the supreme unarmed prophet, came to grief; He was
crucified and not resurrected. But His message conquered the world through propaganda,
through intellectual arms. This was the war Machiavelli set out to fight.
Social relativism also emerged from Machiavelli's philosophy. He recognized no laws
above those of different societies and since these laws and societies originated in force rather
than morality, the consequence is that morality is based on immorality. The argument went like
this: Morality can only come from society, since there is no God and no God-given universal
natural moral law. But every society originated in some revolution or violence. Roman society,
e.g., the origin of Roman law, itself originated with Romulus' murder of his brother Remus. All
human history begins with Cain's murder of Abel. Therefore, the foundation of law is
lawlessness. The foundation of morality is immorality.
The argument is only as strong as its first premise, which-like all sociological relativism,
including that which dominates the minds of writers and readers of nearly all sociology
textbooks today-is really implicit atheism.
Machiavelli criticized Christian and classical ideals of charity by a similar argument. He asked:
How do you get the goods you give away? By selfish competition. All goods are gotten at
another's expense: If my slice of the pie is so much more, others' must be that much less. Thus
unselfishness depends on selfishness.
The argument presupposes materialism, for spiritual goods do not diminish when shared or given
away, and do not deprive another when I acquire them. The more money I get, the less you have
and the more I give away, the less I have. But love, truth, friendship and wisdom increase rather
than decrease when shared. The materialist simply does not see this, or care about it.
Machiavelli believed we are all inherently selfish. There was for him no such thing as an
innate conscience or moral instinct. So the only way to make men behave morally was by force,
in fact totalitarian force, to compel them to act contrary to their nature. The origins of modern
totalitarianism also go back to Machiavelli.
If a man is inherently selfish, then only fear and not love can effectively move him. Thus
Machiavelli wrote, "It is far better to be feared than loved...[for] men worry less about doing an
injury to one who makes himself loved than to one who makes himself feared. The bond of love
is one which men, wretched creatures that they are, break when it is to their advantage to do so,
but fear is strengthened by a dread of punishment which is always effective" (ch. 17).
The most amazing thing about this brutal philosophy is that it won the modern mind,
though only by watering down or covering up its darker aspects. Machiavelli's successors toned
down his attack on morality and religion, but they did not return to the idea of a personal God or
objective and absolute morality as the foundation of society. Machiavelli's narrowing down came
to appear as a widening out. He simply lopped off the top story of the building of life; no God,
only man; no soul, only body; no spirit, only matter; no ought, only is. Yet this squashed
building appeared (through propaganda) as a Tower of Babel, this confinement appeared as a
liberation from the "confinements" of traditional morality, like taking your belt out a notch.
Satan is not fairy tale; he is a brilliant strategist and psychologist and he is utterly real.
Machiavelli's line of argument is one of Satan's most successful lies to this day. Whenever we
are tempted, he is using this lie to make evil appear as good and desirable; to make his slavery
appear as freedom and "the glorious freedom of the sons of God" appear as slavery. The "Father
52
of Lies" loves to tell not little lies but The Big Lie, to turn the truth upside down. And he gets
away with it-unless we blow the cover of the Enemy's spies.
B. Sigmund Freud
He was the Columbus of the psyche. No psychologist alive escapes his influence.
Yet, along with flashes of genius, we find the most bizarre ideas in his writingse.g.,
that mothers cuddle their babies only as a substitute for their desire to have sexual intercourse
with them.
Sigmund Freud's most influential teaching is his sexual reductionism. As an atheist,
Freud reduces God to a dream of man. As a materialist, he reduces man to his body, the human
body to animal desire, desire to sexual desire and sexual desire to genital sex. All are
oversimplifications.
Freud was a scientist, and in some ways a great one. But he succumbed to an
occupational hazard: the desire to reduce the complex to the controllable. He wanted to make
psychology into a science, even an exact science. But this it can never be because its object, man,
is not only an object but also a subject, an "I."
At the basis of our century's "sexual revolution" is a demand for satisfaction and a confusion
between needs and wants. All normal human beings have sexual wants or desires. But it's simply
not true, as Freud constantly assumes, that these are needs or rights; that no one can be expected
to live without gratifying them; or to suppress them is psychologically unhealthy.
This confusion between needs and wants stems from the denial of objective values and an
objective natural moral law. No one has caused more havoc in this crucial area than Freud,
especially regarding sexual morality. The modern attack on marriage and the family, for which
Freud set the stage, has done more damage than any war or political revolution. For where else
do we all learn the most important lesson in lifeunselfish loveexcept in stable families who
preach it by practicing it?
Yet, with all his faults, Freud still towers above the psychologies that replaced him in
popular culture. Despite his materialism, he explores some of the deeper mysteries of the soul.
He had a real sense of tragedy, suffering and unhappiness. Honest atheists are usually unhappy;
dishonest atheists happy. Freud was an honest atheist.
And his honesty made him a good scientist. He believed that the mere act of raising up
some repression or fear from the hidden darkness of the unconscious into the light of reason
would free us from its power over us. It was the faith that truth is more powerful than illusion,
light than darkness. Unfortunately, Freud classified all religion as mankind's most fundamental
illusion and materialistic scientism as his only light.
We should distinguish sharply among three different dimensions in Freud. First, as an
inventor of the practical, therapeutic technique of psychoanalysis, he's a genius and every
psychologist is in his debt. Just as it's possible for a Christian philosopher like Augustine or
Aquinas to use the categories of non-Christian philosophers like Plato and Aristotle, it's possible
for a Christian psychiatrist to use the techniques of Freud without subscribing to his religious
views.
Second, Freud as a theoretical psychologist is like Columbus, mapping out new
continents but also making some serious mistakes. Some of these are excusable, as Columbus'
were, by the newness of the territory. But others are simply prejudices, such as the reduction of
53
all guilt to pathological feeling and failure to see that faith in God could ever have anything to do
with love.
Third, Freud as a philosopher and religious thinker is strictly an amateur and little more
than an adolescent. Let's explore these points one by one.
Freud's greatest work is certainly "The Interpretation of Dreams." Investigating dreams as a
printout of the subconscious seems obvious today. But it was utterly new to Freud's
contemporaries. His mistake was not to overemphasize the subconscious forces that move us, but
to underemphasize their depth and complexity, as an explorer of a new continent might mistake
it for simply a large island.
Freud discovered that hysterical patients who seemed to have no rational cause for their
disorders were helped by what he called "the talking cure," using "free association" and paying
attention to "Freudian slips" as clues from the subconscious. In a word, the thing worked despite
the inadequacies of the theory behind it.
On the level of psychological theory, Freud divided the psyche into the id, the ego and
the super ego. This seems at first to be quite similar to the traditional and commonsensical
division into appetites, will and intellect (and conscience) that began with Plato. But there are
crucial differences.
First, Freud's "super-ego" is not the intellect or conscience, but the unfree, passive
reflection in the individual's psyche of society's restrictions on his desires"thou shalt nots."
What we take to be our own insight into real good and evil is only a mirror of man-made social
laws, according to Freud.
Second, the "ego" is not free will but a mere facade. Freud denied the existence of free
will, he was a determinist and saw man as a complex animal-machine.
Finally, the "id" ("it") is the only real self, according to Freud, and it's comprised simply
of animal desires. It is impersonal; thus the name "it." Freud thus is denying the existence of a
real personality, individual I-ness. Just as he denied God ("I Am"), he denies God's image, the
human "I."
Freud's philosophical ideas are most candidly expressed in his two most famous anti-
religious books, "Moses and Monotheism" and "The Future of an Illusion." Like Marx, he
dismissed all religion as infantile without seriously examining its claims and arguments. But he
did come up with a detailed explanation of the supposed origin of this "illusion." It has basically
four parts: ignorance, fear, fantasy and guilt.
As ignorance, religion is a pre-scientific guess at how nature works: If there is thunder,
there must be a Thunderer, a Zeus. As fear, religion is our invention of a heavenly substitute for
the earthly father when he dies, gets old, goes away or sends his children out of the secure home
into the frightening world of responsibility. As fantasy, God is the product of wish-fulfillment
that there's an all-powerful providential force behind the terrifyingly impersonal appearances of
life. And as guilt, God is the ensurer of moral behavior.
Freud's explanation of the origin of guilt is one of the weakest parts of his theory. It
amounts to the story that once, long ago, a son killed his father, the head of a great tribe. That
primal murder has haunted the human race's subconscious memory ever since. But this is no
explanation at all; Why did the first murderer feel guilt?
Freud's most philosophical book was his last, "Civilization and its Discontents." In it he raised
the great question of the summum bonumthe greatest good, the meaning of life and human
happiness. He concluded as Ecclesiastes did, that it is unattainable. "Vanity of vanities, all is
54
vanity," he says in effect. Instead, he promised to move us through successful psychotherapy,
"from unmanageable unhappiness to manageable unhappiness."
One reason for his pessimism was his belief that there's a contradiction inherent in the
human condition; this is the point of his title, "Civilization and its Discontents." On the one hand,
we are animals seeking pleasure, motivated only by "the pleasure principle." On the other hand,
we need the order of civilization to save us from the pain of chaos. But the restrictions of
civilization curtail our desires. So the very thing we invented as a means to our happiness
becomes our obstacle.
Toward the end of his life, Freud's thought became even darker and more mysterious as he
discovered thanatos, the death wish. The pleasure principle leads us in two opposite directions:
eros and thanatos. Eros leads us forward, into life, love, the future and hope. Thanatos leads us
back to the womb, where alone we had no pain.
We resent life and our mothers for birthing us into pain. This mother-hate parallels the
famous "Oedipus complex" or subconscious desire to murder our father and marry our mother
which is a perfect explanation of Freud's own atheism, resenting Father God and marrying
Mother Earthiness.
As Freud was dying, Hitler was coming to power. Freud prophetically saw the power of
the death wish in the modern world and was unsure which of these two "heavenly forces," as he
called them, would win out. He died an atheist but almost a mystic. He had enough of the pagan
in him to offer some profound insights, usually mixed up with outrageous blind spots. He calls to
mind C.S. Lewis' description of pagan mythology: "gleams of celestial strength and beauty
falling on a jungle of filth and imbecility."
What raises Freud far above Marx and secular humanism is his insight into the demon in
man, the tragic dimension of life and our need for salvation. Unfortunately, he saw the Judaism
he rejected and the Christianity he scorned as fairy tales, too good to be true. His tragic sense
was rooted in his separation between the true and the good, "the reality principle" and happiness.
Only God can join them at their summit.
C. Karl Marx
Among the many opponents of the Christian faith, Marxism is certainly not the most
important, imposing or impressive philosophy in history.
But it has, until recently, clearly been the most influential. A comparison of 1917, 1947 and 1987
world maps will show how inexorably this system of thought flowed so as to inundate one-third
of the world in just two generations-a feat rivaled only twice in history, by early Christianity and
early Islam.
Ten years ago, every political and military conflict in the world, from Central America to
the Middle East, turned on the axis of communism vs. anti-communism.
Even fascism became popular in Europe, and is still a force to be reckoned with in Latin
America, largely because of its opposition to "the specter of communism," as Marx calls it in the
first sentence of his "Communist Manifesto."
The "Manifesto" was one of the key moments in history. Published in 1848, "the year of
revolutions" throughout Europe, it is, like the Bible, essentially a philosophy of history, past and
55
future. All past history is reduced to class struggle between oppressor and oppressed, master and
slave, whether king vs. people, priest vs. parishioner, guild- master vs. apprentice, or even
husband vs. wife and parent vs. child.
This is a view of history even more cynical than Machiavelli's. Love is totally denied or
ignored; competition and exploitation are the universal rule.
Now, however, this can change, according to Marx, because now, for the first time in history, we
have not many classes but only two-the bourgeoisie (the "haves," owners of the means of
production) and the proletariat (the "have-nots," non-owners of the means of production).
The latter must sell themselves and their labor to the owners until the communist
revolution, which will "eliminate" (euphemism for "murder") the bourgeoisie and thus abolish
classes and class conflict forever, establishing a millennium of peace and equality. After being
utterly cynical about the past, Marx becomes utterly naive about the future.
What made Marx what he was? What are the sources of this creed? Marx deliberately
turned 180 degrees around from the (1) supernaturalism and (2) distinctiveness of his Jewish
heritage to embrace (1)atheism and (2) communism. Yet Marxism retains all the major structural
and emotional factors of biblical religion in a secularized form. Marx, like Moses, is the prophet
who leads the new Chosen People, the proletariat, out of the slavery of capitalism into the
Promised Land of communism across the Red Sea of bloody worldwide revolution and through
the wilderness of temporary, dedicated suffering for the party, the new priesthood.
The revolution is the new "Day of Yahweh," the Day of Judgment; party spokesmen are
the new prophets; and political purges within the party to maintain ideological purity are the new
divine judgments on the waywardness of the Chosen and their leaders. The messianic tone of
communism makes it structurally and emotionally more like a religion than any other political
system except fascism.
Just as Marx took over the forms and the spirit of his religious heritage, but not the
content, he did the same with his Hegelian philosophical heritage, transforming Hegel's
philosophy of "dialectical idealism" into "dialectical materialism!" "Marx stood Hegel on his
head," the saying goes. Marx inherited seven radical ideas from Hegel:
Monism: the idea that everything is one and that common sense's distinction between
matter and spirit is illusory. For Hegel, matter was only a form of spirit; for Marx, spirit was only
a form of matter.
Pantheism: the notion that the distinction between Creator and creature, the distinctively
Jewish idea, is false. For Hegel, the world is made into an aspect of God (Hegel was a pantheist);
for Marx, God is reduced to the world (Marx was an atheist).
Historicism: the idea that everything changes, even truth; that there is nothing above history to
judge it; and that therefore what is true in one era becomes false in another, or vice versa. In
other words, Time is God.
Dialectic: the idea that history moves only by conflicts between opposing forces, a
"thesis" vs. an "antithesis" evolving a "higher synthesis." This applies to classes, nations,
institutions and ideas. The dialectic waltz plays on in history's ballroom until the kingdom of
God finally comes-which Hegel virtually identified with the Prussian state. Marx
internationalized it to the worldwide communist state.
Necessitarianism, or fatalism: the idea that the dialectic and its outcome are inevitable
and necessary, not free. Marxism is a sort of Calvinistic predestination without a divine
Predestinator.
56
Statism: the idea that since there is no eternal, trans-historical truth or law, the state is
supreme and uncriticizable. Marx again internationalized Hegel's nationalism here. Militarism:
the idea that since there is no universal natural or eternal law above states to judge and resolve
differences between them, war is inevitable and necessary as long as there are states.
Like many other anti-religious thinkers since the French Revolution, Marx adopted the
secularism, atheism and humanism of l8th century "Enlightenment," along with its rationalism
and its faith in science as potentially omniscient and technology as potentially omnipotent. Here
again the forms, feel and function of biblical religion are transferred to another god and another
faith. For rationalism is a faith, not a proof. The faith that human reason can know everything
that is real cannot be proved by human reason; and the belief that everything that is real can be
proved by the scientific method cannot itself be proved by the scientific method.
A third influence, on Marx, in addition to Hegelianism and Enlightenment rationalism,
was economic reductionism: the reduction of all issues to economic issues. If Marx were reading
this analysis now, he would say that the real cause of these ideas of mine was not my mind's
power to know the truth, but the capitalistic economic structures of the society that "produced"
me. Marx believed that within man thought was totally determined by matter; that man was
totally determined by society; and that society was totally determined by economics. This stands
on its head the traditional view that mind rules body, man rules his societies, and society rules its
economics.
Finally, Marx adopted the idea of the collective ownership of property and the means of
producing it from previous "utopian socialist" thinkers. Marx says, "The theory of communism
may be summed up in the single phrase: abolition of private property." In fact, the only societies
in history that have ever successfully practiced communism are monasteries, kibbutzes, tribes
and families (which Marx also wanted to abolish). All communist governments (such as that of
the U.S.S.R.) have transferred ownership to the state, not to the people. Marx's faith that the state
would "wither away" of its own accord once it had eliminated capitalism and put communism in
its place has proved to be astonishingly naive. Once power is seized, only wisdom and sanctity
relinquish it.
The deepest appeal of communism, especially in Third World countries, has been not the
will to communalism but "the will to power," as Nietzsche called it. Nietzsche saw more deeply
into the heart of communism than Marx did.
How does Marx deal with the obvious objections to communism: that it abolishes privacy and
private property, individuality, freedom, motivation to work, education, marriage, family,
culture, nations, religion and philosophy? He does not deny that communism abolishes these
things, but says that capitalism has already done so. For example, he argues that "the bourgeois
sees in his wife a mere instrument of production." On the most sensitive and important issues,
family and religion, he offers rhetoric rather than logic; for example: "The bourgeois clap-trap
about the family and education, about the hallowed correlation between parent and child,
becomes all the more disgusting...." And here is his "answer" to religious and philosophical
objections: "The charges against communism made from a religious, a philosophical and,
generally, from an ideological standpoint are not deserving of serious examination."
The simplest refutation of Marxism is that its materialism simply contradicts itself. If
ideas are nothing but products of material and economic forces, like cars or shoes, then
communist ideas are only that too. If all our ideas are determined not by insight into truth but by
the necessary movements of matter if we just can't help the way our tongues happen to wag-then
57
the thoughts of Marx are no more true than the thoughts of Moses. To attack the grounds of
thought is to attack one's own attack.
But Marx sees this, and admits it. He reinterprets words as weapons, not as truths. The functions
of the words of the "Manifesto" (and, ultimately, even of the much longer, more pseudo-
scientific "Capital") is not to prove what is true but to encourage the revolution. "Philosophers
have only interpreted the world; the thing to do is to change it." Marx is basically a pragmatist.
But even on this pragmatic level there is a self-contradiction. The "Manifesto" ends with
this famous appeal: "The communists disdain to conceal their views and aims. They openly
declare that their ends can be attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing social
conditions. Let the ruling classes tremble at a communistic revolution. The proletarians have
nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world to win. Working men of all countries, unite!"
But this appeal is self defeating, for Marx denies free will. Everything is fated; the revolution is
"inevitable" whether I choose to join it or not. You cannot appeal to free choice and at the same
time deny it.
There are strong practical objections to communism as well as these two philosophical
objections. For one thing, its predictions simply have not worked. The revolution did not happen
when and where Marxism predicted. Capitalism did not disappear, nor did the state, the family or
religion. And communism has not produced contentment and equality anywhere it has gained
power.
All Marx has been able to do is to play Moses and lead fools backward into the slavery of
Egypt (worldliness). The real Liberator is waiting in the wings for the jester who now "struts and
frets his hour upon the stage" to lead his fellow "fools to dusty death" the one topic Marxist
philosophers refuse to face.
D. Jean-Paul Sartre
Jean-Paul Sartre may be the most famous atheist of the 20th century. As such, he
qualifies for anyone's short list of "pillars of unbelief."
Yet he may have done more to drive fence-sitters toward the faith than most Christian apologists.
For Sartre has made atheism such a demanding, almost unendurable, experience that few can
bear it.
Comfortable atheists who read him become uncomfortable atheists, and uncomfortable
atheism is a giant step closer to God. In his own words, "Existentialism is nothing else than an
attempt to draw all the consequences of a coherent atheistic position." For this we should be
grateful to him.
He called his philosophy "existentialism" because of the thesis that "existence precedes essence."
What this means concretely is that "man is nothing else than what he makes of himself." Since
there is no God to design man, man has no blueprint, no essence. His essence or nature comes
not from God as Creator but from his own free choice.
There's profound insight here, though it is immediately subverted. The insight is the fact
that man by his free choices determines who he will be. God indeed creates what all men are. But
the individual fashions his own unique individuality. God makes our what but we make our who.
God gives us the dignity of being present at our own creation, or co-creation; He associates us
with Himself in the task of co-creating our selves. He creates only the objective raw material,
58
through heredity and environment. I shape it into the final form of myself through my free
choices.
Unfortunately, Sartre contends that this disproves God, for if there were a God, man
would be reduced to a mere artifact of God, and thus would not be free. He constantly argues that
human freedom and dignity require atheism. His attitude is like that of a cowboy in a Western,
saying to God as to an enemy cowboy: "This town ain't big enough for both you and me. One of
us has to leave."
Thus Sartre's legitimate concern with human freedom and his insight into how it makes persons
fundamentally different from mere things lead him to atheism because (1) he confuses freedom
with independence, and because (2) the only God he can conceive of is one who would take
away human freedom rather than creating and maintaining ita sort of cosmic fascist.
Furthermore, (3) Sartre makes the adolescent mistake of equating freedom with rebellion. He
says freedom is only "the freedom to say no."
But this is not the only freedom. There's also the freedom to say yes. Sartre thinks we
compromise our freedom when we say yes, when we choose to affirm the values we've been
taught by our parents, our society, or our Church. So what Sartre means by freedom is very close
to what the beatniks of the `50s and the hippies of the `60s called "doing your own thing," and
what the Me generation of the `70s called "looking out for No. 1."
Another concept Sartre takes seriously but misuses is the idea of responsibility. He thinks
that belief in God would necessarily compromise human responsibility, for we would then blame
God rather than ourselves for what we are. But that's simply not so. My heavenly Father, like my
earthly father, is not responsible for my choices or the character I shape by means of those
choices; I am. And the fact of my responsibility no more disproves the existence of my heavenly
Father than it disproves the existence of my earthly father.
Sartre has a keen awareness of evil and human perversity. He says, "We have learned to
take Evil seriously...Evil is not an appearance...Knowing its causes does not dispel it. Evil cannot
be redeemed."
Yet he also says that since there is no God and since we therefore create our own values
and laws, there really is no evil: "To choose to be this or that is to affirm at the same time the
value of what we choose, because we can never choose evil." So Sartre gives both too much
reality to evil ("Evil cannot be redeemed") and too little ("We can never choose evil").
