Michon-Sobre El Temps A Foucault-2002-Time Society
Michon-Sobre El Temps A Foucault-2002-Time Society
Michon-Sobre El Temps A Foucault-2002-Time Society
http://tas.sagepub.com/
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
Additional services and information for Time & Society can be found at:
Subscriptions: http://tas.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
Citations: http://tas.sagepub.com/content/11/2-3/163.refs.html
What is This?
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
Strata, Blocks, Pieces, Spirals,
Elastics and Verticals
Six figures of time in Michel Foucault
Pascal Michon
One perhaps remembers the controversies provoked in the middle of the 1960s
by the publication of The Order of Things. Sartre and, following him, almost the
entire Left under Marxist influence saw in the book a refusal of history.1 At
that time, nobody was afraid of oversimplifications: time was left wing and
space right wing.2 Structuralism received a bad press. Now many years have
passed, but the question of Foucaults relation to time remains a source of mis-
understanding. If he wrote enough history to silence his most superficial critics,
the concepts he coined and the images he used in his works have often led to the
conclusion that the concern for space and visible prevailed in Foucault, in spite
of everything, over the concern for time and sensible. It is true that Foucault
himself, because of his style and his theoretical choices, might have reinforced
that impression. Table of representations in The Order of Things, dispersion
plane of statements in Archaeology of Knowledge, planning of town, map-
ping of society, panopticism in Discipline and Punish: there is in the
Foucaldian texts an abundance of visual and spatial metaphors on which the
Time & Society copyright 2002 SAGE (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi)
VOL. 11 No. 2/3 (2002), pp. 163192 0961-463X[200209]11:2/3;163192; 027926
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
164 time & society 11(2/3)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 165
totally assured of its cognitive and moral powers. He sought to reconsider the
question of time and of his relation to thought without regret or resentment.
This probably explains why Foucault is one of the most original thinkers of
the 20th century regarding the question of time, and why some critics have
compared him to Heidegger. The struggle engaged by Foucault against the
transcendental subject and the deepening of the theme of finitude, the full
acceptation of the historicity of thought and of all of its consequences would
have drawn him close to the Heideggerian ontology (Dreyfus and Rabinow,
1982; Ijsseling, 1986; Dreyfus, 1989). I think, however, that this interpretation
is questionable and doesnt give a full understanding of Foucaults work.
Certainly, Foucault builds a post-phenomenology philosophy, which opens new
ways for the thought, but that doesnt lead him to adopt an attitude of retreat and
to regard time as sacred, as Heidegger did at the end of his life. In this article, I
would like to show the full originality of the Foucaldian conception of time:
what differentiates it both from historicism and from its subsequent critique by
the phenomenology, but also from the Heideggerian attempt to supersede the
latter as well as the former.
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
166 time & society 11(2/3)
splitting of the past into unchanging time blocks, which he advocates at the end
of the 1960s in his studies in history of science, is not very different from the
concept of immobile history that already surfaces in Braudel and which will
be fully elaborated a few years later by Le Roy Ladurie.7 Likewise, the idea of
discontinuity, of swift destruction of structural orders, which are very slowly
altering, inherits certainly the tradition of the Bachelardian history of science
(the famous epistemological split), but it has already appeared in Labrousse
and Braudel.8 Thus, it is of great significance that the two first pages of
Archaeology of Knowledge are dedicated to a tribute to Les Annales and to an
analysis of their methodological contribution:
For many years now historians have preferred to turn their attention to long
periods, as if beneath the shifts and changes of political events, they were trying
to reveal the stable, almost indestructible system of checks and balances, the
irreversible processes, the constant readjustments, the underlying tendencies that
gather force, and are then suddenly reversed after centuries of continuity, the
movements of accumulation and slow saturation, the great silent, motionless bases
that traditional history has covered with a thick layer of events [. . .]. These tools
have enabled workers in the historical field to distinguish various sedimentary
strata; linear successions, which for so long have been the object of research, have
given way to discoveries in depth. (Foucault, 1969a: 3)
Later on, when the influence of Les Annales becomes less determining, the
dialogue with the historians will continue sotto voce. During the 1970s,
Foucault will engage a history of the event mostly inspired by Nietzsche, and
yet this reorientation wont be without relations with the historians new
objects. After having been dominated by the structuralist vision, by the slow,
indeed almost immobile evolution, the historians will progressively reintroduce
the explosive time of the event. The scope will be to reconstruct the events of
the past as if they were present, i.e. instead of replacing them in an explicative
historical continuity and looking for their origin, the historians will seek to show
all their ambiguities, their contradictory aspects and especially their potential
openness, their singularity and their power of breakthrough.9
From The Order of Things one usually remembers the splitting of time in suc-
cessive epistema. For Foucault, as we know, the history of human sciences is
neither linear nor cumulative. It doesnt show any progress. It doesnt link, as
traditional historians of science do, the diversity of its contents to a transcen-
dental pole be it the subject or the man whose expression would be always
more precisely grasped. But it follows a succession of periods consisting of as
many regulating systems of discourse production rules and as many limited
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 167
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
168 time & society 11(2/3)
Husserl and later Merleau-Ponty have oscillated between the assertion that
the background practices (the implicit, the inactual, the sedimented, the non-
effected) on which the thought rests, since it is intricate in temporality, are not
representable and the other assertion that these practices can be controlled and
made explicit by the exercise of reflection between an ontology of the
Lebenswelt and a transcendental analysis of time.
