The Psychology of Judicial Decision Making
The Psychology of Judicial Decision Making
The Psychology of Judicial Decision Making
Series Editor
Ronald Roesch
Editorial Board
Gail S. Goodman
Thomas Grisso
Craig Haney
Kirk Heilbrun
John Monahan
Marlene Moretti
Edward P. Mulvey
J. Don Read
N. Dickon Reppucci
Gary L. Wells
Lawrence S. Wrightsman
Patricia A. Zapf
Edited by
David Klein
Gregory Mitchell
1
2010
1
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford Universitys objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
www.oup.com
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
v
vi Series Foreword
While the book is grounded in psychological theory and research, the editors
recognize that the study of the behavior of judges is complex, so both theory
and research would be enhanced through debate and discussion by contri-
butors from many professional backgrounds. To accomplish their goal, Klein
and Mitchell assembled an impressive interdisciplinary group representing
law, political science, and, of course, psychology. This group first came
together at a conference in Virginia, where the participants had an opportu-
nity to share and critique each others ideas. Klein and Mitchell had a
forward-looking perspective, as they wanted the book to provide an agenda
for future research rather than a review of prior studies of judicial decision
making. The contributors were asked to identify theories, concepts, or find-
ings from psychology that could usefully be incorporated into thinking about
how judges make decisions, and describe new research questions and the
accompanying methodology to test hypotheses generated from this process.
Having worked in an interdisciplinary faculty for a few years early in my
career, I appreciate that bringing together an interdisciplinary group does not
easily result in increased collaborations. Each discipline has its own traditions
and approaches to scholarship, and the interdisciplinary boundaries often
seem insurmountable. As the editors note in their introduction, examples of
other disciplines drawing on psychology to inform the study of judicial
decision making are rare. That the participants in the Klein and Mitchell
project were able to overcome these interdisciplinary barriers is an impressive
achievement. Klein and Mitchell wanted a book that would encourage stu-
dents of judicial behavior to incorporate psychology into their work and also
persuade psychologists and other students of decision making to pay more
attention to the decision-making process used by judges. This book serves this
purpose well.
Ronald Roesch
Series Editor
Contents
Series Foreword v
Contributors ix
Introduction xi
vii
viii Contents
ix
x Contributors
David Klein
xi
xii Introduction
The study of judicial decision making has indisputably made great strides
in recent years, through the labors of hundreds of scholars from political
science, law, economics, and other disciplines. Nevertheless, one could argue
that there remains a lack of both depth and breadth to our understanding of
what judges do. Even where scholars can make consensual and successful
predictions of a judges behaviorfor example, that Justice J will vote for the
conservative position in case Cthey will often disagree sharply about exactly
what happens in the judges mind to generate the predicted result. (Does
Justice J vote conservatively in a conscious effort to further his policy pre-
ferences, in an unconscious effort to do so despite a sincere desire to be guided
by legal texts, or as a result of a method of interpretation that is independent
of his ideology?) And as soon as we move beyond ideology, we enter areas
where good predictions are much harder to come by. How will a judges
decision on a motion, verdict, or appeal be affected by precedents, the
presence of an amicus curiae brief from the federal government, the plaintiffs
race, a particularly eloquent brief or oral argument by the defendants
attorney, the preferences and arguments of other panelists on a collegial
court, the opinions of the local bar, the presentations of expert witnesses,
other demands on the judges time? Why will it be affected that way? Some of
these questions have been the subject of excellent scholarly analysis, but none
have received definitive answers.
Naturally, various methodological difficulties unrelated to psychology
have hindered attempts to study judging, and as scholars devise creative new
ways to measure previously intractable concepts, observe hidden behaviors
and influences, and design studies so as to control for more confounding
factors, our understanding of judging will continue to improve. Still, anyone
who has ever tried to choose fairly between serious competing legal argu-
ments must have been struck by the depth, complexity, and mysteriousness of
the mental processes involved in the evaluation. It is hard to see how we can
hope to achieve a profound understanding of the far more complex and
difficult undertaking we call judicial decision making without a close analysis
of these underlying mental processes.
