Towards A Philosophy of Photography PDF
Towards A Philosophy of Photography PDF
Towards A Philosophy of Photography PDF
A PHILOSOPHY OF PHOTOGRAPHY
Towards a Philosophy of Photography
Vilm Flusser
REAKTION BOOKS
Published by Reaktion Books Ltd
33 Great Sutton Street, London EC1 V 0 DX, UK
www.reaktionbooks.co.uk
eISBN: 9781780232447
Contents
Introductory Note
The Image
The Technical Image
The Apparatus
The Gesture of Photography
The Photograph
The Distribution of Photographs
The Reception of Photographs
The Photographic Universe
Why a Philosophy of Photography Is Necessary
Lexicon of Basic Concepts
This book is based on the hypothesis that two fundamental turning points
can be observed in human culture since its inception. The first, around the
middle of the second millennium , can be summed up under the heading
BC
the invention of linear writing; the second, the one we are currently
experiencing, could be called the invention of technical images. Similar
turning points may have occurred previously but are beyond the scope of
this analysis.
This hypothesis contains the suspicion that the structure of culture
and therefore existence itself is undergoing a fundamental change. This
book attempts to strengthen this suspicion and, in order to maintain its
hypothetical quality, avoids quotations from earlier works on similar
themes. For the same reason, there is no bibliography. However, there is a
short glossary of the terms employed and implied in the course of the
discussion; these definitions are not intended to have general validity but
are offered as working hypotheses for those who wish to follow up the
concepts arising from the thoughts and analyses presented here.
Thus the intention of this book is not to defend a thesis but to make a
contribution informed by philosophy to the debate on the subject of
photography.
The Image
their images reached critical proportions. For this very reason, some
people tried to remember the original intention behind the images. They
attempted to tear down the screens showing the image in order to clear a
path into the world behind it. Their method was to tear the elements of
the image (pixels) from the surface and arrange them into lines: They
invented linear writing. They thus transcoded the circular time of magic
into the linear time of history. This was the beginning of historical
consciousness and history in the narrower sense. From then on,
historical consciousness was ranged against magical consciousness a
struggle that is still evident in the stand taken against images by the
Jewish prophets and the Greek philosophers (particularly Plato).
The struggle of writing against the image historical consciousness
against magic runs throughout history. With writing, a new ability was
born called conceptual thinking which consisted of abstracting lines
from surfaces, i.e. producing and decoding them. Conceptual thought is
more abstract than imaginative thought as all dimensions are abstracted
from phenomena with the exception of straight lines. Thus with the
invention of writing, human beings took one step further back from the
world. Texts do not signify the world; they signify the images they tear
up. Hence, to decode texts means to discover the images signified by
them. The intention of texts is to explain images, while that of concepts is
to make ideas comprehensible. In this way, texts are a metacode of
images.
This raises the question of the relationship between texts and images
a crucial question for history. In the medieval period, there appears to
have been a struggle on the part of Christianity, faithful to the text,
against idolaters or pagans; in modern times, a struggle on the part of
textual science against image-bound ideologies. The struggle is a
dialectical one. To the extent that Christianity struggled against
paganism, it absorbed images and itself became pagan; to the extent that
science struggled against ideologies, it absorbed ideas and itself became
ideological. The explanation for this is as follows: Texts admittedly
explain images in order to explain them away, but images also illustrate
texts in order to make them comprehensible. Conceptual thinking
admittedly analyzes magical thought in order to clear it out of the way,
but magical thought creeps into conceptual thought so as to bestow
significance on it. In the course of this dialectical process, conceptual and
imaginative thought mutually reinforce one another. In other words,
images become more and more conceptual, texts more and more
imaginative. Nowadays, the greatest conceptual abstraction is to be found
in conceptual images (in computer images, for example); the greatest
imagination is to be found in scientific texts. Thus, behind ones back, the
hierarchy of codes is overturned. Texts, originally a metacode of images,
can themselves have images as a metacode.
That is not all, however. Writing itself is a mediation just like images
and is subject to the same internal dialectic. In this way, it is not only
externally in conflict with images but is also torn apart by an internal
conflict. If it is the intention of writing to mediate between human beings
and their images, it can also obscure images instead of representing them
and insinuate itself between human beings and their images. If this
happens, human beings become unable to decode their texts and
reconstruct the images signified in them. If the texts, however, become
incomprehensible as images, human beings lives become a function of
their texts. There arises a state of textolatry that is no less hallucinatory
than idolatry. Examples of textolatry, of faithfulness to the text, are
Christianity and Marxism. Texts are then projected into the world out
there, and the world is experienced, known and evaluated as a function of
these texts. A particularly impressive example of the incomprehensible
nature of texts is provided nowadays by scientific discourse. Any ideas
we may have of the scientific universe (signified by these texts) are
unsound: If we do form ideas about scientific discourse, we have decoded
it wrongly; anyone who tries to imagine anything, for example, using
the equation of the theory of relativity, has not understood it. But as, in
the end, all concepts signify ideas, the scientific, incomprehensible
universe is an empty universe.