When Heidegger tried, in turn, to break the objectivist and eschatological
conceptions of time, he wanted to radicalize the Husserlian project founding his
conception of temporality no longer on the actually experienced but on the
Dasein as ek-sistent. Henceforth, it was no longer the depths of the conscious-
ness but the being-in-the-world of the Dasein itself which allows definition of
time and thus its relation to being. This strategy allowed demolition of the
historicist conception of historicity, which, in order to oppose the disintegration
of man by the originary, had promised him plenitude and achievement, and the
contrasting of it with a conception which, restoring to the Dasein the void or at
least the extreme recession of the origin made out of the historicity a ceasless
rending open which frees the origin in exactly that degree to which it recedes
(Foucault, 1966: 334). However, this analytic, even though it aimed at describ-
ing time in its ontological purity, remained imprisoned in the anthropological
paradigm from which it tried to escape. In Sein und Zeit, as Heidegger himself
acknowledged later, the man, thanks to the retreat he maintains respectively to
the retreat of things back to their origin, is still the one who allows them to
develop into their being. Man is always the clearing [Lichtung] that allows
access to all things of the world: [Man] is the opening from which time in
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 169
general can be reconstituted, duration can flow, and things, at the appropriate
moment, can make their appearance (1966: 332). Thus, the work of Heidegger
remains an attempt to connect the two separate yet solidary aspects of anthro-
pology: the positive (the temporal beginning) and the fundamental (the
temporalizing clearing) (Dreyfus and Rabinow, 1982). And the reproach made
by Foucault to this strategy is of the same type as the one made against Husserl.
This solution is unstable: as soon as the origin is understood as the historicity of
practices, it retreats again and disappears, because these practices, which are
constitutive, are actually out of reach for the practicians.
Thus the phenomenology, like the historicism, which the former criticizes,
are not anything but symmetrical products of the epistemic conditions of their
epoch. Both have looked at the question of time from the anthropocentric, con-
tradictory and always unbalanced form of knowledge of the modern episteme.
And that is why they appeared as an insatiable and invading will to truth, whose
conditions of possibilities are shown by the archaeology.
The conception of time that Foucault wants to oppose both to historicism and
phenomenology is undergoing a great transformation at the beginning of the
1970s. In Archaeology of Knowledge (1969a), Foucault systematizes his
epistemic conception and extends it to his former studies on madness and clinic,
that were designed in quite a different spirit:
The unity of the discourses on madness would not be based upon the existence of
the object madness, or the constitution of a single horizon of objectivity; it
would be the interplay of the rules that made possible that appearance of objects
during a given period of time. (1969a: 35)
But beside the temporal categories inspired by Les Annales and by Lvi-Strauss
appear new notions. To Braudelian principles of discontinuity (rupture and
branching of processes described traditionally as linear), of multiplicity (tempo-
rality contains differing chronologies which cannot be unified), Foucault adds
the Nietzschean principles of discreteness (irruption and temporal spreading of
the events) and of contingency (no necessity of the events).10
In his inaugural address at the Collge de France, LOrdre du discours (The
Order of Discourse) (1971a), and in the essay entitled Nietzsche, la gnalogie,
lhistoire (Nietzsche, Genealogy, History) (1971b/1994), Foucault explains
that he wants to genealogically rework the question of the conditions of possi-
bility regarding the insatiable deployment of modern knowledge, structurally
studied in The Order of Things. He wants to try to describe the entanglement of
desires and powers that have been at its origin:
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
170 time & society 11(2/3)
True discourse, liberated by the nature of its form from desire and power, is
incapable of recognizing the will to truth which pervades it; and the will to truth,
having imposed itself upon us for so long, is such that the truth it seeks to reveal
cannot fail to mask it. (Foucault, 1971a: 219)
Nietzsche offers, henceforth, the model for a use of history and a conception of
time which are no longer organized by metaphysical concepts. Unlike a great
part of the history written during the 19th century, which was organized around
notions such as unity of meaning, continuity, development and progress, the
Nietzschean genealogy proposes to restore the dispersion, the proliferation, the
heterogeneity, the difference of the event:
The wirkliche Historie transposes the relationship ordinarily established between
the eruption of an event and necessary continuity. An entire historical tradition
(theological or rationalistic) aims at dissolving the singular event into an ideal
continuity as a teleological movement or a natural process. Effective history,
however, deals with events in terms of their most unique characteristics, their
most acute manifestations. An event, consequently, is not a decision, a treaty, a
reign, or a battle, but the reversal of a relationship of forces, the usurpation of
power, the appropriation of a vocabulary turned against those who have once used
it. (Foucault, 1971b/1994: 88)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 171
entire juridical discourse and especially the discourse of human rights, would
have been used to hide the generalization and intensification of the detailed play
