Mythology, Madness, and Laughter PDF
Mythology, Madness, and Laughter PDF
Mythology, Madness, and Laughter PDF
AND LAUGHTER
Also available from Continuum:
www.continuumbooks.com
B2745.G33 2009
141.0943dc22 2009008265
Notes 168
Bibliography 190
Index 199
vi
Introduction: A Plea for a Return to Post-Kantian
Idealism
Markus Gabriel and Slavoj iek
1
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
2
INTRODUCTION
3
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
such. For precisely this reason, Schelling in his Essay on Human Freedom
recommends a higher realism of freedom:
It will always remain odd, however, that Kant, after having rst distin-
guished things-in-themselves from appearances only negatively
through their independence from time and later treating independence
from time and freedom as correlate concepts in the metaphysical
discussions of his Critique of Practical Reason, did not go further toward
the thought of transferring this only possible positive concept of the
in-itself also to things; thereby he would immediately have raised
himself to a higher standpoint of reection and above the negativity
that is the character of his theoretical philosophy.12
The status of the limits of knowledge changes with German Idealism.
The epistemological nitude of reason which cannot legitimately be
transgressed without generating metaphysical nonsense for the Idealists
indicates the limitations of Kantian reection. They believe that Kant got
stuck half-way, whereas from a thoroughly Kantian perspective, his
idealist successors completely misunderstood his critical project and fell
back into pre-critical metaphysics or, worst even, mystical Schwrmerei.
Accordingly, there are mainly two versions of the passage from Kant to
German Idealism which respectively result from the unfortunate and
often even hostile dividing line within contemporary philosophy. Philo-
sophers who characterize themselves by belonging to the analytic tradi-
tion (a term which, as a matter of fact, denotes at the most a family
resemblance of methods) tend to believe that Kant is the last traditional
philosopher who, at least partially, makes sense. Until most recently,
analytic philosophers dened themselves by a deep hostility towards the
Post-Kantian turn of German philosophy and (in the wake of Moore and
Russell) regarded it as one of the greatest catastrophes, as a bunch of
undisciplined regressions into meaningless speculation and so forth. On
the other hand, there is a group of philosophers who deem the Post-
Kantian speculative-historical approach to philosophical thought the
highest achievement of philosophy which we have not yet even fully
understood. They believe that many of the central insights of German
Idealism still wait to be translated into contemporary philosophy.
However, the latter group of philosophers tends to neglect those features
of German Idealism which, at rst glance, do not appear to be translat-
able into contemporary philosophy. Yet, we rmly believe that it is an
4
INTRODUCTION
5
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
6
INTRODUCTION
7
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
8
INTRODUCTION
9
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
10
INTRODUCTION
11
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
12
INTRODUCTION
Hegelianism has lost its innocence forever. To act like a full Hegelian today
is the same as to write tonal music after the Schnberg revolution.
The predominant Hegelian strategy that is emerging as a reaction to
this scare-crow image of Hegel the Absolute Idealist, is the deated
image of Hegel freed of ontological-metaphysical commitments, reduced
to a general theory of discourse and to discourses constitutive norma-
tivity. This approach is best exemplied by so-called Pittsburgh Hegelians
(Brandom, McDowell): no wonder Habermas praises Brandom, since
Habermas also avoids directly approaching the big ontological question
(are humans really a subspecies of animals, is Darwinism true?), the
question of God or nature, of idealism or materialism. It would be easy
to prove that Habermass neo-Kantian avoidance of ontological commit-
ment is in itself necessarily ambiguous: while Habermasians treat
naturalism as the obscene secret not to be publicly admitted (of course
man developed from nature, of course Darwin was right . . .), this
obscure secret is a lie, it covers up their deeply idealist form of thought
(the a priori transcendentals of communication which cannot be deduced
from natural being). The truth is hidden and at the same time manifested
in the form: while Habermasians secretly think they are really material-
ists, the truth lies in the idealist form of their thinking. To put it provoca-
tively, Habermasians tend to be royalists in the republican form. They
reduce naturalism to a fruitful hypothesis which seems to be inevitable
given that contemporary discourse has committed itself to a scientic
world-picture. Yet, to be an actual naturalist is not to subscribe to neces-
sary ction, but to really believe in materialism. It is, in other words, not
enough to insist that Kant and Hegel have to teach us something about
the realm of normativity which takes place in the wider domain of the
realm of nature. It is, on the contrary, important to re-appropriate
German Idealism to a fuller extent. If discourse, representation, mind, or
thought in general cannot consistently be opposed to the substantial real
which is supposed to be given beforehand, independent of the existence
of concept-mongering creatures, then we have to bite the bullet of ideal-
ism: we need a concept of the world or the real which is capable of accounting for
the replication of reality within itself.21
Our theories of the world as such are part of the world. Our system(s)
of belief are not transcendent entities occupying a deontological space
thoroughly distinguished from the ontological space best described in the
language of physics. We rmly believe that the deated image of Hegel
13
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
does not sufce. The fetishism of quantication and of the logical form prevail-
ing in much of contemporary philosophical discourse is characterized by a lack of
reection on its constitution. It is our aim to dismantle this lack and to argue
that we are in need of a twenty-rst-century Post-Kantian Idealism
which would, of course, not be geographically restricted. The era of
German Idealism is over, but the era of Post-Kantian Idealism has just
begun (with neo-Hegelianism as its rst necessary error).
14
CHAPTER ONE
The Mythological Being of Refl ection An Essay
on Hegel, Schelling, and the Contingency of
Necessity
Markus Gabriel
15
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
16
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
17
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
18
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
19
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
20
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
21
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
22
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
23
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
24
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
25
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
26
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
27
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
that the whole world is inside our head. This is what I call the modern
stance of reection.
It is quite remarkable to see contemporary cinema rediscovering the
dream-like structure of experience and substituting it for the intermina-
ble ironical self-denial of postmodern fragmentation. Postmodernism (in
the totality of its aesthetic and philosophical expressions) refrained from
asserting any metaphysical position. On the contrary, contemporary
cinema is widely characterized by the return of metaphysics. If we assume
that contemporary art/lm actually reects something we could call the
contemporary general state of mind, then we have to accept that we are
again searching for a more plausible, a more digestible, a more bearable
answer to our lack of certainty about the world and its meaning.
Many movies are shot in a transcendent light, a phenomenon Raoul
Eshelman describes as theistic creation.38 A variety of recent examples
may illustrate this general tendency, in particular The Chumscrubber
(2005), directed by Arie Posin, and Francis Ford Coppolas new movie
Youth without Youth (2007) which is based on a mysticism-driven novel
by Mircea Eliade.
At the end of The Chumscrubber, a point of view transcending the
dream-like reality of suburban America is achieved in symbolic drawings
of a blue dolphin. The Mayor Michael Ebbs at some point of the story
discovers his artistic energies which identify him with the theist creator
of the suburban universe. He feels a sudden urge to ll up walls with
pictures of blue dolphins, which literally represent the structure of the
city (whose mayor he is) as we can see in the nal shot of the movie
from a Gods eye point of view. We can interpret this as the expression of
a longing for a mystical unity, for the hidden harmony of all nite things
(blue is always a symbol for transcendence, like the blue ower of
romanticism; Picassos blue period; Blue Velvet; Wallace Stevens The Man
with the Blue Guitar, etc.). This idea is also conveyed in Charlie Kaufmans
Synecdoche, New York (2008). Here, the mystical unity turns out to be a
synecdoche, an innite interlacing of imaginary strata of the protago-
nists fragmentary life. Despite the turbulent rupture we experience in
our personal life and despite the utter contingency of the roles we play,
there ultimately is a background in front of which we enact our lives.
Contemporary cinema returns to metaphysical harmony after post-
modern turmoil. Yet, we must not forget that this new harmony may
very well be the reection of capitalisms monistic self-assertion after
28
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
29
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
30
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
First Critique and his argument is as plain as it is striking. If the self was
a substance, our cognitive access to it would have to be the grasp of a
substance. Yet, our cognitive access to any substance is fallible insofar as
it has to represent the substance in question. Even if we represent our-
selves, the represented self is not identical with the representing self
given that the subject of experiencing is never identical with any possible
object of experience. Whatever the object of our scrutiny may be, it has
to become an object among others whereby it is determined as such in a
wider context. Intentional correlates, i.e. objects of experience, generally
are determined in the wider framework of a world-view, a meshwork of
mutually inclusive or exclusive conceptual mediations.
31
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
subject, threatening its identity from within. Kant is thus one of the
rst to become aware of the intimidating possibility of total semantic
schizophrenia inherent in the anonymous transcendental subjectivity as
such. The subject is itself the space in which something might appear,
Heideggers open space (offene Stelle). For this reason, it cannot itself
appear on the stage of its world-picture. The self therefore becomes an
appearance. The subject assumes the paradoxical position of the proper
void, the zero which becomes the One once it enters the sphere of
representation without ever being able to ll out its internal gap between
its determination (One) and its void (the zero).
For Kant the uncanny structure of the selfs elusiveness, i.e. the
subjects nothingness, ultimately opens a space for consolation and hope:
if, in principle, we cannot gure out who or what we really are (our
substance), we are at least entitled to behave as if we dwelled in an intel-
ligible realm of pure freedom ruled by God . . . Of course, nobody really
took this option seriously in a literal sense. If Kant were indeed right
with his epistemological claim of nitude, i.e. if we could not know any-
thing about the in-itself, then the in-itself might have any or no struc-
ture whatsoever. The truth about the in-itself could appear as far-fetched
as any possible science-ction scenario or literary experiment enacts it.
Under strictly Kantian premises there is no suitable reason for transcen-
dental optimism; and certainly not the moral one Kant has in mind. In a
post-Schopenhauer-Nietzsche-Marx-Kierkegaard-Freud world we would
be quite nave to assume that the subject really might be a disembodied
pure spirit striving for moral perfection in the face of the protestant God
of conscience and duty.
Be this as it may, Kant is nevertheless right that the blind spot of reec-
tion, the indenite space of our ignorance, cannot be made transparent
in reection. This is why it refers us to the dimension of the ethical in a
precise sense: the ethical indeed designates the space we inhabit qua
decision-processing agents, a blank space which cannot have any positive
substance apart from the ethical substance we bestow on it. It is precisely
this aspect that corresponds to Hegels notion of the ethical substance in
the Phenomenology of Spirit.
In the wake of later nineteenth-century philosophy, subjectivity was
taught the important lesson that ignorance is not necessarily iterative,
i.e. that we are not ignorant about our ignorance. The eld of ignorance
is rather occupied by the coordinates of our desire: we desire precisely
32
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
that which we do not know. Ignorance and desire are two faces of the
same coin. As iek points out,
This idea also lies at the bottom of Schellings most original thesis
according to which Will is primal Being (Wollen ist Urseyn).42 The point
is that the Kantian intelligible world does not guarantee the stability of
the phenomenal world. On the contrary, in its elusiveness it rather desta-
bilizes the allegedly law-like totality of appearance, the symbolic order.
Any proper insight into the paradoxical nitude of knowledge entails
that the very assumption of an elusive in-itself is an expression of the
libidinal instability of the coordinates of the phenomenal world. This is a
lesson to be learned from Schelling as much as from David Lynch.43 This
willingness to explore and even to embrace the uncanniness of existence
grounded in its libidinal instability is certainly what makes Schelling
extraordinarily contemporary.
Yet not only Schelling, but also already Fichte clear-sightedly diag-
nosed the problem of the internal world in The Vocation of Man and freed
it from Kants enlightenment optimism. If the representing sphere, the
self or ego, were indeed a substance, i.e. some given stable item open to
become the object of a theory, it would paradoxically turn out to be com-
pletely elusive. Whenever we were to believe to have it in view, it would
already have withdrawn. This problem famously referred to as Fichtes
original insight by Dieter Henrich entails, as I have been saying, that
modern epistemology is not so much characterized by the problem of the
external world, as many believe, but rather by the problem of the internal
world.44 Given that the representing sphere, the subject, self or ego, qua
substance is itself part of the world (the world being made up of thinking
and extended substance), reality turns out to be a dream of a dream. As
Fichte writes,
33
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
The represented representing sphere, i.e. the subject qua substance, is itself
subject to the skeptical hypotheses developed in modern epistemology.
It is epistemologically no better off than any other entity to be encoun-
tered in the world. That which seemed to be relieved from paradox, i.e.
the unequivocal unitary thinking substance, proves to be as much of an
illusion as the so-called external world. This also motivates Pyotr Voyds
passionate question: is it my inamed consciousness that creates the
nightmare, or is my consciousness itself a creation of the nightmare?46
More generally, there is a serious philosophical issue as to how to
distribute essence and illusion, the essential and the inessential, as Hegel
puts it. The problem with the essential and the inessential is that the
essential is determined over against the inessential without reecting the
constituting act separating the essential from the inessential. The essen-
tial simply seems to be essential. The whole point is that the essence or,
otherwise put, reality, cannot be opposed to appearance or illusion.
Illusion itself occurs within reality because reality only consists in its
being determined over against illusion. Reality is not out there, but the
result of an operation which distinguishes illusion and reality. Without
this distinction, the term reality does not make sense.
We only understand that there is truth and reality because we are
constantly confronted with dissent: given that we do not agree on all
matters, we know that there are subject matters (truths) to agree upon.
However, that truth only becomes salient in discourse does not mean
that the referents of true statements are mere by-products of discourse.