Thinking about the intersection of psychology and judicial decision
making can do more than help us answer questions that have long troubled
scholars; it can also point us toward equally exciting but less explored ques-
tions. To give just a few examples: What does it mean to judge well? Are some
circumstances, personalities, or cognitive styles more conducive to good
judging than others? Do most judges possess special reasoning skills that
other people lack? Do judges care what other people think about them, and,
if so, how does this affect their decision making? When different motivations
come into play at the same time, which have the most influence on judges
behavior, and why?
While students of judging may be the primary beneficiaries of an engage-
ment with psychology, the topics covered in this book should also interest
academics doing basic research in the psychology of expertise, analogical
Introduction xiii
argument for this approach. The other essays either engage this argument
directly or direct our attention to specific tasks judges are required to perform
or particular modes of reasoning in which they are expected to engage.
The essays in the third part of the book turn from what we know and can
learn about how judges make decisions to reflections on the assessment of
judicial performance. Understanding judicial behavior is not, after all, simply
an academic exercise. Judges wield substantial power, including the power to
make policy, and we naturally want our judges to exercise that power as fairly,
competently, and appropriately as possible. The ability to draw on research to
improve judging, say by predicting which of two candidates was more likely
to excel as a judge or how court practices could be changed to help sitting
judges perform better, would provide important practical benefits to society.
In the final essay of the book, Daniel Farber and Suzanna Sherry make the best
of current knowledge to offer some prescriptions. But the dominant focus of
the essays in this section, beginning with Gregory Mitchells, is on the
challenges posed by this project, on the theoretical side as we attempt to
determine precisely what it means for judges to perform well, and on the
methodological side as we seek to assess judges performance.
The practical and technical difficulties involved in studying judges are
daunting, to say the least. Psychological research most often entails conducting
experiments with the subjects of interest, but this method can take us only so far
in studying judges. Judges are far from the most accessible subjects and typically
are considerably less willing than undergraduates to participate in experiments.
Even when researchers can persuade judges to participate (e.g., Guthrie,
Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2001), the experiments must necessarily lack something
of the complexity and unpredictability of real-world judging situations; more
importantly, they lack the stakes. The challenges involved in analyzing judges
thinking occupy the attention of a number of the authors here.
Methodological challenges is just one of several themes running through
the book. Two others are particularly important. One of these is skepticism
about the theoretical approaches to judicial decision making that dominate
the political science and legal literatures. Viewed through the lens of psycho-
logical research, these approaches (fully described in Lawrence Baums
chapter in this volume) can appear both overly simplistic and unrealistically
demanding. The essays point to a number of ways in which the dominant
theories seem psychologically implausible and in which we can improve our
understanding of judging by going beyond them.
The other major theme is the importance of differences across indivi-
duals, tasks, and situations. To be sure, students of judging have not simply
ignored such differences in the past. But it seems fair to say thatperhaps
because of excessive attention to the U.S. Supreme Courtwe have often
given less attention than we should to variation in types of cases judges hear,
the environments in which they operate, and the exact nature of the reasoning
tasks they are asked to perform. Psychology teaches us that we should not
expect the mental processes judges engage in to remain invariant across very
Introduction xv
Lawrence Baum
3
4 Judges and Human Behavior
Attitudinal Models
In its original form, the attitudinal model was not linked to judges
motivations: the linkage between attitudes and votes was treated as more or
less reflexive. By the 1960s, however, both scholars who embraced the attitu-
dinal model and other students of judicial behavior were doing research that
assumed a conscious judicial goal of achieving good policy (e.g., Rohde,
1972). In stages of the decision process such as selection of cases to hear on
the merits (Schubert, 1962), judges were depicted as making calculations
based on their desire to advance the policies they favored. In other words,
they were behaving strategically. The reflexive and conscious conceptions of
the linkage between attitudes and behavior have continued to coexist unea-
sily. But in pure strategic models, considered next, the conscious conception
is dominant.
