Mythology, Madness, and Laughter PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 209

MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS,

AND LAUGHTER
Also available from Continuum:

Interrogating the Real, Slavoj iek


The Universal Exception, Slavoj iek
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS,
AND LAUGHTER
Subjectivity in German Idealism
Markus Gabriel and Slavoj iek
Continuum International Publishing Group
The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane
11 York Road Suite 704
London SE1 7NX New York NY 10038

www.continuumbooks.com

Markus Gabriel and Slavoj iek 2009

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced


or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical,
including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or
retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers.

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data


A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

ISBN: HB: 978-1-4411-9105-2

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


Gabriel, Markus, 1980-
Mythology, madness, and laughter: subjectivity in german idealism/Markus
Gabriel and Slavoj Zizek.
p. cm.
ISBN-13: 978-1-4411-9105-2 (HB)
ISBN-10: 1-4411-9105-4 (HB)
1. Idealism, German. 2. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770-1831.
3. Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von, 1775-1854. 4. Fichte, Johann
Gottlieb, 1762-1814. I. iek, Slavoj. II. Title.

B2745.G33 2009
141.0943dc22 2009008265

Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems Pvt Ltd, Chennai, India


Printed and bound in Great Britain by the MPG Books Group
Contents

Introduction: A Plea for a Return to Post-Kantian Idealism 1


Markus Gabriel and Slavoj iek

1. The Mythological Being of Reection An Essay on Hegel,


Schelling, and the Contingency of Necessity 15
Markus Gabriel
1. The Appearances Hegel on Reection 27
2. The Unprethinkable Being of Mythology Schelling on the
Limits of Reection 50
3. The Contingency of Necessity 81

2. Discipline between Two Freedoms Madness and


Habit in German Idealism 95
Slavoj iek
1. The Hegelian Habit 99
2. The Auto-poiesis of the Self 104
3. Expressions that Signify Nothing 112
4. Habits, Animal and Human 118

3. Fichtes Laughter 122


Slavoj iek
1. From Fichtes Ich to Hegels Subject 123
2. Absolute and Appearance 130
3. The Fichtean Wager 137
4. Ansto and Tat-Handlung 146
CONTENTS

5. Division and Limitation 151


6. The Finite Absolute 154
7. The Posited Presupposition 164

Notes 168
Bibliography 190
Index 199

vi
Introduction: A Plea for a Return to Post-Kantian
Idealism
Markus Gabriel and Slavoj iek

Although an insurmountable abyss seems to separate Kants critical


philosophy from his great idealist successors (Fichte, Schelling, Hegel),
the basic coordinates which render Post-Kantian Idealism possible are
already clearly discernible in Kants Critique of Pure Reason. The original
motivation for doing philosophy is a metaphysical one, to provide an
explanation of the totality of noumenal reality; as such, this motivation
is illusory, it prescribes an impossible task.1 This is why Kants explicit
motivation is a critique of all possible metaphysics (which is not yet
science). Kants endeavor thus necessarily comes after the fact of meta-
physics: in order for there to be a critique of metaphysics, there rst has
to be an original metaphysics; in order to denounce the metaphysical
transcendental illusion, this illusion rst has to occur. In this precise
sense, Kant was the inventor of the philosophical history of philoso-
phy2: there are necessary stages in the development of philosophy, i.e.,
one cannot directly get at truth, one cannot begin with it, philosophy neces-
sarily began with metaphysical illusions.3 Post-Kantian Idealists share
Kants preoccupation with transcendental illusion but argue that illusion
(appearance) is constitutive of the truth (being). This is what this whole
book is about.4
According to Post-Kantian Idealists, the path from illusion to its critical
denunciation is the very movement of philosophy, which means that the

1
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

successful (true) philosophy is no longer dened by its truth-apt


discursive explanation (or representation) of the totality of being, but by
successfully accounting for illusions, i.e., by explaining not only why
illusions are illusions, but also why they are structurally necessary,
unavoidable, why they are not just accidents. The occurrence of illusions
is necessary for the eventual emergence of truth, an idea Fichte, Schelling,
and Hegel inherited from Kant.5 The system of philosophy thus no
longer represents the alleged ontological structure of reality, but becomes
a complete system of all metaphysical statements. The proof of the
illusory nature of metaphysical propositions in the traditional sense
consists in an argument to the effect that they necessarily engender
antinomies (contradictory conclusions). Since metaphysics attempts to
avoid the very antimonies which emerge when we make our metaphy-
sical commitments downright explicit, the system of critical philosophy
is the complete and therefore self-contradictory, antinomic series of
metaphysical notions and propositions: Only the one who can look
through the illusion of metaphysics can develop the most coherent, con-
sistent system of metaphysics, because the consistent system of meta-
physics is also contradictory6 that is to say, precisely, inconsistent.7
The critical system amounts to a presentation (Darstellung) of the
systematic a priori structure of all possible/thinkable errors in their
immanent necessity, thus preparing the ground for Hegels presentation
of appearing knowledge (Darstellung des erscheinenden Wissens)8: what we
get at the end is not the Truth that overcomes/sublates the preceding
illusions the only truth is the inconsistent edice of the logical inter-
connection of all possible illusions . . . This shift from the representation
of metaphysical Truth to the truth of the shift from error to error is
exactly what Hegel presented in his Phenomenology (and, at a different
level, in his Logic). The only (but crucial) difference is that, for Kant, this
dialogic process of truth emerging as the critical denouncing of the
preceding illusion is restricted to the sphere of our knowledge, i.e. to
epistemology, and does not concern the noumenal reality which remains
external and indifferent to it, while, for Hegel, the proper locus of this
process is the Thing itself. Like Hegel, the later Fichte and Schelling
ultimately locate the necessary displacement of truth, the necessity of
error, in the noumenal itself.9 In other words, the relative occurs within
the absolute. The absolute is not distinguished from its contingent mani-
festations. It loses the status of a substance underlying the illusory

2
INTRODUCTION

appearances and becomes the movement of a self-othering without


which the illusion of a substance could not take place. The traditional
hierarchy of substance and accident is thus completely inverted. The
accidents take over and dissolve substance into a misleading appearance.
In our view, the reason for this ontological overcoming of epistemo-
logical dichotomies (appearances vs. the thing in itself; necessity vs.
freedom etc.) can indeed be motivated by the Post-Kantian insight that
the very mode of appearance occurs within the noumenal. If we oppose
the noumenal and the phenomenal in terms of an account of the
nitude of knowledge we blind ourselves to the fact that this opposition
ex hypothesi occurs within the noumenal itself. Otherwise put, the whole
domain of the representation of the world (call it mind, spirit, language,
consciousness, or whatever medium you prefer) needs to be understood
as an event within and of the world itself. Thought is not at all opposed to
being, it is rather beings replication within itself.
In what, then, does the break between Kant and Post-Kantians
consist? Kant sets out with our cognitive capacities. The apparatus of our
cognitive capacities is affected by (noumenal) things and, through its
active synthesis, organizes affections into phenomenal reality. However,
once Kant arrives at the ontological result of his critique of knowledge
(the distinction between phenomenal reality and the noumenal world of
Things-in-themselves), there can be no return to the self. There is no
plausible interpretation of the self as a member of one of the two worlds.10
This is where practical reason enters the picture: the only way to return
from ontology back to the domain of the Self is freedom. Freedom unites
the two worlds, and it provides the ultimate maxim of the Self: subordi-
nate everything to freedom.11
Yet, at this point a gap between Kant and his followers is opened up.
For Kant, freedom is an irrational, i.e. unexplainable fact of reason, it
is simply and inexplicably given, something like the umbilical cord inex-
plicably rooting our experience in the unknown noumenal reality. While
Kant would refuse to regard freedom as the rst theoretical principle out
of which one can develop a systematic notion of reality, Post-Kantian
Idealists from Fichte onwards transgress the limit constitutive of noume-
nal freedom in Kants sense and endeavor to provide the systematic
account of freedom itself. Freedoms self-explication assumes a different
shape. Freedom is no longer opposed to necessity, it does not remain a
transcendent postulate, but becomes an inherent feature of being as

3
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

such. For precisely this reason, Schelling in his Essay on Human Freedom
recommends a higher realism of freedom:

It will always remain odd, however, that Kant, after having rst distin-
guished things-in-themselves from appearances only negatively
through their independence from time and later treating independence
from time and freedom as correlate concepts in the metaphysical
discussions of his Critique of Practical Reason, did not go further toward
the thought of transferring this only possible positive concept of the
in-itself also to things; thereby he would immediately have raised
himself to a higher standpoint of reection and above the negativity
that is the character of his theoretical philosophy.12
The status of the limits of knowledge changes with German Idealism.
The epistemological nitude of reason which cannot legitimately be
transgressed without generating metaphysical nonsense for the Idealists
indicates the limitations of Kantian reection. They believe that Kant got
stuck half-way, whereas from a thoroughly Kantian perspective, his
idealist successors completely misunderstood his critical project and fell
back into pre-critical metaphysics or, worst even, mystical Schwrmerei.
Accordingly, there are mainly two versions of the passage from Kant to
German Idealism which respectively result from the unfortunate and
often even hostile dividing line within contemporary philosophy. Philo-
sophers who characterize themselves by belonging to the analytic tradi-
tion (a term which, as a matter of fact, denotes at the most a family
resemblance of methods) tend to believe that Kant is the last traditional
philosopher who, at least partially, makes sense. Until most recently,
analytic philosophers dened themselves by a deep hostility towards the
Post-Kantian turn of German philosophy and (in the wake of Moore and
Russell) regarded it as one of the greatest catastrophes, as a bunch of
undisciplined regressions into meaningless speculation and so forth. On
the other hand, there is a group of philosophers who deem the Post-
Kantian speculative-historical approach to philosophical thought the
highest achievement of philosophy which we have not yet even fully
understood. They believe that many of the central insights of German
Idealism still wait to be translated into contemporary philosophy.
However, the latter group of philosophers tends to neglect those features
of German Idealism which, at rst glance, do not appear to be translat-
able into contemporary philosophy. Yet, we rmly believe that it is an

4
INTRODUCTION

important task of contemporary philosophy to create new possibilities of


expression out of an original approach to the problem of subjectivity in
German Idealism.
There are roughly speaking two perspectives on the turn from Kant
to Post-Kantian Idealism. (1) According to the rst approach, Kant
correctly claims that the gap of nitude only allows for a negative access
to the noumenal, while Hegels absolute idealism, to name one example,
dogmatically closes the Kantian gap and returns to pre-critical metaphys-
ics. (2) According to the second approach, Kants destruction of meta-
physics does not even go far enough, because it still maintains the
reference to the Thing-in-itself as an external, albeit inaccessible entity.
Seen from this vantage point, Hegel merely radicalizes Kant, by offering
a transition from a negative access to the Absolute to the Absolute itself
as negativity.
In this volume, we will defend a reading along the lines of (2). However,
we will not just offer another perspective of the transition from Kant to
Hegel. We will rather focus on some widely neglected features of Post-
Kantian Idealism which speak in favor of our overall thesis: German
Idealism was designed to effectuate a shift from epistemology to a new ontology
without simply regressing to pre-critical metaphysics. It locates the gap between
the alleged absolute (the thing in itself) and the relative (the phenomenal world)
within the absolute itself. It is a crucial duty of contemporary Post-Kantian
Idealism to make sense of this shift in order to contribute to the overcoming of
epistemology as prima philosophia.
If totality exists, then it necessarily remains incomplete if we continue
to exclude error from truth. Error, illusion, misunderstanding, negativ-
ity, nitude, etc. are necessary preconditions for an adequate, non-
objectied understanding of the absolute as the opening up of a domain
within which determinate (nite) objects can appear.
As Slavoj iek argues, Hegels decisive move draws on the dialectical
insight that our incomplete knowledge of the thing turns into a positive
feature of the thing which (qua nite, determinate object) is in itself
incomplete and inconsistent. This is the Hegelian shift from the episte-
mological obstacle to the positive ontological condition of appearance.
In other words, Hegel does not re-ontologize the Kantian framework.
On the contrary, Kants philosophy needs to be properly de-ontologized,
insofar as it conceives the gap of nitude as merely epistemological,
insofar as he continues to presuppose (or postulate) the vision of a fully

5
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

constituted noumenal realm existing out there. The Post-Kantian destruc-


tion of this potentially damaging remainder of ontology consists in trans-
posing the gap into the very texture of reality. In other words, Fichtes,
Schellings, and Hegels move is not to overcome the Kantian division,
but, rather, to assert it as such, to drop the need for the additional
reconciliation of the opposites. Through a purely formal, parallactic
shift, Post-Kantian Idealism gains the insight that the reective positing
of the distinction constitutive of nitude already is the reconciliation.13
Kants failure lies thus not so much in his remaining within the connes
of nite oppositions, in his inability to reach the innite, but, on the
contrary, in his very longing for a transcendent domain beyond or behind
the realm of nite oppositions: Kant is not unable to reach the innite,
because there is no such thing as the innite waiting to be discovered.
This is why Kantian reection always already inhabits the allegedly
transcendent realm of freedom. Our freedom consists in the ability to
draw the distinction constitutive of nitude.
To acquire a more precise insight into the uniqueness of Post-Kantian
Idealism, it is also possible to access it from the other end of history, that
is from the vantage point of Post-Hegelian anti-philosophy and its
criticism of the idea of a mirror of nature (Rorty), i.e. of representatio-
nalism as such. Post-Hegelian anti-representationalism in its various
disguises (deconstruction, post-structuralism, neo-pragmatism, and so
forth) seems to debunk the language of representation/appearance
altogether. Instead, it emphasizes the excess of the pre-conceptual pro-
ductivity of Being or nature over its representation: representation is
reduced to truth-apt discourse which is rooted in the productive ground
of what there really is. Whereas Hegelianism still seems to operate on a
transcendental level, apparently ascribing the power of world produc-
tion to an absolute subjectivity, Post-Hegelian anti-philosophy is charac-
terized by the introduction of a determination of self-determination that
cannot be dissolved into the movement of a self-othering of absolute
subjectivity. As Walter Schulz has argued in his inuential book The
Completion of German Idealism in Schellings Late Philosophy, Post-Hegelian
anti-philosophy which already begins with the later Fichte and Schelling
denes itself as mediated self-mediation (vermittelte Selbstvermittlung).14
The subject is thrown into a process of self-mediation it ultimately
neither controls nor triggers. The subject, in other words, turns out to be
the result of an inversion which alienates the subject from its alleged

6
INTRODUCTION

capacity to transparently manage itself. The later Schelling refers to this


process in terms of an ecstasy of the subject or, even more fundamen-
tally, as an uni-versio, an inversion of the One.

If we regard the process that we postulate here or rather whose


possibility we indicated in general, this process appears to be a process
of inversion, that is to say, of an inversion of the One, of the pre-
actual Being, of the prototype of all existence, for that which is the
subject, A, becomes the object, and that which is the object (+A),
becomes the subject. Hence, this process can be called universio
whose immediate result is the inverted One Unum versum, whence
universe.15
To be sure, according to our view of Post-Kantian Idealism, Hegelian
dialectics too draws on inversion as the true motor of the dialectical
movement; recall the inverted world of philosophy Hegel refers to in
the Phenomenology.16 Hegelian dialectics is precisely a movement of auto-
displacement which is not enacted by a pre-established absolute subjec-
tivity or, even more absurd, by some transcendent absolute subject.
The general thrust of our argument is that the alleged Post-Hegelian
turn of philosophy really takes place in the work of Fichte, Schelling, and
Hegel and it does so in a more reected manner than much of the self-
declared overcoming of Hegel in twentieth- century analytic and conti-
nental philosophy.
In so-called post-structuralism, for example, the relation between the
two terms of a binary opposition (phenomenal/noumenal, subject/
object, etc.) is inverted: the presence (the space) divided and thereby
required by the opposition is denounced as the illusory result of a pro-
ductive process which can never be presented. The self-othering of
binary oppositions exhibited by the performance of deconstruction
generates an absence which is, however, not the absence of something
which antecedes the inversion of the opposition. In other words, post-
structuralism could object against our reading of German Idealism that it
still privileges one relatum of a binary opposition over the other in order
to dene an absolute immune to inversion. It could make the case that
we leave the original One untouched to the effect that it remains the
subject of a merely accidental uni-versio. Post-structuralism invokes an
account of the shift taking place in the inversion which might appear to
dispose of the absolute in an even more radical way than suggested by

7
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Post-Kantian Idealisms interpretation of the notion of the absolute in


terms of a self-othering activity.
However, we will argue against precisely this objection. The absolute
of the German Idealists is not some pre-existing totality or some absolute
subject creating the course of worldly events out of its unhampered
spontaneity. Such an interpretation of German Idealism would miss the
crucial shift from substance to subject. The subject Hegel has in mind is
an absolute negativity which can only constitute itself after the fact.
Without its manifestation, i.e. without the nite, it would be nothing.
The absolute is, hence, nothing but the proper name of the belatedness
constitutive of any logical space as such: our conceptual abilities to refer
to something determinate in the world can only take place after the fact.
The fact is constituted by this after, by the belatedness of the subject.
Lets say that ontological excess denotes the excess of productive
presence over its representation, the X which eludes the totalization-
through-representation. Once we accomplish the step towards the gap
within the space of productive presence itself, the excess becomes the
excess of representation which always already supplements productive
presence. A simple political reference can make this point clear: the
Master (a King, a Leader) at the center of a social body, the One who
totalizes it, is simultaneously the excess imposed on it from outside. The
struggle of the center of power against the marginal excesses threatening
its stability cannot ever obfuscate the fact, visible once we accomplish a
parallactic shift of our view, that the original excess is that of the central
One itself. As Reiner Schrmann would put it, all hegemonies as such
are broken.17 In Lacanian terms we can also say that the One is always
already ex-timate with regard to what it unies. The One totalizes the
eld it unies by way of condensing in itself the very excess that threat-
ens this eld.
In other words, any totalizing gesture of completion derives its energy
from something which cannot be constituted by the very gesture itself.
The very intention of completion, of a fully determinate, all-encompass-
ing structure fails because the activity of constituting cannot itself be
constituted in the terms of the overall sphere of intelligibility which is
the result of the activity.
To illustrate this point, let us consider Italo Calvinos A King Listens.18
In an anonymous kingdom, the royal palace becomes a giant ear and the

8
INTRODUCTION

king, obsessed and paralyzed by fears of rebellion, tries to hear every


sound that reverberates in his palace: footsteps of the servants, whispers
and conversations, fanfare trumpets at the raising of the ag, ceremo-
nies, sounds of the city at the outskirts of the palace, riots, the rumble of
ries, etc. He cannot see their source but is obsessed by interpreting their
meaning and the destiny they are predicting. This state of interpretive
paranoia only seems to halt when he hears something that completely
enchants him: through the window the wind brings a singing voice of a
woman, a voice of pure beauty, unique and irreplaceable. For the king it
is the sound of freedom: he steps out of the palace into the open space
and mingles there with the crowd . . . The rst thing to bear in mind
here is that this king is not the traditional monarch, but a modern totali-
tarian tyrant: the traditional king doesnt care about his environment, he
arrogantly ignores it and leaves the worry and care to prevent plot to his
ministers; it is the modern leader who is obsessed by plots. This is why
the perfect formula of Stalinism, of the system of endless paranoiac
hermeneutics is to rule is to interpret. So when the king is seduced by
the singing voice of the woman pronouncing immediate life-pleasure,
this is obviously (although, unfortunately, not for Calvino himself) a
fantasy precisely the fantasy of breaking out of the closed circle of rep-
resentations and of rejoining the pure outside of the innocent presence
of the feminine voice. However, the fantasy of the pure outside, the
fantasy of the original One anteceding its inversion or even perversion
by the symbolic order, is nothing but the excess of the self-mirroring
prison-house of representations. What this fantasy misses is the way this
innocent externality of the voice is itself already reexively marked by
the mirror of interpretive representations. This is why one can imagine
what the storys ending really is, what is missing in Calvinos explicit
narrative: when the king exits the palace, following the voice, he is
immediately arrested: for the feminine voice was an instrument of the
plotters to lure him out of the safety of the guarded palace.
If one translates the moral of this story into the language of philoso-
phy, it becomes evident that the One, the master-signier which is
supposed to constitute the divine gift of intelligibility, is not exempt
from the process of totalization. The obvious problem is that there are
various simulacra of the One, various totalizing opportunities which are
inherently destabilized because they are only maintained by the fantasy

9
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

of an original One. In other words, the Hegelian true innite is the


innity generated by the self-relating of a totality, by the short-circuit
which makes a totality an element of itself (or, rather, which makes a
genus its own species), which makes re-presentation part of presence
itself. The One is included in the act of excluding it. It becomes the inclu-
sion of exclusion, i.e. the inversion of itself. This inversion occurs within
totality: rst, a paradoxical element (which is not a proper element of
the apparently all-encompassing set-structure in question) is designated
as transcendent and secondly this paradoxical element is drawn into
totality in an act of closure. The impossibility of reconciling transcendence
and closure motivates Hegels claim that totality is not complete, that it
constantly stands in need of its realization in nitude. The innite is not
always already established but turns out to be the result of an excess of
intelligibility.19
This structure can also be made apropos the properly dialectical notion
of abstraction: what makes Hegels concrete universality innite is that
it includes abstractions into concrete reality itself, as their immanent constitu-
ents. For Hegel, the elementary move of philosophy with regard to
abstraction consists in abandoning the common-sense empiricist notion
of abstraction as a step away from the wealth of concrete empirical
reality with its irreducible multiplicity of features: life is green, concepts
are grey, they dissect and mortify concrete reality. (This common-
sense notion even has its pseudo-dialectical version, according to which
such abstraction is a feature of mere Understanding, while dialectics
recuperates the wealth of reality.) Philosophical thought proper begins
when we become aware of how such a process of abstraction is inherent in
reality itself: the tension between empirical reality and its abstract
notional determinations is immanent to reality, it is a feature of things
themselves. Therein resides the anti-nominalist accent of dialectical
thinking (just like the basic insight of Marxs critique of political econ-
omy is that the abstraction of the value of a commodity is its objective
constituent).
This brings us to the question: what is a dialectical self-deployment of
a notion? Imagine, as a starting point, our being caught in a complex and
confused empirical situation which we try to understand, to bring some
order into it. Since we never start from the zero-point of pure pre-
notional experience, we begin with the double movement of directly

10
INTRODUCTION

applying the abstract-universal notions at our disposal to the situation.


We analyze it and compare its elements with our previous experience,
generalizing, formulating empirical universals. Sooner or later, we
become aware of inconsistencies in the notional schemes we employ to
understand the situation: something which should have been a subordi-
nate species seems to encompass and dominate the entire eld, different
classications and categorizations clash, without us being able to decide
which one is true, etc.
In what, then, resides Hegels uniqueness? Hegels thought stands
for the moment of passage between philosophy as Master discourse
(the philosophy of the One that totalizes the multiplicity) and anti-
philosophy (which asserts the Real that escapes the grasp of the One).
On the one hand, he clearly breaks with the metaphysical logic of count-
ing-for-One; on the other hand, he does not allow for any excess exter-
nal to the eld of notional representations. For Hegel, totalization-in-One
always fails, the One is always already in excess with regard to itself, it is
itself the subversion of what it purports to achieve, and it is this tension
internal to the One, this Two-ness which both makes the One one and
simultaneously dislocates it, it is this tension which is the movens of the
dialectical process. In other words, Hegel effectively denies that there is
a Real external to the network of notional representations (which is why
he is regularly misread as an absolute idealist in the sense of the self-
enclosed circle of the totality of the Notion). However, the Real does not
disappear here in the global self-relating play of symbolic representa-
tions: it returns with a vengeance as the immanent gap or obstacle on
account of which representations cannot ever totalize themselves, on
account of which they are non-All.20
In our spontaneous mind-frame, we dismiss such inconsistencies as
signs of the deciency of our understanding: reality is much too rich and
complex for our abstract categories, we will never be able to deploy a
notional network able to capture its entire wealth . . . However, once we
develop a rened theoretical sense, we sooner or later notice something
strange and unexpected: it is not possible to clearly distinguish the incon-
sistencies of our notion of an object from the inconsistencies which are
immanent to this object itself. The thing itself is inconsistent, full of
tensions, struggling between its different determinations, and the deploy-
ment of these tensions, this struggle, is what makes it alive. Take

11
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

a particular state: when it malfunctions, it is as if its particular (specic)


features are in tension with the universal idea of the state. Or take the
Cartesian cogito: the difference between me as a particular person
embedded in a particular life-world and myself as abstract subject is part
of my particular identity, since to act as abstract subject is a feature that
characterizes individuals in modern Western society. The notional reality
is not opposed to the empirical. It is not the case that we simply take in
an in itself consistent world to which we then apply a propositionally
structured system of beliefs. This idea itself is already the application
of a notional structure, one way of describing our position in the world,
what Gabriel in his chapter will call a constitutive mythology.
The transition from Kant to Hegel can be formulated as the passage
from the notion of a substantial Real to the purely formal Real. The for-
mal Real is the immanent gap within the coordinates of representation.
Another key gure of nineteenth-century philosophy, Schopenhauer,
also contributed to this transition in his interpretation of the noumenal
thing as will. The Kantian unknowable which escapes our cognitive
grasp turns out to be the ontological essence of cognition. Intentionality,
i.e. our reference to determinate objects in the world, is directed by the
will, by the noumenal itself, which objecties itself in our referring
to determinate objects. What happens in Hegel is that the Real is thor-
oughly de-substantialized: it is not the transcendent X which resists
symbolic representations, but the immanent gap, rupture, inconsistency,
the curvature of the space of representations itself.
One of the most prominent anti-Hegelian arguments reminds us of the
fact of the Post-Hegelian break: what even the most fanatical partisan of
Hegel apparently cannot deny is that something changed after Hegel, that
a new era of thought began which can no longer be accounted for in
Hegels own explication of absolute conceptual mediation; this rupture
occurs in different guises, from Schellings assertion of the abyss of pre-
logical will (later vulgarized by Schopenhauer) and Kierkegaards
insistence on the uniqueness of faith and subjectivity, through Marxs
assertion of actual socio-economic life-process, up to Freuds notion of
death-drive as a repetition that persists beyond all dialectical mediation.
Something happened after Hegel, there is a division between before and
after, and while one can argue that Hegel already announces this break,
that he is the last of the idealist metaphysicians and the rst of the post-
metaphysical historicists, one cannot really be a Hegelian after this break.

12
INTRODUCTION

Hegelianism has lost its innocence forever. To act like a full Hegelian today
is the same as to write tonal music after the Schnberg revolution.
The predominant Hegelian strategy that is emerging as a reaction to
this scare-crow image of Hegel the Absolute Idealist, is the deated
image of Hegel freed of ontological-metaphysical commitments, reduced
to a general theory of discourse and to discourses constitutive norma-
tivity. This approach is best exemplied by so-called Pittsburgh Hegelians
(Brandom, McDowell): no wonder Habermas praises Brandom, since
Habermas also avoids directly approaching the big ontological question
(are humans really a subspecies of animals, is Darwinism true?), the
question of God or nature, of idealism or materialism. It would be easy
to prove that Habermass neo-Kantian avoidance of ontological commit-
ment is in itself necessarily ambiguous: while Habermasians treat
naturalism as the obscene secret not to be publicly admitted (of course
man developed from nature, of course Darwin was right . . .), this
obscure secret is a lie, it covers up their deeply idealist form of thought
(the a priori transcendentals of communication which cannot be deduced
from natural being). The truth is hidden and at the same time manifested
in the form: while Habermasians secretly think they are really material-
ists, the truth lies in the idealist form of their thinking. To put it provoca-
tively, Habermasians tend to be royalists in the republican form. They
reduce naturalism to a fruitful hypothesis which seems to be inevitable
given that contemporary discourse has committed itself to a scientic
world-picture. Yet, to be an actual naturalist is not to subscribe to neces-
sary ction, but to really believe in materialism. It is, in other words, not
enough to insist that Kant and Hegel have to teach us something about
the realm of normativity which takes place in the wider domain of the
realm of nature. It is, on the contrary, important to re-appropriate
German Idealism to a fuller extent. If discourse, representation, mind, or
thought in general cannot consistently be opposed to the substantial real
which is supposed to be given beforehand, independent of the existence
of concept-mongering creatures, then we have to bite the bullet of ideal-
ism: we need a concept of the world or the real which is capable of accounting for
the replication of reality within itself.21
Our theories of the world as such are part of the world. Our system(s)
of belief are not transcendent entities occupying a deontological space
thoroughly distinguished from the ontological space best described in the
language of physics. We rmly believe that the deated image of Hegel

13
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

does not sufce. The fetishism of quantication and of the logical form prevail-
ing in much of contemporary philosophical discourse is characterized by a lack of
reection on its constitution. It is our aim to dismantle this lack and to argue
that we are in need of a twenty-rst-century Post-Kantian Idealism
which would, of course, not be geographically restricted. The era of
German Idealism is over, but the era of Post-Kantian Idealism has just
begun (with neo-Hegelianism as its rst necessary error).

14
CHAPTER ONE
The Mythological Being of Refl ection An Essay
on Hegel, Schelling, and the Contingency of
Necessity
Markus Gabriel

Anything we encounter in the world and to which we are capable of


referring by some singular term, i.e. anything to which we concede
existence, is part of a certain domain. Renaissance paintings belong to
a different domain than our own feelings and mental states. National
states belong to a different domain than physical particles or, lets say, the
ora and fauna of the Amazons. So, if what we call the world or the
universe is some kind of totality, then we must agree it is primarily a
totality made up of sub-sets, of domains of objects. It cannot simply be
the totality of elements (say space-time particles) because it is an essen-
tial feature of the world to be accessible under various descriptions. Any
attempt to reduce the world to one object domain, i.e. any variety of a
nave ontic monism, necessarily fails because it cannot account for its
own theory-building process, its own operation of singling out a sub-set
of the world and arranging its elements in a particular (and therefore
contingent) manner. To overcome this irresolvable logical disjunction it
would have to include the activity of presenting the elements within its
elements, which is impossible as long as the elements are determined
within a given domain, i.e. as long as they are proper elements.
If we say of something that it exists, we necessarily refer to some deter-
minate object. Even elusive objects that exhibit vague predicates are

15
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

determinate objects in a higher-order sense: they are determined as


indeterminate. This simple reection apparently enables us to say that
the world is made up of objects the determinacy of which is investigated
in a suitable discourse quantifying over a relevant domain of objects.
However, the trouble with this whole train of thought is that it forgets
to take account of the obvious fact that it always already refers to the
domains of objects as higher-order-objects. The very discourse in which
we are able to distinguish between domains generates a higher-order-
domain of these domains. This regress necessarily comes to a halt once
we reach the level of the domain of all domains, i.e. the proper concept
of the world. At this point we are bound to accept some variety of onto-
logical monism, i.e. the thesis that there is only one world (one ultimate
domain of all domains), a thesis which runs contrary to ontic monism
which picks out its preferred domain and denes it as the only really
existing domain thereby drawing a sharp line between appearance
(all other theories) and reality (the single true general theory). Ontologi-
cal monism ultimately accommodates the different world-views within
the world by tearing down the barrier between the so-called mind-
independent external world and its representations in nite thinkers.
Ontological monism draws on the fact that the various forms of repre-
senting the world occur within the world such that the world must
be capable of an ontological doubling: it replicates itself within itself.
Classical varieties of ontological monism (like those of Parmenides, Plato,
and Plotinus, to name some examples) render this thought by claiming
that being and thought are one and the same: being necessarily expresses
itself in thought, it becomes aware of itself.1 Hegel seeks to reposition
this ontological doubling by installing the doubling within a third term,
i.e. within reection. The doubling is always already an inner doubling.
Being does not (contingently) manifest itself in nite thinkers but, con-
versely, depends on its doubling into being and appearance. Being ceases
to be the name for the thing, for the absolute supposed to be indepen-
dent of our activity of referring to it. It becomes the proper name of
a disjunction into being and appearance.
If to exist is to exist as an object within a domain, i.e. if existence presup-
poses determinacy, then the domain of all domains cannot exist. Other-
wise it would be an object within a domain and therefore it would not be
the domain of all domains because we would have formed a higher-order
domain of all domains containing the supposed domain of all domains.

16
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

In other words, there is no way to refer to the domain of all domains


within ordinary (propositional) language. Ordinary (propositional)
language presupposes substances, i.e. objects that can be referred to by
singular terms (such as dog, the Mona Lisa, Rome etc.).2 However,
the domain of all domains and, hence, the world cannot be referred to by
a singular term lest it loses its ontological status of being the world. If the
world is not an object we can talk about, then how do we manage to
understand the line of thought with which I am opening this chapter?
Did I not refer to the world for the last ve paragraphs?
One immediately feels troubled by the thought that the ultimate
domain within which everything takes place is not itself a place, but the
proper void itself. One undergoes a vertiginous experience beautifully
rendered by Victor Pelevin in his novel Buddhas Little Finger. In an ironi-
cally philosophical discussion with a character named Chapaev (obvi-
ously an allusion to Vasily Ivanovich Chapayev, the famous Red Army
Commander during the Russian Civil War) the protagonist Pyotr Voyd
(sic!) realizes that the domain of all domains is not really a place.
Confronted with the question where the universe is, Pyotr understands
that it is nowhere.3
Our relation to objects, i.e. intentionality, is ultimately exposed to
nothingness, as Heidegger put it.4 However, this nothingness is the world
itself. If the world itself does not exist, then how can we believe that the
domains included within the world can exist? Is there any way to avoid
ontological nihilism, that is, the claim that nothing really exists because
everything takes place nowhere and hence does not take place at all?
As we shall see in the course of this chapter, the fact that language fails
vis--vis an all-encompassing nothingness releases creative energies
which eventually overturn nothingness: this is why there is something
rather than nothing. Nothing becomes something in our constant activity
of naming the void. To be more precise, the void is of course not even the
void, for the void is but another singular term within the chain of signi-
ers. If there is no way to refer to the void, that is to say if there is no way
to gain access to any sort of transcendence, then we cannot even refer to
the void by describing it as the void. The void precedes, transcends,
outreaches (or whichever way you want to name this relation which is
not a proper relation between two terms) any apophantic environment, it
cannot be captured within any sphere of intelligibility or cosmological model
as I call it.5

17
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

The difference between language and the paradoxical domain of all


domains (traditionally dealt with under the name of the absolute)
generates discourse. Discourses select one object domain rather than
another with the aim of discovering what is the case in a particular
domain. However, by selecting one domain rather than another, they
generate the absolute by triggering its withdrawal. Any attempt to deter-
mine our position within the world and therefore any attempt to catch
up with the world in language generates a set of background (objective)
certainties in Wittgensteins sense, a set of inaccessible presuppositions
governing discourse. Whenever we try to determine the presuppositions
governing a discourse about some object domain or other, we ipso facto
generate higher-order presuppositions governing our meta-discourse
to the effect that we are never capable of formulating any fully self-
transparent meta-language.6 Nevertheless, discourse needs to stabilize its
preconditions incessantly in order to defend itself against the ongoing
threat of absolute indeterminacy.
The threat of absolute indeterminacy is the origin of the mythological
narrations of the origin of the world. All such narrations attempt to
articulate the conditions of possibility of a language by transposing lan-
guages internal difference between itself and the absolute (i.e. between
form and content) on to some natural order which is supposed to deter-
mine language from its outside. In this context Wittgenstein writes that
any doxastic system, i.e. any system of beliefs, creates a background
mythology or a world-picture.7 There is no way to transcend a given
mythology without generating another one. This is why all language
(including Wittgensteins own form of presentation (Darstellungsform)
includes a mythology: A whole mythology is deposited in our language.8
Heidegger, too, refers to the inviolability of world-pictures as the sine
qua non of determinacy in his The Age of the World-Picture. In our age of
the world-picture, the mythological conditioning of our experience
hides itself behind the mythology of de-mythologization. The world seems
to be fully disenchanted; we have bypassed traditional societies by
giving up values based on authority, etc. This story is one of the corner-
stones of our mythology that believes in scientic, manipulatory
rationalitys capacity to transcend historicity. It does blind itself to the
possibility that the very era of the world as picture ready to be manipu-
lated might itself be a world-picture, namely the world-picture of the
world-picture.

18
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

As Schelling, Heidegger, and Wittgenstein agree, reection is inevitably


bound to a set of nite, discursive expressions of itself generating imagi-
nary frameworks, mythologies. Those frameworks are usually not reected
and cannot be fully reected: any attempt to achieve such a totalizing reection
simply generates another myth, a different imaginary, another image which will
sooner or later hold us captive.9 Incompleteness cannot be overcome because
it is a condition of possibility of determinacy and therefore paradoxi-
cally of completion. In this sense, Schelling, Heidegger, and Wittgen-
stein argue that there is no ultimate meta-theory, no standpoint outside
of the limits of language.
And yet, many philosophers such as Hegel or Badiou in our times
believe themselves capable of expressing the absolute form of presenta-
tion.10 Even though reection in Hegel also fails to the extent that it
discovers that it depends on natural and spiritual developments within
the sphere of the nite, Hegel nevertheless claims to uncover truth as it
is without veil and in its own absolute nature.11 To be sure, Hegel is not will-
ing to admit this failure of reection. Even if one can argue (as I will in
fact do) that it is entailed by his account of reection, this failure is lost on
Hegel himself, because he associates the insistence on the failure with
romantic deance that in his eyes stubbornly insists on incompleteness.
The aim of this chapter is systematic and not historical in nature. I do not
venture to repeat what Schelling and Hegel said in a different language.
I do not even believe that this is possible. There is no such thing as
Schellings or Hegels philosophy out there in the texts ready to be discov-
ered by the historian of philosophy. Such a view of the relation between
the text and its meaning is predicated on a variety of nave hermeneutical
and metaphysical presuppositions I fortunately do not share. Philosophical
ideas are not out there like stones, they are discursively created. Philoso-
phy is a thoroughly creative business, an insight carried out by Nietzsche
and Deleuze in an irreducible manner. This also holds for the ideas we
extract from the classical texts of the various traditions of philosophy. Any
reading of a philosophical text rather repeats the text in the Deleuzian
sense of repetition: it retroactively generates a minimal difference in our
understanding, which is why understanding always entails understanding
differently. Or, to borrow Gadamers famous phrase, it is enough to say
that we understand in a different way, if we understand at all.12
Given that I will reconstruct the outlines of Schellings critique of
Hegel, it seems important to indicate that Schellings critique is barely

19
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

known, let alone philosophically appreciated in the context of Anglo-


phone philosophy. Whereas Hegels philosophy is enjoying an ever better
reputation due to the prospects of its pragmatist and semantic revival,
Schelling remains largely marginal. Despite some recent efforts in the
German literature on Schelling beginning with the path-breaking work
of Wolfram Hogrebe on Predication and Genesis, Schellings variety of
ontological monism has the bad reputation of being untranslatable into
contemporary terms.13 This is why there have been only a few attempts
to reconstruct the later Schellings critique of Hegel.14 However, most
writers tend to dismiss Schellings criticism as shallow or beside the point
concentrating on his admittedly supercial discussion of Hegels system
in his lectures On the History of Modern Philosophy.15 Yet, this approach
misses the richer material and deep insights spread throughout Schellings
late philosophy, i.e. throughout his Munich and Berlin Lectures on the
Philosophy of Mythology and the Philosophy of Revelation.16
Manfred Frank has convincingly argued that the difference between
Schelling and Hegel ultimately lies in their different conceptions of the
relation between being and reection.17 Whereas Hegel claims that being
is an aspect (Moment) of reection which eventually becomes fully trans-
parent within the root-and-branch self-referential Notion, Schelling
maintains that reection depends on and is thus necessarily secondary to
what he calls unprethinkable being (unvordenkliches Seyn).18 In other
words, Schelling stresses the fact that reection necessarily indicates the
brute fact of existence, which is per se inexplicable (indeterminable) in
logical terms. Reection is therefore by no means the unconditional.
It ultimately depends on that which is unequal to itself (das sich selbst
Ungleiche),19 a form of dependence Schelling also refers to under the
heading of the uncanny principle.20 This uncanny principle expresses
itself in the various disguises of mythology from ancient (Egyptian,
Greek, Indian, etc.) mythology to contemporary ideology based on the
scientic imaginary.
It is precisely in this sense that we must understand the importance of
mythology in Schellings critique of Hegel. Mythology denominates the
brute fact of existence of a logical space, which cannot be accounted for
in logical terms. It deals with sub-semantical (a-semic) energies organiz-
ing our eld of experience by establishing links between the elements of
experience, which, as a matter of fact, only become elements of experi-
ence after the links have been established. The elements are therefore

20
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

generated retroactively: once (a) logical space is established, it will auto-


matically be able to discern elements within its reach.
Schellings point thus resembles an observation of Badious: the values
of logical variables (and therefore existence from a logical point of view)
cannot be determined by those variables themselves. Whether there
really are horses, stones, or elephants cannot be determined with sole
recourse to our concepts. However, even if there is no logically consistent
way to refer to logics ontological conditions, this does not necessarily
entail the absoluteness of reection. In order to make sense of objectivity
at all, we need to admit that there has to be something that cannot be
absorbed in reections closure upon itself: any account of objectivity that
tries to exclude fallibility from its notion of truth is indefensible.
Any similarity between Schelling and Badiou comes to a denite end
once we consider Badious thoroughly Platonist identication of mathe-
matics and ontology. Indeed, in opposition to Badious idea of an abso-
lute discourse (which is based on set-theory) Schelling argues for a
mythological heteronomy of reection. For Schelling reection bears an
indelible mythological remainder (Rest): it has a mythological origin it
can never fully get rid of. In other words Schelling claims that every
theory-building process that attempts to get hold of its own precondi-
tions necessarily misres. And this necessary failure is due to the very
nature of reection.21
Moreover, reection is inapt to grasp itself because it always already
accesses itself under a certain description, that is to say, within the reach
of one eld of sense among others. Reections belatedness (which I just
attempted to put into words), however, cannot be described without
thereby misring again. There is no ultimate exposition of reections
nitude for any such exposition implies a paradoxical claim to innity.22
Reection is always already the result of a determinate framework
whose determinacy is not in turn the result of reection. Being precedes
reection because reection is based on an experience Wolfram Hogrebe
coined the trauma of God (Gottesschock).23 This trauma takes place as soon
as consciousness aspires to get a hold on itself. In this act of self-constitu-
tion it loses itself because it becomes an other to itself. This other returns
in the form of the Gods and haunts consciousness throughout its history.
In order to examine Schellings critical re-evaluation of the essence of
reection, i.e. of its mere being there, one should begin with a systematic
reconstruction of Hegels competing claim, namely that nothing exists

21
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

outside of that theory-building process which Hegel envisages under the


heading of reection. For Hegel, Being is but an aspect of reection, its
blind spot or remainder. Being is the effect of reections incapacity to
fully reect itself. If by being we understand that which is in-itself, that
which we discover in truth-apt discourse, then we have to learn the
crucial lesson of Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, that the in-itself is only
in-itself for us. We determine being over against reection such that
being for us turns out to be a coagulation of reection. If we go on to
claim that there must be being prior to reection, this in-itself again is
in-itself for us. Reection thereby divides itself in being and reection in
such a manner that it tends to be unaware of this very operation in order
to secure its very being. Closer analysis, however, reveals that reection
never encounters anything but itself such that it is the movement of
nothing to nothing, and so back to itself.24
For Hegel, being is thus never unexplainable; if you think you cannot
understand reality, it is because you are not reecting properly! Surprises
are only the result of a false reection. Reection attempts to take pos-
session of its own preconditions by constantly appropriating them.
Reection in Hegel, therefore, radicalizes the project of modern subjec-
tivity to include being within the limits of representation. Like in Kant,
Reinhold, and the early Fichte, being is reduced to being posited within
the coordinates of representation. Kants oft-quoted claim that being is
not a real predicate is backed up by his concept of being as the position
of a thing.25 To be is to be posited as an object of (possible) experience. Whether
there actually is something outside of the eld of experience, that is,
something that transcends the bounds of sense, can neither be afrmed
nor denied because we have no means to substantiate any transcendent
ontological commitment.26 The coordinates of representation determine
what there can be: we then assert that the conditions of the possibility of
experience in general are likewise the conditions of the possibility of the
objects of experience, and that for this reason they have objective validity in
a synthetic a priori judgment.27 For Kant this means that the a priori
conditions of a possible experience in general are at the same time condi-
tions of the possibility of objects of experience.28
The modern subject poses itself as unhampered self-reection thereby
ruling out the threat of heteronomy, let alone theonomy. And yet, as
both Schelling and Hegel point out, it cannot properly account for the
fact of its own existence. In effect, the very idea of a free-oating

22
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

solipsistic ego constructing the world out of nothing turns out to be


intrinsically incoherent as soon as we realize that the subject itself
becomes part of the world, part of the very nothingness it supposedly has
to transform into a world. The subject itself is part of the world it con-
structs out of nothing because it is represented within the context of the
epistemological theory accounting for the objectivity of experience. The
allegedly unconditioned subject constitutes and, therefore, conditions
itself by asserting its position as unconditioned subject.
The subject reduces itself to one representation among all others in the
very activity of its self-directed cognition. It thus misses itself in the act
of grasping itself. To put it with Wittgenstein: where in the world is a
metaphysical subject to be found? You will say that this is exactly like the
case of the eye and the visual eld. But really you do not see the eye. And
nothing in the visual eld allows you to infer that it is seen by an eye.29
Unsurprisingly, the problem of reection plays an important role in
lm (theory): in principle, it is impossible to see the actual camera that
shoots the movie. Even if a camera is shown in a movie (which is a stan-
dard self-referential trope of cinema) and even if the camera that shoots
a scene is seen in a mirror, we do not see the actual camera when we see
it in a movie. The camera in a movie is just as little the camera that
shoots the movie as the mental image of an elephant is an elephant. The
actual apparatus enabling the appearance of the world of a movie cannot
appear within the world of a movie.
Dieter Henrich, Manfred Frank, and Dieter Sturma, among others, have
argued that the dilemma of self-directed cognition can be solved if we
adequately account for the primacy of an original non-conceptual self-
awareness preceding reective self-cognition. The early idealist master-
concept of intellectual intuition seems to sustain this position.30 Yet, as
Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel soon realized, the postulate of an intellectual
intuition does not help because it is itself formulated in a discursive, non-
intuitive language, i.e. within the range of a theory. The alleged immedi-
acy and original unity of self-awareness is mediated by the underlying
duplicity of subject and object presupposed in every theory that is not
thoroughly self-referential. And even if a theory ever managed to become
downright self-referential, it would still presuppose an internal rupture.
And this means that immediacy only becomes salient when it is lost, for
it is lost in the very act of talking, thinking, and theorizing about it. It is
displaced: instead of remaining in the position of the original unity

23
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

preceding the sphere of conceptual division (of judgment), it turns into


an empty promise of transcendence, i.e. into a postulate as Hegel convin-
cingly argued against Fichte in the Difference Essay. The subject enters the
realm of the ought (of Sollen) as a consequence of its decision to grasp
itself. It ought to be something it has not yet become, it has a pre-discursive
grasp of its lost unity that it tries to exhibit within the world. We might say
that the subject feels the urge (Trieb, Sehnen) to become part of the
world, to manifest itself within the world, just like cinema since the 1960s
and 1970s has been compelled to experiment with the possibility of creat-
ing a world whose elements represent the very act of creation.
Hegels crucial point is that any supposed reality transcending the con-
ceptually mediated realm of differentiality is only a side-effect of concep-
tual mediation, an expression of reections misred attempt to grasp itself.
iek aptly recapitulates this when he writes that according to Hegel

non-conceptual reality is something which emerges when notional


self-development gets caught in an inconsistency, and becomes non-
transparent to itself. In short, the limit is transposed from the exterior
to the interior: there is Reality because, and in so far as, the Notion is
inconsistent, does not coincide with itself.31
The standard reading of the early Fichte and the early Schelling sees
them entangled in the paradox of nihilism famously diagnosed by Jacobi:
either the subject is nothing determinate, some transcendent paradoxical
vanishing point, or it is itself an object among others. If it is nothing
determinate, then we cannot grasp it at all, not even as unconditioned
without thereby determining it. If it is something determinate, then it
completely dissolves into its own products. Given that the world of
objects is determined as the purely causal realm of space and time
(in Kant) or even as nothingness compared to the creative subject (in
Fichte and German Romanticism) the ego annihilates itself in the very
act of its self-determination as purely creative center. That is, as soon as
the creative center on which determinacy is supposed to hinge is deter-
mined (be it as the indeterminable creative center) it is lost. It can either
become a part of the determinate world-order it creates by objectifying
itself or it can seek refuge in an everlasting denial of its objectivity,
thereby losing any determinacy, even that of being indeterminate.32
The transcendence of the ego remains ambiguous precisely because
it can never be claimed. We have to eradicate any rm belief in the

24
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

possibility of grasping the absolute as some stable principle. Instead we


have to practice the deconstruction of conceptual mediation what
Fichte calls the destruction of the concept (Vernichtung des Begriffs)33
a practice (in principle incompletable) anticipating the postmodern
situation of endless deferral. The absolute thereby becomes the activity
of deferring. Fichtes point is not the eradication of any belief in the
possibility of grasping the absolute (the in-itself), but the brilliant insight
that the absolute is the deferral itself. The distortion of the absolute in
the medium of conceptual relativity is the absolute itself. Fostering this
insight Fichte avoids the trap of reication by establishing a methodological
instead of an ontic monism. He argues that the absolutes unity consists in
the very activity of presenting its absence. It is hence not itself something
absent, transcendent or hidden but the blind spot of every presentation
as such. It only manifests itself in the withdrawal which must not be
hypostatized as the withdrawal of something pre-existing the with-
drawal. The withdrawal constitutes a space in which the thing in its
elusiveness might appear.
The modern subject is entangled in a set of paradoxes of reection.
This situation became explicit in Hegels and Schellings theories of sec-
ond-order reection of reection which should be read as an attempt to
overcome Kants and the earlier Fichtes object-directed theorizing. Kant
and Fichte still work with a concept of reection modeled after the
Cartesian paradigm wherein thought is opposed to (material) being. The
subject turns her gaze inwards in order to experience her radical alterity
from the external world. Despite themselves, Kant and Fichte are
committed to the assumption of a primarily cognitive subject which is
practical (ethical) because its cognitive powers are limited. The primacy
of the practical is not assumed from the outset but turns out to be the
consequence of the necessary nitude of knowledge. Hegel and Schelling,
however, convincingly argued that the gap constituting the Kantian and
Fichtean primacy of practice cuts deeper than the subjects activity of
distinguishing itself from the world. It affects reection as an ontological
and not only as an epistemological operation. For them nitude is thus
an ontological event.
In the rst part of this chapter I shall argue that Hegel uncovers the
dialectic of modern subjectivity in the appearance chapter of his Logic of
Essence and that he also offers a solution to the epistemological dilemma
of the modern subject. Nevertheless, I will also argue that Hegel himself

25
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

falls prey to the dialectic of modern subjectivity because he fails to apply


his own reection on nitude to itself. The very nitude of reection laid
out in his discussion of reection is dissolved into the lucidity of the
Notion. Hegel thereby ultimately loses track of the nitude he himself
discovers in his revolutionary thesis that Being is illusory being (das Sein
ist Schein).34
In the second part of my chapter, I will then reconstruct the outlines of
Schellings late Philosophy of Mythology. Here, Schelling argues that the
idea (Idee) is a result of the subjects forgetfulness of its paradoxical
origin. The idea is the realm of intelligibility. Contrary to the tradition
of absolute autonomy, Schelling insists that the subject does not generate
itself and thereby insists on the thrownness characteristic of our being-
in-the-world. On top of that, Schelling also maintains that the subjects
determining activity is itself determined by the unattainable withdrawal
of the event of being, which Schelling calls the unprethinkable being.
Yet, unlike Heidegger, Schelling locates the primordial withdrawal of the
event in mythology. The indispensability of a mythology constitutive of
intelligibility as such can never be rendered fully transparent by reec-
tion, thinking, or poetry.
For Schelling, being thus turns into the fragmentary history of mytho-
logical images and narratives, or otherwise put: being turns out to be diony-
sian. In fact I shall argue that the process of mythology Schelling envisages
under the name of Dionysos still endures. The work that Heidegger and
Wittgenstein are trying to do when talking about world-picture and
mythology respectively amounts to developing the conceptual tools nec-
essary for a theory of the mythological being of contemporary reection.
The indispensability of constitutive mythology does not preclude
thinking the absolute, as Meillassoux claims, but rather allows us to
absolutize relativity. The absolutization of relativity does not add up to a
simple-minded relativism asserting that everything (including this
statement) is relative. On the contrary, it asserts that everything is
relative to an absolute, to something which cannot be relativized, not
even to the relation of knowledge. Meillassoux is therefore mistaken
when he ascribes correlationism to the thinkers we will deal with
herein, i.e. the claim that nothing can precede the circle of reections
identication with being.35 In the third part of this chapter I shall argue
against Meillassoux claim that contingency is necessary replacing it by
the even stronger assertion that necessity is contingent. In my view, the

26
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

contingency of necessity, i.e. higher-order contingency, is the adequate


modal category of a new (philosophy of) mythology.

