CH 7 Real Numbers
CH 7 Real Numbers
LECTURE NOTES FOR MATH 378 (CSUSM, SPRING 2009). WAYNE AITKEN
1. Introduction
In this chapter we construct the set of real numbers R. There are sev-
eral ways to introduce the real numbers. Three popular approaches are to
introduce R with (i) new axioms, with (ii) Dedekind cuts of Q, or with
(iii) Cauchy sequences in Q. We will use the third approach and construct
real numbers as equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rational num-
bers. This approach is chosen since it avoids the need for additional axioms,
and gives students practice with the concept of Cauchy sequence.
The main theorem of this chapter is that R is a complete ordered field.
We begin with a discussion of the limitations of Q. Then we discuss infinite
sequences. At first the sequences we require are rational sequence. However,
much of what we do easily extends to other ordered fields. So instead of
proving theorems for Q, we will often prove the result for a general ordered
field. With this in mind, throughout this chapter we let F be an ordered
field that is either equal to Q, or contains Q.1
2. Limitations of Q
In geometry we learn the Pythagorean Theorem which allows us to com-
pute one side of a right triangle assuming we know the lengths of the other
two sides. As an application,
one easily shows that the diagonal of the unit
square has length 2. In other words, the length d of the diagonal has the
property that d2 = 2. There is a problem: there is no such d in the field Q.
This elementary observation shows that Q does not have all the numbers
required to do even basic geometry. This compels us to construct a richer
number system R called the real numbers. Any real number that is not in
Q is called an irrational real number.
Before constructing R, we prove that there is no r Q such that r2 = 2.
There are several proofs of this fact. The proof given here is designed to
build on our familiarity with modular arithmetic.
Theorem 1. There is no r Q with the property that r2 = 2.
Here we use the triangle inequality and the fact that i k1 and i k2 .
Since = 20 ,
|ai ci | < .
Thus k has the desired property.
Theorem 7. The relation is symmetric on the set of all sequences in F .
Exercise 7. Prove the above.
Corollary 8. The relation is an equivalence relation on the set of se-
quences of (ai ) in F where F is any given ordered field.
Remark 5. When we restrict just to Cauchy sequences, it is still an equiv-
alence relation. In fact, any equivalence relation on a set restricts to an
equivalence relation on any subset.
Exercise 8. Show that if (ai ) (bi ) and if (ai ) has a limit, then (bi ) converges
and has the same limit as (ai ).
Remark 6. A similar argument gives the following: if (ai ) (bi ) and if (ai )
is Cauchy, then (bi ) is Cauchy. However, in this case we choose 0 = /3
instead of 0 = /2. The key step of the proof is
|bi bj | = |(bi ai ) + (ai aj ) + (aj bj )| < 0 + 0 + 0 .
Remark 7. Suppose (ai ) and (bi ) have the property that ai = bi for suffi-
ciently large i. In other words, suppose that there is a k such that ai = bi
for all i k. Then (ai ) (bi ). This is easily proved from the definition.
As a consequence, if one is Cauchy then both are, and if one converges then
both do with the same limit.
In particular, if we take a sequence (ai ) and change a finite number of
terms, then the resulting sequence is equivalent to (ai ). Likewise, if we
change the domain of (ai )in0 by replacing n0 with a larger integer, then
the resulting sequence is equivalent.
Remark 8. Several of the definitions and proofs given in this section are
similar in nature. Be very careful to learn the subtle differences between
them.
4. Boundedness Lemmas
In this section we will consider lemmas concerning bounds on Cauchy
sequences. These lemmas will be needed in later sections.
Lemma 9. Every Cauchy sequence (ai )in0 in an ordered field F is bounded
from above and below. In other words, there is a B F such that ai B
for all i n0 , and there is an element b F such that ai b for all i n0 .
Proof. Since (ai ) is Cauchy, there is a k N such that |ai aj | < 1 for
all i, j k (choose = 1). Let A be the maximum of an0 , . . . , ak , and let
B = A + 1. We will show that B is an upper bound for (ai ).
CHAPTER 7: REAL NUMBERS 7
Exercise 9. Prove the above. Hint: you may wish to look at Lemma 13 for
guidance. However, Lemma 13 is more difficult since it requires the use of
Lemma 10.
Lemma 13. Given Cauchy sequences with values in F , if (ai ) (a0i ) then
(ai bi ) (a0i bi ),
and if (bi ) (b0i ) then
(ai bi ) (ai b0i ).