It only means that we do not have any immediate access to any particu-
lar way the world is apart from our cognitive access to it. Now, our cogni-
tive access to the world only functions if we presuppose a certain set of
access conditions suitable for the object domain over which we quantify
in order to ascribe the correct predicates to that which appears within
the domain we are interested in. As any profound encounter with skep-
tical paradoxes teaches us, there is no way to guarantee the truth-
conditions of a certain discourse about a determinate object domain (that
is: objectivity) and the truths about objects within that domain at the
same time. The truth-conditions we draw on exist on a different logical
layer than the objects the truth about which we want to discover. This
amounts to a weak distinction between the transcendental and the empiri-
cal: the very framework (the discourse) constituting determinacy for an
object domain by dening what it is to belong to the object domain,
34
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
35
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
appear to itself?48 Kant starts off from the assumption that the in-itself
cannot be known because our access to it is mediated by a complex
conceptual apparatus. In simple structuralist parlance Kant claims that
we do not have any immediate access to the signied (and a fortiori to the
real thing) without always already being caught up in the potentially
misleading innite cobweb of signiers. The signifying chain and the
rules whereby it is established and maintained simply do not allow for
any act of happy-face transcendence.
The problem with this story (obviously leading from Kant to postmod-
ernism in all its varieties) is that it takes as given a blind spot of reection
Hegel calls in question: if we cannot transcend the phenomenal world ex
hypothesi then what makes us believe that there is a noumenal world, an
it-itself, after all? Is the in-itself not ultimately reduced to a friction-
guaranteeing ersatz-substance? If being is prior to judgment then we can-
not assert anything determinate about it, not even that we cannot assert
anything determinate about it! In other words, if the in-itself were inac-
cessible then it would not even be inaccessible. This is why one needs
non-propositional resources if one still wants to safeguard transcendence
from Hegels dialectical criticism of reection.
The chapter on illusion/appearance (Schein) in the Science of Logic
begins with the path-breaking assertion that Being is illusory being
(das Sein ist Schein).49 Illusory being or appearance is all that still remains
from the sphere of being (der ganze Rest, der noch von der Sphre des Seins
briggeblieben ist).50 Illusion appears to be a pure void, the negative
posited as negative,51 whereby it is distinguished from the in-itself. As
Hegel explicitly states, this structure can be found in ancient skepticisms
concept of the phenomena as much as in Kants concept of the phenom-
enal world.52 Even though Hegels claim that the phenomenon of skepti-
cism and the phenomenal world in Kant share the same structure is
highly disputable, his key point is clear: if we distinguish between the
things as they are in themselves (the essence: reality) and the things we
apprehend according to the forms of our understanding (appearances),
what guarantees that the in-itself is not itself part of the appearances?
How can we be so sure that the in-itself is not some higher-order illusion,
a mere simulacrum? What if the system of appearances just produces
certain interferences which look like acts of real transcendence?
A famous philosophical example at hand is the so-called Trendelen-
burg gap in Kants Transcendental Aesthetics.53 Trendelenburg correctly
36
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
37
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
38
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
Illusory being is the negative that has a being, but in an other, in its
negation, it is a non-self-subsistent being which is in its own self-
sublated and null. As such, it is the negative returned into itself, non-
self-subsistent being as in its own self not self-subsistent. This self-relation
of the negative or of non-self-subsistent being is its immediacy; it is an
other than the negative itself; it is its determinateness over against itself;
or it is the negation directed against the negative. But negation directed
against the negative is purely self-related negativity, the absolute sub-
lating of the determinateness itself.57
Appearance is the non-self-subsistent being in itself, or otherwise put:
appearance is the essence of self-relating negativity, the remainder of
which is Being. Being thus is nothing but the remainder of appearance,
its very being there. In Hegels vocabulary Being designates the para-
doxical subsistence of the non-self-subsistent structure of appearance.
Being is therefore not a hidden essence, reality as it is in itself or any-
thing like that, but the contingent being there of appearance.
The move Hegel prescribes for reection therefore consists in the
negation of negation. The rst negation is the positing of the essence
over against the mere appearances, the phenomenal world. The One is
opposed to the multiplicity of being, the innocent origin to the sinful,
fallen world, etc. However, this negation of the appearances is the very
kernel of appearance. The immediacy of appearances, the alleged fact
that they are deceitful, is already a redoubling of appearances. They
39
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
40
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
41
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
42
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
and thus the reection of itself within itself. Essence in this its self-
movement is reection.68
43
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
44
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
45
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
Thus the Notion is, in the rst instance, the absolute self-identity that
is such only as the negation of negation or as the innite unity of the
negativity with itself. This pure relation of the Notion to itself, which is
this relation by positing itself through negativity, is the universality of
the Notion.75
The absolute self-identity of the Notion does not imply that the Notion
exerts a metaphysical agency beyond the phenomenal world. The
Notions substance is its utter substancelessness. Hence, the Notion is
universal which basically means that there is nothing outside of logical
space. Yet, logical space itself is not a substance but a constant move-
ment, the famous Bacchanalian revel from the preface to the Phenome-
nology of Spirit.76 Even according to Hegel, the only guarantee of stability
is therefore the complete instability (substancelessness) of the domain of
all domains, the Notion which can thus be said to be universal. The
Notion consequently is Hegels preferred candidate for the domain of all
domains which commits him to a denial of a pre-logical space outside of
his reection.
Hegels assertion that being ultimately amounts to nothing other than
the universality of the Notion means that there cannot be anything
outside of logical space. Logical space does not exist; it is not an entity, but
a continuous manifestation of actuality. If we want to render this claim of
absolute immanence in a language different from Hegelese, we could say
that the appearance of something as existent outside of a theory-building
process or a discourse and ready to be represented by true statements
emerging within discourse is itself a discursive appearance. There is no
metaphysical hyper-theory; there is only a meta-theory which spells out
the conditions for there not being metaphysical hyper-theories of the
beyond. Accordingly, Hegels Science of Logic is not designed to form an
ultimate hyper-theory which transcends discursive nitude, but on the
contrary investigates into the nature of determinacy or nitude. To be
sure, Hegel says such things as the nite sublates itself by virtue of its
own nature, and passes over, of itself, into its opposite.77 But this does not
mean that the movement of sublation ever terminates in a nal statement of
sublation. The nite only transcends itself into another nite position.
Being, for Hegel, is wholly abstract, immediate relation to self, is nothing
else than the abstract moment of the Notion, which moment is abstract
46
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
47
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
Being as the wholly abstract, immediate relation to self, is nothing else than
the abstract moment of the Notion, which moment is abstract univer-
sality. This universality also effects what one demands of being, namely,
to be outside the Notion; for though this universality is moment of the
Notion, it is equally the difference, or abstract judgment, of the Notion
in which it opposes itself to itself . . . A philosophizing that in its view
of being does not rise above sense, naturally stops short at merely
abstract thought, too, in its view of the Notion; such thought stands
opposed to being.82
The alleged arche-separation between subject and object really amounts
to the separation between being and judgment (thought) which only
occurs within thought. Thought alienates itself from itself, an act through
which it objecties its innermost conditions of possibility. For Hegel,
there is consequently no Being prior to reection. In his own way, he
follows Kants path at this point. In the Transcendental Dialectic of the
First Critique Kant introduced the concept of transcendental subrep-
tion83 in the context of his destruction of the ontological proof of the
existence of God. According to Kant, the ontological proof mistakes the
conditions of our access to any determinate world-order for this world-
order itself. He suggests that the ontological proof confuses the distribu-
tive unity of the empirical employment of the understanding with the
collective unity experience as a whole,84 an operation Kant calls tran-
scendental subreption.85 Transcendental subreption consists in the con-
fusion of judgment and being, in misrepresenting the conditions for
there being anything accessible to cognition (i.e. the conditions of deter-
minacy) by hypostatizing them into some determinate object (i.e. God or
any other determinate representation of the absolute). Transcendental
subreption amounts to a dialectic in Kants sense, that is to say to a logic
48
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
49
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
50
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
But I should think that today we are at least far from the ridiculous
immodesty that would be involved in decreeing from our corner that
perspectives are permitted only from this corner. Rather has the world
become innite for us all over again, inasmuch as we cannot reject
the possibility that it may include innite interpretations?90
Lets say that contingency is the possibility-to-be-other of a certain arrange-
ment of elements. Accordingly, necessity is the impossibility-to-be-other
of a certain arrangement of elements. Necessary statements or state-
ments about necessity presuppose the availability and stability of a given
framework relative to which a set (of elements) can legitimately be said
to consist of relations between its elements that could not be otherwise.
For example, true arithmetical statements, i.e. arithmetical theorems are
necessary in this sense. Yet, even if there are as many necessary state-
ments as there are mathematical theorems and scientically recordable
facts, the frameworks themselves within which this necessity is recorded
are not thereby made necessary. We are always confronted with the
higher-order problem as to how to determine the necessity or contin-
gency of a given framework which allows for necessary statements. If we
are to assert that a given framework F is necessary then we ipso facto have
to rely on another framework F* which allows for the quantication
over frameworks. Whenever we record the existence of a framework
and thereby quantify over a certain object domain, we generate a set of
background assumptions (axioms) which ascertain the conditions for
there being an object in the relevant domain. These assumptions are
51
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
52
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
to choose a framework F rather than (say) G. If I assert that the dogs in the
park in front of my window are barking, I refer to a determinate scene.
The determinacy (and the meaning) of the scene hinges on various
parameters such as my (typically unconsidered) decision to rely on
ordinary sense-perception to determine what is going on around me, my
exclusion of far-fetched hypotheses (which, of course, might be relevant)
such as the possibility that somebody might be playing his favorite record
of the barking dogs or a secret agent playing a record of barking dogs
because all the dogs in the park have gone mute due to a strange virus
which the government does not want us to know about, etc. I also decide
against innitely many other (paranoid, scientic, or what have you)
ways of conceptualizing the scene in the park (which under some
description or other would not even be a scene in a park). The relative
consistency of our everyday arrangement of and engagement with things
presupposes that we blind ourselves to innitely more possibilities and
actual matters of fact than we allow to be explicitly processed in the form
of information within our preferred eld of sense. In other words, we
have to take account of the fact that the indenitely comprehensive manifold of
data exceeds the discursively available, nite information.
The very fact just stated (which Kant inadequately captures with his
distinction between the manifold of sensibility and the conceptually
structured appearances) is itself not capable of referring to the multiplic-
ity it envisages. The multiplicity which exceeds the discursively available,
nite information is, to be sure, not even a multiple. We should not try
to comprehend that which precedes the activity of concept-mongering
creatures in terms of a result of concept-mongering. The trouble is that
to think is to identify.98 This is why we can only agree to some extent
with Badious assumption of an inconsistent multiplicity supposedly
prior to discursively available, nite structures. When Badiou writes
Being must be already-there; some pure multiple, as multiple of multi-
ples, must be presented in order for the rule to then separate some con-
sistent multiplicity, itself presented subsequently by the gesture of the
initial presentation,99 he does not seem to be aware of the worrisome
situation he himself creates. The pure multiple or even the term incon-
sistent multiplicity is not capable of capturing that which precedes
consistency, because multiplicity is already the result of a synthesis,
it presupposes the existence of consistency and can, therefore, not
precede it.
53
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
For this reason, Schelling locates total inconsistency which is not even
a multiple at the basis of consistency by introducing his concept of that
which is unequal to itself (das sich selbst Ungleiche).100 Of course, one
could easily try to annex this inconsistency to a set-theoretical ontology
la Badiou by looking back on Freges account of the empty set, for
example. According to Frege, 0 is the Number which belongs to the
concept not identical with itself.101 Yet, reference to contradictory
concepts (under which nothing can fall) is not the only way to introduce
the empty set. One can also dene the empty set as the set of all American
presidents born before 384 BC or the set of all female unicorns wearing
police uniforms and living on Alpha Centauri, etc. Set-theory does not
therefore necessarily lend itself to an insight into the paradoxical condi-
tions of determinacy or anything similar. The empty set can be dened
on the basis of every contradictory concept. Interestingly enough, Frege
happily embraces contradictions, because he believes,
these old friends are not as black as they are painted. To be of any use
is, I admit, the last thing we should expect of them . . . All that can be
demanded of a concept from the point of view of logic and with an eye
to rigour of proof is only that its boundaries should be sharp, so that
we can decide denitely about every object whether it falls under that
concept or not.102
Be this as it may, Badiou is certainly right when he states that the being
of consistency is inconsistency,103 that is, if we add that this follows from
the distinction between a given (nite) structure and the new innite
which provides us with the endless task of making sense of the world
under always different descriptions which will never add up to a fully
coherent picture of totality. We can accept this point so long as we do not
then go on to determine that which is unequal to itself in any such way
as to access it under a denite description.