Sartre's atheism does not merely say that God doesn't exist, but that God is impossible.
He at least pays some homage to the biblical notion of God as "I Am" by calling it the most self-
contradictory idea ever imagined, "the impossible synthesis" of being-for-itself (subjective
personality, the "I") with being-in-itself (objective eternal perfection, the "Am").
God means the perfect person, and this is for Sartre a contradiction of terms. Perfect
things or ideas, like Justice or Truth, are possible; and imperfect persons, like Zeus or Apollo, are
possible. But the perfect person is impossible. Zeus is possible but not real. God is unique among
gods: not only unreal but impossible.
Since God is impossible and since God is love, love is impossible. The most shocking thing in
Sartre is probably his denial of the possibility of genuine, altruistic love. In place of God, most
atheists substitute human love as the thing they believe in. But Sartre argues that this is
impossible. Why?
Because if there is no God, each individual is God. But there can be only one God, one
absolute. Thus, all interpersonal relationships are fundamentally relationships of rivalry. Here,
59
Sartre echoes Machiavelli. Each of us necessarily plays God to others; each of us, as the author
of the play of his own life, necessarily reduces others to characters in his drama.
There is a little word which ordinary people think denotes something real and which
lovers think denotes something magical. Sartre thinks it denotes something impossible and
illusory. It is the word "we." There can be no "we-subject," no community, no self-forgetful love
if each of us is always trying to be God, the one single unique I-subject.
Sartre's most famous play, "No Exit," puts three dead people in a room and watches them
make hell for each other simply by playing God to each othernot in the sense of exerting
external power over each other but simply by knowing each other as objects. The shocking
lesson of the play is that "hell is other people."
It takes a profound mind to say something as profoundly false as that. In truth, hell is precisely
the absence of other people, human and divine. Hell is total loneliness. Heaven is other people,
because heaven is where God is, and God is Trinity. God is love, God is "other persons."
Sartre's tough-minded honesty makes him almost attractive, despite his repellant
conclusions like the meaninglessness of life, the arbitrariness of values and the impossibility of
love. But his honesty, however deep it may have lodged in his character, was made trivial and
meaningless because of this denial of God and thus of objective Truth. If there is no divine mind,
there is no truth except the truth each of us makes of himself. So if there's nothing for me to be
honest about except me, what meaning does honesty have?
Yet we cannot help rendering a mixed verdict on Sartre, and being gratified by his very
repulsivenessfor it flows from his consistency. He shows us the true face of atheism: absurdity
(that's the abstract word), and nausea (that's the concrete image he uses, and the title of his first
and greatest novel).
"Nausea" is the story of a man who, after arduous searching, finds the terrible truth that
life has no meaning, that it's simply nauseating excess, like vomit or excrement. (Sartre
deliberately tends toward obscene images because he feels life itself is obscene.)
We cannot help agreeing with William Barrett when he says that "to those who are ready
to use this [nausea] as an excuse for tossing out the whole Sartrian philosophy, we may point out
that it is better to encounter one's existence in disgust than never to encounter it at all."
In other words, Sartre's importance is like that of Ecclesiastes: He asks the greatest of all
questions, courageously and unswervingly, and we can admire him for that. Unfortunately, he
also gives the worst possible answer to it, as Ecclesiastes did: "Vanity of vanity, all is vanity."
We can only pity him for that, and with him the many other atheists who are clear-headed
enough to see as he did that "without God all things are permissible"but nothing has meaning.
E. Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche called himself "the Anti-Christ," and wrote a book by that title. He
argued for atheism as follows: "I will now disprove the existence of all gods. If there were gods,
how could I bear not to be a god? Consequently, there are no gods."
He scorned reason as well as faith, often deliberately contradicted himself, said that "a
sneer is infinitely more noble that a syllogism" and appealed to passion, rhetoric and even
deliberate hatred rather than reason.
He saw love as "the greatest danger" and morality as mankind's worst weakness. He died insane,
in an asylum, of syphilis-signing his last letters "the Crucified One." He was adored by the Nazis
as their semi-official philosopher.
60
Yet he is admired as profound and wise by many of the greatest minds of our century. How can
this be?
There are three schools of thought about Nietzsche. Most popular among academics is the
school of the "gentle Nietzscheans," who claim that Nietzsche was, in effect, a sheep in wolf's
clothing; that his attacks should not be taken literally and that he was really an ally, not an
enemy, of the Western institutions and values which he denounced.
These scholars resemble theologians who interpret sayings of Jesus like: "no one can
come to the Father but through me" as meaning "all religions are equally valid," and "he who
marries a divorced woman commits adultery" as meaning "let your divorces be creative and
reasonable."
Second, there are the "awful, awful" Nietzscheans. They at least pay Nietzsche the compliment
of taking him seriously. They are typified by the footnote in an old Catholic textbook on modern
philosophy, which said only that Nietzsche existed, was an atheist and died insane-a fate which
may well await anyone who looks too long into his books.
A third school of thought sees Nietzsche as a wolf indeed and not a sheep, but as a very
important thinker because he shows to modern Western civilization its own dark heart and
future. It's easy to scapegoat and point fingers at "blacksheep" like Nietzsche and Hitler, but is
there not a "Hitler in ourselves" (to quote Max Picard's title)? Did not Nietzsche let the cat out of
the bag? The demonic cat that was hidden in the respectable bag of secular humanism? Once
"God is dead," so is man, morality, love, freedom, hope, democracy, the soul and ultimately,
sanity. No one shows this more vividly than Nietzsche. He may have been responsible (quite
unintentionally) for many conversions.
Nietzsche's main themes can be summarized by the titles of his main books. Each is, in a
different way, an attack on faith. The center of Nietzsche's philosophy is always the same: He is
as centered on Christ as Augustine was, only he centered on Christ as his enemy.
Nietzsche's first book, "The Birth of Tragedy from the Spirit of Music," single-handedly
revolutionized the accepted view of the ancient Greeks as all "sweetness and light," reason and
order. For Nietzsche, the tragic poets were the great Greeks, and the philosophers, starting with
Socrates, were the small ones, pale and passionless. All the Western world had followed Socrates
and his rationalism and moralism, and had denied the other, darker side of man, the tragic side.
Nietzsche instead exalted tragedy, chaos, disorder and irrationality, symbolized by the
god Dionysus, god of growth and drunken orgies. He claimed that Socrates had turned the world
instead to the worship of Apollo, god of the sun, light, order and reason. But the fate of
Nietzsche's god Dionysus was soon to overtake Nietzsche himself; as Dionysus was literally torn
apart by the Titans, supernatural monsters of the underworld, Nietzsche's mind was to be cracked
asunder by his own inner Titans.
"The Use and Abuse of History" continued the Dionysian-vs.-Apollonian theme. The
"abuse of history" is (according to Nietzsche) theory, science, objective truth. The right use of
history is to enhance "life." Life and truth, fire and light, Dionysus and Apollo, will and intellect,
are set in opposition. We see Nietzsche being torn apart here, for these are the two parts of the
self.
"Ecce Homo" was pseudo-autobiographical shameless egotism. Though he was only a
stretcher-bearer in the war, Nietzsche calls himself a "swaggering old artillery man" adored by
all the ladies. In fact, he was a lonely old man who could not stand the sight of blood, an
emotional dwarf prancing like Napoleon. What's most terrifying is that he willingly embraces his
61
falsehood and fantasy. It is consistent with his philosophy or preferring "whatever is life-
enhancing" to truth. "Why not live a lie?" He asks.
"The Genealogy of Morals" claimed that morality was an invention of the weak
(especially the Jews, and then the Christians) to weaken the strong. The sheep convinced the
wolf to act like a sheep. This is unnatural, argues Nietzsche, and seeing morality's unnatural
origin in resentment at inferiority will free us from its power over us.
"Beyond Good and Evil" is Nietzsche's alternative morality, or "new morality." "Master
morality" is totally different from "slave morality," he says. Whatever a master commands
becomes good from the mere fact that the master commands it. The weak sheep have a morality
of obedience and conformity. Masters have a natural right to do whatever they please, for since
there is no God, everything is permissible.
"The Twilight of the Idols" explores the consequences of "the death of God." (Of course
God never really lives, but faith in Him did. Now that is dead, says Nietzsche.) With God dies all
objective truths (for there is no mind over ours) and objective values, laws and morality (for
there is no will over ours). Soul, free will, immortality, reason, order, love-all these are "idols,"
little gods that are dying now that the Big God has died.
What will replace God? The same being who will replace man; the Superman.
Nietzsche's masterpiece, "Thus Spake Zarathustra," celebrates this new god.
Nietzsche called "Zarathustra" the new Bible, and told the world to "throw away all other books;
you have my "Zarathustra." It is intoxicating rhetoric, and it has captivated adolescents for
generations. It was written in only a few days, in a frenzy, perhaps of literally demon-inspired
"automatic writing." No book ever written contains more Jungian archetypes, like a fireworks
display of images from the unconscious.
Its essential message is the condemnation of present-day man as a weakling and the
announcement of the next species, the Superman, who lives by "master morality" instead of
"slave morality." God is dead, long live the new god!
But in "The Eternal Return" Nietzsche discovers that all gods die, even the Superman. He
believed that all history necessarily moved in a cycle, endlessly repeating all past events-"There
is nothing new under the Sun." Nietzsche deduced this disappearing conclusion from the two
premises of (1) a finite amount of matter and (2) an infinite amount of time (since there is no
creator and no creation); thus every possible combination of elementary particles, every possible
world, occur an infinite number of times, given infinite time. All, even the Superman, will return
again to dust, and evolve worms, apes, man and Superman again and again.
Instead of despairing, as Ecclesiastes did, at this hopeless new history, Nietzsche seized the
opportunity to celebrate history's irrationality and the triumph of "life" over logic. The supreme
virtue was the will's courage to affirm this meaningless life, beyond reason, for no reason.
But in Nietzsche's last work, "The Will to Power," the lack of an end or goal appears as
demonic, and mirrors the demonic character of the modern mind. Without a God, a heaven, truth,
or an absolute Goodness to aim at, the meaning of life becomes simply "the will to power."
Power becomes its own end, not a means. Life is like a bubble, empty within and without; but its
meaning is self-affirmation, egotism, blowing up your bubble, expanding the meaningless self
into the meaningless void. "Just will," is Nietzsche's advice. It does not matter what you will or
why.
We are now in a position to see why Nietzsche is such a crucially important thinker, not despite
but because of his insanity. No one in history, except possibly the Marquis de Sade, has ever so
clearly, candidly and consistently formulated the complete alternative to Christianity.
62
Pre-Christian (i.e., pagan) societies and philosophies were like virgins. Post-Christian
(i.e., modern) societies and philosophies are like divorcees. Nietzsche is no pagan pre-Christian,
but the essential, modern post-Christian and anti-Christian. He rightly saw Christ as his chief
enemy and rival. The spirit of Anti-Christ has never received such complete formulation.
Nietzsche was not only the favorite philosopher of Nazi Germany, he is the favorite philosopher
of hell.
We can thank Satan's own foolishness in "blowing his cover" in this man. Like Nazism,
Nietzsche may scare the hell out of us and help save our civilization or even our souls by turning
us away in terror before it's too late.
F. Immanuel Kant
Few philosophers in history have been so unreadable and dry as Immanuel Kant. Yet few
have had a more devastating impact on human thought. Kant's devoted servant, Lampe, is said
to have faithfully read each thing his master published, but when Kant published his most
important work, "The Critique of Pure Reason," Lampe began but did not finish it because, he
said, if he were to finish it, it would have to be in a mental hospital. Many students since then
have echoed his sentiments.
Yet this abstract professor, writing in abstract style about abstract questions, is, I believe, the
primary source of the idea that today imperils faith (and thus souls) more than any other; the idea
that truth is subjective.
The simple citizens of his native Konigsberg, Germany, where he lived and wrote in the
latter half of the 18th century, understood this better than professional scholars, for they
nicknamed Kant "The Destroyer" and named their dogs after him.
He was a good-tempered, sweet and pious man, so punctual that his neighbors set their clocks by
his daily walk. The basic intention of his philosophy was noble: to restore human dignity amidst
a skeptical world worshiping science.
This intent becomes clear through a single anecdote. Kant was attending a lecture by a
materialistic astronomer on the topic of man's place in the universe. The astronomer concluded
his lecture with: "So you see that astronomically speaking, man is utterly insignificant." Kant
replied: "Professor, you forgot the most important thing, man is the astronomer."
Kant, more than any other thinker, gave impetus to the typically modern turn from the
objective to the subjective. This may sound fine until we realize that it meant for him the
redefinition of truth itself as subjective. And the consequences of this idea have been
catastrophic.
If we ever engage in conversation about our faith with unbelievers, we know from
experience that the most common obstacle to faith today is not any honest intellectual difficulty,
like the problem of evil or the dogma of the trinity, but the assumption that religion cannot
possibly concern facts and objective truth at all; that any attempt to convince another person that
your faith is trueobjectively true, true for everyoneis unthinkable arrogance.
The business of religion, according to this mindset, is practice and not theory; values, not
facts; something subjective and private, not objective and public. Dogma is an "extra," and a bad
extra at that, for dogma fosters dogmatism. Religion, in short, equals ethics. And since Christian
ethics is very similar to the ethics of most other major religions, it doesn't matter whether you are
a Christian or not; all that matters is whether you are a "good person." (The people who believe
63
this also usually believe that just about everyone except Adolf Hitler and Charles Manson is a
"good person.")
Kant is largely responsible for this way of thinking. He helped bury the medieval
synthesis of faith and reason. He described his philosophy as "clearing away the pretensions of
reason to make room for faith"as if faith and reason were enemies and not allies. In Kant,
Luther's divorce between faith and reason becomes finalized.
Kant thought religion could never be a matter of reason, evidence or argument, or even a
matter of knowledge, but a matter of feeling, motive and attitude. This assumption has deeply
influenced the minds of most religious educators (e.g., catechism writers and theology
departments) today, who have turned their attention away from the plain "bare bones" of faith,
the objective facts narrated in Scripture and summarized in the Apostles' creed. They have
divorced the faith from reason and married it to pop psychology, because they have bought into
Kant's philosophy.
"Two things fill me with wonder," Kant confessed: "the starry sky above and the moral law
within." What a man wonders about fills his heart and directs his thought. Note that Kant
wonders about only two things: not God, not Christ, not Creation, Incarnation, Resurrection and
Judgment, but "the starry sky above and the moral law within." "The starry sky above" is the
physical universe as known by modern science. Kant relegates everything else to subjectivity.
The moral law is not "without" but "within," not objective but subjective, not a Natural Law of
objective rights and wrongs that comes from God but a man-made law by which we decide to
bind ourselves. (But if we bind ourselves, are we really bound?) Morality is a matter of
subjective intention only. It has no content except the Golden Rule (Kant's "categorical
imperative").
If the moral law came from God rather than from man, Kant argues, then man would not
be free in the sense of being autonomous. This is true, Kant then proceeds to argue that man must
be autonomous, therefore the moral law does not come from God but from man. The Church
argues from the same premise that the moral law does in fact come from God, therefore man is
not autonomous. He is free to choose to obey or disobey the moral law, but he is not free to
create the law itself.
Though Kant thought of himself as a Christian, he explicitly denied that we could know
that there really exists (1) God, (2) free will, and (3) immorality. He said we must live as if these
three ideas were true because if we believe them we will take morality seriously, and if we don't
we will not. It is this justification of belief by purely practical reasons that is a terrible mistake.
Kant believes in God not because it is true but because it is helpful. Why not believe in Santa
Claus then? If I were God, I would favor an honest atheist over a dishonest theist, and Kant is to
my mind a dishonest theist, because there is only one honest reason for believing anything:
because it is true.
Those who try to sell the Christian faith in the Kantian sense, as a "value system" rather
than as the truth, have been failing for generations. With so many competing "value systems" on
the market, why should anyone prefer the Christian variation to simpler ones with less
theological baggage, and easier ones with less inconvenient moral demands?
Kant gave up the battle, in effect, by retreating from the battlefield of fact. He believed
the great myth of the 18th-century "Enlightenment" (ironic name!): that Newtonian science was
here to stay and that Christianity, to survive, had to find a new place in the new mental landscape
sketched by the new science. The only place left was subjectivity.
64
That meant ignoring or interpreting as myth the supernatural and miraculous claims of
traditional Christianity. Kant's strategy was essentially the same as that of Rudolf Bultmann, the
father of "demythologizing" and the man who may be responsible for more Catholic college
students losing their faith than anyone else. Many theology professors follow his theories of
criticism which reduce biblical claims of eyewitness description of miracles to mere myth,
"values" and "pious interpretations."
Bultmann said this about the supposed conflict between faith and science: "The scientific
world picture is here to stay and will assert its right against any theology, however imposing, that
conflicts with it." Ironically, that very "scientific world picture" of Newtonian physics Kant and
Bultmann accepted as absolute and unchangeable has today been almost universally rejected by
scientists themselves!
Kant's basic question was: How can we know truth? Early in his life he accepted the
answer of Rationalism, that we know truth by the intellect, not the senses, and that the intellect
possesses its own "innate ideas." Then he read the Empiricist David Hume, who, Kant said,
"woke me from my dogmatic slumber." Like other Empiricists, Hume believed that we could
know truth only through the senses and that we had no "innate ideas." But Hume's premises led
him to the conclusion of Skepticism, the denial that we can ever know the truth at all with any
certainty. Kant saw both the "dogmatism" of Rationalism and the skepticism of Empiricism as
unacceptable, and sought a third way.
There was such a third theory available, ever since Aristotle. It was the common sense
philosophy of Realism. According to Realism, we can know truth through both the intellect and
the senses if only they worked properly and in tandem, like two blades of a scissors. Instead of
returning to traditional Realism, Kant invented a wholly new theory of knowledge, usually called
Idealism. He called it his "Copernican revolution in philosophy." The simplest term for it is
Subjectivism. It amounts to redefining truth itself as subjective, not objective.
All previous philosophers had assumed that truth was objective. That's simply what we
common-sensically mean by "truth": knowing what really is, conforming the mind to objective
reality. Some philosophers (the Rationalists) thought we could attain this goal through reason
alone. The early Empiricists (like Locke) thought we could attain it through sensation. The later
skeptical Empiricist Hume thought we could not attain it at all with any certainty. Kant denied
the assumption common to all three competing philosophies, namely that we should attain it, that
truth means conformity to objective reality. Kant's "Copernican revolution" redefines truth itself
as reality conforming to ideas. "Hitherto it has been assumed that all our knowledge must
conform to objects...more progress may be made if we assume the contrary hypothesis that the
objects of thought must conform to our knowledge."
Kant claimed that all our knowledge is subjective. Well, is that knowledge subjective? If
it is, then the knowledge of that fact is also subjective, et cetera, and we are reduced to an infinite
hall of mirrors. Kant's philosophy is a perfect philosophy for hell. Perhaps the damned
collectively believe they aren't really in hell, it's all just in their mind. And perhaps it is; perhaps
that's what hell is.
65
CHAPTER TWO: THE SPIRIT OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY
We now pass to state our fundamental criticism of the whole spirit of contemporary
philosophy on this subject in the light of the age-long traditional principles.
Our basic principles are extracted from the doctrines of Aristotle and St. Thomas
principles whose sole claim to be accepted are their accord with common sense, and not their
authority.
In the tenth book of Aristotles Metaphysics and in the First Question of De Veritate we
find the principles upon which the spirit of modern thought will be judged.
The principles are: -
1. The Divine Intellect is a measure, not a thing measured.
2. Natural things are both a measure and a thing measured.
3. The human intellect is a thing measured, not a measure.
Yet, God in turn is measured by no one. He is the First Cause and Uncaused,
and thus, having never received His existence from another, He has not been
measured by another. He has set the bounds to all created being, yet no one has set
bounds to His Being.
2. Natural things are both a measure and a thing measured They are first of all a
measure; for they determine our knowledge. The object, which I see determines my
knowledge of that object.
Though natural things enjoy a reflected likeness of God they measure us
proximately, as God measures us absolutely. They, however, bear the stamp of their
imperfection, for they too are measured. God has made them; set limits to them,
and given them their measure of existence.
66
3. The human intellect is a thing measured, not a measure. It is measured first of all
by God, who has given it its first principles of the speculative and the practical
order. It is also measured by things. The intellect does not give truth and goodness
to things; it discovers them in things. Only in the case of artificial things can man
be said to be a measure, and to this extent He reflects the Creator Who made him.
The architect is the measure of the house, which he builds; the sculptor is the
measure of the statue, which he chisels; in a greater way, God is the Cause and
Measure of all things. So far as natural things are concerned and this is our
present interest man is not a measure, he is a thing measured.
These three principles are at the basis of common-sense philosophy and their proof, as
we have shown, is ultimately reducible to the principle of contradiction. Not only philosophy
but even religion itself reposes on these principles, for they determine the relations of God and
man. To change them is to change the whole fabric of our thought and to substitute a series of
relations, which pervert the real order of things.
In face of these principles, the spirit of modern thought is clear. After reviewing that
thought in its characteristic statements and conclusions we may now suggest its fundamental
principles in terms of our own system. Possible the philosophers who are thus criticized would
be the first to say that our conclusions were not theirs, and that they were not aware of the
attributed implications. This we state to be just. We, however, consider, after a careful survey,
that the principles and implications lie deeply embedded in the nature, expression, and
structure of their tenets.
What common-sense philosophy attributes to the human intellect, modern philosophy
attributes to the Divine Intellect; and what common sense philosophy attributes to the Divine
Intellect, modern Philosophy attributes to the human intellect.
Putting their formula in the same terms as the common-sense formula, it reads as
follows:
The human intellect is a measure, not a thing measured.
The Divine Intellect is a thing measured, not a measure.