Strategic Models
Students of judicial behavior use the term strategic in multiple ways. The
most common usage relates to intent. In this usage, strategic judges seek to
achieve a desirable outcome for their actions by taking into account the
responses of other people to those actions. In the original form of the
attitudinal model, judges are not strategic when they cast votes on case
outcomes. Instead, they take the position that best reflects their policy pre-
ferences regardless of how others might react to what they do. In strategic
models, in contrast, judges might deviate from their most preferred positions
if doing so would achieve a better result. To take the most prosaic example, an
appellate judge might take a less liberal doctrinal position in a case than she
would prefer in order to secure a majority for a relatively liberal position. As
this description indicates, strategic models shift the focus from votes on
dichotomous case outcomes as the dependent variable to doctrinal positions
on an ideological spectrum.
Interest in judicial strategy goes back a long time, and in 1964 Walter
Murphy published an influential book in which he explored an array of
strategies that policy-oriented Supreme Court justices might employ. But in
the 1990s scholars began giving more attention to strategic behavior, pri-
marily because of the influence of rational choice models imported from
economics. Pulling together these developments, Lee Epstein and Jack Knight
(1998) wrote a book advocating a strategic model of Supreme Court decision
making. In depictions by them and by other scholars, strategic considerations
might lead the justices to take into account the prospective reactions of their
colleagues as well as a variety of groups outside the Court, including the other
branches of government and the general public.
Within political science, strategic models are now quite popular. Scholars
routinely consider the possibility of strategic behavior, and much of the
research on judicial behavior posits or assumes that judges are strategic.
One example is the book on Supreme Court decision making by Forrest
Maltzman, James Spriggs, and Paul Wahlbeck (2000), which uses
Motivation and Judicial Behavior 7
within a limited range, and competing camps share basic assumptions that are
largely unnoticed. That is certainly true of the several models of judicial
behavior.
It is useful on occasion to step back to identify and consider the assump-
tions that serve as foundations for work in a field. From a psychological
perspective, several key assumptions seem problematical in certain respects.
First, each of the models of judicial behavior implicitly centers on motivation,
in that judges actions are treated as driven solely by their goals: legal and
policy preferences turn directly into choices in cases. Scholars who utilize
these models seldom mention cognition explicitly (but see Segal, 1986), but
the implicit assumption is that the cognitive processes involved in judicial
decision making are straightforward and unproblematic.
This assumption is questionable on its face. The processing of informa-
tion, analysis of alternatives, and selection among those alternatives that
culminate in judges choices are hardly straightforward. Even if we conceive
of judicial decision making primarily in motivational terms, cognitive pro-
cesses surely intervene between goals and choices. In reality, motivation and
cognition are closely intertwined (Kruglanski, 1996).
The value of incorporating cognition into the study of judicial behavior is
underlined by the limited body of scholarship that has done so (Rowland &
Carp, 1996; D. Simon, 1998, 2004; Guthrie, Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2001;
Braman, 2004; Braman & Nelson, 2007) and by several chapters in this book.
One important issue, especially relevant to this essays concern with motiva-
tion, is the issue of cognitive capacity. There is reason to question the implicit
assumption that judges can easily identify the course of action that will best
advance their goals.
The pure attitudinal model probably makes the most minimal cognitive
demands on judges, but even the task of applying policy preferences to the
alternatives in a case can be difficult. In the spatial metaphor that adherents to
the attitudinal model have always used, judges must locate both their pre-
ferences and the alternatives in a case along an ideological dimension. The
other models, in their simple and complex forms, require more from judges.
This is especially true of strategic models in which judges consider the
prospective responses of other policy makers to their courts decisions.
Psychologists and behavioral economists have amply demonstrated peoples
cognitive limitations (Kahneman & Tversky, 2000; see Mitchell, 2002). Judges
certainly are not immune to those limitations (Guthrie, Rachlinski, &
Wistrich, 2001).
Students of decision making in some other arenas have grappled with the
impact of human cognitive limitations. Behavioral economists, for instance,
have raised fundamental questions about the cognitive assumptions that
underlie orthodox models of economic behavior and probed the ways that
economic actors might depart from the predictions of the orthodox models as
a result (Thaler, 1991). Similar inquiries into the cognitive element in judicial
behavior are both necessary and potentially quite fruitful.