1. THE APPEARANCES HEGEL ON REFLECTION

Before I can get to Hegels solution of the deadlock of modern subjectiv-


ity, it is necessary to prepare the ground for the following discussion.
In this context, we will see how Hegel actually understood the problem
of the subject (raised by Descartes, Hume, and Kant) much more pre-
cisely than his predecessors.
Fichtes philosophy chiey investigates the conditions of possibility of
appearance. Consequently, the later Fichte develops the outlines of a
theory of absolute appearance, i.e. of an appearance beneath which
there is no substantial Being.36 Fichte incessantly reects on and makes
us aware of the fact that every assertion contained in his own theory
(and in any theory for that matter) is only the sclerotic, reied objecti-
vation of a theory-building process called the actual deed (Tathand-
lung). To be sure, any analysis of Hegels chapter on Appearance in his
Science of Logic should bear this in mind since it is to a great extent the
result of Hegels grappling with the dialectic of Fichtes philosophy. Here
Hegel unveils the internal dialectic of reections attempt to become
absolute.
It is characteristic for modern philosophy to dene thought as the
essence of the world. According to the modern stance of reection we
could just as well be completely sealed off from the world, eternally
caught up in an unfullled desire to encounter the world. The modern
answer to the question of the veridicality of determinacy from Descartes
onwards has it that even if we do not know whether there is an external
world, we are still aware of the intentional structure of representation
(i.e. of the existence of an internal world). In effect, Descartes is known
for having argued for an epistemological asymmetry between the mental
and the external world; an asymmetry between thought and esh which
actually enables us to afrm with absolute certainty that there are repre-
sentings, i.e. that there is representational purport, without thereby
knowing that the success conditions of that very purport are ever
fullled.37 So even if we cannot know what is real, we can at least know

27
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

that the whole world is inside our head. This is what I call the modern
stance of reection.
It is quite remarkable to see contemporary cinema rediscovering the
dream-like structure of experience and substituting it for the intermina-
ble ironical self-denial of postmodern fragmentation. Postmodernism (in
the totality of its aesthetic and philosophical expressions) refrained from
asserting any metaphysical position. On the contrary, contemporary
cinema is widely characterized by the return of metaphysics. If we assume
that contemporary art/lm actually reects something we could call the
contemporary general state of mind, then we have to accept that we are
again searching for a more plausible, a more digestible, a more bearable
answer to our lack of certainty about the world and its meaning.
Many movies are shot in a transcendent light, a phenomenon Raoul
Eshelman describes as theistic creation.38 A variety of recent examples
may illustrate this general tendency, in particular The Chumscrubber
(2005), directed by Arie Posin, and Francis Ford Coppolas new movie
Youth without Youth (2007) which is based on a mysticism-driven novel
by Mircea Eliade.
At the end of The Chumscrubber, a point of view transcending the
dream-like reality of suburban America is achieved in symbolic drawings
of a blue dolphin. The Mayor Michael Ebbs at some point of the story
discovers his artistic energies which identify him with the theist creator
of the suburban universe. He feels a sudden urge to ll up walls with
pictures of blue dolphins, which literally represent the structure of the
city (whose mayor he is) as we can see in the nal shot of the movie
from a Gods eye point of view. We can interpret this as the expression of
a longing for a mystical unity, for the hidden harmony of all nite things
(blue is always a symbol for transcendence, like the blue ower of
romanticism; Picassos blue period; Blue Velvet; Wallace Stevens The Man
with the Blue Guitar, etc.). This idea is also conveyed in Charlie Kaufmans
Synecdoche, New York (2008). Here, the mystical unity turns out to be a
synecdoche, an innite interlacing of imaginary strata of the protago-
nists fragmentary life. Despite the turbulent rupture we experience in
our personal life and despite the utter contingency of the roles we play,
there ultimately is a background in front of which we enact our lives.
Contemporary cinema returns to metaphysical harmony after post-
modern turmoil. Yet, we must not forget that this new harmony may
very well be the reection of capitalisms monistic self-assertion after

28
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

1989, i.e. after postmodernisms fragmentary, relativistic vision of the


world. The harmony is therefore necessarily fractured, torn apart and
instilled with irony like in David O. Russells I Heart Huckabees (2004), in
which two forces compete for the heros salvation from capitalisms
bellum omnium contra omnes: metaphysical harmony with the universe
(symbolized by the Buddhist practices of Bernard and Vivian) and
French existentialism (represented by Caterine Vauban) in the sense of
an aggressive, hedonistic attitude which afrms nitude beyond the
need for a metaphysical refuge. The movie somehow points out the fact
that it is not self-sufcient, that it is conditioned by the differentiality
suppressed by its ultimately violent harmony.
In Coppolas Youth without Youth the distinction between dream and
reality is transgressed. The protagonist, a seventy-year-old Rumanian
orientalist, is rejuvenated after being struck by a lightning. As his new,
younger self, he rejoins his lost and strangely reborn ance who had
left him because he devoted his whole life to discovering the origin(s) of
language. His resurrected ance happens to be the reincarnation of an
ancient Indian, native Sanskrit female philosopher whose soul mysteri-
ously regresses back to the origin of language such that the professor
gains access to prehistoric material through the soul of his beloved.
It seems fairly obvious that the return of the ance and the (sexual)
rejuvenation of the Rumanian professor just take place in his fantasy
while he is dying in the hospital. Everything which happens after the
lightning seems to be purely phantasmagoric. At the end of his journey
through time and space, the protagonist returns to Rumania and tells
Shuang-Tses philosophical allegory of the king and the buttery in
which a king is not sure whether he is a buttery dreaming he is a king
or the other way around.
Without going into the details of interpretation of the abovementioned
movies, at least one thing seems clear: Descartes dream problematic is
still haunting us, however naturalistic we wish to be . . . One reason for
this is that the naturalistic, scientic world-view paradoxically engenders
its own impossibility. It leads into epistemological skepticism by relying
on scientic procedures in order to get a grasp on the whole. By asserting
that everything which is the case is natural (in the sense of being the case
in the universe described by the best scientic theory), it denes thought
on the basis of an inductive construction of reality. If there is no whole-
sale truth but only scientic results, this is itself a whole-sale truth,

29
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

a very bold and uncritical metaphysical assertion on top of that. Be this


as it may, one should also note that this eternal recurrence of the
Cartesian dream problematic in popular culture, art, and epistemology
seems to be missing an important philosophical point, which became
predominant in modern philosophy and was explicitly accounted for in
Kant and his idealist successors, a point we ought to recollect, namely
the problem of the internal world ensuing from the problem of the external
world.
In the course of modern philosophy from Descartes through empiri-
cism to Kant, the concept of substance preceding or transcending the
subjects grasp got lost. At some point, in particular in Hume, the self
threatened to dissolve into a bundle of representations because it also
lost its substantial status as a unitary soul. The idea behind this develop-
ment is simple, yet it is missed by most of the contemporary debate about
dream and reality and accordingly about the problem of the external
world: if the self represents itself, it ipso facto becomes a dream-like
experience, i.e. an appearance of itself. The problem is therefore not so
much that the phenomenal world might be an illusion, a dream-like
construction of an omnipotent solipsistic ego. Whatever you think about
transcendental solitude, at least it promises a primordial satisfaction of
narcissisms imaginary position. The real problem of the external world
lies in the fact that it entails an even more radical problem, namely the
problem of the internal world only implicitly at work in empiricism and
nally made explicit by Kant and his successors.
The problem of the external world arises out of a certain interpretation
of our intentional grasp of the world. If our relation to determinate
objects in the world, i.e. our relation to substances, is conceptually medi-
ated and, therefore, presupposes the possibility of getting it right or
wrong, then we cannot rule out for any supposed representation of
a substance that we are misled by its appearances. If we can only grasp
a substance through its modes then we can never guarantee that the
collection of ideas which we believe to inhere in a certain substance
actually belong together. Now, if we relate to ourselves and our position
within the meshwork of potentially true beliefs, i.e. if we have beliefs
about ourselves, we eo ipso assume a position towards ourselves in which
we might get it wrong.
The self becomes an object among others as soon as it is drawn within
the sphere of representation. Kant developed this problem in his

30
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

First Critique and his argument is as plain as it is striking. If the self was
a substance, our cognitive access to it would have to be the grasp of a
substance. Yet, our cognitive access to any substance is fallible insofar as
it has to represent the substance in question. Even if we represent our-
selves, the represented self is not identical with the representing self
given that the subject of experiencing is never identical with any possible
object of experience. Whatever the object of our scrutiny may be, it has
to become an object among others whereby it is determined as such in a
wider context. Intentional correlates, i.e. objects of experience, generally
are determined in the wider framework of a world-view, a meshwork of
mutually inclusive or exclusive conceptual mediations.

[T]he intentionality, the objective purport, of perceptual experience in


general whether potentially knowledge yielding or not depends
[. . .] on having the world in view, in a sense that goes beyond glimpses
of the here and now. It would not be intelligible that the relevant
episodes present themselves as glimpses of the here and now apart
from their being related to a wider world view.39
According to Kant, the very idea of the world requires that the world be
completely determined, i.e. made up of things the properties of which
can be expressed as predicates in judgments. The activity of judging,
however, cannot be grasped by a determinate predicate because it gener-
ates judgments, i.e. predicate-functions in the rst place. The generating
activity of coordinating elements in judgments is not itself an element of
judgment, or to use Lacanian terms the subject of enunciation is
never identical with the subject of the enunciated. In fact, the former is
not even a part of the world because the world is only the result of the
synthesizing activity of judging. The determinacy of the world hinges
thus on the synthesizing activity of the logical I which can never become
part of the world. The constituting principle of experience cannot itself
be experienced.
Emphasizing this insight, Kant reduces the former Cartesian self to the
state of a factor X of determination, to an indeterminate condition of possibi-
lity of determinacy. In the strict sense, it is not even determined as an ego
but only as this I or He or It (the thing) which thinks.40 The constituting
activity of experience is as a result put out of reach. We have no grasp of
that which constitutes our world even though it is we who perform said
constitution. The uncanny stranger begins to pervade the sphere of the

31
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

subject, threatening its identity from within. Kant is thus one of the
rst to become aware of the intimidating possibility of total semantic
schizophrenia inherent in the anonymous transcendental subjectivity as
such. The subject is itself the space in which something might appear,
Heideggers open space (offene Stelle). For this reason, it cannot itself
appear on the stage of its world-picture. The self therefore becomes an
appearance. The subject assumes the paradoxical position of the proper
void, the zero which becomes the One once it enters the sphere of
representation without ever being able to ll out its internal gap between
its determination (One) and its void (the zero).
For Kant the uncanny structure of the selfs elusiveness, i.e. the
subjects nothingness, ultimately opens a space for consolation and hope:
if, in principle, we cannot gure out who or what we really are (our
substance), we are at least entitled to behave as if we dwelled in an intel-
ligible realm of pure freedom ruled by God . . . Of course, nobody really
took this option seriously in a literal sense. If Kant were indeed right
with his epistemological claim of nitude, i.e. if we could not know any-
thing about the in-itself, then the in-itself might have any or no struc-
ture whatsoever. The truth about the in-itself could appear as far-fetched
as any possible science-ction scenario or literary experiment enacts it.
Under strictly Kantian premises there is no suitable reason for transcen-
dental optimism; and certainly not the moral one Kant has in mind. In a
post-Schopenhauer-Nietzsche-Marx-Kierkegaard-Freud world we would
be quite nave to assume that the subject really might be a disembodied
pure spirit striving for moral perfection in the face of the protestant God
of conscience and duty.
Be this as it may, Kant is nevertheless right that the blind spot of reec-
tion, the indenite space of our ignorance, cannot be made transparent
in reection. This is why it refers us to the dimension of the ethical in a
precise sense: the ethical indeed designates the space we inhabit qua
decision-processing agents, a blank space which cannot have any positive
substance apart from the ethical substance we bestow on it. It is precisely
this aspect that corresponds to Hegels notion of the ethical substance in
the Phenomenology of Spirit.
In the wake of later nineteenth-century philosophy, subjectivity was
taught the important lesson that ignorance is not necessarily iterative,
i.e. that we are not ignorant about our ignorance. The eld of ignorance
is rather occupied by the coordinates of our desire: we desire precisely

32
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

that which we do not know. Ignorance and desire are two faces of the
same coin. As iek points out,

ignorance is not a sufcient reason for forgiveness since it conveys a


hidden dimension of enjoyment. Where one doesnt (want to) know, in
the blanks of ones symbolic universe, one enjoys, and there is no
Father to forgive, since these blanks escape the authority of the
Name-of-the-Father.41

This idea also lies at the bottom of Schellings most original thesis
according to which Will is primal Being (Wollen ist Urseyn).42 The point
is that the Kantian intelligible world does not guarantee the stability of
the phenomenal world. On the contrary, in its elusiveness it rather desta-
bilizes the allegedly law-like totality of appearance, the symbolic order.
Any proper insight into the paradoxical nitude of knowledge entails
that the very assumption of an elusive in-itself is an expression of the
libidinal instability of the coordinates of the phenomenal world. This is a
lesson to be learned from Schelling as much as from David Lynch.43 This
willingness to explore and even to embrace the uncanniness of existence
grounded in its libidinal instability is certainly what makes Schelling
extraordinarily contemporary.
Yet not only Schelling, but also already Fichte clear-sightedly diag-
nosed the problem of the internal world in The Vocation of Man and freed
it from Kants enlightenment optimism. If the representing sphere, the
self or ego, were indeed a substance, i.e. some given stable item open to
become the object of a theory, it would paradoxically turn out to be com-
pletely elusive. Whenever we were to believe to have it in view, it would
already have withdrawn. This problem famously referred to as Fichtes
original insight by Dieter Henrich entails, as I have been saying, that
modern epistemology is not so much characterized by the problem of the
external world, as many believe, but rather by the problem of the internal
world.44 Given that the representing sphere, the subject, self or ego, qua
substance is itself part of the world (the world being made up of thinking
and extended substance), reality turns out to be a dream of a dream. As
Fichte writes,

all reality is transformed into a fabulous dream, without there being


any life the dream is about, without there being a mind which dreams;
a dream which hangs together in a dream of itself.45

33
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

The represented representing sphere, i.e. the subject qua substance, is itself
subject to the skeptical hypotheses developed in modern epistemology.
It is epistemologically no better off than any other entity to be encoun-
tered in the world. That which seemed to be relieved from paradox, i.e.
the unequivocal unitary thinking substance, proves to be as much of an
illusion as the so-called external world. This also motivates Pyotr Voyds
passionate question: is it my inamed consciousness that creates the
nightmare, or is my consciousness itself a creation of the nightmare?46
More generally, there is a serious philosophical issue as to how to
distribute essence and illusion, the essential and the inessential, as Hegel
puts it. The problem with the essential and the inessential is that the
essential is determined over against the inessential without reecting the
constituting act separating the essential from the inessential. The essen-
tial simply seems to be essential. The whole point is that the essence or,
otherwise put, reality, cannot be opposed to appearance or illusion.
Illusion itself occurs within reality because reality only consists in its
being determined over against illusion. Reality is not out there, but the
result of an operation which distinguishes illusion and reality. Without
this distinction, the term reality does not make sense.
We only understand that there is truth and reality because we are
constantly confronted with dissent: given that we do not agree on all
matters, we know that there are subject matters (truths) to agree upon.
However, that truth only becomes salient in discourse does not mean
that the referents of true statements are mere by-products of discourse.
It only means that we do not have any immediate access to any particu-
lar way the world is apart from our cognitive access to it. Now, our cogni-
tive access to the world only functions if we presuppose a certain set of
access conditions suitable for the object domain over which we quantify
in order to ascribe the correct predicates to that which appears within
the domain we are interested in. As any profound encounter with skep-
tical paradoxes teaches us, there is no way to guarantee the truth-
conditions of a certain discourse about a determinate object domain (that
is: objectivity) and the truths about objects within that domain at the
same time. The truth-conditions we draw on exist on a different logical
layer than the objects the truth about which we want to discover. This
amounts to a weak distinction between the transcendental and the empiri-
cal: the very framework (the discourse) constituting determinacy for an
object domain by dening what it is to belong to the object domain,

34
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

i.e. the domains count-as-one (Badiou), is not itself an object within


the domain. There is nothing wrong with calling the objects empirical
and the domain transcendental as long as we do not presuppose that
we can ever grasp an object from nowhere. There is no view from
nowhere because it would not be a view. Determinacy presupposes
negation and the very negativity constitutive of ontological as much as
epistemological determinacy entails the nitude of discourse.47
Appearance or illusion and reality both emerge within reality to the
effect that we have to come to terms with the idea defended by Fichte,
Schelling, and Hegel that reality is nothing but the process of its own
reduplication. Reality or essence is not one relatum in a relation, say the
totality of mind-independent objects extended in space and time, but
that which splits itself up in appearance and reality. That which splits
itself up in such a way is what Hegel addresses under the heading of
essence. Reality essentially splits itself up, thereby producing represen-
tations of itself.
If we want to safeguard the absolute from being drawn into the sphere
of relativity, we have to install it at the heart of relativity. Given that we
must not oppose it to the relative (for this would establish a relation
between the relative and the absolute), we must nd a way for the
absolute to manifest itself within the relative without thereby becoming
relative. One way to achieve this is ontological monism according to
which representation (the internal world) is itself part of the (external)
world. We do not look at the world from outside but inhabit it from
within. This entails that the world simply cannot be reduced to being the
natural realm of necessity but has to be compatible with the outburst of
various elds of sense within itself. The world creates images of itself in
the activity of our creation of images of the world. Our world pictures are
not cheap copies of what there really is because they are an essential
aspect of what there really is.
iek succinctly renders the step from Kant to German Idealism in the
following way: if the gap which separates the pure multiplicity of the
Real from the appearing of a world whose co-ordinates are given in a
set of categories which predetermine its horizon is the very gap which, in
Kant, separates the Thing-in-itself from our phenomenal reality that is,
from the way things appear to us as objects of our experience, then the
question becomes: how does the gap between the pure multiplicity of
being and its appearance in the multitude of worlds arise? How does being

35
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

appear to itself?48 Kant starts off from the assumption that the in-itself
cannot be known because our access to it is mediated by a complex
conceptual apparatus. In simple structuralist parlance Kant claims that
we do not have any immediate access to the signied (and a fortiori to the
real thing) without always already being caught up in the potentially
misleading innite cobweb of signiers. The signifying chain and the
rules whereby it is established and maintained simply do not allow for
any act of happy-face transcendence.
The problem with this story (obviously leading from Kant to postmod-
ernism in all its varieties) is that it takes as given a blind spot of reection
Hegel calls in question: if we cannot transcend the phenomenal world ex
hypothesi then what makes us believe that there is a noumenal world, an
it-itself, after all? Is the in-itself not ultimately reduced to a friction-
guaranteeing ersatz-substance? If being is prior to judgment then we can-
not assert anything determinate about it, not even that we cannot assert
anything determinate about it! In other words, if the in-itself were inac-
cessible then it would not even be inaccessible. This is why one needs
non-propositional resources if one still wants to safeguard transcendence
from Hegels dialectical criticism of reection.
The chapter on illusion/appearance (Schein) in the Science of Logic
begins with the path-breaking assertion that Being is illusory being
(das Sein ist Schein).49 Illusory being or appearance is all that still remains
from the sphere of being (der ganze Rest, der noch von der Sphre des Seins
briggeblieben ist).50 Illusion appears to be a pure void, the negative
posited as negative,51 whereby it is distinguished from the in-itself. As
Hegel explicitly states, this structure can be found in ancient skepticisms
concept of the phenomena as much as in Kants concept of the phenom-
enal world.52 Even though Hegels claim that the phenomenon of skepti-
cism and the phenomenal world in Kant share the same structure is
highly disputable, his key point is clear: if we distinguish between the
things as they are in themselves (the essence: reality) and the things we
apprehend according to the forms of our understanding (appearances),
what guarantees that the in-itself is not itself part of the appearances?
How can we be so sure that the in-itself is not some higher-order illusion,
a mere simulacrum? What if the system of appearances just produces
certain interferences which look like acts of real transcendence?
A famous philosophical example at hand is the so-called Trendelen-
burg gap in Kants Transcendental Aesthetics.53 Trendelenburg correctly

36
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

diagnosed the following mistake in Kants argumentation. If space and


time are pure forms of intuition, they are indispensable forms for our
apprehension of things. However, if we apprehend things in a certain
form (or under a certain description), this does not entitle us to the claim
that the things themselves exhibit this very form. Wearing my blue
sunglasses and, therefore, seeing the Empire State Building in a blue
manner does not make it blue. Yet, if I constantly wore blue sunglasses,
I might encounter a lot of objects which actually were blue whereas
others might, in reality, be red or white without me ever being in a posi-
tion to draw a distinction between blue and red objects on the basis of
sense-perception alone. If Kant is right, then we cannot strip our space
and time glasses off in order to see the things as they are in themselves.54
And yet, he explicitly asserts that the things in themselves are not in
space and time which is an illegitimate act of transcendence.

Space does not represent any property of things in themselves, nor


does it represent them in their relation to one another. That is to say,
space does not represent any determination that attaches to the objects
themselves, and which remains even when abstraction has been made
of all the subjective conditions of intuition. [. . .] It is, therefore, solely
from the human standpoint that we can speak of space, of extended
things, etc. If we depart from the subjective condition under which
alone we can have outer intuition, namely, liability to be affected by
objects, the representation of space stands for nothing whatsoever.55
Here Kant simply claims too much by making a metaphysical assertion
about the things in themselves. He is tricked by appearances into the
attempt to transcend them. In fact, any such attempt at transcendence is
misleading in precisely this way. If our knowledge is restricted to our
epistemic, social, or whatever conditioning, then there is no straightfor-
ward way of embracing this nitude given that any specic assertion
about nitude amounts to an illegitimate act of transcendence. We can-
not draw the boundaries of our nitude without thereby either undoing
them or drawing a ctional boundary within our nitude between our
nitude and some innite item.
In this sense, as theorists of nitude we are in no better epistemologi-
cal position than a thermometer. Thermometers can tell the difference
between 80 Fahrenheit and 95 Fahrenheit. However, they do not in
themselves register the difference between telling the difference between

37
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

temperatures and telling the difference between Picasso and Botticelli or


between 1 AM and 2 PM. Thermometers carve up reality in a certain
way without being in any position to access their own conditioning as
thermometers. If the subject consisted of a determinate set of access
conditions opening up a world of things to it, then it could not access
these access conditions without further ado. This is why Kant introduces
the innite intuitus originarius in order to get a grip on our nitude via a
mythological story of nitudes other.56 However, all the stories he goes
on to tell about the realm of freedoms internal structure, etc. are results
of illegitimate acts of transcendence whereby our nitude is determined
in a certain way. Kants standpoint is therefore and despite himself
super-human. His analysis of our access conditions simply generates
a non-human framework, an intelligible realm, laid out in his texts. His
own position of enunciation is strangely exempted from the enunciated posi-
tion whereby he creates a split between the noumenal and the phenom-
enal that he then ascribes to the human realm as such. The way he
accesses this split, his way of uncovering it, necessarily presents it under
a certain description ipso facto distorting it.
Hegel generally concludes that any theoretical setting in which some
in-itself is distinguished from its appearance, from its for-us, is a case of
the structure he labels essence and he adds the further reection that
essence is itself nothing but the gap within which the distinction between
appearance and reality occurs. His crucial point is that the distinction
between appearance and reality, between the inessential and the essen-
tial, is necessarily reected into itself: the inessential really occupies
the position of the essential precisely because it places the essential at
our disposal. The inessential mediates the essential in such a way that
the essential becomes the inessential. The essential is only placed at our
disposal by error and dissent which means that it is contingent on the
inessential which thereby assumes primacy over the essential.
A similar insight is conveyed by Nietzsches and Heideggers diagnosis
of Platonism as the ultimate origin of European nihilism. Platonisms
degradation of the sensible realm (the inessential) in favor of its underly-
ing organizational principles (the essential) masks the very reective
operation by which the underlying organizational principles are consti-
tuted. As a matter of fact, they are only available to epistm in the latters
desire for transcendence. Platonism is inspired by an attempt at tran-
scendence without reecting on the nitude of this intention.

38
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

Transcendence is not a matter of fact but always depends on the act


and direction of transcending. The way transcendence is achieved is pre-
scribed by the elements structure of appearance. Appearance seems to
be organized in such a manner that it betrays some underlying, elemen-
tary reality. The elements which seem to reveal a hidden essence retro-
actively generate the hidden essence. The degradation of the sensible
realm (i.e. nihilism) thus amounts to a reversal of itself: it pretends to
cling to the essence of things instead of leading a life of appearances and
yet it essentially leads a life of appearances based on a denial, namely on
the denial of appearances. It therefore annihilates itself and becomes an
aggressive force of civilization in the name of the true nature of things.
Hegel makes this dialectic explicit by claiming that appearance itself
does indeed have being or reality, namely in the very other it posits as its
underlying hidden essence.

Illusory being is the negative that has a being, but in an other, in its
negation, it is a non-self-subsistent being which is in its own self-
sublated and null. As such, it is the negative returned into itself, non-
self-subsistent being as in its own self not self-subsistent. This self-relation
of the negative or of non-self-subsistent being is its immediacy; it is an
other than the negative itself; it is its determinateness over against itself;
or it is the negation directed against the negative. But negation directed
against the negative is purely self-related negativity, the absolute sub-
lating of the determinateness itself.57
Appearance is the non-self-subsistent being in itself, or otherwise put:
appearance is the essence of self-relating negativity, the remainder of
which is Being. Being thus is nothing but the remainder of appearance,
its very being there. In Hegels vocabulary Being designates the para-
doxical subsistence of the non-self-subsistent structure of appearance.
Being is therefore not a hidden essence, reality as it is in itself or any-
thing like that, but the contingent being there of appearance.
The move Hegel prescribes for reection therefore consists in the
negation of negation. The rst negation is the positing of the essence
over against the mere appearances, the phenomenal world. The One is
opposed to the multiplicity of being, the innocent origin to the sinful,
fallen world, etc. However, this negation of the appearances is the very
kernel of appearance. The immediacy of appearances, the alleged fact
that they are deceitful, is already a redoubling of appearances. They

39
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

thereby exhibit the structure of reection, i.e. the movement of nothing


to nothing, and so back to itself, a structure Hegel designates as
becoming in essence:

Consequently, becoming is essence, its reective movement, is the


movement of nothing to nothing, and so back to itself. The transition, or
becoming, sublates itself in its passage; the other that in this transition
comes to be, is not the non-being of a being, but the nothingness of a
nothing, and this, to be the negation of a nothing, constitutes being.
Being only is as the movement of nothing to nothing, and as such it is
essence; and the latter does not have this movement within it, but is this
movement as a being that is itself absolutely illusory, pure negativity,
outside of which there is nothing for it to negate but which negates
only its own negative, which latter is only in this negating.58
In other words, reection is absolute negativity and, therefore, freedom.59
It is the activity of establishing autonomy by dismantling the beyond, i.e.
the very movement of Hegelian philosophy. Hence Henrich is right in
claiming that the Logic of Essence denes the dialectical operations charac-
teristic of the Hegelian enterprise as such.60 Being is no longer opposed to
becoming as it is in the Platonic tradition: on the contrary, it is explicitly
identied with the becoming of essence (and ultimately with the univer-
sality of the Notion).61
One of Hegels most brilliant insights is that being is absolute illusion.
The idea behind this is an application of the Hegelian principle of
inversion by self-reference: philosophical dichotomies like identity and
difference, universal and particular, appearance and reality, law and
crime are applied to themselves in such a manner that the implicit hier-
archy between the terms is inverted, the result of which is contradic-
tion in Hegels sense. Contradiction arises once we realize that all
reective determinations (Reexionsbestimmungen) replicate the matrix
of reections negation of negation. We come to understand that in its
self-subsistence [the self-subsistent determination of reection] excludes
from itself its own self-subsistence: The self-subsistent determination of
reection that contains the opposite determination, and is self-subsistent
in virtue of the inclusion, at the same time also excludes it; in its self-
subsistence, therefore, it excludes from itself its own self-subsistence.62
Reection-in-itself and reection-into-another coincide and by this
means reveal their common ground, what Hegel captures with his

40
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

wordplay on zu-Grunde-gehen, i.e. return to the ground by destruc-


tion. The rm identity of the terms related in reection reveals their
ground, namely the absolute, self-relating negativity of reection. The
essence as ground turns out to be a positedness, something that has become
(ein Gesetztsein, ein Gewordenes).63
If transcendence is to be achieved against Hegels strictly speaking
atheistic closure of immanence upon itself, one has indeed to look for
traces of something which escapes reection. As we will see later, Hegels
own form of expression falls short of the content it attempts to express.
Hegel does not achieve any absolute closure of form. There is no logical
absolute form, as Hegel believes, precisely because reection in its
all-embracing claim to positivity cannot sufciently reect its being
conditioned by a process which is not always already reexive.
The reection of being and the being of reection do not coincide
because there is no self-sufcient medium of expression, no possible
identity of the position of enunciation (Fregean sense) and of the Thing
or states of affairs (Fregean reference). We can only attain the Thing in
its conceptual disguises, i.e. under a certain description, without ever
making sure once and for all that the Thing is there. For even the desig-
nator Thing is part of the eld of sense: language is its own minimal
difference.
Hegels master-thought is conveyed by his logic of reection. Whatever
we refer to as the One that true referent or meaning of our expressions
that is supposedly distorted by the propositional structure of judgment
is in point of fact only a side-effect of the movement of absolute negativ-
ity. There is no originary abiding One. Substance becomes subject
designates Hegels epoch-shifting move beyond transcendent metaphys-
ics: the subjects substance is only retroactively posited by the process of
the subjects self-constitution. This process necessarily misres if we con-
ceive of it in terms of some underlying metaphysical reality manifesting
itself. The history of philosophy text-book version of Hegel according to
which absolute spirit is some God-like super-mind steering the course of
events until Hegel emerges and assumes the role of the mouthpiece of
the super-mind thereby even overcoming Jesus Christs confused expres-
sion of the absolute spirit etc., ignores Hegels concept of manifestation.
Hegels point indeed is that the determination of spirit is manifestation
(die Bestimmtheit des Geistes ist die Manifestation).64 It is crucial to remark
that manifestation here does not refer to some representational

41
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

structure, i.e. to a manifestation of something which is ontologically


prior to its manifestation. As Hegel writes, spirit does not reveal some
thing, but its very mode and meaning is this revelation (nicht Etwas [. . .],
sondern seine Bestimmtheit und Inhalt ist dieses Offenbaren selbst).65 Hegel
calls this structure of revealing (which reveals nothing but the fact that
there is nothing besides, prior to, or beyond this revealing) revealing in
the notion (Offenbaren im Begriffe) and creating (Erschaffen) respec-
tively.66 Subjectivity is, thus, a radical instance of ontological genesis: it
consists in its positing itself, in generating a eld of sense, and in this
sense a world to be inhabited.67 This process has no external foothold in
a transcendent realm but rests solely on and in itself.
In this vein, Hegel radicalizes Kantian autonomy on the conceptual
level. We are not only autonomous beings whose being bound by rules
consists in our acceptance of those rules as guiding. The real abyss of our
freedom is reection. Whatever we encounter in the world is framed by a wider
context which is not itself encountered in the world. However, the wider
context denes the rules of entry into our world. The elements to be
accounted for in truth-apt cognition and discourse are determined by the
wider context of reection which is usually not reected in those
elements. This is why they appear as not posited, as simply being out
there. Hegel reects on the conditioning of experience and concludes
that it precludes transcendence even in its mitigated Kantian sense of the
inaccessible thing in itself, the unknown something.

In the sphere of being, there arises over against being as an immediacy,


non-being, which is likewise an immediacy, and their truth is becoming.
In the sphere of essence, we have rst essence opposed to the unessen-
tial, then essence opposed to illusory being, that is, to the unessential
and to illusory being as the remainder of being. But both essence and
illusory being, and also the difference of essence from them derive
solely from the fact that essence is at rst taken as an immediate, not as
it is in itself, namely, not as an immediacy that is as pure mediation or
absolute negativity. The rst immediacy is thus only the determinateness
of immediacy. The sublating of this determinateness of essence, there-
fore, consists simply and solely in showing that the unessential is only
illusory being and that the truth is rather that essence contains the
illusory being within itself in its innite immanent movement that
determines its immediacy as negativity and its negativity as immediacy,

42
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

and thus the reection of itself within itself. Essence in this its self-
movement is reection.68

In this passage Hegel draws a distinction between essences being something


determinate and the determinacy of essence. The idea behind this distinction
is that essence should not be referred to in the objective mode: it is not
something determinate or out there, as it were. Essence does not exist as
an entity among others which is disclosed to reection. Such a view of
essence (of the in-itself) would entail a fallback to the sphere of being.
The in-itself does not exist independent of our activity of conceptualizing
it. It is a pure ens rationale, the result of our penetrating the veil of
appearances. In other words, essence comes close to being (Seyn) in the
peculiar Heideggerian sense. It is the very ontological difference between
essence and appearance which may be interpreted in different ways
throughout the history of being (Seyn) or reection. In this context, it is,
of course, absolutely crucial to insist that Heidegger is not talking about
some Being independent of our access to it (which would be metaphys-
ics). The history of Being is not the history of mistaken identications of
the One beyond discourse. Heideggerian Being is therefore not pre-, but
post-Hegelian. Heidegger is far from falling back behind Hegelian reec-
tion. He rather tries to radicalize it so as to eradicate any rm belief into
Being as a transcendent agency revealing itself in history. Despite the
theological ring of Heideggers formulations, he protests against theology
in a particularly modern gesture of ghting ontotheology, a gesture
Gadamer calls his raising ones hands against God (Handaufheben gegen
Gott).69 In this vein, Heidegger famously asserts that theology is a positive
science and as such, therefore, is absolutely different from philosophy.70 In
particular, he explicitly ghts any identication of his project with
Christian theology, an opposition he never gave up. Even in the Contribu-
tions resurrection of the last God he unambiguously declares that what
he refers to as God is totally other over against gods who have been,
especially over against the Christian God.71
Being is the name for the fact that the movement of reection generates
determinacy. On the level of reection we understand that we generate
the discursive frameworks which open up a certain domain of determi-
nate objects for and of a discourse. Discourses generate a set of norms-
in-context which lay out input- and output-rules.72 They dene the
framework of a discourse and thereby create a domain of objects.

43
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

This operation can be reconstructed in simple system-theoretic terms.


Whenever we refer to some object, we draw a distinction between the
object, the domain to which it belongs (which determines it as such-
and-such a type of object), and a set of other domains over against which
the object domain we picked out is determined. Determinacy presupposes
negation. However, the very activity of making determinacy work, i.e. the
activity of selecting, cannot itself be something determinate. As Castoria-
dis puts it, the activity of formalization is itself not formalizable.73
If determinacy is the result of some ontological decision as to how to pick
out objects, then this decision cannot itself be determinate. Ontological
genesis therefore is prior to determinacy.
The ultimate framework within which the event of determinacy takes
place can be called absolute negativity, because it is the domain of all
domains within which determinacy occurs as the result of some onto-
logical decision or other. Yet, this domain cannot itself be determined.
It is the very freedom of the One as operation which cannot be counted
as one. As soon as a distinction is drawn, reection generates a blind spot
so that there necessarily is something which cannot be accounted for in
reection. However, this something does not exist. It is no mysterious
item or super-item like in classical ontotheology. Hegel rightly insists that
the blind spot of reection is part and parcel of reection as such. That
which cannot be accounted for in reection is the Notion itself which for
Hegel is the activity of putting logical space together. The deciency of
traditional formal logic (and contemporary logic for that matter) consists
in its incapability to account for the genesis of the framework it calls
upon within the framework. The hardness of the logical must seems
to foreclose any pre-logical energy. If we ascribe necessity to some truth
or other within the domain of propositions, we forget that the constitu-
tion of the domain is itself contingent. Any framework relative to which
necessity can be claimed presupposes the discipline of rules and there-
fore of rule-following practices in order to make sense for nite creatures
like us. Therefore, anything to which we concede necessity is higher-
order contingent, because the framework to which it owes its determi-
nacy cannot itself be necessary. To put it differently: at some point or
other we encounter a brute decision the decision constitutive of ratio-
nality which itself is neither rational nor reasonable. This groundless-
ness adds up to an experience of contingency which cannot itself be
described as necessary without thereby creating another contingent

44
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

framework. Contingency is thus a condition of possibility of necessity.


The ultimate contingency of world-constitution is pre-logical in view of
the fact that the domain of logic or logical space is only one domain
among others.74
In this sense, the traditional epistemology of logical space (that is, the
discipline of logic) simply presupposes that the order of logical concepts
can be represented in logical thought. Logical forms seem to ground
rationality. Hegel objects against formal logic that its logical space presup-
poses conditions exceeding its resources of expression. In this objection,
however, Hegel is not admitting a pre-logical domain. That is, for Hegel
what is pre-logical with regard to formal logic is logical with regard to his
all-encompassing form of reection which he identies with Logos.
Hegels introduction of movement (genesis) into the realm of logic is
meant to achieve a logical account of that which is pre-logical in order
to make sure that even the allegedly pre-logical is governed by Logos.
The motor of this theory of Logos is the Notion which is but the name for
the activity of putting the system of categories together and thinking
them through. This way, Hegel ultimately fails because he is not in pos-
session of pre-logical tools. He thereby contradicts his own methodologi-
cal requirement that form and content must become identical in logical
thought. Given that there can be no fully logical expression of that which
antecedes the expressive resources of logic, we need to nd a form corre-
sponding to the pre-logical content constitutive of the domain of Logos.

The pure Notion is the absolutely innite, unconditioned and free. It is


here, at the outset of the discussion which has the Notion for its con-
tent, that we must look back once more at its genesis. Essence is the out-
come of being, and the Notion the outcome of essence, therefore also of
being. But this becoming has the signicance of a self-repulsion, so that
it is rather the outcome which is the unconditioned and original. Being, in
its transition into essence, has become an illusory being or a positedness,
and becoming or transition into an other has become a positing; and
conversely, the positing or reection of essence has sublated itself and
has restored itself as a being that is not posited, that is original. The
Notion is the interfusion of these moments, namely, qualitative and
original being is such only as a positing, only as a return-into-self, and
this pure reection-into-self is a sheer becoming-other or determinateness
which, consequently, is no less innite, self-relating determinateness.

45
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Thus the Notion is, in the rst instance, the absolute self-identity that
is such only as the negation of negation or as the innite unity of the
negativity with itself. This pure relation of the Notion to itself, which is
this relation by positing itself through negativity, is the universality of
the Notion.75

The absolute self-identity of the Notion does not imply that the Notion
exerts a metaphysical agency beyond the phenomenal world. The
Notions substance is its utter substancelessness. Hence, the Notion is
universal which basically means that there is nothing outside of logical
space. Yet, logical space itself is not a substance but a constant move-
ment, the famous Bacchanalian revel from the preface to the Phenome-
nology of Spirit.76 Even according to Hegel, the only guarantee of stability
is therefore the complete instability (substancelessness) of the domain of
all domains, the Notion which can thus be said to be universal. The
Notion consequently is Hegels preferred candidate for the domain of all
domains which commits him to a denial of a pre-logical space outside of
his reection.
Hegels assertion that being ultimately amounts to nothing other than
the universality of the Notion means that there cannot be anything
outside of logical space. Logical space does not exist; it is not an entity, but
a continuous manifestation of actuality. If we want to render this claim of
absolute immanence in a language different from Hegelese, we could say
that the appearance of something as existent outside of a theory-building
process or a discourse and ready to be represented by true statements
emerging within discourse is itself a discursive appearance. There is no
metaphysical hyper-theory; there is only a meta-theory which spells out
the conditions for there not being metaphysical hyper-theories of the
beyond. Accordingly, Hegels Science of Logic is not designed to form an
ultimate hyper-theory which transcends discursive nitude, but on the
contrary investigates into the nature of determinacy or nitude. To be
sure, Hegel says such things as the nite sublates itself by virtue of its
own nature, and passes over, of itself, into its opposite.77 But this does not
mean that the movement of sublation ever terminates in a nal statement of
sublation. The nite only transcends itself into another nite position.
Being, for Hegel, is wholly abstract, immediate relation to self, is nothing
else than the abstract moment of the Notion, which moment is abstract

46
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

universality.78 Among other things, Hegel seems to have Hlderlins


Judgment and Being in mind which can be read as an attempt to
overcome Kants restriction of thinking to judgment, i.e. his identica-
tion of objectively contentful thought with propositional thought
partially retracted in the Third Critique. Commenting on Kant and Fichte,
Hlderlin denes judgment as the original separation of object and
subject which are most deeply united in intellectual intuition, that
separation through which alone object and subject become possible, the
arche-separation.79 Indeed, Kantian epistemology can be read as an
attempt to display the realm of the arche-separation, the realm of discur-
sive nitude in terms of the subject-object dichotomy. This is why
Kantian semantics hinges on the concept of meaning qua relation to
the object (Beziehung aufs Objekt).80 The Kantian enterprise consists in
analyzing the conditions under which we are capable of referring to
objects which potentially differ from our actual representations of them.
In other words, Kant denes objectivity in terms of subjectivity: the
domain of objects accessible to our understanding (i.e. the world of
appearances) is dened in terms of our access conditions. That which
precedes the arche-separation and therefore the totality of our access
conditions to what is, cannot be grasped by us. Hlderlins concept of
being as opposed to judgment nevertheless hints at what is, at what ante-
cedes (but does not transcend!) the arche-separation.

Being expresses the connection between subject and object. Where


subject and object are united altogether and not only in part, that is,
united in such a manner that no separation can be performed without
violating the essence of what is to be separated, there and nowhere
else can be spoken of Being proper, as is the case with intellectual
intuition.81
Of course, Hlderlin instantly remarks that Being proper cannot be the
value of any logical variable, that it is not even identical with itself or,
more precisely, that it cannot be conceptualized as identity without
thereby subjecting it to the laws of propositional thought. Nevertheless,
he does not seem to be aware of the fact that the very separation between
being and judgment is a repetition of the arche-separation. Thereby,
Being itself loses its original status. In order to solve this problem
Hlderlin later created a new mythology in the expressive medium of

47
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

poetry which disrupts the establishment of purely object-directed, truth-


only cognition in order to show what cannot be said, i.e. in order to show
the essence of what is to be separated by means of a non-propositional
form of expression.
Still, Hegels objection holds against any attempt to transcend logical
space with the help of assertions (positive or negative). As long as we
refer to being as to some extraordinary domain or as to that which pre-
cedes judgment we simply reenact the universality of the Notion.

Being as the wholly abstract, immediate relation to self, is nothing else than
the abstract moment of the Notion, which moment is abstract univer-
sality. This universality also effects what one demands of being, namely,
to be outside the Notion; for though this universality is moment of the
Notion, it is equally the difference, or abstract judgment, of the Notion
in which it opposes itself to itself . . . A philosophizing that in its view
of being does not rise above sense, naturally stops short at merely
abstract thought, too, in its view of the Notion; such thought stands
opposed to being.82
The alleged arche-separation between subject and object really amounts
to the separation between being and judgment (thought) which only
occurs within thought. Thought alienates itself from itself, an act through
which it objecties its innermost conditions of possibility. For Hegel,
there is consequently no Being prior to reection. In his own way, he
follows Kants path at this point. In the Transcendental Dialectic of the
First Critique Kant introduced the concept of transcendental subrep-
tion83 in the context of his destruction of the ontological proof of the
existence of God. According to Kant, the ontological proof mistakes the
conditions of our access to any determinate world-order for this world-
order itself. He suggests that the ontological proof confuses the distribu-
tive unity of the empirical employment of the understanding with the
collective unity experience as a whole,84 an operation Kant calls tran-
scendental subreption.85 Transcendental subreption consists in the con-
fusion of judgment and being, in misrepresenting the conditions for
there being anything accessible to cognition (i.e. the conditions of deter-
minacy) by hypostatizing them into some determinate object (i.e. God or
any other determinate representation of the absolute). Transcendental
subreption amounts to a dialectic in Kants sense, that is to say to a logic

48
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

of illusion.86 In the context of his own logic of illusion, Hegel invali-


dates any attempt to ground reection on something prior or transcen-
dent to reection in a way comparable to Kants approach in the
Transcendental Dialectic.
However, Hegel radicalizes Kants seesaw notion of the thing in itself
which, on the ontic level, clearly denotes an entity (or set of entities)
capable of affecting sensibility which, on the ontological level, equally
clearly evaporates into a pure X, an explanatory factor only introduced to
ensure friction.87 Hegel (like Fichte) opts for the radical view according
to which there is no way to transcend the absolute immanence of reec-
tion. Though he agrees with Kant that illusion is unavoidable he radical-
izes this insight: if illusion is unavoidable, then there is no ultimate
criterion which distinguishes the phenomenal and illusory from the
noumenal and real for the precise reason that the criterion has to appear.
For Kant, transcendental subreption is hypostatization, it phenomenal-
izes the noumenal. Hegel, on the contrary, argues that the phenomenal-
ization of the noumenal is not only unavoidable, a aw of human nature,
but that it is rather constitutive of the noumenal (which only persists in
its phenomenalization as the whole Phenomenology of Spirit argues).
As a matter of fact, this is meaning of the term phenomenology in
Fichtes Science of Knowing 1804, a revolutionary set of lectures in which
he rst introduced the notion of absolute knowing and tied it to the
impossibility of achieving transcendence. The later Fichtes name for the
sphere of absolute immanence is being which, therefore, does not
entail any break with transcendental philosophy but its outmost realiza-
tion: being is only accessible in judgments which entails that we cannot
even assume that there might be something which precedes judgment.
For how are we to make sure that there really is being prior to judg-
ment, some original unity, without thereby always already dragging it
into the sphere of judgment? There seems, hence, no straightforward
way to assert the difference of being from judgment without
ipso facto canceling the very distinction in question. In other words, if
we want to make sense of an outside of reection we need to nd
a different mode of expression than assertion. One way to motivate the
move from the propositional to the non-propositional is to argue that
the propositional (qua open region) is always already opened by the
non-propositional.