Its first principle, in other words, is the superiority of mind over being; its second
principle is the superiority of man over God. One has as its consequence the divinization of
man, the other, the humanization of God.
These two results are not diverse; they are reciprocal. One is the concave, the other is
the convex side of the same reality. The divination of man means always the humanization of
God.
This is true of nations and individuals. At that point in history of a people or the
history of a soul when man stresses unduly his own powers and self-sufficiency, faith is lost in
both gods and God. John the Baptist, seized with the tremendous truth of this fact, cried out
to his hearers beyond the Jordan: I must decrease and He must increase. As man takes on an
added and undue gravity through an undue estimation of his worth, God naturally becomes
less in His estimation. Humility, on the contrary, is not so much an emphasis upon ones own
insufficiency as it is upon Gods worth and power. God becomes greater in our eyes, according
67
as we become less in our own. In either case, there is no change in God, the psychological and
real but in us.
The first perversion of a fundamental principle of the philosophia perennis is, that man is the
measure of all things. This anthropometrism and deification of man finds concrete expression
in two principles underlying modern thought, and asserting respectively:
Modern thought, on the contrary, subverts this order of mind and being and makes
mind a measure instead of the thing measured. Whether it be Idealism of Empiricism, both
agree in this Kantian Copernican revolution: reality is to some extent the work of the mind.
The planets of reality revolve about the world of self. Mind is the measure of reality. But how,
on these theories, does mind measure reality? Either by the use of a priori forms native to the
mind and this is the Idealists answer; or by practical forms arising from need and utility -
and this is the Empirical answer. One is the modern interpretation of the First Critique of
Kant, the other that of the Second Critique.
Professor Ralph Barton Perry of Harvard has given the following principle as
representative of idealism: the assertion of the priority of the cognitive consciousness, the
assertion that being is dependent upon the knowing of it, may be regarded as the cardinal
principle of idealism. What therefore is real, is real only in virtue of mind. That he has
68
defined idealism well is evident from the words of the chief of the English Idealists: We
perceive, on reflection, that to be real, or even barely to exist, must be to fall within sentience.
Sentient experience, in short, is reality and what is not this is not real. We may say, in other
words, that there is no real being or fact outside of that which is commonly called psychical
experience. Feeling, thought and volition (any groups under which we class psychical
phenomenon) are all the material of existence, and there is no other material, actual or even
possible. This by no means implies pure solipsism, the author contends, for there is no such
things as a subject apart from reality. There is only one Reality, of which all things else are but
appearances. Nothing exists independently of it. This system of mind which is and which
measures reality is an Absolute but it is not God. God is only an appearance of reality. A
God can say to himself, I, as against you and me, is not in my judgment defensible as the last
and complete truth of metaphysics.
For the Empiricists of today mind, too is the measure of reality, but instead of mind a
single whole, it is take to mean the combined activities of many minds in the long course of
evolution. There is no ready-made world presented to us which we can suck in with passive
receptivity, Professor Schiller tells us. Reality is not a fact in its own right which pre-exists
the cognitive functioning. It is not something, which measures our mind independently of
any contribution, which we may bring to it. We construct reality, instead of being constructed
by it. Our needs, utilities and experience and conveniences are its determination and measure.
The a priori forms of the Idealist give way to the practical forms of action for the modern
Empiricist. Professor James goes so far as to admit that these practical forms, which measure
reality may even antedate the appearance of real objects.
Though the category of transcendental reality is now one of the foundations of our
life, yet we can speculatively imagine a state of pure experience before the hypothesis of
permanent objects behind its flux had been formed.
In just so far as reality depends upon it, mind may be said to be the measure and in
some sense to be reality. If only that is real which is in thought, and if it is meaningless to
speak of anything outside thought, then man has deified intelligence to the level of Gods
intelligence. A very happy reaction to this Protagorian philosophy has set with Neo-Realism
and Critical realism. Neither, however, has created sufficient metaphysics to merit discussion
here. At present they confine themselves almost exclusively to the problem of sensible
perception.
69
Thirdly, truth oases into human knowledge when it represents things as they are. Thus
God measures truth just as things about us measure us. Thus we see that in the ontological
order, in the order of real gradation and dependence among things, as distinct from the order
of human experience, the reason why reality has ontological truth for the human mind is
because it is essentially and antecedently in accord with the Divine mind, from which it
derives its intelligibly.
Modern philosophy has some accord with this traditional notion, at least at first sight.
The source of truth for many is the other but the other is not God. It is man, not as an
individual, but as a stage in the evolutionary process. Ultimately, then, man has become the
measure and the source of truth. This is true of the generality of Pragmatic systems, and even
of those Absolutist systems, which admit evolution of mind and truth.
(a) Man is the source of truth considered from the point of view of evolution. Truth
has a biological, not a Divine source. Its source is not something transcendent to man; it
becomes as man becomes. There is no such thing as a truth with a big T. Truths make
themselves as we go. They are so many new creations that add themselves as fast as history
proceeds. Instead of being an antecedent principle that animates a process, truth is but an
abstract name for its results. The notion of a God as the source of truth is classed as a mere
idol of the tribe. Mach, Semmel, Avenarius and Professor Schiller insist particularly on this
man-made attitude of truth. Just as our organs in the course of evolution acquire a certain
fixity and stability and a certain biological immunity, so too, do our truths. They are to be
ultimately attributed to our ancestors. To speak of their source as residing outside the process
of evolution is nonsense.
The world is essentially [symbol]. It is what we make it. It is fruitless to define it by what it
originally was or by what it is apart from us. Take man from out the evolutionary series, and
truth automatically ceases to exists. Just as organic forms are born into the world, so is truth
born with man. Suppress man, and you suppress truth. For St. Thomas it is the contrary:
suppress man, truth will continue to exist; suppress angels, truth will continue to exist. But
imagine that God were suppressed, then, he concludes, truth would no longer exist. But, to
this the modern will answer, this notion of Scholastic metaphysics was Expedient for
centuries, but human experience has boiled over its limits.
(b) Less remotely, truth has been made by the experience of the individual, considered
not as developing but as developed. Human nature shapes all our questions, human
satisfaction lurks in all our answers, all our formulas have a human twist. But why have we
come to recognize truths as man-made and not something coming from God? Professor
James gives the answer: The enormously rapid multiplication of theories in these Katter days
has well-0nigh upset the notion of any one of them being a more literally objective kind of
thing than another. There are so many geometries, so many logics, so many physical and
chemical hypotheses, so many classifications, each one of them good for so much and yet not
good for anything, that the notion that even the truest formula may be a human device, and
not a literal transcript, has dawned upon us. Being devices, then, their measure will be their
utility their utility to us in handling the facts of experience. Subjective interest, our needs,
our desires, will be at every step the measure of the truths. The measure will not be
something objective; it will be that which satisfies us, or that which is expedient in the way of
70
our thinking. If an idea works, then it is true. If theological ideas prove to have a value for
concrete life, they will be true for pragmatism in the sense that they are good for so much. If
the hypothesis of God works satisfactorily in the widest sense of the world - experience shows
that it certainly does work it is true. If, therefore, at any time reason should come to prove
the fallacy of some popular conclusion, and demonstrate conclusively that it was in
contradiction to the fundamental laws of thought Pragmatism would keep it as a valuable
error or a vital lie. Man, in the philosophical sense, is thus considered as an artist, measuring
not only artificial things, but even the universe itself. The universe that we can know and use
is moulded as potters clay to the measure of the desires of man.
Modern absolutist systems do not adopt this anthropometrism with such boldness, at
least the strictly philosophical part of it. But once the subject of God is introduced, man, either
implicitly or explicitly, is made the measure. To judge or evaluate religion upon any other
grounds than those of our own needs and desires is dangerous and mistaken. But within the
sphere of Absolutism it is difficult to see wherein it can find the other by which truth can be
measured. There is only one, of which we are a part. On the common-sense view the many
may be suppressed world, men and angels yet there will still be truth; on the Absolutionist
position, if you suppress the many world, men and angels you suppress the Absolute.
Ultimately, then, on the Absolutionist position, we are the measure.
Traditionally there had been recognized a double perfection of human nature: one
natural, the other supernatural. The natural perfection is the complete development of the
natural powers in the knowledge of the highest truth, and in union through love with the
highest good. It is not the attainment of God sub ratione Deitatis, this is the object of the
supernatural order. The supernatural perfection is effected through a gratuitous gift of grace
by which we are made partakers of the Divine nature, adopted sons of God and heirs of
heaven. The supernatural order exceeds the powers, the nature, the capacity and the merits of
the natural order. It is in the strictest sense a something not due to human nature an
indebitum. There is greater difference between the state of a soul without grace and the state of
a soul in grace, than a soul in grace on this earth and a soul enjoying the glory of heaven.
Grace is such a precious gift that is worth more than all creation. As we cannot know the
intimate nature of Michael Angelo by looking at his statue of Moses, so, too, we cannot know
the intimate nature of God by regarding His works the visible universe. But thanks to this
participation of the Divine nature, through the gratuitous gift of God, our nature becomes in
an analogical sense deified, as St. Augustine has put it: God became man in order that man
might become God.
Now, this sharp distinction between the natural and the supernatural order, between
knowledge by reason and knowledge by infused faith, between the natural perfection of our
nature and the supernatural perfection through grace, has been lost sight of the modern
philosophy. The result has been that what really is a gift of God is now looked upon as natural
to man, so that man, attributing to himself that Divine quality which makes him a partaker of
the Divine nature, has divinized himself to just that extent.
71
According to the modern doctrines the mystical state is not die to any infusion of
grave. It is properly a psychological state, our soul being mysteriously one with a larger soul
whose instruments we are. Dean Inge rightly insists that to know God intimately we must
become partakers of the Divine nature but the source of this participation he attributes not to
God, but to the Divine spark already within us. But though we are made in the image of
God, our likeness to Him only exists potentially. The Divine spark already shines within us,
but it has to be searched for in the innermost depths of our personality, and its light diffused
over its whole being. The foundation of mystical states being considered as natural and
psychological, has given some the privilege to dispense with the Author of grace. The
indwelling Christ constituted the central doctrine of St. Paul, and can be apprehended and
experienced by each one of us now without any historical difficulties, without any reference
even to the historical Jesus.
This intimate participation by the human nature in the Divine nature is yet more fully
revealed in the various philosophies of Becoming in which man becomes identified with the
life impulse, which is God, or with the elan vital, or becomes continuous with God by a
mystical interpenetration. God is not apart from man, but there is a presence of one in and
through the other. The Divine Imaginal reflects itself in us as well as in Him; for He, like us,
is only a child of the Divine Imaginal. God is above us, it is true, but not far above; He is just
one stage above the stage yet evolved, and we shall in a future day attain the dignity and the
level He now possesses.
Modern philosophy has divinized the power of the human intelligence, making it
the measure of Being and its transcendentals; it has also divinized the mode of this knowledge
by making it like unto Gods. It has divinized human nature by confusing a gift with a claim-
that is, by turning the gift of grace and participation in the Divine nature into a claim and a
debitum to human nature, and a natural consequence of its psychological structure.
This divinization of man has for its counterpart. As we hinted in the beginning of this
chapter, the humanization of God. If we increase, God decreases in our estimation. Man has
made himself like unto God; it now remains for God to be made like unto man by a
misunderstanding if His nature. This is the negative side of the spirit of modern philosophy. It
is that of the humanization of God.
This aspect of modern philosophy is best evidenced in the novel and original concept
of religion. For traditional philosophy and theology, religion is a term, which has meaning
only if a God or gods exist. This notion is not proper to Christianity; paganism implied it and
Cicero defined it. There could no more be religion without God than there could be physics
without bodies, or mathematics without numbers. The creature was considered as related to
God as science to its object. The object is not relative to the science; it can exist without a
science. Life would exist whether biology ever existed or not. So, too, God can exist without
us. As the rays of the sun cease with the setting off the sun, so would our existence cease
without the conservation of God. We are, therefore, dependent on God. This dependence
begets religion. Religion is intelligible only in function of a God. Thus St. Thomas, quoting
Cicero and St. Augustine, the pagan and the Christian, states religion to be a relation to God,
to whom we are bound as to an unfailing principle.
72
But this notion has been changed. The idea of dependence on a Supreme Being has been
lost. Instead of being rays that survive in virtue of our own sufficiency. Today, God is not
conceived as the starting-point of religion; rather religion is the starting-point. Religion first,
God afterwards. George Fonsegrive in his LEvolution des Idees dans la France contemporaine
characterizes this changed attitude in these words: Nos contemporains paraissent aller de la
religion a Dieu plutot que Dieu a la religion. Professor Hoernle in his study on contemporary
metaphysics notes also that this new notion of the relation between God and religion is one of
the characteristics of contemporary thought. A German historian has been so struck by it as to
give it special mention as a trait of modern thought.
The modern conception of the relationship between God and religion can be
understood only in the light of the new definition of religion. To retain the term religion in
the traditional sense, and still to maintain that we proceed from religion to God, would result
in confusion worse confounded. Religion has lost the meaning, which it has always
possessed. Today it means a relation as of old, but not necessarily with God. God is no
longer conceived as the starting-point of religion; rather, it is man. Man is the center around
which religion, revolve, and not God. We are the highest examples of individuals, and
therefore the solution of all riddles is to be found within us. Religion is the pure embodiment
of the practical motive that is, highly interested desire for a plan of action which will secure
the maximum good fortune from the environment as a whole. Religion is a projection in the
roaring loom of time of a concentration or unified complex of psychical values. The term
god or God is left entirely out of consideration; the source of the maximum goodness is
represented as the environment as a whole. Professor James has given a similar definition:
Religion is the feelings, acts and experiences of individual men in their solitude, so far as they
apprehend themselves to stand in relation to whatever they may consider the divine. Lest we
should be tempted to think that God is necessary for religion, and its starting-point, James
goes on to explain what he means by the divine. We must interpret the term divine very
broadly, as denoting the object that is god-like whether it be a concrete deity or not.
Whether God exists or not, is not important to the nature of religion. All the relations
that religion implies may be found within man himself. The explanation which Mr. Bertrand
Russell gives of it, and for which he won much praise from his contemporaries, is as follows:
Religion consists in the transfer from the life of the finite self to that of the infinite, both of -
which are to be found in man. This transition comes when all personal will seems to cease
and the soul feels itself in passive submission to the universe. After passionate struggle for
some particular good, there comes some inward or outward necessity to abandon the pursuit
of the object which has absorbed all our desire, and no other desire is ready to replace the one
that has been relinquished. Hence arises a state of suspension in the will, when the soul no
longer seeks to impose itself upon the world, but is open to every impression that comes to it
from the world. Thus from the moment of self-surrender, which to the finite self appears like
death, new life begins with a larger vision, a new happiness and wider hopes.
But is God required in order that the new infinite life be born in us? Mr. Russell
answers in the negative: To some men the belief in an all-wise God to whom submission is a
73
duty may make the surrender easier. But it is not in its essence dependent upon this belief
or upon any other.
Professor Pringle-Pattison in a commentary on this view of religion remarks: Thus man
creates God, all-powerful and all-good, the mystic unity of what is and what should be. This
is no exaggeration of the position of Mr. Russell; for the latter himself has told us: Thus man
worships at the shrine his own hands have built.
Two entirely different notions of religion are bound to arise according as we take our
point of departure from God or from man. Common-sense philosophy and theology made
God the term of the relations of creatures to Him. Our very being, the conservation of our
being all is from Him. In the intellectual life the knowledge of certain conclusions,
engendered by certain principles, would disappear if we forgot the principles, because it is
these principles, which are the superior cause, not only of the becoming but also of the being
of the effect. In a still deeper way do we depend upon God Religion, then, on the traditional
notion, becomes the sum of mans duties to God either in the natural or in the supernatural
order. Religion is primarily and essentially mans service of God.
Contemporary thought, on the contrary, making religion start with self, makes it sum
of Gods duties to man. If God is the source or the ratio of religion, then creatures are His
servants; if self be the source of religion, then God is the servant of men.
If God is mere appearance in the Absolute, and will eventually be lost in it; if finite
selves are eternal, and have a being independent of God; if God is a mere child of the
Imaginal, a creation of our desire, a being who learns from us how to be more effectively
faithful to His own greater tasks and whose very character depends on our acts, a mere
primus inter pares, without foresight of good and evil, facing the blackness of the unknown
and the blind joys and confusions of life; if God is merely the universe with a nisus towards
deity; if He is the work of our conscience and we worship at the shrine our own hands have
built; if God is the sum of all consciousness and appears at the term of evolution and not at
its beginning; if He is so weak that He Draws strength and increase of being from us, and
owes His being to the pre-existing finites; if we must change our idea of God with every new
scientific advance and change of government; if His nature is sustained by us; if He is a mere
President of a Cosmic Commonwealth then all that common-sense had regarded as holy
and sacred is vain and foolish, and God, instead of being the Lord and Creator of the
Universe, the Supreme Goodness, Beauty and Truth, is merely the servant of man and
religion, whose real end is to express the dependence of man on God, now becomes the
dependence of God on man, whether God be real or a mere creation of our conscience. We
are no longer the mere puppets of God, as Dr. McGiffert reminds us, but rather God-
makers; hence all adoration is looked upon as childish and unworthy of God who can take
delight in toyshop furniture, tapers and tinsel costume and mumbling and mummery and
finding His glory enhanced thereby seems intolerably bald and chalky and bleak. WE are
no longer the subject of God, but His intimate partner. It is, I believe, felt that we help
to sustain the nature of God. Man and God are business partners sharing one anothers losses
and profits. This whole modern conception is concisely summed up in the following sentence,
74
which represents the priority of man over God in this business, of which God is really the
silent partner: We and God have business with each other: To just this extent, God is
humanized and reduced to the level of a mere man who enjoys priority, not in virtue of His
intrinsic nature but in virtue of convention or empty title. Modern theology, taking over the
philosophical notion of religion as the sum of Gods duties to man, has worked it out in the
Christian doctrines of the Incarnation and Redemption. Though such a discussion is outside
the scope of this work, we can note it as another token of the humanization of God. The
Incarnation is represented solely and exclusively as the evolution of Gods love for man, of
which the act of Redemption is the triumph. There is no question of justice not genuine
justification involved. Man has no debt, which he owes to God. The whole idea may be
represented by picturing a man sitting calmly on the wharf of a great sea. Suddenly up from
behind him there rushes a friend who throws himself into the water and is drowned, just to
convince the man on the wharf that he loved him. Such is the modern notion of the
Incarnation and Redemption, viz. God throwing Himself into the sea of suffering and
hardship to convince man of His love. The whole scene would have much more reason if the
man on the wharf really fell into the water and his friend came to save him from drowning by
giving up His own life and this is the traditional notion.
To put the situation bluntly, religion must be separated from the other-worldly pull of
the traditional theologies and be sanely grounded in the outlook of modern knowledge. There
is no need for a rabid antitheism. The truth is, rather, that mankind is outgrowing theism in a
gentle and steady way until it ceases to have any clear meaning A humanists religion can
admit no cunning division into the things which are Gods and the things which are Caesars.
It would be quite as correct, then, to say that the highest term of religion is humanity. And
that Christianity is the religion of humanity. The only possible service of God must consist
in the service of men.
Such is the spirit of modern philosophy divinization of man and humanization of
God. Stressing his own sufficiency, making himself the measure of Being and Truth,
attributing to himself a divine knowledge and a participated Divine nature, man has pulled
down God from the heavens and reduced Him to a mere shadow of Himself. In stressing his
own insufficiency John the Baptist stressed for his own mind the greatness of God. In stressing
his own sufficiency, the modern philosopher stresses for his own mind the poverty of God. He
takes an irreligious humanity as a religion. It is actually much more difficult to worship a
humanity that is not worshipping. A self-contained and self-centered humanity would chill us
in the same way as a self-contained and self-centered human being. For the spiritual hungers
of humanity are never merely hungers for humanity The child in the field, if left entirely to
himself, does not wish to find the perfect parish ruled over by the perfect parish council. The
child in the field wants to find fairly land; and that type of fancy must either be satisfied or
thwarted, but it cannot be turned into something totally different In other words, it is
impossible to turn all eyes of that mutual admiration society inwards. Putting the whole
philosophy in a formula, which expresses the perversion of the traditional notions, we have
the following: -
Mind is confused with Being.
Grace is confused with Nature.
75
Man is confused with God.
Or, in one simple formula contrasted with the traditional notion, it may read:
We take Gods measure God takes our measure.
There is an alteration in the seat of authority. It is the transfer of the seat of authority
from God to man, and a transfer of the measure from God to man. The earth of things, long
thrown into the shadow by the glories of the upper ether, must resume its rights.
In the beginning God made man to His own image and likeness.
76
2.
ERRONEOUS
PHILOSOPHICAL
SYSTEMS
Source:
The
Syllabus
of
Errors
by
St.
Pius
X.
1. There exists no Supreme, all-wise, all-provident Divine Being, distinct from the
universe, and God is identical with the nature of things, and is, therefore, subject to
changes. In effect, God is produced in man and in the world, and all things are God
and have the very substance of God, and God is one and the same thing with the
world, and, therefore, spirit with matter, necessity with liberty, good with evil, justice
with injustice. -- Allocution "Maxima quidem," June 9, 1862.
2. All action of God upon man and the world is to be denied. -- Ibid.
3. Human reason, without any reference whatsoever to God, is the sole arbiter of truth
and falsehood, and of good and evil; it is law to itself, and suffices, by its natural
force, to secure the welfare of men and of nations. -- Ibid.
4. All the truths of religion proceed from the innate strength of human reason; hence
reason is the ultimate standard by which man can and ought to arrive at the knowledge
of all truths of every kind. -- Ibid. and Encyclical "Qui pluribus," Nov. 9, 1846, etc.
6. The faith of Christ is in opposition to human reason and divine revelation not only
is not useful, but is even hurtful to the perfection of man. -- Ibid.