Textolatry reached a critical level in the nineteenth century. To be
exact, with it history came to an end. History, in the precise meaning of
the word, is a progressive transcoding of images into concepts, a
progressive elucidation of ideas, a progressive disenchantment (taking
the magic out of things), a progressive process of comprehension. If texts
become incomprehensible, however, there is nothing left to explain, and
history has come to an end.
During this crisis of texts, technical images were invented: in order to
make texts comprehensible again, to put them under a magic spell to
overcome the crisis of history.
The Technical Image
magic out of images, even if their inventor may not have been aware of
this; the photograph, the first technical image, was invented in the
nineteenth century in order to put texts back under a magic spell, even if
its inventors may not have been aware of this. The invention of the
photograph is a historical event as equally decisive as the invention of
writing. With writing, history in the narrower sense begins as a struggle
against idolatry. With photography, post-history begins as a struggle
against textolatry.
For this was the situation in the nineteenth century: The invention of
printing and the introduction of universal education resulted in everybody
being able to read. There arose a universal consciousness of history that
extended even to people in those strata of society who had previously
lived a life of magic the peasants who now began to live a proletarian
and historical life. This took place thanks to cheap texts: Books,
newspapers, flyers, all kinds of texts became cheap and resulted in a
historical consciousness that was equally cheap and a conceptual thinking
that was equally cheap leading to two diametrically opposed
developments. On the one hand, traditional images finding refuge from
the inflation of texts in ghettos, such as museums, salons and galleries,
became hermetic (universally undecodable) and lost their influence on
daily life. On the other hand, there came into being hermetic texts aimed
at a specialist lite, i.e. a scientific literature with which the cheap kind of
conceptual thinking was not competent to deal. Thus culture divided into
three branches: that of the fine arts fed with traditional images which
were, however, conceptually and technically enriched; that of science and
technology fed with hermetic texts; and that of the broad strata of society
fed with cheap texts. To prevent culture breaking up, technical images
were invented as a code that was to be valid for the whole of society.
Valid in the sense, in fact, that first, technical images were to introduce
images back into daily life; second, they were to make hermetic texts
comprehensible; and third, they were to make visible the subliminal
magic that was continuing to operate in cheap texts. They were to form
the lowest common denominator for art, science and politics (in the sense
of universal values), i.e. to be at one and the same time beautiful, true
and good, and in this way, as a universally valid code, they were to
overcome the crisis of culture of art, science and politics.
In fact, however, technical images function in a different way: They do
not introduce traditional images back into life but, rather than replace
them with reproductions, displace them and, rather than make hermetic
texts comprehensible, as was intended, they distort them by translating
scientific statements and equations into states of things, i.e. images. They
do not make the prehistoric magic contained subliminally within cheap
texts in any way evident but replace it with a new kind of magic, i.e. the
programmed kind. For this reason, they cannot reduce culture, as was
intended, to the lowest common denominator but, on the contrary, they
grind it up into amorphous masses. Mass culture is the result.
The explanation for this is as follows: Technical images are surfaces
that function in the same way as dams. Traditional images flow into them
and become endlessly reproducible: They circulate within them (for
example in the form of posters). Scientific texts flow into them and are
transcoded from lines into states of things and assume magical properties
(for example in the form of models that attempt to make Einsteins
equation comprehensible). And cheap texts, a flood of newspaper articles,
flyers, novels, etc. flow into them, and the magic and ideology inherent
within them are translated into the programmed magic of technical
images (for example in the form of photo-novels). Thus technical images
absorb the whole of history and form a collective memory going
endlessly round in circles.
Nothing can resist the force of this current of technical images there
is no artistic, scientific or political activity which is not aimed at it, there
is no everyday activity which does not aspire to be photographed, filmed,
videotaped. For there is a general desire to be endlessly remembered and
endlessly repeatable. All events are nowadays aimed at the television
screen, the cinema screen, the photograph, in order to be translated into a
state of things. In this way, however, every action simultaneously loses
its historical character and turns into a magic ritual and an endlessly
repeatable movement. The universe of technical images, emerging all
around us, represents the fulfilment of the ages, in which action and
agony go endlessly round in circles. Only from this apocalyptic
perspective, it seems, does the problem of photography assume the
importance it deserves.