49
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

2. THE UNPRETHINKABLE BEING OF MYTHOLOGY


SCHELLING ON THE LIMITS OF REFLECTION

The logical space of reection is part of a wider domain which is ulti-


mately only accessible in the mode of mythopoiesis. In this mode, reec-
tion is capable of confronting its nitude and of having an experience of
being which is not yet sutured to the expressive restrictions of logical
reection. I am aware that the recourse to the concept of myth runs
counter to contemporary philosophys prevailing ideology, i.e. scientism.
The expressive dimension of the natural sciences (however mathematiz-
able they turn out to be) is restricted to one historical register among
others. We have to be way more serious about incompleteness than sci-
entism suggests: there is no complete theory of the universe precisely
because there is no such thing as the universe accessible to our description.
Our cognition is necessarily restricted to one or other cosmological model.
A simple example from the philosophy of collecting might illustrate
this.88 Lets say you perceive three elements x1, x2, and x3 in a specic
region (for example three cubes with different colors: a blue, a red, and
a white cube). Now you ask yourself how many objects there are in the
region. The easy answer would, of course, be three. This way, you build
the set A: {x1, x2, x3}. Yet, we clearly know that there are objects com-
posed of other objects (and we might suspect there may very well be
only composite objects). The three cubes might be one object. Also, any
two cubes might be one object. It might look reasonable for someone to
connect the red and the blue cube and to oppose them to the white cube.
Someone else could also divide the objects into geometrical parts of a
particular size and count those. Lets call any arrangement of objects in
the region which we rst considered as a collection of three cubes a uni-
verse: we can then generalize and assert that the various schemes of
counting the objects in a certain region are cosmological models. On
the basis of this example, it now appears straightforward that there are
innitely many ways of collecting objects, of arranging them. Even if
there was a region which contained a nite set of elements, we could
still arrange the nite set of elements in indenitely many ways (at least
in more ways than there are original elements). Those ways which
Nelson Goodman famously labelled versions cannot be totalized because
any attempt to build the set of all versions (of all cosmological models)
would itself create a higher-order cosmological model of the versions to

50
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

the effect that it would invariably generate the possibility to do so


otherwise.89
This does not only hold for the red, white, and blue cube universe, but
for what we ordinarily refer to as the universe qua singulare tantum. The
trouble with this, however, does not so much lie in the possibility of
describing the universe in various ways, but in the self-referential insight
that the very description according to which there are various descrip-
tions of the universe qua singulare tantum is itself yet another description
but of what?
In other words, contingency, the constant possibility of being other,
cannot be eliminated on any layer of reality accessible to our under-
standing, including this one. Nietzsche nicely sums this insight up in his
concept of the new innite in The Gay Science:

But I should think that today we are at least far from the ridiculous
immodesty that would be involved in decreeing from our corner that
perspectives are permitted only from this corner. Rather has the world
become innite for us all over again, inasmuch as we cannot reject
the possibility that it may include innite interpretations?90
Lets say that contingency is the possibility-to-be-other of a certain arrange-
ment of elements. Accordingly, necessity is the impossibility-to-be-other
of a certain arrangement of elements. Necessary statements or state-
ments about necessity presuppose the availability and stability of a given
framework relative to which a set (of elements) can legitimately be said
to consist of relations between its elements that could not be otherwise.
For example, true arithmetical statements, i.e. arithmetical theorems are
necessary in this sense. Yet, even if there are as many necessary state-
ments as there are mathematical theorems and scientically recordable
facts, the frameworks themselves within which this necessity is recorded
are not thereby made necessary. We are always confronted with the
higher-order problem as to how to determine the necessity or contin-
gency of a given framework which allows for necessary statements. If we
are to assert that a given framework F is necessary then we ipso facto have
to rely on another framework F* which allows for the quantication
over frameworks. Whenever we record the existence of a framework
and thereby quantify over a certain object domain, we generate a set of
background assumptions (axioms) which ascertain the conditions for
there being an object in the relevant domain. These assumptions are

51
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

never accessible within a given framework unless a meta-language


is introduced, and this meta-language is itself threatened by
contingency.
If you call the realm of necessity reason or rationality it is obvious why
Kant assumes that everything which we can make sense of (i.e. the phe-
nomenal world) is fully determined within an ultimate horizon he calls
the world.91 This horizon is the omnitudo realitatis, the totality of all possi-
ble (non-contradictory) predicates. In Kant, to be real amounts to being
representable in the sense of being perceivable. Everything which is real
is either something perceivable (everything which can be met with in
space and/or in time is part of the perceivable) or a condition of perceiv-
ability (such as space and time themselves). Reality consists hence in a
relation to possible experience.
For Kant reality (Realitt, Sachheit) is the result of transcendental afr-
mation92 which afrms that there are determinate objects which Kant
calls things.93 Ultimately, transcendental afrmation consists in building
the set of all possible things by creating the idea of a totality of predicates.
This totality of predicates provides us with the material (Stoff)94 of cog-
nition; it is the name for the materiality of cognition, its being confronted
with given material in all its contentful operations (i.e. cognitions). If we
postulate that everything that is is determined in a wider framework to
which it belongs, we can easily generalize and form the idea of an all of
reality, omnitudo realitatis.95 As Kant suggests, all true negations are noth-
ing but limitations a title which would be inapplicable, were they not
thus based upon the unlimited, that is, upon, the All.96
When Schelling speaks of the idea of being (Idee des Seyenden), also
addressed as the gure of being (Figur des Seyenden) or the blueprint of
being (das Seyende im Entwurf),97 he makes implicit reference to Kants
concept of the idea. Before we can move from Kant to Schelling, how-
ever, we need to introduce another modication of the Kantian concept
of complete determinacy in order to fully understand the impact of
Schellings ground-breaking assertion that the idea (the realm of neces-
sity, including the necessity of contingency) is itself contingent. We have
to take on board the insight that the Kantian totality of predicates (his
concept of the world) should be re-interpreted along the lines of
Nietzsches new innite: there is no consistent set of all predicates or all things
because the concept of a thing as much as the way we record predicates and delin-
eate the semantic rules which make them meaningful depend on a prior decision

52
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

to choose a framework F rather than (say) G. If I assert that the dogs in the
park in front of my window are barking, I refer to a determinate scene.
The determinacy (and the meaning) of the scene hinges on various
parameters such as my (typically unconsidered) decision to rely on
ordinary sense-perception to determine what is going on around me, my
exclusion of far-fetched hypotheses (which, of course, might be relevant)
such as the possibility that somebody might be playing his favorite record
of the barking dogs or a secret agent playing a record of barking dogs
because all the dogs in the park have gone mute due to a strange virus
which the government does not want us to know about, etc. I also decide
against innitely many other (paranoid, scientic, or what have you)
ways of conceptualizing the scene in the park (which under some
description or other would not even be a scene in a park). The relative
consistency of our everyday arrangement of and engagement with things
presupposes that we blind ourselves to innitely more possibilities and
actual matters of fact than we allow to be explicitly processed in the form
of information within our preferred eld of sense. In other words, we
have to take account of the fact that the indenitely comprehensive manifold of
data exceeds the discursively available, nite information.
The very fact just stated (which Kant inadequately captures with his
distinction between the manifold of sensibility and the conceptually
structured appearances) is itself not capable of referring to the multiplic-
ity it envisages. The multiplicity which exceeds the discursively available,
nite information is, to be sure, not even a multiple. We should not try
to comprehend that which precedes the activity of concept-mongering
creatures in terms of a result of concept-mongering. The trouble is that
to think is to identify.98 This is why we can only agree to some extent
with Badious assumption of an inconsistent multiplicity supposedly
prior to discursively available, nite structures. When Badiou writes
Being must be already-there; some pure multiple, as multiple of multi-
ples, must be presented in order for the rule to then separate some con-
sistent multiplicity, itself presented subsequently by the gesture of the
initial presentation,99 he does not seem to be aware of the worrisome
situation he himself creates. The pure multiple or even the term incon-
sistent multiplicity is not capable of capturing that which precedes
consistency, because multiplicity is already the result of a synthesis,
it presupposes the existence of consistency and can, therefore, not
precede it.

53
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

For this reason, Schelling locates total inconsistency which is not even
a multiple at the basis of consistency by introducing his concept of that
which is unequal to itself (das sich selbst Ungleiche).100 Of course, one
could easily try to annex this inconsistency to a set-theoretical ontology
la Badiou by looking back on Freges account of the empty set, for
example. According to Frege, 0 is the Number which belongs to the
concept not identical with itself.101 Yet, reference to contradictory
concepts (under which nothing can fall) is not the only way to introduce
the empty set. One can also dene the empty set as the set of all American
presidents born before 384 BC or the set of all female unicorns wearing
police uniforms and living on Alpha Centauri, etc. Set-theory does not
therefore necessarily lend itself to an insight into the paradoxical condi-
tions of determinacy or anything similar. The empty set can be dened
on the basis of every contradictory concept. Interestingly enough, Frege
happily embraces contradictions, because he believes,

these old friends are not as black as they are painted. To be of any use
is, I admit, the last thing we should expect of them . . . All that can be
demanded of a concept from the point of view of logic and with an eye
to rigour of proof is only that its boundaries should be sharp, so that
we can decide denitely about every object whether it falls under that
concept or not.102
Be this as it may, Badiou is certainly right when he states that the being
of consistency is inconsistency,103 that is, if we add that this follows from
the distinction between a given (nite) structure and the new innite
which provides us with the endless task of making sense of the world
under always different descriptions which will never add up to a fully
coherent picture of totality. We can accept this point so long as we do not
then go on to determine that which is unequal to itself in any such way
as to access it under a denite description.
As one can learn from Schelling, this enterprise is paradoxical and
leads to an insight into the impossibility of carrying it out in any deter-
minate framework, whether it be set-theory of poetry. Nonetheless, this
impossibility does not render the enterprise meaningless. It rather con-
fronts us with the utter contingency and groundlessness of our ways of
giving meaning to that which is unequal to itself. In other words, the
world cannot prescribe how to conceptualize it because it is compatible
with more than one description and there is no ultimate meta-language

54
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

in which it is possible to specify the totality of truth-conditions for any


discourse whatsoever. At some point or other we run out of grounds and
encounter the groundlessness of grounding: at the foundation of
well-founded belief lies belief that is not founded.104
It is important to bear in mind that the world, the domain of all
domains, that which is unequal to itself, unprethinkable Being, the
absolute, etc., are always already part of the cobweb of predicates. This
means that inconsistency is not a state of affairs, a primordial nameless
tohubohu in the beginning happily waiting to be ordered by the divine
word. It rather co-originates with logical space as such. As soon as there
is something determinate, the paradoxical indeterminate conditions of
determinacy are retroactively generated: everything determinate is
therefore determined to collapse at some point in time or other.
If determinacy presupposes negation, then we are justied in applying
the procedure of determining something by negation to the totality of
what there is. In the most boring universe, there would at least be two
things: one thing and the space it occupies. If the thing were not distin-
guishable from the space it inhabits, it would not be determined because
in the world of the One there is nothing else over against which to deter-
mine the single object existing in the singleton universe.105 Even if we think
of the empty set, that which it contains, , is still distinguished from { }.
There is still the distinction between the set and its elements, even if
there are no elements. iek pithily captures this point as he suggests,

reection, to be sure, ultimately always fails any positive mark


included in the series could never successfully represent/reect the
empty space of the inscription of marks. It is, however, this very failure
as such which constitutes the space of inscription. The place of the inscrip-
tion of marks is nothing but the void opened by the failure of the
re-mark. [. . .] the very act of reection as failed constitutes retroactively that
which eludes it.106
That which eludes our grasp (however we name it) is nothing substan-
tial; it does not even exist (a preservable insight of the apophatic tradi-
tion). In this sense there is no ontological secret apart from the secret
that the secret does not exist. Even though Hegel did indeed stress this
point in his reading of the concept of revelation, he nonetheless under-
estimates the power of inconsistency. Whatever the prospects for a read-
ing of Hegel in terms of a philosophy of nitude and contingency, it is

55
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

after all obvious that Hegel in the long run proves to be too optimistic
regarding the expressive resources of his dialectics. In a particularly
presumptuous passage in the introduction to his Lectures on the History of
Philosophy, Hegel writes (full of sadistic enjoyment):

Man, because he is Spirit, should and must deem himself worthy of the
highest; he cannot think too highly of the greatness and power of his
mind, and, with this belief, nothing will be so difcult and hard that it
will not reveal itself to him. The Being of the universe, at rst hidden
and concealed, has no power which can offer resistance to the search
for knowledge; it has to lay itself open before the seeker to set before
his eyes and give for his enjoyment, its riches and depths.107
Hegels identication of being and reection his thesis that being is but
the remainder of reection and that it is ultimately nothing but the
universality of the Notion draws on a distorted vision of the Kantian
thing-in-itself and its successor notion in Hlderlin and Schelling, namely
being. Hegel wrongly believes that being in Hlderlin and Schelling
designates an entity or state of affairs which precedes reection. What
Hlderlin and Schelling envisage, however, is not an entity which under-
lies reection. They do not intend to substantialize being nostalgically
returning to ancient metaphysics. Being is rather supposed to be the
name of the union of form and content which only manifests itself in
phenomena which cannot be made fully transparent (such as aesthetic
experience in Hlderlin and the blind theonomy of mythological con-
sciousness in Schelling). The very distinction between form and content
underpins Hlderlins and Schellings insight that the space of ignorance
(the possibility to be other) innitely exceeds the realm of knowledge.
Only in the experience of the elusiveness of the unity of form and con-
tent are we capable of a prescience (Ahnung) of the unknown some-
thing which makes a unity of form and content possible.108 This truly
Kantian unknown something is not just a self-inicted blind spot of
reection but the space of marks, the domain of domains, which every
reection, even the Hegelian one, inhabits. Being is therefore not identi-
cal with the being at the beginning of the Hegelian enterprise of positing
the presuppositions of determinacy. It never fully manifests itself in the
form of a being which is nothing: it cannot be dissolved into determinate
being (Dasein) as Hegel believes because otherwise the possibility of
anything to be other would be eliminated a priori.

56
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

Of course, any thought which refers to the unknown something seems


to entail a semantic antinomy due to the limits of its own expressibility:
if it is expressed, then it does not express the content it claims to have
grasped. However, this antinomy only arises if we restrict language to its
function of expressing propositions. This is exactly what Hlderlin and
Schelling try to avoid with their recovering of a sub-semantical (a-semic)
dimension preceding discourse. Any form of expression is nite insofar
as it already relies on the availability of a referential use of language.109
In his almost entirely unknown essay Another Deduction of the Prin-
ciples of Positive Philosophy (Andere Deduction der Principien der positiven
Philosophie), Schelling advances the question of whether the being of
logical space can be conceived of as contingent, having in mind the prob-
lem of facticity or groundlessness. If being is contingent, it has to have
the possibility to be otherwise: The question is, hence, whether this
unprethinkable Being absolutely does not allow for a contradistinction,
which could alter it, over against which it would, therefore, prove to be
contingent.110 It is important to refer to Schellings formulation. Es fragt
sich also, ob . . ., which means both The question is, whether . . . and,
literally, It [namely unprethinkable Being!] asks itself, whether . . .
In other words, our question as to the necessity or contingency of unpr-
ethinkable Being is an ontological event. The possibility to be otherwise
which is implicit in our understanding of being changes the ontological
structure of unprethinkable Being, or more precisely, it gives it an
ontological structure in the rst place. This way, blind necessity (which
is not even a proper modality) suddenly and for no reason becomes self-
awareness: reason is established and sense is made of some non-sensical
being there (cogitatur). Unprethinkable Being ceases to be unprethink-
able Being as soon as thought is established. In Schellinguian terms,
unprethinkable Being turns into the rst potency.
The term unprethinkable Being prima facie refers to that which
cannot not be thought as not existing, which we must, despite appear-
ances, not confuse with the God of ontotheology. Schelling rather insists
that the unprethinkable Being is not God, because it is not capable of any-
thing. Insofar as it is pure actuality, it is fully impotent. The modal-logical
principle that actuality entails possibility does not yet hold for the actual-
ity of unprethinkable Being which precedes the establishment of possi-
bility. It is merely that, which, however early we come, is already there
(das, so frh wir kommen, schon da ist).111 It is nothing but the name for the

57
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

facticity of reason: reason (and thought) cannot ground themselves. Yet,


in which sense could the pure actuality, the mere being there of reason
be contingent? After all, are facticity and contingency not different
concepts?112
Schellings answer is as simple as it is bewildering: the necessity of the
unprethinkable Being, i.e. the very necessity of the necessario existens113 is
contingent because it depends on the existence of something contingent.
The necessity of the necessario existens can only be ascertained after contingency is
established. The assessment of necessity presupposes the availability of
judgments which can only exist as soon as there are concept-mongering
creatures whose very core is contingency. The realm of judgment is that
of the duality of the true and the false which opens up the space for
contingency. In other words, being only becomes necessary as a result of
the retroactive causality of reason. This entails that we have to ask
ourselves a question Hegel, in Schellings eyes, tends to foreclose:

The whole world lies, so to speak, in the nets of the understanding or


of reason, but the question is how exactly it got into those nets, since
there is obviously something other and something more than mere
reason in the world, indeed there is something which strives beyond
these barriers.114
The necessity of being qua starting-point of reection is only the result of
reections activity of establishing a thoroughgoing order of identity and
difference, an activity which, in principle, is not capable of presenting
itself within the cobweb of totality that it sets up. This is why Castoriadis
correctly points out against the traditional equation of being with deter-
minacy (which he believes to be a tenet of Hegelian ontology) that deter-
minacy is the result of ontological genesis, a process which cannot be
accounted for in terms of an always already established order of things.
The yet unmediated facticity of the unprethinkable Being cannot rule
out the possibility of another being (Mglichkeit eines anderen Seyns).115
Facticity and contingency are compatible in this instance. In the case of
unprethinkable Being, facticity is pure unmediated actuality, the primor-
dial being there, or Dasein,116 we encounter in our relation to the world
and to ourselves. This entails that facticity can neither rule out nor antic-
ipate the possibility of another being, contingency, without ipso facto
transcending itself. Contingency is therefore itself contingent. It can
neither be ruled out a priori nor is its appearing determined by some

58
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

given absolute origin of things. Facticity is not an origin in the sense of a


principle. At most, it is a non-ground (Ungrund), as Schelling famously
puts it in the Freedom Essay.117
The non-ground is pure facticity. And yet the precedence of the non-
ground cannot even be spelled out in terms of logical or ontological
priority without thereby determining that which cannot be determined.
The very indeterminacy Schelling refers to under the heading of
absolute indifference has to be such that its indifference can only be
realized in difference. Indifference only lies in difference or to be precise:
indifference only manifests itself in the process of a differentiation.
In other words, the non-ground, the unprethinkable Being is that which
eludes any distinction and, at the same time, makes all distinctions
possible by making possibility possible. It is the facticity which turns out
to be contingent necessity, a necessity established retroactively by the
existence of some apophantic environment or other. Once there are
object domains, there necessarily is a domain of all domains (which does
not entail that there is a set of all domains in the sense of a xed totality).
That which precedes all distinctions can only be there without any pos-
sibility of ever fully becoming mediated. It always retreats to the back-
ground, it slips away under our grasp precisely because we want to grasp
it, a situation Novalis succinctly rendered in an oft-quoted aphorism:
everywhere we seek the unconditioned (das Unbedingte), but nd only
things (Dinge).118
The unprethinkable existing119 is Schellings expression for facticity.
Due to the contingent existence of apophantic environments or spheres
of intelligibility, facticity turns into contingency. The very contingency of
a given framework transforms its starting point, its terminus a quo,120
into something contingent. This lets us discern Schellings subcutaneous
inuence on Blumenberg who uses the distinction between terminus ad
quem and terminus a quo in his own criticism of the one-sided Enlighten-
ment rejection of myth.121 Blumenbergs notion of the absolutism of
reality which has to be overcome by the work of logos in both the form
of myth and of science corresponds to Schellings unprethinkable Being.
Just like Schelling, Blumenberg postulates an intentionality of con-
sciousness without an object,122 i.e. anxiety (Angst), which precedes the
fragile stability of symbolic practices distancing the object from con-
sciousness so as to let it grasp its own contingency. What Blumenberg
does not sufciently point out, however, is that the alleged status

59
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

naturalis123 of existential anxiety threatens to be a projection of the


uneasiness of modernity onto prehistoric man which would itself be just
another myth. Blumenbergs way of picturing the absolutism of reality,
of giving a face to the unprethinkable, does not at all do justice to the
elusiveness which is at stake.
For this reason, Schellings account of facticity which is always to be
transformed into contingency in order for determinacy to possibly take
place is more sophisticated than Blumenbergs account of myth suggests.
Schelling draws on the observation that every assertion transforms the
yet-to-be determined fact of the matter from something merely actual
into something potentially different from the way we grasp it. The world
we grasp is not necessarily identical with the world as it is in itself. As
soon as there are concept-mongering creatures, the world itself changes
from mere actuality into something accessible to understanding. As this
process of transformation ontological genesis takes place within the
world, the world itself changes from facticity, mere actuality, to potenti-
ality. It opens up a space within itself between itself and its being repre-
sented, desired, etc. As Schelling writes, for the very reason that the
potency [i.e. possibility, M.G.] did not precede the unprethinkable Being,
it could not be overcome in the act of this unprethinkable existing. But
thereby an ineliminable contingency is posited in this very unprethink-
able existing.124
As we saw in the rst part of this chapter, Hegel believes that there is
nothing which precedes logical space. According to Hegel, the unpre-
thinkable Being is the very being of the Notion itself which supersedes
facticity and proves to be absolute necessity.125 Hegel would be right in
objecting against Hlderlin and Schelling if their conceptions of the
unprethinkable Being were restricted to a metaphysical account of the
domain of all domains and therefore operated within the absolute
immanence of reection. What Hlderlin and Schelling attempt to artic-
ulate, however, is motivated by an experience of elusiveness. There simply
are phenomena which cannot be made fully transparent within the
domain of Logos without thereby being reducible to a logical act of self-
alienation. Contra Hegel, the very existence of intelligibility owes itself to
a process it cannot account for. This is the point of introducing the inde-
terminate conditions of determinacy into logical space. If there are expe-
riences of elusiveness which cannot be overcome, then logical space
must have properties which point to a dimension which is not logical.

60
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

As a matter of fact, Hegels unmitigated logocentricism is incapable of


accommodating certain unwelcome pre-logical phenomena it tries to
reduce to clumsy attempts at expressing logical forms. This leads him to
reinstall the ancient method of allegory in the context of his actual
philosophy of mythology and religion respectively.126 For Hegel, religion
expresses the absolute content (i.e. the absolute) in the nite form of
representation. This assumption licenses the use of the method of
allegory: religious representations say something else (allo agoreuein)
than what appears at their surface. For example, the Christian dogma of
trinity is really about mediation, the death of God (i.e. of Christ) really
signies the auto-destruction of transcendence, etc. Religion uses images,
metaphors, parables, etc. in order to express a mystery which does not
exist. The true mystery is to understand that there has never been
a mystery apart from the mystery that people believed in, a mystery
which turns out to be an error, necessary for the eventual resurgence of
truth as it is in truth.
This method of interpreting myths has already been extensively
employed by ancient philosophers in late antiquity. Yet, the allegorical
method is, of course, not restricted to ancient interpreters of myths but
is employed by every theory of mythology which presupposes that the
myths are really about something which they do not explicitly address.
All theories of mythology which subject myths to an interpretation
which presupposes a difference between form and content are allegori-
cal: this is the dominant mode of thinking about mythology. For exam-
ple, a simple-minded psychoanalytic reading of mythology would be
allegorical to the extent that it simply projected psychoanalytical
patterns onto a mythological story.
A sophisticated modern case of an allegorical interpretation of mythol-
ogy is Lvi-Strauss Mythologiques. According to Lvi-Strauss mythology
consists of mythemes, elements which structure native thought and
which add up to myths in a full-edged sense. The job of the structuralist
theory of mythology consists in making the mythemes explicit and
re-describing the way(s) in which they are arranged such that one even-
tually achieves an understanding of the binary oppositions structuring a
given eld of sense. Mythos is thereby reduced to logos, to an arrange-
ment of elements according to a law, a count-as-one. With structuralist
optimisim Lvi-Strauss explicitly sets himself about to prove that there
is a kind of logic in tangible qualities, and to demonstrate the operation

61
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

of that logic and reveal its laws.127 To be sure, Lvi-Strauss operates on


the basis of the highly reected methodological assumption that his
book itself is a myth: it is, as it were, the myth of mythology.128 And yet,
the structuralist paradigm he draws on presupposes that mythology is
governed by a syntax, a natural logic.
In a truly ingenious manner, Schelling objects that any allegorical
interpretation that attempts to translate mythology into a different lan-
guage thereby misses the point of the mythological form of expression.
Myths are not faulty efforts of expressing a logical truth, they rather
enact the very unity of sense of being, of content and form.
Because mythology is not something that emerged articially, but is
rather something that emerged naturally indeed, under the given
presupposition, with necessity form and content, matter and outer
appearance, cannot be differentiated in it. The ideas are not rst present
in another form, but rather they emerge only in, and thus also at the
same time with, this form. [. . .] In consequence of the necessity with
which the form emerges, mythology is thoroughly actual that is,
everything in it is thus to be understood as mythology expresses it, not
as if something else were thought, something else said. Mythology is
not allegorical; it is tautegorical.129
Schellings concern is to safeguard the sense of mythology against Logos
project of absolutizing itself in the form of reection. Reection is limited
precisely because it is engendered by mythology and not the other way around.
Schelling thus advances the thesis that mythology makes language
possible: One is almost tempted to say: language itself is only faded
mythology; what mythology still preserves in living and concrete differ-
ences is preserved in language only in abstract and formal differences.130
Attention should be paid to Schellings carefully chosen expression: one
is almost tempted to say, which indicates that he is aware of the difcul-
ties of expressing something which precedes language. It cannot be
claimed that language is faded mythology without resorting to a meta-
phorical register, without creating a mythology of language.
Whereas Hegel tried to uncover the necessity of the content of mythol-
ogy (of art, religion, history, etc.), Schelling insists on the necessity of the
form of representation which cannot be sidestepped: the form appears as
a necessary and to that extent reasonable one.131 There is no absolute
content prior to the mythological form. Any absolute content arises out

62
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

of the mythological process rather than preceding it. The whole process
is therefore substantiated from bottom up,132 in its actuality it is
independent of thinking and willing.133 Hence, there is no transcendent
guarantor, no God, organizing the mythological process. God is nothing
but the name for an as-yet unfullled promise,134 the promise of a pure
self as Schelling puts it.135 This pure self can only be realized through an
insight into the necessity of a form which disrupts the alleged absolute-
ness of self-consciousness. The self-constitution of consciousness and its
attempt to grasp itself as comprehending both form and content gener-
ates heteronomy. Consciousness becomes dependent on itself which is
expressed for consciousness in the form of Gods reigning over it.
Schelling here anticipates Freuds diagnosis of the structure of
animism (Freuds term for the mythological consciousness): animism
projects the mental apparatus (the internal world) onto the external
world in such a manner that it makes itself blind to this very operation.
Animism is a mythopic consciousness136 which objecties the internal
world and its emotional ambivalence thereby creating a realm of demons
and Gods. Freuds important discovery is, nevertheless, not restricted to
his claim that the savages project their emotional ambivalence onto
their environment but that civilized, neurotic consciousness is partially
subject to the same hallucinatory attitude towards the world.

The projection outwards of internal perceptions is a primitive mecha-


nism, to which, for instance, our sense perceptions are subject, and
which therefore normally plays a very large part in determining the
form taken by our external world. Under conditions whose nature has
not yet been sufciently established, internal perceptions of emotional
and intellective processes can be projected outwards in the same way
as sense perceptions; they are thus employed for building up the
external world, though they should by rights remain part of the internal
world.137
Self-consciousness (and therefore autonomy) is therefore deeply hetero-
nomical: it only realizes itself through becoming its own other on which
it depends. Consciousness is thus not original but the result or end of
nature.138 Self-consciousness attempt to ground itself is the very origin
of its alienation from nature. Of course, by nature Schelling does not
understand the object of science (in our sense of the term). Nature rather
refers to the transcendental past of the Ages of the World, the primordial

63
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

being which is not yet bound by reason. Nature is consequently not what
is given beforehand, that which is always already there anyway, but the
very cause of an absolute estrangement, of existential Angst.139
Whoever sees in mythology only what is opposed to our usual
concepts to such extent that mythology appears to him as it were
unworthy of all consideration, especially of all philosophical consider-
ation, he had better consider that nature hardly still evokes amaze-
ment for the thoughtless person and for one dulled by the habit of
what he sees every day, but that we can think to ourselves very well
a spiritual and ethical disposition for which nature would have to
appear just as amazing and strange as mythology, and no less unbeliev-
able. Whoever would be accustomed to living in a high spiritual or
moral ecstasy could easily ask, if he directed his look back onto nature:
what is the purpose of this stuff, uselessly lavished for fantastic form in
the mountains and cliffs?140
Mythology exhibits all features of a strange event, a term Schelling
himself frequently uses.141 The very historicity142 of mythology indicates
the fact, the event, which you have to think to yourself in the con-
cept!143 Mythology is an unprethinkable event in the sense that there is
no reason (no thought) anterior to mythology which could transform it
into a reasonable product. In its brute meaninglessness, it is the founda-
tion of meaning, even of the meaning of meaninglessness. There is no
purely logical space which can be freed from all myths and metaphors as
even the notion of logical space obviously serves as a metaphor to
delineate the boundless sphere of rationality, to give us a picture in
which we can recognize ourselves.144
The crucial thought is that, despite itself, logocentricism is based on
a mythology. By opposing logos to myth it surreptitiously admits its
dependence on myth. Blumenberg, therefore, is right in stressing the fact
that Hegels closure of reection upon itself is only expressible in the
form of mythology. When Hegel speaks about the circle of circles,145 the
Bacchanalian revel,146 or the Eleusinian mysteries,147 and so on in
order to elucidate the gesture of logos closure upon itself, he himself
makes use of the mythological unity of form and content.148 In this sense,
Hegel does not transcend being towards reection. Reection rather
implodes into being, it replicates the matrix of the unity of sense and
being in the form of its own expression. This is why Hegels Science of Logic

64
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

creates a new mythology, the mythology of reason thereby (I suppose,


unwittingly) continuing the project of the Oldest System-Program of
German Idealism, with its famous call-to-arms: We must have a new
mythology, but this mythology must be in the service of the ideas, it
must become a mythology of reason.149
Schelling insists that Hegel is not capable of overcoming mythology
precisely because he reads logical contents into the form of mythology
instead of self-consciously creating a new mythology. Hegel presup-
poses that there is an ultimate rational (that is dialectical) form of
expression in which form and content coincide, that is an absolute
phrase establishment in Lyotards sense.150 However, he is unwilling to
concede that mythology or art has reached this absolute form of expres-
sion because for him mythology and art are restricted to the form of
representation. Nevertheless, does Hegel himself not make use of repre-
sentations? Is his extensive use of metaphors, wordplays, etc. not itself
an aesthetic expression?

Philosophical concepts are not supposed to be merely general catego-


ries; they should be actual, determinate essentialities [Wesenheiten].
And the more they are, the more they are endowed by the philosopher
with actual and individual life, then the more they appear to approach
poetic gures, even if the philosopher scorns every poetic wordings:
here the poetic idea is included in philosophical thought and does not
need to come to it from outside.151
We have to insist that there is a boundary within language which is not
imposed on it, namely the boundary between sense and reference in
Freges sense: the semantic organization of meaning, i.e. the order of
words, is not identical with the ontological order of things. Of course,
this distinction is drawn within language and yet it is a real distinction, a
distinction we experience as the nitude of assertions in general and
knowledge-claims in particular: by accepting any version of the classical
distinction between sensing and perceiving, between what is there and
what we say about what is there, between form and content, etc. we
ipso facto replicate on unprethinkable Being.
There is no ultimate way of undoing contingency, of eliminating the
paradoxes of the domain of all domains. Conceptual lucidity (reason) is a
very limited sphere of intelligibility, even if reasons imaginary position
attempts to assimilate everything. And yet, it is not capable of assimilating

65
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

its own facticity without transforming it into contingency. Reason


operates under the precondition that there are modalities. It presupposes
that there is a distinction between necessity and contingency. However,
this very distinction cannot be applied to the facticity of unprethinkable
Being. It is the indifference of necessity and contingency because it
cannot be made sense of at all. It is the primordial non-sense of existence
which cannot be made intelligible in terms of a meaningful (either
contingent or necessary) arrangement of states of affairs, for any such
arrangement presupposes the availability of the possibility to be other-
wise which is not available to unprethinkable Being.
Schellings crucial anti-Hegelian move is to identify unprethinkable
Being with mythology. This way he escapes the Hegelian objection that
unprethinkable Being amounts to nothing more than a reassertion of the
beginning of the Science of Logic. Mythology is the brute fact of our
thrownness into a meshwork of beliefs, into a belief-system which is
only accessible from within. The project of achieving a survey of the
belief-system we inhabit necessarily engenders a metaphorical use of
language. Foundationalists, like Descartes, describe our belief-system as
an edice: it is supposed to be a building resting on foundations and so
on, whereas coherentists or pragmatist holists (like Quine) tend to use
organic metaphors or talk of elds of force.152 If we try to access our belief-
system from without, we can only do so by entertaining a belief about
our belief-system. Lets say that our belief-system is a set B: {B1, . . . , Bn}.
If we entertain any particular belief about our belief-system we just add
another belief to the set which hence alters it. Therefore, we cannot
build the set of all beliefs without thereby transgressing it. For this rea-
son, even whole-hearted rationalists like Descartes at some point or
other seek refuge in metaphors in order to entertain their allegedly self-
sufcient thoughts about thought. As Samuel Johnson has already
remarked in his correspondence with Berkeley: it is scarce possible to
speak of the mind without a metaphor.153
At this point, we need to introduce a distinction unknown to Schelling,
that is the distinction between constitutive and regulative mythology.154
Constitutive mythology opens up the space of reasons by dening a set
of certainties which allow us to interact with a limited object domain.
It rests on some conceptual preference or other which allows us to refer
to determinate objects at all. Regulative mythology, on the contrary, is
the rather common phenomenon we know as myth: it consists of tales

66
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

of Gods and heroes whereby a community denes itself (or whatever


function one prefers to grant to regulative mythology). Whereas regula-
tive mythology makes use of specic metaphors, symbols, personae, and
the like, constitutive mythology bases itself on absolute metaphors in
Blumenbergs sense. For Blumenberg, absolute metaphors are funda-
mental stocks of philosophical language [. . .], transfers which cannot be
retrieved within the sphere of proper meaning, within logicity.155 They
cannot be broken down to conceptualities.156 The project of dismantling
myths always produces remaining stocks (Restbestnde).157
Blumenbergs examples of absolute metaphors often stem from the
tradition of negative theology (in particular, that of Nicolaus Cusanus).
However, his claim can be reconstructed without a particular reference
to theology if we simply investigate any language-use which pretends to
either be able to refer to the domain of all domains in a particular lan-
guage or to say something about the totality of beliefs. The metaphysical
use of language always creates a framework of supposedly basic concepts
which turn out to be metaphors which cannot be translated into a purely
conceptual language. A very straightforward example is the concept
object and its philosophical cognates such as physical or mathemati-
cal or ordinary object. As Stanley Cavell has pointed out, the modern
(post-Cartesian) concept of an object presupposes the availability of a
generic object, that is the availability of run-of-the-mill examples sug-
gesting that the world can be itemized in such a manner that we can
make sense of simple cases of knowledge.158 The concept of an object is
surrounded by a large mythology, in which the subject is a candidate
for a pure spectator of the world, itself not belonging to the extended
substance, a mirror of nature (Rorty), etc. If we structure our experi-
ence along the axis of the subject-object dichotomy we come to see the
world in a certain light which is not natural in the sense of necessary and
inevitable. For this reason, the concept of an object (and the concept of
the natural) belongs to a constitutive mythology, one which denes
being as representation, i.e. the nowadays obviously prevailing mythol-
ogy of technique in Heideggers sense of the term.
Constitutive mythologies open up a world. In this sense, Hesiod has to
be granted the status of an ultimate meta-mythologist when he describes
the origin of the Gods (and therefore of his own mythology) as Chaos.159
Chaos (from chask, to gape, to yawn) means an opening, a gape
within which something might appear. Schelling rightly stresses the

67
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

importance of Chaos because it refers to theexpanse (from , ),


to that which still stands open to everything, that which was unlled, thus
the space empty of all matter.160 However, most modern philosophical inter-
preters of Hesiods Chaos did not attend to the exact wording of Hesiods
verse, to wit, verily at the rst Chaos came to be [ ]. Hesiod
does not say that Chaos was at the beginning, but that it came to be.161
The crucial lesson to be learned from Hesiod thus cuts even deeper
than Schelling suspected. For Hesiod does not only start the ontological
genesis of determinacy (the theogony) with a yawning opening, but
reects on the fact that the opening is itself always already part of the
mythological narrative. The opening is derivative because it belongs to
the chain of signiers, it is accessed from within a regulative mythology.
Consequently, Hesiod does not write a single word about that from
which Chaos originates.
Wittgenstein clearly has constitutive mythology in mind when he
refers to the inherited background against which I distinguish between
true and false.162 He explicitly suggests that the propositions describing
this world-picture might be part of a kind of mythology. And their role is
like that of rules of a game; and the game can be learned purely practi-
cally, without learning any explicit rules.163 Examples he gives for a
proposition belonging to his mythological framework are my body has
never disappeared and reappeared again after an interval,164 every
human being has a brain, [. . .] there is an island, Australia, of such-and-
such a shape, [. . .] I had great-grandparents, [. . .] the people who gave
themselves out as my parents really were my parents, etc.165 Other
examples clearly show Wittgensteins ideology-critical approach, which
he avows in the preface to his Philosophical Remarks where he opposes the
spirit of the vast stream of European and American civilization in which
all of us stand. That spirit expresses itself in an onwards movement, in
building ever larger and more complicated structures.166 Wittgensteins
use of mythology is critical in the sense that it creates a distance towards
the modern techno-centric and bureaucratic world-view. Wittgenstein is
far from being a scientistic philosopher precisely because he points out
that there is no world-picture without pictures which hold us captive.

Men have judged that a king can make rain; we say this contradicts all
experience. Today they judge that aeroplanes and the radio etc. are
means for the closer contact of people and the spread of people.167

68
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

The concept of experience employed by Wittgenstein is decisive.


Experience is a system of beliefs governed by rules which dene what
can belong to the system and what has to be excluded. The way we rst
become acquainted with the system cannot yet be determined by the
systems rules. This is why experience cannot tell us to judge by experi-
ence. Our use of experience is always already governed by rules which
constitute experience and which are, therefore, not results of
experience.
But isnt it experience that teaches us to judge like this, that is to say,
that it is correct to judge like this? But how does experience teach us,
then? We may derive it from experience, but experience does not direct
us to derive anything from experience. If it is the ground of our judging
like this, and not just the cause, still we do not have a ground for see-
ing this in turn as a ground.168
According to Wittgenstein, then, our epistemic commerce with the world
is mythological in a precise sense: we always already nd ourselves
thrown into a mythology, i.e. a systematic web of beliefs which enables
us to determine respective scenes of our lives as, say philosophical lec-
tures, divine services, dinners with friends, marriages, scientic investi-
gations, etc. We are acquainted with a web of beliefs, i.e. with our
mythology, by typical images and by the anticipation of patterns of
behavior codied by these images. Our scenic knowledge of acquain-
tance with the world is mythological, i.e. non-propositional and non-sci-
entic. It is pre-scientic and yet basic, because it opens up the possibility
of orientation. Without a mythology that helps us to re-identify scenes of
our lives, we would not be able to lead a human life at all. Mythology, for
Wittgenstein, therefore is something natural or animal, as it were; of
course, this claim deserves another self-reective displacement, one
which Wittgenstein does not entertain. For him it simply is an expression
of the mere being there, the ungrounded facticity of life.
You must bear in mind that the language-game is so to say something
unpredictable. I mean: it is not based on grounds. It is not reasonable
(or unreasonable).
It is there like our life.169
Wittgensteins recourse to life and nature serves a similar, mitigating
function as in Humes Treatise of Human Nature. It is meant to make sure

69
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

that language-games work, because they are embedded in a wider


(animal, natural-historic, and evolutionary) context which secures the
practical functioning of the language-game without itself being
grounded. It is the way we latch onto the world, a way made possible by
the world itself which we inhabit. Qua sentient creatures, we are part of
nature which justies a claim to mitigated naturalism, that is to a natural-
ism of second nature. The obvious trouble with all this is that it is an
attempt to transcend nitude and substitute nature for mythology. This
very operation takes place in reection which is not capable of simply
letting nature into its absolute circularity, as Hegel aptly pointed out.
Wittgenstein himself creates a new mythology, dictated by an explicit
will to power. His philosophy is meant to hold us captive and to substi-
tute some world-picture for another.

I want to regard man here as an animal; as a primitive being to which


one grants instinct but not ratiocination. As a creature in a primitive
state. Any logic good enough for a primitive means of communication
needs no apology from us. Language did not emerge from some kind
of ratiocination.170
He declares an intention to regard man as an animal. In general, the lan-
guage-games he invents in his ethnological thought experiments serve as
a picture-generating device. They are part of Wittgensteins new mythol-
ogy which appears to make implicit reference to Marxs and Nietzsches
naturalization of man. Nonetheless, despite its welcome alignment with
the modern project of absolute immanence, mitigated naturalism simply
ignores the nitude of reection and the logic of presuppositions. It ven-
tures to identify the real, to identify it with nature in the sense of that
which drives human beings ultimately blind doings. However, we must
not forget the ultimate impossibility of drawing a clear distinction
between deceptive reality and some rm positive kernel of the Real:
every positive bit of reality is a priori suspicious, since (as we know from
Lacan) the Real thing is ultimately another name for the void.171
What we can learn from Wittgensteins use of mythology in On
Certainty and elsewhere is that there is a constitutive use of mythology.
Mythology and world-picture are aligned in a perspicuous manner so as
to give the term mythology a clearly constitutive meaning in order to
distinguish it from mythology in its regulative use, that is in the ordi-
nary sense of the word. Nevertheless, Wittgenstein does not explicitly

70
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

draw the consequence for his own reection which looms large in
Schellings Philosophy of Mythology, namely that there is no purely scien-
tic (in the sense of non-mythological) vantage point. This is why we
need to combine Schelling and Wittgenstein.
To be sure, mythology is only opposed to propositional, knowledgeable,
or scientic discourse as long as we choose the vague concept of
modern science as the hinge on which our world-picture turns. Given
Wittgensteins careful remarks on the hinges on which the language-
game turns, it is possible to equate them with constitutive mythology in
the sense defended here. Our mythological being-in-the-world consists
in the fact that we have to impose limits of discourse in order to organize
our experience at all. This imposition of limits is not itself a rational act
which we can be held fully responsible for. At some point or other we
run out of means to justify our justicatory practices. Precisely because
there always is a groundless ground which can never fully be identied,
that is to say, because there is unprethinkable Being, mythology takes
place. This leads Schelling to his claim that at the beginning unprethink-
able Being rst assumes the shape of some unprethinkable God172 taking
hold of consciousness.
Without going into historical details, it is possible to distinguish at least
three manifestations of constitutive mythology, three successive stages of
mythologys immanent metamorphosis: theonomy, ontonomy, and auton-
omy. Obviously, theonomy is the shape of mythological consciousness
Schelling envisages with his concept of mythology as theogony.
It is suggested by the common usage of the term mythos in the sense of
a fable or a story about Gods and heroes and their relation to man-
kind. In its opposition to logos, mythos seems to be restricted to such a
theonomical shape of consciousness. Yet, if one takes a look at the
Pre-Socratic foundation of ontonomy, in particular in the Eleatics, it is
obvious that God (or the Gods) is simply replaced by Being without
losing its functional status. The functional space God(s) used to occupy is
simply redistributed. That which is always already there anyway, that
which is not up to us, turns from God into Being; even the Gods are
thusly thrown. This is what I call ontonomy. Finally, the myth of moder-
nity assumes the form of autonomy. Being is reduced to thought, author-
ity to reason, tradition to creation, community to the individual, the
universal to the particular, etc. Modernity assumes the shape of an irre-
versible reversal of traditional hierarchies.

71
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Even if we are in favor of autonomy which alone is compatible with


radical, fully immanent democracy it ultimately betrays a sophisticated
variety of heteronomy: it stands in need of absolute metaphors and of
specic pictures in order to undo its contingency, at the same time admit-
ting that contingency cannot and must not be undone. Autonomy needs
to present the existence of its framework in such a manner that it appears
necessary, scientically justiable, mathematizable, quantiable, etc.
Thus, the still-by-no-means resolved trouble with autonomy is that it is
subject to the dialectic of enlightenment. Autonomy inscribes itself within
the tradition of giving meaning to the world, of creating a constitutive
mythology. It creates regulative mythologies which are manifested as the
rules which govern our epistemic commerce with the scientically
adjusted world-order. Yet, those regulative mythologies hide the practice
of meaning-constitution which grounds the commitment to down-to-
earth disenchantment. However, this amounts itself to an ethos which
cannot be justied scientically and which, nevertheless, imposes itself
upon each and every member of society (including those societies yet to
submit to or yet to be conquered by the scientic world-view).
For the scientic temper, any deviation of thought from the business of
manipulating the actual, any stepping outside of the jurisdiction of
existence, is no less insane and self-destructive than it would be for the
magician to step outside the magic circle drawn for his incantation;
and in both cases violation of the taboo carries a heavy price for the
offender.173
In their radical gesture of the disenchantment of disenchantment,
Adorno and Horkheimer go so far as to maintain that enlightenment is
totalitarian as only a system can be.174 According to them
enlightenment is mythical fear radicalized. The pure immanence of
positivism, its ultimate product, is nothing other than a form of univer-
sal taboo. Nothing is allowed to remain outside, since the mere idea of
the Outside is the real source of fear.175
This way, scientic positivism reduces all events to a mere repetition of
some basic combinatory principles which are, in any case, devoid of
existential meaning. However, this very assertion itself creates a new
mythology. It betrays the will of creating a world in which the human
does not need to take place and it is a way of suppressing the human

72
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

need for meaning by creating a meaning in disguise in the form of


a scientically justied adoption of utter meaninglessness. The assertion
that there is no meaning, that the world is ultimately nothing but a func-
tion of particles (or waves or whatever candidate one prefers) in space
and time itself generates comfort and meaning. The German philosopher
Wolfram Hogrebe in his keynote adress at the XXI. German Congress of
Philosophy recently described this phenomenon of attempting to articu-
late ourselves and meaning out of the world as the unwitting construc-
tion of a cold home (kalte Heimat).
It is striking that most of contemporary philosophy tends to subscribe
to scientism without ever reecting on the awesome potential of its ideo-
logical misuse. Scientism is dangerous because it belongs to a mythology
which wants to assert its full autonomy without recognizing any limits.
Everything which seems to be external to it, is declared to be non-sensi-
cal. While it is of course true that we cannot undercut the modern stance
of autonomy by ad hoc re-introducing God or Gods into our world-
picture, this does not necessarily entail a commitment to scientism.
Perhaps contrary to the hyperbolic contemporary philosophical scene,
there are indeed many paths between scientisms wish for a mathesis
universalis and obscurantism. And we only need to recall the mythologi-
cal foundation of science, the use of absolute metaphors constitutive of
the elimination of meaning from the res extensa in Descartes, for instance,
in order to understand that secularization is (at least, partly) a theologi-
cal project.176 And there is no way to fully get rid of heteronomy because
we are not in a position to make sure that any description actually
matches the metaphysical properties of the domain of all domains, the
world, because any concept of the world is only a regulative idea in
Kants sense, a horizon thrown up by our activities of handling the world;
the domain of all domains cannot be given to any position.
I must stress that I am far from promulgating obscurantism or a cheap
relativism according to which it is just as good to believe that the sun is
many millions of years old as to believe that it has been manufactured by
some super-mind some thousand years ago. Any philosophy of mytho-
logy which adopts an afrmative stance towards mythos needs to bal-
ance out two tendencies: monism, on the one hand, and skepticism or
nihilism on the other. Monism would be the thesis that there really is
only mythology: it would be a metaphysical claim about the nature of all
belief-systems to the effect that due to the heteronomous nature of their

73
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

foundations, all statements within belief-systems, that is, all beliefs are
mythological. We must temper this monistic tendency in order to
prevent beliefs from what Crispin Wright identies as leaching.177 The
leaching problem is roughly this: if every framework allowing for mean-
ingful statements consists of a set of axiomatic propositions such that
every meaningful statement within the framework can be described as an
element in a chain of inference always beginning with an axiom, that is
to say, if we adopt a deductive view of the relation between frameworks
and statements, then all beliefs indeed turn out to be mythological if the
frameworks are. However, not all frameworks consist of a denumerable
set of axiomatic propositions. The hinges around which language-games
turn are necessarily fuzzy, they are the indeterminate conditions of deter-
minacy. As Wittgenstein repeatedly points out, there are no sharp bound-
aries between empirical and a priori propositions on the foundational
level. The framework propositions cannot be determined without ipso
facto generating another mythology in the background: in attempting to
account for the mythological conditions of a belief system A1, we merely
generate a higher-order discourse, meta-belief-system A2, which has its
own hinges and background. For this very reason, it is simply impossible
to defend a dogmatic monism about mythology.
However, (non-Pyrrhonian) skepticism or nihilism also amounts to a
dogmatic claim, namely the dogmatic claim that there is no way to
evaluate the mythology of a world-picture at all because this itself simply
generates another mythological picture which holds us captive. Even if it
is true that ideology-critique is always threatened by ideology, this does
not entail that it is always ideological. If the concept of mythology is
supposed to do some critical and theoretical work at all, we have to steer
a course between monism and nihilism.
My explicit aim is to set up a new mythology, namely the mythology of
mythology. In this, my project does not differ from that of any other mod-
ern philosopher, if by mythology we understand the creation of con-
cepts (such as: mythology) which exhibit and perform the nitude of
concept-mongering activities. This assertion of nitude is not dogmatic in
that it draws on a ladder-theory: axioms of determinacy are only set up in
order to invert them. In the very moment of inversion, in which we
discover the indeterminacy of that which was introduced as determi-
nate, we experience the elusiveness of the domain of all domains we,
despite its elusiveness, constantly inhabit. This is why philosophy deep

74
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

down in its essence qua groundlessly creative activity always amounts to


an encounter with ourselves, to an existential project. It cannot be
reduced to a science, that is if we restrict science to an activity which
presupposes the negation of existential involvement.
In other words, the decision to grasp the constitutive elusiveness of the
conditions of possibility of (epistemo- and onto-logical) determinacy and
to refer to it in terms of the mythology of a domain of all domains is
ethical. In this regard, Fichte was right when he said that the philosophy
one chooses depended on ones character. However, for him there were
only two types of philosophy, idealism and materialism (criticism and
dogmatism), and, naturally, he believed that the materialist is simply a
bad person.
It is important to highlight the fact that philosophy before Nietzsche
was not capable of fully realizing the insight into the ethical nature of
metaphysics. Even the most pluralist philosophers (like the romantics)
were not prepared to admit of innitely many frameworks, therefore
were resistant to the availability of micro-metaphysics (psychology in
Nietzsches and Kierkegaards sense): we need to draw attention to the
fact that the inversion of the unconditioned into conditioned experience
takes place in every second of our conscious lives. One could even claim
that life is this very process of objectifying itself, an idea most clearly
(albeit on a macro-metaphysical scale) defended by Schopenhauer with
his distinction between the world as will and as representation.
To be sure, Schlegels concept of the innite and the necessity of its
artistic (versus scientic) expression comes closest to Nietzsches revolu-
tionary introduction of the new innite. In his Talk on Mythology, where
he defends the idea of a new mythology, he aptly claims that

physics cannot conduct an experiment without hypothesis, and every


hypothesis, even the most limited, if systematically thought through,
leads to hypotheses of the whole, and depends on such hypotheses
even if without the conscious knowledge of the person who uses
them.178
Accordingly, if we expand the notion of a hypothesis we can go as far as
Wittgenstein and say that we do not fashion but rather that we are our
hypotheses: that is to say, our lives express themselves in the way we
objectify the unconditioned, in and as the world we inhabit. Our lives
consist in taking many things for granted which is not a cognitive

75
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

shortcoming but the condition of possibility of determinacy. As Wittgen-


stein writes, my life consists in my being content to accept many
things.179 If the only way to confer meaning on statements is to blindly
accept certain things, then this acceptance cannot be seen as an irrational
shortcoming. It rather enables rationality without itself being rational.
It is crucial to draw another distinction at this point, namely a distinc-
tion between objectication and reication. Art is capable of objectifying
life, of presenting a picture of our being-in-the-world in which we
recognize ourselves. It is capable of rendering the spirit of a life-form, of
an epoch, of a typical life in our century, of an atmosphere, etc. In the
arrangement of colors and tones, it shows us the multifarious possibilites
of the synthesizing activity we implicitly adhere to. Philosophy and
psychoanalysis in their connatural constant effort of making It explicit,
of confronting the unconscious, also objectify the unconditioned (even
by using the very concepts unconditioned, unconscious, etc.). Objec-
tication as such can therefore not be the problem. Without objectica-
tion, the domain we have in view could not even be manifested, because
it consists only in its withdrawal. The withdrawal could not occur if we
did not constantly attempt to objectify It, to make It legible. The with-
drawal thus presupposes objectication in order to take place.
However, mythologies highly susceptible to ideology reify the uncondi-
tioned over and above objectifying it. They present it (It, the absolute,
the unconditioned) in such a manner that the elusiveness and nitude
of discourse as such is excluded. And yet they are not aware of this oper-
ation. On the contrary, they speak the language of total transparency
and unlimited feasibility. Cum grano salis, this is what Kant has in mind
when he criticizes ontotheology for transforming the idea of a totality of
predicates (the ultimate condition of determinacy) into an ideal, into
something unattainable which is always already there anyway, indepen-
dent of our activity of relating to it as to a condition of possibility of
experience.