7. The prophecies and miracles set forth and recorded in the Sacred Scriptures are the
fiction of poets, and the mysteries of the Christian faith the result of philosophical
investigations. In the books of the Old and the New Testament there are contained
mythical inventions, and Jesus Christ is Himself a myth.
9. All the dogmas of the Christian religion are indiscriminately the object of natural
science or philosophy, and human reason, enlightened solely in an historical way, is
77
able, by its own natural strength and principles, to attain to the true science of even the
most abstruse dogmas; provided only that such dogmas be proposed to reason itself as
its object. -- Letters to the Archbishop of Munich, "Gravissimas inter," Dec. 11, 1862,
and "Tuas libenter," Dec. 21, 1863.
10. As the philosopher is one thing, and philosophy another, so it is the right and duty
of the philosopher to subject himself to the authority which he shall have proved to be
true; but philosophy neither can nor ought to submit to any such authority. -- Ibid.,
Dec. 11, 1862.
11. The Church not only ought never to pass judgment on philosophy, but ought to
tolerate the errors of philosophy, leaving it to correct itself. -- Ibid., Dec. 21, 1863.
12. The decrees of the Apostolic See and of the Roman congregations impede the true
progress of science. -- Ibid.
13. The method and principles by which the old scholastic doctors cultivated theology
are no longer suitable to the demands of our times and to the progress of the sciences.
-- Ibid.
15. Every man is free to embrace and profess that religion which, guided by the light
of reason, he shall consider true. -- Allocution "Maxima quidem," June 9, 1862;
Damnatio "Multiplices inter," June 10, 1851.
16. Man may, in the observance of any religion whatever, find the way of eternal
salvation, and arrive at eternal salvation. -- Encyclical "Qui pluribus," Nov. 9, 1846.
17. Good hope at least is to be entertained of the eternal salvation of all those who are
not at all in the true Church of Christ. -- Encyclical "Quanto conficiamur," Aug. 10,
1863, etc.
18. Protestantism is nothing more than another form of the same true Christian
religion, in which form it is given to please God equally as in the Catholic Church. --
Encyclical "Noscitis," Dec. 8, 1849.
78
CHAPTER THREE: THE MODERN SUPERSTITIONS
The superstition of Progress asserts itself in some such fashion as this in our classrooms,
best-sellers and high-class journals: Man is naturally good and indefinitely perfectible, and
thanks to great cosmic floods of evolution will be swept forward and forward until he becomes a
kind of a god. Goodness increases with time, while evil and error decline. History represents the
gradual but steady advance of man up the hill of the more abundant and happy life. No special
institutions, no moral discipline, no Divine grace are necessary for the progress of man; for
progress is automatic, due to the free play of natural forces and the operation of freedom in a
world released from the superstition of religion. Because evil and sin are only vestigial remnants
from the bestial past, evolution and science and education will finally eradicate them.
This superstition of Progress is false because it completely ignores the goal and purpose
of progress. The modern world confuses motion with progress: instead, of working toward an
ideal, it changes the ideal and calls it progress. If every time an artist looked up he saw a
different person sitting for the portrait, how would he ever know he was making any progress in
painting? As Chesterton said: "There is one thing that never makes any progress and that is the
idea of progress." Progress in an indefinite future, but not beyond history, makes present moral
lives meaningless and endows them with no other value than that of so many sticks to keep the
cosmic bonfire blazing for the next generation. When the only kind of happiness men can enjoy
is one, which they celebrate in the distant future on the graves of their ancestors, then indeed
their happiness is the happiness of gravediggers in the midst of a pestilence. As Berdyaev so well
expressed it: "Both from the religious and ethical points of view this positivist conception of
progress is inadmissible, because by its very nature it excludes a solution to the tragic torments,
conflicts and contradictions of life valid for all mankind, for all those generations who have lived
and suffered. For it deliberately asserts that nothing but death and the grave awaits the vast
majority of mankind and the endless succession of human generations throughout the ages,
because they have lived in a tortured and imperfect state torn asunder by contradictions. But
somewhere on the peaks of historical destiny, on the ruins of preceding generations, there shall
appear the fortunate race of men reserved for the bliss and perfection of integral life. All the
generations that have gone before are but the means to this blessed life, to this blissful generation
of the elect as yet unborn.... Thus the religion of progress regards all the generations and epochs
that have been as devoid of intrinsic value, purpose or insignificance, as the mere means and
instruments to the ultimate goal." It is this fundamental moral contradiction that invalidates the
doctrine of progress, turning it into a religion of death instead of resurrection and eternal life.
There is no valid ground for degrading those generations whose lot has been cast among pain and
imperfection beneath that whose pre-eminence has been ordained in blessedness and joy. No
future perfection can expiate the sufferings of past generations. Such a sacrifice of all human
destinies to the messianic consummation of the favored race can only revolt man's moral and
79
religious conscience. A religion of progress based on this apotheosis of a future fortunate
generation is without compassion for either present or past; it addresses itself with infinite
optimism to the future, with infinite pessimism to the past. It is profoundly hostile to the
Christian expectation of resurrection for all mankind, for all the dead, fathers and forefathers.
"This Christian idea rests on the hope of an end to historical tragedy and contradiction valid for
all human generations, and of resurrection in eternal life for all who have ever lived. But the
nineteenth-century conception of progress admits to the messianic consummation only that
unborn generation of the elect to which all preceding generations have made their sacrifice. Such
a consummation, celebrated by the future elect among the graves of their ancestors, can hardly
rally our enthusiasm for the religion of progress. Any such enthusiasm would be base and
inappropriate." *
The doctrine of Progress confuses mechanical advancement with moral betterment. There
is no denying the fact that there has been great progress in the material order, but mechanical
development does not necessarily imply moral development. Progress in "things" is not
necessarily progress in "persons." Planes may go faster, but man does not become happier.
Progress in medicine is not necessarily progress in ethics, and mastery over disease is not
necessarily mastery over sin. Conquest of nature does not mean conquest of selfishness.
Scientific advancement is no guarantee of moral betterment. Greater power over nature can
increase our potentiality for evil. Put the forces of evil in charge of radio, the press and the new
inventions and you corrupt or destroy a nation. Mechanics is one thing, freedom is quite another.
Moral optimism, based on mechanical progress and the assumption of the natural goodness of
man, understands neither the heights to which man can climb through the grace of God, nor the
depths to which he can fall through the abandonment of a Divine life purchased through a cross.
The conquest of nature does not parallel our conquest of evil. We are equipped like giants to
subdue the environment of the air and the sea and the bowels of the earth, but we are as weak as
pigmies for the conquest of ourselves. The greater power which science has put into man's hands
can, unless his will is right, increase his potentiality for evil, as the present chaos so well bears
witness. Time does not always operate in favor of human betterment; because a man is sick, time
does not necessarily make him better. Unless evil is corrected, time operates in favor of disease,
decay and death.
The superstition of Progress denies human responsibility. When human goodness is
attributed to automatic laws of nature, but never to good will; when evil is explained in terms of
environment, heredity, bad milk, insufficient playgrounds and those naughty ductless glands, but
never to a perverse order, then the world is most in danger of losing freedom when it talks about
it. Someone was recently horrified at the immorality of young girls between the ages of fifteen
and seventeen and suggested that the solution to this problem was to "build more dance halls
where they sold soft drinks." If we attribute evil to external circumstances, and believe that we
can cultivate virtue by a swing band and soda pop, we will have become a nation where there is
no freedom because there is no responsibility. Evil is not in the absence of opportunities for
amusement. Evil is in the will, and in the heart and in the decisions of each and every one of us.
Youth can be vicious with dance halls; it can be virtuous without them, but youth will never be
good unless its will is ordered to the moral law of the all holy God. The confusion of the idea of
progress with the idea of evolution, kills the value of intention and the fruits of high resolves.
True progress is ethically and not cosmically conditioned; it depends not on the refinement of
luxuries, but in their deliberate control through human intention. There is really therefore only
80
one true progress in the world and that consists in the diminution of the traces of original sin.
Historical facts do not support the Utopian illusion that goodness increases with time. What
happens in reality is something quite different. Evil grows along with the good. The history of
the world is rather like a tension between good and evil than an escalator, which keeps going
upwards. "The kingdom of heaven is likened to a man that sowed good seed in his field. But
while men were asleep, his enemy came and over sowed cockle among the wheat and went his
way. And when the blade sprang up and had brought forth fruit, then appeared also the cockle.
And the servants of the good man of the house coming said to him, 'Sir, didst thou not sow good
seed in thy field? Whence then hath it cockle?' And he said to them, 'An enemy hath done this.'
And the servants said to him, 'Wilt thou that we go and gather it up?' And he said, 'No, lest
perhaps gathering up the cockle, you root up the wheat also together with it. Suffer both to grow
until the harvest, and in the time of the harvest I will say to the reapers: gather up first the cockle
and bind it into bundles to burn, but the wheat gather ye into my barn' " (Matthew 13: 24-30).
Nothing better proves the fallacy of progress than to recall the interval between modern wars. It
has been a common fashion for the Utopians to explain wars away as "falls in the evolutionary
process," or as "necessary incidents in the evolution from savagery to civilization," or as
"survivals of the animal in civilized man." But history does not prove we are making progress;
instead of evolving from savagery to civilization, we seem to be devolving from civilization to
savagery. The interval between the Napoleonic war and the Franco-Prussian war was fifty-five
years; the interval between the Franco- Prussian war and the first World War was forty-three
years; and the interval between the first World War and this one was twenty-one years. Fifty-
five, forty-three, twenty-one yearsand each war more destructive than the former, and at a time
when man materially had more to make for happiness than any other period of history. Is that
progress? Shall we not learn from our modem history its record that man, once he forgets his
God, has also an increasing capacity for evil?
The sad and tragic fact is that modern man under sufficient stress, and even amidst
comforts spiced with lust, will do deeds of evil as terrible as anyone recorded in history.
Barbarism is not behind us; it is beneath us. And it can emerge at any moment unless our wills,
aided by the grace of God, repress it. The modern superstition of man's indefinite perfectibility,
without God's sustaining graces, forgets the historical data before our eyes, that history is
creating ever-increasing possibilities for chaos and wars. Our mechanical progress in moving
quickly can go hand in hand with power to do more evil. Let no one deny it: our scientific
progress has outstripped our moral progress. We are a more comfortable people than our
ancestors, but are we necessarily a happier people? The myth of necessary progress is exploded.
But that is no reason why the Liberals who were so optimistic about Progress, like Bertrand
Russell, should now fall into a hellish despair. Because the evil in the world does not evolve
right does not mean there is no right. It only means that we have to put the evil right, and in order
to do this we may have to learn the lesson of a cross and the toil of Gethsemane. Neither is the
solution to be found among those Fascist intelligentsia who appeal to the authority of H. G.
Wells and re quote in the darkness of their souls: "Men are borne along through space and time
regardless of themselves, as if to the awakening greatness of Men." The answer is somewhere
else. Maybe we had better get back again to God.
81
2. The Superstition of Scientism
By the superstition of Scientism we do not mean science, but rather that particular abuse
of it which affirms that the scientific method is, as John Dewey put it, "The sole authentic mode
of revelation." For the modem sensate mind, to understand is to measure; to know is to count.
The senses are the only sources of knowledge. Hence any knowledge derived from any source
other than counting and experimentation is illusory. Sensible knowledge is the final arbiter of
experience. Science says "this," or science says "that," is the last word to be said on any subject.
Hence there is no place for values, tradition, metaphysics, revelation, faith, authority, or
theology. God has no purposes in the universe; first of all because there is no God, and secondly
because there are no purposes.
Scientism does not say we ignore purposes in our laboratory, but rather we eliminate
purposes from the universe. The greatest obstacle to progress, according to Dewey, is the
survival of old institutions such as the Church, and the best guarantee of freedom in the world is
the spread of the scientific method. Wherever there is science there is freedom, he declares. Or,
as Russell puts it, wherever there is science there is culture. Such is the superstition of Scientism.
Science is a very valid and necessary way of knowing, but only of knowing those things,
which are subject to experimentation and to the methods of a laboratory. The great values of life
such as justice, truth, and charity are beyond such experimentation. No one yet has ever been
able to put a mother's love into a test tube, and yet who will deny its reality. Nor can we throw a
man into a caldron to boil to see if he gives forth the unmistakable green fumes of envy and
jealousy. Once the modem mind denied that man was a creature made in the image and likeness
of God, it naturally fell into the error of saying that man was made in the image and likeness of
the beast. Man then ceased to be studied theologically or philosophically, and began to be
studied with the other sciences of nature, biology, physiology and physics. But this identification
of man with nature deprived man of all value. Once you make man a cog in a vast astronomical
machine, or a molecule in a spatio-temporal continuum, or an enlarged cell of some original
protoplasmic stuff, you deny that man has a right to be treated differently than anything in
nature. But, if man is not different from nature, then what value has man? If there is no specific
difference between a man and a horse, then why not yoke man to the plow of Nazism or the
tractor of Marxian Socialism, or make him an instrument of the State as the Fascist intelligentsia
teaches today.
The answer to this superstition of Scientism, which makes man meaningless by making
him one with nature, is not in the repudiation of science but in the recognition that there are
higher values beyond the ken of science. Professor Hocking, of Harvard University, speaking of
Scientism says, "This desiccated picture of the world is a damnable liefor values are there;
values are among the inescapable facts of the worldand whoever disseminates this death's-
head world-view in the schools and colleges of this era any other land is disseminating falsehood
with the brow-beaten connivance of a whole herd of intellectual sheep, and of culpable guardians
of the young. . . . This is one of the insights with which the new era of History begins." *
Scientism has ruined higher education in the United States by prostrating itself before the
god of counting, and by assuming that anyone who has counted something that has never been
counted before is a learned man. It makes no difference what you count, but in the name of
heaven, count! A certain western university has awarded a Doctor of Philosophy degree for a
thesis on the "Microbic Content of Cotton Undershirts." A mid-western university has counted
the ways of washing dishes; and some eastern universities have counted the infinitives in
82
Augustine, the datives in Ovid, and the four ways of cooking ham; while another counted the
"psychological reactions of the post-rotational eye-movement of squabs." These subjects seem
amusing when extracted from the context of universities, but the universities unfortunately take
them seriously. The result is we are giving our students theories, opinions and facts, which would
be out of date before the ink on the diploma fades; but we are not equipping them for life by
proposing its high purposes. In the madness of specialization we have come to know more and
more about less and less, but in the meantime we have lost ourselves in the maze of numbers.
Fed with huge quantities of undigested facts, our judgment has become hampered and we have
only unrelated bits of information instead of wisdom, which alone is true knowledge. Go into
any parochial school in the United States, take out a child in the first or second grade and ask
him: "Who made you?" "What is the purpose of life?" "Are you different from an animal?" Any
such child aged seven or eight could answer the question of the purpose of life. But ask a Ph.D.
graduate, who has counted the microbes on cotton undershirts, why he is here or where he is
going; he could not tell you.
He would not have a five-cent-gadget in his house five minutes without knowing its
purpose, but he would live ten, twenty or sixty years without knowing why he is here, or where
he is going. What is the use of living unless we know the purpose of being a man? It is not true,
as is so often asserted, that modem youth is revolutionary because he has lacked sufficient
economic advantages. Never in the history of the world did youth have so many advantages. The
modem youth is revolutionary because he has no purpose in life and hence doubts the
worthwhileness of living amidst plenty. Anything that loses its purpose becomes revolutionary.
When a boiler loses its purpose it explodes; when a man loses his purpose he revolts. Is it true, as
Dr. Dewey has said, that the use of the scientific method is the guarantee of freedom? What
country, before this world war began, was generally recognized as the most advanced in the
scientific method? To what nation of the world did our American universities look as the
paragon of scientific perfection, and from which did they draw their greatest scientific
inspiration? It was from Germany. And yet there is no country in the world where freedom is
more universally suppressed. Is it true, as a Mr. Russell affirms, that if you spread science you
spread culture? We gave Japan science. But will these philosophers of the superstition of
Scientism dare assert that culture went with it? The scientific method did not bring to a benighted
people an increase of tolerance and kindness and brotherhood. They have proven what we ought
to recognize; namely, that a high degree of scientific advancement can exist with utter and
absolute moral depravity.
We are paying the penalty for divorcing our science from God. Nature, which science
studies, belongs to God, and when man turns against God nature or science turns against man.
Francis Thompson beautifully spoke of this when he found that the whole world turned against
him because he would not answer the call of God:
I tempted all His servitors, but to find My own betrayal in their constancy. In faith to Him
their fickleness to me, their traitorous trueness, and their loyal deceit.
That is the true story: Nature will be false to anyone who is untrue to its Maker. I am free to
break the law of gravitation but if I do, the law breaks me. The law still stands. I am free to
ignore God the Creator of nature, but if I do, nature will wreck me. For years science has been
discovering the wonders of nature, finding in the tiny atom a miniature of the great solar system.
But, instead of glorifying God for the order, law, and harmony they found in His universe,
scientists vainly assumed that because they discovered the laws they were the authors of the
Book of Nature, instead of only its proofreaders.
83
Tearing nature away from God, nature now turned against man; refusing to serve God,
nature refused to serve man. The result is that science, which was supposed to be our servant is
now our master. Why do millions in the world shrink in terror from a machine in the air? Why
does man use his technique to destroy man? Why do children crouch in dread and mothers dig
like moles into the bowels of the earth as bombs fall from the skies, as all hell is let loose, if it is
not because something has gotten out of our control?
Science has become a source of destruction, because we refused to use it as a means for
lifting us to God. It is not that God has punished man for his ingratitude to nature; it is rather that
nature, in unconscious loyalty, has punished man for his disloyalty. No creature can be used for
the happiness of man, which has alienated itself from the service to its Creator. Something else
that we have forgotten in our glorification of science as the only true knowledge, is that science
itself has no morality. An isosceles triangle for example is no more moral than a square; vitamins
may be more hygienic than the pointer-readings, but they are not more ethical. The morality of
science is derived from the purpose for which it is used. But in denying all purposes in life, we
have made science its own justification. If there is no higher knowledge than science, how will
we know what is good or bad? Hitler, using science, spreads tyranny on a vast scale and
suppresses human rights and liberties through new weapons which science puts into his hands.
How shall we say he is unmoral and we, who use science to defend liberties, are moral, unless
there be a standard outside of both? Cannot we see that by making science an ultimate, we have
deprived ourselves of a criterion by which to judge our cause from theirs?
Divorce the products of science from the higher objectives of human life, which reason
and faith reveal to us, and you have a mad world wherein "humanity preys upon itself like
monsters of the deep."
The superstition of Relativism tells us there is no distinction between truth and error,
right and wrong; everything depends upon one's point of view. All values are relative and depend
entirely upon the way people live in any generation. If in the twentieth-century they live
monogamously, then monogamy is right; if in the future, they live polygamous, then polygamy is
right. Whatever the majority decides is right, and a Gallup Poll is the best way to find it out.
When expedient, moral conventions can be accepted; when a hindrance, they can be rejected.
There are no objective moral standards; no absolute distinction between good and evil. Everyone
is his own lawgiver; everyone is his own judge. Tolerance is the greatest virtue and tolerance
means indifference to truth and error, right and wrong. Such is Relativism. The superstition of
Relativism, or the notion that there is no absolute distinction between right and wrong, stems in
this country from the philosophy of Pragmatism. This philosophy denied that God was an
Absolute; it judged truth neither by its consistency, nor its correspondence with reality, but by its
utility. In the words of one of its best known exponents: Truth is to be judged by its "cash value
in terms of a particular experience." "The gods we stand by are the gods we need and can use."
"The 'true' to put it very briefly, is only the expedient in the way of thinking, just as the 'right' is
only the expedient in the way of our behaving, expedient in almost any fashion. In other words,
whatever succeeds is right." This particular philosophy was boom of an excessive adoration of
the scientific method.
Science evolved practical prescriptions for dealing with particular problems; when the
practical problems changed, the prescription changed. This method was practical in dealing with
84
phenomena, but the philosopher enlarged it to apply to all truth. Nothing was considered
immutable or changeable. Everything was relative to a point of view. Not being able to apply his
method to religion and morals, instead of acknowledging the insufficiency of his method, the
pragmatist denied the value of religion and morals. The pragmatists thus assume that the spiritual
and moral needs of man and a nation needed no other foundation than that of the utilitarian
activities associated with earning a living. Ideas thus were regarded as instruments of power.
These ideasthat there is no absolute distinction between truth and error, right and wrong, that
morality is determined by the subjective outlook of every individual and is devoid of all
objective standards,are taught in many secular colleges and universities in the United States. A
distinguished professor in a mid-western university revealed that there was not a single student in
his class who could give a rational justification for democracy. The students justified democracy
solely on the grounds of expediency and the fact that it had the greatest power; none saw any
intrinsic value in democracy. Very few saw the evil implications in a morality of self-advantage,
and some who did were reluctant to abandon it in a world where success was the measure of
greatness. It took a great catastrophe to bring home its falsity. And this is how it happened. What
moral standards are the Japs violating, if the criterion of truth and righteousness is expediency?