of subjecting forces, the microphysics of power and the body disciplines that
were imposed at the same time in factories, worker accommodation, barracks,
schools, hospitals and prisons. These assertions sparked off a disapproval as
spectacular as the one provoked by the structuralist-styled analysis, which he
had been developing a few years before against humanism, historicist Marxism
and existentialist philosophy. Ironically, Foucault, who was condemned for his
refusal of history, was now rebuked by critics reproaching him for liking
history too much and disintegrating the transcendental, man and the subject in
the chaos of time. The relativist epistemological and ethical position, which
would have been adopted by Foucault as his critique of democracy, would take
their roots in a vitalist and metaphysical conception of historicity and time,
inherited directly from Nietzsche.12
If we look more closely, the matter seems to be less simple than what his
critics say. Nietzsche refers all representations, science, philosophy and
morality, but also art, to the interplay of forces and the will to power that
expresses itself through them. From this viewpoint, there is no more thing-in-
itself; only phenomena instituted by a perspective and without any vis--vis in a
background-world. There are only events dispersed in time. The thing-in-itself
and the transcendental that faces it seem to be fantasies made up by a will gone
astray, which tries to stop the becoming and to give itself the feeling of control-
ling its proliferation. But at the same time, the world can appear as this surface
without depth, only because it is perceived as deployment of the will to power.
In his last texts, particularly in those edited by his sister, Nietzsche seems to find
again an explanatory systematicity. Then the will to power regains simultane-
ously both roles of the thing in itself, which just disappeared: its critical role of
limit of human knowledge and its ontological role of substratum of the reality.
The will to power means both the disappearance and the reappearance of the
thing in itself in the plane of immanence.
This phenomenon explains why Nietzsches thought can be interpreted in two
absolutely different ways and why we must be cautious not to impute to
Foucault a vitalist thought. Some critics such as Gtz,13 Jaspers14 or Heidegger
(1961), reading mostly from The Will to Power and arguing that the critical role
of the thing-in-itself cannot be detached from its ontological role, consider that
Nietzsche, repatriating the latter in the plane of immanence, builds dogmatic-
ally, whatever one may say, a doctrine of being which aims at establishing the
most general feature of all beings, as when he claims that the most intimate
essence of being is the will to power (cited in Granier, 1966: 372 et seq.).
Nietzsche seems to be then as the one thinker who, inverting the Platonism and
getting rid of the suprasensible lining of the world, actually brought forth the
exact contrary of what he was looking for and put the metaphysical dualism of
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
172 time & society 11(2/3)
the transcendental and the empirical to its climax. But others, no less numerous,
like Deleuze (1962), Granier (1966) or Foucault himself, who refer only to the
greatest of Nietzsches texts and reject the very suspicious edition of his last
writings made up by his sister,15 see, in his thought on the contrary, a critical
radicalization and argue that it aims at the way the essence of being accom-
plishes itself as Being-interpreted (Granier, 1966: 378), i.e. necessarily split or
differentiated. The Nietzschean view is then understood as an antimetaphysical
hyper-Kantism emancipating the thought of any transcendence, as a philosophy
of temporality freed of any synthetic vis--vis.
For not having taken this renewal into account and for not having under-
stood its critical force, in particular, regarding Heidegger his censors, inspired
by the latter, have attributed a questionable interpretation to him. Thus, in a
double irony, they remained blind to the Foucaldian hyper-Kantism,16 which
should have satisfied them, and they unconsciously adopted a philosophy which
they rejected on the other hand. Instead of understanding the critical force of the
new Foucaldian approach, the permanent split that it postulates inside of the
being and the new conception of time that it implies, they only saw in it, like
Heidegger in Nietzsche, a new metaphysics of force, an energetism generalizing
dogmatically to the globality of being a particular quality of human experi-
ence.17
The apparatus [dispositif] of sexuality that appeared in the West at the end of
the 18th century and in which we have been living since then, neither consists of
a system of rules, nor is generated by a vital, natural, already given entity,
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 173
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
174 time & society 11(2/3)
All these changes form a series of comings and goings, which progressively
increase or decrease the tension: capture and seduction, confrontation and
mutual reinforcement (1976: 45). After each step the respective places shift and
the general form of temporal processes looks like a bouquet of rising or
descending spirals: These attractions, these evasions, these circular incitements
have traced around bodies and sexes, not boundaries not to be crossed, but
perpetual spirals of power and pleasure (1976: 45). Further on in the book, the
same idea: It [the power] attracts its varieties by means of spirals in which
pleasure and power reinforce one another; it does not set up a barrier; it pro-
vided places of maximum saturation (1976: 47). Still further on: Pleasure and
power do not cancel or turn back against one another; they seek out, overlap,
and reinforce one another. They are linked together by complex mechanisms
and devices of excitation and incitement (1976: 48).