As one can learn from Schelling, this enterprise is paradoxical and
leads to an insight into the impossibility of carrying it out in any deter-
minate framework, whether it be set-theory of poetry. Nonetheless, this
impossibility does not render the enterprise meaningless. It rather con-
fronts us with the utter contingency and groundlessness of our ways of
giving meaning to that which is unequal to itself. In other words, the
world cannot prescribe how to conceptualize it because it is compatible
with more than one description and there is no ultimate meta-language
54
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
55
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
after all obvious that Hegel in the long run proves to be too optimistic
regarding the expressive resources of his dialectics. In a particularly
presumptuous passage in the introduction to his Lectures on the History of
Philosophy, Hegel writes (full of sadistic enjoyment):
Man, because he is Spirit, should and must deem himself worthy of the
highest; he cannot think too highly of the greatness and power of his
mind, and, with this belief, nothing will be so difcult and hard that it
will not reveal itself to him. The Being of the universe, at rst hidden
and concealed, has no power which can offer resistance to the search
for knowledge; it has to lay itself open before the seeker to set before
his eyes and give for his enjoyment, its riches and depths.107
Hegels identication of being and reection his thesis that being is but
the remainder of reection and that it is ultimately nothing but the
universality of the Notion draws on a distorted vision of the Kantian
thing-in-itself and its successor notion in Hlderlin and Schelling, namely
being. Hegel wrongly believes that being in Hlderlin and Schelling
designates an entity or state of affairs which precedes reection. What
Hlderlin and Schelling envisage, however, is not an entity which under-
lies reection. They do not intend to substantialize being nostalgically
returning to ancient metaphysics. Being is rather supposed to be the
name of the union of form and content which only manifests itself in
phenomena which cannot be made fully transparent (such as aesthetic
experience in Hlderlin and the blind theonomy of mythological con-
sciousness in Schelling). The very distinction between form and content
underpins Hlderlins and Schellings insight that the space of ignorance
(the possibility to be other) innitely exceeds the realm of knowledge.
Only in the experience of the elusiveness of the unity of form and con-
tent are we capable of a prescience (Ahnung) of the unknown some-
thing which makes a unity of form and content possible.108 This truly
Kantian unknown something is not just a self-inicted blind spot of
reection but the space of marks, the domain of domains, which every
reection, even the Hegelian one, inhabits. Being is therefore not identi-
cal with the being at the beginning of the Hegelian enterprise of positing
the presuppositions of determinacy. It never fully manifests itself in the
form of a being which is nothing: it cannot be dissolved into determinate
being (Dasein) as Hegel believes because otherwise the possibility of
anything to be other would be eliminated a priori.
56
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
57
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
58
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
59
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
60
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
61
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
62
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
of the mythological process rather than preceding it. The whole process
is therefore substantiated from bottom up,132 in its actuality it is
independent of thinking and willing.133 Hence, there is no transcendent
guarantor, no God, organizing the mythological process. God is nothing
but the name for an as-yet unfullled promise,134 the promise of a pure
self as Schelling puts it.135 This pure self can only be realized through an
insight into the necessity of a form which disrupts the alleged absolute-
ness of self-consciousness. The self-constitution of consciousness and its
attempt to grasp itself as comprehending both form and content gener-
ates heteronomy. Consciousness becomes dependent on itself which is
expressed for consciousness in the form of Gods reigning over it.
Schelling here anticipates Freuds diagnosis of the structure of
animism (Freuds term for the mythological consciousness): animism
projects the mental apparatus (the internal world) onto the external
world in such a manner that it makes itself blind to this very operation.
Animism is a mythopic consciousness136 which objecties the internal
world and its emotional ambivalence thereby creating a realm of demons
and Gods. Freuds important discovery is, nevertheless, not restricted to
his claim that the savages project their emotional ambivalence onto
their environment but that civilized, neurotic consciousness is partially
subject to the same hallucinatory attitude towards the world.
63
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
being which is not yet bound by reason. Nature is consequently not what
is given beforehand, that which is always already there anyway, but the
very cause of an absolute estrangement, of existential Angst.139
Whoever sees in mythology only what is opposed to our usual
concepts to such extent that mythology appears to him as it were
unworthy of all consideration, especially of all philosophical consider-
ation, he had better consider that nature hardly still evokes amaze-
ment for the thoughtless person and for one dulled by the habit of
what he sees every day, but that we can think to ourselves very well
a spiritual and ethical disposition for which nature would have to
appear just as amazing and strange as mythology, and no less unbeliev-
able. Whoever would be accustomed to living in a high spiritual or
moral ecstasy could easily ask, if he directed his look back onto nature:
what is the purpose of this stuff, uselessly lavished for fantastic form in
the mountains and cliffs?140
Mythology exhibits all features of a strange event, a term Schelling
himself frequently uses.141 The very historicity142 of mythology indicates
the fact, the event, which you have to think to yourself in the con-
cept!143 Mythology is an unprethinkable event in the sense that there is
no reason (no thought) anterior to mythology which could transform it
into a reasonable product. In its brute meaninglessness, it is the founda-
tion of meaning, even of the meaning of meaninglessness. There is no
purely logical space which can be freed from all myths and metaphors as
even the notion of logical space obviously serves as a metaphor to
delineate the boundless sphere of rationality, to give us a picture in
which we can recognize ourselves.144
The crucial thought is that, despite itself, logocentricism is based on
a mythology. By opposing logos to myth it surreptitiously admits its
dependence on myth. Blumenberg, therefore, is right in stressing the fact
that Hegels closure of reection upon itself is only expressible in the
form of mythology. When Hegel speaks about the circle of circles,145 the
Bacchanalian revel,146 or the Eleusinian mysteries,147 and so on in
order to elucidate the gesture of logos closure upon itself, he himself
makes use of the mythological unity of form and content.148 In this sense,
Hegel does not transcend being towards reection. Reection rather
implodes into being, it replicates the matrix of the unity of sense and
being in the form of its own expression. This is why Hegels Science of Logic
64
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
65
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
66
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
67
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
Men have judged that a king can make rain; we say this contradicts all
experience. Today they judge that aeroplanes and the radio etc. are
means for the closer contact of people and the spread of people.167
68
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
69
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
70
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
draw the consequence for his own reection which looms large in
Schellings Philosophy of Mythology, namely that there is no purely scien-
tic (in the sense of non-mythological) vantage point. This is why we
need to combine Schelling and Wittgenstein.
To be sure, mythology is only opposed to propositional, knowledgeable,
or scientic discourse as long as we choose the vague concept of
modern science as the hinge on which our world-picture turns. Given
Wittgensteins careful remarks on the hinges on which the language-
game turns, it is possible to equate them with constitutive mythology in
the sense defended here. Our mythological being-in-the-world consists
in the fact that we have to impose limits of discourse in order to organize
our experience at all. This imposition of limits is not itself a rational act
which we can be held fully responsible for. At some point or other we
run out of means to justify our justicatory practices. Precisely because
there always is a groundless ground which can never fully be identied,
that is to say, because there is unprethinkable Being, mythology takes
place. This leads Schelling to his claim that at the beginning unprethink-
able Being rst assumes the shape of some unprethinkable God172 taking
hold of consciousness.
Without going into historical details, it is possible to distinguish at least
three manifestations of constitutive mythology, three successive stages of
mythologys immanent metamorphosis: theonomy, ontonomy, and auton-
omy. Obviously, theonomy is the shape of mythological consciousness
Schelling envisages with his concept of mythology as theogony.
It is suggested by the common usage of the term mythos in the sense of
a fable or a story about Gods and heroes and their relation to man-
kind. In its opposition to logos, mythos seems to be restricted to such a
theonomical shape of consciousness. Yet, if one takes a look at the
Pre-Socratic foundation of ontonomy, in particular in the Eleatics, it is
obvious that God (or the Gods) is simply replaced by Being without
losing its functional status. The functional space God(s) used to occupy is
simply redistributed. That which is always already there anyway, that
which is not up to us, turns from God into Being; even the Gods are
thusly thrown. This is what I call ontonomy. Finally, the myth of moder-
nity assumes the form of autonomy. Being is reduced to thought, author-
ity to reason, tradition to creation, community to the individual, the
universal to the particular, etc. Modernity assumes the shape of an irre-
versible reversal of traditional hierarchies.
71
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
72
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
73
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
foundations, all statements within belief-systems, that is, all beliefs are
mythological. We must temper this monistic tendency in order to
prevent beliefs from what Crispin Wright identies as leaching.177 The
leaching problem is roughly this: if every framework allowing for mean-
ingful statements consists of a set of axiomatic propositions such that
every meaningful statement within the framework can be described as an
element in a chain of inference always beginning with an axiom, that is
to say, if we adopt a deductive view of the relation between frameworks
and statements, then all beliefs indeed turn out to be mythological if the
frameworks are. However, not all frameworks consist of a denumerable
set of axiomatic propositions. The hinges around which language-games
turn are necessarily fuzzy, they are the indeterminate conditions of deter-
minacy. As Wittgenstein repeatedly points out, there are no sharp bound-
aries between empirical and a priori propositions on the foundational
level. The framework propositions cannot be determined without ipso
facto generating another mythology in the background: in attempting to
account for the mythological conditions of a belief system A1, we merely
generate a higher-order discourse, meta-belief-system A2, which has its
own hinges and background. For this very reason, it is simply impossible
to defend a dogmatic monism about mythology.
However, (non-Pyrrhonian) skepticism or nihilism also amounts to a
dogmatic claim, namely the dogmatic claim that there is no way to
evaluate the mythology of a world-picture at all because this itself simply
generates another mythological picture which holds us captive. Even if it
is true that ideology-critique is always threatened by ideology, this does
not entail that it is always ideological. If the concept of mythology is
supposed to do some critical and theoretical work at all, we have to steer
a course between monism and nihilism.
My explicit aim is to set up a new mythology, namely the mythology of
mythology. In this, my project does not differ from that of any other mod-
ern philosopher, if by mythology we understand the creation of con-
cepts (such as: mythology) which exhibit and perform the nitude of
concept-mongering activities. This assertion of nitude is not dogmatic in
that it draws on a ladder-theory: axioms of determinacy are only set up in
order to invert them. In the very moment of inversion, in which we
discover the indeterminacy of that which was introduced as determi-
nate, we experience the elusiveness of the domain of all domains we,
despite its elusiveness, constantly inhabit. This is why philosophy deep
74
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
75
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
76
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
Reication mistakes its own activity of setting up its world (in the sense
of a framework in which determinate things can appear) for the activity
of something external to it to the effect that the world appears as the
given par excellence. The essence of reication is not simple objectication
(which is inherent in language itself or, better, is expression itself) but
rather the objectication of objectication, i.e. the objectication of the
contingent activity of objectifying as necessary. Reication denies the
paradoxes and antinomies which lie at the basis of determinacy and
accredits itself the capacity to investigate into the conditions of possibility
of determinacy (of meaning, truth, etc.) with, for example, the means of
natural science; scientism is but one mode of reication.
Scientism is a standpoint of alienation: that which is of our own mak-
ing aficts us in the disguise of something natural. It is crucial here to
insist that nature itself is a historical concept. The modern concept of
nature as the totality of space-time-particles governed by necessary laws
of nature is the result of a historical shift in the self-explication of living
creatures. In his The Phenomenon of Life, Hans Jonas has forcefully argued
that the concept of nature which underlies modern scientistic materialist
monism is committed to a thoroughgoing ontology of death.181 The
experience of death as the inevitable effect of life assumes center stage in
modern materialism which denes itself in opposition to any sort of
anthropomorphism, animism, or panvitalism. Even if animism as an
ontology itself is the result of a reication of life and therefore not much
better off than modern materialism, it nonetheless contains a grain of
truth.182 Animism objecties the world-creating activity of objectication
which is life itself. Life objecties itself, it realizes itself in animal bodies
which in turn are capable of manifesting expressions. The inwardness of
life is only realized in its outward manifestations, an idea which plays an
essential role in Hegels Philosophy of Subjective Spirit. Life is not a mysteri-
ous spiritual quality but the activity of expression, of objectication. This
is why objectication as such cannot be the culprit of alienation. Reica-
tion is the problem and it begins where reection denies access to itself. Animism
and materialism are both guilty of reifying life because they are not
77
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
78
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
79
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
80
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
81
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
82
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
83
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
domain beyond the limits. This dialectic is also the grain of truth in
Schmitts account of the state of exception: any structure and, therefore,
any state creates its own state of exception which is needed in order for
it to be determined from within against its internal without. This does
not mean that the other beyond the limits of the state necessarily exists.
Dialectics does not yield an ontological proof of the existence of weapons
of mass destruction or anything of that sort. However, the acceptance of
the nitude of any state qua structure helps to embrace contingency as
the only honest modality of democracy.
The dialectic just sketched can be viewed as a manifestation of the
instability of structure as such. All structures (including higher-order
intelligible structures such as theories and consciousness, etc.) are part
of the world which is why the world is chaotic and contradictory: if
the world is not only the object of theories but if it contains those
theories (after all, theories are not transcendent) and if there are
contradictory theories and a variety of perspectives on the world, then
the world itself is a paradoxical unity which contradicts itself. The
unity of the world is unstable and ever-changing, because it depends
on the plurality of frameworks within which its unity can appear.
Truth can only take place under the premises of dissent, difference,
and misunderstanding.
Political philosophy always draws on a theory of order. Given that
order is the result of an establishment of determinacy, the ontology of
reection I have developed in the rst two parts of this chapter has
obvious consequences for a political philosophy. The dimension of the
political is only available under the condition of logos, as Aristotle notori-
ously pointed out. Logos, i.e. language in the sense of truth-apt dis-
course, opens up a realm of contingency. It denes a domain of possibility,
because it generates the distinction between the true and the false:
whatever is meaningfully asserted is either true or false (or has another
truth-value depending on your preferred logical system). The crucial
point is that the political only takes place as soon as the possibility of
rearrangement becomes manifest. And this manifestation takes place
in discourse. Discourse generates a variety of universes of discourse,
a plurality of object domains, as Aristotle was well aware of. For this
reason, his metaphysics bears on his political philosophy: being qua
being is only manifested in the possibility and actuality of dissent that
is the very manifestation of logos. This is why logos can still mean
84
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
85
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
86
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
Kant, Husserl, and Heidegger were not capable of understanding that the
sun has existed before man. Neither idealism nor phenomenology is an
ontic theory according to which the existence of human beings is the
efcient cause of the existence of particular objects such as the sun, the
Milky Way, or Niagara Falls. That there are epistemological conditions of
possibility of experience or even ontological conditions of possibility of
determinacy berhaupt is a second-order claim of reection. This is fully
compatible with internal realism: as soon as a framework is xed, it allows
for reference and therefore ordinary truth (and falsity) to take place.