Motivation and Judicial Behavior 9
Indeed, the anecdotal evidence that some judges make less than a full
commitment to their judicial work, a common subject of newspaper stories, is
compelling. A few legal scholars, including some who take an economic
perspective on the courts, posit that judges have a preference for leisure
(e.g., Posner, 1995, pp. 123126; Bainbridge & Gulati, 2002). These scholars
surely are right. In thinking about judges choices, we need to recognize their
interest in limiting the time and labor they devote to their jobs.
Finally, scholarship on judicial behavior generally treats that behavior as
homogeneous in important respects. This scholarship does allow for situa-
tional variation in the determinants of judges choices, primarily across courts
whose institutional characteristics vary in important respects. Scholars fre-
quently note another source of situational variation, the relative salience of
cases, and they have provided persuasive evidence of its impact (e.g.,
Maltzman, Spriggs, & Wahlbeck, 2000; Bartels, 2005, 2006; Unah &
Hancock, 2006; and McAtee & McGuire, 2007). But salience has not been
directly incorporated into the models that dominate the field, models that
typically treat every case as equal.
More striking is the implicit but deeply rooted assumption that, at least
within a particular court level, all judges act in the same ways. In attitudinal and
strategic models, every Supreme Court justice acts solely on personal policy
preferences. Justices also act on their preferences in uniform ways, responding
to cases in terms of the same ideological dimensions and (in strategic models)
adopting the same strategies. In these models the justices differ in their behavior
because their preferences differ, but in other respects they are alike.
There are good theoretical and empirical reasons to question the
emphasis on homogeneity in the dominant models. First of all, the potential
impact of situational variation on judging is greater than these models allow.
Though students of judicial behavior are sensitive to the effects of courts
institutional characteristics, those effects are likely more fundamental than
the scholarship recognizes. This is especially true of the differences between
trial and appellate courts (Rowland & Carp, 1996, chs. 67). And for judges
on a particular court, case salience is only one of the situational variables that
could affect decision making. In particular, judges might well act on different
bases in carrying out different taskscase selection and opinion writing, for
example.
Interpersonal differences are a more complicated matter. Research in
social psychology makes it clear that the situations in which people find
themselves play a powerful role in structuring their behavior. One effect is
to reduce interpersonal differences in the behavior of people who share the
same situations: inherent characteristics of individuals are less important
than most people think (Ross & Nisbett, 1991). Still, there remains consider-
able room for differences in behavior within a particular setting. The role of
appellate judge and the structure in which appellate judges do their work
constrain variation across individuals, but they hardly eliminate the potential
for variation.
Motivation and Judicial Behavior 11
The assumption that judges seek primarily (or solely) to make good policy,
widely accepted in political science, has primarily an inductive basis.
Unsystematic observation of judges choices and systematic analysis of
those choices suggest to scholars that judges are acting on their policy
preferences. To take one example, the evidence of an ideological dimension
in the votes of Supreme Court justices on case outcomes lends itself to the
conclusion that the justices choices are strongly policy-oriented.
The assumption that the goal of making good law is important to judges,
accepted by most legal scholars and many political scientists, is more deeply
rooted in theory. But the theory on which scholars rely is primarily norma-
tive: trying to interpret the law accurately and well is a role prescription for
judges. Here too, little is done to connect the goals that scholars posit and the
motivations that must underlie these goals.
Some political scientists have developed a rationale for judges concen-
tration on legal policy, one that sidesteps the question of motivation. This
rationale rests on the exclusion of other goals. Focusing on the Supreme
Court, these scholars argue that institutional characteristics of the Court
render other goals irrelevant (Epstein & Knight, 1998, pp. 3649; Segal &
Spaeth, 2002, pp. 9296). One key attribute is the Courts ability to select the
cases it will hear, so that it typically hears difficult cases in which decisions
on both sides can readily be justified in legal terms.6
This rationale, though quite reasonable as far as it goes, is not entirely
satisfying. Most important, the scholars who offer it consider only a limited
range of goals that might compete with good legal policy, almost exclusively
career considerations. They point out that career goals are irrelevant to at
least the great majority of Supreme Court justices in the current era, since
other positions are seldom attractive enough to entice justices away from
the Court. But they do not consider other quite plausible goals, including
those relating to life at work (such as the quality of the working environ-
ment) and to the justices standing with colleagues and people outside the
Court.