This ideal of the ens realissimum, although it is indeed a mere represen-


tation, is rst realised, that is, made into an object, then hypostatised,
and nally, by the natural progress of reason towards the completion
of unity, is, as we shall presently show, personied. For the regulative
unity of experience is not based on the appearances of themselves (on
sensibility alone), but on the connection of the manifold through the

76
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

understanding (in an apperception); and consequently the unity of the


supreme reality and the complete determinability (possibility) of all
things seems to lie in a supreme understanding, and therefore in an
intelligence.180

Reication mistakes its own activity of setting up its world (in the sense
of a framework in which determinate things can appear) for the activity
of something external to it to the effect that the world appears as the
given par excellence. The essence of reication is not simple objectication
(which is inherent in language itself or, better, is expression itself) but
rather the objectication of objectication, i.e. the objectication of the
contingent activity of objectifying as necessary. Reication denies the
paradoxes and antinomies which lie at the basis of determinacy and
accredits itself the capacity to investigate into the conditions of possibility
of determinacy (of meaning, truth, etc.) with, for example, the means of
natural science; scientism is but one mode of reication.
Scientism is a standpoint of alienation: that which is of our own mak-
ing aficts us in the disguise of something natural. It is crucial here to
insist that nature itself is a historical concept. The modern concept of
nature as the totality of space-time-particles governed by necessary laws
of nature is the result of a historical shift in the self-explication of living
creatures. In his The Phenomenon of Life, Hans Jonas has forcefully argued
that the concept of nature which underlies modern scientistic materialist
monism is committed to a thoroughgoing ontology of death.181 The
experience of death as the inevitable effect of life assumes center stage in
modern materialism which denes itself in opposition to any sort of
anthropomorphism, animism, or panvitalism. Even if animism as an
ontology itself is the result of a reication of life and therefore not much
better off than modern materialism, it nonetheless contains a grain of
truth.182 Animism objecties the world-creating activity of objectication
which is life itself. Life objecties itself, it realizes itself in animal bodies
which in turn are capable of manifesting expressions. The inwardness of
life is only realized in its outward manifestations, an idea which plays an
essential role in Hegels Philosophy of Subjective Spirit. Life is not a mysteri-
ous spiritual quality but the activity of expression, of objectication. This
is why objectication as such cannot be the culprit of alienation. Reica-
tion is the problem and it begins where reection denies access to itself. Animism
and materialism are both guilty of reifying life because they are not

77
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

aware of their respective constitutive mythology as such. They rather


regard their constitution as something extraneous, prescribed by the
nature of the cosmos (animism) or by nature qua causally closed totality
of physical objects (materialism).
This is why the concept of mythology, my mythology of mythology,
can be used as an ideology-critical tool. It is meant to secure the stand-
point of an unrestricted higher-order contingency. Ultimately, we are not
capable of objectifying the conditions of possibility of objectivity. And
yet, we create images of those conditions, works of art, science, religion,
philosophy, etc. which function to transcend the given limits of determi-
nacy and, by doing so, make their contingency visible. Science is not
inextricably tied to its ideological interpretation as an ultimate form of
presentation and ontological truth. It need not be interpreted as presup-
posing modern materialism and its background mythology. We can be
scientists without buying into the totalizing gesture of scientism.
Scientisms attempt to identify the world with only one possible set of
descriptions denies the contingency of choice (despite the important role
decisionism played in logical positivism and even in Quine), the will
which gures and congures itself in the creation of frameworks and the
appearance of objects within these frameworks.
This might be the appropriate place for insisting on the distinction
between ontic and ontological creation. According to ontic creation (which
is commonly, although improperly associated with the term idealism),
we would literally create the objects of experience, a claim which is
indeed absurd. We do not create the objects of experience but rather
horizons of objectivity.183 Ontological creation consists in the creation of
frameworks within which objects might then appear. Ontological frame-
works are like echo-sounders. They set up a standard for registering
objects under a certain description. By no means does this entail that we
create objects, certain features of which are registered by the echo-
sounders. Nevertheless, there is no way for us to access objects without
objectivity; objects come to be objects by means of objectication.
Mythology necessarily arises when we push reection to its limits. It is
only harmful when ideological use is made of it. It can also serve the just
ends of radical democracy which does not admit necessary natural
conditions at the basis of its laws, an idea perspicuously expressed in
contemporary (Hegelian) accounts of normativity in the work of Robert
Pippin, Robert Brandom, and others. The insistence on normativity as

78
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

opposed to nature equals a commitment to radical democracy: authority


depends on recognition and is not derived from nature (or God) any-
more. However, we should not forget that the nature-norm distinction
arises itself out of an opposition to a myth, to the myth of the given.
Instead of ridding itself of mythology, it creates a new mythology, a new
preferred set of metaphors (score-keeping, games, logical space, etc.)
which depict the contingency of our world-picture. Qua determinate
negation of mythology, the enlightement normative picture of concepts
unavoidably inherits mythological features. The absolute metaphors
constitutive of autonomys self-explication furnish expressive resources
which condition the modern experience of autonomous normativity.
Autonomous normativity therefore betrays its own heteronomy in the
use of metaphors which can never be fully sublated.
With evidently Hegelian ardor, Jean Hyppolite criticizes Schellings use
of metaphors and myths for being based on a one-sided conception of
the innite which posits the innite or absolute as some thing transcend-
ing reection.

Schellings philosophy, which makes use of the dialectic in order to


dissolve the nite, and which claims to induce in us the conditions of
this intellectual intuition that makes us transcend the human and
coincide with the source of all productivity, is a philosophy that
overcomes all reection. And it is a philosophy that turns out to be
incapable of understanding conceptually how the nite can emerge
from the innite, how difference can appear at the heart of the
Absolute. It can only make use of images, only use analogies, myths,
or symbols. This type of philosophy, which refers to intuition, is char-
acterized by the fact that it communicates only by breaking through
conceptual language and by substituting the image for the concept.184
What Hyppolite misses is that Schelling does not refer to intuition at all.
Even the concept of intellectual intuition which he employed in his ear-
lier philosophy is not reducible to the immediacy of intuition in the
Hegelian sense of the term. If Schelling breaks through conceptual lan-
guage his aim is to show the limits of conceptual language which are,
however, not external to conceptual language. Aesthetic experience, for
example, can only be described in conceptual language to a limited
extent. The experience of the inexhaustibility of aesthetic experience,
the experience of the fact that the work of art in its materiality cannot be

79
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

reduced to one description among others, is not restricted to our


exposure to art. On the contrary, it is the very experience of being
a sentient being gifted with conceptual capacities enabling us to tran-
scend a given sensory episode and relate it to a wider world-view. We
understand that the world offers more data than we can ever process as
information, i.e. as accessible under a certain description. And yet, this
insight arouses paradoxes because it confronts us with the non-identical.
That which precedes or exceeds a given framework and, indeed, all
frameworks cannot be adequately accounted for within a single frame-
work. When we refer to It in whatever language, we necessarily miss
It. However, even though it slips away under our conceptual grasp, it can
be conceptually demonstrated that there is some event, something but
we dont know what, a Kantian unknown something which manifests
itself and answers to our echo-sounders.

All our representations are, it is true, referred by the understanding to


some object; and since appearances are nothing but representations,
the understanding refers them to a something, as the object of sensible
intuition. But this something, thus conceived, is only the transcenden-
tal object; and by that is meant a something=X, of which we know, and
with the present constitution of our understanding can know, nothing
whatsoever . . . This transcendental object cannot be separated from
the sensible data, for nothing is then left through which it might be
thought. Consequently it is not in itself an object of knowledge, but
only the representation of appearances under the concept of an object
in general a concept which is determinable through the manifold of
these appearances.185
Schelling makes use of metaphors and myths in order to give us a picture
of our nitude. He does not claim to have a special faculty of intellectual
intuition which reveals some utterly inaccessible truth to him. He simply
maintains that our creation of frameworks is supplied by energies which
are not part of the meshwork of reason. Every alleged totality is, there-
fore, a non-All (pas-tout) in the Lacanian sense: by dening itself it is
incapable of dening the activity of denition.
In his Beyond the Limits of Thought Graham Priest renders this problem
in terms of a paradox of transcendence and closure. There is no way to
exclude something from a totality, say from language or thought ber-
haupt, without ipso facto including it thereby deferring transcendence

80
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

once more.186 The eld of objectivity cannot be closed because it is con-


stituted. Given that the constitution itself can never fully be manifested
within the constituted due to its elusive (nite and contingent) nature
we always engender paradoxes when we run against the limits of
language.
Non-conceptual language is thus a necessary means of showing that
which cannot be said in ordinary propositional language, but neverthe-
less needs to be said in some way or other if we want to make sense of
our nitude. It is necessary in order to make us aware of the ultimate
contingency of necessity, of the fact that necessity can only be claimed
within a given framework which is itself the contingent result of the
(onto-)logical genesis of determinacy. The assertion of the nitude of
language does not imply that there is something beyond language. We
only experience a certain elusiveness when language tries to ground
itself. As Bataille puts it: what is nevertheless paradoxical is that I spoke
about the unknown, a singular possibility of knowledge begins here. Of
course, the unknown cannot be given to me as an object, as a thing,
I cannot hypostatize it. In other words, I cannot know the unknown.
I have only really spoken about myself.187
Reection is contingent upon a form of presentation. Every form of
presentation is contingent and thus entails its own possibility to be other.
What can be said, can be said otherwise. The creative energy manifesting
itself in a determinate set of philosophical categories cannot be fully sub-
lated. And this is the depth of contingency.188

3. THE CONTINGENCY OF NECESSITY

We begin to feel, or ought to, terried that maybe language


(and understanding, and knowledge) rests upon very shaky
foundations a thin net over an abyss.
Stanley Cavell

Quentin Meillassoux has recently argued for the necessity of contingency: it


could not be otherwise than that everything could be otherwise. His goal
is to prove that the only necessity is that of contingency: it is necessary

81
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

that there be no necessary being. His decision to introduce the necessity


of contingency is partly based on his criticism of the return of religion in
our times. According to Meillassoux, the religionizing [enreligement] of
reason,189 which takes place today and which ultimately originates from
the unleashing of new ideological energies within global capitalism after
1989, hinges on a mistaken conception of the omnipotence of chaos.190
If we draw the limits of knowledge in such a way as to create a zone of
ignorance, then the temptation arises to furnish this zone with divine
omnipotence. If we allow for the conception of a transcendent God
beyond any reasonable approach, dwelling in the unknowable beyond,
then we risk losing the certainty of contingency which actually lies at the
basis of democracy. For politics as such presupposes the unconditional
acknowledgment of contingency thus ruling out any natural or divine
foundation of order as such.191 According to this argument, the only
possible way in which religion can be philosophically appreciated
(as Badiou and iek have argued in their respective reading of St. Paul)
is in its potential capacity to offer a counterpart, i.e. in its critical stance
towards all established orders (to this world) and hence in its potential
political function. In other words, religion can only be tolerated by
politics to the extent that it does not undermine contingency. But to see
religion as a political voice among other voices in this way presupposes
the successful overcoming of ontotheology.
Meillassoux resolutely ghts the metaphysics constitutive of certain
religious strands in contemporary politics that threaten to undo radical
democracy. In a (in spite of himself) Hegelian vein, he argues that we
need to take a strong conception of the absolute and the corresponding
notion of absolute knowing on board in order to ght enreligement
with enlightenment. Just like Hegel, he makes the case that the dogmatic
assertion of the unknowable entails the petrifaction of the political status
quo: if we cannot know anything about the absolute, if it might even be contra-
dictory and paradoxical to such an extent that it eludes any conceptual, even
apophatic grasp, then we cannot hinder the temptation to project the power bonds
which constitute the status quo onto the absolute.
Radical democracy consists in the acknowledgment of the fact that a
necessary entity is impossible,192 as Meillassoux puts it. This afrmation
functions to deny any natural basis for (political) action. The way power
relations are organized is never backed up by any non-human entity that
lies behind them and grounds them. That much should indeed have

82
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

been the lesson of the history of philosophy since the nineteenth-


century revolution of philosophical reection from Hegel and Marx to
Nietzsche. The way the world is is not justied by anything that lies
behind or beyond it. And even if there were transcendence, we could not
have any access to a transcendent entity. Transcendence in the sense of a
transcendent entity (and not, for example in the sense of Lvinas claim that tran-
scendence is our relation to another person and, therefore, always already social)
is strictly speaking unattainable.
To this degree I fully agree with Meillassouxs crucial assertion that
the absolute is the absolute impossibility of a necessary being.193 We
need to dispose of any remainder of a metaphysics of necessary being(s)
in order to make sense of the utter contingency of our being here. Being
here (Hiersein) is not identical with being there (Dasein).194 By the term
being here I designate the utter contingency of unrestricted imma-
nence. Only contingency in the most radical sense is compatible with
democracys denial of the relevance of absolute truth for politics. Only if
we can make sense of our contingency can we really argue about the
constitution of our community without making reference to a stable
item transcending the decision-making of the community. We hence
need to acknowledge,

that there is no reason for anything to be or to remain thus and so


rather than otherwise, and this applies as much to the laws that govern
the world as to the things of the world. Everything could actually col-
lapse: from tress to stars, from stars to laws, from physical laws to logi-
cal laws; and this not by virtue of some superior law whereby everything
is destined to perish, but by virtue of the absence of any superior law
capable of preserving anything, no matter what, from perishing.195
Case in point of what Meillassoux describes is the current crises of nan-
cial markets. Everything could collapse; the order (or at least the appar-
ent order) only continues as long as the decisions that uphold it are not
abused by the ravenous appetite of the ruling (monetary) class. Every-
thing could always collapse. This is not only true of nancial markets, but
it is an expression of life itself: life can only establish itself over against death
and thereby confronts itself with the utter non-sense of death in the fragile estab-
lishment of sense. The prole of life is dened by the possibility of death.
It is a Paulinian truth that the self-assertion of structure (law) always
triggers its transgression because the specication of limits generates a

83
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

domain beyond the limits. This dialectic is also the grain of truth in
Schmitts account of the state of exception: any structure and, therefore,
any state creates its own state of exception which is needed in order for
it to be determined from within against its internal without. This does
not mean that the other beyond the limits of the state necessarily exists.
Dialectics does not yield an ontological proof of the existence of weapons
of mass destruction or anything of that sort. However, the acceptance of
the nitude of any state qua structure helps to embrace contingency as
the only honest modality of democracy.
The dialectic just sketched can be viewed as a manifestation of the
instability of structure as such. All structures (including higher-order
intelligible structures such as theories and consciousness, etc.) are part
of the world which is why the world is chaotic and contradictory: if
the world is not only the object of theories but if it contains those
theories (after all, theories are not transcendent) and if there are
contradictory theories and a variety of perspectives on the world, then
the world itself is a paradoxical unity which contradicts itself. The
unity of the world is unstable and ever-changing, because it depends
on the plurality of frameworks within which its unity can appear.
Truth can only take place under the premises of dissent, difference,
and misunderstanding.
Political philosophy always draws on a theory of order. Given that
order is the result of an establishment of determinacy, the ontology of
reection I have developed in the rst two parts of this chapter has
obvious consequences for a political philosophy. The dimension of the
political is only available under the condition of logos, as Aristotle notori-
ously pointed out. Logos, i.e. language in the sense of truth-apt dis-
course, opens up a realm of contingency. It denes a domain of possibility,
because it generates the distinction between the true and the false:
whatever is meaningfully asserted is either true or false (or has another
truth-value depending on your preferred logical system). The crucial
point is that the political only takes place as soon as the possibility of
rearrangement becomes manifest. And this manifestation takes place
in discourse. Discourse generates a variety of universes of discourse,
a plurality of object domains, as Aristotle was well aware of. For this
reason, his metaphysics bears on his political philosophy: being qua
being is only manifested in the possibility and actuality of dissent that
is the very manifestation of logos. This is why logos can still mean

84
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

structure in general in Aristotle. It is not only epistemological, but


ontological as well.
The unity of the world is a presupposition of the inconsistent multi-
plicity of manifest structures. They are inconsistent precisely because
they are part of a wider context that encompasses them. This wider
context cannot itself be structurally realized without ipso facto ceasing to
be what it is: the horizon within which the manifold takes place, a hori-
zon which does not itself take place within the world, a horizon which
does not even exist. If we call this horizon substance and everything
determinate manifested within it structure, it is undemanding to under-
stand why all structures bear an indivisible remainder within them. The
very substance of the world, which unites the manifold, nite structures
into the contradictory unity of the polemos of determinacy, cannot itself
be structurally realized. It is therefore the proper void or, to be more
precise, it is not even the void in the sense of a paradoxical elusive object.
The substance of the world is substanceless. It is not something determi-
nate, but the blank space which is a presupposition of determinacy. For
this reason, democracy is a manifestation of the worlds elusiveness.196
It goes hand in hand with an ontology of substancelessness.
The void is the substanceless substance of the world and, hence, it
cannot simply be dismissed for being paradoxical. Without this paradox,
which sustains the perpetual struggle between substance and structure
(the real and the ideal in the post-Kantian sense of the terms), determi-
nacy could not take place. This explanation of the determinacy of struc-
ture relegates us thus to substance which stands for the background
relating all structures to all others in the meshwork of relations of
identity and difference. This background cannot become a determinate
object of inquiry lest it moves to the foreground such that another back-
ground is generated.197 The substance is hence not something substantial
in the sense of some sacrosanct stable unity. It is like the Lacanian Real
or Heideggerian Being, a rupture within the symbolic order which only
exists in the momentary breakdown of order.
As liberating and welcome as Meillassouxs avowal of instability and
contingency appears at the rst glance, he nevertheless gives away part
of his insight by backing it up with a claim to necessity. Despite his actual
commitment to absolute contingency he believes there must be an ulti-
mate law, a principle of unreason that necessarily governs the auto-
normalization of chaos. In the vein of Badious ontology, Meillassoux

85
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

clings to the identication of ontology and mathematics, which explains


his return to the Cartesian absolute. The thing-in-itself not only exists
according to Meillassoux, but it is a substance the properties of which are
all primary, i.e. mathematizable qualities.198
In his polemics against correlationism, as he calls it, Meillassoux argues
that the Kantian redenition of objectivity in terms of (inter-)subjectiv-
ity disqualies the truth predicate operative in ancestral statements, i.e.
in statements which describe temporally indexed states of affairs sup-
posed to have occurred before the event of the human (consciousness,
language, representation, subjectivity, etc.). The only argument he pres-
ents against correlationism in favor of metaphysical realism relies on the
truth predicate in ancestral statements. Yet, there is no need to restrict
the debate with idealism (which appears to be Meillassouxs real enemy)
to the truth predicate operative in a particular domain. Perhaps one
should engage in the realism-antirealism debate instead of tying the
weaknesses of correlationism to ancestral statements alone. Perhaps one
would better consider the most sophisticated arguments against meta-
physical realism presented by Putnam or the systematic elaboration of a
theory of objectivity in terms of a plurality of truth predicates pro-
pounded by Crispin Wright in his Truth and Objectivity which presents a
sophisticated account of antirealism.199 Instead of this, Meillassoux com-
mits himself to a rather nave sort of objectivism, even if it is for the just
cause of ghting creationism and its ilk.
Bataille relates a famous meeting between A. J. Ayer, Merleau-Ponty,
Ambrosino, and himself on the night of January 11, 1951.200 On this
occasion, the topic of the debate was the ancestral proposition that the
sun existed before man.201 Back in those days, Bataille could still ascer-
tain that there is a sort of abyss between French philosophers and
English philosophers, which isnt there between French philosophers
and German philosophers.202 This alliance between French and German
philosophy seems to have come to an end if we consider Badious and
Meillassoux new scientism as well as a large part of contemporary
German philosophers whose work chiey consists in an unoriginal (and
fortunately widely neglected) attempt to imitate Anglophone analytic
philosophy. The prevailing ideology among those philosophers is a vague
naturalism or scientism that endows science with the magical power of
getting It right. However, it should be the cause of extreme astonishment
if the philosophers referred to as correlationists by Meillassoux, such as

86
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

Kant, Husserl, and Heidegger were not capable of understanding that the
sun has existed before man. Neither idealism nor phenomenology is an
ontic theory according to which the existence of human beings is the
efcient cause of the existence of particular objects such as the sun, the
Milky Way, or Niagara Falls. That there are epistemological conditions of
possibility of experience or even ontological conditions of possibility of
determinacy berhaupt is a second-order claim of reection. This is fully
compatible with internal realism: as soon as a framework is xed, it allows
for reference and therefore ordinary truth (and falsity) to take place.
Meillassoux critique of correlationism simply misses the distinction
between ontic (rst-order) and ontological (reective) theorizing. In
order to repudiate correlationism, he would have to show that the onto-
logical claim according to which the in-itself is only in-itself for us entails
ontic non-sense. Yet, he does not even distinguish the various layers of
reection and theorizing, a shortcoming very common in the debate
about idealism, constructivism, etc.203
At the same time that Bataille discusses ancestral statements and
indeed asserts that they are not literally true, he also establishes a differ-
ently motivated alliance between French and German philosophy which
is not dened on the epistemological basis of correlationism alone. In
general, he does not plainly refer to a continental commitment to ontic
idealism but goes on to describe a curiosity about the unknown
domain204 which manifests itself in an experience of nonknowledge
Bataille characterizes as uneasiness.205 He writes, it seems to me [. . .]
that the fundamental question is posed only from that moment on, when
no formula is possible, when we listen in silence to the absurdity of the
world.206 This sense of uneasiness is repressed by the scientic attitude
and by the respective ideology prevailing in most departments of philos-
ophy in the Western world. However, without this sense of uneasiness,
anxiety, Sartrean nause, or Wittgensteinian paradox philosophy does
not exist. No wonder that scientists in philosophy limit their research to
the undoing of philosophy proper.
Science ultimately serves the existential project of making the human
being at home in the world. It constantly reduces the absolutism of
reality (Blumenberg) by availing itself of means to substitute the famil-
iar for the unfamiliar in such a manner that it transforms directionless
anxiety into object-directed fear. This still holds despite the oft-lamented
loss of meaning (of teleology, animism, etc.) associated with the alleged

87
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

modern disenchantment of nature. Science denes a domain of know-


ability, of stable objects that resist the human experience of elusiveness,
of death, of the impossible, and of the insatiable longing for transcen-
dence (which is a manifestation of the death drive).207 This experience is,
of course, not geographically restricted as Batailles alliance between
France and Germany suggests. Poe in defending himself against the
charges of Germanism already correctly stated in 1840 that terror is
not of Germany [and of France, we might add], but of the soul.208
The uneasiness at the bottom of language that Bataille tries to give
voice to is the experience of language as such, i.e. the experience of con-
tingency. Semantically gifted creatures are capable of referring to the
world in such a manner that they generate possibilities, such as the
possibility of getting it right or wrong. Language discloses a dimension of
possibility and therefore of contingency. A particularly convincing
account of this has been given by Cavell in his The Claim of Reason. Cavell
insists on the standpoint of nonknowledge in Batailles sense, repeatedly
pointing out that there is a truth in skepticism, the mortal enemy of
scientism and naturalized epistemology. Cavell writes, our relation to
the world as a whole, or to others in general, is not one of knowing.209
Language opens up the space of contingency, of possible assertions.
Without this possibility, the actuality, let alone necessity of anything
would not be salient or not even available. In other words, language
unfolds the unity of Being into the modalities, thereby generating a space
of marks within which determinacy then takes place.
Scientism transgresses the boundaries of knowledge. It objecties our
activity of objectication, i.e. it reies our concept-mongering practices
and bases itself on a disavowal of nitude. This decision is an expression
of the human wish to deny humanity in order to achieve absolute knowl-
edge and thereby mastery. Scientism requires an inconsistent, because
indeterminate view from nowhere. This is why Thomas Nagels classic
diagnosis still holds: to be human is to oscillate between the subjective
and the objective, between the world sub specie humanitatis and the world
in so far as it is not of our own making.210 But there is no straightforward
way of transcending discourse. In other words: the domain we refer to as
the objective is itself the objective sub specie humanitatis. Ancestral state-
ments are no exception. They serve the goal of designing a world with-
out mythology. Yet, the recourse to ancestrality is only appealing because
it responds to the mythological consciousness. As Cavell notes, myths

88
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

generally will deal with origins that no one can have been present at,211
that is, with ancestral statements. Hence, ancestrality is downright
mythological.
Against scientism we should side with philosophers such as Heidegger,
Wittgenstein, Bataille, and Cavell who manage to verbalize contingency
without disavowing it at the same time. And there is no need to fear that
contingency throws us back to creationism. Scientism (which is not
science, but the faith in science, the enreligement of science!) and creation-
ism are equally prejudiced mythologies serving ideological goals.
Of course, creationism is a paranoid world-picture. It rests on thoroughly
nave assumptions about science and on a hermeneutics of the Holy
Scriptures whose stupidity has hardly ever been outmatched. Scientism,
on the other hand, neglects the role reection plays in the constitution
of determinacy and tries to make mankind feel at home in the world by
telling us that we can nally stop searching for a meaning outside of the
meanings of the realist propositions of science. That is, scientism too rests
on the somewhat nave belief that science does not need to justify its
ultimate grounds, because it believes them to be as evident as they are
objective and material, but without asking itself who is actually
determining them as being evident.
If we dont want to lose track of the contingency we are ineradicably
confronted with (in the soul, as humans, etc.), we need a remedy against
both ideologies. And, unlike Meillassoux, I insist that this remedy is ni-
tude. Only the reective analysis of nitude initiated by Descartes and
continued by Kant and all his successors (including Wittgenstein and
Heidegger) can secure the validity of science for the object domains rele-
vant for science, on the one hand, and the total invalidity of creationism,
on the other hand. Fortunately, many philosophers, such as Quine and
Bachelard, assist us in this task in that they make explicit the ontological
commitments of science and the contingency of the decisions that lie at
the basis of scientic inquiry.
The mythological being of reection reects our own contingency.
Ultimately, language only talks about itself. There is no way to guarantee
that we ever get It right without generating a new mythology that cre-
ates a community of reection. The community of reection contests
that transcendence could ever assume a determinate shape. This is why
the acceptance of nitude and contingency decisively opposes the enre-
ligement of reason.

89
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

To sum up, neither creationism nor scientism can escape the fact that
they are based upon a completely unstable soil, which I have been
calling here a mythology. The question we need to ask ourselves is
whether or not this also holds for philosophical discourse. In effect before
coming to conclusions, there is at least one objection which I need to
fend off in order to make my argument for the indispensability (and
radical inevitability) of mythology more convincing. The objection says
that in emphasizing the contingency associated with the paradoxes of
the domain of all domains we are rendered incapable of distinguishing
between the contingency of the realm of reason as such and the arbitrari-
ness of a particular reason, or a particular practice of giving and asking for
reasons. If we unrestrictedly ascertain the possibility-to-be-other of
everything, are we not committing ourselves to a non-sensical and irra-
tional overgeneralization of arbitrariness?
In order to address this problem and to motivate a distinction between
contingency and unlimited arbitrariness (threatening to destroy deter-
minacy berhaupt), it is crucial to bear in mind that the contingency of
reection is always already a higher-order contingency. I do not claim
that a particular set of necessary statements is really contingent. My claim
is rather that necessity can only be assessed within a determinate object
domain and that the existence of a discourse quantifying over a determi-
nate object domain hinges on contingent parameters. If it is indeed the
case (as I have argued throughout this whole chapter) that local determi-
nacy presupposes conditions which are indeterminate for the domain in
question and if this also holds for the domain of all domains (whose par-
adoxical existence we have to presuppose in order to make sense of the
existence of a multitude of mutually determined object domains), then
necessity always hinges on the contingent stability of a particular frame-
work. As soon as this framework becomes the object of further scrutiny,
another higher-order framework is created which, in turn, brings along
a trail of indeterminacy and so on ad transnitum.
We are conditioned to always go on in a certain, determinate way as
long as we are recognized as members of a particular community. In this
chapter, I have tried to argue that the community I take myself to belong
to should continue to be a community of free reection dening itself on
the basis of an unrestricted acknowledgment of contingency. Nature
will not guarantee that radical democracy will prove to be our future.
It is threatened all the time by the human need to dispose of the human

90
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

condition, i.e. by our need to transcend contingency and ground it in


some stable item.
The ultimate higher-order contingency of frameworks and therefore of
determinacy as such, is not identical with arbitrariness. It is rarely optional
for us to really choose between applying this or that framework to
a particular situation. As a matter of fact, we cannot even apply any
framework to a particular situation without already having the situation
in view, which presupposes the prior application of a framework. When
Wittgenstein, for example, considers that knowledge might be related to
a decision,212 he does not mean a selection, but rather something far more
decisive, namely that the decision is always already made: If someone
says that he will recognize no experience as proof of the opposite, that is
after all a decision. It is possible that he will act against it.213 This is why we
need to side with Blumenbergs re-appropriation of Gehlens concept of
institutions.214 Institutions are objectications of the way we go about our
world and they are handed on to us without ever being stable items. Due
to the diachronic change of the way we go about our world which takes
place in the history of thought and language, institutions change but they
are always changed from within. Even revolutions rely on institutions in
this sense because they also presuppose a way to do things on a basic level
(revolutionaries still brush their teeth and clothe themselves, etc.). Even
revolutions are determinate negations and not just natural events like
Tsunamis. Otherwise they could not be justied (after or before the fact).
It is important to stress that mythology is bound to institutions and that it
is not up to the free imagination of individual thinkers or seers.
This is why our relation to institutions is one of thrown projection
(geworfener Entwurf), as Heidegger famously pointed out. And yet, we
institute frameworks all the time by identifying particular scenes of our
lives. Our being-in-the-world is the realization of a creatio continua. It is
synthetic in Kants sense of the term, a putting together of elements,
rearrangements of meanings and things without which determinacy
(and the minimal mental sanity of human everydayness) could not even
get off the ground. This is precisely what both scientism and creationism
misrepresent: committing transcendental subreption, they mistake the
activity of reection for someone elses activity, which is, to say the least,
a paranoid stance . . .
The dogmatic reassertion of the Cartesian absolute runs the risk of
allying itself with the ideological gesture of the blatant and ill-motivated

91
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

naturalism of our time which believes that materialism equals the reduc-
tion of all events to ultimately necessary arrangements of space-time
particles. Apart from its ridiculous anti-modernist disavowal of the
ontological uncertainty (and fundamental contingency) discovered by
quantum physics, the fetishism of scientic determinacy commonly
taken for granted in contemporary main-stream analytic philosophy
reects the ontology of our nancial markets, i.e. the assumption of the
omnipotence of quantication. With Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel we
could even venture the hypothesis that contemporary naturalism is the
expression of the perverse way of thinking heading towards an
anal-sadistic universe in which all differences are reduced to a mere
rearrangement of (excremental) matter.

In the universe [of the pervert, M.G.] I am describing, the world has
been engulfed in a gigantic grinding machine (the digestive tract) and
has been reduced to homogeneous (excremental) particles. Then all is
equivalent. The distinction between before and after has disap-
peared, as, too, of course, has history. Only quantities are taken into
account, as in the case of the fetishist who told me: I cant see why the
Jews complain so much. They suffered six million dead, but the
Russians suffered twenty!215
Surely, Meillassoux is very far from being a naturalist in this tradition.
Nevertheless, he comes close to the ideological gesture of reinstalling
necessity. Like Schelling, Blumenberg, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and
many others (he would not like to associate with), Meillassoux rightly
emphasizes the absolutism of reality, i.e. the facticity of the glacial world
that is revealed to the moderns, a world in which there is no longer any
up or down, centre or periphery, nor anything else that might make of it
a world designed for humans.216 However, he does not take the fact into
account that the glacial world is not a fact, but itself a world-picture
designed by humans for human purposes, a metaphor as Nietzsche
would put it. What Meillassoux ultimately neglects or disavows is that
the hypothesis of a meaningless world (or at least of something which
cannot be reduced to being an element within the chain of signiers)
serves the function of justifying a radical democracy that would upset his
desire to position himself after nitude, or, what is the same, after the
community. If God (that is to say, his representatives on earth) does not
dictate politics any more, then we are left alone with the community.

92
THE MYTHOLOGICAL BEING OF REFLECTION

The metaphysical solitude of the community would be threatened by


God which is why God (the father) had to be eliminated: in the same
vein, scientism must be extirpated.
As Freud speculates in Totem and Taboo, his most mythological text,
the murder of the father is the great crime which was the beginning of
society and of the sense of guilt.217 The great crime at the bottom of
modernity is its suppression of the longing for the father,218 the long-
ing for something to ll the hollow that, as Nietzsche famously said, we
devised ourselves. Unlike Freud, I do not believe that the great crime
literally took place in the inconceivably remote past.219 The very notion
of crime already presupposes the symbolic order which is, however,
only established by crime. The great crime without which no
symbolic order could be established can, hence, not yet be determined
as a crime unless we illegitimately retroject the structure of the sym-
bolic order. But the mythology Freud creates may help us better under-
stand what Schelling designated as mythological consciousness,
a shape of consciousness which still manifests itself in our relation
towards the world as such (the domain of all domains). And yet, we still
need to deconstruct the need for the transcendent father, the determi-
nate absolute which guarantees stability, even the seductive stability
of instability Meillassoux so convincingly argues for in his daringly
original treatise.
In his book Fashionable Nihilism: A Critique of Analytic Philosophy, Bruce
Wilshire defends classical metaphysics against the analytic disavowal of
the paradoxical presence of the domain of all domains.220 He reminds us
that philosophy in its proper form is an activity the ultimate aim of
which is to keep us open to the unencompassable, the domain of what
we dont know we dont know.221 This is what Bataille had in mind
when he opposed the uneasiness of French and German (nowadays
called Continental) philosophy to Ayers attitude (priding itself with the
name of analytic, that is, not geographically restricted philosophy). This
uneasiness can never be fully sublated (or sublimated); it is the indivisi-
ble remainder of fuzziness that attaches to meaning as such. To be a
creature gifted with language is to be exposed to contingency. It is only
natural that we attempt to make sense of the senseless facticity we
confront by naming it, thereby achieving the distance necessary for
contingency to have a liberating effect. However, we must never give in
to the ideological gesture of reifying objectication.

93
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

For this reason, I have defended the contingency of necessity through-


out this chapter. We need to acknowledge the nitude of expression and
the ineliminable contingency of all frameworks in order to confront our
own being here. We must avow this nitude, for the position outside or
after nitude is not available to us: we must avow nitude precisely
because, as Bataille says, the essential is inavowable.222 Once we have
been through the process of the ladder-theory we come to understand
that the world is made by us an insight which gives us an important
device for criticizing ideology. The mythology of mythology creates a
universe of discourse enabling us to confront contingency and to embrace
the task of sublimation without believing that the stability of the culture
(and community) of contingency is backed up by either Nature or
God. We are alone. Mythology can assist us in coming to an end with this
attempt at making sense of contingency in terms of the mythological
being of reection: Since it has no interest in denite beginnings or end-
ings, mythological thought never develops any theme to completion:
there is always something left unnished.223
Hence, the ladder-theory I have developed in this chapter ultimately
gives voice to its own contingency. It becomes reective contingency because
it is meant to express the contingency of reection. Reection could not
have taken place. It just so happened that the world became entangled
in the web of reason. As soon as a realm of reason is established, it can
only be maintained by reason. However, reason is nite: it generates its
own preconditions retroactively. Fortunately, contingency is not a lam-
entable fact about our nature, but the proper name for the chance of
expression. If it did not exist, there would not even be a world. As soon
as there is a world, the simulation of determinacy takes place. It conceals
the utter contingency of determinacy which is nevertheless constantly
manifested in the fact that everything takes place nowhere. Because the
world does not exist, it is always up to us to negotiate our various decisions
as to how to overturn nothingness as long as the evanescent ickering
of semantic elds within nothingness endures.

94
CHAPTER TWO
Discipline between Two Freedoms Madness
and Habit in German Idealism
Slavoj iek

The antagonism of the Kantian notion of freedom (as the most concise
expression of the antagonism of freedom in bourgeois life itself) does
not reside where Adorno locates it (the autonomously self-imposed
law means that freedom coincides with self-enslavement and self-
domination, that the Kantian spontaneity is in actu its opposite, utter self-
control, thwarting of all spontaneous impetuses), but, as Robert Pippin
put it, much more on the surface.1 For Kant as for Rousseau, the greatest
moral good is to lead a fully autonomous life as a free rational agent, and
the worst evil subjection to the will of another. However, Kant has to
concede that man does not emerge as a free mature rational agent
spontaneously, through his/her natural development, but only through
the arduous process of maturation sustained by harsh discipline and
education which cannot but be experienced by the subject as imposed
on his/her freedom, as an external coercion. Pippin continues:

Social institutions both to nourish and to develop such independence


are necessary and are consistent with, do not thwart, its realization,
but with freedom understood as an individuals causal agency this will
always look like an external necessity that we have good reasons to try
to avoid. This creates the problem of a form of dependence that can be
considered constitutive of independence and that cannot be under-
stood as a mere compromise with the particular will of another or as a

95
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

separate, marginal topic of Kants dotage. This is, in effect, the antin-
omy contained within the bourgeois notions of individuality, individual
responsibility . . .2

One can effectively imagine here Kant as an unexpected precursor on


Foucaults thesis, from his Discipline and Punish, of the formation of the
free individual through a complex set of disciplinary micro-practices
and, as Pippin does not hesistate to point out, this antinomy becomes
even more hyperbolic in Kants socio-historical reections, focused on
the notion of unsocial sociability: what is Kants notion of the historical
relation between democracy and monarchy if not this same thesis on the
link between freedom and submission to educative dependence applied
to the historical process itself? In the long term (or in its notion), democ-
racy is the only appropriate form of government; however, because of
the immaturity of people, conditions for a functioning democracy can
only be established through a non-democratic monarchy which, through
the exertion of its benevolent power, educates people to political matu-
rity. And, as expected, Kant does not fail to mention the Mandevillean
rationality of the market in which each individuals pursuit of his/her
egotistic interests is what works best (much better than direct altruistic
work) for the common good. At its most extreme, this brings Kant to the
notion that human history itself is a deployment of an inscrutable divine
plan, within which we mortals are destined to play a role unbeknownst
to us. Here, the paradox grows even stronger: not only is our freedom
linked to its opposite from below, but also from above, i.e., not only
can our freedom arise only through our submission and dependence, but
our freedom as such is a moment of a larger divine plan our freedom is
not truly an aim-in-itself, it serves a higher purpose.
A way to clarify if not resolve this dilemma would have been to
introduce some further crucial distinctions into the notion of noumenal
freedom itself. That is to say, upon a closer look, it becomes evident that,
for Kant, discipline and eduction do not directly work on our animal
nature, forging it into human individuality: as Kant points out, animals
cannot be properly educated since their behavior is already predestined
by their instincts. What this means is that, paradoxically, in order to be
educated into freedom (qua moral autonomy and self-responsibility),
I already have to be free in a much more radical, noumenal, even mon-
struous, sense. The Freudian name for this monstrous freedom, of course,

96
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

is the death drive. It is interesting to note how philosophical narratives


of the birth of man are always compelled to presuppose a moment in
human (pre)history when (what will become) man, is no longer a mere
animal and simultaneously not yet a being of language, bound by sym-
bolic Law; a moment of thoroughly perverted, denaturalized, derailed
nature which is not yet culture. In his anthropological writings, Kant
emphasized that the human animal needs disciplinary pressure in order
to tame an uncanny unruliness which seems to be inherent to human
nature a wild, unconstrained propensity to insist stubbornly on ones
own will, at any cost. It is on account of this unruliness that the human
animal needs a Master to discipline him: discipline targets this unruli-
ness, not the animal nature in man.
In Hegels Lectures on Philosophy of History, a similar role is played by the
reference to negroes: signicantly, Hegel deals with negroes before
history proper (which starts with ancient China), in the section entitled
The Natural Context or the Geographical Basis of World History:
negroes stand there for the human spirit in its state of nature, they are
described as a kind of perverted, monstrous child, simultaneously nave
and extremely corrupted, i.e. living in the pre-lapsarian state of inno-
cence, and, precisely as such, the most cruel barbarians; part of nature
and yet thoroughly denaturalized; ruthlessly manipulating nature
through primitive sorcery, yet simultaneously terried by the raging nat-
ural forces; mindlessly brave cowards . . .3 This in-between is the
repressed of the narrative form (in this case, of Hegels grand narrative
of world-historical succession of spiritual forms): not nature as such, but
the very break with nature which is (later) supplemented by the virtual
universe of narratives. According to Schelling, prior to its assertion as the
medium of the rational Word, the subject is the innite lack of being
[unendliche Mangel an Sein], the violent gesture of contraction that
negates every being outside itself. This insight also forms the core of
Hegels notion of madness: when Hegel determines madness to be a
withdrawal from the actual world, the closing of the soul into itself, its
contraction, the cutting-off of its links with external reality, he all too
quickly conceives of this withdrawal as a regression to the level of the
animal soul still embedded in its natural environs and determined by
the rhythm of nature (night and day, etc.). Does this withdrawal, on the
contrary, not designate the severing of the links with the Umwelt, the end
of the subjects immersion into its immediate natural environs, and is it,

97
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

as such, not the founding gesture of humanization? Was this with-


drawal-into-self not accomplished by Descartes in his universal doubt
and reduction to cogito, which, as Derrida pointed out in his Cogito and
the history of madness,4 also involves a passage through the moment of
radical madness?
This brings us to the necessity of the Fall: what the Kantian link
between dependence and autonomy amounts to is that the Fall is
unavoidable, a necessary step in the moral progress of man. That is to
say, in precise Kantian terms: The Fall is the very renunciation of my
radical ethical autonomy; it occurs when I take refuge in a heterono-
mous Law, in a Law which is experience as imposed on me from the out-
side, i.e., the nitude in which I search for a support to avoid the dizziness
of freedom is the nitude of the external-heteronomous Law itself.
Therein resides the difculty of being a Kantian. Every parent knows that
the childs provocations, wild and transgressive as they may appear,
ultimately conceal and express a demand, addressed at the gure of
authority, to set a rm limit, to draw a line which means This far and no
further! thus enabling the child to achieve a clear mapping of what is
possible and what is not possible. (And does the same not go also for
hysterics provocations?) This, precisely, is what the analyst refuses to do,
and this is what makes him so traumatic paradoxically, it is the setting
of a rm limit which is liberating, and it is the very absence of a rm limit
which is experienced as suffocating. This is why the Kantian autonomy
of the subject is so difcult its implication is precisely that there is
nobody outside, no external agent of natural authority, who can do the
job for me and set me my limit, that I myself have to pose a limit to my
natural unruliness. Although Kant famously wrote that man is an ani-
mal which needs a master, this should not deceive us: what Kant aims at
is not the philosophical commonplace according to which, in contrast to
animals whose behavioral patterns are grounded in their inherited
instincts, man lacks such rm coordinates which, therefore, have to be
imposed on him from the outside, through a cultural authority. Kants
true aim is rather to point out how the very need of an external master is a
deceptive lure: man needs a master in order to conceal from himself the
deadlock of his own difcult freedom and self-responsibility. In this
precise sense, a truly enlightened mature human being is a subject who
no longer needs a master, who can fully assume the heavy burden of den-
ing his own limitations. This basic Kantian (and also Hegelian) lesson

98
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

was put very clearly by Chesterton: Every act of will is an act of self-
limitation. To desire action is to desire limitation. In that sense every act
is an act of self-sacrice.5
The lesson here is thus in the very precise sense a Hegelian one: the
external opposition between freedom (transcendental spontaneity, moral
autonomy, and self-responsibility) and slavery (submission, either to my
own nature, its pathological instincts, or to external power) has to be
transposed into freedom itself, as the highest antagonism between the
monstrous freedom qua unruliness and the true moral freedom. How-
ever, a possible counter-argument here would have been that this nou-
menal excess of freedom (the Kantian unruliness, the Hegelian Night
of the World) is a retroactive result of the disciplinary mechanisms
themselves (along the lines of the Paulinian motif of Law creates trans-
gression, or of the Foucauldian topic of how the very disciplinary mea-
sures that try to regulate sexuality generate sex as the elusive excess),
the obstacle thereby creates that which it endeavors to control.
Are we then dealing with the closed circle of a process of positing ones
own presuppositions? Our wager is that the Hegelian dialectical circle of
positing presuppositions, far from being a closed one, generates its own
opening and thus the space for freedom.