Why do we say that Japan has violated the conscience of the world, if the conscience- of the
world has no other measure than the useful? Incidentally, where was this moral conscience of the
world before the war began? How shall the Tightness of our cause be distinguished from the
Tightness of our enemies, if there is no objective standard outside of both? If there is no right
and wrong, independent of the whims of individuals, how shall we defend ourselves against
despotism? The ultimate bulwark of democracy is in the recognition of moral standards, so
absolute that citizens are willing in the end, if need be, to give everythingeven lifeto
maintain them. If there is no objective distinction between right and wrong, how can Hitler be
wrong? How can he be right? Our journalists, our educators, our movies, our best sellers, our
forums, and even some of the Churches have been sniping away for years at the moral law,
knocking off first its application to politics and economics, and then to the family, then the
individual. They have sneered at and ridiculed those who still held on to the moral law, calling
them "reactionary," "behind the times," and labelling purity and truthfulness as "bourgeois
virtues" in the language of Marx. They now say that all we need do about evil is to forget it, and
that faith and morality can be brought back into civilization as one might buy a commodity at a
drugstore. We have an active barbarism to defeat on the outside, and we have a passive
barbarism from within; the first is openly violent, the second is sinister and secretive. The first
endangers our shores, the second pollutes our souls the first would take away external liberties
such as freedom of speech and press, and the second would take away internal liberty, or the
right to call our soul our own. The first makes us stronger by the mere fact that we resist; the
second makes us weaker by the mere fact that like a cancer we are blind to its dangers. We could
defeat the enemy on the outside, and still completely collapse from the inside. We could win the
war and lose peace. "Fear ye not them that kill the body and are not able to kill the soul: but
rather fear him that can destroy both soul and body in hell" (Mt. 10: 28).
When Colin Kelly as a selfless pilot sank the first Japship of this war and in doing so lost
his life; when Edward O'Hara shot down the first Jap plane; when Dick Fleming made himself
the first human torpedo; when Daniel O'Callaghan became the first Admiral to go down fighting
on the bridge of the San Francisco; when Mike Moran became the first naval officer to sink six
Jap ships in single combat; when Commander Shea became the first fighting man whose last
letter to his son became a famous American testament on patriotism ; when the five Sullivans
85
became the first American family of boys to be snuffed out in this war; these men had no
"opinion" about America's cause; they did not believe that the righteousness of the stars and
stripes depended upon this subjective outlook. They believed in an absolute distinction between
right and wrong, our cause and our enemy; in fact, so much did they believe in it that life was
secondary to that cause. And while these and millions of men in our armed forces believe in such
an absolute distinction between right and wrong, our Fascist intelligentsia are telling us: "right
and wrong are relative to expediency; it all depends upon your point of view." Nonsense! It does
not! Our cause is right! It is right before God! It is right under God! And in God's name we will
defend it!
The superstition of Materialism affirms that man has no soul, that there is no future life,
and that man has no other destiny than that of the animals. Being devoid of spirit man may best
be described not as a creature made to the image and likeness of God but as a "psychoanalytical
bag with physiological libido," or a "stimulus response mechanism." Since there is no future life,
it follows that the good life consists in material improvement; that civilization and culture vary in
direct ratio with wealth and the two chickens in every pot; that want is the greatest cause of
misery and unhappiness, and that abundance is the surest guarantee of peace and happiness.
Goodness, truth, honor, and beauty are natural by-products of the increase of national dividends.
The end of life is the acquisition of money, the ceaseless enjoyment of pleasure, and the
avoidance of sacrifice. Such is the superstition of Materialism. It simply is not true that peace
follows material prosperity, and unhappiness follows the want of it; rather unhappiness flows
from loss of a goal and purpose of life through the denial of the human soul. It is not economic
hardship nor political injustice, which has driven modem man to revolutionary action: it is the
horror of an empty sterile world. Men lived with only the necessities of life before, but they were
never as revolutionary as they are today. Religious communities throughout the Qiurch survive
on the minimum of existence, with vows of poverty, chastity and obedience, and where shall you
find greater happiness? The major frustrations of life are not economic. Glance around at those
who possess abundance of material goods. Does happiness increase with wealth? There is more
frustration among the rich than the poor. It is the former who are most addicted to selfishness,
who are satiated and unhappy. Sin and evil do not disappear with the advent of gold. Society can
become inhuman while preserving all the advantages of great material prosperity.
The materialist superstition that man has no other end than this life, and no other task
than economic betterment, and that education must produce a race of doers rather than an
"impractical" race of knowers, will eventually build a civilization in which we will have no
standards to judge what is economically good or socially bad. The philosopher could make a
good world without the economist, but the economist could not make one without the
philosopher. By making acquisitiveness supreme, we lose all standards of knowing what is right
or wrong. Social reform then has no other inspiration than envy. As Tawney says of them: "They
denounce, and rightly, the injustices of capitalism; but they do not always realize that capitalism
is maintained not only by capitalists but by those who, like some of themselves, would be
capitalists if they could, and that these injustices survive, not merely because the rich exploit the
poor, but because in their hearts too many of the poor admire the rich. They know and complain
that they are tyrannized over by the power of money. But they do not yet see that what makes
86
money the tyrant of society is largely their own reverence of it." And to complete Tawney's
picture, if we make material standards the only standards, then we become incapable of judging
the new acquisitive society, which is arisingthe acquisitiveness of power. As fortunes dwindle,
as taxes eat up inheritances, and as bureaucracies begin to administer vast sums of money
formerly administered by capitalists and bankers, envious, greedy and lustful men will seek to
become dispensers of that social booty, and who shall say that these new financiers of power are
wrong? Given no standards other than materialism, wherein remorse is disjoined from power,
and we will have a new capitalism - the capitalism of power, wherein the bureaucrats become the
bankers. Bidding the law makes courtesy to their will; Hooking both right and wrong to the
appetite, To follow as it draws!
*
The modern man wants back his soul! He wants the intelligentsia to stop the nonsense of
regarding him as an animal, a libido, a tool-maker, or a voter and to begin to look at him as a
creature made in the image and likeness of God. It is pathetic to hear people asking: "What can I
as an individual do in this crisis?" So many feel that they are like robots in a great machine, that
they would like to get away from it all, even if it meant climbing back into the Catacombs. Like
the Jews in exile they hang their harps on the trees, and ask how they can sing a song without a
soul. In plain, simple language, all these individuals want their souls back! They want to be
whole again. They are sick of being thrown into a Darwinian pot to boil as a beast, or into a
Freudian stew to squirm as a libido, or thrust into the Marxian sandwich to be squeezed between
two conflicting slices of capital and labor. They want to possess that which makes them human,
gives meaning to politics, economics, psychology, sociology; namely, the soul.
Listen to them: "I want my soul back; that I may be free from earth; that I may surrender
it to Him. I want to hold my own life, as a responsible creature, in my own hands, that I may
emancipate it not only from Nature, but even from the man-made environment. Somewhere I am
lost amid organized chaos. Everywhere I hear talk about freedom, but how can I be free unless I
have a soul? Stones are not free; neither are cows or cabbages. From every side I am told I have
no soul. If I have no soul, then I have nothing to lose, and if I have nothing to lose why should I
feel unhappy when I sin? "In my misery I go to the modern world and it tells me that I need to be
integrated with society, and hence I must throw myself into the vast social experiences and
sociological adventuring. But society cannot help me, for it is in the same mess as I. Society is
made up of millions of frustrated souls exactly like myself. How can it cure me, when it has the
same disease? Then the world tells me I should have ideals, for no one can live without faith;
give yourself over to aims, and you will find your soul. But when I ask whether these ideals are
real, such as God and the moral law, I am told that they are myths; that it makes no difference
whether there is a God, or Christ ever lived, or that there is any reason behind these ideals; but
that they are just helpful fictions. "I am thus back to where I was at the beginning. I am told I
should have faith, but the world can give me none; I am told to have ideals and at the same time
told that they are only fictions. I am not an animal, not a libido, not a proletarian, not an atom; I
am something else, more and greater than these things. And I want to be more! I want back my
soul!" *
To get back our souls we have to turn our backs on all the twaddle we have been fed for
the last century about the nature of man. We might just as well put it bluntly, and say that what
we call modern is only an old error with a new label. The modem view of man is wrong
completely and absolutely wrong, and if we go on following it we will end in blind alleys,
87
frustrated hopes and unhappy existences. It is not nearly as funny as we thought to make a
monkey out of a man.
The millions of our boys on the battlefronts of the world, fighting for their lives and for
great moral issues, will recover their souls. Amidst wounds of death, fire and shell, they will get
close to the meaning of life and to that something within them that makes them human. They will
be angry when they look back on the way some of them were educated. They will come to hate
not only the enemy they meet in battle, but the intelligentsia who told them they were only
animals. They will begin to realize that these intelligentsia robbed them of their greatest
possessionfaith. For a while they will wander around the battlefields like Magdalene in the
Garden saying: "They have taken away my Lord, and I know not where they laid Him." But
when they do stumble on Him as Magdalene did when she saw the livid marks of nails, they will
enter once again into the possession of the soul. And when they come marching home there will
be a judgment on those who told them they had no soul; they will live like new men and they
will give a rebirth to America under God. Recovering our souls demand doing two things:
turning our backs completely on the way the modem world thinks, and facing our Divine
Original, Who made us and Who alone can tell us what we are. Instead of drifting with the
current into the abyss of hopeless paganism, we must learn to swim against it like the salmon
back to the spawning ground where man is born again.
The superstition of License here means perverted freedom. It defines freedom as the right
to do whatever you please or the absence of law, restraint, and discipline. A man is considered
free when his desires are satisfied; he is not free when they are unsatisfied. The goal of freedom
is self-expression. Such is the superstition of License. This superstition is grounded on a false
definition of freedom. Freedom does not mean the right to do whatever we please. If it did, it
would be a physical power, not a moral power. Certainly, we can do whatever we please, but
ought we? Freedom means the right to do whatever we ought, and therefore is inseparable from
law. It was precisely because we made freedom consist in the right to do whatever we pleased,
that we produced a civilization, which was nothing but a criss-cross of individual egotisms in the
economic, political and international order. Communism, Nazism and Fascism arose to organize
that chaos and became as so many convulsive attempts to arrest a disintegration by the false
method of going to the other extreme, by extinguishing all freedom in order to preserve law.
The solution lies along other lines, namely that we are most free when we act within the
law and not outside it. An aviator is most free to fly when he obeys the law of gravitation. As
Our Lord said: "The truth will make you free." Nor is it true that freedom consists in the shaking-
off of convention and tradition and authority. What is called self-expression is in reality often
nothing else than self-destruction. The railroad engine that suddenly becomes so "progressive"
88
that it will not follow the tracks laid out by an engineer of a previous generation soon discovers
that it is not "free" to be an engine at all. If freedom means only the lessening of authority, then
we shall have indeed the thrill of risk, but in the end we shall have no freedom. As Leo XIII
expressed it, "liberty will ever be more free and secure, in proportion as license is kept in
restraint." About the only curbs, which the sensate man allows himself are those which
contribute to his own physical well-being. Dieting is about the only discipline left, and dieting is
not fasting. Dieting is for the body; fasting is for the soul. Moral restraints, spiritual discipline,
ascetic life, denial of evil thoughts and temptations, restraint in the use of the legitimate
pleasures of lifethese things are meaningless to the modem man who feels he has sufficient
warrant in throwing off moral standards for no other reason than because they are old. When we
reach a point where we measure our self-expression by the height of the pile of our discarded
disciplines, inhibitions, and moral standards, then anyone who would die to preserve that
disemboweled ghost of liberty is a fool.
Salvation lies in the fact that freedom exists for a purpose; that is, we have freedom to
give it away. No one keeps his freedom. A man in love surrenders it to the woman he loves and
calls it a "sweet slavery"; the modem man who has thrown off morality surrenders it to public
opinion, becomes the slave of fashion and passing moods; the Christian who uses his freedom
gives it to God, "to serve Whom is to reign" and then purchases the slavery of the Infinite in
Whom is Love and Life and Truth. Every freedom is for the sake of bondage, and we are all in
bondageto a fellow creature, to the mob, to Hitler, or to God Who alone can make us truly
free. That is why freedom for freedom's sake is meaningless. I want to be free from something,
only because I want to be free for something. That is why freedom is inseparable from purpose.
Freedom from restraint is justified only when it depends on freedom for something else. The
fallacy of the superstition of License is that it makes us free just to be free, which is as
meaningless and as unsatisfying as a cold in the head. The superstition of License assumes that
men will always do the right thing if they are educated; hence they need no restraint and no
discipline. And here we touch on the basic weakness of Sensate education; namely, it assumes
that sin is due to ignorance and not to the abuse of freedom. When evil was attributed to the will,
the school belonged to the Church. Now that we believe there is no sin, and that what we call
evil is only want of enlightenment, the school stands in isolation from religion and morality.
Schools once belonged to religious groups in order that moral training of the will might keep
pace with enlightenment of the intellect. Now the universities have for the most part lost all
concern for the will. When confronted with the problem of evil, they immediately rush to a
conference to discuss greater knowledge, when what is really needed is more discipline.
The Sensate culture is right in saying that sin is irrational because every sin is a violation
of a law of Eternal Reason, but the unreason or ignorance is not the citadel of sin. A man sins,
not because he is ignorant, but because he is perverse. The intellect makes mistakes, but the will
sins. A man may know all we teach him and still be a bad man; the intelligentsia are not
necessarily the saints. The ignorant are not necessarily devils. Enlightenment and education can
become the servants of a perverse will, and when they do it is like hell being let loose. Unless a
man's will has a purpose and it is a good one, education will do nothing for him except to fortify
his own egotism.
There is an almost unpardonable naivet about those who say that reason alone can
conquer anarchic impulses. Rather, the reverse is true. Reason can be used just as easily to justify
evil, to rationalize evil, to destroy supernatural truths and, in the form of science, to invent lethal
instruments for the defence of those wicked tendencies in time of war.
89
Reason was made to lead us to faith as the senses were made to lead us to reason. Now
when reason is torn up from its roots in God, how can we trust its conclusions? If chance, blind
evolution, or chaos were its origin, then why should it now be expected to be anything less than
chaotic, unstable and fluid? An age which has put all its trust in enlightenment as the cure of evil
has found itself possessed of the greatest evil and war in the history of the world. These
superstitions constitute the cult of our contemporary Western Civilization. The chaos into which
they have led us reveals their fallacies more effectively than any intellectual argument. The so-
called progressive man, who today is bewildered, baffled and depressed at the disorder in the
world need only go into his own godless disordered interior life to find its secret; the man
without moral standards and therefore chaotic is the miniature of the world without a moral
standard and therefore at war. If these superstitions still exercise some influence, it is only
because of artificial respiration given them by two classes of reactionarieseconomic
reactionaries and intellectual reactionaries.
The economic reactionaries are those who believe that any system, which enables them to get
rich must necessarily be a good system; hence any change in the existing order they regard as
radicalism, revolutionism or Communism. The intellectual reactionaries are the intelligentsia (we
use that word to distinguish them from true intellectuals).
By the intelligentsia we mean those who have been educated beyond their intelligence.
Like the economic reactionaries they equate what they have with what is best, the difference
being that their wealth is ideological, not material. Their clichs, catch-words, and ideologies
have value only in a world of a chaos which produced two world wars in twenty-one years; but
they would be without validity any other time or in any other order based on justice and charity.
They would be just as out of place in such a world as a teeter-totter in an old folks' home. A
high-school youngster who thinks the "Jersey Bounce" is the highest expression of music would
be lost at a concert of Toscanini. Despite these two reactionary forces, it should now be
recognized that these superstitions have failed to provide an adequate dynamic for either peace or
war. The longer we try to keep them alive, the ruder will be our awakening; the more terrible will
be our judgment. It is no answer to retort with the old clich that religion has been the enemy of
science, for he who has eyes can see that science today is the enemy of man.
It is not religion, which has tyrannized man. Science has its place in the world; this we
not only admitthis we insist upon. But its place is not at the peak of the pyramid of knowledge
where Descartes placed it when he enthroned mathematics, or where Kant placed it when he
enthroned physics, and where Comte placed it when he enthroned sociology. That place belongs
to theology, the one science, which makes a university, for as the word "university" implies all
knowledge and all sciences and all arts turn on one axis, which is God. Cardinal Newman in his
masterly treatise, "The Idea of a University" allowed the imagination to run riot by picturing a
university of the future where there would be no theology. To bring home the horror of such a
condition, he described it as follows: "Henceforth, man is to be as if he were not, in the general
course of Education; the moral and mental sciences are to have no professional chairs, and the
treatment of them is to be left as a matter of private judgment, which each individual may carry
out as he will. I can just fancy such a prohibition abstractly possible; but one thing I cannot fancy
possible, viz.: that the parties in question, after this sweeping act of exclusion, should henceforth
send out proposals on the basis of such exclusion for publishing an Encyclopedia, or erecting a
National University." But these conditions are upon us now, and so strongly entrenched is the
opposition that to plead for a return of theology to university curricula would be to bring down
90
upon one's head the wrath of those intelligentsia who still live in the Dark Ages and still feed on
the superstition that the proper way to study man is to study nature. Someday under the pressure
of catastrophe we will come to see that as science reveals nature, so theology reveals man. In that
day, universities will be universities. In this conflict we must not save everything just as it is nor
seek to maintain the status quo, nor preserve an empire, nor get back the kind of a world that
existed before this war began, for if we did we would be fighting to keep a world from whose
womb came the satellites of anti- Christ: Hitler and Hirohito and others.
Some things are not worth fighting for. One of these things is an unredeemed,
materialistic selfish order, organized on the basis of neglect of God and the abandonment of
moral standards. The victors who won the war of 1918 lost the peace because they attempted to
keep a world together on the basis of the outworn slogans and the really bad philosophy of the
French Revolution. Our peace-makers, inspired more by the expiring convulsions of a liberal
world boom 150 years before, became blinded to the needs of a new world expressed in the
protests of the revolutions of Germany, Italy and Russia. We won the war because we were
stronger; we lost the peace because we tried to keep everything together on the basis of the
liberalistic, capitalistic, individualistic, irreligious world of the outworn nineteenth century.
Napoleon carried the ideas of the French Revolution over Europe. Hitler carried the ideas of
Marx over Europe. Both have done a service. Both swept away the litter of a bad world; one a
monarchical world based on privilege of power, the other the capitalistic world based on the
privilege of money. Both are wrong. He who would will to keep either privilege of power or
money will keep only the dynamite for the next world war. We are not out to preserve either the
Marxian or the French Revolutionwe are at war this time to build an order not for the common
man, spoon-fed by democracies, but for common service to a common good: a world of free men
free from economic want and therefore free to save their souls. This is worth fighting for!
When the ship is sinking, we must not think of the cargo. It is neither the ship of
democracy nor the ship of America, nor the ship of our Four Freedoms we must abandon. But
the barnacles we must abandon. Our task is not the restoration of everything as it was; restoration
could be our greatest obstacle to peace. It is regeneration we are seeking. No sane person would
suggest that when this war is over London should rebuild its bombed buildings just exactly as
they were, just as no sane person would suggest the restoration of a world which in fifteen years
vomited three terrific revolutions: red, brown and black. Nor would he suggest that we re-
establish the same old boundaries, the same sovereignties and the same anemic League of
Nations. Blind indeed would anyone be who suggests that we preserve the present order. There is
one other order and that is our hopethe Christian order, which starts with man.
91
CHAPTER THREE: A RETURN TO THE PHILOSOPHIA PERENNIS
The term perennial means permanent. It upholds that truth is not changed
and eroded through the elapse of time. This philosophy is attributed to the
philosophy of Aristotle and St. Thomas Aquinas. Others call it the Philosophy of
Common Sense (G.K. Chesterton), Primeval Platitudes (Peter Kreeft) or the Tao
(C.S. Lewis).
The crisis of truth and the collapse of civilization convince us that there is
a great and a dire need to return to perennial philosophy, which is the natural
standard of human rationality.55
(1) To regain our lost humanity. C.S. Lewis describes these new
ideologies as the rebellion of the branches against the tree, if the
rebels would succeed, they would find that they have destroyed
themselves.56 When man refuses to acknowledge the supernatural, he
becomes unnatural.57 When man refuses to be human, he descends into
the level of subhuman.58 Fulton Sheen writes in his book God and
Intelligence contending that the erroneous modern systems of thought
is a direct assault to mans intelligence. It tries to mold a new man
49
Fulton
J.
Sheen,
God
and
Intelligence,
14.
50
Pope
Benedict
XVI,
Freedom,
Truth
and
Tolerance
51
Carlos
A.
Walker,
The
Missionary
Pope,
45.
52
Ibid,
54.
The modern man focuses on the functional truth but not the truth about
himself. Hand in hand with the growing knowledge of functional truth,
there seems to be an increasing blindness toward truth itself- toward the
question of mans real identity and purpose.62 This has lead to scientific
projects that does not acknowledge the real value of man, such as cloning,
the production of fetuses- that is of people simply in order to use their
organs for developing pharmaceutical products.63
There is a grave split between science and morality, between humanity and
spirituality. Our modern schools focus to teach us solving mathematical
problems, learning how to increase incomes, generating more profits,
producing more technologies but not so much not to make a man a better
person.
59
Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, Truth and Tolerance, 158.
60
John
Paul
II,
Fides
et
Ratio,
16-17.
61
Gaudium
et
Spes
22.
62
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth
3. The need to return to St. Thomas Aquinas
For all the reasons stated above, the Holy Catholic Church honors St.
Thomas as: Common Doctor of the Church, Angelic Doctor, Heavenly Patron of
Highest Studies, Patron of Catholic Schools and Universities and Apostle of Truth.
The Church herself embraces the doctrine of St. Thomas as her own doctrinexxiv.
Thus we have to be formed under his magisteriumxxv, and hold him especially
as a teacherxxvi
Better than anyone else, Fabro has been able to define the speculative
essence of Thomism as the comprehensive overcoming of Aristotelianism and
Platonism. His genetic, historical and critical study of original Thomism drove him
to assert the centrality of the metaphysical notion of participation, through which
the metaphysical understanding of creatures always has to be read.
b. The defense of the main thesis of authentic Thomism
Fabro also can be credited for denouncing the formalist downward trend of the
Thomistic school, which was increasingly adopting the terminology of its
opponents in order to ease the pressure of several controversies. In this way, the
school ended up reducing the value of the Thomistic thesis and sometimes even
encouraging the opposite position (gaetanistic principle of the mihi aliter
dicendum est).