Even if all potentially competing goals could be dismissed as irrelevant, it
would be useful to determine what basic motives of judges are satisfied
through efforts to make good legal policy. Because other goals cannot easily
be dismissed, that inquiry is even more important.
Judicial interest in good legal policy can be given firmer theoretical roots
by subsuming it within general inventories of motivation. Of the various
inventories that psychologists have offered (e.g., Beck, 2000, ch. 12; Fiske,
2003; Reeve, 2005, ch. 5), David Winters (2002, 2003a) typology is especially
relevant because it was developed to analyze political leaders.7 In Winters
conception, leaders act on their needs for achievement, power, and affiliation.
The power motive encompasses prestige, and it may be appropriate to treat
the need for prestige as a separate category.
Motivation and Judicial Behavior 13
some time and energy to other pursuits, the gap between the ideal and actual
levels of scrutiny is wider.
One way that judges might deal with this gap is to rely on the efforts of
others. In particular, they can defer to colleagues and delegate to law clerks
and staff attorneys. The costs to their goals of yielding some control over their
choices can be minimized if they rely on people whose judgment they trust.
Thus policy-oriented judges may consult like-minded colleagues, and they
may choose clerks who seem to mirror their own views (Ward & Weiden,
2006, pp. 99107).
Judges may also rely on heuristics in making choices. One example
concerns the selection of cases to hear in courts that have discretionary
jurisdiction. Some of these courts, such as the California and U.S. Supreme
Courts, face thousands of petitions for hearings each year. It is likely that
members of these courts (and the law clerks who assist them in screening
petitions) base their choices of cases to hear on a limited number of case
characteristics. Indeed, that was the conclusion of one study based on inter-
views with Supreme Court justices and law clerks (Perry, 1991, ch. 5).
The same is true of decisions on the merits. Whatever they seek to
accomplish with their decisions, judges must simplify the process by which
they reach those decisions. For example, some scholars have posited that
Supreme Court justices choose their positions in cases with the goal of
avoiding congressional overrides of their decisions through new statutes
(e.g., Eskridge, 1991; Bergara, Richman, & Spiller, 2003). The models that
scholars have used to test this hypothesis incorporate complicated calcula-
tions by the justices about the ideological placement of potential decisions
and of subsets of Congress (Segal, 1997; Bergara, Richman, & Spiller, 2003;
Sala & Spriggs, 2004). But even these models leave aside relevant considera-
tions such as the positions and activities of interest groups. If some justices do
try to avoid overrides, undoubtedly they make their task less time-consuming
by identifying a few variables that seem especially helpful in predicting
congressional action and ignoring others. This example underlines the need
to take into account both unavoidable and voluntary limits on judges efforts
to achieve their goals.
satisfaction from taking a position that perfectly reflects those beliefs. This
satisfaction helps in understanding Justice Antonin Scalias (1994, p. 42)
lyrical description of writing an opinion to express precisely his own
position as an unparalleled pleasure.
Among the dominant models of judicial behavior, only strategic models
incorporate the impression management motivation, and they do so only in a
limited way. Strategic judges seek to affect the impressions of other people
only for instrumental reasonsto win support for their positions from
colleagues, to avoid negative reactions to their courts decisions from other
policy makers and the public, to win reelection or reappointment so they can
continue to make legal policy. Yet judges are not social isolates, so their
interest in impression management cannot be instrumental alone.
Inevitably, they also seek the regard of other people for its own sake. Thus
self-presentation is at least as important to judges as it is to ordinary people
(Goffman, 1959; Schlenker & Pontari, 2000). And judges are especially well
situated to present themselves to relevant audiences.9
Impression motivation can help to explain the goals posited by the
standard models of judicial behavior, in that judges interest in the approval
of salient audiences might reinforce their interest in good law or good policy.
But social motives can lead people to make choices that diverge from both
their conceptions of accuracy and their own directional preferences.10 For this
reason, separating impression motivation from other goals expands inquiry
into the motives that drive judicial behavior.