1. THE HEGELIAN HABIT

In the shift from Aristotle to Kant, to modernity with its subject as pure
autonomy, the status of habit changes from organic inner rule to some-
thing mechanic, the opposite of human freedom: freedom cannot ever
become habit(ual), if it becomes a habit, it is no longer true freedom
(which is why Thomas Jefferson wrote that, if people are to remain free,
they have to rebel against the government every couple of decades). This
eventuality reaches its apogee in Christ, who is the gure of a pure
event, the exact opposite of the habitual.6
Hegel provides here the immanent corrective to the Kantian moder-
nity. As Catherine Malabou notes, Hegels Philosophy of Spirit begins with
the study of the same topic that Philosophy of Nature ends with: the soul
and its functions. This redoubling provides a clue to how Hegel concep-
tualizes the transition from nature to spirit: not as a sublation, but as a

99
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

reduplication, a process through which spirit constitutes itself in and as a


second nature.7 The name for this second nature is habit. So it is not that
the human animal breaks with nature through the creative explosion
of spirit, which then gets habituated, alienated, turned into a mindless
habit: the reduplication of nature in second nature is primordial,
that is, it is only this reduplication that opens up the space for spiritual
creativity.
Perhaps, this Hegelian notion of habit allows us to account for the
cinema-gure of zombies who drag themselves slowly around in
a catatonic mood, but persisting forever: are they not gures of pure
habit, of habit at its most elementary, prior to the rise of intelligence (of
language, consciousness, and thinking)?8 This is why a zombie par
excellence is always someone whom we knew before, when he was still
normally alive the shock for a character in a zombie-movie is to recog-
nize the former best neighbor in the creeping gure tracking him persis-
tently. (Zombies, these properly un-canny (un-heimlich) gures are
therefore to be opposed to aliens who invade the body of a terrestrial:
while aliens look and act like humans, but are really foreign to human
race, zombies are humans who no longer look and act like humans;
while, in the case of an alien, we suddenly become aware that the one
closest to us wife, son, father is an alien, was colonized by an alien, in
the case of a zombie, the shock is that this foreign creep is someone close
to us.) What this means is that at the most elementary level of our human
identity, we are all zombies, and our higher and free human activities
can only take place insofar as they are founded on the reliable function-
ing of our zombie-habits: being-a-zombie is a zero-level of humanity, the
inhuman/mechanical core of humanity. This, of course, is Hegels analy-
sis of habit. The shock of encountering a zombie is not the shock of
encountering a foreign entity, but the shock of being confronted by the
disavowed foundation of our own humanness.9
Hegel conceives habit as unexpectedly close to the logic of what Derrida
called pharmakon, the ambiguous supplement which is simultaneously a
force of death and a force of life. Habit is, on the one hand, the dulling of
life, its mechanization (Hegel characterizes it as a mechanism of self-
feeling10): when something turns into a habit its vitality is lost and we
just mechanically repeat it without being aware of it. Habit thus appears
to be the very opposite of freedom: freedom means creative choice,
inventing something new, in short, precisely breaking with (old) habits.

100
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

Think about language, whose habitual aspect is best emphasized by


standard ritualized greetings: Hello, how are you? Nice to see you! we
dont really mean it when we say it, there is no living intention in it, it is
just a habit . . .
On the other hand, Hegel emphasizes again and again that there is no
freedom without habit: habit provides the background and foundation
for every exercise of freedom. Let us, again, take language: in order for
us to exercise the freedom in using language, we have to get fully accus-
tomed to it, habituated (in)to it, i.e., we have to learn to practice it, to
apply its rules blindly, mechanically, as a habit: only when a subject
externalizes what he learns into mechanized habits, is he open to be
otherwise occupied and engaged.11 Not only language, a much more
complex set of spiritual and bodily activities have to be turned into a
habit in order for a human subject to be able to exert his higher func-
tions of creative thinking and working all the operations we are mind-
lessly performing all the time, walking, eating, holding things, etc., have
to be learned and turned into a mindless habit. Through habits, a human
being transforms his body into a mobile and uid means, the souls
instrument, which serves as such without us having to focus consciously
on it. In short, through habits, the subject appropriates his body, as Alain
points out in his commentary to Hegel:

When freedom comes it is in the sphere of habit. [. . .] Here the body


is no longer a foreign being, reacting belligerently against me; rather it
is pervaded by soul and has become souls instrument and means; yet
at the same time, in habit the corporeal self is understood as it truly is;
body is rendered something mobile and uid, able to express directly
the inner movements of thought without needing to involve thereby
the role of consciousness or reection.12
More radically even, for Hegel, living itself (leading a life) is for us,
humans, something we should learn as a habit, starting with birth itself.
Recall how, seconds after birth, the baby has to be shaken and thereby
reminded to breath otherwise, it can forget to breath and die . . .
Effectively, as Hegel reminds us, a human being can also die of a habit:
Human beings even die as result of habit that is, if they have become
totally habituated to life, and spiritually and physically blunted.13
Nothing thus comes naturally to human being, including walking and
seeing:

101
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

The form of habit applies to spirit in all its degrees and varieties. Of all
these modications, the most external is the determination of the
individual in relation to space; this, which for man means an upright
posture, is something that by his will he has made into a habit. Adopted
directly, without thinking, his upright stance continues through the
persistent involvement of his will. Man stands upright only because
and insofar as he wants to stand, and only as long as he wills to do so
without consciousness of it. Similarly, to take another case, the act of
seeing, and others like it, are concrete habits which combine in
a single act the multiple determinations of sensation, of consciousness,
intuition, understanding, and so forth.14
Habit is thus depersonalized willing, a mechanized emotion: once I get
habituated to standing, I will it without consciously willing it, since my
will is embodied in the habit. In a habit, presence and absence, appro-
priation and withdrawal, engagement and disengagement, interest and
disinterest, subjectivization and objectivization, consciousness and uncon-
sciousness, are strangely interlinked. Habit is the un(self)consciousness
necessary for the very functioning of consciousness:

in habit our consciousness is at the same time present in the subject-mat-


ter, interested in it, yet conversely absent from it, indifferent to it; [. . .] our
Self just as much appropriates the subject-matter as, on the contrary, it
draws away from it; [. . .] the soul, on the one hand, completely
pervades its bodily activities and, on the other hand, deserts them, thus
giving them the shape of something mechanical, of a merely natural
effect.15

And the same goes for my emotions: their display is not purely natural
or spontaneous, we learn to cry or laugh at appropriate moments (recall
how, for the Japanese, laughter functions in a different way than for us
in the West: a smile can also be a sign of embarrassment and shame). The
external mechanization of emotions from the ancient Tibetan praying
wheel which prays for me to todays canned laughter where the TV
set laughs for me, turning my emotional display quite literally into
a mechanic display of the machine, is thus based in the fact that emo-
tional displays, including the most sincere ones, are already in them-
selves mechanized. However, the highest level (and, already,
self-sublation) of a habit is language as the medium of thought: in it, the

102
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

couple of possession and withdrawal is brought to extreme. The point is


not only that, in order to uently speak a language, we have to master
its rules mechanically, without thinking about it; much more radically,
the co-dependence of insight and blindness determines the very act of
understanding: when I hear a word, not only do I immediately abstract
from its sound and see through it to its meaning (recall the weird expe-
rience of becoming aware of the non-transparent vocal stuff of a word
it appears as intrusive and obscene . . .), but I have to do it if I am to
experience meaning.
If, for Hegel, (1) man is fundamentally a being of habits, and (2) if
habits actualize themselves when they are adopted as automatic reac-
tions which occur without a subjects conscious participation, and, nally,
(3) if we locate the core of subjectivity in its ability to perform inten-
tional acts, to realize conscious goals, then, paradoxically, the human
subject is at its most fundamental a disappearing subject.16 Habits
unreective spontaneity17 accounts for the well-known paradox of
subjectively choosing an objective necessity, of willing what unavoidably will
occur: through its elevation into a habit, a reaction of mine which was
rst something imposed on me from outside, is internalized, transformed
into something that I perform automatically and spontaneously, from
inside:

If an external change is repeated, it turns into a tendency internal to


the subject. The change itself is transformed into a disposition, and
receptivity, formerly passive, becomes activity. Thus habit is revealed
as a process through which man ends by willing or choosing what came
to him from outside. Henceforth the will of the individual does not
need to oppose the pressure of the external world; the will learns grad-
ually to want what is.18
What makes habit so central is the temporality it involves: having a habit
involves a relationship to future, since habit is a way which prescribes
how I will react to some events in the future. Habit is a feature of econo-
mizing the organisms forces, of building a reserve for the future. That is
to say, in its habits, subjectivity embraces in itself its future ways of
being, the ways it will become actual.19 This means that habit also com-
plicates the relationship between possibility and actuality: habit is stricto
sensu the actuality of a possibility. What this means is that habit belongs to
the level of virtuality (dened by Deleuze precisely as the actuality of the

103
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

possible): habit is actual, a property (to react in a certain way) that I fully
possess here and now, and simultaneously a possibility pointing towards
future (the possibility/ability to react in a certain way, which will be
actualized in multiple future occasions).
There are interesting conceptual consequences of this notion of habit.
Ontologically, with regard to the opposition between particular accidents
and universal essence, habit can be designed as the becoming-essential
of the accident:20 after an externally caused accident repeats itself, it is
elevated into the universality of the subjects inner disposition, i.e., into
a feature that belongs to and denes his inner essence. This is why we
cannot ever determine the precise beginning of a habit, the point at
which external occurrences change into habit once a habit is here, it
obliterates its origin and it is as if it was always already here. The conclu-
sion is thus clear, almost Sartrean: man does not have a permanent
substance or universal essence; he is in his very core a man of habits, a
being whose identity is formed through the elevation of contingent
external accidents/encounters into an internal(ized) universal habit.
Does this mean that only humans have habits? Here, Hegel is much more
radical and he accomplishes a decisive step further and leaves behind the
old topic of nature as fully determined in its closed circular movement
versus man as a being of openness and existential freedom: for Hegel,
nature is always second nature.21 Every natural organism has to regulate
the exchange with its environs, the assimilation of the environs into
itself, through habitual procedures that reect into the organism, as its
inner disposition, its external interactions.

2. THE AUTO-POIESIS OF THE SELF

The ontological consequences of this (self-)reection of the external


difference into inner difference are crucial. In one of the unexpected
encounters of contemporary philosophy with Hegel, the Christian
materialist Peter van Inwagen developed the idea that material objects
like automobiles, chairs, computers, etc. simply do not exist. A chair is not
effectively, for itself, a chair: all we have is a collection of simples
(i.e. more elementary objects arranged chairwise, so, although a chair
functions as a chair, it is composed of a multitude (wood pieces, nails,

104
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

cushions . . .)) which are, in themselves, totally indifferent towards this


arrangement. There is, stricto sensu, no whole a nail is here a part of.
It is only with organisms that we have a Whole. Here, the unity is mini-
mally for itself; parts effectively interact.22 As it was developed already
by Lynn Margulis, the elementary form of life, a cell, is characterized
precisely by such a minimum of self-relating, a minimum exclusively
through which the limit between Inside and Outside that characterize an
organism can emerge. And, as Hegel put it, thought is only a further
development of this For-itself.
In biology, for instance, we have, at the level of reality, only bodily
interacting. Life proper emerges only at the minimally ideal level, as
an immaterial event which provides the form of unity of the living body
as the same in the incessant change of its material components. The
basic problem of evolutionary cognitivism that of the emergence of the
ideal life-pattern is none other than the old metaphysical enigma of
the relationship between chaos and order, between the Multiple and the
One, between parts and their whole. How can we get order for free,
that is, how can order emerge out of initial disorder? How can we account
for a whole that is larger than the mere sum of its parts? How can a One
with a distinct self-identity emerge out of the interaction of its multiple
constituents? A series of contemporary researchers, from Lynn Margulis
to Francisco Varela, assert that the true problem is not how an organism
and its environs interact or connect, but, rather, the opposite one: how
does a distinct self-identical organism emerge out of its environs?
How does a cell form the membrane which separates its inside from its
outside? The true problem is thus not how an organism adapts to its
environs, but how it is that there is something, a distinct entity, which
must adapt itself in the rst place. And, it is here, at this crucial point,
that todays biological language starts to resemble, quite uncannily, the
language of Hegel. When Varela, for example, explains his notion of
autopoiesis, he repeats, almost verbatim, the Hegelian notion of life as a
teleological, self-organizing entity. His central notion, that of a loop or
bootstrap, points towards the Hegelian positing of the presuppositions:

Autopoiesis attempts to dene the uniqueness of the emergence


that produces life in its fundamental cellular form. Its specic to the
cellular level. Theres a circular or network process that engenders a
paradox: a self-organizing network of biochemical reactions produces

105
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

molecules, which do something specic and unique: they create a


boundary, a membrane, which constrains the network that has
produced the constituents of the membrane. This is a logical bootstrap,
a loop: a network produces entities that create a boundary, which
constrains the network that produces the boundary. This bootstrap is
precisely whats unique about cells. A self-distinguishing entity exists
when the bootstrap is completed. This entity has produced its own
boundary. It doesnt require an external agent to notice it, or to say,
Im here. It is, by itself, a self-distinction. It bootstraps itself out of a
soup of chemistry and physics.23

The conclusion to be drawn is thus that the only way to account for the
emergence of the distinction between the inside and outside constitu-
tive of a living organism is to posit a kind of self-reexive reversal by
means of which to put it in Hegelese the One of an organism as a
Whole retroactively posits as its result, as that which it dominates and
regulates, the set of its own causes (i.e. the very multiple process out of
which it emerged). In this way and only in this way an organism is
no longer limited by external conditions, but is fundamentally self-
limited again, as Hegel would have articulated it, life emerges when the
external limitation (of an entity by its environs) turns into self-
limitation. This brings us back to the problem of innity: for Hegel, true
innity does not stand for limitless expansion, but for active self-
limitation (self-determination) in contrast to being-determined-by-the-
other. In this precise sense, life (even at its most elementary, as a living
cell) is the basic form of true innity, since it already involves the mini-
mal loop by means of which a process is no longer simply determined by
the Outside of its environs, but is itself able to (over)determine the mode
of this determination and thus posits its presuppositions. Innity
acquires its rst actual existence the moment a cells membrane starts to
functions as a self-boundary.
Back to habits: because of the virtual status of habits, to adopt a (new)
habit is not simply to change an actual property of the subject; rather, it
involves a kind of reexive change, a change of the subjects disposition
which determines his reaction to changes, i.e., a change in the very mode
of changes to which the subject is submitted: Habit does not simply
introduce mutability into something that would otherwise continue
without changing; it suggests change within a disposition, within its

106
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

potentiality, within the internal character of that in which the change


occurs, which does not change.24 This is what Hegel means by self-
differentiation as the sublation of externally imposed changes into
self-changes, of external into internal difference. Only organic bodies
self-differentiate themselves: an organic body maintains its unity by
internalizing an externally imposed change into habit to deal with future
such changes.
If, however, this is the case, if all (organic, at least) nature already is
second nature, in what, then, does the difference between animal and
human habits consist? Hegels most provocative and unexpected contri-
bution concerns this very question of the genesis of human habits: in
his Anthropology (which opens Philosophy of Spirit) we nd a unique
genealogy of habits reminding us of Nietzsche. This part of Philosophy of
Spirit is one of the hidden, not yet fully exploited, treasures of the
Hegelian system, where we nd the clearest traces of what one cannot
but name the dialectical-materialist aspect of Hegel: the passage from
nature to (human) spirit is here developed not as a direct outside
intervention of Spirit, as a direct intervention of another dimension
disturbing the balance of the natural circuit, but as the result of a long
and tortuous working through by means of which intelligence (embod-
ied in language) emerges from natural tensions and antagonisms.25
This passage is not direct, i.e., Spirit (in the guise of speech-mediated
human intelligence) does not directly confront and dominate biological
processes Spirits material base forever remains the pre-symbolic
(pre-linguistic) habit.
So how does habit itself arise? In his genealogy, Hegel conceives habit
as the third, concluding, moment of the dialectical process of the Soul,
whose structure follows the triad of notion judgment syllogism.
At the beginning, there is Soul in its immediate unity, in its simple notion,
the feeling soul: In the sensations which arise from the individuals
encounter with external objects, the soul begins to awaken itself.26
The Self is here a mere sentient Self, not yet a subject opposed to objects,
but just experiencing a sensation in which the two sides, subject and
object, are immediately united: when I experience a sensation of touch,
this sensation is simultaneously the trace of the external object I am
touching and my inner reaction to it; sensation is a Janus-like two-faced
entity in which subjective and objective immediately coincide. Even in
later stages of the individuals development, this sentient Self survives

107
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

in the guise of what Hegel calls magical relationship, referring to


phenomena that, in Hegels times, were designated with terms like
magnetic somnambulism (hypnosis), all the phenomena in which
my Soul is directly in a pre-reexive, non-thinking way linked to
external processes and affected by them. Instead of bodies inuencing
each other at a distance (Newtonian gravity), we have spirits inuencing
each other at a distance. Here, the Soul remains at the lowest level
of its functioning, directly immersed in its environs. (What Freud called
the oceanic feeling, the source of religious experience, is thus for Hegel
a feature of the lowest level of the soul.) What the Soul lacks here is a
clear self-feeling, a feeling of itself as distinguished from external reality,
which is what happens in the next moment, that of judgment (Urteil
Hegel mobilizes here the wordplay of Urteil with Ur-Teil, primordial
divide/division):
The sensitive totality is, in its capacity as an individual, essentially the
tendency to distinguish itself in itself, and to wake up to the judgment
in itself, in virtue of which it has particular feelings and stands as a sub-
ject in respect of these aspects of itself. The subject as such gives these
feelings a place as its own in itself.27
All problems arise from this paradoxical short-circuit of the feeling of
Self becoming a specic feeling among others, and, simultaneously, the
encompassing container of all feelings, the site where all dispersed
feelings can be brought together. Malabou provides a wonderfully
precise formulation of this paradox of the feeling of Self:
Even if there is a possibility of bringing together feelings manifold
material, that possibility itself becomes part of the objective content.
The form needs to be the content of all that it forms: subjectivity does
not reside in its own being, it haunts itself. The soul is possessed by
the possession of itself.28
This is the crucial feature: possibility itself has to actualize itself, to
become a fact, or, the form needs to become part of its own content (or,
to add a further variation on the same motif, the frame itself has to
become part of the enframed content). The subject is the frame/form/
horizon of his world and part of the enframed content (of the reality he
observes), and the problem is that he cannot see/locate himself within
his own frame: since all there is is already within the frame, the frame as

108
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

such is invisible or, as the early Wittgenstein put it: Our life has no end
in just the way in which our visual eld has no limits (TLP 6.4311). Like
the eld of vision, life is nite, and, for that very reason, we cannot ever
see its limit. In this precise sense, eternal life belongs to those who live
in the present (ibid.): precisely because we are within our nitude, we
cannot step out of it and perceive its limitation. The possibility of locating
oneself within ones reality has to remain a possibility: however, and
herein resides the crucial point, this possibility itself has to actualize itself
qua possibility, to be active, to exert inuence, qua possibility.
There is a link to Kant here, to the old enigma of what, exactly,
Kant had in mind with his notion of transcendental apperception, of
self-consciousness accompanying every act of my consciousness (when
I am conscious of something, I am thereby always also conscious of the
fact that I am conscious of this)? Is it not an obvious fact that this is
empirically not true, that I am not always reexively aware of my
awareness itself? The way interpreters try to resolve this deadlock is by
way of claiming that every conscious act of mine can be potentially
rendered self-conscious: if I want, I always can turn my attention to
what I am doing. This, however, is not strong enough: the transcenden-
tal apperception cannot be an act that never effectively happens, that
just could have happened at any point. The solution of this dilemma is
precisely the notion of virtuality in the strict Deleuzian sense, as the
actuality of the possible, as a paradoxical entity the very possibility of
which already produces/has actual effects. One should oppose Deleuzes
notion of the virtual to the all-pervasive topic of virtual reality: what
matters to Deleuze is not virtual reality, but the reality of the virtual (which,
in Lacanian terms, is the Real). Virtual reality in itself is a rather miserable
idea: that of imitating reality, of reproducing its experience in an articial
medium. The reality of the virtual, on the other hand, stands for the reality
of the virtual as such, for its real effects and consequences. Let us take an
attractor in mathematics: all positive lines or points in its sphere of attrac-
tion only approach it in an endless fashion, never reaching its form the
existence of this form is purely virtual, being nothing more than the
shape towards which lines and points tend. However, precisely as such,
the virtual is the Real of this eld: the immovable focal point around
which all elements circulate. Is not this Virtual ultimately the Symbolic
as such? Let us take symbolic authority: in order to function as an effec-
tive authority, it has to remain not-fully-actualized, an eternal threat.

109
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

This, then, is the status of the Self: its self-awareness is as it were the
actuality of its own possibility. Consequently, what haunts the subject
is his inaccessible noumenal Self, the Thing that thinks, an object in
which the subject would fully encounter himself. (Hume drew a lot
too much of mileage out of this observation on how, upon introspec-
tion, all I perceive in myself are my particular ideas, sensations, emotions,
never my Self itself.) Of course, for Kant, the same goes for every object
of my experience which is always phenomenal, i.e., inaccessible in its
noumenal dimension. However, with the Self, the impasse is accentu-
ated: all other objects of experience are given to me phenomenally, but,
in the case of subject, I cannot even get a phenomenal experience of me
since I am dealing with myself, in this unique case, phenomenal
self-experience would equal noumenal access, i.e., if I were to be able
to experience myself as a phenomenal object, I would thereby eo ipso
experience myself in my noumenal identity, as a Thing.
The underlying problem here is the impossibility the subject faces in
trying to objectivize himself: the subject is singular and is the universal
frame of his world, i.e., every content he perceives is his own; so how
can the subject include himself (count himself) into the series of his
objects? The subject observes reality from an external position, and is
simultaneously part of this reality, without ever being able to attain an
objective view of reality with himself in it. The thing that haunts the
subject is himself in his objectal counterpoint, qua object. Hegel writes:

the subject nds itself in contradiction between the totality system-


atized in its consciousness, and the particular determination which, in
itself, is not uid and is not reduced to its proper place and rank. This
is mental derangement (Verrcktheit).29
We must read this passage in a very precise way. Hegels point is not
simply that madness signals a short-circuit between totality and one of
its particular moments, a xation of totality in this moment on account
of which the totality is deprived of its dialectical uidity although some
of his formulations may appear to point in this direction. (Is paranoiac
xation not such a short-circuit in which the totality of my experience
gets non-dialectically xated onto a particular moment, the idea of my
persecutor?) The particular determination which, in itself, is not uid
and resists being reduced to its proper place and rank is the subject
himself, more precisely: the feature (signier) that re-presents him (holds

110
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

his place) within the structured (systematized) totality, and since the
subject cannot ever objectivize himself, the contradiction is here
absolute.30 With this gap, the possibility of madness emerges and, as
Hegel puts it in proto-Foucauldian terms, madness is not an accidental
lapse, distortion, illness of human spirit, but something which is
inscribed into individual spirits basic ontological constitution: to be a
human means to be potentially mad.

This interpretation of insanity as a necessarily occurring form or stage


in the development of the soul is naturally not to be understood as if
we were asserting that every mind, every soul, must go through this
stage of extreme derangement. Such an assertion would be as absurd
as to assume that because in the Philosophy of Right crime is consid-
ered as a necessary manifestation of the human will, therefore to com-
mit crime is an inevitable necessity for every individual. Crime and
insanity are extremes which the human mind in general has to overcome
in the course of its development.31
Although not a factual necessity, madness is a formal possibility constitu-
tive of human mind: it is something whose threat has to be overcome if
we are to emerge as normal subjects, which means that normality
can only arise as the overcoming of this threat. This is why, as Hegel puts
it a couple of pages later, insanity must be discussed before the healthy,
intellectual consciousness, although it has that consciousness for its
presupposition.32 Hegel evokes here the relationship between the abstract
and the concrete: although, in the empirical development and state
of things, abstract determinations are always already embedded in a con-
crete Whole as their presupposition, the notional reproduction/deduc-
tion of this Whole has to progress from the abstract to the concrete:
crimes presuppose the rule of law, they can only occur as their violation,
but must be nonetheless grasped as an abstract act that is sublated
through the law; abstract legal relations and morality are de facto always
embedded in some concrete totality of Customs, but, nonetheless, the
Philosophy of Right has to progress from the abstract moments of legality
and morality to the concrete Whole of Customs (family, civil society,
state). The interesting point here is not only the parallel between mad-
ness and crime, but the fact that madness is located in a space opened up
by the discord between actual historical development and its conceptual
rendering, i.e., in the space which undermines the vulgar-evolutionist

111
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

notion of dialectical development as the conceptual reproduction of the


factual historical development which puries the latter of its insigni-
cant empirical contingencies. Insofar as madness de facto presupposes
normality, while, conceptually, it precedes normality, one can say that a
madman is precisely the subject who wants to live to reproduce in
actuality itself the conceptual order, i.e., to act as if madness also effec-
tively precedes normality.
We can see, now, in what precise sense habits form the third, conclud-
ing, moment of this triad, its syllogism: in a habit, the subject nds a way to
possess itself, to stabilize its own inner content in having as its property
a habit, i.e., not a positive actual feature, but a virtual entity, a universal
disposition to (re)act in a certain way. Habit and madness are to be
thought together: habit is the way to stabilize the imbalance of madness.

3. EXPRESSIONS THAT SIGNIFY NOTHING

Another way to approach this same topic is via the relationship between
soul and body as the Inner and the Outer, of their circular relationship in
which body expresses the soul and the soul receives impressions from
the body the Soul is always already embodied and the Body always
already impregnated with its Soul:

What the sentient self nds within it is, on the one hand, the naturally
immediate, as ideally in it and made its own. On the other hand and
conversely, what originally belongs to the central individuality [. . .] is
determined as natural corporeity, and is so felt.33
So, on the one hand, through feelings and perceptions, I internalize
objects that affect me from outside: in a feeling, they are present in me
not in their raw reality, but ideally, as part of my mind. On the other
hand, through grimaces, etc., my body immediately gives body to my
inner Soul which thoroughly impregnates it. However, if this were to be
the entire truth, then man would have been simply a prisoner of his
state of nature (67), moving in the close loop of absolute transparency
provided by the mutual mirroring of body and soul. (Physiognomy and
phrenology remain at this level, as well as todays New Age ideologies
enjoining us to express/realize our true Self.) What happens with the

112
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

moment of judgment is that the loop of this closed circle is broken not
by the intrusion of an external element, but by a self-referentiality which
twists this circle into itself. That is to say, the problem is that, since the
individual is at the same time only what he has done, his body is also the
expression of himself which he has himself produced.34 What this means
is that the process of corporeal self-expression has no pre-existing
referent as its mooring point: the entire movement is thoroughly self-
referential, it is only through the process of expression (externalization
in bodily signs) that the expressed Inner Self (the content of these signs)
is retroactively created or, as Malabou puts it concisely: Psychosomatic
unity results from an auto-interpretation independent of any referent.35
The transparent mirroring of the Soul and the Body in the natural
expressivity thus turns into total opacity:

If a work signies itself, this implies that there is no outside of the


work, that the work acts as its own referent: it presents what it inter-
prets at the same moment it interprets it, forming one and the same
manifestation. [. . .] The spiritual bestows form, but only because it is
itself formed in return.36
What this lack of any ontological guarantee outside the play of signica-
tions37 means is that the meaning of our gestures and speech acts is
always haunted by the spirit of irony: when I say A, it is always possible
that I do it in order to conceal the fact that I am non-A. Hegel refers to
Lichtenbergs well-known aphorism: You certainly act like an honest
man, but I see from your face that you are forcing yourself to do so and
are a rogue at heart.38 The ambiguity is here total and undecidable,
because the deception is the one that Lacan designates as specically
human, namely the possibility of lying in the guise of truth. Which is
why it goes even further than the quote from Lichtenberg the reproach
should rather be: You act like an honest man in order to convince us
that you mean it ironically, and thus to conceal from us the fact that you
really are an honest man! This is what Hegel means in his accurate claim
that, for the individuality, it is as much its countenance as its mask
which it can lay aside:39 in the gap between appearance (mask) and my
true inner stance, the truth can be either in my inner stance or in my
mask. What this means is that the emotions I perform through the mask
(false persona) that I adopt can in a strange way be more authentic and
truthful than what I really feel in myself. When I construct a false image

113
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

of myself which stands for me in a virtual community in which I partici-


pate (in sexual games, for example, a shy man often assumes the screen
persona of an attractive promiscuous woman), the emotions I feel and
feign as part of my screen persona are not simply false: although (what
I experience as) my true self does not feel them, they are nonetheless in
a sense true. What if, deep in myself, I am a sadist pervert who
dreams of beating other men and raping women; in my real-life interac-
tion with other people, I am not allowed to enact this true self, so I adopt
a more humble and polite persona is it not that, in this case, my true
self is much closer to what I adopt as a ctional screen-persona, while
the self of my real-life interactions is a mask concealing the violence of
my true self?
Habit provides the way out of this predicament how? Not as the
subjects true expression, but by putting the truth in mindless expres-
sion recall Hegels constant motif that truth is in what you say, not in
what you mean to say. Exemplary is here the enigmatic status of what we
call politeness: when, upon meeting an acquaintance, I say, Glad to see
you! How are you today?, it is clear to both of us that, in a way, I do not
mean it seriously (if my partner suspects that I am really interested, he
may even be unpleasantly surprised, as though I were aiming at some-
thing too intimate and of no concern to me or, to paraphrase the old
Freudian joke, Why are you saying youre glad to see me, when youre
really glad to see me!?). It would nonetheless be wrong to designate my
act as simply hypocritical, since, in another way, I do mean it: the polite
exchange does establish a kind of pact between the two of us; in the
same sense as I do sincerely laugh through the canned laughter (the
proof of it being the fact that I effectively do feel relieved afterwards).
This brings us to one of the possible denitions of a madman: the subject
who is unable to enter this logic of sincere lies, so that, when, say, a
friend greets him Nice to see you! How are you?, he explodes: Are you
really glad to see me or are you just pretending it? And who gave you the
right to probe into my state?
In Shakespeares As You Like It, Orlando is passionately in love with
Rosalind who, in order to test his love, disguises herself as Ganymede
and, as a male companion, interrogates Orlando about his love. She even
takes on the personality of Rosalind (in a redoubled masking, she pre-
tends to be herself, i.e., to be Ganymede who plays to be Rosalind) and
persuades her friend Celia (also disguised as Aliena) to marry them in a

114
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

mock ceremony. In this ceremony, Rosalind literally feigns to feign to be


what she is: truth itself, in order to win, has to be staged in a redoubled
deception in a homologous way to Alls Well in which marriage, in
order to be asserted, has to be consummated in the guise of an extramar-
ital affair.
The same overlapping of appearance with truth is often at work in
ones ideological self-perception. Recall Marxs brilliant analysis of
how, in the French Revolution of 1848, the conservative-republican
Party of Order functioned as the coalition of the two branches of
royalism (orleanists and legitimists) in the anonymous kingdom of the
Republic.40 The parliamentary deputees of the Party of Order perceived
their republicanism as a mockery: in parliamentary debates, they all the
time generated royalist slips of tongue and ridiculed the Republic to let it
be known that their true aim was to restore the kingdom. What they
were not aware of is that they themselves were duped as to the true
social impact of their rule. What they were effectively doing was to estab-
lish the conditions of bourgeois republican order that they despised so
much (by for instance guaranteeing the safety of private property). So it
is not that they were royalists who were just wearing a republican
mask: although they experienced themselves as such, it was their very
inner royalist conviction which was the deceptive front masking their
true social role. In short, far from being the hidden truth of their public
republicanism, their sincere royalism was the fantasmatic support of
their actual republicanism it was what provided the passion to their
activity. Is it not, then, that the deputees of the Party of Order were also
feigning to feign to be republicans, be what they really were?
Hegels radical conclusion is that the sign with which we are dealing
here, in corporeal expressions, in truth signies nothing (in Wahrheit
nichts bezeichnet).41 Habit is thus a strange sign which signies the fact
that it signies nothing.42 What Hlderlin put forward as the formula
of our destitute predicament, of an era in which, because gods have
abandoned us, we are signs without meaning, acquires here an unex-
pected positive interpretation. And we should take Hegels formula liter-
ally: the nothing in it has a positive weight, i.e., the sign which in truth
signies nothing is what Lacan calls signier, that which represents the
subject for another signier. The nothing is the void of the subject itself,
so that the absence of an ultimate reference means that absence itself is
the ultimate reference, and this absence is the subject itself. This is why

115
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Malabou writes: Spirit is not that which is expressed by its expressions;


it is that which originally terries spirit.43 The dimension of haunting,
the link between spirit qua the light of Reason and spirit qua obscene
ghosts, is crucial here: spirit/Reason is forever, by a structural necessity,
haunted by the obscene apparitions of its own spirit.

The human being is this night, this empty nothing, that contains every-
thing in its simplicity an unending wealth of many representations,
images, of which none belongs to him or which are not present. This
night, the interior of nature, that exists here pure self in phantasma-
gorical representations, is night all around it, in which here shoots a
bloody head there another white ghastly apparition, suddenly here
before it, and just so disappears. One catches sight of this night when
one looks human beings in the eye into a night that becomes awful.44
Again, one should not be blinded by the poetic power of this description,
but read it precisely. The rst thing to note is how the objects which
freely oat around in this night of the world are membra disiecta,
partial objects, objects detached from their organic Whole is there not
a strange echo between this description and Hegels description of the
negative power of Understanding which is able to abstract an entity
(a process, a property) from its substantial context and treat it as if
it has an existence of its own? that the accidental as such, detached
from what circumscribes it, what is bound and is actual only in its con-
text with others, should attain an existence of its own and a separate
freedom this is the tremendous power of the negative.45 It is thus as if,
in the ghastly scenery of the night of the world, we encounter some-
thing like the power of Understanding in its natural state, spirit in the guise
of a proto-spirit this, perhaps, is the most precise denition of horror:
when a higher state of development violently inscribes itself in the
lower state, in its ground/presupposition, where it cannot but appear as
a monstrous mess, a disintegration of order, a terrifying unnatural com-
bination of natural elements. With regards to todays science, where do
we encounter its horror at its purest? When genetic manipulations
go awry and generate objects never seen in nature, freaks like goats
with a gigantic ear instead of a head or a head with one eye, meaningless
accidents which nonetheless touch our deeply repressed fantasies
and thus trigger wild interpretations. The pure Self as the inner of
nature (a strange expression, since, for Hegel, nature, precisely, has no

116
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

interior: its ontological status is that of externality, not only externality


with regard to some presupposed Interior, but externality with regard to
itself) stands for this paradoxical short-circuit of the super-natural (spiri-
tual) in its natural state. Why does it occur? The only consistent answer
is a materialist one: because spirit is part of nature, and can occur/arise only
through a monstrous self/afiction (distortion, derangement) of nature.
Therein resides the paradoxical materialist edge of cheap spiritualism: it
is precisely because spirit is part of nature, because spirit does not inter-
vene into nature already constituted, ready-made somewhere else, but
has to emerge out of nature through its derangement, that there is no
spirit (Reason) without spirits (obscene ghosts), that spirit is forever
haunted by spirits.
It is from this standpoint that one should (re)read Sartres deservedly
famous description of the waiter in a caf who, with exaggerated theatri-
cality, performs the clicheic gestures of a waiter and thus plays at being
a waiter in a caf from his Being and Nothingness:

His movement is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too
rapid. He comes toward the patrons with a step a little too quick. He
bends forward a little too eagerly; his voice, his eyes express an interest
a little too solicitous for the order of the customer. Finally there he
returns, trying to imitate in his walk the inexible stiffness of some
kind of automaton . . .46

Does Sartres underlying ontological thesis that the waiter in the caf can
not be immediately a caf waiter in the sense that this inkwell is an inkwell
not point forward towards Lacans classic thesis that a madman is not
only a beggar who thinks he is a king, but also a king who thinks he is a
king? One should be very precise in this reading: as Robert Bernasconi
pointed out in his commentary, Sartres thesis is here much more rened
than a simple point about mauvaise foi and self-objectivization (in order to
cover up or escape from the void of his freedom, a subject escapes into
a rm symbolic identity). What Sartre does show is how, through the
very exaggeration in his acting as a waiter, through his very over-
identication with the role of the waiter, the waiter in question signals his
distance from it and thus asserts his subjectivity. True, this French waiter

plays at being a waiter by acting like an automaton, just as the role of


a waiter in the United States, by a strange inversion, is to play at acting

117
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

like ones friend. However, Sartres point is that, whatever game the
waiter is called upon to play, the ultimate rule that the waiter follows
is that he must break the rules, and to do so by following them in an
exaggerated manner. That is to say, the waiter does not simply follow
the unwritten rules, which would be obedience to a certain kind of
tyranny, but, instead, goes overboard in following those rules. The
waiter succeeds in rejecting the attempt to reduce him to nothing more
than being a waiter, not by refusing the role, but by highlighting the
fact that he is playing it to the point that he escapes it. The waiter does
this by overdoing things, by doing too much. The French waiter,
instead of disappearing into the role, exaggerates the movements that
make him something of an automaton in a way that draws attention
to him, just as, we can add, the quintessential North American waiter
is not so much friendly as overfriendly. Sartre uses the same word, trop,
that we saw him using in Nausea to express this human superuity.47
And it is crucial to supplement this description with its symmetrical
opposite: one is truly identied with ones role precisely when one does
not over-identify with it, but accompanies ones playing the role,
following its rules, with small violations or idiosyncrasies destined to sig-
nal that, beneath the role I am playing, there is a real person who cannot
be directly identied with it or reduced to it. In other words, it is totally
wrong to read the waiters behavior as a case of mauvaise foi: his very
exaggerated acting opens up, in a negative way, the space for his authen-
tic self, since its message is I am not what I am playing to be. The true
mauvaise foi consists precisely in embellishing my playing a role with
idiosyncratic details it is this personal touch which provides the space
of false freedom, allowing me to accommodate myself to my self-objec-
tivization in the role I am playing. (So what about those rare and weird
moments in an American cafeteria where we suddenly suspect that the
waiters friendliness is genuine?)48

4. HABITS, ANIMAL AND HUMAN

And this brings us back to our starting question: the change from animal
to properly human habit. Only humans, spiritual beings, are haunted by
spirits why? Not simply because, in contrast to animals, they have

118
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

access to universality, but because this universality is for them simultane-


ously necessary and impossible, i.e., a problem. In other words, while, for
human subjects, the place of universality is prescribed, it has to remain
empty, it cannot ever be lled in by its proper content. The specicity of
man thus concerns the relationship between universal essence and its
accidents: for animals, accidents remain mere accidents; only a human
being posits universality as such, relates to it, and can therefore reec-
tively elevate accidents into universal essence. This, after all, is why man
is a generic being (Marx): to paraphrase Heideggers denition of
Dasein, man is a being for which its genus is for itself a problem: Man can
present the genus to the degree that habit is the unforeseen element of
the genus.49
This formulation opens up an unexpected link to the notion of
hegemony as it was developed by Ernesto Laclau: there is forever a gap
between the universality of mans genus and the particular habits which
ll in its void; habits are always unexpected, contingent, an accident
elevated to universal necessity. The predominance of one or another
habit is the result of a struggle for hegemony, for which accident will
occupy the empty place of the universality. That is to say, with regard to
the relationship between universality and particularity, the contradic-
tion in the human condition a human subject perceives reality from
the singular viewpoint of subjectivity and, simultaneously, perceives
himself as included into this same reality as its part, as an object in it
means that the subject has to presuppose universality (there is a univer-
sal order, some kind of Great Chain of Being, of which he is a part),
while, simultaneously, it is forever impossible for him to entirely ll in
this universality with its particular content, to harmonize the Universal
and the Particular (since his approach to reality is forever marked
colored, twisted, distorted by his singular perspective). Universality is
always simultaneously necessary and impossible.
Let me begin with Ernesto Laclaus concept of hegemony which
provides an exemplary matrix of the relationship between universality,
historical contingency, and the limit of an impossible Real one should
always keep in mind that we are dealing here with a distinct concept
whose specicity is often missed (or reduced to some proto-Gramscian
vague generality) by those who refer to it. The key feature of the concept
of hegemony resides in the contingent connection between intra-social
differences (elements within the social space) and the limit that separates

119
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

society itself from non-society (chaos, utter decadence, dissolution


of all social links). The limit between the social and its exteriority, the
non-social, can only articulate itself in the guise of a difference (by map-
ping itself onto a difference) between elements of social space. In other
words, radical antagonism can only be represented in a distorted way,
through the particular differences internal to the system; external differ-
ences are always already also internal, and, furthermore, that the link
between the two is ultimately contingent, the result of political struggle
for hegemony.
The standard anti-Hegelian counter-argument here is, of course: but is
this irreducible gap between the Universal (frame) and its particular
content not what characterizes the Kantian nite subjectivity? Is not the
Hegelian concrete universality the most radical expression of the
fantasy of full reconciliation between the Universal and the Particular? Is
its basic feature not the self-generation of the entire particular content
out of the self-movement of universality itself? Against this common
reproach, one should insist on how Laclaus notion of hegemony is effec-
tively close to the Hegelian notion of concrete universality in which the
specic difference overlaps with the difference constitutive of the genus
itself, as in Laclaus hegemony in which the antagonistic gap between
society and its external limit, non-society (the dissolution of social link),
is mapped onto an intra-social structural difference. Laclau himself
rejects the Hegelian reconciliation between Universal and Particular on
behalf of the gap that forever separates the empty/impossible Universal
from the contingent particular content that hegemonizes it. If, however,
we take a closer look at Hegel, we see that insofar as every particular
species of a genus does not t its universal genus when we nally
arrive at a particular species that fully ts its notion, the very universal
notion is transformed into another notion. No existing historical shape of
State fully ts the notion of State the necessity of dialectical passage
from State (objective spirit, history) into Religion (absolute spirit)
involves the fact that the only existing State that effectively ts its notion
is a religious community which, precisely, is no longer a State. Here we
encounter the properly dialectical paradox of concrete universality qua
historicity: in the relationship between a genus and its subspecies, one of
these subspecies will always be the element that negates the very univer-
sal feature of the genus. Different nations have different versions of
soccer; Americans do not have soccer, because baseball is their soccer.

120
DISCIPLINE BETWEEN THE TWO FREEDOMS

See also Hegels famous claim that modern people do not pray in the
morning, because reading the newspaper is their morning prayer. In the
same way, in the disintegrating socialism, writers and other cultural clubs
did act as political parties. Perhaps, in the history of cinema, the best
example is the relationship between western and sci- space operas:
today, we no longer have substantial westerns, because space operas
occupied their place, i.e. space operas are todays westerns. So, in the classi-
cation of westerns, we would have to supplement the standard subspe-
cies with space opera as todays non-western stand-in for western. Crucial
is here this intersection of different genuses, this partial overlapping of
two universals: western and space opera are not simply two different
genres, they intersect, i.e. in a certain epoch, space opera becomes a sub-
species of western (or, western is sublated in space opera) . . . In the
same way, woman becomes one of the subspecies of man, Heideggerian
Daseinsanalyse one of the subspecies of phenomenology, sublating the
preceding universality.
The impossible point of self-objectivization would have been precisely
the point at which universality and its particular content would have
been fully harmonized in short, where there would have been no
struggle for hegemony. And this brings us back to madness: its most suc-
cinct denition is that of a direct harmony between universality and its
accidents, of the cancellation of the gap that separates the two for a
madman, the object which is my impossible stand-in within objectal
reality loses its virtual character and becomes its full integral part. In
contrast to madness, habit avoids this trap of direct identication by way
of its virtual character: the subjects identication with a habit is not a
direct identication with some positive feature, but the identication
with a disposition, with a virtuality. Habit is the outcome of a struggle
for hegemony: it is an accident elevated to essence, to universal necessity,
i.e., made to ll in its empty place.

121
CHAPTER THREE
Fichtes Laughter
Slavoj iek

Whenever we are dealing with an ofcial progressive succession of


philosophers, the truly interesting thing is to consider how a philosopher
who was, according to this ofcial line, overcome or completed by
his successor(s), reacts to his successor(s). Say, how does (or would)
Plato react to Aristotle, or Wagner to Nietzsche, or Husserl to Heidegger,
or Hegel to Marx?1
The most intriguing case of this rebellion of the vanquished takes
place in German Idealism, where each of the predecessors in the
ofcial line of progress Kant-Fichte-Schelling-Hegel(-late Schelling)
reacted to the critique or interpretation of his work by his successor.
While Fichte claimed to nally accomplish Kants philosophy with his
Wissenschaftslehre Kants disparaging remarks about Fichte are well-
known: he rejected as meaninglessly tautological the very term Wissen-
schaftslehre (doctrine about knowledge). Fichtes subjective idealism is
then followed by Schellings philosophy-of-identity, which supplements
the transcendental-subjective genesis of reality with philosophy of
nature; Fichte bitterly rejected this supplement as a misreading of his
Wissenschaftslehre, as one can read in their correspondence. Of course,
Schelling himself did not hesitate to retort that Fichte radically changed
his position as a reaction to Schellings critique. Hegels overcoming of
Schelling is a case in itself: Schellings reaction to Hegels idealist dialectic
was so strong and profound that more and more it is counted as the next
(and concluding) step in the inner development of German Idealism.2

122
FICHTES LAUGHTER

Schellings rst and decisive break out of the constraints of his early
philosophy-of-identity is his Treatise on the Essence of Human Freedom from
1809, to which Hegel reacted in his (posthumously published) lectures
on the history of philosophy with a brief and ridiculously inadequate
dismissal which totally misses the point of Schellings masterpiece: what
is today considered one of the highpoints of the entire history of philoso-
phy appears to Hegel as an insignicant, minor, and obscure essay. No
wonder, then, that the topic among todays Hegel-scholars is rather:
what would have been Hegels rejoinder to Schellings critique of dialec-
tics as a mere negative philosophy? Among others, Dieter Henrich and
Frederick Beiser have tried to reconstruct a Hegelian answer.
What is the philosophical status of these retroactive rejoinders? It is all
too easy to claim (in the postmodern vein of the end of the grand narra-
tives) that they bear witness to the failure of every general scheme of
progress: they do not so much undermine the underlying line of succes-
sion (from Kant to late Schelling) as, rather, bring forth its most interesting
and lively moment, the moment when, as it were, a thought rebels against
its reduction to a term in the chain of development and asserts its abso-
lute right or claim. Sometimes, such reactions are mere outbursts of a
helpless disorientation; sometimes, they are themselves the true moments
of progress. That is to say, when the Old is attacked by the New, this rst
appearance of the New is as a rule at and nave the true dimension of
the New arises only when the Old reacts to the (rst appearance of) the
New. Pascal reacted from a Christian standpoint to scientic secular moder-
nity, and his reaction (his struggling with the problem of how one can
remain a Christian in the abyssal new conditions of the secular scientic
universe) tells us much more about modernity than its direct partisans. Or,
in the history of cinema, it was the silent directors resisting sound, from
Chaplin to Eisenstein, who brought to light the truly shattering dimension
of sound cinema. The true progress emerges from the reaction of the Old
to the progress. True revolutionaries are always reected conservatives.