Meillassoux critique of correlationism simply misses the distinction
between ontic (rst-order) and ontological (reective) theorizing. In
order to repudiate correlationism, he would have to show that the onto-
logical claim according to which the in-itself is only in-itself for us entails
ontic non-sense. Yet, he does not even distinguish the various layers of
reection and theorizing, a shortcoming very common in the debate
about idealism, constructivism, etc.203
At the same time that Bataille discusses ancestral statements and
indeed asserts that they are not literally true, he also establishes a differ-
ently motivated alliance between French and German philosophy which
is not dened on the epistemological basis of correlationism alone. In
general, he does not plainly refer to a continental commitment to ontic
idealism but goes on to describe a curiosity about the unknown
domain204 which manifests itself in an experience of nonknowledge
Bataille characterizes as uneasiness.205 He writes, it seems to me [. . .]
that the fundamental question is posed only from that moment on, when
no formula is possible, when we listen in silence to the absurdity of the
world.206 This sense of uneasiness is repressed by the scientic attitude
and by the respective ideology prevailing in most departments of philos-
ophy in the Western world. However, without this sense of uneasiness,
anxiety, Sartrean nause, or Wittgensteinian paradox philosophy does
not exist. No wonder that scientists in philosophy limit their research to
the undoing of philosophy proper.
Science ultimately serves the existential project of making the human
being at home in the world. It constantly reduces the absolutism of
reality (Blumenberg) by availing itself of means to substitute the famil-
iar for the unfamiliar in such a manner that it transforms directionless
anxiety into object-directed fear. This still holds despite the oft-lamented
loss of meaning (of teleology, animism, etc.) associated with the alleged
87
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
88
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
generally will deal with origins that no one can have been present at,211
that is, with ancestral statements. Hence, ancestrality is downright
mythological.
Against scientism we should side with philosophers such as Heidegger,
Wittgenstein, Bataille, and Cavell who manage to verbalize contingency
without disavowing it at the same time. And there is no need to fear that
contingency throws us back to creationism. Scientism (which is not
science, but the faith in science, the enreligement of science!) and creation-
ism are equally prejudiced mythologies serving ideological goals.
Of course, creationism is a paranoid world-picture. It rests on thoroughly
nave assumptions about science and on a hermeneutics of the Holy
Scriptures whose stupidity has hardly ever been outmatched. Scientism,
on the other hand, neglects the role reection plays in the constitution
of determinacy and tries to make mankind feel at home in the world by
telling us that we can nally stop searching for a meaning outside of the
meanings of the realist propositions of science. That is, scientism too rests
on the somewhat nave belief that science does not need to justify its
ultimate grounds, because it believes them to be as evident as they are
objective and material, but without asking itself who is actually
determining them as being evident.
If we dont want to lose track of the contingency we are ineradicably
confronted with (in the soul, as humans, etc.), we need a remedy against
both ideologies. And, unlike Meillassoux, I insist that this remedy is ni-
tude. Only the reective analysis of nitude initiated by Descartes and
continued by Kant and all his successors (including Wittgenstein and
Heidegger) can secure the validity of science for the object domains rele-
vant for science, on the one hand, and the total invalidity of creationism,
on the other hand. Fortunately, many philosophers, such as Quine and
Bachelard, assist us in this task in that they make explicit the ontological
commitments of science and the contingency of the decisions that lie at
the basis of scientic inquiry.
The mythological being of reection reects our own contingency.
Ultimately, language only talks about itself. There is no way to guarantee
that we ever get It right without generating a new mythology that cre-
ates a community of reection. The community of reection contests
that transcendence could ever assume a determinate shape. This is why
the acceptance of nitude and contingency decisively opposes the enre-
ligement of reason.
89
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
To sum up, neither creationism nor scientism can escape the fact that
they are based upon a completely unstable soil, which I have been
calling here a mythology. The question we need to ask ourselves is
whether or not this also holds for philosophical discourse. In effect before
coming to conclusions, there is at least one objection which I need to
fend off in order to make my argument for the indispensability (and
radical inevitability) of mythology more convincing. The objection says
that in emphasizing the contingency associated with the paradoxes of
the domain of all domains we are rendered incapable of distinguishing
between the contingency of the realm of reason as such and the arbitrari-
ness of a particular reason, or a particular practice of giving and asking for
reasons. If we unrestrictedly ascertain the possibility-to-be-other of
everything, are we not committing ourselves to a non-sensical and irra-
tional overgeneralization of arbitrariness?
In order to address this problem and to motivate a distinction between
contingency and unlimited arbitrariness (threatening to destroy deter-
minacy berhaupt), it is crucial to bear in mind that the contingency of
reection is always already a higher-order contingency. I do not claim
that a particular set of necessary statements is really contingent. My claim
is rather that necessity can only be assessed within a determinate object
domain and that the existence of a discourse quantifying over a determi-
nate object domain hinges on contingent parameters. If it is indeed the
case (as I have argued throughout this whole chapter) that local determi-
nacy presupposes conditions which are indeterminate for the domain in
question and if this also holds for the domain of all domains (whose par-
adoxical existence we have to presuppose in order to make sense of the
existence of a multitude of mutually determined object domains), then
necessity always hinges on the contingent stability of a particular frame-
work. As soon as this framework becomes the object of further scrutiny,
another higher-order framework is created which, in turn, brings along
a trail of indeterminacy and so on ad transnitum.
We are conditioned to always go on in a certain, determinate way as
long as we are recognized as members of a particular community. In this
chapter, I have tried to argue that the community I take myself to belong
to should continue to be a community of free reection dening itself on
the basis of an unrestricted acknowledgment of contingency. Nature
will not guarantee that radical democracy will prove to be our future.
It is threatened all the time by the human need to dispose of the human
90
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
91
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
naturalism of our time which believes that materialism equals the reduc-
tion of all events to ultimately necessary arrangements of space-time
particles. Apart from its ridiculous anti-modernist disavowal of the
ontological uncertainty (and fundamental contingency) discovered by
quantum physics, the fetishism of scientic determinacy commonly
taken for granted in contemporary main-stream analytic philosophy
reects the ontology of our nancial markets, i.e. the assumption of the
omnipotence of quantication. With Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel we
could even venture the hypothesis that contemporary naturalism is the
expression of the perverse way of thinking heading towards an
anal-sadistic universe in which all differences are reduced to a mere
rearrangement of (excremental) matter.
In the universe [of the pervert, M.G.] I am describing, the world has
been engulfed in a gigantic grinding machine (the digestive tract) and
has been reduced to homogeneous (excremental) particles. Then all is
equivalent. The distinction between before and after has disap-
peared, as, too, of course, has history. Only quantities are taken into
account, as in the case of the fetishist who told me: I cant see why the
Jews complain so much. They suffered six million dead, but the
Russians suffered twenty!215
Surely, Meillassoux is very far from being a naturalist in this tradition.
Nevertheless, he comes close to the ideological gesture of reinstalling
necessity. Like Schelling, Blumenberg, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and
many others (he would not like to associate with), Meillassoux rightly
emphasizes the absolutism of reality, i.e. the facticity of the glacial world
that is revealed to the moderns, a world in which there is no longer any
up or down, centre or periphery, nor anything else that might make of it
a world designed for humans.216 However, he does not take the fact into
account that the glacial world is not a fact, but itself a world-picture
designed by humans for human purposes, a metaphor as Nietzsche
would put it. What Meillassoux ultimately neglects or disavows is that
the hypothesis of a meaningless world (or at least of something which
cannot be reduced to being an element within the chain of signiers)
serves the function of justifying a radical democracy that would upset his
desire to position himself after nitude, or, what is the same, after the
community. If God (that is to say, his representatives on earth) does not
dictate politics any more, then we are left alone with the community.
92
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION
93
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
94
CHAPTER TWO
Discipline between Two Freedoms Madness
and Habit in German Idealism
Slavoj iek
The antagonism of the Kantian notion of freedom (as the most concise
expression of the antagonism of freedom in bourgeois life itself) does
not reside where Adorno locates it (the autonomously self-imposed
law means that freedom coincides with self-enslavement and self-
domination, that the Kantian spontaneity is in actu its opposite, utter self-
control, thwarting of all spontaneous impetuses), but, as Robert Pippin
put it, much more on the surface.1 For Kant as for Rousseau, the greatest
moral good is to lead a fully autonomous life as a free rational agent, and
the worst evil subjection to the will of another. However, Kant has to
concede that man does not emerge as a free mature rational agent
spontaneously, through his/her natural development, but only through
the arduous process of maturation sustained by harsh discipline and
education which cannot but be experienced by the subject as imposed
on his/her freedom, as an external coercion. Pippin continues:
95
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
separate, marginal topic of Kants dotage. This is, in effect, the antin-
omy contained within the bourgeois notions of individuality, individual
responsibility . . .2
96
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
97
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
98
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
was put very clearly by Chesterton: Every act of will is an act of self-
limitation. To desire action is to desire limitation. In that sense every act
is an act of self-sacrice.5
The lesson here is thus in the very precise sense a Hegelian one: the
external opposition between freedom (transcendental spontaneity, moral
autonomy, and self-responsibility) and slavery (submission, either to my
own nature, its pathological instincts, or to external power) has to be
transposed into freedom itself, as the highest antagonism between the
monstrous freedom qua unruliness and the true moral freedom. How-
ever, a possible counter-argument here would have been that this nou-
menal excess of freedom (the Kantian unruliness, the Hegelian Night
of the World) is a retroactive result of the disciplinary mechanisms
themselves (along the lines of the Paulinian motif of Law creates trans-
gression, or of the Foucauldian topic of how the very disciplinary mea-
sures that try to regulate sexuality generate sex as the elusive excess),
the obstacle thereby creates that which it endeavors to control.
Are we then dealing with the closed circle of a process of positing ones
own presuppositions? Our wager is that the Hegelian dialectical circle of
positing presuppositions, far from being a closed one, generates its own
opening and thus the space for freedom.
In the shift from Aristotle to Kant, to modernity with its subject as pure
autonomy, the status of habit changes from organic inner rule to some-
thing mechanic, the opposite of human freedom: freedom cannot ever
become habit(ual), if it becomes a habit, it is no longer true freedom
(which is why Thomas Jefferson wrote that, if people are to remain free,
they have to rebel against the government every couple of decades). This
eventuality reaches its apogee in Christ, who is the gure of a pure
event, the exact opposite of the habitual.6
Hegel provides here the immanent corrective to the Kantian moder-
nity. As Catherine Malabou notes, Hegels Philosophy of Spirit begins with
the study of the same topic that Philosophy of Nature ends with: the soul
and its functions. This redoubling provides a clue to how Hegel concep-
tualizes the transition from nature to spirit: not as a sublation, but as a
99
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
100
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
101
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
The form of habit applies to spirit in all its degrees and varieties. Of all
these modications, the most external is the determination of the
individual in relation to space; this, which for man means an upright
posture, is something that by his will he has made into a habit. Adopted
directly, without thinking, his upright stance continues through the
persistent involvement of his will. Man stands upright only because
and insofar as he wants to stand, and only as long as he wills to do so
without consciousness of it. Similarly, to take another case, the act of
seeing, and others like it, are concrete habits which combine in
a single act the multiple determinations of sensation, of consciousness,
intuition, understanding, and so forth.14
Habit is thus depersonalized willing, a mechanized emotion: once I get
habituated to standing, I will it without consciously willing it, since my
will is embodied in the habit. In a habit, presence and absence, appro-
priation and withdrawal, engagement and disengagement, interest and
disinterest, subjectivization and objectivization, consciousness and uncon-
sciousness, are strangely interlinked. Habit is the un(self)consciousness
necessary for the very functioning of consciousness:
And the same goes for my emotions: their display is not purely natural
or spontaneous, we learn to cry or laugh at appropriate moments (recall
how, for the Japanese, laughter functions in a different way than for us
in the West: a smile can also be a sign of embarrassment and shame). The
external mechanization of emotions from the ancient Tibetan praying
wheel which prays for me to todays canned laughter where the TV
set laughs for me, turning my emotional display quite literally into
a mechanic display of the machine, is thus based in the fact that emo-
tional displays, including the most sincere ones, are already in them-
selves mechanized. However, the highest level (and, already,
self-sublation) of a habit is language as the medium of thought: in it, the
102
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
103
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
possible): habit is actual, a property (to react in a certain way) that I fully
possess here and now, and simultaneously a possibility pointing towards
future (the possibility/ability to react in a certain way, which will be
actualized in multiple future occasions).
There are interesting conceptual consequences of this notion of habit.
Ontologically, with regard to the opposition between particular accidents
and universal essence, habit can be designed as the becoming-essential
of the accident:20 after an externally caused accident repeats itself, it is
elevated into the universality of the subjects inner disposition, i.e., into
a feature that belongs to and denes his inner essence. This is why we
cannot ever determine the precise beginning of a habit, the point at
which external occurrences change into habit once a habit is here, it
obliterates its origin and it is as if it was always already here. The conclu-
sion is thus clear, almost Sartrean: man does not have a permanent
substance or universal essence; he is in his very core a man of habits, a
being whose identity is formed through the elevation of contingent
external accidents/encounters into an internal(ized) universal habit.