In combination, defense motivation and impression motivation call
attention to the role of individual and social identities in judging. Judges
act in part to produce desired self-concepts and favorable images of them-
selves among audiences that are important to them. It is doubtful that judges
choices can be fully understood in terms of identity. But that concept
provides a useful counterpoint to the usual ways of conceptualizing judicial
behavior, which leave the human element out of judicial choice.
As a dual-process theory, the heuristic-systematic model takes the ener-
gizing dimension of motivation into account. Under the sufficiency prin-
ciple (Chaiken, Giner-Sorolla, & Chen, 1996, p. 554), whether people engage
in heuristic or systematic processing depends on what level of effort is
sufficient to serve their needs. But very busy public officials must define
sufficiency in relation to the time and effort that are available for decision
making. One result is that judges sometimes engage in heuristic reasoning
even though they would prefer the level of confidence in their choices that
systematic reasoning would provide.
Undoubtedly, the dichotomy between two modes of reasoning over-
simplifies variation in the effort that judges give to their decisions. Yet it is
interesting that courts sometimes divide cases into two categories. Many
intermediate courts explicitly differentiate between two classes of cases. A
central staff of law clerks selects what appear to be easy cases, in the sense that
one side clearly is right under the law, and makes tentative decisions in those
Motivation and Judicial Behavior 19
cases before forwarding them to panels of judges who typically accept the staff
recommendation (Chapper & Hanson, 1990, pp. 1522; Symposium, 2002).
In the U.S. and California Supreme Courts, court personnel assign petitions
for hearings to two categories, and petitions in the two categories receive quite
different levels of scrutiny from the justices (Caldeira & Wright, 1990;
California Supreme Court, n.d.).11
In those examples, judges give more attention to classes of cases that they
care more about, and the discussion of salience suggested the same result. But
the impact of salience might be mediated by another factor. In decisions on
the merits, as suggested by Lawrence Wrightsmans essay in this book, judges
may engage in less systematic evaluation of cases that they can readily locate in
ideological space, because ideology serves as the critical heuristic. In other
words, issues that have clear ideological referents for judges tend to be easier
than those that lack those referents (see Pollock, Lilie, & Vittes, 1993, p. 30).12
On average, such ideological cases are probably more salient to judges than
other cases.
The distinction between two modes of reasoning is one way that the
heuristic-systematic model incorporates variation in motivation. As sug-
gested earlier, the care with which judicial decisions are made can vary
among judges as well as cases. Similarly, the absolute and relative importance
of the three motives in the heuristic-systematic model surely differs among
individuals and across situations.
The most widely shared assumption is that judges as decision makers act
primarily or entirely on the goal of making good legal policy. That assump-
tion is nearly universal in the study of the Supreme Court. The dominant
models of judicial behavior incorporate that assumption but provide only
limited justification for it. Can a justification be developed in psychological
terms?
The dominant models do not connect the posited goals of judges to their
basic motivations, to show the reasons that judges might be drawn to make
good law or good policy as they define it. This limitation is relatively easy to
overcome, and some scholarsprimarily among those who work outside
20 Judges and Human Behavior
number of cases that the Supreme Court accepts for decisions on the merits
(OBrien, 2005).
Most courts have considerably less control over their workloads than the
Supreme Court, and the inherent limits on the use of systematic processing
impinge heavily on judges in these courts. In some courts, the press of cases is
so great that simply disposing of them becomes a major concernsometimes
the central concern. Put differently, judges most immediate goal may be to
reach any conclusion rather than a specific conclusion (Kruglanski &
Webster, 1996; Dhami, 2003). In intermediate appellate courts at least some
judges appear to move consciously between systematic and heuristic proces-
sing modes, giving careful attention to law and policy in a minority of cases
and more limited scrutiny to cases that they characterize as easy (Wold, 1978;
Linder, 1985, pp. 498499).
Thus the widely shared assumption that judges act only on the goal of
achieving good legal policy applies to some courts and cases better than
others. In no context does it fully fit the reality of judicial behavior, but in
somedecisions on the merits in the Supreme Court, for instancethe fit
may be good enough to make the assumption acceptable. In any context,
however, scholars need to take into account the motivational bases for judges
interest in the content of legal policy. By doing so, they can better identify the
ways that this interest affects judges choices and the conditions that affect the
linkage between the two.