1. FROM FICHTES ICH TO HEGELS SUBJECT

Arguably the most interesting case of such a retroactive rejoinder is


Fichtes late philosophy, in which he (implicitly or explicitly) answers his

123
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

critics, primarily Schelling: this response is most audible in Fichtes shift


from the self-positing I to the asubjective divine Being as the ultimate
ground of all reality. Here is Gnter Zllers succinct description of this
basic shift in Fichtes doctrine from the Jena period (17941799) to the
Berlin period (17991814): in the Jena period,

the I, in its capacity as absolute I, had functioned as the principle of all


knowledge. After 1800, the I provides the form (Ichform: I-form), of
knowledge as such. The ground is now no longer identied with the
I qua absolute I but with something absolute prior to and originally
independent of the I (Seyn, Being, or Gott, God). By contrast, the
I qua I-form is the basic mode for the appearance of the absolute,
which does not appear itself and as such.3
One should be very precise in reading this shift: it is not simply that
Fichte abandons the I as the absolute ground, reducing it to a subordi-
nate moment of the trans-subjective Absolute, to a mode or form of
appearance of this Absolute. If anything, it is only now (after Jena) that
Fichte correctly grasped the basic feature of the I: I is as such a split of
the Absolute, the minimal difference of its self-appearing. In other
words, the notion of I as the absolute ground of all being secretly but
unavoidably substantivizes the subject, it reduces subject to substance.
Fichte is, however, not able to clearly formulate this insight and his
limitation is discernible in the wrong answer he gives to the crucial ques-
tion: to whom does the Absolute appear in the I-form? Fichtes answer
is: to (subjective) appearance, to the subject to whom the Absolute
appears. What he is not able to assert is that, in appearing to the subject,
the Absolute also appears to itself, i.e., that the subjective reection of
the Absolute is the Absolutes self-reection.
The key text is here the Wissenschaftslehre from 1812 in contrast to the
Jena versions of Wissenschaftslehre from 17941799. In these early
versions, Fichtes strategy is the standard subjective-idealist procedure of
critically denouncing the reied notion of objective reality, of things
existing out there in the world of which the subject is also part: one
should dispel this necessary illusion of independent objective reality by
way of deploying its subjective genesis. Here, the only Absolute is the
activity of spontaneous self-positing of the absolute I: the absolute
I designates the coincidence of being and acting [Tat-Handlung], or,
simply put, it is what it does. In 1812, however, Fichte takes a further step

124
FICHTES LAUGHTER

back: it is no longer the absoluteness of the things that is unveiled as an


unavoidable illusion, but the absoluteness of the I itself.4 The self-posit-
ing of the I is itself an illusory appearance, an image of the only true
Absolute, the trans-subjective immovable absolute Being (God).
Already back in the 1790s, Madame de Staels reaction upon hearing
about Fichtes self-positing absolute I was that it is like Baron Mnch-
hausen who lifted himself out of the swamp by pulling himself up by his
hair: it is as if the late Fichte accepted this critique, conceding that the
self-reecting I is a chimera oating in the air, which has to be grounded
in some rm, positive Absolute. The critical analysis has thus to accom-
plish a further step back: rst from objective reality to the transcendental
I, then from the transcendental I to the absolute Being. The Is self-
positing is an image of the divine Absolute, not the Absolute itself:

the Absolute appears, as life teaches us. The appearance of the


Absolute means that it appears as the Absolute. Since determinacy
comes with negation, the Absolute must bring forth its own opposite,
a non-Absolute, to be able to appear as the Absolute. This non-Abso-
lute is the Absolutes appearance. The appearance is also that to which
the Absolute appears. Thus, the Absolute can appear to the appearance
only if at the same time its opposite, namely the appearance, appears
to the appearance as well. There is no appearing of the Absolute with-
out an appearing of the appearance to itself, that is, without reectivity
of the appearance. Since the Absolute appears necessarily, the self-
reection of the appearance is necessary too.5
A double mediation has to be accomplished here. If, in the appearing of
the Absolute, the Absolute appears as the Absolute, this means that the
Absolute has to appear as absolute in contrast to other mere appear-
ances: so there must be a cut in the domain of appearances, a cut between
mere appearances and the appearance through which the Absolute
itself transpires. In other words, the gap between appearance and true
Being must inscribe itself into the very domain of appearing.
But what this reexivity of appearing means is that the Absolute also
exposes itself to the danger of merely appearing to be the Absolute the
appearing of the Absolute turns into the (misleading, illusory) appearing
to be the Absolute. Is (from a materialist standpoint, of course) the entire
history of religion not the history of such false appearances of the
Absolute? At this level, the Absolute is its own appearing, i.e., an

125
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

organization of appearances that evokes the mirage that there is, hidden
behind it, an Absolute which appears (shines through it). Here, the
illusion effectively is no longer to mistake appearing for being, but to
mistake being for appearing: the only being of the Absolute is its
appearing, and the illusion is that this appearing is a mere image behind
which there is a transcendent true Being. So when Fichte writes every
error without exception consists in mistaking images for being. The
Wissenschaftslehre has for the rst time pronounced how far this error
extends through showing that being is only in God,6 he misses the error
which is the exact opposite of mistaking images for being (i.e. of taking
as the true being what is effectively only its image), namely the error of
mistaking being for images (i.e., of taking as merely an image of the true
being what is effectively the true being itself). At this level, one should
thus accept the Derridean theological conclusion: God is not an
absolute Being persisting in itself, it is the pure virtuality of a promise, the
pure appearing of itself. In other words, the Absolute beyond appear-
ances coincides with an absolute appearance, an appearance beneath
which there is no substantial Being.
The second half of this double mediation is thus: if the Absolute is to
appear, appearing itself must appear to itself as appearing, and Fichte con-
ceives this self-appearing of appearance as subjective self-reection. Fichte
is right to endorse a two-step critical approach (rst from the object to its
subjective constitution, then the meta-critical deploying of the genesis of
the abyssal mirage of subjects self-positing). What he gets wrong is the
nature of the Absolute that grounds subjectivity itself: the late Fichtes
Absolute is an immovable transcendent in-itself, external to the movement
of reection. What Fichte cannot think is the life, movement, and media-
tion in the Absolute itself: what he misses is how, precisely, the Absolutes
appearing is not a mere appearance, but a self-actualization, a self-revela-
tion, of the Absolute. This immanent dynamics does not make the Absolute
itself a subject, but it inscribes subjectivization into its very core.
What Fichte was not able to grasp is the speculative identity of these
two extreme poles (pure absolute Being and the appearance appearing
to itself): the Is self-positing reexivity is, quite literally, the image of
the Absolute as self-grounded Being. Therein resides the objective irony
of Fichtes development: Fichte, the philosopher of subjective self-
positing, ends up reducing subjectivity to a mere appearance of an immov-
able absolute in-itself. The proper Hegelian reproach to Fichte is thus not

126
FICHTES LAUGHTER

that he is too subjective, but, on the contrary, that he is unable to really


think substance also as subject: the shift of his thought towards the asu-
bjective Absolute is not a reaction to his earlier excessive subjectivism, but
a reaction to his inability to formulate the core of subjectivity.
Hegels true novelty can be seen apropos the standard designation
of the post-Kantian development as forming the triad of Fichtes sub-
jective idealism, Schellings objective idealism, and Hegels absolute
idealism. The designation of Schellings Identittsphilosophie as objective
idealism is, however, deceiving: the whole point of his Identittsphi-
losophie is that subjective idealism (transcendental philosophy) and objec-
tive idealism (philosophy of nature) are two approaches to the Third, the
Absolute beyond or beneath the duality of spirit and nature, of subject
and object, underlying them both and manifesting itself in both of them.
(Late Fichte does something similar when he passes from the transcen-
dental I to the divine Being as the absolute ground of all reality.) In this
sense, it is meaningless to call Hegels philosophy absolute idealism: his
point is precisely that there is no need for a third element, the medium
or ground, beyond subject and object-substance. We start with objectiv-
ity, and the subject is nothing but the self-mediation of objectivity. When,
in Hegels dialectics, we have a pair of opposites, their unity is not a third,
an underlying medium, but one of the two: a genus is its own species, or,
a genus ultimately has only one species, which is why specic difference
coincides with the difference between genus and species.
We can thus globally discern three positions: metaphysical, transcenden-
tal, and speculative. In the rst one, reality is simply perceived as existing
out there, and the task of philosophy is to analyze its basic structure.
In the second one, a philosopher investigates the subjective conditions of
possibility of objective reality, its transcendental genesis; in the third one,
subjectivity is re-inscribed into reality, but not simply reduced to a part
of objective reality. That is, while the subjective constitution of reality,
the split that separates the subject from the in-itself, is fully admitted,
this very split is transposed back into reality as its kenotic self-emptying
(to use the Christian theological term, as Hegel does). Appearance is not
reduced to reality, the very process of appearance is conceived from the
standpoint of reality, so that the question is not How, if at all, can we
pass from appearance to reality?, but How can something like appear-
ance arise in the midst of reality? What are the conditions for reality to
appear to itself?

127
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Hegelian reection is thus the opposite of the transcendental approach


that reexively regresses from the object to its subjective conditions of
possibility. Even philosophy after the linguistic turn remains at this
transcendental level, deploying the transcendental dimension of lan-
guage, i.e., how language, the horizon of possible meaning sustained by
language in which we dwell, functions as the transcendental condition
of possibility of all our experience of reality. Here, then, signied falls
into the signier, i.e., signied is an effect of the signier, it is accounted
for in the terms of the symbolic order as its transcendentally constitutive
condition.7 What dialectical reection adds to this is another reexive
twist, which grounds the very subjective-transcendental site of enuncia-
tion in the self-movement of the Thing itself: here, signier falls into
the signied, the act of enunciation falls into the enunciated, the sign of
the thing falls into the thing itself. How do we proceed when we are
challenged to explain the meaning of a term X to someone who, while
more or less uent in our language, doesnt know this specic term? We
engage in proposing a vast series of synonyms, paraphrases, descriptions
of situations where this term would t . . . In this way, through the very
failure of our endeavor, we circumscribe an empty place, the place of the
right word, precisely the word we are trying to explain. So at some point,
after our paraphrases fail, all we can do is to conclude skeptically:
In short, it is X! Far from functioning as a simple recognition of failure,
this turn can generate an effect of insight: that is, if through our failed
paraphrase we have successfully circumscribed the place of the term to be
explained. At this point, as Lacan would have put it, signier falls into
the signied, the term becomes part of its own denition.
This brings us to the formal denition of subject: a subject tries to artic-
ulate (express) itself in a signifying chain, this articulation fails, and by
means and through this failure, the subject emerges: the subject is the
failure of its signifying representation this is why Jacques Lacan writes
the subject of the signier as $, as barred. Consider, for instance, a love
letter: the very failure of the writer to formulate his declaration in a clear
and efcient way, his oscillations, the letters fragmentation, etc., can in
themselves be the proof (perhaps the necessary and the only reliable
proof) that the professed love is authentic here, the very failure to
deliver the message properly is the sign of its authenticity. If the message
is delivered in a smooth way, it arouses suspicions that it is part of a well-
planned approach, or that the writer loves himself, the beauty of his

128
FICHTES LAUGHTER

writing, more than his love-object, i.e., that the object is effectively
reduced to a pretext for engaging in the narcissistically satisfying activity
of writing. It is a little bit like the old musical mono-recordings: the very
cracking sounds that lter and disturb the pure reproduction of the
human voice generate the effect of authenticity, the impression that we
are listening to (what once was) a real person singing, while the very
perfection of modern recordings with all their Dolby effects etc. strangely
de-realizes what we hear. This is why the enlightened New Age indi-
vidual who extols us to fully realize/express our true Self cannot but
appear as its opposite, as a mechanical, depthless, subject who blindly
repeats his/her mantra.
What this means is that the dialectical reversal is, at its most radical,
the shift of the predicate into the position of subject. Let us clarify this
key feature of the Hegelian dialectic apropos the well-known male-
chauvinist notion of how, in contrast to mans rm self-identity, the
essence of woman is dispersed, elusive, displaced; the thing to do here is
to move from this claim that the essence of woman is forever dispersed,
to the more radical claim that this dispersion/displacement as such is the
essence of femininity. This is what Hegel deployed as the dialectical
shift in which the predicate itself turns into the subject: I found the
essence of femininity. But one cannot nd it, femininity is dispersed,
displaced . . . Well, this dispersion is the essence of femininity . . .
And subject is not just an example here, but the very formal structure
of it: subject as such is a subjectivized predicate; subject is not only
always already displaced, etc., it is this displacement. The supreme case
of this shift constitutive of the dimension of subjectivity is that of suppo-
sition. Lacan rst deployed the notion of the analyst as the subject
supposed to know which arises through transference (supposed to know
what (?) the meaning of the patients symptoms). However, he soon
realizes that he is dealing with a more general structure of supposition in
which a gure of the Other is not only supposed to know, but can also
believe, enjoy, cry and laugh, or even not know for us (from the Tibetan
praying mills to TV canned laughter). This structure of presupposition is
not innite: it is strictly limited, constrained by the four elements of the
discourse (S1, the master-signier; S2, the chain of knowledge; a, the
surplus-enjoyment; $, the subject): S1 subject supposed to believe;
S2 subject supposed to know; a subject supposed to enjoy . . . and
what about $? Do we get a subject supposed to be subject? What would

129
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

this mean? What if we read it as standing for the very structure of sup-
position: it is not only that the subject is supposed to have a quality, to do
or undergo something (to know, enjoy . . .) the subject itself is a suppo-
sition, i.e., the subject is never directly given as a positive substantial
entity, we never directly encounter it, it is merely a ickering void
supposed between the two signiers. (We encounter here again the
Hegelian passage from subject to predicate: from the subject supposed
to . . . to the subject itself as a supposition.) That is to say, what, precisely,
is a subject? Let us imagine a proposition, a statement how, when,
does this statement get subjectivized? When some reexive feature
inscribes into it the subjective attitude (for example, a love letter is sub-
jectivized when the writers turmoil and oscillation blurs the message)
in this precise sense, a signier represents the subject for another
signier. The subject is the absent X that has to be supposed in order to
account for this reexive twist, for this distortion. And Lacan here goes all
the way: the subject is not only supposed by the external observer-
listener of a signifying chain, it is in itself a supposition. The subject is inac-
cessible to itself as Thing, in its noumenal identity, and, as such, it is
forever haunted by itself as object: what are all Doppelganger gures if
not gures of myself as an object that haunts me? In other words, not
only others are a supposition to me (I can only suppose their existence
beneath the reexive distortion of a signifying chain), I myself am no less
a supposition to myself: something to be presumed (there must be an X
that I am, the this I or He or It (the thing) which thinks, as Kant put
it), and never directly accessed. Humes famous observation that, no
matter how close and deep I look into myself, all I will nd there are
specic ideas, particular mental states, perceptions, emotions, etc., never
a Self, misses the point: this non-accessibility to itself as an object is
constitutive of being a self.

2. ABSOLUTE AND APPEARANCE

This reversal-towards-itself is the key dialectical moment. For Hegel, if


the Idea cannot adequately represent itself, if its representation is dis-
torted/decient, then this distortion simultaneously signals a limitation/
deciency of the Idea itself. And, in order to get at the speculative core

130
FICHTES LAUGHTER

of Hegelian dialectics, one should make a step further: not only does the
universal Idea always appear in a distorted/displaced way; this Idea is
nothing other than the distortion/displacement, the self-inadequacy, of the
particular with regard to itself in strict homology with the move from
the subject supposed to . . . to subject itself as a supposition. One could
even claim that this reversal as such, formally, denes subjectivity: sub-
stance appears in phenomena, while a subject is nothing but its own
appearance. (And one can multiply these formulas: the universal is
nothing but the inadequacy, the non-identity, of the particular to/with
itself; the essence is nothing but the inadequacy of the appearance to
itself, etc.) This does not mean that the subject is the stupid tautology of
the Real (things just are what they seem to be, the way they seem to
be), but, much more precisely, that the subject is nothing but its own
appearing, the appearing reected-into-itself,8 the paradoxical torsion in
which a thing starts to function as a substitute for itself.
We encounter the Hegelian oppositional determination (gegenstzliche
Bestimmung), for example, in the prominent gure of the gay basher rap-
ing a homosexual, where homophobia encounters itself in its opposi-
tional determination, i.e., tautology (self-identity) appears as the highest
contradiction.9 A further example is provided by the extreme case of
interpassivity, when I tape a movie instead of simply watching it on TV,
and when this postponement takes a fully self-reected form: worrying
that there will be something wrong with the recording, I anxiously watch
TV while the tape is running, just to be sure that everything is alright
with the recording, so that the lm will be there on the tape, ready for a
future viewing. In this case, the paradox is that I do indeed watch a lm,
even very closely, but in a kind of suspended state, without really follow-
ing it all that interests me is that everything is really there, that the
recording is alright. Do we not nd something similar in a certain per-
verse sexual economy in which I perform the act only in order to be sure
that I can in future really perform the act: even if the act is, in reality,
indistinguishable from the normal act done for pleasure, as an end-in-
itself, the underlying libidinal economy is totally different.
Watching a movie appears here as its own oppositional determination
in other words, the structure is that of the Mobius strip: if we progress
far enough on one side, we reach our starting point again (watching the
movie, a gay sex act), but on the obverse side of the band. Lewis Carroll
was therefore right: a country can serve as its own map insofar as the

131
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

model/map is the thing itself in its oppositional determination, i.e.,


insofar as an invisible screen ensures that the thing is not taken to be
itself. In this precise sense, the primordial difference is not between
things themselves, also not between things and their signs, but between
the thing and the void of an invisible screen which distorts our percep-
tion of the thing so that we do not take the thing for itself. The move-
ment from things to their signs is not that of replacement of the thing by
its sign, but that of the thing itself becoming the sign of not another
thing, but itself, the void in its very core. And the same goes for the
relationship of masking. In December 2001, Argentinians took to the
streets to protest against the current government, and especially against
Cavallo, the economy minister. When the crowd gathered around
Cavallos building, threatening to storm it, he escaped wearing a mask of
himself (sold in costume shops so that people could mock him by wear-
ing his mask). It thus seems that at least Cavallo did learn something
from the widely spread Lacanian movement in Argentina the fact that
a thing is its own best mask. And is this also not the ultimate denition
of the divinity god also has to wear a mask of himself? Perhaps god is
the name for this supreme split between the absolute as the noumenal
Thing and the absolute as the appearance of itself, for the fact that the
two are the same, that the difference between the two is purely formal.
In this precise sense, god names the supreme contradiction: god the
absolute irrepresentable Beyond has to appear as such. Along the same
lines, recall the scene from Spike Lees formidable Bamboozled, in which
black artists themselves blacken their faces in the style of Al Johnson:
perhaps, wearing a black mask is the only strategy for them to appear
white (i.e. to generate the expectation that the true face beneath their
black mask is white). In this properly Lacanian deception, wearing
a black mask is destined to conceal the fact that we are black no wonder,
then, that the effect of discovering black under black, when they rinse off
their masks, is shocking. Perhaps as a defense against this shock, we
nonetheless spontaneously perceive their true face beneath the mask as
more black than their mask, as if attesting to the fact that the blackening
of their face is a strategy of their assimilation into the white culture . . .10
Recall the scene, from Vertigo, of Scotties and Judys initial evening
date (at Ernies again, as with Madeleine), with the couple seated at a
table opposite each other, obviously failing to engage in a meaningful
conversation. All of a sudden, Scotties gaze gets xed on some point

132
FICHTES LAUGHTER

behind Judy, and we see that it is a woman vaguely similar to Madeleine,


dressed in the same gray gown. When Judy notices what attracted
Scotties gaze, she is, of course, deeply hurt. The crucial moment here is
when we see, from Scotties point-of-view, the two of them in the same
shot: Judy on the right side, close to him, the gray woman to the left, in
the background. Again, we get the vulgar reality side-by-side with the
ethereal apparition of the ideal. The split from the shot of Midge and the
portrait of Carlotta is here externalized onto two different persons: Judy
right here and the momentary spectral apparition of Madeleine with
the additional irony, missed by Scottie, that the vulgar Judy really is the
Madeleine for whom he is desperately seeking among eeting appear-
ances of strangers. The brief moment when Scottie is deluded into think-
ing that what he sees is Madeleine is the moment at which the Absolute
appears: it appears as such in the very domain of appearances, in those
sublime moments when a supra-sensible dimension shines through in
our ordinary reality. When Plato dismisses art as the copy of a copy,
when he introduces three ontological levels (ideas, their material copies,
and copies of these copies), what gets lost is that the Idea can only emerge
in the distance that separates our ordinary material reality (second level)
from its copy. When we copy a material object, what we effectively copy,
what our copy refers to, is never this particular object itself but its Idea.
It is similar with a mask which engenders a third reality, a ghost in the
mask which is not the face hidden beneath it. In this precise sense, the
Idea is the appearance as appearance (as Hegel and Lacan put it): the
Idea is something that appears when reality (the rst-level copy/
imitation of the Idea) is itself copied. It is that which in the copy is more
than the original itself. It is against this background that one should grasp
the Kafkaesque claim from Hegels Aesthetics that a portrait of a person
can be more like the individual than the actual individual himself: what
this implies is that the person itself is never fully itself, that it does not
coincide with its Idea. No wonder that Plato reacted in such a panicky
way against the threat of art: as Lacan pointed out in his Seminar XI, art
(as the copy of a copy) does not compete with material objects as direct,
rst-level copies of the Idea; rather, it competes with the supra-sensible
Idea itself.
In one of Agatha Christies stories, Hercule Poirot discovers that an
ugly nurse is the same person as a beauty he met on a trans-Atlantic
voyage: she merely put on a wig and obfuscated her natural beauty.

133
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Hastings, Poirots Watson-like companion, sadly remarks how, if a


beautiful woman can make herself appear ugly, then the same can also
be done in the opposite direction what, then, remains in mans infatu-
ation beyond deception? Does this insight into the unreliability of the
beloved woman not announce the end of love? Poirot answers: No, my
friend, it announces the beginning of wisdom. Such a skepticism, such
an awareness of the deceptive nature of feminine beauty, misses the
point, which is that feminine beauty is nonetheless absolute, an absolute
which appears: no matter how fragile and deceptive this beauty is at the
level of substantial reality, what transpires in/through in the moment of
Beauty is an Absolute there is more truth in the appearance than in
what is hidden beneath it. Therein resides Platos deep insight: Ideas are
not the hidden reality beneath appearances (Plato was well aware that
this hidden reality is that of ever-changing corruptive and corrupted
matter); Ideas are nothing but the very form of appearance, this form as
such or, as Lacan succinctly rendered Platos point: the Suprasensible is
appearance as appearance. For this reason, neither Plato nor Christianity
are forms of Wisdom they are both anti-Wisdom embodied.
What this means is that in conceiving art, we should return without
shame to Plato. Platos reputation suffers because of his claim that poets
should be thrown out of the city a rather sensible advice, judging from
my post-Yugoslav experience, where ethnic cleansing was prepared by
poets dangerous dreams (the Bosnian Serb leader Radovan Karadzic
being only one among them). If the West has the industrial-military
complex, we in the ex-Yugoslavia had a poetic-military complex: the
post-Yugoslav war was triggered by the explosive mixture of the poetic
and the military component. So, from a Platonic standpoint, what does a
poem about the holocaust do? It provides its description without place:
in renders the Idea of holocaust.
Recall the old Catholic strategy to guard men against the temptation of
the esh: when you see in front of you a voluptuous feminine body,
imagine how it will look in a couple of decades the dried skin, sagging
breasts . . . (Or, even better, imagine what lurks now already beneath
the skin: raw esh and bones, inner uids, half-digested food and excre-
ments . . .) Far from enacting a return to the Real destined to break the
imaginary spell of the body, such a procedure equals the escape from
the Real, the Real which announces itself in the seductive appearance of
the naked body. That is to say, in the opposition between the spectral

134
FICHTES LAUGHTER

appearance of the sexualized body and the repulsive body in decay, it is


the spectral appearance which is the Real, and the decaying body which
is reality we take recourse to the decaying body in order to avoid the
deadly fascination of the Real which threatens to draw us into its vortex
of jouissance.
In Alls Well That Ends Well, Shakespeare provided a breathtakingly
rened insight into such a redoubling of appearance. Count Bertram,
who on the Kings orders was forced to marry Helen, a common doctors
daughter, refuses to live with her and consummate the marriage, telling
her that he will agree to be her husband only if she removes the
ancestral ring from his nger and bears his child; at the same time,
Bertram tries to seduce the young and beautiful Diana. Helen and Diana
concoct a plan to bring Bertram back to his lawful wife. Diana agrees to
spend the night with Bertram, telling him to visit her chamber at mid-
night; there, in darkness, the couple exchange their rings and make love.
However, unknowingly to Bertram, the woman with whom he spent the
night was not Diana but Helen, his wife. When they are later confronted,
he has to admit that both of his conditions for recognizing the marriage
are met. Helen removed his ancestral ring and bears his child. What,
then, is the status of this bed-trick? At the very end of Act III, Helen
herself provides a wonderful denition:

Why then to-night / Let us assay our plot; which, if it speed, / Is wicked
meaning in a lawful deed / And lawful meaning in a wicked act,
/ Where both not sin, and yet a sinful fact:/But lets about it.

We are effectively dealing both with a wicked meaning in a lawful deed


(what can be more lawful than a consummated marriage, a husband
sleeping with his wife? And yet the meaning is wicked: Bertram thought
he is sleeping with Diana) and a lawful meaning in a wicked act (the
meaning Helens intention is lawful, to sleep with her husband, but
the act is wicked: she deceives her husband, who does it thinking he is
cheating on her). Their affair is not sin, and yet a sinful fact: not sin,
because what happened is merely a consummation of marriage; but a
sinful fact, something that involved intentional cheating from both part-
ners. The true question here is not merely whether alls well that ends
well, whether the nal outcome (nothing wrong effectively happened,
and the married couple is reunited, the marriage bond fully asserted)
cancels the sinful tricks and intentions, but a more radical one: what if

135
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

the rule of law can only be asserted through wicked (sinful) meanings
and acts? What if, in order to rule, the law has to rely on the subterra-
nean interplay of cheatings and deceptions? This, also, is what Lacan
aims at with his paradoxical proposition il ny a pas de rapport sexuel (there
is no sexual relationship): was not Bertrams situation during the night
of love the fate of most married couples? You make love to your lawful
partner while cheating in your mind, fantasizing that you are doing it
with another partner. The actual sex-relationship has to be sustained by
this fantasmatic supplement.
One can imagine a variation of Shakespeares plot in which this fantas-
matic dimension would have been even more palpable, a variation along
the lines of the Jewish story of Jacob who fell in love with Rachel and
wanted to marry her; his father, however, wanted him to marry Leah,
Rachels elder sister. In order that Jacob will not be tricked by the father
or by Leah, Rachel taught him so that that he would recognize her at
night in bed. Before the sexual event, Rachel felt guilty towards her
sister, and told her what the signs were. Leah asked Rachel what will
happen if he recognizes her voice. So the decision was that Rachel will lie
under the bed, and while Jacob is making love to Leah, Rachel will make
the sounds, so he wont recognize that hes having sex with the wrong
sister . . .11 So we can also imagine, in Shakespeare, Diana hidden beneath
the bed where Helen and Bertram are copulating, making the appropri-
ate sounds so that Bertram will not realize that he is not having sex with
her, her voice serving as the support of the fantasmatic dimension.
From the Lacanian perspective, what then is appearance at its most
radical? Imagine a man having an affair about which his wife doesnt
know, so when he is meeting his lover, he pretends to be on a business
trip or something similar; after some time, he gathers the courage
and tells the wife the truth that, when he is away, he is staying with his
lover. However, at this point, when the front of happy marriage falls
apart, the mistress breaks down and, out of sympathy with the aban-
doned wife, avoids meeting her lover. What should the husband do in
order not to give his wife the wrong signal? How not to let her think that
the fact that he is no longer so often on business trips means that he is
returning to her? He has to fake the affair and leave home for a couple
of days, generating the wrong impression that the affair is continuing,
while, in reality, he is just staying with some friend. This is appearance at
its purest: it occurs not when we put up a deceiving screen to conceal the

136
FICHTES LAUGHTER

transgression, but when we fake that there is a transgression to be


concealed. In this precise sense, fantasy itself is for Lacan a semblance: it
is not primarily the mask which conceals the Real beneath, but, rather,
the fantasy of what is hidden behind the mask. So, for instance, the
fundamental male fantasy of the woman is not her seductive appear-
ance, but the idea that this dazzling appearance conceals some impon-
derable mystery.

3. THE FICHTEAN WAGER

What are the philosophical roots of Fichtes error with regard to the
status of appearing? Let us return to the early Fichte (of the Jena period)
who is usually perceived as a radical subjective idealist: there are two
possible descriptions of our reality, dogmatic (Spinozean deterministic
materialism: we are part of reality, submitted to its laws, an object among
others, our freedom is an illusion) and idealist (the subject is autono-
mous and free, as the absolute I it spontaneously posits reality); reason-
ing alone cannot decide between the two, the decision is practical, or,
to quote his famous dictum, which philosophy one chooses depends
on what kind of man one is. Of course, Fichte passionately opts for
idealism . . . However, a closer look quickly makes clear that this is not
Fichtes position. Idealism is for Fichte not a new positive teaching that
should replace materialism, but to quote Peter Preusss perspicuous
formulation

merely an intellectual exercise open to anyone who accepts the auton-


omy of theoretical reason. Its function is to destroy the current deter-
ministic dogma. But if it were now itself to become a theoretical
understanding of reality it would be every bit as bad. While human
life is no longer seen as a mere natural event it would now be seen as
a mere dream. We would be no more human in the one understand-
ing than the other. In the one understanding I am the material to
which life happens as an event, in the other I am the uninvolved spec-
tator of the dream which is my life. Fichte nds each of these to be
equal cause for lament. No, the task is not to replace one theoretical
philosophy with another one, but to get out of philosophy altogether.

137
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Philosophical reason is not autonomous, but has its foundation in


practical reason, i.e., the will. [. . .] Fichte is widely misunderstood as
opting for idealism over realism. [. . .] neither realism (of whatever
kind) nor idealism (of whatever kind) yields knowledge, theoretical
understanding of reality. Both yield unacceptable nonsense if taken to
their nal conclusions. And precisely this yields the valuable conclu-
sion that the intellect is not autonomous. The intellect, to function
properly as part of a whole human being, must relate to the activity of
that being. Human beings do contemplate and try to understand real-
ity, but not from a standpoint outside the world. Human beings are in
the world and it is as agents in the world that we require an under-
standing of the world. The intellect is not autonomous but has its
foundation in our agency, in practical reason or will.12
How does the will provide this foundation?

[. . .] in an act of faith it transforms the apparent picture show of


experience into an objective world of things and of other people. [. . .]
faith indicates a free (i.e., theoretically unjustiable) act of mind by
which the conditions within which we can act and use our intellects
come to be for us.13

Fichtes position is thus not that a passive observer of reality chooses


determinism, and an engaged agent idealism: taken as an explanatory
theory, idealism does not lead to practical engagement, but to the
passive position of being the observer of ones own dream (reality is
already constituted by me, I only have to observe it like that, i.e., not as
a substantial independent reality, but as a dream). Both materialism and
idealism lead to consequences that make practical activity meaningless
or impossible. In order for me to be practically active, engaged in the
world, I have to accept myself as a being in the world, caught in a situ-
ation, interacting with real objects which resist me and which I try to
transform. Furthermore, in order to act as a free moral subject, I have to
accept the independent existence of other subjects like me, as well as
the existence of a higher spiritual order in which I participate and which
is independent of natural determinism. Accepting all this is not a matter
of knowledge: it can only be a matter of faith. Fichtes point is thus that
the existence of external reality (of which I myself am a part) is not
a matter of theoretical proofs, but a practical necessity, a necessary

138
FICHTES LAUGHTER

presupposition of me as an agent intervening into reality, interacting


with it.
The irony is that Fichte comes here uncannily close to Nikolai
Bukharin, a die-hard dialectical materialist who, in his Philosophical
Arabesques (one of the most tragic works in the entire history of philoso-
phy, a manuscript written in 1937, when he was in the Lubyanka
prison, awaiting execution), tries to bring together for the last time his
entire life-experience into a consistent philosophical edice. The rst
crucial battle that he confronts is the one between the materialist asser-
tion of the reality of the external world and what he calls the intrigues
of solipsism. Once this key battle is won, once the life-asserting reli-
ance on the real world liberates us from the damp prison-house of ones
fantasies, one can breathe freely, one only has to draw all the conse-
quences of this rst key result. The mysterious feature of the books rst
chapter in which Bukharin confronts this dilemma, is its tension
between form and content: although, at the level of content, Bukharin
adamantly denies that we are dealing here with a choice between two
beliefs or primordial existential decisions, the whole chapter is struc-
tured like a dialogue between a healthy but nave materialist and
Mephistopheles, standing for the devil of solipsism, a cunning spirit
which drapes itself into an enchantingly patterned cloak of iron logic,
and it laughs, poking out its tongue.14 Curling his lips ironically,
Mephistopheles tempts the materialist with the idea that, since all we
have directly access to are our subjective sensations, the only way we
can pass from here to the belief into some external reality which exists
independently of our sensations is by way of a leap of faith, a salto
vitale (as opposed to salto mortale).15 In short, Mephistopheles, the
devil of logic, tries to seduce us into accepting that the independent
external reality is a matter of faith, that the existence of holy matter is
the fundamental dogma of the theology of dialectical materialism.
After a series of arguments (which, one has to admit, although not all
totally devoid of philosophical interest, are irredeemably marked by the
pre-Kantian navety), Bukharin concludes the chapter with the ironic
call (which, nonetheless, cannot conceal the underlying despair): Hold
your tongue, Mephistopheles! Hold your dissolute tongue!16 (In spite
of this exorcism, devil continues to reappear throughout the book see
the rst sentence of chapter 12: After a long interval, the demon of
irony again makes his appearance.17) As in Fichte, external reality is

139
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

a matter of faith, of breaking the deadlock of theoretical sophistry


with a practical salto vitale.
Where Fichte is more consequent than Bukharin is in his awareness
that there is an element of credo quia absurdum in this leap: the discord
between our knowledge and our ethico-practical engagement is irreduc-
ible, one cannot bring them together in a complete world view. Fichte
thus radicalizes Kant who already conjectured that the transcendental
I in its spontaneity occupies a third space between phenomena and
noumenon itself: the subjects freedom/spontaneity, though, of course, it
is not the property of a phenomenal entity, so that it cannot be dismissed
as a false appearance which conceals the noumenal fact that we are
totally caught in an inaccessible necessity, is also not simply noumenal.
In a mysterious subchapter of his Critique of Practical Reason entitled Of the
Wise Adaptation of Mans Cognitive Faculties to His Practical Vocation,
Kant endeavors to answer the question of what would happen to us if we
were to gain access to the noumenal domain, to the Ding an sich:

instead of the conict which now the moral disposition has to wage
with inclinations and in which, after some defeats, moral strength of
mind may be gradually won, God and eternity in their awful majesty
would stand unceasingly before our eyes. [. . .] Thus most actions con-
forming to the law would be done from fear, few would be done from
hope, none from duty. The moral worth of actions, on which alone the
worth of the person and even of the world depends in the eyes of
supreme wisdom, would not exist at all. The conduct of man, so long
as his nature remained as it is now, would be changed into mere mech-
anism, where, as in a puppet show, everything would gesticulate well
but no life would be found in the gures.18
In short, the direct access to the noumenal domain would deprive us of
the very spontaneity which forms the kernel of transcendental free-
dom: it would turn us into lifeless automata, or, to put it in todays terms,
into thinking machines. The implication of this passage is much more
radical and paradoxical than it may appear. If we discard its inconsis-
tency (how could fear and lifeless gesticulation coexist?), the conclusion
it imposes is that, at the level of phenomena as well as at the noumenal
level, we humans are a mere mechanism with no autonomy and
freedom: as phenomena, we are not free, we are a part of nature, a mere
mechanism, totally submitted to causal links, a part of the nexus of

140
FICHTES LAUGHTER

causes and effects, and as noumena, we are again not free, but reduced
to a mere mechanism. (Is what Kant describes as a person that directly
knows the noumenal domain not strictly homologous to the utilitarian
subject whose acts are fully determined by the calculus of pleasures and
pains?) Our freedom persists only in a space in between the phenomenal
and the noumenal. It is therefore not that Kant simply limited causality
to the phenomenal domain in order to be able to assert that, at the nou-
menal level, we are free autonomous agents: we are only free insofar as
our horizon is that of the phenomenal, insofar as the noumenal domain
remains inaccessible to us. (Kants own formulations are misleading,
since he often identies the transcendental subject with the noumenal
I whose phenomenal appearance is the empirical person, thus shirking
from his radical insight into how the transcendental subject is a pure for-
mal-structural function beyond the opposition of the noumenal and the
phenomenal.) Kant formulated this deadlock in his famous statement
that he had to limit knowledge in order to create space for faith. Along
the same lines,

Fichtes philosophy ends in total cognitive skepticism, i.e., in the aban-


donment of philosophy proper, and looks for wisdom instead to a kind
of quasi-religious faith. But he thinks that this is not a problem, since
all that matters is practical: to produce a world t for human beings,
and to produce myself as the person I would be for all eternity.19
The limitation of this position resides in Kants and Fichtes inability to
think positively the ontological status of this autonomous-spontaneous
subject who is neither phenomenal nor noumenal (this is already
Heideggers reproach in Being and Time: traditional metaphysics cannot
think the ontological status of Dasein). Hegels solution is the transposi-
tion of the epistemological limitation into an ontological fact: the void of
our knowledge corresponds to a void in being itself, to the ontological
incompleteness of reality.
This transposition enables us to throw a new light on the Hegelian
denition of freedom as conceived necessity: the consequent notion of
subjective idealism compels us to invert this thesis and to conceive neces-
sity as (ultimately nothing but) conceived freedom. The central tenet
of Kants transcendental idealism is that it is the subjects spontaneous
(i.e. radically free) act of transcendental apperception that changes the
confused ow of sensations into reality, which obeys necessary laws.

141
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

Even clearer is this point in moral philosophy: when Kant claims that
moral Law is the ratio cognoscendi of our transcendental freedom, does he
not literally say that necessity is conceived freedom? That is to say, the
only way for us to get to know (to conceive) our freedom is via the fact
of the unbearable pressure of the moral Law, of its necessity, which enjoins
us to act against the compulsion of our pathological impulses. At the
most general level, one should posit that necessity (the symbolic neces-
sity that regulates our lives) relies on the abyssal free act of the subject,
on his contingent decision, on what Lacan calls the point de capiton,
the quilting point which magically turns confusion into a new order.
This freedom that is not yet caught in the cobweb of necessity, is it not
the abyss of the night of the world?
For this reason, Fichtes radicalization of Kant is consistent, not just a
subjectivist eccentricity. Fichte was the rst philosopher to focus on the
uncanny contingency in the very heart of subjectivity: the Fichtean
subject is not the overblown Ego = Ego as the absolute Origin of all real-
ity, but a nite subject thrown, caught, in a contingent social situation
forever eluding mastery.20 The Ansto, the primordial impulse that sets in
motion the gradual self-limitation and self-determination of the initially
void subject, is not merely a mechanical external impulse: it also points
towards another subject who, in the abyss of its freedom, functions as
the challenge [Aufforderung] compelling me to limit/specify my freedom,
i.e. to accomplish the passage from the abstract egotist freedom to con-
crete freedom within the rational ethical universe perhaps this inter-
subjective Aufforderung is not merely the secondary specication of the
Ansto, but its exemplary original case. It is important to bear in mind the
two primary meanings of Ansto in German: check, obstacle, hin-
drance, something that resists the boundless expansion of our striving,
and an impetus, stimulus, something that incites our activity. Ansto is
hence not simply the obstacle the absolute I posits to itself in order to
stimulate its activity so that, by overcoming the self-posited obstacle, it
asserts its creative power, like the games the proverbial perverted ascetic
saint plays with himself by inventing ever new temptations and then, in
successfully resisting them, conrming his strength. If the Kantian Ding
an sich corresponds to the Freudian-Lacanian Thing, Ansto is closer to
objet petit a, to the primordial foreign body that sticks in the throat of the
subject, to the object-cause of desire that splits it up: Fichte himself
denes Ansto as the non-assimilable foreign body that causes the subject

142
FICHTES LAUGHTER

division into the empty absolute subject and the nite determinate
subject, limited by the non-I.
Ansto thus designates the moment of the run-in, the hazardous
knock, the encounter of the Real in the midst of the ideality of the abso-
lute I: there is no subject without Ansto, without the collision with an
element of irreducible facticity and contingency the I is supposed to
encounter within itself something foreign. The point is thus to acknowl-
edge the presence, within the I itself, of a realm of irreducible otherness,
of absolute contingency and incomprehensibility . . . Ultimately, not just
Angelus Silesiuss rose, but every Ansto whatsoever ist ohne Warum.21
In clear contrast to the Kantian noumenal Ding that affects our senses,
Ansto does not come from the outside, it is stricto sensu ex-timate: a non-
assimilable foreign body in the very core of the subject as Fichte him-
self emphasizes, the paradox of Ansto resides in the fact that it is
simultaneously purely subjective and not produced by the activity of
the I. If Ansto were not purely subjective, if it were already the non-I,
part of objectivity, we would fall back into dogmatism, i.e. Ansto would
effectively amount to no more than a shadowy remainder of the Kantian
Ding an sich and would thus bear witness to Fichtes inconsequentiality
(the commonplace reproach against Fichte); if Ansto were simply sub-
jective, it would present a case of the subjects hollow playing with itself,
and we would never reach the level of objective reality, i.e. Fichte would
effectively be a solipsist (another commonplace reproach against his
philosophy). The crucial point is that Ansto sets in motion the constitu-
tion of reality: at the beginning is the pure I with the non-assimilable
foreign body in its heart; the subject constitutes reality by way of assum-
ing a distance towards the Real of the formless Ansto and conferring on
it the structure of objectivity. What imposes itself here is the parallel
between the Fichtean Ansto and the Freudian-Lacanian scheme of the
relationship between the primordial Ich (Ur-Ich) and the object, the
foreign body in its midst, which disturbs its narcissistic balance, setting in
motion the long process of the gradual expulsion and structuration of
this inner snag, through which (what we experience as) external, objec-
tive reality is constituted.
If Kants Ding an sich is not Fichtes Ansto, what is their difference?
Or, to put it in another way: where do we nd in Kant something
announcing Fichtes Ansto? One should not confuse Kants Ding an sich
with the transcendental object, which (contrary to some confused and

143
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

misleading formulations found in Kant himself) is not noumenal but the


nothingness, the void horizon of objectivity, of that which stands against
the (nite) subject, the minimal form of resistance that is not yet any
positive determinate object that the subject encounters in the world.
Kant here uses the German expression Dawider, what is out there oppos-
ing itself to us, standing against us. This Dawider is not the abyss of the
Thing, it does not point to the dimension of the unimaginable, but is, on
the contrary, the very horizon of openness towards objectivity within
which particular objects appear to a nite subject.
In the middle of David Finchers Fight Club (1999), there is an almost
unbearably painful scene, worthy of the weirdest David Lynch moments,
which serves as a kind of clue for the lms nal surprising twist. In order
to blackmail his boss into continuing to pay him even after he quits
working, the hero throws himself around the mans ofce, beating him-
self bloody before the buildings security ofcers arrive. In front of his
embarrassed boss, the narrator thus enacts upon himself the bosss
aggression towards him. The only similar case of self-beating is found in
Me, Myself and Irene, in which Jim Carrey beats himself up here, of
course, in a comic (although painfully exaggerated) way, as one part of a
split personality pounding the other part. In both lms, the self-beating
begins with the heros hand acquiring a life of its own, escaping the
heros control in short, turning into a partial object, or, to put it in
Deleuzes terms, into an organ without a body (the obverse of the body
without an organ). This provides the key to the gure of the double with
whom, in both lms, the hero is ghting: the double, the heros Ideal-
Ego, a spectral/invisible hallucinatory entity, is not simply external to the
hero its efcacy is inscribed within the heros body itself as the autono-
mization of one of its organs (hand). The hand acting on its own is the
drive ignoring the dialectic of the subjects desire: drive is fundamentally
the insistence of an undead organ without a body, standing, like Lacans
lamella, for that which the subject had to lose in order to subjectivize
itself in the symbolic space of the sexual difference.
This is the Kantian reason why a double causes such anxiety: the
double is directly the object-Thing that the subject noumenally is.
In Wolfgang Petersens thriller Shattered (1991), Tom Berenger barely
survives a car accident: when, weeks later, he awakens in the hospital,
with his face and body patched up by plastic surgery, he has total amne-
sia concerning his identity he cannot remember who he is, although all

144
FICHTES LAUGHTER

the people around him, including a woman who claims to be his wife,
treat him as the head of a rich corporation. After a series of mysterious
events, he goes to an abandoned warehouse where he was told that, in
a barrel full of oil, the corpse of the person he had killed is hidden. When
he pulls the bodys head out of the liquid, he stiffens in consternation
the head is his own.22 This horror of encountering oneself in the guise of
ones double, outside oneself, is the ultimate truth of the subjects self-
identity: in it, the subject encounters itself as an object.
Jean-Pauls (Richters) Titan is a properly Romantic parody (decon-
struction even) of Fichte: he fully developed how the non-I is the Is
double, i.e., a part of the I active (in the guise of) as Is passivity, not the
Is real opposite. (What this means is that the Fichtean I is I should be
read as a Hegelian innite judgment whose truth is the coincidence of
opposites (I is non-I).) It is with regard to this topic of the double that
Fichte belongs to the aftermath of the Kantian revolution: the scope of
this revolution can be discerned precisely through the sudden change in
the perception of the theme of the double in literature. Till the end of
eighteenth century, this theme mostly gave rise to comic plots (two
brothers who look alike are seducing the same girl; Zeus seducing
Amphitrions faithful wife disguised as Amphitrion, so that, when
Amphitrion unexpectedly returns home, he encounters himself leaving
his bedroom, etc.); all of a sudden, however, in the historic moment
which exactly ts the Kantian revolution, the topic of the double becomes
associated with horror and anxiety encountering ones double or being
followed and persecuted by him is the ultimate experience of terror, it is
something which shatters the very core of the subjects identity.
The horrifying aspect of the theme of the double thus has something to
do with the emergence of the Kantian subject as pure transcendental
apperception, as the substanceless void of self-consciousness which is
not an object in reality. What the subject encounters in the guise of his
double is himself as object, i.e. his own impossible objectal counter-
point. In the pre-Kantian space, this encounter was not traumatic, since
the individual conceived of himself as a positive entity, an object within
the world. Another way to make the same point is to locate in my
double, in the encountered object which is myself, the Lacanian objet
petit a: what makes the double so uncanny, what distinguishes it from
other inner-worldly objects, is not simply its resemblance to me, but the
fact that he gives body to that which is in myself more than myself, to

145
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

the inaccessible/unfathomable object that I am, i.e. to that which


I forever lack in the reality of my self-experience . . .
In Le prix du progres, one of the fragments that conclude The Dialectic
of Enlightenment, Adorno and Horkheimer quote the argumentation of
the nineteenth- century French physiologist Pierre Flourens against
medical anaesthesia with chloroform: Flourens claims that it can be
proven that the anaesthetic works only on our memorys neuronal
network. In short, while we are butchered alive on the operating table,
we fully feel the terrible pain, but later, after awakening, we do not
remember it . . . For Adorno and Horkheimer, this, of course, is the per-
fect metaphor of the fate of Reason based on the repression of nature in
itself: his body, the part of nature in the subject, fully feels the pain, it is
only that, due to repression, the subject does not remember it. Therein
resides the perfect revenge of nature for our domination over it: unknow-
ingly, we are our own greatest victims, butchering ourselves alive . . .
Is it not also possible to read this as the perfect fantasy scenario of the
subject witnessing oneself as object?

4. ANSTO AND TAT-HANDLUNG

So, to recapitulate, Ansto is formally homologous to the Lacanian objet a:


like a magnetic eld, it is the focus of the Is positing activity, the point
around which this activity circulates, yet it is in itself entirely insubstan-
tial, since it is created-posited, generated, by the very process which reacts
to it and deals with it. It is as in the old joke about the conscript who
pleaded insanity in order to avoid military service; his symptom was to
compulsively examine every paper at his reach and exclaim Thats not
it!; when he is examined by the military psychiatrists, he does the same,
so the psychiatrists nally give him a paper conrming that he is released
from military service. The conscript reaches for it, examines it, and
exclaims: Thats it! Here, also, the search itself generates its object.
Therein resides the ultimate paradox of the Fichtean Ansto: it is not
immediately external to the circular movement of reection, but an
object which is posited by this very circular (self-referential) movement.
Its transcendence (absolute impenetrability, impossibility to be reduced to
an ordinary represented object) coincides with its absolute immanence.

146
FICHTES LAUGHTER

Is Ansto, then, immanent or transcendent? Does it suscite/disturb


the I from the outside, or is it posited by the I itself? In other terms: do
we have (ideally) rst the pure Life of the self-positing I, which, then,
posits the obstacle? If it is transcendent, we have the nite subject
limited by Ansto (be it in the form of the Kantian Thing-in-itself, or in
the form, today much more acceptable, of intersubjectivity, of another
subject as the only true Thing, as the ethical Ansto); if it is immanent, we
get the boring perverse logic of the I which posits an obstacle in order
to overcome it . . . So the only solution is: absolute simultaneity/
overlapping of self-positing and obstacle, i.e., the obstacle is the excre-
mental reject of the process of self-positing, it is not so much posited as
ejected, excreted/secreted, as the obverse of the activity of self-positing.
In this sense, Ansto is the transcendental a priori of positing, that which
incites the I to endless positing, the only non-posited element. Or, in
Lacanese, following Lacans logic of non-All: the (nite) I and the non-I
(object) limit each other, while, at the absolute level, there is nothing
which is not I, the I is illimited, and for that reason non-All the Ansto
is that which makes it non-All.
Sylvain Portier clearly formulated this crucial point: if we are trying to
account for the limit, one should be careful never to represent it in an
objective, or, rather, objectivized way.23 The standard version according
to which Kant was still aware of the necessity to presuppose an external
X that affects us when we experience sensations, while Fichte closed the
circle of transcendental solipsism, misses the point, the nesse of Fichtes
argumentation: Fichte dispenses with the thing-in-itself not because he
posits the transcendental subject as an innite Absolute, but precisely
on account of the transcendental subjects nitude or, to quote
Wittgenstein again: Our life has no end in just the way in which our
visual eld has no limits.24 As I noted above, precisely because we are
within our nitude, we cannot step out of it and perceive its limitation.
This is also what Fichte aims at when he emphasizes that one should not
conceive the transcendental I as a closed space surrounded by another
external space of noumenal entities.
The same point can be made very clearly in the terms of Lacans
distinction between the subject of the enunciated and the subject of the
enunciation: when I directly posit-dene myself as a nite being, existing
in the world among other beings, at the level of enunciation, of the posi-
tion from which I speak, I already objectivize the limit between myself

147
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

and the rest of the world, i.e., I adopt the innite position from which
I can observe reality and locate myself in it; on the contrary, the only
way for me to truly assert my nitude is to accept that my world is in-
nite, since I cannot locate its limit within it. (This is also what makes
Fichtes notion of Ansto so difcult: Ansto is not an object within the
represented reality, but the stand-in, within reality, of what is outside
reality.) As Wittgenstein points out, this is also the problem with death:
death is the limit of life which cannot be located within life and it is only
a true atheist that can fully accept this fact, as it was made clear by
Ingmar Bergman in his great manifesto for atheism, which he develops
precisely apropos his most religious lm, The Seventh Seal:

My fear of death was to a great degree linked to my religious concepts.