The Apparatus
Almost everyone today has a camera and takes snaps. Just as almost
everyone has learned to write and produce texts. Anyone who is able to
write can also read. But anyone who can take snaps does not necessarily
have to be able to decode photographs. For us to see why the amateur
photographer can be a photographic illiterate, the democratization of the
taking of photographs has to be considered and at the same time, a
number of aspects of democracy in general have to be addressed.
Cameras are purchased by people who were programmed into this
purchase by the apparatus of advertising. The camera purchased will be
the latest model: cheaper, more automatic and more efficient than
earlier models. As has already been established, this progressive
improvement of camera models is based on the feedback mechanism by
which those taking snaps feed the photographic industry: The
photographic industry learns automatically from the actions of those
taking snaps (and from the professional press that constantly supplies it
with test results). This is the essence of post-industrial progress.
Apparatuses improve by means of social feedback.
Despite the fact that the camera is based on complex scientific and
technical principles, it is a very simple matter to make it function. The
camera is a structurally complex, but functionally simple, plaything. In
this respect, it is the opposite of chess which is a structurally simple, and
functionally complex, game: Its rules are easy, but it is difficult to play
chess well. Anyone who holds a camera in their hands can create
excellent photographs without having any idea what complex processes
they are setting off when they push the button.
People taking snaps are distinguishable from photographers by the
pleasure they take in the structural complexity of their plaything. Unlike
photographers and chess-players they do not look for new moves, for
information, for the improbable, but wish to make their functioning
simpler and simpler by means of more and more perfect automation.
Though impenetrable to them, the automaticity of the camera intoxicates
them. Amateur photographers clubs are places where one gets high on
the structural complexities of cameras, where one goes on a photograph-
trip post-industrial opium dens.
Cameras demand that their owners (the ones who are hooked on them)
keep on taking snaps, that they produce more and more redundant images.
This photo-mania involving the eternal recurrence of the same (or of
something very similar) leads eventually to the point where people taking
snaps feel they have gone blind: Drug dependency takes over. People
taking snaps can now only see the world through the camera and in
photographic categories. They are not in charge of taking photographs,
they are consumed by the greed of their camera, they have become an
extension to the button of their camera. Their actions are automatic
camera functions.
A permanent flow of unconsciously created images is the result. They
form a camera memory, a databank of automatic functions. Anyone who
leafs through the album of a person who takes snaps does not recognize,
as it were, the captured experiences, knowledge or values of a human
being, but the automatically realized camera possibilities. A journey to
Italy documented like this stores the times and places at which the person
taking snaps was induced to press the button, and shows which places the
camera has been to and what it did there. This goes for all documentary
photography. The documentary photographer, just like the person taking
snaps, is interested in continually shooting new scenes from the same old
perspective. The photographer in the sense intended here is, on the other
hand, interested (like the chess-player) in seeing in continually new ways,
i.e. producing new, informative states of things. The evolution of
photography, from its origins right up to the present, is a process of
increasing awareness of the concept of information: from an appetite for
the continually new using the same old method to an interest in
continually evolving new methods. Both those taking snaps and
documentary photographers, however, have not understood information.
What they produce are camera memories, not information, and the better
they do it, the more they prove the victory of the camera over the human
being.
Anyone who writes has to master the rules of spelling and grammar.
Anyone who takes snaps has to adhere to the instructions for use
becoming simpler and simpler that are programmed to control the
output end of the camera. This is democracy in post-industrial society.
Therefore people taking snaps are unable to decode photographs: They
think photographs are an automatic reflection of the world. This leads to
the paradoxical result that the more people take snaps, the more difficult
it becomes to decode photographs: Everyone thinks there is no need to
decode photographs, since they know how photographs are made and
what they mean.
That is not all. The photographs that we are deluged by are seen as
contemptible flyers which are cut out of the newspaper, torn up or used
for packing paper; in short: We can do what we like with them. An
example: If one sees a scene from the war in Lebanon on television or at
the cinema, one knows one has no alternative but to look at it. If one sees
it in a newspaper, on the other hand, one can cut it out and keep it, send it
to friends with comments or screw it up in rage. One thinks one is thereby
able to react in an active way to the scene in Lebanon. The last vestiges of
materiality adhering to the photograph give rise to the impression that we
are able to act in a historical way towards it. In fact, the actions described
are nothing but ritual acts.