Does this mean that only humans have habits? Here, Hegel is much more
radical and he accomplishes a decisive step further and leaves behind the
old topic of nature as fully determined in its closed circular movement
versus man as a being of openness and existential freedom: for Hegel,
nature is always second nature.21 Every natural organism has to regulate
the exchange with its environs, the assimilation of the environs into
itself, through habitual procedures that reect into the organism, as its
inner disposition, its external interactions.
104
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
105
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
The conclusion to be drawn is thus that the only way to account for the
emergence of the distinction between the inside and outside constitu-
tive of a living organism is to posit a kind of self-reexive reversal by
means of which to put it in Hegelese the One of an organism as a
Whole retroactively posits as its result, as that which it dominates and
regulates, the set of its own causes (i.e. the very multiple process out of
which it emerged). In this way and only in this way an organism is
no longer limited by external conditions, but is fundamentally self-
limited again, as Hegel would have articulated it, life emerges when the
external limitation (of an entity by its environs) turns into self-
limitation. This brings us back to the problem of innity: for Hegel, true
innity does not stand for limitless expansion, but for active self-
limitation (self-determination) in contrast to being-determined-by-the-
other. In this precise sense, life (even at its most elementary, as a living
cell) is the basic form of true innity, since it already involves the mini-
mal loop by means of which a process is no longer simply determined by
the Outside of its environs, but is itself able to (over)determine the mode
of this determination and thus posits its presuppositions. Innity
acquires its rst actual existence the moment a cells membrane starts to
functions as a self-boundary.
Back to habits: because of the virtual status of habits, to adopt a (new)
habit is not simply to change an actual property of the subject; rather, it
involves a kind of reexive change, a change of the subjects disposition
which determines his reaction to changes, i.e., a change in the very mode
of changes to which the subject is submitted: Habit does not simply
introduce mutability into something that would otherwise continue
without changing; it suggests change within a disposition, within its
106
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
107
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
108
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
such is invisible or, as the early Wittgenstein put it: Our life has no end
in just the way in which our visual eld has no limits (TLP 6.4311). Like
the eld of vision, life is nite, and, for that very reason, we cannot ever
see its limit. In this precise sense, eternal life belongs to those who live
in the present (ibid.): precisely because we are within our nitude, we
cannot step out of it and perceive its limitation. The possibility of locating
oneself within ones reality has to remain a possibility: however, and
herein resides the crucial point, this possibility itself has to actualize itself
qua possibility, to be active, to exert inuence, qua possibility.
There is a link to Kant here, to the old enigma of what, exactly,
Kant had in mind with his notion of transcendental apperception, of
self-consciousness accompanying every act of my consciousness (when
I am conscious of something, I am thereby always also conscious of the
fact that I am conscious of this)? Is it not an obvious fact that this is
empirically not true, that I am not always reexively aware of my
awareness itself? The way interpreters try to resolve this deadlock is by
way of claiming that every conscious act of mine can be potentially
rendered self-conscious: if I want, I always can turn my attention to
what I am doing. This, however, is not strong enough: the transcenden-
tal apperception cannot be an act that never effectively happens, that
just could have happened at any point. The solution of this dilemma is
precisely the notion of virtuality in the strict Deleuzian sense, as the
actuality of the possible, as a paradoxical entity the very possibility of
which already produces/has actual effects. One should oppose Deleuzes
notion of the virtual to the all-pervasive topic of virtual reality: what
matters to Deleuze is not virtual reality, but the reality of the virtual (which,
in Lacanian terms, is the Real). Virtual reality in itself is a rather miserable
idea: that of imitating reality, of reproducing its experience in an articial
medium. The reality of the virtual, on the other hand, stands for the reality
of the virtual as such, for its real effects and consequences. Let us take an
attractor in mathematics: all positive lines or points in its sphere of attrac-
tion only approach it in an endless fashion, never reaching its form the
existence of this form is purely virtual, being nothing more than the
shape towards which lines and points tend. However, precisely as such,
the virtual is the Real of this eld: the immovable focal point around
which all elements circulate. Is not this Virtual ultimately the Symbolic
as such? Let us take symbolic authority: in order to function as an effec-
tive authority, it has to remain not-fully-actualized, an eternal threat.
109
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
This, then, is the status of the Self: its self-awareness is as it were the
actuality of its own possibility. Consequently, what haunts the subject
is his inaccessible noumenal Self, the Thing that thinks, an object in
which the subject would fully encounter himself. (Hume drew a lot
too much of mileage out of this observation on how, upon introspec-
tion, all I perceive in myself are my particular ideas, sensations, emotions,
never my Self itself.) Of course, for Kant, the same goes for every object
of my experience which is always phenomenal, i.e., inaccessible in its
noumenal dimension. However, with the Self, the impasse is accentu-
ated: all other objects of experience are given to me phenomenally, but,
in the case of subject, I cannot even get a phenomenal experience of me
since I am dealing with myself, in this unique case, phenomenal
self-experience would equal noumenal access, i.e., if I were to be able
to experience myself as a phenomenal object, I would thereby eo ipso
experience myself in my noumenal identity, as a Thing.
The underlying problem here is the impossibility the subject faces in
trying to objectivize himself: the subject is singular and is the universal
frame of his world, i.e., every content he perceives is his own; so how
can the subject include himself (count himself) into the series of his
objects? The subject observes reality from an external position, and is
simultaneously part of this reality, without ever being able to attain an
objective view of reality with himself in it. The thing that haunts the
subject is himself in his objectal counterpoint, qua object. Hegel writes:
110
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
his place) within the structured (systematized) totality, and since the
subject cannot ever objectivize himself, the contradiction is here
absolute.30 With this gap, the possibility of madness emerges and, as
Hegel puts it in proto-Foucauldian terms, madness is not an accidental
lapse, distortion, illness of human spirit, but something which is
inscribed into individual spirits basic ontological constitution: to be a
human means to be potentially mad.
111
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
Another way to approach this same topic is via the relationship between
soul and body as the Inner and the Outer, of their circular relationship in
which body expresses the soul and the soul receives impressions from
the body the Soul is always already embodied and the Body always
already impregnated with its Soul:
What the sentient self nds within it is, on the one hand, the naturally
immediate, as ideally in it and made its own. On the other hand and
conversely, what originally belongs to the central individuality [. . .] is
determined as natural corporeity, and is so felt.33
So, on the one hand, through feelings and perceptions, I internalize
objects that affect me from outside: in a feeling, they are present in me
not in their raw reality, but ideally, as part of my mind. On the other
hand, through grimaces, etc., my body immediately gives body to my
inner Soul which thoroughly impregnates it. However, if this were to be
the entire truth, then man would have been simply a prisoner of his
state of nature (67), moving in the close loop of absolute transparency
provided by the mutual mirroring of body and soul. (Physiognomy and
phrenology remain at this level, as well as todays New Age ideologies
enjoining us to express/realize our true Self.) What happens with the
112
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
moment of judgment is that the loop of this closed circle is broken not
by the intrusion of an external element, but by a self-referentiality which
twists this circle into itself. That is to say, the problem is that, since the
individual is at the same time only what he has done, his body is also the
expression of himself which he has himself produced.34 What this means
is that the process of corporeal self-expression has no pre-existing
referent as its mooring point: the entire movement is thoroughly self-
referential, it is only through the process of expression (externalization
in bodily signs) that the expressed Inner Self (the content of these signs)
is retroactively created or, as Malabou puts it concisely: Psychosomatic
unity results from an auto-interpretation independent of any referent.35
The transparent mirroring of the Soul and the Body in the natural
expressivity thus turns into total opacity:
113
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
114
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
115
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
The human being is this night, this empty nothing, that contains every-
thing in its simplicity an unending wealth of many representations,
images, of which none belongs to him or which are not present. This
night, the interior of nature, that exists here pure self in phantasma-
gorical representations, is night all around it, in which here shoots a
bloody head there another white ghastly apparition, suddenly here
before it, and just so disappears. One catches sight of this night when
one looks human beings in the eye into a night that becomes awful.44
Again, one should not be blinded by the poetic power of this description,
but read it precisely. The rst thing to note is how the objects which
freely oat around in this night of the world are membra disiecta,
partial objects, objects detached from their organic Whole is there not
a strange echo between this description and Hegels description of the
negative power of Understanding which is able to abstract an entity
(a process, a property) from its substantial context and treat it as if
it has an existence of its own? that the accidental as such, detached
from what circumscribes it, what is bound and is actual only in its con-
text with others, should attain an existence of its own and a separate
freedom this is the tremendous power of the negative.45 It is thus as if,
in the ghastly scenery of the night of the world, we encounter some-
thing like the power of Understanding in its natural state, spirit in the guise
of a proto-spirit this, perhaps, is the most precise denition of horror:
when a higher state of development violently inscribes itself in the
lower state, in its ground/presupposition, where it cannot but appear as
a monstrous mess, a disintegration of order, a terrifying unnatural com-
bination of natural elements. With regards to todays science, where do
we encounter its horror at its purest? When genetic manipulations
go awry and generate objects never seen in nature, freaks like goats
with a gigantic ear instead of a head or a head with one eye, meaningless
accidents which nonetheless touch our deeply repressed fantasies
and thus trigger wild interpretations. The pure Self as the inner of
nature (a strange expression, since, for Hegel, nature, precisely, has no
116
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
His movement is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too
rapid. He comes toward the patrons with a step a little too quick. He
bends forward a little too eagerly; his voice, his eyes express an interest
a little too solicitous for the order of the customer. Finally there he
returns, trying to imitate in his walk the inexible stiffness of some
kind of automaton . . .46
Does Sartres underlying ontological thesis that the waiter in the caf can
not be immediately a caf waiter in the sense that this inkwell is an inkwell
not point forward towards Lacans classic thesis that a madman is not
only a beggar who thinks he is a king, but also a king who thinks he is a
king? One should be very precise in this reading: as Robert Bernasconi
pointed out in his commentary, Sartres thesis is here much more rened
than a simple point about mauvaise foi and self-objectivization (in order to
cover up or escape from the void of his freedom, a subject escapes into
a rm symbolic identity). What Sartre does show is how, through the
very exaggeration in his acting as a waiter, through his very over-
identication with the role of the waiter, the waiter in question signals his
distance from it and thus asserts his subjectivity. True, this French waiter
117
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
like ones friend. However, Sartres point is that, whatever game the
waiter is called upon to play, the ultimate rule that the waiter follows
is that he must break the rules, and to do so by following them in an
exaggerated manner. That is to say, the waiter does not simply follow
the unwritten rules, which would be obedience to a certain kind of
tyranny, but, instead, goes overboard in following those rules. The
waiter succeeds in rejecting the attempt to reduce him to nothing more
than being a waiter, not by refusing the role, but by highlighting the
fact that he is playing it to the point that he escapes it. The waiter does
this by overdoing things, by doing too much. The French waiter,
instead of disappearing into the role, exaggerates the movements that
make him something of an automaton in a way that draws attention
to him, just as, we can add, the quintessential North American waiter
is not so much friendly as overfriendly. Sartre uses the same word, trop,
that we saw him using in Nausea to express this human superuity.47
And it is crucial to supplement this description with its symmetrical
opposite: one is truly identied with ones role precisely when one does
not over-identify with it, but accompanies ones playing the role,
following its rules, with small violations or idiosyncrasies destined to sig-
nal that, beneath the role I am playing, there is a real person who cannot
be directly identied with it or reduced to it. In other words, it is totally
wrong to read the waiters behavior as a case of mauvaise foi: his very
exaggerated acting opens up, in a negative way, the space for his authen-
tic self, since its message is I am not what I am playing to be. The true
mauvaise foi consists precisely in embellishing my playing a role with
idiosyncratic details it is this personal touch which provides the space
of false freedom, allowing me to accommodate myself to my self-objec-
tivization in the role I am playing. (So what about those rare and weird
moments in an American cafeteria where we suddenly suspect that the
waiters friendliness is genuine?)48
And this brings us back to our starting question: the change from animal
to properly human habit. Only humans, spiritual beings, are haunted by
spirits why? Not simply because, in contrast to animals, they have
118
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
119
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
120
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS
See also Hegels famous claim that modern people do not pray in the
morning, because reading the newspaper is their morning prayer. In the
same way, in the disintegrating socialism, writers and other cultural clubs
did act as political parties. Perhaps, in the history of cinema, the best
example is the relationship between western and sci- space operas:
today, we no longer have substantial westerns, because space operas
occupied their place, i.e. space operas are todays westerns. So, in the classi-
cation of westerns, we would have to supplement the standard subspe-
cies with space opera as todays non-western stand-in for western. Crucial
is here this intersection of different genuses, this partial overlapping of
two universals: western and space opera are not simply two different
genres, they intersect, i.e. in a certain epoch, space opera becomes a sub-
species of western (or, western is sublated in space opera) . . . In the
same way, woman becomes one of the subspecies of man, Heideggerian
Daseinsanalyse one of the subspecies of phenomenology, sublating the
preceding universality.