In The Use of Pleasure (1984a) and The Care of the Self (1984b), Foucault
abandoned the history of sexuality for a history of the forms and modalities of
the relation to self by which the individual constitutes and recognizes himself
qua subject (1984a: 6), a history thanks to which he hoped to be able to under-
stand the birth of the subject of desire (1984a: 6). But this new turn in his work
gave rise once again to many critiques. The fact that the individual, at the same
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 175
time both subjugates and subjectivizes himself seemed to many, at best para-
doxical, at worst a useless complication to bring to light the fact that the
individual possesses a priori an ethical subjectivity. Seeking to understand how
the individual institutes himself as a subject, Foucault would play with words
and hide under the cloak of the individual and his practices, the classical
patterns of the subject (it is he who observes and understands his own state,
imagines what he could be, wants to transform himself and then acts according-
ly). According to others, since the subject is simultaneously constituting and
constituted, free and produced by practices, Foucault would repeat the error for
which he has blamed Husserl and he would give a transcendental value to
empirical contents. The surprising reappearence of a theme which was until
then at the neuralgic centre of Foucaults own critiques and refusals would be
the symptom of the failure of the archeological and genealogical methods to
supersede the phenomenology and the aporia of the analytic of finitude.
Foucault would have ended up to be very close, in his last years, to Heidegerrian
hermeneutics and ontology of time (Dreyfus and Rabinow, 1982), which could
be read as the unthought of Foucaults work not what he wouldnt have
thought of, or what he would have forgotten, but what functions in it without
being clearly formulated and thus demands an exterior elaboration (Han, 1998:
27). Finally, the truth of Foucaults conception of time would thus be found in
Heidegger.
With the passing of time, we can judge better both the continuity and the
articulations of his thought. His last approach remains fundamentally genealogi-
cal: the aim is not only to demystify the pseudo-evidence of the cogito on which
we lean, by showing the historical construction of what we take for natural and
transcendental,19 but also to find in the past other forms of subjectivation,
which, Foucault hopes, could be used as basis for an alternative definition of the
subject, usable today (Foucault, 1984c/1994: 343, 34950). On the other hand,
Foucault doesnt aim at a genealogy of the subject conceived as a unitary entity,
but he contents himself by following only the history of the moral subject. As
far as the epistemic and the political subjects are concerned, he refers to his
former studies (Foucault, 1982a/1994: 2223; 1984c/1994: 352). That implies
that there is not one but many subjects to which the individuals have access
according to various ways (epistemic rules, mechanisms of knowledge-power,
practices of the self) and varying temporalities (the epistema, the apparatus and
the practices of the self have different chronologies).20 Thus to affirm that the
individual sets himself up as moral subject doesnt imply the autonomy of his
sensibility or of his reason, nor even of his will or of his imagination. Both the
former and the latter are all instituted, but in various ways and within interfering
histories. What distinguishes moral from epistemic and political subjects is
that it is instituted by a folding of the forces upon themselves;21 whereas the
epistemic subject is cast within a system of rules and the political subject
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
176 time & society 11(2/3)
emerges in the midst of a field of force relations. Thus we must see the indi-
vidual as the seat of an ill-assorted bouquet of processes of subjectivation,
which lean on each other according to an irregular and changing pattern.
It is true that the incompletion of Foucaults work certainly played a great
role in the misconception of his effort to build an ethics yet maintaining the
same spirit as in his former studies. And I must say a few words about that. If
he explicitly contemplated its possibility, Foucault didnt have enough time to
present a complete and organized historical description of all these modes of
subjectivation. His last two books do concentrate essentially on the relation
between practices of the self and problematizations, between working on ones
own life and games of truth. But they leave their relations with the technolo-
gies of power a little bit in the darkness, without anywhere considering either
their relations with the epistemic systems. The former are not absent, as, for
example, in the reflection on the power belonging, in Greece, to the master of
the house over his wife and his people, but the problem is only tackled in other
contemporary texts.22 I cannot but ask the reader to look at these texts, most of
which are unfortunately still inaccessible, but which are essential for an under-
standing of the global meaning of Foucaults thought in its last stage. While
restricting myself to the published texts and knowing that this limitation entails
an under-representation of the theme of power (except the very particular topic
of the power over oneself), which we must keep in mind, it is still possible to
grasp the principal characteristics of the last Foucaldian conceptions of time.