The photograph of the scene in Lebanon is an image which, as ones
gaze wanders over the surface, produces magical not historical
relationships between the elements of the image and the reader. In the
photograph, rather than seeing historical events with their causes and
consequences, we see magical connections. It is true that the photograph
illustrates a newspaper article whose structure is linear and which is
made up of concepts with meaningful causes and consequences. But we
read this article through the photograph: It is not the article that explains
the photograph, but the photograph that illustrates the article. This
reversal of the textphoto relationship is typically post-industrial and
renders any historical action impossible.
Throughout history, texts have explained images; now photographs
illustrate articles. Illuminated capital letters used to illustrate Bible texts;
now newspaper articles illustrate photographs. The Bible broke the magic
spell of capital letters, the photograph is recasting the magic spell of the
article. Throughout history, texts dominated, today images dominate. And
where technical images dominate, illiteracy takes on a new role. The
illiterate are no longer excluded, as they used to be, from a culture
encoded in texts, but participate almost totally in a culture encoded in
images. If the complete subordination of texts to images comes about in
future, then we shall be faced with a general state of illiteracy, and only a
few specialists will learn to read any more. There are signs of this
already: Johnny cant spell in the , and even the so-called developing
USA
This, I think, shows what being free means. Not cutting off ones ties with
others but making networks out of these connections in co-operation with
them. migrs become free, not when they deny their lost homeland, but
when they come to terms with it. VILM FLUSSER
Changing the question free from what? into free for what?; this
change that occurs when freedom has been achieved has
accompanied me on my migrations like a basso continuo. This is
what we are like, those of us who are nomads, who come out of the
collapse of a settled way of life.*
In the same way that, in the process of photography, things lose their
place, are displaced and go on a journey made up of countless
experiences, and that telematic images capture and encircle displaced
people, Flussers thought should be seen as a process of wandering that
does not come either to a clearing (in Heideggers sense) or to any
transcendental place. The forward movement of this way of thinking
consists much more of the deliberate repetition of every step that
nevertheless fails ultimately to indicate the way out. Perhaps it is thanks
to this migration, as experienced and reflected upon, that Flusser, in his
best essayist manner, is able to show us everyday things with precisely
the urgency and sharp analytic focus that characterizes the great
philosophers and theorists of the twentieth century (Nietzsche, Husserl,
Heidegger, Wittgenstein and Kafka).
Flussers thinking proceeds by means of etymological statements,
perceiving language very much as the home of being as movement, as
media communication whose capacity to integrate experience is being
altered increasingly by technological media. Since he always wrote in a
number of languages and translated them back and forth Portuguese,
English, French, German and Czech the idea of translation is at the
heart of all of his works, of his way of thinking. However, translation
means not so much the formal linguistic act of translation as the human
act of leaving and then rediscovering an area of language. Thus, in this
continual state of being on the move like nomads, languages acquired for
Flusser the original character born out of elemental difference or
separation and out of the desire to be on the move, to build bridges, to
communicate. The demand for translation originates from all those
migrations that did not arise out of persecution and the need to seek
refuge elsewhere; at the same time, Flussers writing demands that one
learns the lesson of translation by looking at catastrophes and human
degradation caused by political persecution. Every translation signifies
the space-between, the gap, the historical chasm or the repression of
history; translation is the most cautious form of communication since
there is always the inherent admission of a certain departure and an
uncertain arrival. In this sense, Flussers philosophical writing must be
seen as a departure attempting to grasp the transition from a world view
characterized by humanism to a world of the techno-imaginary
springing from nowhere and viewing the artificial paradises of digital
fog as the end of the grand projects of the philosophy of history.
Flusser has been called the philosopher of new media; his name is
often mentioned in the same breath as Jean Baudrillard and Paul Virilio.
Flussers thought is nevertheless far removed from the eschatalogical
dimension of Virilios theory of the media and from the criminological
dimension of Baudrillards theory of simulations. Flusser pinned his
hopes on the potentiality of the Now that is based neither on human
vigilance nor on social progress of the late Marxist or the late capitalist
variety but on a nameless, post-historical universe of technical images.
Flusser is no apologist for new media, yet it is with deep melancholy that
he sees in the disappearance of historical references a devastation of the
territory of history and an ushering in of a dislocated world view. In this
respect, his philosophy of photography is very much a philosophy of
translation continually moving towards the philosophy of emigration that
was the aim of his writing:
If the relationship of the subject to the text (textolatry) and to the image
(idolatry) was determined by magic and ritual, in the universe of
photography this relationship is characterized by the functionalism of the
apparatus and the operator. Whereas transcendence once occupied the
field of meaning in the form of myth, and gods like authors stood at
the centre of the hermeneutic circle, the interpretation of the technical
image becomes an act of grasping the transdescendent functional and
circular interactions between the four essential and non-causal
determinants of the photographic universe: image, apparatus, program
and information. The gods have, as it were, been turned into
functionaries who put their efforts into the processes of communication
i.e. manipulated information that they think they have under their
control, but whose computative logic they are nevertheless subject to.