The impossible point of self-objectivization would have been precisely
the point at which universality and its particular content would have
been fully harmonized in short, where there would have been no
struggle for hegemony. And this brings us back to madness: its most suc-
cinct denition is that of a direct harmony between universality and its
accidents, of the cancellation of the gap that separates the two for a
madman, the object which is my impossible stand-in within objectal
reality loses its virtual character and becomes its full integral part. In
contrast to madness, habit avoids this trap of direct identication by way
of its virtual character: the subjects identication with a habit is not a
direct identication with some positive feature, but the identication
with a disposition, with a virtuality. Habit is the outcome of a struggle
for hegemony: it is an accident elevated to essence, to universal necessity,
i.e., made to ll in its empty place.
121
CHAPTER THREE
Fichtes Laughter
Slavoj iek
122
FICHTES LAUGHTER
Schellings rst and decisive break out of the constraints of his early
philosophy-of-identity is his Treatise on the Essence of Human Freedom from
1809, to which Hegel reacted in his (posthumously published) lectures
on the history of philosophy with a brief and ridiculously inadequate
dismissal which totally misses the point of Schellings masterpiece: what
is today considered one of the highpoints of the entire history of philoso-
phy appears to Hegel as an insignicant, minor, and obscure essay. No
wonder, then, that the topic among todays Hegel-scholars is rather:
what would have been Hegels rejoinder to Schellings critique of dialec-
tics as a mere negative philosophy? Among others, Dieter Henrich and
Frederick Beiser have tried to reconstruct a Hegelian answer.
What is the philosophical status of these retroactive rejoinders? It is all
too easy to claim (in the postmodern vein of the end of the grand narra-
tives) that they bear witness to the failure of every general scheme of
progress: they do not so much undermine the underlying line of succes-
sion (from Kant to late Schelling) as, rather, bring forth its most interesting
and lively moment, the moment when, as it were, a thought rebels against
its reduction to a term in the chain of development and asserts its abso-
lute right or claim. Sometimes, such reactions are mere outbursts of a
helpless disorientation; sometimes, they are themselves the true moments
of progress. That is to say, when the Old is attacked by the New, this rst
appearance of the New is as a rule at and nave the true dimension of
the New arises only when the Old reacts to the (rst appearance of) the
New. Pascal reacted from a Christian standpoint to scientic secular moder-
nity, and his reaction (his struggling with the problem of how one can
remain a Christian in the abyssal new conditions of the secular scientic
universe) tells us much more about modernity than its direct partisans. Or,
in the history of cinema, it was the silent directors resisting sound, from
Chaplin to Eisenstein, who brought to light the truly shattering dimension
of sound cinema. The true progress emerges from the reaction of the Old
to the progress. True revolutionaries are always reected conservatives.
123
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
124
FICHTES LAUGHTER
125
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
organization of appearances that evokes the mirage that there is, hidden
behind it, an Absolute which appears (shines through it). Here, the
illusion effectively is no longer to mistake appearing for being, but to
mistake being for appearing: the only being of the Absolute is its
appearing, and the illusion is that this appearing is a mere image behind
which there is a transcendent true Being. So when Fichte writes every
error without exception consists in mistaking images for being. The
Wissenschaftslehre has for the rst time pronounced how far this error
extends through showing that being is only in God,6 he misses the error
which is the exact opposite of mistaking images for being (i.e. of taking
as the true being what is effectively only its image), namely the error of
mistaking being for images (i.e., of taking as merely an image of the true
being what is effectively the true being itself). At this level, one should
thus accept the Derridean theological conclusion: God is not an
absolute Being persisting in itself, it is the pure virtuality of a promise, the
pure appearing of itself. In other words, the Absolute beyond appear-
ances coincides with an absolute appearance, an appearance beneath
which there is no substantial Being.
The second half of this double mediation is thus: if the Absolute is to
appear, appearing itself must appear to itself as appearing, and Fichte con-
ceives this self-appearing of appearance as subjective self-reection. Fichte
is right to endorse a two-step critical approach (rst from the object to its
subjective constitution, then the meta-critical deploying of the genesis of
the abyssal mirage of subjects self-positing). What he gets wrong is the
nature of the Absolute that grounds subjectivity itself: the late Fichtes
Absolute is an immovable transcendent in-itself, external to the movement
of reection. What Fichte cannot think is the life, movement, and media-
tion in the Absolute itself: what he misses is how, precisely, the Absolutes
appearing is not a mere appearance, but a self-actualization, a self-revela-
tion, of the Absolute. This immanent dynamics does not make the Absolute
itself a subject, but it inscribes subjectivization into its very core.
What Fichte was not able to grasp is the speculative identity of these
two extreme poles (pure absolute Being and the appearance appearing
to itself): the Is self-positing reexivity is, quite literally, the image of
the Absolute as self-grounded Being. Therein resides the objective irony
of Fichtes development: Fichte, the philosopher of subjective self-
positing, ends up reducing subjectivity to a mere appearance of an immov-
able absolute in-itself. The proper Hegelian reproach to Fichte is thus not
126
FICHTES LAUGHTER
127
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
128
FICHTES LAUGHTER
writing, more than his love-object, i.e., that the object is effectively
reduced to a pretext for engaging in the narcissistically satisfying activity
of writing. It is a little bit like the old musical mono-recordings: the very
cracking sounds that lter and disturb the pure reproduction of the
human voice generate the effect of authenticity, the impression that we
are listening to (what once was) a real person singing, while the very
perfection of modern recordings with all their Dolby effects etc. strangely
de-realizes what we hear. This is why the enlightened New Age indi-
vidual who extols us to fully realize/express our true Self cannot but
appear as its opposite, as a mechanical, depthless, subject who blindly
repeats his/her mantra.
What this means is that the dialectical reversal is, at its most radical,
the shift of the predicate into the position of subject. Let us clarify this
key feature of the Hegelian dialectic apropos the well-known male-
chauvinist notion of how, in contrast to mans rm self-identity, the
essence of woman is dispersed, elusive, displaced; the thing to do here is
to move from this claim that the essence of woman is forever dispersed,
to the more radical claim that this dispersion/displacement as such is the
essence of femininity. This is what Hegel deployed as the dialectical
shift in which the predicate itself turns into the subject: I found the
essence of femininity. But one cannot nd it, femininity is dispersed,
displaced . . . Well, this dispersion is the essence of femininity . . .
And subject is not just an example here, but the very formal structure
of it: subject as such is a subjectivized predicate; subject is not only
always already displaced, etc., it is this displacement. The supreme case
of this shift constitutive of the dimension of subjectivity is that of suppo-
sition. Lacan rst deployed the notion of the analyst as the subject
supposed to know which arises through transference (supposed to know
what (?) the meaning of the patients symptoms). However, he soon
realizes that he is dealing with a more general structure of supposition in
which a gure of the Other is not only supposed to know, but can also
believe, enjoy, cry and laugh, or even not know for us (from the Tibetan
praying mills to TV canned laughter). This structure of presupposition is
not innite: it is strictly limited, constrained by the four elements of the
discourse (S1, the master-signier; S2, the chain of knowledge; a, the
surplus-enjoyment; $, the subject): S1 subject supposed to believe;
S2 subject supposed to know; a subject supposed to enjoy . . . and
what about $? Do we get a subject supposed to be subject? What would
129
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
this mean? What if we read it as standing for the very structure of sup-
position: it is not only that the subject is supposed to have a quality, to do
or undergo something (to know, enjoy . . .) the subject itself is a suppo-
sition, i.e., the subject is never directly given as a positive substantial
entity, we never directly encounter it, it is merely a ickering void
supposed between the two signiers. (We encounter here again the
Hegelian passage from subject to predicate: from the subject supposed
to . . . to the subject itself as a supposition.) That is to say, what, precisely,
is a subject? Let us imagine a proposition, a statement how, when,
does this statement get subjectivized? When some reexive feature
inscribes into it the subjective attitude (for example, a love letter is sub-
jectivized when the writers turmoil and oscillation blurs the message)
in this precise sense, a signier represents the subject for another
signier. The subject is the absent X that has to be supposed in order to
account for this reexive twist, for this distortion. And Lacan here goes all
the way: the subject is not only supposed by the external observer-
listener of a signifying chain, it is in itself a supposition. The subject is inac-
cessible to itself as Thing, in its noumenal identity, and, as such, it is
forever haunted by itself as object: what are all Doppelganger gures if
not gures of myself as an object that haunts me? In other words, not
only others are a supposition to me (I can only suppose their existence
beneath the reexive distortion of a signifying chain), I myself am no less
a supposition to myself: something to be presumed (there must be an X
that I am, the this I or He or It (the thing) which thinks, as Kant put
it), and never directly accessed. Humes famous observation that, no
matter how close and deep I look into myself, all I will nd there are
specic ideas, particular mental states, perceptions, emotions, etc., never
a Self, misses the point: this non-accessibility to itself as an object is
constitutive of being a self.
130
FICHTES LAUGHTER
of Hegelian dialectics, one should make a step further: not only does the
universal Idea always appear in a distorted/displaced way; this Idea is
nothing other than the distortion/displacement, the self-inadequacy, of the
particular with regard to itself in strict homology with the move from
the subject supposed to . . . to subject itself as a supposition. One could
even claim that this reversal as such, formally, denes subjectivity: sub-
stance appears in phenomena, while a subject is nothing but its own
appearance. (And one can multiply these formulas: the universal is
nothing but the inadequacy, the non-identity, of the particular to/with
itself; the essence is nothing but the inadequacy of the appearance to
itself, etc.) This does not mean that the subject is the stupid tautology of
the Real (things just are what they seem to be, the way they seem to
be), but, much more precisely, that the subject is nothing but its own
appearing, the appearing reected-into-itself,8 the paradoxical torsion in
which a thing starts to function as a substitute for itself.
We encounter the Hegelian oppositional determination (gegenstzliche
Bestimmung), for example, in the prominent gure of the gay basher rap-
ing a homosexual, where homophobia encounters itself in its opposi-
tional determination, i.e., tautology (self-identity) appears as the highest
contradiction.9 A further example is provided by the extreme case of
interpassivity, when I tape a movie instead of simply watching it on TV,
and when this postponement takes a fully self-reected form: worrying
that there will be something wrong with the recording, I anxiously watch
TV while the tape is running, just to be sure that everything is alright
with the recording, so that the lm will be there on the tape, ready for a
future viewing. In this case, the paradox is that I do indeed watch a lm,
even very closely, but in a kind of suspended state, without really follow-
ing it all that interests me is that everything is really there, that the
recording is alright. Do we not nd something similar in a certain per-
verse sexual economy in which I perform the act only in order to be sure
that I can in future really perform the act: even if the act is, in reality,
indistinguishable from the normal act done for pleasure, as an end-in-
itself, the underlying libidinal economy is totally different.
Watching a movie appears here as its own oppositional determination
in other words, the structure is that of the Mobius strip: if we progress
far enough on one side, we reach our starting point again (watching the
movie, a gay sex act), but on the obverse side of the band. Lewis Carroll
was therefore right: a country can serve as its own map insofar as the
131
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
132
FICHTES LAUGHTER
133
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
134
FICHTES LAUGHTER
Why then to-night / Let us assay our plot; which, if it speed, / Is wicked
meaning in a lawful deed / And lawful meaning in a wicked act,
/ Where both not sin, and yet a sinful fact:/But lets about it.
135
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
the rule of law can only be asserted through wicked (sinful) meanings
and acts? What if, in order to rule, the law has to rely on the subterra-
nean interplay of cheatings and deceptions? This, also, is what Lacan
aims at with his paradoxical proposition il ny a pas de rapport sexuel (there
is no sexual relationship): was not Bertrams situation during the night
of love the fate of most married couples? You make love to your lawful
partner while cheating in your mind, fantasizing that you are doing it
with another partner. The actual sex-relationship has to be sustained by
this fantasmatic supplement.
One can imagine a variation of Shakespeares plot in which this fantas-
matic dimension would have been even more palpable, a variation along
the lines of the Jewish story of Jacob who fell in love with Rachel and
wanted to marry her; his father, however, wanted him to marry Leah,
Rachels elder sister. In order that Jacob will not be tricked by the father
or by Leah, Rachel taught him so that that he would recognize her at
night in bed. Before the sexual event, Rachel felt guilty towards her
sister, and told her what the signs were. Leah asked Rachel what will
happen if he recognizes her voice. So the decision was that Rachel will lie
under the bed, and while Jacob is making love to Leah, Rachel will make
the sounds, so he wont recognize that hes having sex with the wrong
sister . . .11 So we can also imagine, in Shakespeare, Diana hidden beneath
the bed where Helen and Bertram are copulating, making the appropri-
ate sounds so that Bertram will not realize that he is not having sex with
her, her voice serving as the support of the fantasmatic dimension.