Later on, I underwent minor surgery. By mistake, I was given too
much anesthesia. I felt as if I had disappeared out of reality. Where did
the hours go? They ashed by in a microsecond. Suddenly I realized,
that is how it is. That one could be transformed from being to non-
being it was hard to grasp. But for a person with a constant anxiety
about death, now liberating. Yet at the same time it seems a bit sad.
You say to yourself that it would have been fun to encounter new
experiences once your soul had had a little rest and grown accustomed
to being separated from your body. But I dont think that is what
happens to you. First you are, then you are not. This I nd deeply
satisfying. That which had formerly been so enigmatic and frightening,
namely, what might exist beyond this world, does not exist. Every-
thing is of this world. Everything exists and happens inside us, and we
ow into and out of one another. Its perfectly ne like that.25
There is thus a truth in Epicurus apparently common argument against
the fear of death (there is nothing to fear: while you are still alive, you
are not dead, and when you are dead, you do not feel anything): the
source of the fear of death is the power of imagination; death as an event
is the ultimate anamorphosis in fearing it, we experience a non-event,
a non-entity (our passage to non-being), as an event.
Ernesto Laclau developed how, in an antagonistic relationship,
external difference coincides with internal difference: the difference that
separates me from other entities around me and thus guarantees my
identity, simultaneously cuts into my identity, making it awed, instable,
truncated.26 One should bring this tension up to the full dialectical

148
FICHTES LAUGHTER

identity of the opposites: the condition of possibility of identity is at the


same time its condition of impossibility, the assertion of self-identity is
based on its opposite, on an irreducible remainder that truncates every
identity.
And this is why Fichte is right in claiming that the arch-model for all
identity is I = I, the subjects identity with itself the formal-logical
notion of (self)identity comes second, it has to be grounded in the tran-
scendental logical notion of the self-identity of the I. When Fichte empha-
sizes that the absolute I is not a fact (Tatsache), but a deed (Tathandlung),
that its identity is purely and thoroughly processual, it means precisely
that the subject is the result of its own failure to become subject: I try to
fully actualize myself as subject, I fail (to become subject), and this fail-
ure is the subject (that I am). Only in the case of the subject do we get this
full coincidence of failure and success, of identity as grounded in its own
lack; in all other cases, there is the appearance of a substantial identity
that precedes or underlies processuality. And the point of Fichtes
critique of realist dogmatism is the transcendental-ontological priority
of this pure processuality of the I over every substantial entity: every
appearance of substantial identity has to be accounted for in the terms of
transcendental genesis, as the reied result of the pure Is processuality.
The passage from I = I to the delimitation between the I and the non-I is
thus the passage from immanent antagonism to external limitation that
guarantees the identity of the opposed poles: the pure self-positing I does
not simply divide itself into the posited non-I and the nite I opposed to
it, it posits the non-I and the nite I as mutually limiting opposites in
order to resolve the immanent tension of its processuality.
The claim that the limitation of the subject is simultaneously external
and internal, that the subjects external limit is always its internal limita-
tion, is, of course, developed by Fichte into the main thesis of his abso-
lute transcendental idealism: every external limit is the result of an
internal self-limitation. This is what Kant does not see: for him, the
thing-in-itself is directly the external limit of the phenomenal eld con-
stituted by the subject, i.e., the limit that separates the noumenal from
the phenomenal is not the transcendental subjects self-limitation, but
simply its external limit. Does, however, all this endorse the standard
reading according to which Fichte marks the passage to transcendental
absolute idealism in which every external limit of subjectivity is co-
opted, re-inscribed as a moment of the subjects innite self-mediation/

149
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

self-limitation? Maybe we should read the thesis as the claim that every
limit of the subject is (grounded in) the subjects self-limitation in con-
junction with the overlapping of external with internal limitation. This
would account for the shifting of the accent of the subjects self-limita-
tion from subjective to objective genitive: it is not about the limitation
of the self in the sense that the subject is the full agent and master of its
own limitation, encompassing its limits into the activity of its self-media-
tion, but the limitation of the self in the sense that the external limita-
tion of the self truncates from within the very identity of the subject.
It was (again) Portier who clearly spelled out this point:

What the I, insofar as it is precisely the absolute I, is not, that is to say,


the non-I itself, is thus (for the I) absolutely nothing, a pure nothing-
ness or, as Fichte himself put it, a kind of non-being. [. . .] we should
thus take care not to represent to ourselves the non-I as an other level
than that of the I: outside the transcendental eld of the positing I,
there is truly nothing but the absence of all space, in other words, the
non-level, the void that is proper to the non-I.27
What this means is that, since there is nothing outside the (self)positing
of the absolute I, the non-I can only emerge can only be posited as
correlative to the Is non-positedness: the non-I is nothing but the non-
positedness of the I. Or, translated into terms closer to our common
experience: since, in Fichtes absolute egological perspective, all positing
activity is the activity of the I, when the I encounters the non-I as active,
as objective reality exerting active pressure on the I, actively resisting it,
this can only be the result of the Is own passivity: the non-I is active only
insofar as I render myself passive and thus let it act back upon me. (With
regard to Fichtes intense ethico-practical stance this means that, when-
ever I succumb to the pressure of circumstances, I let myself be deter-
mined by this pressure I am determined by external causes only insofar
as I let myself be determined by them, i.e., my determination by external
causes is never direct, it is always mediated by my acquiescing to them.)
Therein resides, for Fichte, the fatal aw of Kants thing-in-itself: insofar
as the Kantian Thing is conceived as existing independently of the I and,
as such, exerting pressure on it, we are dealing with an activity in the
non-I to which no passivity in the I itself corresponds and this is
what is for Fichte totally unthinkable, a remainder of metaphysical
dogmatism. This brings us to the topic of the subjects nitude: only in

150
FICHTES LAUGHTER

Fichte, the a priori synthesis of the nite and the innite is the nitude
of the positing I:

the I, that is to say, the act of reection-into-itself, always has to posit


something absolute outside itself, all the while recognizing that this
entity can only exist for it, that is to say, relatively to the nitude and
the precise mode of intuition of the I.28
Fichte thus resumes the basic insight of the philosophy-of-reection,
which is usually formulated in a critical mode: the moment the subject
experiences itself as redoubled in reection, caught in oppositions, etc.,
it has to relate its own split/mediated condition to some presupposed
Absolute inaccessible to it, set up as the standard the subject tries to
rejoin. The same insight can also be made in more common-sense terms:
when we humans are engaged in a turmoil of activity, it is a human
propensity to imagine an external absolute point of reference which
provides orientation and stability to our activity. What Fichte does here
is that, in the best tradition of transcendental phenomenology, he reads
this constellation in a purely immanent way: we should never forget that
this Absolute, precisely insofar as it is experienced by the subject as the
presupposition of its activity, is actually posited by it, i.e., can only exist
for it. Two crucial consequences follow from such an immanent read-
ing: rst, the innite Absolute is the presupposition of a nite subject, its
specter can only arise within the horizon of a nite subject experiencing
its nitude as such. Second consequence: this experience of the gap that
separates the subject from the innite Absolute is inherently practical, it
is what pushes the subject to incessant activity. Seidel perspicuously con-
cludes29 that, with this practical vision, Fichte also opens up the space for
a new radical despair: not only my personal despair that I cannot realize
the Ideal, not only the despair that reality is too hard, but a suspicion
that the Ideal is in itself invalidated, that it simply is not worth it.

5. DIVISION AND LIMITATION

One can see now the absolutely central role of the notion of limitation in
Fichtes entire theoretical edice: in contrast to dogmatic realism which
posits the substantial non-I as the only true and independent agency, as

151
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

well as to the idealist realism la Descartes or Leibniz, for whom the


only true reality is the one of the monadic spiritual substance, and all
activity of the non-I is a mere illusion, for Fichte, the relationship of the
I and the non-I is one of mutual limitation. Although this mutual limita-
tion is always posited within the absolute I, the key point is not to con-
ceive this I in a realist way, as a spiritual substance which contains in
itself everything, but as an abstract, purely transcendental-ideal, a
medium in which the I and the non-I delimit themselves mutually. It is
not the absolute I which is (the highest) reality; the I itself, on the con-
trary, only acquires reality through/in its real engagement with the oppos-
ing force of the non-I which frustrates it and limits it there is no reality
of the I outside its opposition to the non-I, outside this shock, this encoun-
ter of an opposing/frustrating power (which, in its generality, encompasses
everything, from the natural inertia of ones own body to the pressure of
social constraints and institutions upon the I, not to mention the trau-
matic presence of another I). Depriving the I of the non-I equals depriving
it of its reality. The non-I is thus primordially not the abstract object
(Objekt) of the subjects distanced contemplation, but the object as Gegen-
stand, what stands there against me, as an obstacle to my effort. As such,
the subjects passivity when facing an object that frustrates its practical
effort of positing, its thetic effort, is properly pathetic, or, rather, pathic.30
Or, to put it in yet another way, the subject can only be frustrated/
thwarted, it can only experience the object as an obstacle, insofar as it is
itself oriented towards outside, pushing outside in its practical effort.
So, within the (absolutely positing) I, the (nite) I and the non-I are
posited as divisible, limiting each other or, as Fichte put it in his famous
formula: I oppose in the I a divisible non-I to the divisible I. Jacobi was
thus in a way right when, in a unique formula from his famous letter to
Fichte, he designated the latters Wissenschaftslehre as a materialism with-
out matter: the pure consciousness of the absolute I within which the
I and the non-I mutually delimit each other effectively functions as the
idealist version of matter in abstract materialism, i.e., as the abstract
(mathematical) space endlessly divided between the I and the non-I.
Nowhere are the proximity and, simultaneously, the gap that separates
Fichte from Hegel more clearly discernible than in the difference that
separates their respective notions of limitation. What they both share is
the insight into how, paradoxically, far from excluding each other,
limitation and true innity are two aspects of the same constellation.

152
FICHTES LAUGHTER

In Hegel, the overlapping of true innity and self-limitation is developed


in the notion of self-relating: in true innity, the relation-to-other coin-
cides with self-relating this is what, for Hegel, denes the most elemen-
tary structure of life. As I pointed out above, a series of contemporary
researchers in biology, from Lynn Margulis to Francisco Varela, assert that
the true problem is not how an organism and its environs interact or con-
nect, but, rather, the opposite one: how does a distinct self-identical
organism emerge out of its environs? How does a cell form the mem-
brane which separates its inside from its outside? The true problem is
thus not how an organism adapts to its environs, but how it is that there
is something, a distinct entity, which must adapt itself in the rst place.
However, in Fichte the link between innity and limitation is thor-
oughly different from Hegel: the Fichtean innity is acting innity,31
the innity of the subjects practical engagement. Although an animal
obviously can also be frustrated by objects/obstacles, it does not experi-
ence its predicament as stricto sensu limited, it is not aware of its limita-
tion, since it is simply constrained by/into it. But man does experience
his predicament itself as frustratingly limited, and this experience is
sustained by his innite striving to break out of it. In this way, mans
acting innity is directly grounded in his experience of his own ni-
tude. Or, to put it in a slightly different way, while an animal is simply/
immediately limited, i.e., while its limit is external to it and thus invisible
from within its constrained horizon (if an animal were to speak, it would
not be able to say I am constrained to my small poor world, unaware of
what I am missing), mans limitation is self-limitation in the precise
sense that it cuts from within into his very identity, frustrating it, nitiz-
ing it. It is as if the objects/obstacles that frustrate mans efforts under-
mine mans identity from within, preventing him not only from
becoming the world, but from becoming himself. This is the (often
overlooked) other side of Fichtes basic thesis on how I oppose in the I a
divisible non-I to the divisible I: the fact that the limit between the I and
the object/obstacle falls within the I does not only entail the triumphant
conclusion that the I is the encompassing unity of itself and its objective
other; it also entails the much more unpleasant and properly traumatic
conclusion that the object/obstacle cuts into my very identity, making it
nite/frustrated.
This crucial insight enables us to approach what some interpreters
perceive as the problem of Fichte: how to pass from the I to the non-I as

153
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

an in-itself that has a consistency outside the Is reexive self-


movement? Does the Is circular self-positing hang in empty air such that
it cannot really ground itself? Was it not already Madame de Stael who,
as we mentioned above, after Fichte explained her the Is self-positing,
snapped back: So you mean that the absolute I is like Baron
Mnchhausen who saved himself from drowning in a swamp by way of
grabbing his hair and pulling himself up by his own hands? Pierre Livet32
proposed an ingenious solution. He suggests, since there must be a kind
of external point of reference for the I (without it, the I would simply
collapse into itself), and since this point nonetheless cannot be directly
external to the I (any such externality would amount to a concession to
the Kantian Thing-in-itself that impedes the Is absolute self-positing),
there is only one consistent way out of this deadlock: to ground the
circular movement of reexivity in itself not by way of pulling the
impossible Mnchhausen trick in which the founded X retroactively
provides its own foundation, but by way of referring to another I. In this
way, we get a point of reference which is external to a singular I, which
the latter experiences as an opaque impenetrable kernel, yet which is
nonetheless not foreign to the reexive movement of (self)positing, since
it is merely another circle of such (self)positing. (In this way, Fichte can
ground the a priori necessity of intersubjectivity.)
One cannot but admire the elegant simplicity of this perspicuous
solution which calls to mind the Lacanian-Freudian notion of the neigh-
bor as the impenetrable traumatic Thing. However, perspicuous as it is,
this solution nonetheless does not work: it leaves out of consideration
the fact that the Is relating to the object, in a strict formal sense of tran-
scendental genesis, precedes the Is relating to another I: the primordial
Other, the Neighbor qua Thing, is not another subject. The Ansto which
awakens (what will have been) the subject out of its pre-subjective
status is an Other, but not the Other of (reciprocal) intersubjectivity.

6. THE FINITE ABSOLUTE

We can see now the fatal aw of the dismissal of Fichte as the extreme
point of German Idealism, as idealism at its worst. According to this
commonplace, Hegel is the moment of madness, the dream of a system

154
FICHTES LAUGHTER

of absolute nowing . . . but, as the saying goes, he nonetheless brings


much concrete, historical, material, valuable insights on history, politics,
culture, aesthetics. Fichte, on the contrary, as an early crazy version of
Hegel, is only madness (see Bertrand Russell in his History of Western Phi-
losophy). Even Lacan in passing refers to the radical position of solipsism
as a madness advocated by no wise man . . . And even those who praise
Fichte see in his thought an extreme formulation of modern subjectivity.
As a matter of fact, upon a fast reading of Fichte, it cannot but appear so:
Fichte starts with I = I, the Is self-positing; then we pass to not-I; then . . .
pure abstract ratiocinations, supported by ridiculous references to math-
ematics and argumentation, oscillating between weird jumps and poor
common-sense.
However, the paradox is that, as in Kant, Schelling, and in all of Ger-
man Idealism, what appears an abstract speculation becomes substantial
insight the moment we relate it to our most concrete experience. For
example, when Fichte claims that it is because the absolute/ideal self is
posited by the nite self that the opposing of the non-self occurs, this
makes sense as a speculative description of the nite subjects concrete
practical engagement: when I (nite subject) posit an ideal/unattain-
able practical goal, the nite reality outside me appears as not-self, as
an obstacle to my goal to be overcome, transformed. In the wake of Kant
this is Fichtes primacy of practical reason: the way I perceive reality
depends on my practical project no project, no obstacles, my cognitive
recognition of reality around me is always conditioned/colored by my
practical project. The obstacle is not an obstacle to me as an entity, but to
me as engaged in realizing a project: if my ideal as a health professional
is to save lives, then I will begin to see in my patients the things I need to
be concerned about: I will begin to see things such as high blood pres-
sure, high cholesterol levels, etc.33 Or, an even more perspicuous exam-
ple: If [. . .] I am a rich capitalist being driven through a slum district in
my air-conditioned limousine, I do not see the poverty and misery of the
local inhabitants. What I see is people on welfare who are too lazy to
work, etc.34 Sartre was thus effectively Fichtean when, in a famous
passage from Being and Nothingness, he claimed that

whatever may be the situation in which he nds himself, the for-itself


must wholly assume this situation with its peculiar coefcient of
adversity, even though it be insupportable. Is it not I who decides the

155
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

coefcient of adversity in things and even their unpredictability by


deciding myself?35

The weird-sounding syntagm coefcient of adversity belongs to Gaston


Bachelard, who reproached Husserls phenomenology with ignoring the
inertia of objects resisting subjective appropriation in its notion of
noematic objectivity as constituted by the transcendental subjects noetic
activity. While conceding the point about the inertia of the in-itself, the
idiocy of the real, Sartre points out, in a Fichtean way, that one experi-
ences this inertia of the Real as adversity, as an obstacle, only with regard
to our determinate projects:

my freedom to choose my goals or projects entails that I have also


chosen the obstacles I encounter along the way. It is by deciding to
climb this mountain that I have turned the weakness of my body and
the steepness of the cliffs into obstacles, which they were not so long
as I was content simply to gaze at the mountain from the comfort of
my chair.36

It is only this primacy of the practical which provides the key to the
proper understanding of how Fichte reduces the perceived thing to the
activity of its perceiving, i.e., of how endeavors to generate the (per-
ceived) thing out of the perceiving. From this phenomenological
standpoint, the in-itself of the object is the result of the long arduous
work by means of which the subject learns to distinguish, within the
eld of its representations, between the mere illusory appearance and
the way the appearing thing is itself. The in-itself is thus also a category
of appearing: it is not the immediacy of the thing independently of how
it appears to us, but the most mediated mode of appearing how?
The I transfers a certain quantum of reality outside itself, it externalizes
part of its activity in a non-I which is thereby posited as non-posited,
i.e., it appears as independent of the I. Fichtes paradox is here that it is
the Is nitude [. . .] and not its reexivity proper, which renders neces-
sary the different modalities of the objectivization of the non-I to which
this I relates itself:37 to put it in somewhat simplied terms, the I is
caught in its self-enclosed circle of objectivizations not because he is the
innite ground of all being, but precisely because he is nite. The key
point not to be missed is hence the paradoxical link between innity
(in the sense of the absence of external limitation) and nitude: every

156
FICHTES LAUGHTER

limitation has to be self-limitation not because the I is an innite divine


ground of all being, but precisely because of its radical nitude: as such,
as nite, it cannot step on its own shoulder (or, it cannot jump over its
own shadow) and perceive its own external limitation. Portier is fully
justied in speaking about the circle of the nite absolute Knowing:38
nitude and innity are no longer opposed: it is our very encounter of
the obstacle (and thus brutal awareness of our nitude) that, simultane-
ously, makes us aware of the innity within ourselves, of the innite
duty that haunts us in the very core of our being.
The standard reproach according to which Fichte cannot deduce the
necessity of the shock, i.e., of encountering the obstacle which triggers
the subjects activity, thus simply misses his point: this shock has to arise
out of nowhere because of the subjects radical nitude it stands for
the intervention of the radical Outside which, as such, by denition can-
not be deduced (if it were to be possible to deduce it, we would be back
at the metaphysical subject/substance which generates its entire content
out of itself):

Fichtes stroke of genius resides undoubtedly in the fact that he makes


out of the inevitable lack that pertains to his categorical deduction,
not the weakness, but the supreme force of his system: the fact that
Necessity can only be deduced from the practical point of view is itself
(theoretically and practically) necessary.39
It is here, in this coincidence of contingency and necessity, of freedom
and limitation, that we effectively encounter the acme of Fichtes edi-
ce:40 in this shock, impact, of the non-I onto the I, described by Fichte
as simultaneously impossible and necessary. At this point, nitude
(being constrained by an Other) and freedom are no longer opposed,
since it is only through the shocking encounter of the obstacle that
I becomes free.
This is why, for Fichte, it is the innite I, not the non-I, which has to
nitize itself, to appear as the (self)limited I, to split itself into the
absolute I and the nite I opposed to non-I. What this means is that, as
Portier put it in a wonderfully concise way, every non-I is the non-I of
an I, but no I is the I of a non-I.41 This, however, does not mean that the
non-I is simply internal to the I, the outcome of its self-relating one
should be very precise here: over and above the standard dogmatic
temptation to conceive the I as part of the non-I, as part of objective

157
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

reality, there is a much more tricky and no less dogmatic temptation of


transcendental realism itself, of hypostasizing the absolute I into a kind
of noumenal meta-Subject/Substance which engenders the nite subject
as its phenomenal/empirical appearance. In this case, there would be
no truly real objects: the objects would be ultimately mere phantom-
objects, specters engendered by the absolute I in its circular playing with
itself. This point is absolutely crucial, if we are to avoid the notion of
Fichte as the ridiculous gure of an absolute idealist: the absolute I is
not merely playing with itself, positing obstacles and then overcoming
them, all the time secretly aware that he is the only player/agent in the
house. The absolute I is not the absolute real/ideal ground of everything;
its status is radically ideal, it is the ideal presupposition of the practically
engaged nite I as the only reality (since, as we have seen, the I becomes
real only through its self-limitation in encountering the obstacle of the
non-I). This is why Fichte is a moralist idealist, an idealist of innite
duty: freedom is not something that substantially co-exists with the I,
it is something that has to be acquired through arduous struggle, through
the effort of culture and self-education the innite I is nothing but the
process of its own innite becoming.
This brings us to Fichtes solution of the problem of solipsism: although,
at the level of theoretical observation of reality, we are passive receivers,
while, at the level of practice, we are active, we intervene, impose our
project onto the world, one cannot overcome solipsism from a theoreti-
cal standpoint, but only from the practical one: /if/ no effort, /then/ no
object.42 As a theoretical I, I can easily imagine myself as a sole monad
caught in the ethereal, non-substantial, cobweb of my own phantasma-
gorias, while the moment I engage in practice, I have to struggle with the
objects resistance or, as Fichte himself put it: The coercion on account
of which belief in reality imposes itself is a moral coercion, the only one
possible for a free being.43 Or, as Lacan expresses the same thought much
later, ethics is the dimension of the Real, the dimension in which imagi-
nary and symbolic balances are disturbed. This is why Fichte can and has
to reject the Kantian solution of the dynamic antinomies: if we resolve
them in the Kantian way, by simply allocating each of the two opposed
theses to a different level (phenomenally we are caught into necessity,
while noumenally we are free), we obfuscate the fact that it is the very
phenomenal reality which is the world in which we struggle for free-
dom, into which we intervene with free acts. This is also why Fichte can

158
FICHTES LAUGHTER

avoid Kants already-mentioned deadlock from his Critique of Practical


Reason, where Kant endeavors to answer the question of what would
happen to us if we were to gain access to the noumenal domain, to the
thing-in-itself: we would have been mere puppets deprived of freedom
. . . Fichte allows us to clarify this confusion which arises if we insist on
the opposition between the noumenal and the phenomenal: the I is not
a noumenal substance, but the pure spontaneity of self-positing; this is
why its self-limitation does not need a transcendent God who manipu-
lates our terrestrial situation (limiting our knowledge) in order to foster
our moral growth one can deduce the subjects limitation in a totally
immanent way.
Interpreters like to emphasize the radical break, paradigm-shift,
between Kant and Fichte; however, Fichtes focus on the subjects ni-
tude compels us to acknowledge a no less radical break between Fichte
and Schelling. Schellings idea (shared also by the young Hegel) has it
that Fichtes one-sided subjective idealism should be supplemented by
objective idealism, since it is only this two-sided approach that gives us a
complete image of the absolute Subject-Object. What gets lost in this
shift from Fichte to Schelling is Fichtes unique standpoint of the subjects
nitude (this nitude determines Fichtes basic attitude towards reality
as an engaged-practical one: the Fichtean synthesis can only be given as
practical effort, as endless striving). In Fichte, the synthesis of the nite
and the innite is given in the innite effort of the nite subject, and the
absolute I itself is a hypo-thesis of the thetic practical-nite subject,
while for Schelling, the original datum is the Absolute qua indifference
of the subject-object, and the subject as opposed to the object emerges as
the Abfall, falling-off, from the Absolute, which is why rejoining the
Absolute is for Schelling no longer a matter of the Is practical effort, but
a matter of the aesthetic submerging into the Absolutes indifference
which equals the subjects self-overcoming. In other words, from Fichtes
standpoint, Schelling regresses to the pre-Kantian idealist realism: his
Absolute is again the noumenal absolute entity, and all nite/delimitated
entities are its results/fall-offs. For Fichte, on the contrary, the status of
the Absolute (the self-positing I) remains thoroughly transcendental-
ideal, it is the transcendental condition of the nite Is practical engage-
ment, its hypo-thesis, never a positively-given ens realissimum.
It is precisely because, for Fichte, the status of the Absolute remains
transcendental-ideal, that he remains faithful to the basic Kantian insight

159
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

that time and space are a priori forms of sensibility; this prohibits any
nave-Platonic notion of the nite/material/sensual reality as the
secondary confused version of the intelligible/noumenal true universe
for Kant (and Fichte), material reality is not a blurred version of the
true noumenal kingdom, but a fully constituted reality of its own.
In other words, the fact that time and space are a priori forms of sensibil-
ity means that what Kant called transcendental schematism is irreduc-
ible: the orders/levels of sensibility and intelligibility are irreducibly
heterogeneous, one cannot deduce from the categories of pure reasons
themselves anything about material reality.
Fichtes position with regard to the status of nature nonetheless
remains the radicalized Kantian one: if reality is primordially experi-
enced as the obstacle to the Is practical activity, this means that nature
(the inertia of material objects) exists only as the stuff of our moral
activity, that its justication can only be practical-teleological, not specu-
lative. This is why Fichte rejects all attempts at a speculative philosophy
of nature. No wonder, then, that Schelling, the great practitioner of the
philosophy of nature, ridiculed Fichte: if nature can only be justied
teleologically, this means that air and light exist only so that moral
individuals can see each other and thus interact . . . Well aware of the
difculties such a view poses to our sense of credibility, Fichte replied
with sarcastic laughter:

They reply to me, the air and the light a priori! Dream therefore about
it ha!ha!ha! [. . .] laugh then with us, hahaha! hahaha! air and light
a priori: cream pie ha!ha!ha! air and light a priori! Cream pie ha!ha!ha!
[. . .] And so on to innity.44
The weird nature of this outburst of laughter resides in the fact that it is
the very opposite of the common-sense laughter at the philosophers
strange speculations, i.e., of the laughter whose exemplary case is the
bad taste joke against the philosopher-solipsist: Let him hit with his
head into a hard wall and he will soon discover if he is alone in the
world, hahaha! Here, the philosopher-Fichte laughs at the common-
sense argument that air and light are obviously not here just to enable
our moral activity they just are out there, if we act or not . . . Fichtes
laughter is all the more strange since it is similar to the traditional realist
philosophers direct reference to obvious reality as the best argument
against abstract speculations when Diogenes the Cynic was confronted

160
FICHTES LAUGHTER

with the Eleatic proofs of the non-existence of movement, he simply


raised and moved his middle nger, or so the story goes . . . In another
version, he simply stood up and started to walk; however, according to
Hegel, when one of the students present applauded the master for this
proof that movement exists, Diogenes beat him up immediate reality
doesnt count in philosophy, only conceptual thinking can do the job of
demonstration. What, then, could Fichtes laughter mean, since he
laughs not from the standpoint of common-sense realism (which tells us
that movement exists as well as that air and light are out there indepen-
dently of our activity), but rather laughs at this standpoint? The key to
the answer is (as is often the case with philosophers who hide the crucial
formulation in a footnote or as a secondary remark) squeezed between
the brackets here is Fichtes crucial explanation of the non-I:

(According to the usual opinion, the concept of the non-self is merely


a general concept which emerges through abstraction from everything
represented [allem Vorgestellten]. But the shallowness of this explana-
tion can easily be demonstrated. If I am to represent anything at all,
I must oppose it to that which represents [the representing self]. Now
within the object of representation [Vorstellung] there can and must be
an X of some sort, whereby this object discloses itself as something to
be represented, and not as that which represents. But that everything
wherein this X may be is not that which represents but something to
be represented, is something that no object can teach me; for merely to
be able to posit something as an object, I have to know this already;
hence it must lie initially in myself, that which represents, prior to any
possible experience. And this is an observation so striking that any-
one who fails to grasp it and is not thereby uplifted into transcendental
idealism, must unquestionably be suffering from mental blindness.)45
The logic of this argumentation may appear surprising to anyone not
versed in German Idealism: it is precisely because there is something
more in the non-Self, in the object, than the subjects representations
(Vorstellungen), precisely because it cannot be reduced to a general,
shared, feature abstracted from representations; it is precisely because it
discloses itself as something to be represented, and not as that which
represents, that this surplus over my representations must lie in me, in
the representing subject. (Kant already made the same point in his
account of transcendental synthesis: how do we get from the confused

161
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

multitude of passive subjective impressions to the consistent perception


of objective reality? By way of supplementing this subjective multitude
with, again, the subjects act of transcendental synthesis . . . )
Seidel is thus fully justied in emphasizing that Fichtes non-I is to be
read according to what Kant called innite judgment. Kant introduced
the key distinction between negative and innite judgment: the positive
judgment the soul is mortal can be negated in two ways, when a pred-
icate is denied to the subject (the soul is not mortal), and when a non-
predicate is afrmed (the soul is non-mortal) the difference is exactly
the same as the one, known to every reader of Stephen King, between
he is not dead and he is un-dead. The innite judgment opens up
a third domain which undermines the underlying distinction: the
undead is neither alive nor dead, it is precisely the monstrous living
dead. And the same goes for inhuman: he is not human is not the
same as he is inhuman he is not human means simply that he is
external to humanity, animal or divine, while he is inhuman means
something thoroughly different, namely the fact that he is neither
human nor not human, but marked by a terrifying excess which,
although it negates what we understand as humanity, is inherent to
being-human. And, perhaps, one should risk the hypothesis that this is
what changes with the Kantian revolution: in the pre-Kantian universe,
humans were simply humans, beings of reason, ghting the excesses of
animal lusts and divine madness, while only with Kant and German
Idealism the excess to be fought became absolutely immanent, the very
core of subjectivity itself (which is why, with German Idealism, the
metaphor for the core of subjectivity is Night, Night of the World, in
contrast to the Enlightenment notion of the Light of Reason ghting
the darkness around). So, when in the pre-Kantian universe a hero
goes mad, it means he is deprived of his humanity, i.e., the animal
passions or divine madness took over, while with Kant, madness signals
the unconstrained explosion of the very core of a human being. In
precisely the same way, the Fichtean non-Self is not a negation of the
predicate, but an afrmation of a non-predicate: it is not this is not a
Self, but rather this is a non-Self, which is why one should translate it
into English more often as non-Self rather than not-Self.46 (More
precisely: the moment we pass to Fichtes third proposition the mutual
delimitation/determination of Self and non-Self, the non-Self effec-
tively turns into a not-Self, something.)

162
FICHTES LAUGHTER

Fichte starts with the thetic judgment: I = I, pure immanence of Life,


pure Becoming, pure self-positing, Tat-Handlung, the full coincidence of
the posited with the positing. I am only through my process of positing
myself, and I am nothing but this process this is intellectual intuition,
this mystical ow inaccessible to consciousness: every consciousness
needs something opposed to itself. Now here comes the key the rise
of non-I out of this pure ow is not (yet) a delimitation of the I: it is
a pure formal conversion, like Hegels passage from Being to Nothing-
ness. Both I and non-I are unlimited, absolute. How, then, do we pass from
the non-I to the object as not-I? Through Ansto, this ex-timate obstacle.
Ansto is neither non-I (which comprises me) nor an object (which is
externally opposed to me). Ansto is neither absolutely nothing nor
something (a delimited object); it is (to refer to the Lacanian logic of
suture, as it was deployed by Miller in his classical text) nothing counted
something (in the same way as the number one is zero counted as one).
The distinction between form and content on which Fichte insists so
much is crucial here: as to its content, Ansto is nothing; as to its form, it
is (already) something it is thus nothing in the form of something.
This minimal distinction between form and content is already at work in
the passage from the rst to the second thesis: A = A is the pure form, the
formal gesture of self-identity, the self-identity of a form with itself; non-
Self is its symmetrical opposite, a formless content. This minimal reex-
ivity is also what makes the passage from A = A (I = I) to the positing of
non-self necessary: without this minimal gap between form and content,
the absolute Self and the absolute non-Self would simply and directly
overlap.
In the preface to the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason Kant
contends that all possible speculative knowledge of reason is limited to
mere objects of experience. But our further contention must also be duly
borne in mind, namely, that though we cannot know these objects as
things in themselves, we must yet be in position at least to think them as
things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd con-
clusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.47
Is this not exactly the Hegelian-Lacanian thesis? Is the Suprasensible
which is appearance qua appearance not precisely an appearance in
which nothing appears? Or, as Hegel put it in another passage of his
Phenomenology, beyond the veil of appearances there is only what the
subject puts there.48 This is the secret of the Sublime that Kant was not

163
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

ready to confront. And, back to Fichte, is the Ansto not precisely such an
appearance without anything that appears, a nothing which appears
as something? This is what makes the Fichtean Ansto uncannily close
to the Lacanian objet petit a, the object-cause of desire, which is also
a positivization of a lack, a stand-in for a void.
Some decades ago, Lacan provoked reactions of ridicule when he stated
that the meaning of phallus is the square of 1 but it was already Kant
who compared the thing-in-itself as ens rationis to a square root of a neg-
ative number.49 It is insofar as we apply this comparison also to Fichtes
Ansto that the Kantian distinction between what we can only think and
what we can know assumes all its weight: we can only think the Ansto,
we cannot know it as a determinate object-of-representation.

7. THE POSITED PRESUPPOSITION

To recapitulate, Fichtes attempt to get rid of the thing-in-itself follows a


very precise logic and intervenes at a very precise point of his critique of
Kant. Let us recall that, for Kant, the Thing is introduced as the X that
affects the subject when it experiences an object through its senses: the
Thing is primarily the source of sensual affections. If, then, we are to get
rid of the Thing, it is absolutely crucial to show how the subject can affect
itself, how it can act upon itself, not only at the intelligible level but also
at the level of (sensual) affections the absolute subject must be capable
of temporal auto-affection.
For Fichte, this Is sentimental auto-affection by means of which the
subject experiences its own existence, its own inert given character, and
thus relates to itself (or, rather, is for itself) as passive, as affected, is the
ultimate foundation of all reality. This does not mean that all reality, all
experience of the other as inert/resisting, can be reduced to the subjects
self-experience; it means that it is only the subjects passive self-relation
which opens the subject up to experience otherness.
Therein culminates Fichtes entire effort, in the deployment of the
notion of the subjects sensual auto-affection as the ultimate synthesis
of the subject and the object. If this is feasible, then there is no longer the
need to posit, behind the transcendental Is spontaneity, the unknowable
noumenal X that the subject really is: if there is genuine self-affection,

164
FICHTES LAUGHTER

then the I is also able to fully know itself, i.e, we no longer have to refer
to a noumenal I or He or It (the thing) which thinks as Kant does in the
Critique of Pure Reason. And, thereby, we can also see how Fichtes urgency
to get rid of the thing-in-itself is linked to his focus on the ethico-
practical engagement of the subject as grounded in the subjects freedom:
if the subjects phenomenal (self)experience is just the appearance of an
unknown noumenal substance, then our freedom is merely an illusory
appearance and we are really like puppets whose acts are regulated by an
unknown mechanism. As I pointed out, Kant was fully aware of this
radical consequence and, perhaps, the entire Fichte can be read as an
attempt to avoid this Kantian impasse.
But, one may ask, does this assertion of the subjects capacity to get to
fully know itself not contradict Fichtes very focus on the subject as
practically engaged, struggling with objects/obstacles that frustrate its
endeavor, which necessarily makes the subject nite? Is it not that only
an innite being can fully know itself? The answer is that the Fichtean
subject is precisely the paradoxical conjunction of these two features, of
nitude and freedom, since its innity itself (the innite striving of its
ethical engagement) is an aspect of its nite condition.
The key is here again provided by Fichtes notion of the mutual delimi-
tation of subject and object, of Self and non-Self: every activity posited
in/as the object only insofar as the Self is posited as passive; and this
positing of the Self as passive is still an act of the Self, its self-limitation.
I am only a passive X affected by objects insofar as I (actively) posit myself
as a passive recipient Seidel ironically calls this the law of the conser-
vation of activity: when reality (activity) is canceled in the self, that
quantum of reality (activity) gets posited in the non-self. If activity is
posited in the non-self, then its opposite (passivity) is posited in the self:
I (passively) see the (actively) blooming apple. However, this can only
happen because I (actively) posit passivity in my-self so that activity
may be posited in the non-self. [. . .] The non-self cannot act upon my
consciousness unless I (actively, that is, freely) allow it to do so.50
Kant already pregured this in his so-called incorporation thesis:
causes only affect me insofar as I allow them to affect me. This is why
you can because you ought: every external impossibility (to which the
excuse I know I must do it, but I cannot, it is impossible . . . refers) relies
on a disavowed self-limitation. Applied to the sexual opposition of the
active male and passive female stance, this Fichtean notion of the

165
MYTHOLOGY, MADNESS, AND LAUGHTER

activity of the non-I as strictly correlative to the Is passivity brings us


directly to Otto Weiningers notion of woman as the embodiment of
mans fall: woman exists (as a thing out there, acting upon man, disturb-
ing/perturbing his ethical stance, throwing him off the rails) only insofar
as man adopts the stance of passivity. She is literally the result of mans
withdrawal into passivity, so there is no need for man to ght actively
woman his adopting of an active stance automatically pulls the ground
from womans existence, since her entire being is nothing but mans
non-being.
Here, the question emerges: Fichte asks himself whether the quantity
(that is, the activity) of the self can ever equal zero (= 0), whether the
self can ever be totally at rest, ever totally passive. Fichtes answer is, of
course, no: For the non-self has reality only to the extent that the self
is affected by it; otherwise, as such, it has no reality at all [. . .]. I do not
see anything I do not will to see.51 However, it is here that the way we
read the exact status of the non-Self is crucial: if we read it in accor-
dance with the Kantian innite judgment, i.e., as a non-Self that
comprises self itself (in the same way that the undead comprises the
dead), then, previous to positing objectivity, the constituting/constitu-
tive gesture of Ich should be an immobilization, a withdrawal, a self-
emptying of the non-Self, a self-reduction to zero, to a zero which is the
Self; this reduction to zero opens up the space, literally, for Is activity of
positing/mediating.
Fichte gets caught in a circle. His rst proposition is: A = A, I = I,
i.e., the absolute self-positing, the pure substanceless becoming, Tat-
Handlung, intellectual intuition. Then comes the second proposition:
A = non-A, I = non-I, the self posits a non-self which is absolutely
opposed to it the absolute contradiction. Then comes the mutual limi-
tation which resolves this self-contradiction, in its double form, practical
(the Self posits the not-self as limited by the self) and theoretical (the self
posits itself as limited by the not-self) they are at the same level, divisi-
ble. (Note the nesse of Fichtes reexive formulation: in theoretical
form, the self posits itself as limited, it does not directly posit the object
as limiting the self; in practical form, it posits the object as limited/
determined by the self, it does not directly posit itself as limiting/forming
the object.) The ambiguity lies in the fact that the absolute self of the
rst principle is not something [. . .]; it is simply what it is.52 Only with
delimitation,

166
FICHTES LAUGHTER

both are something: the not-self is what the self is not, and vice versa.
As opposed to the absolute self (though, as will be shown in due course,
it can only be opposed to it insofar as it is represented /by it/, not
insofar as it is in itself), the non-self is absolutely nothing [schlechthin
Nichts]; as opposed to the limitable self, it is a negative quantity.53
However, from the practical standpoint, the nite Self posits the innite
Self in the guise of the ideal of a unity of Self and not-Self, and, with it,
the non-self as an obstacle to be overcome. We thus nd ourselves in a
circle: the absolute Self posits non-self and then nitizes itself by its
delimitation; however, the circle closes itself, the absolute presupposition
itself (the pure self-positing) returns as presupposed, i.e., as the presup-
position of the posited, and, in this sense, as depending on the posited.
Far from being an inconsistency, this is the crucial, properly speculative,
moment in Fichte: the presupposition itself is (retroactively) posited by
the process it generates.
So, perhaps, before dismissing him as the climactic point of subjectivist
madness, we should give Fichte a chance.

167
Notes

Markus Gabriel/Slavoj iek

Introduction
1 Henrich (2008), p. 32.
2 Ibid.
3 See Kants own brief sketch of the history of pure reason at the end
of the First Critique: Kant (2003), B880884.
4 We thank Tom Krell (New York) for his various comments on the
text and for his help with the preparation of this manuscript for
publication.
5 This also accounts for the integration of skepticism into the motiva-
tion of the theoretical activity of Post-Kantian philosophy as such.
See Gabriel (2007); Franks (2000), (2003), (2005).
6 Henrich (2008), p. 32.
7 This point is brilliantly argued in Brandom (2005).
8 Hegel (1977), 76. Miller (poorly) translates this as an exposition of
how knowledge makes its appearance.
9 To be sure, for the later Fichte and Schelling, this necessity turns out
to be contingent on a higher order!
10 Henrich (2008), p. 52.
11 Ibid., p. 59.
12 Schelling (2006), p. 22.
13 iek (2006) offers an elaborate account of the notion of a
parallax.
14 Schulz (1975), p. 279.
15 My translation from the German: SW, X, 311: Betrachten wir den
hier geforderten oder als mglich gezeigten Vorgang im Allgemeinen,

168
NOTES

so erscheint er als ein Vorgang der Umkehrung und zwar einer


Umkehrung des Einen, des vorwirklichen Seyenden, des Prototyps
aller Existenz, indem, was in diesem das Subjekt ist, A, zum
Objekt, was Objekt ist (+A), zum Subjekt wird. Dieser Vorgang kann
daher die Universio genannt werden, das unmittelbare Resultat des
Vorgangs ist das umgekehrte Eine Unum versum, also Universum.
16 Cf. Hegel (1977), 155165.
17 See his magnum opus: Schrmann (2003).
18 Calvino (1993).
19 For a corroboration of this point see also Gabriel (2009d).
20 At the very outset of philosophy, Plato also approached this non-All
of the eld of logos in his Parmenides this is why Parmenides occupies
a unique place between early and late Plato: a gap becomes visible
here which Plato desperately tries to ll-in in his late dialogues.
Parmenides is a proto-version of Hegels logic, truly readable only
retroactively, from the standpoint of Hegels logic. Its 8 (or 9) hypo-
theses are the rst version of the complete (and non-All: complete in
the sense of no exception) set of categories, and, as in Hegels logic,
it is meaningless to ask which hypothesis is true true is the con-
clusion (nothing exists . . .), which throws us back into the entire
movement.
21 For an outline and explication of the various forms of naturalism
operative in contemporary normativity-Hegelianism see my Gabriel
(2007). There it is shown clearly that Hegel is not the naturalist Hegel
many contemporary readers would like him to be.

Markus Gabriel

The Mythological Being of Reection An Essay on Hegel, Schelling, and


the Contingency of Necessity
1 For a more comprehensive historical account of ontological monism
see Gabriel (2009a).
2 See Brandoms argument that the ontology of substances is rooted in
the usage of singular terms in Brandom (2000), chapter 4; Brandom
(1994), pp. 360404.
3 Pelevin (2001), pp. 139141.

169
NOTES

4 Heidegger (1997), p. 51: And what is it that we, from out of oursel-
ves, allow to stand-against? It cannot be a being. But if not a being,
the just a nothing [ein Nichts]. Only if the letting-stand-against of . . .
is a holding oneself in the nothing can the representing allow a not-
nothing [ein nicht-Nichts], i.e., something like a being if such a thing
shows itself empirically, to be encountered instead of a within the
nothing.
5 Seen in this light, Badious concept of the void ultimately commits
him (despite himself) to the void actually being out there. He does not
leave cosmology behind, as he claims, but rather reasserts it with his
recourse to an ontology of the void. Naming the void means displa-
cing it. It has no proper name, not even the void. For this reason,
there can be no ontology of the void. It is nothing but a withdrawal
that always forces us to yet another revocation of necessity.
6 I argue for the necessary incompleteness of metabasis, i.e. of the acti-
vity of constructing meta-languages, in Gabriel (2008), pp. 209215.
7 Wittgenstein (1969), 9397, 162, 167, 233, 262.
8 Wittgenstein (1979), p. 10e.
9 Wittgenstein (1953). Wittgenstein writes, a picture held us captive.
And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and
language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably (PI, 115).
10 Badiou (2007), p. 30: Ontology, axiom system of the particular
inconsistency of multiplicities, seizes the in-itself of the multiple by
forming into consistency all inconsistency and forming into inconsi-
stency all consistency. It thereby deconstructs any one-effect; it is
faithful to the non-being of the one, so as to unfold, without explicit
nomination, the regulated game of the multiple such that it is none
other than the absolute form of presentation, thus the mode in which
being proposes itself to any access.
11 Hegel (1969), p. 50.
12 Gadamer (2004), p. 296.
13 Hogrebe (1989). I give an overview of the contemporary debate on
Schelling in Gabriel (2005), pp. 271301 as well as in Gabriel (2006b),
13.
14 Michelle Kosch gives a good account of the relation between
Kierkegaards and Schellings critique of Hegel; Kosch (2006). See
also Matthews (2008), pp. 184, in particular, pp. 5468 and Houlgate
(1999). A good introduction is Bowie (1993).

170
NOTES

15 See the excellent edition with translation, introduction and notes by


Andre Bowie, Schelling (1994).
16 Some of the material is nally available in English. See Schelling
(2007) and (2008).
17 Frank (1975). See also the discussion of this topic in Bowie (1994),
pp. 2335.
18 Schelling, F. W. J., Smmtliche Werke, XIII, 353; XIV, 343, 347351.
19 SW, X, 101, 309; SW, XIII, 230.
20 SW, XII, 649.
21 For a comprehensive reconstruction of this aspect of Schelling
see Hay (2008).
22 See also Gabriel (2007) and Gabriel (forthcoming).
23 Hogrebe (2007b). A similar point is made by Bataille (2005).
24 Hegel (1969), p. 400.
25 Kant (2003), B626.
26 Ibid., A601/B629: Whatever, therefore, and however much, our
concept of an object may contain, we must go outside it, if we are to
ascribe existence to the object. In the case of objects of the senses,
this takes place through their connection with some one of our
perceptions, in accordance with empirical laws. But in dealing with
objects of pure thought, we have no means whatsoever of knowing
their existence, since it would have to be known in a completely
a priori manner. Our consciousness of all existence (whether
immediately through perception, or mediately through inferences
which connect something with perception) belongs exclusively to
the unity of experience; any [alleged] existence outside this eld,
while not indeed such as we can declare to be absolutely impossible,
is of the nature of an assumption which we can never be in a position
to justify.
27 Ibid., pp. A158/B197.
28 Ibid., p. A111.
29 Wittgenstein (1961), prop. 5.633.
30 See Henrich (1967); Sturma (1985); Frank (1991).
31 iek (2008), p. XXIX.
32 In order to avoid the deadlock of reication the later Fichte in his
1804 lectures on The Science of Knowing, proposed the method of
genesis (Genetisieren) as opposed to facticity: whenever we believe
to have grasped some seemingly original unity (an original fact,

171
NOTES

therefore: facticity), we must reect on the fact that we necessarily


missed the original unity. Fichte refers to this act of higher-order reec-
tion on the constitution of a domain of facts in terms of a genesis.
33 Fichte (2005), p. 42: If the absolutely inconceivable is to be manifest
as solely self-substaining, then the concept must be annulled, but to
be annulled, it must be posited, because the inconceivable becomes
manifest only with the negation of the concept.
34 Hegel (1969), p. 395.
35 Meillassoux (2008), pp. 37. In the second part of this chapter I will
side with Meillassoux (and Schelling) arguing that we do indeed
have to make sense of some absolute outside (p. 7). In my Man
in Myth (Der Mensch im Mythos Gabriel (2006b)) I already argued
that Schellings philosophy is concerned with the absolute outside
(absolutes Auerhalb) of reason (p. 113 and the whole 9). However,
pace Meillassoux, this does not entail the return to pre-critical (After
Finitude, p. 7) thinking he himself envisages.
36 See p. 126 in this volume.
37 This distinction has been elaborated by Brandom (1994), p. 72.
38 Eshelman (2008).
39 McDowell (1998), p. 435. It is remarkable that McDowell whose pri-
mary work is called Mind and World spends almost all of his concep-
tual effort analyzing the former while barely mentioning the latter.
40 Kant (2003), B404.
41 iek (2008), p. 2.
42 Schelling (2006), p. 21.
43 I elaborate on the relation between Schelling and Lynch in Gabriel
(2009b). See also iek (2000).
44 In my Skeptizismus und Idealismus in der Antike (Gabriel (2009a))
I argue that ancient philosophy (pace Bernard Williams and Myles
Burnyeat) is build on external world skepticism. What changes
in modern philosophy after Descartes is that the subject gradually
discovers that it cannot be a substance which entails a more radical
problem of the internal world.
45 Fichte (1987), p. 64.
46 Pelevin (2001), p. 270.
47 In the vein of Nagel (1989) I argue for this in my recent book An den
Grenzen der Erkenntnistheorie; Gabriel (2008).
48 iek (2008), p. LXXXV.

172
NOTES

49 Hegel (1969), p. 395.


50 Ibid.
51 Ibid.
52 In the chapter on illusory being Hegel equates the phenomenon of
skepticism with the Appearance of idealism; Hegel (1969), p. 396.
53 Trendelenburg (1867).
54 The metaphor of the glasses is, of course, due to Heinrich von Kleist.
Cf. Kleist (1999), pp. 213214 for his famous letter to Wilhelmine
von Zenge from March 22, 1801.
55 Kant (2003), A26/B42.
56 Ibid., B72.
57 Hegel (1969), p. 398.
58 Ibid., p. 400.
59 See for example Hegel (2002), 7.
60 See Henrich (1978), p. 228.
61 If we apply this to the paradoxical twists of contemporary French
philosophy, in particular to the emergence of the event, we can
easily discern its (disavowed) Hegelian origin and its attempt to
overcome Hegelian immanence in favor of either Messianic openness
to the Other (Lvinas, Derrida) or of the event of Truth despite its
apparent impossibility (Badiou). The thought of the event tries to
think something which cannot be accounted for by reection.
If there is to be an event, it must surpass the limits of reection.
62 Hegel (1969), p. 431.
63 Ibid., p. 434.
64 Hegel (1971), 383.
65 Ibid.
66 Ibid., 384.
67 See Castoriadis notion of ontological genesis or absolute creation
in Castoriadis (1997a), pp. 180, 190, 227.
68 Hegel (1969), p. 399.
69 Gadamer (1999), p. 1.
70 Heidegger (1998), p. 41.
71 Heidegger (1999), p. 283.
72 Crispin Wright has developed a very subtle account of the role of
norms-in-context play in the constitution of discursive determinacy
in Wright (2004a). For the Wittgensteinian origins of this idea
see also Wright (2004b).