Fabro himself considered his magnificent speculation about freedom as the last
step in the overcoming of formalism and Western rationalism. This speculation,
which might be seen as the fulfillment of all his merits, is a controversial point and
has been the cause of rejections even among some sectors of Thomism. However,
apart from every polemical aspect, the merit of Fabros touching the central point
of modern thought has to be recognized.
i
Fides
et
Ratio,
6.
ii
Leo
XIII,
Aeterni
Patris
iii
Pope
Paul
VI,
Lumen
Ecclessiae,
22.
iv
Leo
XIII,
Aeterni
Patris
22.
vi
Cf.
Declaration
on
Christian
Education,
Gravissimum
Educationis,
n.
10:
AAS
58,
1966,
p.
737.
vii
Pius
XI,
Encyclical
Studiorum
Ducem,
AAS
15,
1923,
p.
324.
viii
Pope
Leo
XIII,
Aeterni
Patris,
23.
ix
St.
Pius
V,
Mirabilis
Deus;
cf.
Leo
XIII,
Aeteni
Patris
13.
x
Pope
Innocent
VI,
Sermo
de
S.
Thoma.
37.
Bucer,
14.
xiPerennial
Philosophy
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
for
the
Youth
of
our
Times.
St.
John
Paul
IIs
Address
at
Angelicum
1980.)
xiii
Discorsi
di
Pio
XII,
vol.
I,
Turin
1960,
pp.
668-669.
xiv
Perennial
Philosophy
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
for
the
Youth
of
our
Times.
St.
John
Paul
IIs
Address
at
xvii Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I-II, p.109, a. I ad 1: Ed, Leonina, v. VII, p. 290.
xxii Cardinal Thomas Cajetan, Commentary on Summa Theologiae, II-II, 148, 9,4. Quoted by Leo XIII, Aeterni
Patris, 10.
xxiii
John XXII, Allocution in the Consistory, July 14, 1323.
Part
IV.
PHILOSOPHY
AND
CHRISTIANITY
A.
THEOLOGY
AS
SCIENCE
A.1.
REASON
AND
FAITH
We
have
to
state,
in
the
first
place,
that
faith
does
not
destroy
reason;
rather,
it
goes
beyond
it
and
gives
fullness
or
perfection
to
it.
Faith
is
a
supernatural
virtue
by
which,
we,
inspired
and
helped
by
Gods
grace,
believe
as
true
what
God
has
revealed,
not
because
of
the
intrinsic
truth
of
things
perceived
by
the
natural
light
of
reason,
but
because
of
the
authority
of
God
Himself
revealing
them,
who
can
neither
deceive
nor
be
deceived.
The
Christian
faith
leads
us
to
a
firmer
assent
to
truths
that
can
be
known
by
reason,
such
as
those
about
God,
the
human
soul,
and
the
natural
law,
and
besides,
to
the
acceptance
of
truth
that
the
human
mind
cannot
attain
through
its
natural
power.
Faith
in
revelation
does
not
end
up
destroying
the
rationality
of
our
knowledge.
Rather,
it
allows
it
to
develop
more
fully.
Just
as
grace
does
not
destroy
nature
but
rather
heals
and
perfects
it
and
renders
it
fruitful,
so
too,
faith,
through
the
influence
it
exerts
from
above
on
reason
as
such,
allows
the
development
of
a
more
fruitful
and
genuine
rational
activity.
Faith
presupposes
reason.
If
a
person
did
no
have
the
capacity
to
attain
intellectual
knowledge,
he
could
not
be
raised
to
the
knowledge
of
supernatural
truths.
Besides,
these
supernatural
truths
are
beyond
reason,
but
not
contrary
to
it.
They
somehow
rely
on
rational
knowledge,
since
a
person
gets
a
glimpse
of
them
through
rational
concepts.
For
instance,
without
a
rational
knowledge
of
the
meaning
of
concepts
such
as
person,
nature,
and
God,
a
person
would
not
be
able
to
understand
anything
about
the
mysteries
of
the
Blessed
Trinity
and
the
Incarnation.
Nevertheless,
we
have
to
say,
too,
that
reason
is
healed
and
elevated
by
faith.
Faith
illumines
the
darkness
in
which
reason
dwells
as
a
consequence
of
sin.
It
also
makes
it
easier
for
reason
to
know
the
basic
truths
it
can
attain
by
itself,
and
raises
it
to
the
knowledge
of
supernatural
truths
that
are
completely
beyond
it
natural
power.
These
two
levels
of
knowledge
are
present
in
the
believer,
even
though
they
are
distinct
and
separable,
as
one
can
see
when
a
person
loses
his
faith.
Through
the
use
of
reason,
a
person
can
know
a
set
of
truth
called
preambles
of
faith,
because
they
serve
as
a
basis
for
revealed
supernatural
truths.
They
include
the
existence
of
God,
the
spirituality
and
immortality
of
the
human
soul,
human
freedom
and
the
natural
law.
Although
these
truths
can
be
known
through
the
use
of
natural
reason,
God
revealed
them
as
well,
so
that
they
may
be
known
by
everyone,
even
in
the
present
state
of
human
race,
with
ease,
with
solid
certitude,
and
with
no
trace
of
error.
Hence,
compared
with
an
unbeliever,
the
believer
is
in
a
better
position
to
make
good
use
if
reason
in
tackling
the
basic
problems
of
human
existence,
whose
inherent
difficulties
are
heightened
by
the
consequences
of
sin.
Since
revealed
truths
are
backed
by
Gods
authority,
they
offer
a
greater
certitude
than
that
attained
through
merely
natural
truths.
However,
the
misuse
of
reason
can
hinder
the
acceptance
of
faith.
This
may
happen,
for
instance,
when
a
person
erroneously
strives
to
derive
from
the
sciences
arguments
contrary
to
revealed
truths.
In
these
cases,
the
right
use
of
reason
will
suffice
to
show
that
those
alleged
difficulties
are
baseless.
The
truth
is
that
reason
is
helped
and
guided
by
faith
in
its
task,
and
faith
clearly
points
out
to
it
where
errors
lie.
It
is
important
to
note
that
aside
from
those
errors
directly
contrary
to
the
truths
of
faith,
there
are
others,
which
are
indirectly
contrary
to
them,
through
their
consequences.
This
is
the
case
of
doctrines,
which
give
rise
to
conclusions
incompatible
with
the
faith
when
they
are
coherently
led
to
their
ultimate
consequences.
Examples
of
these
are:
philosophical
positions
affirming
that
man
can
never
gave
certainty
in
his
knowledge
of
reality,
or
that
he
cannot
know
reality
s
it
really
is.
Materialist
evolutionism,
for
instance,
is
contrary
to
the
faith.
Nevertheless,
it
is
easy
to
prove
that
materialism
cannot
be
based
on
science
or
on
any
rational
grounds.
Kantian
doctrines
are
indirectly
against
the
faith.
By
ruling
out
the
possibility
of
knowing
reality
as
it
really
is,
they
destroy
the
rational
basis
if
the
faith.
At
times,
the
alleged
difficulties
in
accepting
the
faith
come
from
more
sweeping
general
attitudes.
For
instance,
some
people
say
science
progresses
by
taking
hold
of
fields
that
were
previously
entrusted
to
faith.
In
the
case
of
the
Christian
faith,
this
stand
is
outrightly
erroneous.
There
is
no
single
truth
contained
in
Catholic
doctrine
that
has
been
or
can
possibly
be
suppressed
by
scientific
progress.
A.2.
WHAT
THEOLOGY
IS?
Theology
is
the
science
of
faith.
It
is
the
science,
which
deals
with
God
and
creatures
in
so
far
as
they
refer
to
God,
in
the
light
of
divine
revelation.
When
we
speak
of
theology
in
this
chapter,
we
obviously
refer
to
supernatural
theology
whose
starting
point
is
faith
in
divine
revelation.
We
have
already
seen
that
natural
theology,
which
studies
what
can
be
known
about
God
through
reason,
is
a
part
of
metaphysics,
and
therefore,
of
philosophy.
The
subject
matter
of
theology,
therefore,
includes:
- God
in
Himself:
His
existence,
essence
and
attributes
(such
as
infinity,
providence),
as
well
as
the
Trinity
of
Persons
in
God;
- And
the
works
of
God:
creation
and
created
beings,
the
elevation
of
man
to
the
supernatural
level,
the
Incarnation
and
Redemption,
the
Church,
the
sacraments.
Theology
studies
all
reality
in
the
light
of
divine
revelation,
from
the
most
profound
perspective
man
can
have,
that
is,
the
supernatural
light
of
faith.
Hence,
it
is
the
science
that
fully
represents
the
concept
of
wisdom.
As
a
supreme
wisdom,
theology
has
the
right
to
judge
and
guide
all
the
other
branches
ok
knowledge,
without
making
them
lose
their
own
autonomy.
All
these
topics
are
studied
in
theology
by
using
reason
enlightened
by
revelation.
The
source
of
theological
knowledge
is
revelation,
transmitted
through
Sacred
Scripture
and
Tradition,
and
safeguarded
and
interpreted
in
an
authentic
way
by
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church.
Therefore,
faith
is
the
starting
point,
the
foundation
and
norm
of
theology.
A
statement
contrary
to
faith
would
be
unacceptable,
even
though
it
might
be
expressed
with
the
trappings
of
theological
terminology.
A
theological
doctrine
contrary
to
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
would
be
automatically
erroneous.
Theological
study
and
research
demands
adequate
personal
dispositions,
especially
those
related
to
the
faith
and
to
fidelity
to
the
mission
of
the
Church
in
union
with
its
authentic
Magisterium.
The
essential
link
between
theology
and
faith,
based
and
focused
on
Christ,
illumines
with
great
clarity
the
bond
existing
between
theology
and
the
Church
with
its
Magisterium.
One
cannot
believe
in
Christ
without
believing
in
the
Church,
the
Body
of
Christ.
One
cannot
have
a
Catholic
belief
in
the
Church
without
believing
in
its
irrenounceable
Magisterium
Hence,
the
ecclesial
Magisterium
is
not
something
alien
to
theology,
but
rather
something
intrinsic
and
essential
to
it.
If
a
theologian
id
basically
and
above
all
a
believer,
and
if
his
Christian
faith
is
faith
in
the
Church
of
Christ
and
in
the
Magisterium,
his
theological
effort
will
certainly
remain
faithfully
linked
to
his
ecclesial
faith,
whose
authentic
and
binding
interpreter
is
the
Magisterium.
The
correct
use
of
reason
allows
us
to
go
deeper
into
the
content
of
revealed
truths.
However,
through
the
natural
power
of
reason
alone,
we
cannot
attain
the
knowledge
of
supernatural
mysteries
and
accept
them.
Neither
can
we
proceed
to
demonstrate
them
once
they
have
been
known.
The
theological
process
should
not
be
regarded
as
some
sort
of
centrifugal
movement
through
which,
starting
from
an
essential
nucleus
of
faith,
one
derives
conclusions
which
are
progressively
distant
from
the
center
and
increasingly
irrelevant
from
the
perspective
of
Christian
living.
It
should
rather
be
seen
as
a
centripetal
movement,
for
its
task
is
to
bring
towards
its
center
all
truth
and
knowledge
in
order
to
illumine
them.
Theology
is
something
that
internally
belongs
to
the
faith;
it
is
based
on
faith
and
serves
it.
Thus,
theology
is
not
a
form
of
knowledge
dissociated
from
Christian
living.
Its
mission
is
to
illumine
the
most
varied
practical
problems
through
the
light
provided
by
an
in-
depth
view
of
the
truths
of
faith.
The
Christian
faith
presupposes
both
an
objective
content
and
personal
proximity
to
God.
Hence,
as
a
science
of
faith,
theology
seeks
to
help
the
person
get
closer
to
God,
by
giving
him
a
better
knowledge
of
God
Himself
and
of
the
truths
He
has
revealed,
and
illumining
with
that
knowledge
the
problems
and
concerns
of
human
existence.
A.3.
THE
ROLE
OF
REASON
IN
THEOLOGY
In
line
with
what
we
have
previously
seen,
we
should
state
that
in
theology
we
make
use
of
reason
enlightened
by
faith.
Reason
and
faith
are
two
distinct
sources
of
knowledge.
They
are
not
mutually
opposed;
rather,
they
complement
one
another.
The
role
of
reason
in
theology
is
not
to
demonstrate
the
supernatural
truths
of
faith,
but
to
attain
a
greater
understanding
of
them.
For
this,
it
has
recourse
to
analogies
found
in
the
natural
order
of
things,
and
takes
into
account
the
interconnection
of
divine
mysteries
and
their
relation
to
mans
last
end.
Even
though
we
may
draw
up
some
rational
explanation
of
the
truths
of
faith,
it
is
quite
clear
that
they
will
continue
to
be
mysteries
for
us.
Theological
errors
oftentimes
arise
as
a
consequence
of
wanting
to
make
supernatural
truths
more
understandable.
For
example,
from
a
purely
natural
point
of
view,
it
might
seem
more
reasonable
to
reduce
the
Eucharist
to
a
symbol
through
which
God
works
in
a
special
manner,
or
to
affirm
that
Jesus
Christ
is
a
human
person
in
whom
God
acted
in
a
unique
way.
However,
doing
so
will
not
be
a
way
of
expounding
s
true
Christian
theology.
It
would
mean
deforming
and
mutilating
the
content
of
the
faith,
and
in
the
final
analysis,
reducing
the
theological
endeavor
to
a
useless,
meaningless
and,
above
all,
false
activity.
Through
the
correct
use
of
reason
enlightened
by
faith,
theology
carries
out
the
following
tasks:
(a) The
demonstration
of
the
preambles
of
faith,
in
the
theoretical
aspect
(the
existence
of
God
and
of
the
human
soul,
for
instance),
in
the
historical
aspect
(the
authenticity
of
Sacred
Scripture,
the
Catholic
Church
as
the
Church
founded
by
Christ,
for
example),
and
in
the
personal
aspect
(analysis
of
the
faith,
its
rational
foundation,
for
instance).
This
task
is
carried
out
by
Fundamental
Theology.
Reason
provides
for
this
task
arguments
that
are
truly
demonstrative
at
times.
At
other
times,
however,
these
arguments
only
show
the
conformity
of
faith
with
the
demands
of
human
nature.
For
these
purposes,
one
may
rely
on
philosophy,
history
and
psychology,
and
secondarily,
on
other
sciences.
(b) The
systematic
study
of
Sacred
Scripture,
with
the
help
provided
by
human
sciences.
This
is
carried
out
by
Exegesis
of
Sacred
Scripture.
Historical
as
well
as
linguistic
knowledge
is
widely
employed
in
this
field.
Nevertheless,
one
has
to
bear
in
mind
that
Sacred
Scripture
must
be
interpreted
according
to
its
own
nature,
hence,
in
the
light
of
faith.
This
has
important
consequences.
For
instance,
the
unity
and
truthfulness
of
scriptural
texts,
in
accordance
with
their
respective
literary
forms,
should
be
regarded
as
a
given
fact,
and
not
a
conclusion
that
still
has
to
be
reached.
(c) The
systematic
study
of
Tradition.
Patrology
us
the
study
of
the
doctrine
that
the
Fathers
of
the
Church
have
left
us
as
a
legacy.
The
study
of
Tradition
necessarily
complements
the
exegesis
of
Sacred
Scripture,
for
the
guarantees
concerning
Scripture
and
its
correct
interpretation
come
from
Tradition.
(d) The
study
of
the
truths
of
faith,
which
seeks
to
grasp
their
content,
examine
the
relationships
existing
among
them,
and
facilitate
our
understanding
of
them
through
analogies
taken
from
the
natural
order
of
things.
This
is
done
by
Dogmatic
Theology.
In
order
to
carry
out
these
tasks,
theology
makes
use
of
reason
and
of
philosophical
doctrines,
which
enable
a
person
to
rigorously
deepen
his
understanding
of
revealed
truths.
Obviously,
doctrines
such
as
immanentism,
existentialism,
and
historicism
are
hardly
suitable
for
theological
use.
Theology
understandably
demands
philosophical
foundations
in
conformity
with
common
sense
and
objectivity,
which
faith
presupposes,
and
these
foundations
are
not
automatically
present
in
just
any
type
of
philosophy.
(e) The
study
of
the
application
of
revealed
truths
to
the
moral
dimension
of
human
lives.
This
is
carried
out
by
Moral
Theology.
Supernatural
morality
is
founded
on
natural
ethics.
Hence,
the
conclusions
reached
in
philosophical
ethics
will
have
repercussions
in
moral
theology.
(f) The
study
of
different
facets
of
the
life
of
the
Church,
such
as
Liturgy
and
History
of
the
Church.
Historical
accuracy
is
particularly
necessary
in
modern
times.
There
are
some
doctrines,
which
seek
to
change
important
elements
of
the
Christian
faith
by
appealing
to
changing
needs
of
the
times.
(g) The
defense
of
faith,
by
showing
that
the
attacks
wages
against
it
are
based
on
false
or
inconclusive
arguments.
This
is
an
integral
part
of
the
previously
mentioned
tasks
theology
carries
out.
The
use
of
human
reason
suffices
for
this
task.
One
does
not
have
to
make
use
of
faith
in
this
regard,
for
those
attacks
against
the
faith
stem
from
supposedly
rational
arguments
and
must
therefore
be
scrutinized
through
the
natural
use
of
reason.
B.
PHILOSOPHY
AND
THEOLOGY
B.1.
THE
ROLE
OF
PHILOSOPHY
IN
THEOLOGY
Taking
into
account
what
we
mentioned
in
the
preceding
chapter
regarding
the
role
of
reason
in
theology,
and
the
fact
that
philosophy
is
simply
the
systematic
actualization
of
the
capacity
to
know
reality
through
natural
reason,
we
can
easily
conclude
that
philosophy
plays
an
important
role
in
theology,
and
that
that
role
is
only
an
instrumental
one,
since
the
source
and
norm
of
theology
is
faith
and
not
reason.
It
would
be
a
mistake
to
try
to
make
theology
do
away
with
philosophy,
under
the
pretext
of
freeing
divine
revelation
from
all
conditioning
influences
of
human
perception.
It
would
be
equally
wrong
to
make
theology
depend
on
some
particular
philosophical
systems,
s
if
that
were
the
only
way
it
could
adapt
to
the
real
needs
of
every
historical
period.
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
clearly
states
that
theology
does
not
need
philosophy,
since
its
principles
(revealed
truths)
are
above
any
other
science.
Theology
makes
use
of
philosophy,
not
because
it
cannot
stand
by
itself,
but
because
of
the
limits
of
human
reason:
by
means
of
what
an
individual
comes
to
known
through
the
use
of
natural
reason,
he
can
more
easily
deepen
his
understanding
of
supernatural
truths.
One
should
note
that
this
particular
perspective
successfully
avoids
the
pitfalls
laid
by
the
two
previously
mentioned
extreme
attitudes.
Indeed,
the
Church
does
not
adhere
to
particular
philosophical
systems;
it
makes
use
of
philosophical
notions
coherent
with
faith.
In
our
discussion
of
philosophy
of
nature,
we
referred
to
the
continuity
that
must
exist
between
spontaneous
natural
knowledge
and
philosophical
knowledge.
Philosophy
presupposes
this
spontaneous
knowledge
and
it
should
perfect
it.
It
carries
out
its
task
by
clarifying
vague
notions,
explicitly
and
systematically
taking
up
matters
that
require
careful
study,
examining
the
basis
of
different
kinds
of
knowledge,
and
proceeding
to
a
critical
study
of
false
presumptions
that
could
have
crept
into
a
generally
accepted
and
prevailing
mentality.
This
correct
philosophical
perspective
is
made
easily
accessible
to
the
believer
by
his
faith.
Faith
clearly
points
out
to
him
the
truths
about
the
meaning
of
human
life
that
natural
reason
can
attain,
and
thus
makes
it
easier
for
him
to
perceive
the
continuity
that
exists
between
philosophy
and
the
correct
spontaneous
use
of
reason.
We
have
to
state,
however,
that
although
faith
points
to
the
truth
of
some
knowledge
accessible
to
reason,
the
latter
can
ultimately
be
satisfied
inly
by
evidence.
Faith
does
not
spare
reason
the
effort
needed
to
acquire
such
knowledge.
Here
we
are
dealing
with
two
distinct
levels
with
regard
to
the
way
of
arriving
at
the
truth.
Hence,
just
like
reason,
philosophy
is
an
instrument
of
theology,
for
philosophy
systematically
actualizes
the
possibilities
of
natural
reason.
One
may
say
that
philosophy
is
a
necessary
instrument
of
theology,
since
the
scientific
exposition
of
faith
is
not
possible
without
relying
on
the
scientific
use
of
natural
reason.
In
fact,
one
can
easily
observe
that
theological
explanations
make
use
of
philosophical
thought.
We
have
already
touched
upon
the
precise
meaning
of
the
necessity
of
philosophy
for
theology.
We
are
dealing
here
with
instrumental
necessity
in
varying
degrees,
according
to
the
different
branches
of
theology
that
may
be
considered.
B.2.
CHRISTIAN
PHILOSOPHY
Historically,
the
study
of
theology
has
been
carried
out
by
starting
from
faith
and
making
use
of
philosophy
as
an
instrument.
With
the
help
of
faith,
the
Fathers
of
the
Church
fashioned
a
philosophical
instrument
in
harmony
with
faith,
and
this
ahs
been
called
Christian
philosophy.
This
philosophy
takes
Christian
dogmas
into
account,
but
it
proceeds
in
the
study
of
its
subject
matter
by
using
arguments
drawn
up
by
reason.
It
is
not
theology,
therefore;
nevertheless,
it
facilitates
theological
study.
It
has
been
enriched
all
throughout
history
by
significant
contributions;
it
reached
its
summit
with
the
doctrine
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas.