From the Lacanian perspective, what then is appearance at its most
radical? Imagine a man having an affair about which his wife doesnt
know, so when he is meeting his lover, he pretends to be on a business
trip or something similar; after some time, he gathers the courage
and tells the wife the truth that, when he is away, he is staying with his
lover. However, at this point, when the front of happy marriage falls
apart, the mistress breaks down and, out of sympathy with the aban-
doned wife, avoids meeting her lover. What should the husband do in
order not to give his wife the wrong signal? How not to let her think that
the fact that he is no longer so often on business trips means that he is
returning to her? He has to fake the affair and leave home for a couple
of days, generating the wrong impression that the affair is continuing,
while, in reality, he is just staying with some friend. This is appearance at
its purest: it occurs not when we put up a deceiving screen to conceal the
136
FICHTES LAUGHTER
What are the philosophical roots of Fichtes error with regard to the
status of appearing? Let us return to the early Fichte (of the Jena period)
who is usually perceived as a radical subjective idealist: there are two
possible descriptions of our reality, dogmatic (Spinozean deterministic
materialism: we are part of reality, submitted to its laws, an object among
others, our freedom is an illusion) and idealist (the subject is autono-
mous and free, as the absolute I it spontaneously posits reality); reason-
ing alone cannot decide between the two, the decision is practical, or,
to quote his famous dictum, which philosophy one chooses depends
on what kind of man one is. Of course, Fichte passionately opts for
idealism . . . However, a closer look quickly makes clear that this is not
Fichtes position. Idealism is for Fichte not a new positive teaching that
should replace materialism, but to quote Peter Preusss perspicuous
formulation
137
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
138
FICHTES LAUGHTER
139
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
instead of the conict which now the moral disposition has to wage
with inclinations and in which, after some defeats, moral strength of
mind may be gradually won, God and eternity in their awful majesty
would stand unceasingly before our eyes. [. . .] Thus most actions con-
forming to the law would be done from fear, few would be done from
hope, none from duty. The moral worth of actions, on which alone the
worth of the person and even of the world depends in the eyes of
supreme wisdom, would not exist at all. The conduct of man, so long
as his nature remained as it is now, would be changed into mere mech-
anism, where, as in a puppet show, everything would gesticulate well
but no life would be found in the gures.18
In short, the direct access to the noumenal domain would deprive us of
the very spontaneity which forms the kernel of transcendental free-
dom: it would turn us into lifeless automata, or, to put it in todays terms,
into thinking machines. The implication of this passage is much more
radical and paradoxical than it may appear. If we discard its inconsis-
tency (how could fear and lifeless gesticulation coexist?), the conclusion
it imposes is that, at the level of phenomena as well as at the noumenal
level, we humans are a mere mechanism with no autonomy and
freedom: as phenomena, we are not free, we are a part of nature, a mere
mechanism, totally submitted to causal links, a part of the nexus of
140
FICHTES LAUGHTER
causes and effects, and as noumena, we are again not free, but reduced
to a mere mechanism. (Is what Kant describes as a person that directly
knows the noumenal domain not strictly homologous to the utilitarian
subject whose acts are fully determined by the calculus of pleasures and
pains?) Our freedom persists only in a space in between the phenomenal
and the noumenal. It is therefore not that Kant simply limited causality
to the phenomenal domain in order to be able to assert that, at the nou-
menal level, we are free autonomous agents: we are only free insofar as
our horizon is that of the phenomenal, insofar as the noumenal domain
remains inaccessible to us. (Kants own formulations are misleading,
since he often identies the transcendental subject with the noumenal
I whose phenomenal appearance is the empirical person, thus shirking
from his radical insight into how the transcendental subject is a pure for-
mal-structural function beyond the opposition of the noumenal and the
phenomenal.) Kant formulated this deadlock in his famous statement
that he had to limit knowledge in order to create space for faith. Along
the same lines,
141
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
Even clearer is this point in moral philosophy: when Kant claims that
moral Law is the ratio cognoscendi of our transcendental freedom, does he
not literally say that necessity is conceived freedom? That is to say, the
only way for us to get to know (to conceive) our freedom is via the fact
of the unbearable pressure of the moral Law, of its necessity, which enjoins
us to act against the compulsion of our pathological impulses. At the
most general level, one should posit that necessity (the symbolic neces-
sity that regulates our lives) relies on the abyssal free act of the subject,
on his contingent decision, on what Lacan calls the point de capiton,
the quilting point which magically turns confusion into a new order.
This freedom that is not yet caught in the cobweb of necessity, is it not
the abyss of the night of the world?
For this reason, Fichtes radicalization of Kant is consistent, not just a
subjectivist eccentricity. Fichte was the rst philosopher to focus on the
uncanny contingency in the very heart of subjectivity: the Fichtean
subject is not the overblown Ego = Ego as the absolute Origin of all real-
ity, but a nite subject thrown, caught, in a contingent social situation
forever eluding mastery.20 The Ansto, the primordial impulse that sets in
motion the gradual self-limitation and self-determination of the initially
void subject, is not merely a mechanical external impulse: it also points
towards another subject who, in the abyss of its freedom, functions as
the challenge [Aufforderung] compelling me to limit/specify my freedom,
i.e. to accomplish the passage from the abstract egotist freedom to con-
crete freedom within the rational ethical universe perhaps this inter-
subjective Aufforderung is not merely the secondary specication of the
Ansto, but its exemplary original case. It is important to bear in mind the
two primary meanings of Ansto in German: check, obstacle, hin-
drance, something that resists the boundless expansion of our striving,
and an impetus, stimulus, something that incites our activity. Ansto is
hence not simply the obstacle the absolute I posits to itself in order to
stimulate its activity so that, by overcoming the self-posited obstacle, it
asserts its creative power, like the games the proverbial perverted ascetic
saint plays with himself by inventing ever new temptations and then, in
successfully resisting them, conrming his strength. If the Kantian Ding
an sich corresponds to the Freudian-Lacanian Thing, Ansto is closer to
objet petit a, to the primordial foreign body that sticks in the throat of the
subject, to the object-cause of desire that splits it up: Fichte himself
denes Ansto as the non-assimilable foreign body that causes the subject
142
FICHTES LAUGHTER
division into the empty absolute subject and the nite determinate
subject, limited by the non-I.
Ansto thus designates the moment of the run-in, the hazardous
knock, the encounter of the Real in the midst of the ideality of the abso-
lute I: there is no subject without Ansto, without the collision with an
element of irreducible facticity and contingency the I is supposed to
encounter within itself something foreign. The point is thus to acknowl-
edge the presence, within the I itself, of a realm of irreducible otherness,
of absolute contingency and incomprehensibility . . . Ultimately, not just
Angelus Silesiuss rose, but every Ansto whatsoever ist ohne Warum.21
In clear contrast to the Kantian noumenal Ding that affects our senses,
Ansto does not come from the outside, it is stricto sensu ex-timate: a non-
assimilable foreign body in the very core of the subject as Fichte him-
self emphasizes, the paradox of Ansto resides in the fact that it is
simultaneously purely subjective and not produced by the activity of
the I. If Ansto were not purely subjective, if it were already the non-I,
part of objectivity, we would fall back into dogmatism, i.e. Ansto would
effectively amount to no more than a shadowy remainder of the Kantian
Ding an sich and would thus bear witness to Fichtes inconsequentiality
(the commonplace reproach against Fichte); if Ansto were simply sub-
jective, it would present a case of the subjects hollow playing with itself,
and we would never reach the level of objective reality, i.e. Fichte would
effectively be a solipsist (another commonplace reproach against his
philosophy). The crucial point is that Ansto sets in motion the constitu-
tion of reality: at the beginning is the pure I with the non-assimilable
foreign body in its heart; the subject constitutes reality by way of assum-
ing a distance towards the Real of the formless Ansto and conferring on
it the structure of objectivity. What imposes itself here is the parallel
between the Fichtean Ansto and the Freudian-Lacanian scheme of the
relationship between the primordial Ich (Ur-Ich) and the object, the
foreign body in its midst, which disturbs its narcissistic balance, setting in
motion the long process of the gradual expulsion and structuration of
this inner snag, through which (what we experience as) external, objec-
tive reality is constituted.
If Kants Ding an sich is not Fichtes Ansto, what is their difference?
Or, to put it in another way: where do we nd in Kant something
announcing Fichtes Ansto? One should not confuse Kants Ding an sich
with the transcendental object, which (contrary to some confused and
143
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
144
FICHTES LAUGHTER
the people around him, including a woman who claims to be his wife,
treat him as the head of a rich corporation. After a series of mysterious
events, he goes to an abandoned warehouse where he was told that, in
a barrel full of oil, the corpse of the person he had killed is hidden. When
he pulls the bodys head out of the liquid, he stiffens in consternation
the head is his own.22 This horror of encountering oneself in the guise of
ones double, outside oneself, is the ultimate truth of the subjects self-
identity: in it, the subject encounters itself as an object.
Jean-Pauls (Richters) Titan is a properly Romantic parody (decon-
struction even) of Fichte: he fully developed how the non-I is the Is
double, i.e., a part of the I active (in the guise of) as Is passivity, not the
Is real opposite. (What this means is that the Fichtean I is I should be
read as a Hegelian innite judgment whose truth is the coincidence of
opposites (I is non-I).) It is with regard to this topic of the double that
Fichte belongs to the aftermath of the Kantian revolution: the scope of
this revolution can be discerned precisely through the sudden change in
the perception of the theme of the double in literature. Till the end of
eighteenth century, this theme mostly gave rise to comic plots (two
brothers who look alike are seducing the same girl; Zeus seducing
Amphitrions faithful wife disguised as Amphitrion, so that, when
Amphitrion unexpectedly returns home, he encounters himself leaving
his bedroom, etc.); all of a sudden, however, in the historic moment
which exactly ts the Kantian revolution, the topic of the double becomes
associated with horror and anxiety encountering ones double or being
followed and persecuted by him is the ultimate experience of terror, it is
something which shatters the very core of the subjects identity.
The horrifying aspect of the theme of the double thus has something to
do with the emergence of the Kantian subject as pure transcendental
apperception, as the substanceless void of self-consciousness which is
not an object in reality. What the subject encounters in the guise of his
double is himself as object, i.e. his own impossible objectal counter-
point. In the pre-Kantian space, this encounter was not traumatic, since
the individual conceived of himself as a positive entity, an object within
the world. Another way to make the same point is to locate in my
double, in the encountered object which is myself, the Lacanian objet
petit a: what makes the double so uncanny, what distinguishes it from
other inner-worldly objects, is not simply its resemblance to me, but the
fact that he gives body to that which is in myself more than myself, to
145
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
146
FICHTES LAUGHTER
147
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
and the rest of the world, i.e., I adopt the innite position from which
I can observe reality and locate myself in it; on the contrary, the only
way for me to truly assert my nitude is to accept that my world is in-
nite, since I cannot locate its limit within it. (This is also what makes
Fichtes notion of Ansto so difcult: Ansto is not an object within the
represented reality, but the stand-in, within reality, of what is outside
reality.) As Wittgenstein points out, this is also the problem with death:
death is the limit of life which cannot be located within life and it is only
a true atheist that can fully accept this fact, as it was made clear by
Ingmar Bergman in his great manifesto for atheism, which he develops
precisely apropos his most religious lm, The Seventh Seal:
148
FICHTES LAUGHTER
149
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
self-limitation? Maybe we should read the thesis as the claim that every
limit of the subject is (grounded in) the subjects self-limitation in con-
junction with the overlapping of external with internal limitation. This
would account for the shifting of the accent of the subjects self-limita-
tion from subjective to objective genitive: it is not about the limitation
of the self in the sense that the subject is the full agent and master of its
own limitation, encompassing its limits into the activity of its self-media-
tion, but the limitation of the self in the sense that the external limita-
tion of the self truncates from within the very identity of the subject.
It was (again) Portier who clearly spelled out this point:
150
FICHTES LAUGHTER
Fichte, the a priori synthesis of the nite and the innite is the nitude
of the positing I:
One can see now the absolutely central role of the notion of limitation in
Fichtes entire theoretical edice: in contrast to dogmatic realism which
posits the substantial non-I as the only true and independent agency, as
151
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
152
FICHTES LAUGHTER
153
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
We can see now the fatal aw of the dismissal of Fichte as the extreme
point of German Idealism, as idealism at its worst. According to this
commonplace, Hegel is the moment of madness, the dream of a system
154
FICHTES LAUGHTER
155
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
It is only this primacy of the practical which provides the key to the
proper understanding of how Fichte reduces the perceived thing to the
activity of its perceiving, i.e., of how endeavors to generate the (per-
ceived) thing out of the perceiving. From this phenomenological
standpoint, the in-itself of the object is the result of the long arduous
work by means of which the subject learns to distinguish, within the
eld of its representations, between the mere illusory appearance and
the way the appearing thing is itself. The in-itself is thus also a category
of appearing: it is not the immediacy of the thing independently of how
it appears to us, but the most mediated mode of appearing how?
The I transfers a certain quantum of reality outside itself, it externalizes
part of its activity in a non-I which is thereby posited as non-posited,
i.e., it appears as independent of the I. Fichtes paradox is here that it is
the Is nitude [. . .] and not its reexivity proper, which renders neces-
sary the different modalities of the objectivization of the non-I to which
this I relates itself:37 to put it in somewhat simplied terms, the I is
caught in its self-enclosed circle of objectivizations not because he is the
innite ground of all being, but precisely because he is nite. The key
point not to be missed is hence the paradoxical link between innity
(in the sense of the absence of external limitation) and nitude: every
156
FICHTES LAUGHTER
157
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
158
FICHTES LAUGHTER
159
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
that time and space are a priori forms of sensibility; this prohibits any
nave-Platonic notion of the nite/material/sensual reality as the
secondary confused version of the intelligible/noumenal true universe
for Kant (and Fichte), material reality is not a blurred version of the
true noumenal kingdom, but a fully constituted reality of its own.
In other words, the fact that time and space are a priori forms of sensibil-
ity means that what Kant called transcendental schematism is irreduc-
ible: the orders/levels of sensibility and intelligibility are irreducibly
heterogeneous, one cannot deduce from the categories of pure reasons
themselves anything about material reality.