First of all, there is, in these studies, a type of temporality familiar to
Foucaults readers, which seems to bring them some years back. The ancient
subjectivation patterns have known, between the fifth century bc and the third
century ad, a long and relatively stable period of time, during which, as we
shall see, lifestyles were subjected to very slow mutations. When Christianity
prevailed in the fourth century in the entire Graeco-Roman world, a deep trans-
formation made the old culture fall apart and a new era of the history of subjec-
tivation began the one we are still living in characterized by the constitution
of individuals as subjects of desire.
Looking more closely though, we can see that these outlines differ from the
epistemic patterns, which they recall, by a few aspects, which are important.
1. If Foucault gives very few explanations about the practical reasons that
provoked this rupture, these reasons are not absent. There is, as we have already
seen, a number of unpublished essays, which we shall have to take into account
one day. But, without waiting for these publications, we can figure out what
Foucault had in mind through what Paul Veyne says on a very similar issue. It is
probable that, like his friend and interlocutor, Foucault first thinks of the change
in the modes of domination that occurred under Constantine with the Christian-
ization of the imperial power. Veyne provides as example the cessation of the
gladiator fights, in the late Roman empire, and their reproblematization. This
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 177
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
178 time & society 11(2/3)
part of Antiquity does not have the immobility of an episteme. It goes through a
type of mutation, which implies, for Foucault, a new conception of temporality.
He notes that there is, from the models of ancient Greece (fourth century bc) to
those of the climax of the Roman Empire (third century ad) a whole set of
recommendations, prohibitions or social norms that remains remarkably con-
stant. The main dietetic precepts change very little (Foucault, 1984b: 104). The
advice concerning the sexual life remains more or less the same (1984b: 237).
The new reflections on marriage, which appear in particular in the Stoic texts of
the Imperial era seek to define a mode of coexistence between husband and
wife, a modality of relations between them, and a way of living together that are
rather different from what was proposed in the classical texts (1984b: 150), but
they do so without calling the traditional structures into question (1984b: 150),
especially without ever thinking of proposing to fit the marriage into a different
legal framework (1984b: 150). Last but not least, the new valorization of love
for boys is partly conserved in spite of a new valorization of the theme of love
between sexes (1984b: 2023).
Yet Foucault spots, on this almost immobile ground, variations that drag the
lifestyles into a slow mutation, into a kind of continental drift of ethics.23 The
transformations, during the Roman Empire, of the problematizations and tech-
nologies of the self developed by the Greeks must be read as an inner mutation
of a relatively stable order and a new appreciation of the elements of this order,
as a shift, a change of orientation, a difference in emphasis (Foucault, 1984b:
67). Regarding dietetics and the problematization of health, the change is
marked by an increased apprehension, a broader and more detailed definition of
the correlations between the sexual act and the body, a closer attention to the
ambivalence of its effects and its disturbing consequences (1984b: 238).
Foucault notes that there is a greater preoccupation with the body (1984b:
238), but also a different way of thinking about sexual activity, and of fearing
it (1984b: 238). Regarding wives and marriage, the transformation concerns
the valorization of the conjugal bond and the dual relation that constitutes it
(1984b: 238). Finally, regarding boys, there is, on the contrary, a deproblemati-
zation and a weakening of the value of friendship bonds. Generally, the art of
taking care of the self is modified by a series of little strokes which finally
change its colours: This art of the self no longer focuses so much on the
excesses that one can indulge in [. . .] it gives increasing emphasis to the frailty
of the individual faced with the manifold ills that sexual activity can give rise to.
It also underscores the need to subject that activity to a universal form by which
one is bound (1984b: 238).
Thus the technologies of the self and the problematizations that are linked to
them undergo transformations whose logic is no longer linked to the play of
interacting forces. These transformations rather occur in accordance with a
model which can be, strictly speaking, labelled as stylistic or rhetorical, a model
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 179
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
180 time & society 11(2/3)
The elaboration of a genealogy of ethics in the last years of Foucaults life led
him to a philosophy of present and modernity. One of the objectives aimed by
the use of genealogy, during the 1970s, was to make a history of present.
Foucault understood these terms in a very different way than did the historians,
who, following Pierre Nora, began to use them concurrently.24 According to
him, it was not a matter of making the history of the most contemporary period,
insisting on the acceleration of history and on the reevaluation of the event.
Rather, it was a question of reversing our nave understanding of the present by
a circle going through a diagnosis of the current condition of our societies,
based on the identification of their political body technologies (1975: 35), and
the genealogy of the latter which confirms their hidden significance. The
question was to understand correctly what kind of world we are living in and the
genealogy was used to overcome the apparently obvious facts on which we are
resting.25 Discipline and Punish aimed at showing, for example, starting from
the problem of prison and from its genealogy, the large panel of technologies
that were used to discipline the bodies in our modern societies. In The History of
Sexuality I, the confession, the psychoanalytic cure, were singled out as occa-
sions for the elaboration of the technologies of the body experienced every-
where today and yet not known as such.