The
term
Christian
philosophy
has
given
rise
to
controversies
involving
many
authors:
E.
Gilson,
a
main
protagonist,
states:
Before
everything
else,
I
would
simply
like
to
issue
a
reminder:
before,
the
term
Christian
philosophy
had
nothing
more
than
a
historical
meaning.
It
referred
to
the
immense
work
of
philosophical
speculation
integrated
by
the
Fathers
of
the
Church
and
the
Scholastics
into
their
theological
endeavor.
This
contributions
exists,
it
is
of
such
importance
that
one
cannot
write
the
history
of
philosophy
without
taking
it
into
account.
In
the
end,
the
real
question
that
has
to
be
asked
is:
Can
we
call
real
philosophy
a
system
of
thought,
that
from
the
very
start
already
includes
acceptance,
influenced
by
the
faith,
of
solutions
to
many
significant
philosophical
problems?
Or,
expressed
in
another
way:
Is
it
possible
to
philosophize
without
putting
ones
faith
aside?
A
convincing
reply
can
be
found
by
going
over
the
works
if
St.
Thomas
Aquinas,
the
most
preeminent
Christian
philosopher.
It
is
quite
clear
that
his
main
concern
for
theology
did
not
prevent
him
from
studying
philosophical
issues
with
scientific
rigor.
In
his
philosophical
works,
and
in
the
philosophical
discussions
included
in
his
theological
works,
his
reasoning
exclusively
relies
on
strictly
rational
arguments.
Undoubtedly,
the
certitude
of
faith
served
as
a
firm
support
for
him
in
tackling
basic
philosophical
issues.
But
it
was
like
a
stimulus
that
inspired
reason
in
its
intellectual
work,
never
a
form
of
suppression
of
rational
though.
If
he
managed
to
achieve
an
outstanding
harmony
between
philosophy
and
theology,
he
did
not
accomplish
the
feat
at
the
expense
of
philosophical
precision.
He
did
it
precisely
by
paying
heed
to
the
truth.
This
can
easily
be
confirmed.
One
can
make
use,
for
instance
of
the
arguments
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
employs
regarding
the
existence
of
finality
ion
nature.
This
is
an
important
philosophical
issue
that
is
especially
relevant
in
our
time.
St.
Thomas
expressly
links
it
with
one
of
his
proofs
to
establish
the
truth
of
Gods
existence.
The
pagan
philosopher
Aristotle
dealt
with
this
matter
deeply.
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
studies
Aristotles
reasoning
rigorously,
and
makes
use
of
his
conclusion
to
argue
in
favor
of
the
existence
of
a
provident
God.
There
is
nothing
in
this
process
that
is
not
strictly
rational.
This
also
applies
to
other
philosophical
issues.
For
instance,
the
problems
and
solutions
presented
by
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
in
connection
with
his
doctrine
about
the
act
of
being
are
perfectly
in
line
with
natural
and
supernatural
theology;
nevertheless,
they
are
always
backed
by
rational
arguments,
and
they
can
be
assessed
and
accepted
by
any
person,
regardless
of
his
attitude
towards
the
Christian
faith.
Hence,
the
so-called
Christian
philosophy
is
true
philosophy
in
the
strict
sense.
The
term
Christian
points
to
its
inspired
origin
and
its
continuity,
which
do
not
go
against
its
strictly
rational
nature.
B.3.
PHILOSOPHY
AND
DOGMATIC
STATEMENTS
The
Magisterium
of
the
Church
has
made
use
of
philosophical
terms
in
formulating
dogmas.
This
does
not
mean
that
the
Magisterium
makes
dogma
depend
in
some
concepts
found
in
the
most
outstanding
philosophical
systems,
since
that
would
entail
subordinating
the
faith
to
a
form
of
human
thought,
which
is
always
limited.
In
its
doctrinal
formulations,
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
uses
philosophical
terms
which
represent
a
more
precise
continuation
of
correct
spontaneous
knowledge.
This
happens,
for
instance,
when
the
Magisterium
uses
terms
such
as
person
and
nature
in
connection
with
the
mysteries
of
the
Blessed
Trinity
and
the
Incarnation,
or
substance
in
connection
with
the
Eucharist,
in
order
to
define
transubstantiation.
Thus,
Church
Magisterium
strives
to
clearly
expound
the
meaning
of
truths
of
faith
and
defend
it
against
all
errors.
This
also
makes
us
realize
that
abandoning
the
use
of
such
terms
carries
with
it
the
risk
of
falling
once
again
into
the
errors
that
provoked
the
need
to
devise
those
terms.
Referring
to
concepts
used
by
Catholic
doctrine,
Pope
Pius
XII
teaches:
No
one
denies
that
the
terms
used,
in
the
teaching
of
theology
as
well
as
of
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
itself,
in
order
to
express
the
corresponding
concepts,
can
be
perfected
and
made
more
precise
it
is
also
obviously
true
that
the
Church
cannot
adhere
to
any
ephemeral
philosophical
system.
Nevertheless,
the
ideas
and
terms
that
generally
accepted
Catholic
teachers
have
been
accumulating
are
truly
based
on
principles
and
notions
deduced
from
real
knowledge
of
created
things,
in
the
light
of
revealed
truth.
Hence,
it
is
not
at
all
surprising
that
some
of
those
concepts
were
not
inly
used,
but
also
approved
by
ecumenical
councils
in
such
a
way
that
it
would
not
be
lawful
to
deviate
from
them.
The
real
issue
we
are
facing
here
is
the
safeguarding
of
the
content
of
the
Christian
faith.
There
is
always
the
possibility
of
a
greater
understanding
and
a
better
expression
of
that
content,
but
these
should
not
be
achieved
at
the
expense
of
truth.
Genuine
advancement
in
this
matter
will
never
involve
a
rejection
or
a
watering
down
of
content
found
in
the
formulations
of
the
faith
used
by
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church.
Pope
Paul
VI
wrote:
The
norm
of
expression
that
the
Church,
in
its
sustained
effort
through
the
centuries,
has
established
with
the
help
of
the
Holy
Spirit,
and
which
it
has
confirmed
by
the
authority
of
the
councils
should
be
faithfully
observed
For
those
formulas,
like
all
the
rest
which
the
Church
makes
use
of
to
propound
dogmas
of
faith,
express
concepts
which
are
not
tied
to
a
particular
form
of
culture,
or
a
specific
period
of
scientific
progress,
or
any
theological
school;
rather,
they
manifest
what
he
human
mind
perceives
in
reality
through
universal
and
necessary
experience,
and
they
express
it
trough
adequate
and
specific
words
taken
from
either
common
or
cultural
parlance.
Hence
they
are
suitable
to
all
men,
in
varied
circumstances
of
time
and
place.
Theological
errors
are
frequently
the
result
of
using
an
erroneous
philosophy.
Thus,
the
correct
use
of
philosophy
enables
us
to
pinpoint
in
many
instances
the
root
causes
of
those
errors
and
correct
flawed
perspectives,
and
it
provides
a
great
help
more
than
what
mere
abundance
of
data
offers-
to
discern
truth
and
error
in
theology.
And
individual
who
ahs
a
vast
knowledge
of
the
life
and
history
of
the
Church,
for
instance,
may
easily
fall
into
errors
in
theology
if
he
does
not
have
a
solid
training
in
philosophy.
He
may
easily
fit
and
interpret
the
facts
he
has
obtained
within
excessively
partial
systems
of
thought,
subject
to
intellectual
or
practical
tendencies
in
vogue.
B.4.
PHILOSOPHY,
AN
INSTRUMENT
OF
THEOLOGY
We
must
stress,
however,
that
philosophy
us
used
by
theology
only
as
in
instrument,
since
faith
is
always
the
norm
or
standard
of
theology.
If
this
truth
is
not
taken
into
account,
faith
may
be
relegated
to
the
level
of
knowledge
that
man
can
acquire
through
the
use
of
natural
reason
alone.
Besides,
there
would
be
the
risk
of
accepting
erroneous
doctrines
presented
as
seemingly
indispensable
by
false
philosophical
systems.
When
we
say
that
philosophy
is
an
instrument
of
theology,
we
are
not
rejecting
the
autonomy
of
philosophy
within
its
proper
order,
nor
are
we
stating
that
it
is
really
nothing
outside
being
a
mere
instrument
of
theology.
Far
from
being
outrightly
degraded,
philosophy
is
rather
ennobled
by
its
use
in
theology,
the
supreme
human
wisdom.
Thus,
there
are
two
ways
of
studying
philosophy.
First,
it
can
be
studied
mainly
for
its
own
sake;
and
second,
in
view
of
its
role
as
an
instrument
of
theology.
Obviously,
these
are
not
two
opposing
perspectives,
and
they
can
even
coincide.
Nevertheless,
when
an
individual
studies
philosophy
mainly
because
of
its
significance
in
theological
doctrine,
he
will
have
no
need
to
tackle
many
issues
which
would,
in
contrast,
be
useful
and
even
indispensable
for
someone
who
pursues
philosophy
as
an
autonomous
science
in
itself,
or
as
his
professional
expertise.
This
does
not
in
any
way
mean
that
a
superficial
dabbling
in
philosophy
already
qualifies
as
a
theological
instrument.
It
simply
mean
that
whoever
is
primarily
interested
in
the
doctrinal
angle
can
skip
matters
that
have
little
or
no
relation
whatsoever
with
it.
Even
though
comparisons
may
not
be
that
exact,
we
can
nonetheless
draw
up
illustrative
analogies
concerning
the
matter
for
instance,
the
physicist
makes
use
of
mathematics
as
an
instrument,
without
rejecting
its
proper
autonomy.
This
use
of
mathematics
makes
it
even
more
important.
The
physicist
does
not
usually
have
to
confront
problems
with
the
technical
rigor
of
the
mathematician.
But
this
does
not
mean
that
he
should
be
satisfied
with
a
superficial
knowledge
of
mathematics,
or
that
he
can
make
use
of
it
as
he
likes.
It
simply
means
that
many
legitimate
requirements
of
purely
mathematical
demonstrations
have
no
practical
application
for
problems
in
physics.
C.
PHILOSOPHY
IN
CHRISTIANITY
C.1.
PHILOSOPHY
IN
EARLY
CHRISTIANITY
In
the
early
centuries
of
the
history
of
the
Church,
theology
arose
for
thee
two-fold
purpose
of
defending
the
faith
against
two
dangers
that
threatened
it,
namely,
criticism
coming
from
pagans,
and
the
heresies
that
originated
within
the
Church.
Theology
made
use
of
classical
philosophy
as
an
instrument.
Whatever
truth
could
be
found
in
ancient
philosophy
was
accepted
in
order
to
defend
the
humanly
reasonable
elements
of
the
faith
against
pagan
attacks,
and
to
express
the
truths
of
the
faith
in
a
way
that
precluded
heretical
interpretations.
The
apologists
defended
Christianity
against
pagan
criticism.
At
times,
they
even
addressed
their
writings
to
the
Roman
emperor
himself.
St.
Justin
loomed
as
an
outstanding
figure
among
them.
He
embraced
Christianity
after
having
sought
the
truth
in
the
most
diverse
ancient
philosophies.
In
the
Apologies
written
during
this
period,
the
stress
was
understandably
on
what
could
be
known
by
the
use
of
reason.
Clement
of
Alexandria,
likewise
a
convert,
exerted
a
great
influence
in
Alexandria,
which
was
an
important
center
of
culture
in
antiquity.
He
combined
the
tasks
of
philosophy
and
theology.
Origen
was
to
become
his
prominent
successor.
From
the
very
start,
the
Church
opposed
heresies
like
Gnosticism.
Nevertheless,
when
the
persecutions
against
Christians
finally
ceased
in
the
year
313,
a
new
doctrinal
era
began.
The
Fathers
of
the
Church
and
the
early
Councils
would
experience
the
need
to
make
doctrinal
formulas
precise,
dictated
by
the
serious
effort
to
acquire
greater
understanding,
and
by
the
difficulties
raised
by
new
heresies.
Christians
of
those
times
had
the
full
awareness
of
the
superiority
of
revealed
doctrine
over
any
discovery
made
by
human
reason.
Revelation
gave
importance
to
truths
that
were
unknown
or
neglected
in
pagan
philosophies,
as
well
as
other
truths
that
were
previously
dealt
with
in
a
fragmentary
way,
thus
bringing
strictly
supernatural
elements
together
with
philosophical
truths.
Christianity
clearly
taught
truths
like
the
existence
of
a
personal
God,
the
creation
of
the
universe
the
spirituality
and
immortality
of
the
human
soul,
and
the
existence
of
human
freedom,
sin
and
objective
morality.
All
these
entailed
superiority,
even
in
the
natural
level,
over
pagan
philosophies.
Christianity
made
use
of
classical
philosophy,
after
having
corrected
it
in
the
light
of
faith.
Such
philosophy
contained
doctrinal
and
practical
errors,
mixed
with
partial
natural
truths,
and
this
fact
justified
a
general
attitude
of
caution
before
it.
The
heresies
that
cropped
up
were
many
times
the
result
of
an
uncritical
use
of
totally
and
partially
erroneous
philosophies
in
the
study
of
revealed
doctrine.
Thus,
a
body
of
natural
truths
gradually
and
laboriously
emerged.
It
constituted
a
Christian
philosophy,
on
account
of
its
origin
and
purpose.
It
took
its
inspiration
mainly
from
revealed
truths,
and
it
sought
to
defend
them,
making
use
of
arguments
of
reason
and
of
whatever
truth
there
was
in
ancient
philosophies.
St.
Augustine
played
a
particularly
significant
role
in
the
development
of
Christian
philosophy.
The
path
that
led
St.
Augustine
to
his
conversion
is
linked
with
different
with
different
philosophical
systems,
especially
those
marked
by
Platonic
influence.
In
his
numerous
writings,
St.
Augustine
dealt
with
all
kinds
of
philosophical
and
theological
matters.
Due
to
the
power
of
his
thought
and
the
richness
of
his
spirituality,
theologians
of
subsequent
historical
periods
would
look
up
to
him
as
the
great
master
of
theological
science.
C.2.
THE
MEDIEVAL
SYNTHESIS
Christian
theology,
together
with
philosophy,
was
developed
and
systematized
during
the
Middle
Ages.
Its
summit
is
represented
by
the
original
synthesis
worked
out
by
St.
Thomas
Aquinas,
which
features
a
deep
harmony
between
reason
and
faith.
In
this
process
of
development,
some
individuals
and
events
proved
significant.
We
should
acknowledge
the
contributions
of
authors
like
Scotus
Eriougena,
St.
Anselm
of
Canterbury,
Peter
Abelard,
Alexander
of
Hales,
St.
Albert
the
Great
and
St.
Bonaventure;
the
importance
of
schools
of
learning
such
as
Chartres
and
Oxford
and
the
foundation
of
universities;
and
the
role
played
by
Jewish
and
Arab
philosophers,
who
also
served
as
transmitters
of
ancient
Greek
Philosophy.
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
successfully
drew
up
a
profound
and
coherent
philosophical
doctrine.
His
philosophy
assimilated
the
valid
elements
of
earlier
philosophies
(Platonism,
Aristotelianism,
Arabic
philosophy,
Christian
philosophical
tradition).
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
made
use
of
this
philosophy
to
delve
deeper
into
Catholic
doctrine,
in
full
conformity
with
Sacred
Scriptures
and
Tradition
to
which
he
constantly
referred
and
with
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church.
The
perennial
significance
of
his
work
can
be
explained
in
part
by
his
total
openness
to
the
truth,
which
enabled
him
to
include
in
his
harmonious
synthesis
the
valid
elements
of
many
centuries
of
philosophical
and
theological
thought.
The
work
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
can
be
divided
into
two
general
classifications:
a) Commentaries
on
the
books
of
the
Old
and
New
Testaments,
and
on
different
works,
such
as
the
Book
of
Sentences
of
Peter
Lombard,
and
the
twelve
works
of
Aristotle.
There
are
a
total
of
42
commentaries
written
by
St.
Thomas
Aquinas.
b) Personal
works,
which
include
the
Summa
Theologiae
and
the
Summa
Contra
Gentiles,
the
Quaestiones
Quodlibetales,
lectures
and
homilies,
and
minor
theological
and
philosophical
writings.
All
in
all,
there
88
personal
works
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas.
The
philosophical
doctrine
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
can
be
found
in
his
commentaries
on
philosophers
(especially
Aristotle),
in
some
of
the
quaestiones
regarding
philosophical
matters,
in
his
shorter
philosophical
works,
and
in
scattered
fashion,
also
all
throughout
his
theological
writings.
The
philosophy
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
is
a
profound
synthesis
of
permanent
value,
because
of
its
correct
use
of
philosophical
elements
in
conformity
with
properly
fostering
the
development
of
natural
reason,
and
because
of
its
coherence
with
Catholic
doctrine.
Obviously,
it
has
room
for
further
perfection
and
development.
It
cannot
be
expected
to
provide
solutions
to
all
the
issues
that
have
cropped
up
in
subsequent
periods.
In
some
particular
topics,
linked
in
a
special
manner
with
the
scientific
knowledge
during
the
time
in
which
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
lived,
the
doctrine
has
become
out
of
date.
Nevertheless,
the
philosophy
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
continues
to
provide
a
valid
view
of
fundamental
philosophical
issue.
With
regard
to
its
basic
principles
and
conclusions,
it
can
be
described
as
perennially
valid.
Thus,
anyone
can
readily
see
why
the
doctrine
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
has
been
widely
used
by
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church,
and
why
the
Magisterium
has
expressly
and
repeatedly
endorsed
it
up
to
our
time,
presenting
it
as
a
sure
and
indispensable
guide
for
philosophical
and
theological
studies.
This
can
be
gleaned
from
the
following
official
documents
issued
by
the
Church
in
the
past
100
years:
- Encyclical
Aeterni
Patris,
issued
by
Pope
Leo
XIII
on
August
4,
1879:
it
vigorously
recommends
fidelity
to
Thomistic
doctrine;
- Motu
proprio
Doctoris
Angelici
issued
by
Pope
Pius
X
on
June
29,
1914;
- The
1917
Code
of
Canon
Law;
Canon
1366
stipulates
the
use
of
the
doctrine
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
in
eccelesiastical
studies;
- Encyclical
Studiorum
Ducem,
issued
by
Pope
Pius
XI
on
June
29,
1923;
- Encyclical
Humani
Generis,
issued
by
Pope
Pius
XII
on
August
12,
1950
- Address
Singulari
Sane,
delivered
by
Pope
John
XXIII
on
September
16,
1960;
- Letter
Lumen
Ecclesiae,
issued
by
Pope
Paul
VI
on
November
20,
1974;
- Decree
Optatam
Totius,
nos.
15
and
16,
issued
by
the
Second
Vatican
Council
(and
the
reply
given
by
the
Congregation
for
Seminaries
and
Universities,
dated
December
20,
1965,
in
connection
with
no.
15);
Vatican
II
Declaration
Gravissimim
Educationis
no.
10.
- Pope
John
Paul
II,
Address
delivered
at
the
Pontifical
University
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
on
November
17,
1979;
Address
delivered
at
the
8th
International
Thomistic
Congress
on
September
13,
1980;
- The
19883
Code
of
Canon
Law;
canon
252
states
that
students
of
dogmatic
theology
are
to
have
St.
Thomas
in
particular
as
their
teacher.
In
its
documents
endorsing
the
philosophical
and
theological
doctrine
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas,
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
expressly
highlights
the
perennial
validity
of
his
metaphysics,
its
capacity
to
integrate
whatever
truth
proceeds
from
ancient
and
modern
philosophies,
its
fidelity
to
Catholic
doctrines,
and
its
capacity
to
safeguard
the
truth
in
the
face
of
error,
and
to
serve
as
a
sure
guide
for
study
and
research.
It
also
encourages
a
direct
reading
of
the
works
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas,
stresses
that
the
basic
points
of
his
philosophy
are
certain
truths
and
not
mere
debatable
opinions,
and
points
to
the
need
to
tackle
newer
issues
in
conformity
with
Thomistic
principles,
with
the
openness
to
the
truth
that
was
so
characteristic
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas.
C.3.
CHRISTIANITY
AND
MODERN
PHILOSOPHY
The
direction
Western
Philosophy
has
taken
in
modern
times
is
conditioned
in
great
part
by
currents
of
thought
that
separate
faith
and
reason
and
many
times
pit
one
against
the
other.
Rooted
in
medieval
nominalism,
this
rupture
finds
its
way
into
theology
mainly
thorough
the
influence
of
Luther,
who
affirmed
that
human
nature
is
essentially
corrupt,
and
ended
up
disdaining
reason.
It
finds
its
way
into
philosophy
through
the
influence
of
Descartes,
who
made
the
truth
depend
on
subjective
certitude.
Once
the
harmony
between
reason
and
faith
is
broken,
the
way
is
clear
for
philosophical
systems
espousing
radical
views
and
leading
to
most
varied
errors.
Thus,
the
moral
necessity
of
the
revelation
of
the
principal
natural
truths
appears.
Without
the
help
of
faith,
reason
easily
goes
astray,
and
an
erroneous
reason,
in
turn,
deforms
the
content
of
the
faith.
The
Magisterium
of
the
Church
has
insistently
issued
warnings
about
the
errors
of
different
systems
of
thought.
It
would
be
erroneous
to
conclude
that
this
way
of
acting
reflects
an
attitude
of
hostility
or
mistrust
toward
anything
modern.
The
Church
has
constantly
exerted
the
effort
to
pinpoint
the
truths
these
systems
may
contain,
separating
them
from
the
rest.
Obviously,
however,
this
task
is
fraught
with
serious
difficulties,
since
many
times,
the
errors
proceed
from
false
foundations.
In
the
field
of
philosophy,
the
errors
referred
to
arise
from
materialist,
scientistic,
pragmatist
and
subjectivist
tendencies,
which
clash
with
the
faith
and
frequently
lead
to
explicit
or
implicit
atheism.