Fichtes position with regard to the status of nature nonetheless
remains the radicalized Kantian one: if reality is primordially experi-
enced as the obstacle to the Is practical activity, this means that nature
(the inertia of material objects) exists only as the stuff of our moral
activity, that its justication can only be practical-teleological, not specu-
lative. This is why Fichte rejects all attempts at a speculative philosophy
of nature. No wonder, then, that Schelling, the great practitioner of the
philosophy of nature, ridiculed Fichte: if nature can only be justied
teleologically, this means that air and light exist only so that moral
individuals can see each other and thus interact . . . Well aware of the
difculties such a view poses to our sense of credibility, Fichte replied
with sarcastic laughter:
They reply to me, the air and the light a priori! Dream therefore about
it ha!ha!ha! [. . .] laugh then with us, hahaha! hahaha! air and light
a priori: cream pie ha!ha!ha! air and light a priori! Cream pie ha!ha!ha!
[. . .] And so on to innity.44
The weird nature of this outburst of laughter resides in the fact that it is
the very opposite of the common-sense laughter at the philosophers
strange speculations, i.e., of the laughter whose exemplary case is the
bad taste joke against the philosopher-solipsist: Let him hit with his
head into a hard wall and he will soon discover if he is alone in the
world, hahaha! Here, the philosopher-Fichte laughs at the common-
sense argument that air and light are obviously not here just to enable
our moral activity they just are out there, if we act or not . . . Fichtes
laughter is all the more strange since it is similar to the traditional realist
philosophers direct reference to obvious reality as the best argument
against abstract speculations when Diogenes the Cynic was confronted
160
FICHTES LAUGHTER
161
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
162
FICHTES LAUGHTER
163
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
ready to confront. And, back to Fichte, is the Ansto not precisely such an
appearance without anything that appears, a nothing which appears
as something? This is what makes the Fichtean Ansto uncannily close
to the Lacanian objet petit a, the object-cause of desire, which is also
a positivization of a lack, a stand-in for a void.
Some decades ago, Lacan provoked reactions of ridicule when he stated
that the meaning of phallus is the square of 1 but it was already Kant
who compared the thing-in-itself as ens rationis to a square root of a neg-
ative number.49 It is insofar as we apply this comparison also to Fichtes
Ansto that the Kantian distinction between what we can only think and
what we can know assumes all its weight: we can only think the Ansto,
we cannot know it as a determinate object-of-representation.
164
FICHTES LAUGHTER
then the I is also able to fully know itself, i.e, we no longer have to refer
to a noumenal I or He or It (the thing) which thinks as Kant does in the
Critique of Pure Reason. And, thereby, we can also see how Fichtes urgency
to get rid of the thing-in-itself is linked to his focus on the ethico-
practical engagement of the subject as grounded in the subjects freedom:
if the subjects phenomenal (self)experience is just the appearance of an
unknown noumenal substance, then our freedom is merely an illusory
appearance and we are really like puppets whose acts are regulated by an
unknown mechanism. As I pointed out, Kant was fully aware of this
radical consequence and, perhaps, the entire Fichte can be read as an
attempt to avoid this Kantian impasse.
But, one may ask, does this assertion of the subjects capacity to get to
fully know itself not contradict Fichtes very focus on the subject as
practically engaged, struggling with objects/obstacles that frustrate its
endeavor, which necessarily makes the subject nite? Is it not that only
an innite being can fully know itself? The answer is that the Fichtean
subject is precisely the paradoxical conjunction of these two features, of
nitude and freedom, since its innity itself (the innite striving of its
ethical engagement) is an aspect of its nite condition.
The key is here again provided by Fichtes notion of the mutual delimi-
tation of subject and object, of Self and non-Self: every activity posited
in/as the object only insofar as the Self is posited as passive; and this
positing of the Self as passive is still an act of the Self, its self-limitation.
I am only a passive X affected by objects insofar as I (actively) posit myself
as a passive recipient Seidel ironically calls this the law of the conser-
vation of activity: when reality (activity) is canceled in the self, that
quantum of reality (activity) gets posited in the non-self. If activity is
posited in the non-self, then its opposite (passivity) is posited in the self:
I (passively) see the (actively) blooming apple. However, this can only
happen because I (actively) posit passivity in my-self so that activity
may be posited in the non-self. [. . .] The non-self cannot act upon my
consciousness unless I (actively, that is, freely) allow it to do so.50
Kant already pregured this in his so-called incorporation thesis:
causes only affect me insofar as I allow them to affect me. This is why
you can because you ought: every external impossibility (to which the
excuse I know I must do it, but I cannot, it is impossible . . . refers) relies
on a disavowed self-limitation. Applied to the sexual opposition of the
active male and passive female stance, this Fichtean notion of the
165
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER
166
FICHTES LAUGHTER
both are something: the not-self is what the self is not, and vice versa.
As opposed to the absolute self (though, as will be shown in due course,
it can only be opposed to it insofar as it is represented /by it/, not
insofar as it is in itself), the non-self is absolutely nothing [schlechthin
Nichts]; as opposed to the limitable self, it is a negative quantity.53
However, from the practical standpoint, the nite Self posits the innite
Self in the guise of the ideal of a unity of Self and not-Self, and, with it,
the non-self as an obstacle to be overcome. We thus nd ourselves in a
circle: the absolute Self posits non-self and then nitizes itself by its
delimitation; however, the circle closes itself, the absolute presupposition
itself (the pure self-positing) returns as presupposed, i.e., as the presup-
position of the posited, and, in this sense, as depending on the posited.
Far from being an inconsistency, this is the crucial, properly speculative,
moment in Fichte: the presupposition itself is (retroactively) posited by
the process it generates.
So, perhaps, before dismissing him as the climactic point of subjectivist
madness, we should give Fichte a chance.
167
Notes
Introduction
1 Henrich (2008), p. 32.
2 Ibid.
3 See Kants own brief sketch of the history of pure reason at the end
of the First Critique: Kant (2003), B880884.
4 We thank Tom Krell (New York) for his various comments on the
text and for his help with the preparation of this manuscript for
publication.
5 This also accounts for the integration of skepticism into the motiva-
tion of the theoretical activity of Post-Kantian philosophy as such.
See Gabriel (2007); Franks (2000), (2003), (2005).
6 Henrich (2008), p. 32.
7 This point is brilliantly argued in Brandom (2005).
8 Hegel (1977), 76. Miller (poorly) translates this as an exposition of
how knowledge makes its appearance.
9 To be sure, for the later Fichte and Schelling, this necessity turns out
to be contingent on a higher order!
10 Henrich (2008), p. 52.
11 Ibid., p. 59.
12 Schelling (2006), p. 22.
13 iek (2006) offers an elaborate account of the notion of a
parallax.
14 Schulz (1975), p. 279.
15 My translation from the German: SW, X, 311: Betrachten wir den
hier geforderten oder als mglich gezeigten Vorgang im Allgemeinen,
168
NOTES
Markus Gabriel
169
NOTES
4 Heidegger (1997), p. 51: And what is it that we, from out of oursel-
ves, allow to stand-against? It cannot be a being. But if not a being,
the just a nothing [ein Nichts]. Only if the letting-stand-against of . . .
is a holding oneself in the nothing can the representing allow a not-
nothing [ein nicht-Nichts], i.e., something like a being if such a thing
shows itself empirically, to be encountered instead of a within the
nothing.
5 Seen in this light, Badious concept of the void ultimately commits
him (despite himself) to the void actually being out there. He does not
leave cosmology behind, as he claims, but rather reasserts it with his
recourse to an ontology of the void. Naming the void means displa-
cing it. It has no proper name, not even the void. For this reason,
there can be no ontology of the void. It is nothing but a withdrawal
that always forces us to yet another revocation of necessity.
6 I argue for the necessary incompleteness of metabasis, i.e. of the acti-
vity of constructing meta-languages, in Gabriel (2008), pp. 209215.
7 Wittgenstein (1969), 9397, 162, 167, 233, 262.
8 Wittgenstein (1979), p. 10e.
9 Wittgenstein (1953). Wittgenstein writes, a picture held us captive.
And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and
language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably (PI, 115).
10 Badiou (2007), p. 30: Ontology, axiom system of the particular
inconsistency of multiplicities, seizes the in-itself of the multiple by
forming into consistency all inconsistency and forming into inconsi-
stency all consistency. It thereby deconstructs any one-effect; it is
faithful to the non-being of the one, so as to unfold, without explicit
nomination, the regulated game of the multiple such that it is none
other than the absolute form of presentation, thus the mode in which
being proposes itself to any access.
11 Hegel (1969), p. 50.
12 Gadamer (2004), p. 296.
13 Hogrebe (1989). I give an overview of the contemporary debate on
Schelling in Gabriel (2005), pp. 271301 as well as in Gabriel (2006b),
13.
14 Michelle Kosch gives a good account of the relation between
Kierkegaards and Schellings critique of Hegel; Kosch (2006). See
also Matthews (2008), pp. 184, in particular, pp. 5468 and Houlgate
(1999). A good introduction is Bowie (1993).
170
NOTES
171
NOTES
172
NOTES
173
NOTES
174
NOTES
175
NOTES
176
NOTES
177
NOTES
178
NOTES
179
NOTES
180
NOTES
181
NOTES
182
NOTES
Slavoj iek
183
NOTES
25 Hegel makes this point clear in his Logic: The activity of thought
which is at work in all our ideas, purposes, interests and actions is, as
we have said, unconsciously busy /. . ./ [E]ach individual animal is
such individual primarily because it is an animal: if this is true, then
it would be impossible to say what such an individual could still be if
this foundation were removed, Hegel (1976), pp. 3637.
26 Malabou (2005), p. 32.
27 Hegel (1971), 407.
28 Malabou (2005), p. 35.
29 Hegel (1971), 408.
30 Upon a closer look, it becomes clear that the Hegelian notion of
madness oscillates between the two extremes which one is tempted
to call, with reference to Benjamins notion of violence, constitutive
and constituted madness. First, there is the constitutive madness: the
radical contradiction of the human condition itself, between the
subject as nothing, as the evanescent punctuality and the subject as
all, as the horizon of its world. Then, there is the constituted
madness: the direct xation to, identication with, a particular
feature as an attempt to resolve (or, rather, cut short) the contradic-
tion. In a way homologous with the ambiguity of the Lacanian notion
of objet petit a, madness names at the same time the contradiction/
void and the attempt to resolve it.
31 Hegel (1971), 408, Addition.
32 Ibid.
33 Ibid., 401.
34 Hegel (1977), 310.
35 Malabou (2005), p. 71.
36 Ibid., p. 72.
37 Ibid., p. 68.
38 Hegel (1977), 322.
39 Ibid., 318.
40 See Marx (1978), p. 95.
41 Hegel (1977), 318.
42 Malabou (2005), p. 67.
43 Ibid., p. 68.
44 Hegel (1974b), p. 204. Further, in his Encyclopaedia, Hegel mentions
the night-like abyss within which a world of innitely nume-
rous images and presentations is preserved without being in
184
NOTES
Slavoj iek
Fichtes Laughter
1 As to this last example, there are attempts to reconstruct Hegels
answer to Marxs materialist reversal of dialectics. Cf. Maker (1989).
See also my own defense of Hegel against Marx in chapter 1 of iek
(2006).
2 Walter Schulzs book The Accomplishment of German Idealism in
Schellings Late Philosophy advances just this thesis; see Schulze
(1975).
3 Zoeller (2008), p. 55.
4 Brachtendorf (2008), p. 157.
5 Ibid. This shift can also be formulated as the one from positing to
appearing: while in 1794, the I posits itself as positing itself, in 1812,
the appearance appears to itself as appearing to itself. To appear,
however, is an activity. Thus, the appearance appears to itself as
being active through itself, or as a principle from itself, out of itself,
185
NOTES
186
NOTES
187
NOTES
15 Ibid., p. 41.
16 Ibid., p. 46.
17 Ibid., p. 131.
18 Kant (1956), pp. 152153.
19 Fichte (1987), p. XII.
20 See Breazeadale (1995), pp. 87114.
21 Ibid., p. 100.
22 The solution to the mystery: he is effectively not the husband, but
the lover of the woman who claims to be his wife. When he barely
survived the accident while driving the husbands car, with his face
disgured beyond recognition, the wife killed her husband, identi-
ed HIM as her husband and ordered the surgeons to reconstruct his
face on the model of her husbands.
23 Portier (2005), p. 30.
24 Wittgenstein (1961), prop. 6.4311.
25 Bergman (1995), pp. 240241.
26 See Laclau (1995).
27 Portier (2005), pp. 134, 136.
28 Ibid., p. 54.
29 Seidel (1993), pp. 116117.
30 Portier (2005), p. 154.
31 Portier (2005), p. 158.
32 See Livet (1987).
33 Seidel (1993), p. 102.
34 Ibid., pp. 8788.
35 Sartre (1957), p. 327.
36 Bernasconi (2006), p. 48.
37 Portier (2005), p. 222.
38 Ibid., p. 244.
39 Ibid., p. 230.
40 Ibid., p. 238.
41 Ibid., p. 253.
42 Ibid., p. 232.
43 Ibid., p. 224.
44 Fichte (1971b), pp. 478479.
45 Quoted in Seidel (1993), pp. 5051.
46 Ibid., p. 89.
47 Kant (2003), Bxxvi.
188
NOTES
189
Bibliography
190
BIBLIOGRAPHY
191
BIBLIOGRAPHY
192
BIBLIOGRAPHY
193
BIBLIOGRAPHY
194
BIBLIOGRAPHY
195
BIBLIOGRAPHY
196
BIBLIOGRAPHY
197
BIBLIOGRAPHY
198
Index
199
INDEX
200
INDEX
201
INDEX
202