But this problematic of present has been transformed by the study of the
building of moral subject. This view, according to which our action is a con-
sequence of our correct knowledge of the present, has been replaced by the
complementary view, tracing the roots of our actions back to our temporal con-
dition of being-present itself. In one of his last texts, dedicated partly to Kant (as
curiously his first one too), What is Enlightenment? (Foucault, 1984e/1994),
Foucault no longer contemplates the present as a question of knowledge, but as
a question of ethics, what he calls une ontologie de lactualit. Asking himself
about the meaning of what he is experiencing, the Aufklrung, notes Foucault,
Kant no longer considers the present as one of those revolutions of the world in
which the world is turning backwards (as did Plato in The Stateman), either as
an attempt to decipher in it the heralding signs of a forthcomming event (as did
Augustine), or as a point of transition towards the dawning of a new world (as
did Vico) (1984e/1994: 33). He is probably the first philosopher to try to under-
stand what is the contemporary status [actualit] of his own enterprise, that is
certainly still how the present is placed in the global movement of history, with
its fundamental directions, but also how the individuals are responsible for this
global process:
It is in the reflection on today as difference in history and as motive for a par-
ticular philosophical task that the novelty of this text appears to me to lie. And, by
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 181
We understand why the reflection on the present leads Foucault to join the
panel of thinkers who, having abandoned the criteria for action that were pro-
vided by the various historicisms, collided with the question of the ethics:
Nietzsche, Weber, Sartre and the existentialist thinkers, Heidegger, Bataille,
Benjamin, Derrida and the postmodern philosophers. And it is very interesting
to see what kind of solution he proposes. If he rejects those such as Marx and
Habermas, who think that the modernity is the historical period in which uni-
versal emancipation was promised to humankind and that we just have to realize
that not-yet-fulfilled promise, he refuses, on the other hand, to adopt the theme
of postmodernity developed by some thinkers who see, in Heideggers wake,
modernity as an ordinary epoch of the history of being arriving to its end.
Criticizing Lyotard, without spelling things out, he writes:
I know that the modernity is often spoken of as an epoch, or at least as a set of
features characteristic of an epoch; situated on a calendar, it would be preceded by
a more or less naive or archaic premodernity, and followed by an enigmatic and
troubling postmodernity. (. . .) Thinking back on Kants text, I wonder whether
we may not envisage modernity rather as an attitude than as a period of history.
(Foucault, 1984e/1994: 39)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
182 time & society 11(2/3)
narcissistic wave, which submerged the entire Occident during those years.28
But here, once again, it seems that these objections go in the wrong direction.29
First, Foucault was not unconscious of the risks of misinterpretation of an
ethics, which wants to be an aesthetics of existence. We know that very early
on, he read and appreciated Christopher Laschs (1979) book, The Culture of
Narcissism, one of the first studies on contemporary narcissism (whose begin-
ning Lasch traces, besides, much before the 1980s) (Martin et al., 1988: 4).
Second, if the practices of liberty, which Foucault now refers to, are not
practices of liberation or emancipation, it is not because these practices are
not sometimes, indeed often, necessary, but because they are not sufficient by
themselves and because their mottos are still greatly inspired by metaphysical
humanist concerns (Foucault, 1984f/1994: 710). The practices of liberty cannot
use any transcendental criteria as guides, be they transcendental markers emerg-
ing gradually out of the historical actions, or a vanishing transcendence as in the
phenomenology. They are condemned to permanently invent and spring up, as
untimely verticals, perpendicular to the flow of history, in order to break
through the walls of the passing time. In this morality, which is closer to Walter
Benjamins than to Sartres, the present opens onto a multiplicity of forms of
action in which authenticity has less worth than autonomy (Foucault, 1984c/
1994: 351).
Third, Foucault avoids a simple return of the transcendental subject or the
glorification of the I, because he considers the ethical subject in a very new
way, i.e. not hermeneutically, as assert Dreyfus, Rabinow and Han, but from a
poetics viewpoint. The analysis dedicated to Baudelaire escapes from the
genealogy versus phenomenology dilemma and shows what very few philo-
sophers or specialists in human sciences have been able to see.30 Baudelaire
invents, from his own literary practice, a conception of modernity which is
not historicist or simply aesthetic, or aimed at flattering the sensibility, nor
defined by the Heideggerian experience of the Sprache. He sees that modernity
is not, as contend numerous philosophers, historians and sociologists, a never
satisfied will to break with the tradition and a sterile attraction for the new. It is
not even an epoch dominated by the subjectivity or the science. For Baudelaire,
it is first of all an ethical attitude, an ethos, a twofold mode of existence: on the
first hand, it is imagining the present different as it is, it is criticizing it intransi-
gently and transforming it through practices of liberty (Foucault, 1984e/1994:
41); on the other hand, it is looking very carefully at it, and attempting to
extract from fashion whatever element it may contain of poetry within history
(Baudelaire, 1976: 693), that is to say, it is looking for something lasting and
transmissible:
For him, being modern does not lie in recognizing and accepting this perpetual
movement; on the contrary, it lies in adopting a certain attitude with respect to this
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 183
Conclusion
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
184 time & society 11(2/3)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 185
us, especially, Heidegger added in the last part of his life, through language
[Sprache].