Photographers are functionaries, they make use of apparatuses using
programs linked to them and produce information. The industrial
evolution of apparatuses and programs has to be ordered in such a way
that photographers abilities are exceeded and yet program capabilities
are not exhausted. To a certain extent, the black box as the hermeneutic
residue of magic must still be able to offer its functionary a guarantee of
meaning. This is the measure of individuality and the degree of
information provided by the photographic image; in the end, Flusser
identifies these two things only as experimental photography, i.e. the
literal deconstruction of the whole apparatus and the overall program of
photography.
Photography initiated the transition from the industrial and historical
to the post-industrial and post-historical age. This was determined,
according to Flusser, by the shift or redirection of power from the
material to the symbolic and replaced matter and work with the twin
pillars of information and play Instead of having to work, the human
being is able to play. The apparatus, the black box, the hardware
represent a form of robotization and automation of cultural production
(not therefore to be confused with the debate about apparatus in film
theory since the 1960s); as a work-thing (Werkzeug) it is a plaything
(Spielzeug) that simulates a way of thinking and creates images according
to the combinations offered by the program (the software). Flusser was
no Luddite; he did, however, press for a criticism of apparatuses whose
production serves the interests of social power and whose aim was that
the human being would be ruled out. He differentiated his criticism of
apparatuses from humanistic criticism which continued to invoke human
responsibility and denied the fait accompli that the human being had been
excluded from the world of apparatuses. The paradox he formulates about
the photographic criticism that is needed is, to use his words,
uncovering the terrible fact of this unintentional, rigid and
uncontrollable functionality of apparatuses in order to get a hold over
them. In this way, photographers as critical functionaries are charged
with the responsibility of informing by means of images, of imposing
information onto a surface. Whether photography is being employed in
the service of art, science or politics, photographers have a duty to
analyze their own intentions. The aim of any single photograph is as
Adorno says the disclosure of the logic of being produced. Thinking
about photography means defining the playful combinations contained
within the apparatus and seeing the program as a concept of freedom. The
only names mentioned by Flusser, initially just in passing Kafka and
Kant determine the ethical motivation of this social philosophy.
Freedom is playing against the camera, even though the human beings
taking the photographs cannot escape the state of dependence that they
have brought upon themselves, their positive theatre of the absurd.
Their job must be to use images to create spaces running counter to those
that are programmed within apparatuses.
In the information society, questions of property and social
emancipation common to both capitalism and socialism have evolved
into problems of the programming and distribution of information. The
solution to these problems in the post-historical and post-ideological
age is no longer aimed at a social situation that can be achieved
historically. Any such teleological model has now been transformed into
the circular model of self-reflexive, autopoietic apparatus. As long as the
photograph is not yet electromagnetic, it remains the first of all post-
industrial objects, Flusser wrote in 1983. Even though the last vestiges
of materiality are attached to photographs, their value does not lie in the
thing but in the information on their surface. The act of photography, in
which information is encoded and subsequently decoded by the receiver,
signifies an awareness of how things are devalued by their photographic
representation. The moment of loss in creating a photographic image
interpreted by philosophers from Walter Benjamin to Roland Barthes as
being a precondition for phenomenological doubt must not lead to the
fetishizing compensation of lost objects by their symbolic replacement; it
must instead educate us into an awareness of this translation within the
image. Admittedly, Flusser does not present any program for this, makes
no reference either to directions in style and art or to ideal photographers;
instead, by pointing in the direction of experimental photography, he
indicates that this informative photography has to be distinguished from
redundant photography which exhausts itself stylistically and venerates
apparatuses and programs. Experimental photography must expose these
cracks in representation, the absurdity of any post-historical technical
representation.
Flussers work on the philosophy of photography should be read as a
treatise on the crisis of history that can no longer be resolved. The reader
will be unable to avoid being confronted over and over again with the
melancholy reason behind the observations presented here. When texts
were no longer able to form narratives, technical images were invented.
Their job was to make texts comprehensible again, to put them under a
magic spell to overcome the crisis of history. There is a connection
between the invention of photography and Gustave Flaubert, whose
dearest wish is said to have been to write a book about Nothing. After
reading Flusser, one sees that the end of the story turns out to be the basic
information of any informative photography. The obscuring of the
aesthetic component of the program of the twentieth century formed the
dark apocalyptic background to the indescribable catastrophe of human
history against which Flusser formulated his philosophy of freedom.