173
NOTES

73 Castoriadis (1997b), p. 300.


74 Nancy makes a similar observation in The Speculative Remark when
he investigates the sublation of the opening word of the Logic which
cannot be a sublation in the yet-to-be established sense. Therefore,
the rst sublation is suppressed by Hegel, giving way to the always
already of sublation. For this reason Nancy points out that the
beginning of the aufheben is a voice, a language or a word, that is
uttered and becomes more pronounced by itself, without origin and
without grammar (Nancy (2001), p. 34).
75 Hegel (1969), p. 601.
76 Hegel (1977), 47.
77 Hegel (1991), 81, Addition.
78 Hegel (1969), p. 706.
79 Hlderlin (1988), p. 37.
80 Kant (2003), B300.
81 Hlderlin (1988), p. 37.
82 Hegel (1969), pp. 706707.
83 Kant (2003), B610611; 647648.
84 Ibid., A582583/B610611.
85 Kant (2003), A582583/B610611: If we [ . . . ] proceed to hypo-
statize this idea of the sum of all reality, that is because we substi-
tute dialectically for the distributive unity of the empirical employment
of the understanding, the collective unity of experience as a whole;
and then thinking this whole [realm] of appearance as one single
thing that contains all empirical reality in itself; and then again, in
turn, by means of the above-mentioned transcendental subreption,
substituting for it the concept of a thing which stands at the source
of the possibility of all things, and supplies the real conditions for
their complete determination. Further, see Gabriel (2006b), 5.
86 Kant (2003), A293/B349.
87 McDowell (1996), p. 18.
88 This notion goes back to Cavell, Stanley (2006). Cavell explicitly
acknowledges his debt to Foucaults history of collecting in The
Order of Things: We should be cautious in saying that with natural
objects we know where the next specimen or part ts, whereas
with the artifact we have to nd where it ts best cautious because
of what we learn from work made most famous in Foucaults
texts, especially The Order of Things, that knowledge grounded in

174
NOTES

classication is not a discovery derived from a clear accumulation of


facts but itself required a set of intellectual/historical conditions in
which a new conception of knowledge (or episteme) was possible in
which a new counting, or order, of facts was made visible (p. 269).
89 I am, of course, referring here to Goodman (1978).
90 Nietzsche (1974), 374.
91 Kant himself uses the metaphor of a horizon which later became
prominent in the vein of Husserlian phenomenology. Kant (2003),
A658/B686687: The systematic unity, prescribed by the three logi-
cal principles, can be illustrated in the following manner. Every con-
cept may be regarded as a point which, as the station for an observer,
has its own horizon, that is, a variety of things which can be repre-
sented, and, as it were, surveyed from that standpoint. This horizon
must be capable of containing an innite number of points, each of
which has its own narrower horizon; that is, every species contains
subspecies, according to the principle of specication, and the logical
horizon consists exclusively of smaller horizons (subspecies), never
of points which possess no extent (individuals). But for different
horizons, that is, genera, each of which is determined by its own
concept, there can be a common horizon, in reference to which, as
from a common centre, they can all be surveyed; and from this hig-
her genus we can proceed until we arrive at the highest of all genera,
and so at the universal and true horizon, which is determined from
the standpoint of the highest concept, and which comprehends
under itself all manifoldness genera, species, and subspecies.
92 Kant (2003), A574/B602603.
93 Ibid., A575/B603.
94 Ibid.
95 Ibid., A576/B604.
96 Ibid.
97 SW, XI, 291, 313.
98 Adorno (1995), p. 5.
99 Badiou (2007), p. 48.
100 SW, X, 101, 309; SW, XIII, 230.
101 Frege (1950), p. 87 (74).
102 Ibid.
103 Badiou (2007), p. 53.
104 Wittgenstein (1969), 253.

175
NOTES

105 I further elaborate this point in Gabriel (2008), 1415.


106. iek (2008), p. 86.
107 Hegel (1974a), p. XIII.
108 This point is convincingly argued in Hogrebe (1996).
109 As Wittgenstein has argued in a similar vein in the Tractatus, there
is no straightforward way of comparing language with the world
without making use of language which entails that the conditions
of possibility of reference cannot themselves be the objects of
a reference. The conditions of possibility of reference are not them-
selves objects within the world and yet they are the objects of
Wittgensteins meta-discourse which, for this very reason, declares
itself non-sensical at the peak of reection; Wittgenstein (1961).
110 SW, XIV, 337.
111 SW, XIV, 341.
112 See Meillassoux (2008), pp. 3942, 60. Meillassoux points out that
classical correlationism (the a priori identication of being and
thought, of being and being given to . . .) draws a distinction
between 1. The intra-worldly contingency which is predicated of
everything that can be or not be, occur or not occur, within the
world without contravening the invariants of language and
representation through which the world is given to us and 2. The
facticity of these invariants as such, which is a function of our
inability to establish either their necessity or their contingency.
Meillassoux himself absolutizes facticity by stating a new principle
of unreason: There is no reason for anything to be or to remain
the way it is; everything must, without reason, be able not to be
and/or be able to be other than it is. This absolute facticity, how-
ever, has already been developed by Schelling with one important
difference: Schelling argues for the ultimate contingency of neces-
sity, including the necessity of contingency Meillassoux insists on.
113 SW, XI, 317; XIV, 346.
114 Schelling (1994), p. 147.
115 SW, X, 282; XIII, 263278; XIV, 342343.
116 SW, XIV, 354.
117 On the notion of non-ground see Gabriel (2006a).
118 The English translation We seek the absolute everywhere, and only
ever nd things, to be found in: Novalis (1997), p. 23. This transla-
tion, of course, completely misses the wordplay.

176
NOTES

119 SW, XIV, 338.


120 SW, XIV, 341342.
121 Blumenberg (1985a), p. 19.
122 Ibid., p. 4. Curiously, Blumenberg goes on to consider that inten-
tionality the coordination of parts into a whole, of qualities into
an object, of things into a world may be the cooled off aggregate
condition of such early accomplishments of consciousness (p. 21),
whereby he primarily refers to attention and affect. The paradox,
of course, consists in a conjunction of the two claims that
(1) anxiety, i.e. a form of intentionality, triggers the development
of attention and affect such that (2) intentionality as such is the
cooled off outcome of this process. In other words, intentionality
cannot be the result of a process which presupposes a form of
intentionality to get off the ground, in the rst place. This paradox
is an instance of Derridean diffrance. Like in Freuds Totem and Taboo
or in Rousseaus theory of the social contract, that which is sup-
posed to be established through a process (lawlike structures) is
presupposed to be always already operative at the beginning. This is
the interlacing of archeology and teleology, Derrida points out in
Derrida (1967), pp. 168, 283, 326, 349sqq.
123 Ibid., p. 3.
124 SW, XIV, 338.
125 Hegel (1969), pp. 550553.
126 Marx (1988), pp. 159160, makes the same point as Schelling in his
Critique of Hegels Philosophy in General: If, however, the philosophy
of religion, etc., is for me the sole true existence of religion then,
too, it is only as a philosopher of religion that I am truly religious, and
so I deny real religious sentiment and the really religious man. But at
the same time I assert them, in part within my own existence or
within the alien existence which I oppose to them for this is only
their philosophic expression and in part I assert them in their distinct
original shape, since for me they represent merely the apparent
other-being, allegories, forms of their own true existence (i.e. of my
philosophical existence) hidden under sensuous disguises.
127 Lvi-Strauss (1979), p. 1.
128 Ibid., p. 12.
129 Schelling (2008), p. 136.
130 Ibid., p. 40.

177
NOTES

131 Ibid., p. 153.


132 Ibid., p. 152.
133 Ibid., p. 135.
134 Ibid., pp. 120121.
135 SW, XIII, 257.
136 Freud (1950), p. 96.
137 Ibid., p. 81.
138 Schelling (2008), pp. 144, 150.
139 See also Blumenbergs notion of the pluperfect (Vorvergangenheit)
in Blumenberg (1985a), p. 21: To speak of beginnings is always to
be suspected of a mania for returning to origins. Nothing wants to
go back to the beginning that is the point toward which the lines of
what we are speaking of here converge. On the contrary, everything
apportions itself according to its distance from that beginning.
Consequently it is more prudent to speak of the pluperfect rather
than of origins. This pluperfect is not that of an omnipotence of
wishes, which would have submitted to compromise with reality, as
realism, only after colliding with the hostility of what does not
bow to wishes. There we can only imagine the single absolute
experience that exists: that of the superior power of the Other.
140 Schelling (2008), pp. 153154.
141 See for example ibid., p. 126.
142 Ibid., p. 126.
143 Ibid., p. 126.
144 McDowell (1996), Lecture 2.
145 Hegel (1969), p. 842.
146 Hegel (1977), 47.
147 Ibid., 109.
148 Blumenberg argues that the idealistic project of autogenesis
assumes the shape of a last myth. See Blumenberg (1985),
pp. 265270.
149 Bernstein (2002), p. 186.
150 See Lyotards argumentation against the possibility of an absolute
phrase regiment in Lyotard (1988).
151 Schelling (2008), p. 38. Schelling is making an implicit and
critical reference to Hegel here. Hegel himself uses the term pure
essentialities (Wesenheiten) frequently. See, for example, Hegel
(1969), p. 28.

178
NOTES

152 Quine (1964), p. 42: The totality of our so-called knowledge or


beliefs, from the most casual matters of geography and history to
the profoundest laws of atomic physics or even of pure mathema-
tics and logic, is a man-made fabric which impinges on experience
only along the edges. Or, to change the gure, total science is like a
eld of force whose boundary conditions are experience. See also
his famous pragmatist claim that the concept of physical objects
only differs from a belief in Homers gods by degree, itself being a
myth: For my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in physical
objects and not in Homers gods; and I consider it a scientic
error to believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing
the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in
kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conception only as cultural
posits. The myth of physical objects is epistemologically superior
to most in that it has proved more efcacious than other myths
as a device for working a manageable structure into the ux of
experience.
153 Berkeley (1998), p. 182.
154 I owe this distinction to discussions with Tom Krell.
155 Blumenberg (1998), p. 10.
156 Ibid., p. 12.
157 Ibid., p. 10.
158 This observation goes back to Cavell (1999), pp. 5253. See also
Conant (2004).
159 Hesiods Theogony (1999), p. 116.
160 Schelling (2008), p. 30; see also p. 35.
161 Interestingly, Epicurus is said to have rst been drawn to philoso-
phy at the tender age of fourteen when his schoolteacher was not
able to explain to him the origin of Chaos. See Sextus Empiricus
(1936), pp. 1819: For he who said Verily rst created of all was
Chaos; thereafter / Earth broad-bosomd, of all things the seat is
refuted by himself; for if someone asks him from what did Chaos
come into being?, he will have no answer. And this, as some say,
was the reason why Epicurus took to philosophizing. For when still
quite a youth he asked his schoolmaster, who was reading out the
line Verily rst created of all was Chaos, what Chaos was created
from, if it was created rst. And when he replied that it was not his
business, but that of the men called philosophers, to teach things of

179
NOTES

that sort, Well then, said Epicurus, I must go off to them, if it is


they who know the truth of things.
162 Wittgenstein (1969), 94.
163 Ibid., 95.
164 Ibid., 101.
165 Ibid., 159.
166 Wittgenstein (1980), p. 7. The contingency of framework proposi-
tions is obvious when we consider Wittgensteins insistence that
nobody has ever been to the moon or could ever go to the moon:
If we are thinking within our system, then it is certain that no one
has ever been on the moon. Not merely is nothing of the sort ever
seriously reported to us by reasonable people, but our whole system
of physics forbids us to believe it (Wittgenstein (1969), 108).
167 Wittgenstein (1969), 132.
168 Ibid., 130.
169 Ibid., 559.
170 Ibid., 475.
171 iek (2008), p. LXXIV.
172 Scheling (2008), p. 117.
173 Adorno/Horkheimer (2002), p. 19.
174 Ibid., p. 18.
175 Ibid., p. 11.
176 Blumenberg has spelled this out in extenso in both his The Legitimacy
of the Modern Age (1985b) and The Genesis of the Copernican World
(1989).
177 See Wright (2004) in particular pp. 207209.
178 Schlegel (1968).
179 Wittgenstein (1969), 344.
180 Kant (2003), A584/B611, footnote.
181 See the rst essay of Jonas (2001).
182 For a recent defense of animism after disenchantment see Hogrebe
(2007a).
183 I tried to spell this out in the wake of Brandoms distinction
between sense-dependent and reference-dependent idealism in
Gabriel (2008).
184 Hyppolite (1997), p. 95.
185 Kant (2003), A250251.

180
NOTES

186 Priest (1995).


187 Bataille (2004), p. 157. See also his similar remark in Bataille
(2005), p. 123: I insist on the insulated nature of my language. It is
through a brutal, aggressive negation that I designate an experience
that in itself is a negation of understanding.
188 Cavell (1999), p. 236.
189 Meillassoux (2008), p. 47.
190 Ibid., p. 66.
191 I agree with Rancire that democratic politics drawing on the
presupposition of equality at the same time presupposes the pure
contingency of all order. Cf. Rancire (1995), pp. 3637, 48.
192 Meillassoux (2008), p. 67.
193 Ibid., p. 60.
194 Rilke uses being here as a name for radical immanence in the
Duino Elegies; see Rilke (1974). Cf. Seventh Elegy, vs. 39; Ninth
Elegy, vs. 10.
195 Meillassoux (2008), p. 53.
196 Without going into details here, one can even venture to claim that
globalization is the attempt of concealing the void by creating a
world which disavows its contingency. The relation between the
concept of the world and globalization has famously been analyzed
by Nancy (2007).
197 Elsewhere I argued that this is the ontological message of Malevichs
Black Square. See Gabriel/Halfwassen (2008), pp. 257277.
198 Meillassoux (2008), p. 3: In order to reactivate the Cartesian
thesis in contemporary terms, and in order to state it in the same
terms in which we intend to uphold it, we shall therefore maintain
the following: all those aspects of the object that can be formulated in
mathematical terms can be meaningfully conceived as properties of the
object in itself. All those aspects of the object that can give rise to a
mathematical thought (to a formula or to digitalization) rather
than to a perception or sensation can be meaningfully turned into
properties of the thing not only as it is with me, but also as it is
without me.
199 Wright (1992).
200 The Consequences of Nonknowledge, in Bataille (2004),
pp. 111118.

181
NOTES

201 Ibid., p. 111.


202 Ibid., p. 112.
203 This is why I tried to motivate a revival of idealism in the sense of
higher-order reection as the proper domain of philosophy in
Gabriel (2008) arguing against the analytic identication of idea-
lism with ontic creationism. The crudest example of a misunder-
standing of higher-order reection and its relation to correlationism
has recently been set forth by Paul Boghossian (2006) in his book
Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism.
204 Bataille (2004), p. 112.
205 Ibid., p. 113.
206 Ibid., p. 113.
207 Bataille (ibid., p. 157) speaks of the postulate of science: Without
doubt, it is possible to live in the progressively known world, not to
suffer given that one is waiting patiently for the progressive reduc-
tion of the unknown to the known. This is the postulate of science.
Suffering only begins if the vanity of a reduction of the unknown to
the known is revealed.
208 Poe (1996), p. 129.
209 Cavell (1999), p. 45; see also p. 48.
210 See Nagel (1989).
211 Cavell (1999), p. 365.
212 Wittgenstein (1969), 362.
213 Ibid., 368.
214 See Gehlen (1956). I rely here on the convincing remarks in
Robert M. Wallaces introduction to his translation of Blumenberg
(1985a) in particular, pp. XXIIXXIII.
215 Chasseguet-Smirgel (1998), p. 128.
216 Meillassoux (2008), p. 155.
217 Freud (1950), p. 187.
218 Ibid., p. 183.
219 Ibid., p. 164.
220 Wilshire (2002).
221 Ibid., p. 16.
222 Bataille (2004), p. 79. I owe this parallel to Tom Krell.
223 Lvi-Strauss (1979), p. 6.

182
NOTES

Slavoj iek

Discipline between Two Freedoms Madness and Habit in German


Idealism
1 Pippin (2005), p. 118.
2 Ibid., pp. 118119.
3 See Hegel (1975), pp. 176190.
4 See Derrida (1978).
5 Chesterton (1995), p. 45.
6 Malabou (2005), p. 117. (A work on which I rely here extensively.)
7 Ibid., p. 26.
8 I owe this observation to Caroline Schuster (Chicago).
9 There is, of course, a big difference between the zombie-like
sluggish automated movements and the subtle plasticity of habits
proper, of their rened know-how; however, these habits proper
arise only when the level of habits is supplemented by the level of
consciousness proper and speech. What the zombie-like blind
behavior provides is, as it were, the material base of the rened
plasticity of habits proper: the stuff out of which these habits
proper are made.
10 Hegel (1971), 410, Remark.
11 Ibid.
12 Alain (1983), p. 200.
13 Hegel (2002), 151, Addition.
14 Hegel (1971), 410, Addition.
15 Ibid.
16 Malabou (2005), p. 75.
17 Ibid., p. 70.
18 Ibid., pp. 7071.
19 Ibid., p. 76.
20 Ibid., p. 75.
21 Ibid., p. 57.
22 Inwagen (1990).
23 Varela (1996), p. 212.
24 Ravaisson (1984), p. 10.

183
NOTES

25 Hegel makes this point clear in his Logic: The activity of thought
which is at work in all our ideas, purposes, interests and actions is, as
we have said, unconsciously busy /. . ./ [E]ach individual animal is
such individual primarily because it is an animal: if this is true, then
it would be impossible to say what such an individual could still be if
this foundation were removed, Hegel (1976), pp. 3637.
26 Malabou (2005), p. 32.
27 Hegel (1971), 407.
28 Malabou (2005), p. 35.
29 Hegel (1971), 408.
30 Upon a closer look, it becomes clear that the Hegelian notion of
madness oscillates between the two extremes which one is tempted
to call, with reference to Benjamins notion of violence, constitutive
and constituted madness. First, there is the constitutive madness: the
radical contradiction of the human condition itself, between the
subject as nothing, as the evanescent punctuality and the subject as
all, as the horizon of its world. Then, there is the constituted
madness: the direct xation to, identication with, a particular
feature as an attempt to resolve (or, rather, cut short) the contradic-
tion. In a way homologous with the ambiguity of the Lacanian notion
of objet petit a, madness names at the same time the contradiction/
void and the attempt to resolve it.
31 Hegel (1971), 408, Addition.
32 Ibid.
33 Ibid., 401.
34 Hegel (1977), 310.
35 Malabou (2005), p. 71.
36 Ibid., p. 72.
37 Ibid., p. 68.
38 Hegel (1977), 322.
39 Ibid., 318.
40 See Marx (1978), p. 95.
41 Hegel (1977), 318.
42 Malabou (2005), p. 67.
43 Ibid., p. 68.
44 Hegel (1974b), p. 204. Further, in his Encyclopaedia, Hegel mentions
the night-like abyss within which a world of innitely nume-
rous images and presentations is preserved without being in

184
NOTES

consciousness (Hegel (1971) 453). Hegels historical source is here


Jacob Bohme.
45 Hegel (1977), 32.
46 Sartre (1957), p. 59.
47 Bernasconi (2006), p. 38.
48 Sartre also draws attention to a crucial distinction between this
kind of playing a role and a theatrical playing a role where the
subject merely imitates the gestures of a waiter for amusement of
the spectators or as part of a stage performance: in clear opposition
to the theatrical imitation, the waiter who plays being a waiter
really is a waiter. As Sartre put it, the waiter realizes the condition of
being a waiter, while an actor who plays a waiter on stage is irreali-
zed in his role; in linguistic terms, one can say that what accounts
for this difference is the performative status of my acts: in the case of
an actor, the performative efciency is suspended. A psychotic is
precisely the one who doesnt see (or, rather, feel) this difference:
for him, both the real waiter and the actor are just playing a role.
49 Malabou (2005), p. 74.

Slavoj iek

Fichtes Laughter
1 As to this last example, there are attempts to reconstruct Hegels
answer to Marxs materialist reversal of dialectics. Cf. Maker (1989).
See also my own defense of Hegel against Marx in chapter 1 of iek
(2006).
2 Walter Schulzs book The Accomplishment of German Idealism in
Schellings Late Philosophy advances just this thesis; see Schulze
(1975).
3 Zoeller (2008), p. 55.
4 Brachtendorf (2008), p. 157.
5 Ibid. This shift can also be formulated as the one from positing to
appearing: while in 1794, the I posits itself as positing itself, in 1812,
the appearance appears to itself as appearing to itself. To appear,
however, is an activity. Thus, the appearance appears to itself as
being active through itself, or as a principle from itself, out of itself,

185
NOTES

through itself. Fichte concludes that, since the appearance is


constituted by the act of appearing to itself, it conceives of its own
existence (its formal being) as grounded in itself. As soon as the
appearance reects on itself, it understands itself to exist through
itself, that is, to be a se. But this cannot be true, as the Wissenschafts-
lehre demonstrates. Only one is in the sense of aseitas, namely
the Absolute, so that appearance cannot truly be in this sense; Ibid.,
p. 158.
6 Fichte (1971a), Vol. 10, p. 365.
7 A brief note should be added here. The partisans of discourse ana-
lysis often rise against those who continue to emphasize the key
structural role of the economic mode of production and its dyna-
mics, with the reproach of vulgar Marxism or, another popular
catchword, economic essentialism: the insinuation is that such a
view reduces language to a secondary instrument, locating real
historical efciency only in the reality of material production.
There is, however, a symmetrical simplication which is no less
vulgar: that of proposing a direct parallel between language and
production, i.e., of conceiving in Paul de Man style language
itself as another mode of production, the production of sense.
According to this approach, in parallel with the reication of
productive labor in its result, the common-sense notion of speech as
a mere expression of some pre-existing sense also reies sense,
ignoring how sense is not only reected in speech, but generated by
it it is the result of signifying practice, as it was once fashionable
to say . . . One should reject this approach as the worst case of non-
dialectical formalism: it involves a hypostasis of production into
an abstract-universal notion which encompasses economic and
symbolic production as its two species, neglecting their radically
different status.
8 This is why the Kantian transcendental I, its pure apperception, is a
purely formal function which is neither noumenal nor phenomenal
it is empty, no phenomenal intuition corresponds to it, since, if it
were to appear to itself, its self-appearance would be the thing itself,
i.e., the direct self-transparency of a noumenon. The parallel between
the void of the transcendental subject ($) and the void of the tran-
scendental object, the inaccessible X that causes our perceptions,
is misleading here: the transcendental object is the void beyond

186
NOTES

phenomenal appearances, while the transcendental subject already


appears as a void.
9 See Pfaller (unpublished paper, 2002): What is substituted can also
appear itself, in a 1:1 scale, in the role of the substitute there only
must be some feature ensuring that it is not taken to be itself. Such a
feature is provided for by the threshold which separates the place of
what is substituting from what is being substituted or symbolizes
their detachment. Everything that appears in front of the threshold
is then assumed to be the ersatz, as everything that lies behind it is
taken to be what is being substituted. There are scores of examples of
such concealments that are obtained not by miniaturization but only
by means of clever localization. As Freud observed, the very acts
that are forbidden by religion are practiced in the name of religion.
In such cases as, for instance, murder in the name of religion
religion also can do entirely without miniaturization. Those ada-
mantly militant advocates of human life, for example, who oppose
abortion, will not stop short of actually murdering clinic personnel.
Radical right-wing opponents of male homosexuality in the USA act
in a similar way. They organize so-called gay bashings in the course
of which they beat up and nally rape gays. The ultimate homicidal
or homosexual gratication of drives can therefore also be attained,
if it only fulls the condition of evoking the semblance of a counter-
measure. What seems to be opposition then has the effect that the
x to be fended off can appear itself and be taken for a non-x.
10 This gap can also be the gap which separates dream from reality:
when, in the middle of the night, one has a dream about a heavy
stone or animal sitting on ones chest and causing pain, this dream,
of course, reacts to the fact that one has a real chest pain it invents
a narrative to account for the pain. However, the trick is not just to
invent a narrative, but a more radical one: it can happen that, while
having a chest pain, one has a dream of HAVING A CHEST PAIN
being aware that one is dreaming, the very fact of transposing the
pain into the dream has a calming effect (It is not a real pain, it is just
a dream!).
11 Galit (2000).
12 Fichte (1987), pp. IXXI.
13 Ibid., p. XI.
14 Bukharin (2005), p. 40.

187
NOTES

15 Ibid., p. 41.
16 Ibid., p. 46.
17 Ibid., p. 131.
18 Kant (1956), pp. 152153.
19 Fichte (1987), p. XII.
20 See Breazeadale (1995), pp. 87114.
21 Ibid., p. 100.
22 The solution to the mystery: he is effectively not the husband, but
the lover of the woman who claims to be his wife. When he barely
survived the accident while driving the husbands car, with his face
disgured beyond recognition, the wife killed her husband, identi-
ed HIM as her husband and ordered the surgeons to reconstruct his
face on the model of her husbands.
23 Portier (2005), p. 30.
24 Wittgenstein (1961), prop. 6.4311.
25 Bergman (1995), pp. 240241.
26 See Laclau (1995).
27 Portier (2005), pp. 134, 136.
28 Ibid., p. 54.
29 Seidel (1993), pp. 116117.
30 Portier (2005), p. 154.
31 Portier (2005), p. 158.
32 See Livet (1987).
33 Seidel (1993), p. 102.
34 Ibid., pp. 8788.
35 Sartre (1957), p. 327.
36 Bernasconi (2006), p. 48.
37 Portier (2005), p. 222.
38 Ibid., p. 244.
39 Ibid., p. 230.
40 Ibid., p. 238.
41 Ibid., p. 253.
42 Ibid., p. 232.
43 Ibid., p. 224.
44 Fichte (1971b), pp. 478479.
45 Quoted in Seidel (1993), pp. 5051.
46 Ibid., p. 89.
47 Kant (2003), Bxxvi.

188
NOTES

48 Hegel (1977), 165.


49 Kant, unedited reection from 17851788, quoted in Freuler (1992),
p. 223.
50 Seidel (1993), p. 104.
51 Ibid.
52 Ibid., p. 64.
53 Ibid., pp. 6465.

189
Bibliography

Adorno, T. W. (1995), Negative Dialectics. Tr. by E. B. Ashton. New York/


London: Continuum Press.
Adorno, T. W./Horkheimer, M. (2002), Dialectic of Enlightenment. Tr. by
E. Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Alain (1983), Idees. Paris: Flammarion.
Badiou, A. (2007), Being and Event. Tr. by Oliver Feltham. New York/
London: Continuum.
Bataille, G. (2004), The Unnished System of Nonknowledge. Tr. by
S. Kendall. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
(2005), The Cradle of Humanity. Prehistoric Art and Culture. Tr. by
S. Kendall. New York: Zone Books.
Bergman, I. (1995), My Life in Film. London: Faber and Faber.
Berkeley, G. (1998), A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowl-
edge. Ed. by Jonathan Dancy. Oxford/New York: Oxford University
Press.
Bernasconi, R. (2006), How to Read Sartre. London: Granta.
Bernstein, J. M. (ed.) (2002), Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blumenberg, H. (1985a), Work on Myth. Tr. by R. M. Wallace. Cambridge,
MA/London: MIT Press.
(1985b), The Legitimacy of the Modern Age. Tr. by R. M. Wallace.
Cambridge, MA/ London: MIT Press.
(1989), The Genesis of the Copernican World. Tr. by R. M. Wallace.
Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press.
(1998), Paradigmen zu einer Metaphorologie. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.

190
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Boghossian, P. (2006), Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructiv-


ism. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bowie, A. (1993), Schelling and Modern European Philosophy. An Introduc-
tion. London: Routledge.
(1994), Introduction, in Schelling (1994), pp. 140.
Brachtendorf, J. (2008), The Notion of Being in Fichtes Late Philosophy,
in D. Breazeale and T. Rockmore (eds), After Jena. New Essays on Fichtes
Later Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, pp. 151161.
Brandom, R. B. (1994), Making It Explicit. Reasoning, Representing, and
Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(2000): Articulating Reasons. An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge,
MA.: Harvard University Press.
(2005), Sketch of a Program for a Critical Reading of Hegel. Compar-
ing Empirical and Logical Concepts, International Yearbook of German
Idealism, 3, pp. 131161.
Breazeale, D. (1995), Check or Checkmate? On the Finitude of the
Fichtean Self, in K. Ameriks and D. Sturma (eds), The Modern Subject.
Conceptions of the Self in Classical German Philosophy. Albany: SUNY Press.
Bukharin, N. (2005), Philosophical Arabesques. London: Pluto Press.
Castoriadis, C. (1997a), The Imaginary Institution of Society. Tr. by Kathleen
Blamey. Cambridge: Polity Press.
(1997b), The Logic of Magmas and the Question of Autonomy, in
D. A. Curtis (ed.), The Castoriadis Reader. New York/Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Cavell, S. (1999), The Claim of Reason. Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and
Tragedy. New York: Oxford University Press.
(2006), The World as Things, in Id., Philosophy The Day After
Tomorrow. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.
Chasseguet-Smirgel, J. (1998), Creativity and Perversion. London: Free
Association Books.
Chesterton, G. K. (1995), Orthodoxy. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.
Conant, J. (2004), Varieties of Scepticism, in McManus, D. (ed.),
Wittgenstein and Scepticism. London: Routledge.
Derrida, J. (1978), Cogito and the History of Madness, in Id., Writing and
Difference. Tr. by Alan Bass. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
(1996), How to Avoid Speaking: Denials, in S. Budick and W. Iser
(eds), Languages of the Unsayable: The Play of Negativity in Literature and
Literary Theory. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

191
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Eshelman, R. (2008), Performatism or the End of Postmodernism. Aurora:


The Davis Group Publishers.
Fichte, J. G. (1971), Fichtes Werke. Ed. by I. H. Fichte. Berlin/New York:
Walter De Gruyter.
(1987), The Vocation of Man. Tr. by P. Preuss. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing.
(2005), The Science of Knowing: J. G. Fichtes 1804 Lectures on the
Wissenschaftslehre. Tr. by W. E. Wright. Albany: SUNY Press.
Foucault, M. (1994), The Order of Things. Tr. by Alan Sheridan. New York:
Vintage Books.
Frank, M. (1975), Der unendliche Mangel an Sein. Schellings Hegelkritik und
die Anfnge der Marxschen Dialektik. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
(1991), Selbstbewutsein und Selbsterkenntnis. Essays zur analytischen
Philosophie der Subjektivitt. Stuttgart: Reclam.
Franks, P. (2000), Transcendental Arguments, Reason, and Skepticism:
Contemporary Debates and the Origins of Post-Kantian Idealism, in
Robert Stern (ed.), Transcendental Arguments: Problems and Prospects.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 111146.
(2003), Does Post-Kantian Skepticism Exist?, International Yearbook
of German Idealism, 1, pp. 141163.
(2005), All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments, and
Skepticism in German Idealism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Frege, G. (1950), The Foundations of Arithmetic. Tr. by J. L. Austin. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Freud, S. (1950), Totem and Taboo. Some Points of Agreement between the
Mental Lives of Savages and Neurotics. Tr. by James Strachey. New York/
London: W. W. Norton & Company.
Freuler, L. (1992), Kant et la Metaphysique Speculative. Paris: Vrin.
Gabriel, M. (2005), Sein, Mensch und Bewutsein. Tendenzen der
neueren Forschung zur Sptphilosophie Schellings, Philosophische
Rundschau 52/4, pp. 271301.
(2006a), Das Absolute und die Welt in Schellings Freiheitsschrift. Bonn:
University Press.
(2006b), Der Mensch im Mythos. Untersuchungen ber Ontotheologie,
Anthropologie und Selbstbewutseinsgeschichte in Schellings Philosophie der
Mythologie. Berlin/New York: DeGruyter.

192
BIBLIOGRAPHY

(2007), Die metaphysische Wahrheit des Skeptizismus bei Schelling


und Hegel, International Yearbook of German Idealism 5.
(2008), An den Grenzen der Erkenntnistheorie. Die notwendige Endlichkeit
des objektiven Wissens als Lektion des Skeptizismus. Freiburg/Mnchen:
Alber.
Gabriel, M. and Halfwassen, J. (2008), Kunst, Metaphysik und Mythologie.
Heidelberg: Universittsverlag.
(2009a), Der sthetische Wert des Skeptizismus beim spten
Wittgenstein, in J. Volbers and G. Gebauer and F. Goppelsrder (eds),
Philosophie als Lebensform. Mnchen: Fink (forthcoming).
(2009b), Skeptizismus und Idealismus in der Antike. Frankfurt/Main:
Suhrkamp (forthcoming).
(2009), The Dialectic of the Absolute Hegels Critique of Transcen-
dent Metaphysics. Limnatis, Nectarios: The Dimensions of Hegels
Dialectic. New York/ London: Continuum (forthcoming).
(forthcoming), Endlichkeit und absolute Ich Heideggers
Fichtekritik, to be published in Fichte-Studien.
(forthcoming), The Uncanniness of Being Someone According to David
Lynch (Lost Highway, INLAND EMPIRE), in B. Devlin and S. Bidermann
(eds), The Philosophy of David Lynch. Lexington: University of Kentucky
Press.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1999), Kant and the Question of God, in Id.,
Hermeneutics, Religion, and Ethics. Tr. by Joel Weinsheimer. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
(2004), Truth and Method. Tr. by J. Weinsheimer and D. G. Marshall.
New York/London: Continuum.
Gehlen, A. (1956), Urmensch und Sptkultur. Bonn: Athenum.
Goodman, N. (1978), Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Company.
Hasan-Rokem, G. (2000), Web of Life. Folklore and Midrash in Rabbinic
Literature. Tr. by B. Stein. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Hay, K. (2008), Die Notwendigkeit des Scheiterns/Un chec ncessaire. Diss.
Paris/Mnchen.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Science of Logic. Tr. by A. V. Miller. Amherst, NY:
Humanity Books.
(1971), Philosophy of Mind: Part III of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical
Sciences. Tr. by A. V. Miller. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

193
BIBLIOGRAPHY

(1974a), Lectures on the Philosophy of History. Tr. E. S. Haldane and


F. Simson. London: Humanities Press.
(1974b), Jenaer Realphilosophie, in Fruehe politische Systeme.
Frankfurt: Ullstein, p. 204; translation quoted from Verene, D. P.
(1985), Hegels Recollection. Albany: SUNY Press, pp. 78.
(1975), Lectures on the Philosophy of World History. Introduction: Reason in
History. Tr. by H. B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(1977), Phenomenology of Spirit. Tr. by A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
(1991), The Encylopedia Logic. Tr. by H. S. Harris. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing.
(1998), Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. Tr. by T. M. Knox. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
(2002), Philosophy of Right. Tr. by A. White. Newburyport: Focus
Publishing.
Heidegger, M. (1978), Being and Time. Tr. by J. Macquarrie and
E. Robinson. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.
(1997), Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. Tr. by R. Taft. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
(1998), Phenomenology and Theology, Id., Pathmarks. Tr. by
W. McNeil. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(1999), Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning). Tr. by P. Emad and
K. Maly. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Henrich, D. (1967), Fichtes ursprngliche Einsicht. Frankfurt/Main:
Klostermann.
(1978), Hegels Logik der Reexion. Neue Fassung, in Id., Die
Wissenschaft der Logik und die Logik der Reexion. Bonn: Bouvier.
(2008), Between Kant and Hegel. Tr. D. S. Pacini. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Hesiods Theogony. Tr. and ed. by M. West. Oxford: Oxford University Press
(1999).
Hogrebe, W. (1989), Prdikation und Genesis. Metaphysik als Fundamental-
heuristik im Ausgang von Schellings Die Weltalter. Frankfurt/Main:
Suhrkamp.
(1996), Ahnung und Erkenntnis. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
(2007a), Das dunkle Du, in Id., Die Wirklichkeit des Denkens.
Heidelberg: Universittsverlag Winter, pp. 1135.

194
BIBLIOGRAPHY

(2007b), Sein und Emphase Schellings Theogonie als


Anthropologie, in Id. (2007a), pp. 3760.
Hlderlin, F. (1988), Essays and Letters on Theory. Tr. by T. Pfau. Albany:
SUNY Press.
Houlgate, S. (1999), Schellings Critique of Hegels Science of Logic,
in The Review of Metaphysics 1999 (1), pp. 100128.
Hyppolite, J. (1997), Logic and Existence. Tr. by L. Lawlor and A. Sen.
Albany: SUNY Press.
Inwagen, P. van (1990), Material Beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Jonas, H. (2001), The Phenomenon of Life. Toward a Philosophical Biology.
Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Kant, I. (1956), Critique of Practical Reason. Tr. L. W. Beck. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
(2003), Critique of Pure Reason. Tr. N. K. Smith. New York: Palgrave
MacMillan.
Kleist, H. v. (1999), Smtliche Briefe. Stuttgart: Reclam.
Kosch, M. (2006), Freedom and Reason in Kant, Schelling and Kierkegaard.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lacan, J. (1998), The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis ( The
Seminar of Jacques Lacan , Book 11). Tr. by A. Sheridan. New York:
W. W. Norton & Company.
Laclau, E. (1995), Emancipation(s). London: Verso Books.
Lvi-Strauss, C. (1979), The Raw and the Cooked. Introduction to a Science of
Mythology: I. Tr. J. and D. Weightman. Octagon Books: New York.
Livet, P. (1987), Intersubjectivite, reexivite et recursivite chez Fichte,
in Archives de Philosophie, pp. 581619.
Lyotard, J.-F. (1988), The Differend. Phrases in Dispute. Tr. by G. Van Den
Abbeele. Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press.
Maker, W. (1989), Hegels Critique of Marx, in W. Desmond (ed.), Hegel
and His Critics. Buffalo: SUNY Press, pp. 7292.
Malabou, C. (2005), The Future of Hegel. London: Routledge.
Marx, K. (1978), Class Struggles in France, in Id., Collected Works.
Vol. 10. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
(1988), Critique of Hegelian Dialectic and Philosophy as a Whole, in
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. Tr. M. Milligan. Amherst:
Prometheus Books, pp. 141170.
Matthews, Bruce (2007), Introduction, in Schelling (2007), pp. 184.

195
BIBLIOGRAPHY

McDowell, John (1996), Mind and World. Cambridge, MA/London:


Harvard University Press.
(1998), Having the World in View: Sellars, Kant, and Intentionality,
in The Journal of Philosophy XCV/9, pp. 431491.
Meillassoux, Quentin (2008), After Finitude. An Essay on the Necessity of
Contingency. Tr. by R. Brassier. New York/London: Continuum.
Nagel, T. (1989), The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Nancy, J.-L. (2001), The Speculative Remark (One of Hegels Bons Mots).
Tr. by Cline Surprenant. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
(2007), The Creation of the World or Globalization. Tr. by F. Raffoul and
D. Pettigrew. Albany: SUNY Press.
Nietzsche, F. (1974), The Gay Science. Tr. by W. Kaufmann. New York:
Vintage Books.
Novalis (1997), Philosophical Writings. Tr. by M. Stoljar. Albany: SUNY
Press.
Pelevin, V. (2001), Buddhas Little Finger. Tr. by A. Bromeld. New York:
Penguin Books.
Pfaller, R. (unpublished paper, 2002), The Potential of Thresholds
to Obstruct and to Facilitate. On the Operation of Displacement in
Obsessional Neurosis and Perversion.
Pippin, R. (2005), The Persistence of Subjectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Plato (1926), Cratylus, Parmenides, Greater Hippias, Lesser Hippias. Tr. H. N.
Fowler. Cambridge, MA: Loeb Classical Library.
Poe, E. A. (1996), Poetry, Tales, and Selected Essays. New York: Literary
Classics Press.
Portier, S. (2005), Fichte et le depassement de la chose en soi. Paris:
LHarmattan.
Preuss, P. (1987), Translators Introduction, in Fichte (1987), pp. vii xiv.
Priest, G. (1995), Beyond the Limits of Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1964), Two Dogmas of Empiricism, in Id., From
a Logical Point of View (second, revised edn). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, pp. 2046.
Rancire, J. (1995), La Msentente. Politique et philosophie. Paris: Galile.
Ravaisson, F. (1984), De lhabitude. Paris: Fayard.
Rilke, R. M. (1974), Duineser Elegien. Frankfurt/Main: Insel.

196
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Russell, B. (2004), History of Western Philosophy. London: Routledge.


Sartre, J.-P. (1957), Being and Nothingness. Tr. by H. Barnes. London:
Methuen.
Schelling, F. W. J. (18561861), Smmtliche Werke. Ed. by K. F. A.
Schelling, I. Abtheilung Vols. 110, II. Abtheilung Vols. 14. Stuttgart:
Cotta. This edition (SW) is quoted throughout with reference to
volume and page number.
(1994), On the History of Modern Philosophy. Tr. by A. Bowie. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
(2006), Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom.
Tr. by J. Love and J. Schmid. Albany: SUNY Press.
(2007), The Grounding of Positive Philosophy: The Berlin Lectures. Tr. with
an Introduction by B. Matthews. Albany: SUNY Press.
(2008), Historical-critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mythology. Tr. by
M. Richey and M. Zisselsberger with a foreword by J. M. Wirth.
Albany: SUNY Press.
Schlegel, Friedrich (1968), Dialogue on Poetry and Literary Aphorisms. Tr.
by E. Behler. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Schulz, W. (1975), Die Vollendung des Deutschen Idealismus in der Sptphilos-
ophie Schellings. Pfullingen: Neske.
Seidel, G. J. (1993), Fichtes Wissenschaftslehre of 1704. A Commentary on
Part I. West Lafayette: Purdue University Press.
Sextus Empiricus (1936), Against the Physicists. Tr. R. G. Bury. Cambridge,
MA: Loeb Classical Library.
Shakespeare, W. (2008), Alls Well that Ends Well. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press.
Sturma, D. (1985), Kant ber Selbstbewutsein. Zum Zusammenhang von
Erkenntniskritik und Theorie des Selbstbewutseins. Hildesheim/Zrich/
New York: Georg-Olms-Verlag.
Trendelenburg, F. A. (1867), ber eine Lcke in Kants Beweis von
der ausschlielichen Subjectivitt des Raumes und der Zeit,
in Id., Historische Beitrge zur Philosophie. Vol. 3, Berlin: Bethge,
pp. 215276.
Varela, Francisco (1996), The Emergent Self, in John Brockman,
ed., The Third Culture. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Verene, D. P. (1985), Hegels Recollection. Albany: SUNY Press.
Wallace, R. M. (1985), Translators Introduction, in Blumenberg
(1985a), pp. viixl.

197
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Wilshire, B. (2002), Fashionable Nihilism. A Critique of Analytic Philosophy.


Albany: SUNY Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations. Tr. by G. E. M.
Anscombe. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.
(1961), Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Tr. by D. F. Pears and
B. McGuinness. London: Routledge.
(1969), On Certainty. Tr. by G. E. M. Anscombe. Malden: Blackwell
Publishing.
(1980), Philosophical Remarks. Tr. by R. Hargreaves and R. White.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
(1992), Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Wright, C. (2004a), Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?,
in Aristotelian Society Supplementary 78/1, pp. 167212.
(2004b), Wittgensteinian Certainties, in D. McManus (ed.), Wittgenstein
and Scepticism. London: Routledge, pp. 2255.
iek, Slavoj (2000), The Art of the Ridiculous Sublime. On David Lynchs Lost
Highway. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
(2006), The Parallax View. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(2008), For They Know not What They Do. Enjoyment as a Political Factor
(second edition). London: Verso.
Zller, G. (2008), Thinking and Willing in the Later Fichte, in
D. Breazeale and T. Rockmore (eds), After Jena. New Essays on Fichtes
Later Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, pp. 5166.

198
Index

Adorno, Theodor 72, 95, 146 Calvino, Italo 89


Alain 101 Carrey, Jim 144
Ambrosino, Mario 86 Carroll, Lewis 131
Angelus Silesius 143 Castoriadis, Cornelius 44, 58,
Aristotle 845, 99, 122 173
Ayer, Alfred Jules 86, 93 Cavallo, Domingo 132
Cavell, Stanley 67, 81, 889, 174
Bachelard, Gaston 89, 156 Chapayev, Vasily Ivanovich 17
Badiou, Alain 19, 21, 35, 534, Chaplin, Charles 123
82, 856, 170, 173 Chartier, mile see Alain
Bataille, Georges 81, 869, 93, 94 Chasseguet-Smirgel, Janine 92
Beiser, Frederick 123 Chesterton, Gilbert Keith 99
Benjamin, Walter 184 Christie, Agatha 133
Bergman, Ingmar 148 Coppola, Francis Ford 289
Berkeley, George 66
Bernasconi, Robert 117 Darwin, Charles Robert 13
Blumenberg, Hans 5960, 64, 67, de Man, Paul 186
87, 912, 1778 de Stal, Anne Louise
Bhme, Jacob 185 Germaine 125, 154
Botticelli, Sandro 38 Deleuze, Gilles 103, 109, 144
Bowie, Andre 171 Derrida, Jacques 98, 100, 173,
Brandom, Robert 13, 78, 180 177
Bucharin, Nikolai Descartes, Ren 27, 2930, 66,
Iwanowitsch 13940 73, 89, 98, 152, 172
Burnyeat, Myles 172 Diogenes of Sinope 1601

199
INDEX

Eisenstein, Sergei Hogrebe, Wolfram 201, 73


Michailowitsch 123 Hlderlin, Friedrich 47, 567, 60,
Eliade, Mircea 28 115
Epicurus 148, 17980 Homer 179
Eshelman, Raoul 28 Horkheimer, Max 72, 146
Hume, David 27, 30, 69, 110, 130
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 13, 67, Husserl, Edmund 87, 122, 156
225, 27, 33, 35, 47, 49, 75, Hyppolite, Jean 79
1227, 13743, 14568,
171, 186 Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich 24, 152
Fincher, David 144 Jean Paul 145
Flourens, Marie-Jean-Pierre 146 Jefferson, Thomas 99
Foucault, Michel 96, 174 Jesus Christ 41
Frank, Manfred 20, 23 Johnson, Al 132
Frege, Friedrich Ludwig Johnson, Samuel 66
Gottlob 54, 65 Jonas, Hans 77
Freud, Sigmund 12, 63, 93, 108,
177, 187 Kant, Immanuel 16, 1213, 22,
245, 27, 302, 358, 479,
Gadamer, Hans-Georg 19, 43 523, 73, 76, 87, 89, 91,
Gehlen, Arnold 91 959, 109, 110, 122, 130,
Goodman, Nelson 50 1404, 147, 14950, 155,
15965, 168, 175, 189
Habermas, Jrgen 13 Karadic, Radovan 134
Hegel, Georg Friedrich Kaufman, Charlie 28
Wilhelm 12, 58, 1013, Kierkegaard, Sren 12, 32, 75,
16, 1920, 227, 32, 346, 170
3849, 556, 58, 602, King, Stephen 162
645, 70, 77, 823, 97, Kosch, Michelle 170
99101, 1038, 11011, Krell, Tom 168 179, 182
11316, 1203, 127,
12930, 133, 141, 1525, Lacan, Jacques 70, 113, 115, 117,
159, 161, 163, 16970, 12830, 1334, 1367, 142,
1734, 178, 1845 147, 155, 158, 164
Heidegger, Martin 1719, 26, 31, Laclau, Ernesto 11920, 148
38, 43, 67, 87, 89, 912, Lee, Spike 132
119, 122, 141 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 152
Henrich, Dieter 23, 33, 40, 123 Lvi-Strauss, Claude 61, 62
Hesiod 678 Levinas, Emmanuel 83, 173

200
INDEX

Lichtenberg, Georg Christoph 113 Preuss, Peter 137


Livet, Pierre 154 Priest, Graham 80
Lynch, David 33, 144, 172 Putnam, Hilary 86
Lyotard, Jean-Franois 65, 178
Quine, Willard Van Orman 66,
McDowell, John 13, 172 78, 89
Malabou, Catherine 99, 108, 113,
116 Rancire, Jacques 181
Malevic, Kazimir Severinovic 181 Reinhold, Karl Leonhard 22
Margulis, Lynn 105, 153 Richter, Johann Paul Friedrich see
Marx, Karl 10, 12, 32, 70, 83, Jean Paul
115, 119, 122, 185 Rilke, Rainer Maria 181
Meillassoux, Quentin 26, 813, Rorty Richard McKay 6, 67
857, 89, 923, 172, Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 95,
176 177
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 86 Russell, Bertrand 4, 155
Miller, Arnold Vincent 168 Russell, David Owen 29
Miller, Jacques Alain 163
Mbius, August Ferdinand 131 Sartre, Jean-Paul 11718,
Moore, George Edward 4 1556, 185
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm
Nagel, Thomas 88 Joseph 12, 4, 67, 12,
Nancy, Jean-Luc 174 1921, 236, 33, 35, 50,
Nietzsche, Friedrich 32, 38, 70, 52, 54, 5660, 628, 71,
75, 83, 923, 107, 122 7980, 923, 97, 1224,
Nikolaus Cusanus 67 127, 155, 15960, 168,
Novalis 59 1702, 1768
Schlegel, Friedrich 75
Parmenides 16 Schmitt, Carl 84
Pascal, Blaise 123 Schnberg, Claude-Michel 13
Pelevin, Victor Olegovich 17 Schopenhauer, Arthur 12, 32,
Petersen, Wolfgang 144 75
Picasso, Pablo 28, 38 Schulz, Walter 6, 185
Pippin, Robert 78, 956 Schrmann, Reiner 8
Plato 16, 122, 1334, 169 Schuster, Caroline 183
Plotinus 16 Seidel, George 151, 162, 165
Poe, Edgar Allan 88 Shakespeare, William 114, 1356,
Portier, Sylvain 147, 150, 157 Shuang-Tse 29
Posin, Arie 28 St. Paul 82

201
INDEX

Stevens, Wallace 28 Weininger, Otto 166


Sturma, Dieter 23 Williams, Bernard 172
Wilshire, Bruce 93
van Inwagen, Peter 104 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1819, 23,
Varela, Francisco 105, 153 26, 6871, 746, 89, 912,
von Kleist, Heinrich 173 109, 1478, 170, 176, 180
von Zenge, Wilhelmine 173 Wright, Crispin 74, 86, 173

Wagner, Richard 122 iek, Slavoj 5, 24, 32, 35, 55, 82


Wallace, Robert 182 Zller, Gnter 124

202

You might also like