To these statements, Foucault answers that if time cannot indeed be con-
ceived phenomenologically as a mere transcendental and immutable condition
of possibility of any human knowledge and practice, it cannot either be thought
of ontologically as a horizon of a multiple and erratic spreading of the original
essence of truth, which would be independent of the human beings and their
fights. The very idea of an originary, constantly setting back, such as the one
described through the figure of the ontological difference, or the idea of a pri-
mordial opening which would allow all openings by its very obscurity, badly
masks the will and the moral perspectives that motivated them successively.
Behind the radically and willingly destroying concept of a disappearing arche,
we can perceive Heideggers revolutionary desires, experienced between the
wars, whether on the ethical level (against Judaism, Christianity and humanism)
or on the political level (against democracy, capitalism and bolshevism).
Destroying metaphysics is to participate in the destruction of the various worlds,
which are founded on it. Similarly, the language-based reinterpretation of the
relation between being and time proposed by Heidegger after the war doesnt
completely hide the new moral and political viewpoint adopted by the philo-
sopher after the failure of his former political commitment. Thus, the idea that
only the language speaks [nur die Sprache spricht] and that man says and
understands in history only the aspects of the being that the language uncovers
for him, this idea is linked to his search of Gelassenheit, i.e. interior serenity,
mystical wait of the coming of the word, retreat and passivity regarding history.
Thus, the ontology of time, even in the very particular meaning Heidegger
gives to that term, is nothing but a viewpoint about time. The latter, as well as
the being, is actually always interpreted, constituted by the perspective and the
force that apply to it. It only receives form and meaning from the various moral
perspectives, which solicit it in the midst of the current struggles.32 Therefore, it
can be conceived in multiple ways, which correspond each time to a position in
an existing conflict, as shown by the various complaints Foucault had to face
each time he changed his conception of time. For example, time can be seen as
a stratified flow composed of temporalities proceeding at various speeds, as a
string of immobile blocks separated by swift breaks, as a succession of explod-
ing events, as a series of sequences progressing in spirals, as an oriented length
of time following another length of time subjected to a slow systemic drift, or as
a present which raises vertically its practices of liberty. Time has changing faces
according to the objects whose transformation it measures (dividing practices of
reason, rules of knowledge generation, apparatus of power-knowledge disci-
plining the bodies, productions of moral subjects), but these objects are them-
selves chosen accordingly to moral and political projects. That is why our
radical historicity and the critique of the anthropological illusion that it implies
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
186 time & society 11(2/3)
dont indicate that we have to imprison ourselves in the only temporality of the
Sprache and adopt an attitude of retreat and of quasi-mystical waiting. On the
contrary, our historicity opens to us infinite possibilities of interpretations of
time and as many practices of liberty.
Notes
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 187
guage one of those structural ruptures, one of these deep, silent, painless breaks, as
they say. One was born within one particular state of society (that is to say, simulta-
neously, a mentality, some frames, a civilization and especially an economic
civilization), which several generations have known before us, but everything can
collapse before our life ends (Braudel, 1950/1969: 132). A few years later: Still
more significant than the deep structures of life are their breaking points, their swift
or slow deterioration under the pressure of contradictory forces (Braudel, 1958/
1969: 71).
9. The theme of the return of the event is launched by an historian of the contempo-
rary period (Pierre Nora), but is rapidly adopted by the Marxist historians of the
modern period (Michel Vovelle), who want to keep alive the idea of revolutionary
rupture attacked by the supporters of a more right wing conception of the longue
dure (Franois Furet). It is developed as well by the historians inspired by the
1968 events, more attached to restore the speech of the unknowns or of the not
remembered by the history than the one of the masses (Arlette Farge). This trend
is parallel to the Italian development of the micro-history with Carlo Ginzburg and
Giovanni Levi. On history of event, see Nora (1974) and for a good presentation of
the spirit of this period, Farge (1997). Foucault participates in these changes with
works, which are less read than others, but which are not less interesting (Foucault,
1973; Farge and Foucault, 1982).
10. Daddabo (1998) accurately lists these categories.
11. According to a very appropriate metaphor coined by Veyne (1978: 225).
12. The most explicit expression of this thesis can be found in the text Foucault
and Deleuze: the Vitalism against the Law (Ferry and Renaut, 1987: 77 et seq.). But
it supports many other critiques made about Foucault on different grounds. See for
example, Gauchet and Swain (1980), Habermas (1985) and Honneth (1986).