This is valid for any ordered field F.
Proof. We prove the first statement; the second statement is similar. So
suppose that (ai ) (a0j ). We must prove (ai bi ) (ai b0i ). In other words, for
each positive in F we must find a k such that
i k |ai bi a0i bi | < .
By Lemma 10, there is a B F such that |bi | B for all i in the domain
of (bi ). Clearly we can choose B to be positive. Thus B 1 is also positive.
Let 0 = B 1 . Since (ai ) (a0j ), there is a k N such that
i k |ai a0i | < 0 .
Thus, if i k then
|ai bi a0i bi | = |ai a0i | |bi | |ai a0i |B < 0 B.
Since 0 B = we have
i k |ai bi a0i bi | <
as desired.
Remark 10. Identities, if they exist, are unique.3 Thus we can say the
additive identity and the multiplicative identity for R.
Proof. Let x = (ai ) be an arbitrary real number. By definition of + in R,
x + [(0)] = (ai ) + (0) = (ai + 0) = (ai ) = x
where the next to last equality is due to the fact that 0 is the additive
identity of Q (Chapter 5). By the commutative law (Theorem 14) we get
[(0)] + x = x + [(0)] = x. Thus [(0)] is the additive identity.
We leave the proof that [(1)] is the multiplicative identity to the reader.
3For any binary operation on a set S, one can show that if there is an identity, it must
be unique. For example, if 0 and 00 are additive identities, 0 = 0 + 00 = 00 .
CHAPTER 7: REAL NUMBERS 11
= |aj ai | a1 1
i aj
|aj ai | d1 d1
< 0 d2 =
So |a1 1 1
i aj | < as desired. So ai ik0
is Cauchy.
Exercise 20. Prove the above theorem. Hint: if x is positive, use the lemma.
If x is positive, try y where y is the multiplicative inverse of x. Use
the fact that x(y) = (x)y (true in any ring).
We now come to one of the main theorems of this Chapter.
Theorem 33. The real numbers R are an ordered field.
Proof. We know that R is a commutative ring by Theorem 19. We know
that 0 6= 1 by Corollary 22. Multiplicative inverses exist by Theorem 32.
We conclude that R is a field.
To show that R is an ordered field we need to check that (i) the positive
elements are closed under addition and multiplication, and (ii) the positive
elements satisfy the trichotomy law. Both these were done in the previous
section (Theorem 25 and Theorem 29).
Remark 15. Now that we know that R is an ordered field, we can use all
the definitions and results about ordered fields F from the end of Chap-
ter 6 including facts about < and absolute values. You should review these
definitions and results from Chapter 6.
Remark 16. As mentioned above, positivity defined for R is compatible with
the earlier concept of positivity defined for Q. Since x < y means y x is
positive, if follows that inequality in R is compatible with inequality in Q.
In the next chapter, we will see that this sequence is Cauchy. This Cauchy
sequence does not converge in Q, but does converge in R with limit 2.
We will now show that the real numbers R do not have such Cauchy
sequences that fail to converge. This means that R is complete: it does
not have holes. In order to make this discussion formal, we need the
following:
Definition 10. An ordered field F is said to be complete if every Cauchy
sequence in F converges to a limit in F .
We already know, from the previous section, that every Cauchy sequence
of rational numbers converges in R. However, we need to show that every
Cauchy sequence of real numbers converges in R in order to be able to assert
that R is complete. We begin with a lemma.
Lemma 42. If (ai ) is a sequence of real numbers, then there is a se-
quence (bi ) of rational numbers such that (ai ) (bi ). (Equivalence is taken
with F = R).
Proof. For each ai , we know by Corollary 40 that there is a rational num-
ber bi such that |ai bi | < 1/i. Consider the sequence (bi ) formed from such
rational numbers.4 We must show that (ai ) (bi ).
Let R be an arbitrary positive real number. We must find a k N
such that |ai bi | < for all i k. By Lemma 36 we can find a positive
rational number m/n < . Here m, n are chosen to be positive integers.
Then 1/n m/n. So 1/n < . Let k = n. If i k then
|ai bi | < 1/i (choice of bi )
1/n (i k and k = n)
< (choice of n)
4In order to avoid using the axiom of choice, we can select b to have the smallest
i
possible denominator, and among fractions with the smallest possible denominator we
choose the smallest possible numerator.