These
perspectives
gave
influenced
theology
and
have
led
to
positions
seriously
harmful
for
the
faith,
such
as
modernism
and
neo-modernism.
In
the
cultural
field,
they
have
spawned
a
prevalent
attitude
of
using
reason
to
embark
on
a
malignant
criticism,
leaving
no
room
for
fundamental
metaphysical
truths;
isolated
from
all
natural
truths,
faith
is
thus
reduced
to
mere
subjective
sentiment.
Obviously,
not
everything
is
false
in
modern
philosophy.
Nevertheless,
it
is
a
fact
that
the
previously
mentioned
factors
exercise
a
powerful
and
negative
influence
on
philosophical
and
theological
perspectives.
The
development
of
modern
thought
in
these
past
centuries
offers
some
positive
elements
and
partial
truths
of
considerable
interest,
but
it
would
take
a
heavy
dose
of
discernment
to
make
good
use
of
them.
C.4.
CONTINUITY
IN
CHRISTIAN
PHILOSOPHY
Christian
philosophy
has
been
continuously
developing
up
to
the
present
time,
even
though
it
has,
on
not
a
few
occasions,
suffered
from
the
negative
influence
exerted
by
some
philosophies
incompatible
with
the
faith.
For
this
reason,
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church,
especially
after
the
encyclical
Aeterni
Patris
issued
by
pope
Leo
XIII
in
1879,
has
constantly
affirmed
the
need
to
foster
the
study
of
Thomistic
philosophy,
for
it
still
represents
the
summit
of
Christian
thought.
The
study
of
Thomism
declined
in
the
17th
and
18th
centuries,
even
though
during
that
period,
there
were
also
Thomistic
philosophers.
In
the
second
half
of
the
19th
century,
there
was
a
resurgence
of
Thomistic
studies;
worthy
of
mention
were
the
efforts
of
the
Italian
Sanseverino,
of
Naples;
the
magazine
La
Civilta
Cattolica
founded
by
Fr.
Curci,
a
Jesuit;
and
Cardinal
Zigliara
in
Rome.
In
Spain,
the
Dominican
cardinal
Ceferino
Gonzales
exerted
a
considerable
influence.
In
Germany,
the
leading
figure
of
Thomistic
Thought
was
the
Jesuit
Fr.
Joseph
Kleutgen,
who
had
a
hand
in
preparation
of
the
encyclical
Aeterni
Patris.
Pope
Leo
XIIIs
encyclical
was
a
big
boost
to
Thomism
and
it
gave
rise
to
a
wide-based
movement
that
has
been
called
neo-Thomism
or
neo-
Scholasticism.
Among
the
outstanding
figures
of
this
revival
were
Cardinal
Mercier
(especially
during
the
early
years),
founder
of
the
school
of
Louvain,
and
a
host
of
very
different
personalities
like
Louis
de
Raeymaeker,
Francesco
Olgiati,
Cornelio
Fabro,
Reginald
Garrigou-Lagrange,
Martin
Grabmann,
Josef
Pieper,
Antonin-Dalmace
Sertillangesm
Regis
Joliver,
and
two
authors
who
have
exerted
a
vast
influence
up
to
our
present
time
the
French
philosophers
Jacques
Maritain
and
Etienne
Gilson.
D.
THE
CHRISTIAN
BEFORE
PHILOSOPHY
D.1.
FAITH
AND
PHILOSOPHICAL
STUDY
Since
philosophy
deals
with
truths
that
can
be
known
through
reason,
and
some
of
the
truths
are
contained
in
revelation,
obviously,
faith
has
important
consequences
for
a
Christian
who
studies
philosophy.
These
specific
consequences
are
as
follows:
a) God
has
revealed
the
most
sublime
natural
truths
(the
existence
of
God
and
His
attributes,
the
immortality
of
the
human
soul,
the
natural
law,
among
others)
so
that
they
may
be
known
by
all
human
beings
more
firmly,
more
easily,
and
without
any
trace
of
error.
Hence,
a
Christian
knows
these
truths
by
faith.
This
prevents
him
from
falling
into
errors
regarding
them,
and
helps
him
attain
knowledge
of
them
through
the
use
of
reason.
In
this
sense,
a
Christian
finds
himself
in
an
advantageous
position,
since
thorough
his
faith,
he
knows
more
(in
terms
of
supernatural
truths)
and
better
(due
to
the
certitude
he
has,
concerning
natural
truths).
Of
course,
he
does
not
enjoy,
on
account
of
this,
any
advantage
with
regard
to
the
specific
knowledge
provided
by
the
sciences,
which
may
bear
no
relation
to
revealed
truths.
Faith
is
advantageous
to
reason
because
it
perfects
it
without
obliging
it
to
renounce
what
is
proper
to
it.
b) In
the
study
of
philosophy,
one
should
not
momentarily
cast
aside
the
knowledge
of
natural
truths
that
faith
brings,
or
totally
disregard
it.
Fait
heals
the
intellect
darkened
by
sin,
this
making
its
corrects
spontaneous
and
philosophical
use
possible.
Besides,
in
this
manner,
one
can
avoid
presumption,
which
is
a
source
of
errors,
and
preclude
a
false
attitude
that
tends
to
make
everything
problematic
in
an
indefinite
way.
There
is
no
danger
of
producing
a
spurious
philosophy,
since
only
what
has
been
rationally
founded
will
be
acknowledged
in
the
philosophical
plane.
c) The
help
provided
by
the
faith
does
not
suppress
the
natural
development
of
the
intellect
and
the
effort
exerted
by
reason
to
attain
the
most
sublime
truths.
Faith
is
a
stimulus
that
demands
more
from
reason,
since
it
presents
higher
goals
to
it,
without
sparing
it
the
consequent
effort
needed
to
achieve
them.
It
fulfills
its
role
as
a
guiding
light
by
specifying
goals
that
demand
a
more
rigorous
and
careful
study
of
the
rational
process.
Thus,
it
is
against
the
paralyzationof
rational
activity.
d) A
Christian
passes
judgment
on
philosophical
doctrines
in
the
light
of
faith.
Later
on,
by
using
philosophy,
he
can
pinpoint
the
root
causes
of
the
possible
errors
contained
in
such
doctrines.
Just
like
other
previously
mentioned
cases,
the
scrutiny
of
such
doctrines
in
the
field
of
natural
reason
requires
full
philosophical
rigor.
e) Pre-Christian
philosophers
erred
in
basic
points,
indispensable
for
the
task
of
leading
human
life
towards
its
end.
This
makes
us
realize
that
the
revelation
of
the
highest
natural
truths
was
morally
necessary,
although
by
itself
it
was
not
absolutely
indispensable.
Later
on,
philosophers
who
turned
away
from
the
faith
they
had
already
known,
fell
into
even
greater
errors.
This
becomes
understandable
when
we
consider
that
the
sin
of
apostasy
leads
to
consequences
that
are
more
serious
than
those
brought
about
by
mere
ignorance.
We
can
perceive,
without
any
special
difficulty,
that
not
a
few
doctrines
incompatible
with
the
faith
can
be
described
as
pseudo-religious.
They
advocate,
as
substitutes
for
religious
truths,
inadequately
founded
ideologies
which
provide
a
global
view
of
human
problems
by
transforming
into
absolute
factors
some
partial
aspects
of
reality
or
of
human
experience.
f) Faith
puts
man
in
touch
with
spiritual
realities
studied
in
metaphysics,
this
making
it
easier
for
reason
to
acquire
knowledge
concerning
these
realities.
g) As
in
the
case
of
faith,
proper
dispositions
are
also
required
for
correct
philosophical
knowledge,
for
man
is
free
in
the
use
of
his
intellect.
The
attitude
that
accompanies
faith
facilitates
the
acquisition
of
these
dispositions.
Hence,
for
instance,
a
person
with
faith
is
helped
to
avoid
considering
himself
as
the
measure
of
reality
and
falling
into
subjectivist
errors.
The
relations
between
freedom
and
thought
so
tightly-knit
when
it
comes
to
matters
touching
upon
the
meaning
of
human
existence
explain
why
there
can
be
many
philosophical
errors.
Faith
leads
the
human
being
to
see
God,
the
sole
Absolute
Being,
as
the
center
of
reality.
Thus,
faith
frees
him
from
improper
generalizations
and
false
theories
arising
from
a
subjective
and
self-serving
view
of
reality,
allegedly
resting
on
objective
bases
a
claim
which
may
be
either
partially
valid
or
totally
unrealistic.
In
summary,
we
can
say
that
the
present
state
of
human
nature
redeemed
but
with
a
weakened
intellect
and
will
due
to
the
consequences
of
original
sin
and
personal
sins
explains
why
the
faith
per
forms
an
important
service
to
reason
as
the
latter
carries
out
tasks
proper
to
itself,
and
why
the
absence
of
faith
can
enable
errors
to
crop
up
more
easily
even
in
the
natural
level.
Faith
helps
reason
know
the
principal
natural
truths,
but
without
sparing
it
the
effort
it
must
exert
in
order
to
attain
these
truths
through
the
rational
process.
D.2.
PHILOSOPHY
AND
CHRISTIAN
LIVING
The
study
of
philosophy
enhances
the
coherence
of
Christian
living.
a) Since
philosophy
serves
as
an
instrument
of
theology,
the
study
of
philosophy
enables
us
to
acquire
a
better
knowledge
of
Christian
doctrine.
b) Faith
and
theology
must
shed
light
on
the
knowledge
acquired
by
particular
sciences
and
its
applications.
This
is
carried
out
better
through
philosophy,
the
highest
wisdom
in
the
natural
level.
In
the
natural
sciences,
this
link
is
verified
above
all,
in
some
assumptions
and
in
the
interpretation
of
results
(in
reflections
on
the
scientific
method
and
truth,
or
in
statements
about
the
being
of
the
material
universe,
for
instance).
In
the
human
sciences,
the
link
is
more
strongly
significant,
since
philosophical
doctrines
exercise
a
decisive
influence
on
the
idea
a
person
has
of
man,
thus
greatly
affecting
the
basic
approaches
used
in
history,
sociology,
psychology
and
other
related
sciences.
c) Philosophy
must
be
of
help
to
the
faith.
There
can
be
no
absolute
separation
or
mutual
opposition
of
philosophical
thought
and
Christian
faith.
Hence,
knowledge
of
Christian
philosophy
is
extremely
useful.
An
evident
danger
arises
from
inadequate
philosophical
knowledge.
It
lies
in
not
realizing
the
relation
between
the
faith
and
specific
ideologies
arrayed
in
scientific
garb
which
are
really
incompatible
with
it,
such
as
Freudian,
Marxist,
agnostic
or
scientistic
theories.
In
such
cases,
a
Christian
would
actually
possess
an
erroneous
idea
about
the
faith
and
natural
knowledge.
Although
he
may
sincerely
practice
his
faith,
he
will
inevitably
suffer
from
the
negative
effects
such
confusion
necessarily
causes,
leading
him
to
incoherent
attitudes.
d) Catechetical
teaching,
and
in
general,
every
form
of
expounding
Christian
doctrine
is
necessarily
accompanied
by
philosophical
concepts
at
different
levels.
Thus,
even
in
this
field,
knowledge
of
Christian
philosophy
is
of
great
help,
since
it
facilitates
the
understanding
of
doctrine.
Besides,
it
enables
an
individual
to
appreciate
the
value
of
the
Christian
cultural
heritage,
acquired
through
the
effort
of
many
generations
and
destined
to
achieve
further
development
in
continuity
with
already
attained
truths.
Furthermore,
it
helps
one
see
the
importance
of
terminological
precision
in
the
explanation
of
Catholic
doctrine.
All
these
should
be
kept
in
mind
so
as
t
refute
false
charges
of
opposition
between
what
is
doctrinal
and
what
is
vital.
Philosophical
depth
is
not
averse
to
practical
problems.
It
rather
helps
us
discover
their
real
meaning
and
the
proper
approach
to
them.
Superficiality
prevents
us
from
seeing
the
connection
between
life
and
the
doctrinal
truths
that
give
meaning
to
it.
If
this
happens,
there
will
be
problems
that
may
seem
practically
impossible
to
solve,
simply
because
they
are
seen
from
an
erroneous
perspective.
D.3.
CHURCH
MAGISTERIUM
AND
PHILOSOPHY
The
following
are
among
the
most
significant
teachings
and
instructions
on
philosophy,
given
by
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church:
a) It
is
important
to
subordinate
reason
to
faith,
and
philosophy
to
theology.
The
Magisterium
has
constantly
emphasized
this
highly
significant
point,
and
this
insistence
becomes
understandable
when
we
realize
that
many
theological
errors
have
arisen
as
a
consequence
of
not
seriously
taking
this
matter
into
account.
Besides,
faith
is
a
superior
norm
which
never
contradicts
truths
attained
by
reason.
Faith
neither
limits
nor
does
violence
to
reason;
rather,
faith
elevates
it.
Although
faith
is
above
reason,
there
can
never
be
a
real
discrepancy
between
faith
and
reason,
since
the
same
God
who
reveals
mysteries
and
infuses
faith
has
bestowed
the
light
of
reason
on
the
human
mind,
and
God
cannot
deny
himself,
nor
can
truth
ever
contradict
truth.
The
deceptive
appearance
of
such
a
contradiction
is
mainly
due
to
the
fact
that
either
the
dogmas
of
faith
have
not
been
understood
and
expounded
according
to
the
mind
of
the
Church,
or
that
uncertain
theories
are
taken
for
verdicts
of
reason.
Thus,
we
define
that
very
assertion
that
is
opposed
to
enlightened
faith
is
utterly
false.
(Fifth
Lateran
Council).
After
due
corrections
and
adaptations,
the
doctrine
of
Aristotle
as
well
as
those
of
other
philosophers
could
be
and
can
be
accepted
by
virtue
of
the
universal
value
of
their
principles,
their
respect
for
objective
reality,
and
their
acknowledgment
of
a
God
distinct
from
the
world.
The
same
thing
cannot
be
said
of
philosophies
and
scientific
theories
whose
basic
principles
are
incompatible
with
religious
faith
because
they
are
based
on
monism,
or
because
they
deny
transcendence,
or
because
they
advocate
subjectivism
or
agnosticism.
Unfortunately,
there
are
many
modern
doctrines
and
systems
of
thought
which
are
radically
irreconcilable
with
Christian
faith
and
theology.
b) The
Magisterium
recommend
the
study
and
teaching
of
the
philosophy
and
theology
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas.
The
pronouncements
of
the
Magisterium
regarding
this
matter
continue
being
applicable
in
our
time.
This
is
not
equivalent
to
belittling
the
importance
of
other
valid
expressions
of
philosophical
thought,
or
to
suppressing
an
individuals
legitimate
freedom
in
debatable
issues,
or
to
refusing
to
acknowledge
the
existence
of
new
difficulties
and
situations
that
require
further
advances
in
doctrinal
studies.
The
capital
theses
in
the
philosophy
of
St.
Thomas
are
not
to
be
placed
in
the
category
of
opinions
capable
of
being
debated
one
way
or
another,
but
are
to
be
considered
as
the
foundations
upon
which
the
whole
science
of
natural
and
divine
things
is
based;
if
such
principles
are
once
removed
or
in
any
way
impaired,
it
must
necessarily
follow
that
students
of
the
sacred
sciences
will
ultimately
fail
to
perceive
so
much
as
the
meaning
of
the
words
in
which
the
dogmas
of
divine
revelation
are
proposed
by
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church.
We
therefore
desired
that
all
teachers
of
philosophy
and
sacred
theology
should
be
warned
that
if
they
deviate
so
much
as
a
step,
in
metaphysics
especially,
from
Aquinas,
they
will
expose
themselves
to
grave
risk.
The
Second
Vatican
Council,
too,
recommended
to
Catholic
schools,
on
two
separate
occasions,
the
study
of
the
doctrine
of
St.
Thomas
Aquinas.
Indeed,
while
tackling
the
issue
of
priestly
training,
the
Council
said:
In
order
to
throw
as
full
a
light
as
possible
on
the
mysteries
of
salvation,
the
students
should
learn
to
examine
more
deeply,
with
the
help
of
speculation
and
with
St.
Thomas
as
teacher
all
aspects
of
these
mysteries,
and
to
perceive
their
interconnection
(Decree
Optatam
Totius,
no.
16).
The
same
ecumenical
Council,
in
its
Declaration
on
Christian
Education,
exhorted
schools
of
higher
education
to
work
for
the
fulfillment
of
their
objective
in
such
a
way
that
by
a
careful
attentions
to
the
current
problems
of
these
changing
times
and
to
the
research
being
undertaken,
the
convergence
of
faith
and
reason
in
the
one
truth
may
be
seen
more
clearly,
and
right
after
this,
it
affirmed
that
to
achieve
such
an
end,
there
is
a
need
to
follow
the
traditions
of
the
Doctors
of
the
Church,
and
especially
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
(cf.
Declaration
Gravissimum
Educationis,
no.
10)
There
is
no
real
and
fruitful
fidelity
if
the
principles
enunciated
by
St.
Thomas
Aquinas
are
not
accepted
received,
in
some
way,
from
his
own
hands.
c) The
Magisterium
of
the
Church
has
clearly
pointed
out
the
errors
of
different
philosophical
systems
that
are
incompatible
with
the
faith,
and
has
also
issued
warnings
against
other
systems
of
thought
which
lead
to
doctrinal
errors
when
they
are
allowed
to
reach
conclusion
coherent
with
their
principles.
For
instance,
it
has
rejected
doctrines
like
immanentism,
idealism,
materialism
and
pragmatism,
firmly
noting
that
attempts
to
make
Catholic
doctrine
compatible
with
such
doctrines
lead
to
serious
errors.
Pope
Pius
Xii
refereed
to
those
who
scorned
perennial
philosophy
and
at
the
same
time
praised
other
philosophies
ancient
or
modern,
eastern
or
western
-
,
seemingly
insinuating
that
any
debatable
philosophy
or
doctrine,
duly
corrected
or
enhanced
whenever
necessary,
can
be
made
compatible
with
Catholic
dogma.
However,
no
Catholic
can
entertain
doubts
regarding
the
falsity
of
this
attitude,
especially
when
the
philosophies
involved
are
systems
like
immanentism,
idealism,
materialism
whether
historical
or
dialectic
and
existentialism
whether
it
defends
atheism
or
rejects
the
significance
of
reason
ion
the
field
of
metaphysics.
The
Second
Vatican
Council
explains
in
a
positive
light
the
Catholic
doctrine
concerning
man,
explicitly
highlighting
numerous
truths
affirmed
by
perennial
philosophy,
such
a
s
the
composition
of
body
and
soul,
the
spirituality
and
immortality
of
the
human
soul,
the
dignity
of
man
as
a
being
superior
to
the
maternal
universe,
the
human
capacity
to
grasp
reality
with
certainty
through
the
use
of
the
intellect,
the
natural
law
written
in
mans
conscience,
human
freedom
and
the
need
to
overcome
ones
passions
in
order
to
act
in
accordance
with
human
dignity.
At
the
same
time,
it
discusses
several
doctrines
contrary
to
the
truth,
such
as
communism
and
scientism.
It
affirms
that
the
Church,
as
given
over
to
the
service
of
both
God
and
man,
cannot
cease
from
reproving,
with
sorrow
yet
with
the
utmost
firmness,
as
she
has
done
in
the
past,
those
harmful
teachings
and
ways
of
acting
which
are
in
conflict
with
reason
and
with
common
human
experience,
and
which
cast
man
down
from
the
noble
to
state
to
which
he
was
born.
Lastly,
it
teaches
that
these
drawbacks
are
not
necessarily
due
to
modern
culture
and
they
should
not
tempt
us
to
overlook
its
positive
values.
Every
Catholic
has
to
carefully
observe
these
pronouncements
of
the
Magisterium
in
activities
related
to
doctrinal
formation,
teaching
and
research.
They
constitute
an
indispensable
requirement
in
order
to
obtain
fruitful
results.
Confusion
in
doctrinal
and
practical
matters,
against
which
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
has
forewarned
the
faithful
in
times
past
as
well
as
in
our
present
era,
arises
from
the
attitude
of
ignoring
these
pronouncements,
their
acceptance
and
observance,
in
contrast,
constitute
a
firm
guarantee
of
doctrinal
and
moral
integrity,
allowing
a
Catholic
to
share
in
the
task
of
finding
the
right
approaches
and
solutions
to
many
human
conflicts
and
difficulties.
In
our
days,
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
has
constantly
expressed
the
need
for
a
new
humanism
based
on
an
integral
view
of
man,
that
will
be
capable
of
going
beyond
the
inevitable
negative
consequences
of
functionalist
and
pragmatist
currents
of
thought.
For
this,
man
can
rely
above
all
on
the
help
of
his
supernatural
faith.
However,
many
elements
of
this
humanism
are
accessible
to
human
reason;
establishing
its
rational
foundation
is
precisely
the
task
of
philosophy.
The
teachings
and
pronouncements
of
the
Magisterium
of
the
Church
regarding
philosophy
tend
toward
a
clear
objective:
to
serve
man
in
his
quest
for
truth
and
the
meaning
of
his
life,
illumining
his
way
with
the
light
that
God
Himself
has
entrusted
to
the
Church.
Pope
John
Paul
II
affirmed
that
now,
more
than
ever,
there
is
a
need
to
sow
the
good
seed
of
metaphysical
truth
above
all.
Confusion
in
theology
and
crisis
in
morality
are
generally
caused
by
a
crisis
in
philosophy.
Philosophy
has
a
social
role
of
tremendous
importance,
for
mans
path
leading
to
his
end
passes
through
it.
This
explains
why
the
Church
is
so
keen
about
safeguarding
the
integrity
of
philosophy.