13. One can see that the will to power becomes a substitute for what the early meta-
physics called God. It is a formula, a simple word for something that cannot be
expressed with a formula or word.
14. Jaspers writes about Jenseits von Gut und Bse: So Nietzsche ends up with a
determination in the old metaphysical way. The universe seen from within, the
universe defined and described through its intelligible characteristics wont be any-
thing else than the will to power (Jaspers, 1936/1961: 298, cited in Granier, 1966:
375).
15. In one of his last interviews, Foucault explains: My relation to Nietzsche, or what I
owe Nietzsche, derives mostly from the texts of around 1880, where the question of
the truth, the history of the truth and the will to truth were central to his work
(1983/1994: 32). And later on, he adds: I think there is a perceptible displacement in
Nietzsches texts between those which are broadly preoccupied with the question
of will to knowledge and those which are preoccupied with the will to power
(1983/1994: 33).
16. Franois Ewald, who at that time was his assistant at The Collge de France, writes
under his control: If Foucault certainly belongs to the philosophical tradition, it is to
the critical tradition which begins with Kant and one could name its project Critical
History of the Thought (Foucault, 1984d/1994: 631).
17. Certainly, it is not difficult to find in Foucaults works numerous statements which
have vitalist undertones. One finds, for example, especially in the texts written
during the 1970s, a whole set of metaphors linked to generation. He speaks about
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
188 time & society 11(2/3)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 189
26. For a historical and conceptual distinction of modernity and the modern see
Michon (1999).
27. This interpretation of Kant, which could seem strange to some readers, follows the
lines of the interpretation of Nietzsche as hyper-Kantian explained above.
28. See, for example, the question asked by Dreyfus and Rabinow (Foucault, 1984c/
1994: 350; Ferry and Renaut, 1985, 1987; Hadot, 1989: 267).
29. Except those of Pierre Hadot, who reads Foucault all at once with sympathy and
without leniency (Michon, 2002).
30. As far as we know, Henri Meschonnic is the only one thinker, with Foucault, to give
their full significance to Baudelaires intuitions of the necessity to reconceptualize
the concepts of modernity and present them from the viewpoint of the poetics
(Meschonnic, 1988/1993).
31. For a critique of the Heideggerian conception of time and history, see Michon
(2000).
32. Unfortunately, I discovered after writing this paper Leonardo Daddabbos book
(1999) dedicated to the question of time in Foucault. Daddabbo explains the diver-
sity of Foucaults conceptions by the project of thinking the time through the body.
It is an interesting hypothesis, which should be discussed seriously, and I regret not
having been able to do it here.
References
Baudelaire, Ch. (1976) Le Peintre de la vie moderne, in uvres compltes, pp.
790815. Paris: Gallimard.
Braudel, F. (1950/1969) Pour une conomie historique, in crits sur lhistoire, pp.
12333. Paris: Flammarion.
Braudel, F. (1958/1969) Histoire et sciences sociales. La longue dure, in crits sur
lhistoire, pp. 4183. Paris: Flammarion.
Canguilhem, G. (1967) Mort de lhomme ou puisement du cogito, Critique 242:
599618.
Daddabbo, L. (1998) Foucault et le temps, in L. DAlessandro and A. Marino (eds),
Michel Foucault. Trajectoires au cur du prsent, pp. 28190. Paris: LHarmattan.
Daddabbo, L. (1999) Tempocorpo. Forme temporali in Michel Foucault. Napoli: La citt
del sole.
Deleuze, G. (1962) Nietzsche et la philosophie. Paris: PUF.
Deleuze, G. (1986) Foucault. Paris: Minuit.
Dreyfus, H. (1989) De la mise en ordre des choses, in Michel Foucault philosophe, pp.
101121. Paris: Le Seuil.
Dreyfus, H. and Rabinow, P. (1982) Michel Foucault. Beyond Structuralism and
Hermeneutics. With an Afterword by Michel Foucault. Chicago: the University of
Chicago Press.
Eribon, D. (1991) Michel Foucault. Paris: Flammarion.
Farge, A. (1997) Linstance de lvnement, in Au risque de Foucault, pp. 1929.
Paris: Centre Pompidou.
Farge, A. and Foucault, M. (1982) Le dsordre des familles. Paris: Gallimard.
Ferry, L. and Renaut, A. (1985) La pense 68. Paris: Gallimard.
Ferry, L. and Renaut, A. (1987) 6886, Itinraires de lindividu. Paris: Gallimard.
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
190 time & society 11(2/3)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
michon: michel foucault 191
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013
192 time & society 11(2/3)
Downloaded from tas.sagepub.com at Biblioteca de la Universitat Pompeu Fabra on January 23, 2013