Among the scholars who think that judges devote themselves to making good
legal policy, one continuing matter of disagreement is whether judges define
that goal solely in terms of policy or whether good law is also important to
them. Students of judicial behavior who espouse policy-only models treat
their position as more realistic than its alternative. As noted earlier, this
judgment is empirically based for the most part. In part, however, it is
based on an unspoken assumption that judges have stronger motivations to
pursue good policy.
The validity of scholars conclusions from the empirical evidence can be
contested (Baum, 1997, ch. 3), but the assumption about judges motivations
is my concern here. There is no inherent reason that judges should elevate
policy over law. They can get satisfaction from advancing what they see as
desirable public policy, but they can also do so by interpreting the law
effectively. Similarly, they may be rewarded by their audiences in concrete
or symbolic ways by taking either path.13 In the terminology of the motivated
reasoning framework, directional goals do not necessarily take primacy over
accuracy goals.
Situational variation may be more important than any general rule. If the
relative weights of accuracy and directional goals depend on the ease of
identifying the more accurate result, then the extent of legal ambiguity in
22 Judges and Human Behavior
Strategy
Conclusion
As the discussion of strategy illustrates, psychological theory provides new
perspectives on judges motivations and thus informs thinking and research
on issues of motivation. This chapters survey of relevant theory has been quite
24 Judges and Human Behavior
Notes
I appreciate the comments and suggestions by Kathleen McGraw and Tom Nelson.
1. Research in psychology concentrates on ordinary people who are engaged in
ordinary behavior, and the insights of that research do not always apply well to
judges and judicial decision making. Scholarship on political psychology gives
primary attention to the mass public rather than government decision makers,
and the portion of this scholarship that deals with government decision makers
is concerned primarily with officials in the executive branch and with foreign
policy decisions (see Sears, Huddy, & Jevis, 2003).
2. The discussion that follows draws from ideas in Baum (2006, ch. 1).
3. This does not mean that there is always a single correct decision in a case,
because judges legitimately might adopt different rules of legal interpretation or
apply them differently.
4. As noted earlier, studies of state judges who lack life tenure are an exception
(Langer, 2002), though even for those judges continued tenure is typically treated
as a means to the end of making legal policy. Students of Congress tend to give re-
election greater weight as an end in itself (Fenno, 1973; Mayhew, 1974).
5. The use of psychological theory in research on judicial behavior is discussed in
Baum (1997, pp. 135141). In the decade since that time, psychologists, legal
scholars, and political scientists have made additional use of theories in psy-
chology to understand judicial behavior (e.g., [To distinguish from J.F. Simon,
1980) D. Simon, 1998; Gruenfeld & Preston, 2000; Guthrie, Rachlinski, &
Motivation and Judicial Behavior 25
Judges make decisions for a living, and their decisions are unusually conse-
quential, with direct effects on immediate cases, and a ripple of less direct effects
on future cases. Trial court judges must variously act as finders of fact in bench
trials, jury trial supervisors, and overall case managers. Appellate court judges
may, for example, make decisions about the merits of particular cases, deter-
mine whether to join an opinion and whether to write separately (see e.g., Taha,
2004), or participate in decisions about whether to grant cert or en banc review
(George, 1999). Chief judges face an additional set of administrative responsi-
bilities, such as managing the docket and the budget, assigning opinion writing,
coordinating visiting judges and judges on senior status, hiring and firing staff,
and handling issues related to building maintenance and equipment (George &
Yoon, 2007). The Chief Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court has additional
responsibilities, such as appointing judges to the committees of the judicial
conference (Chutkow, 2007). Judges may even need to decide when it is the best
time to retire (see e.g., George & Yoon, 2007).
27
28 Judges and Human Behavior
Each of the varied decisions that judges are called on to make inevitably
evokes a range of possible goals. Different models of judicial decision making
tend to highlight particular goals. For example, traditional legal theory posits
that in making decisions judges strive to reach the correct legal decision as
dictated by precedent. There are various legal realist and critical realist
alternatives to this baseline account; of particular relevance here are the
attitudinal, strategic, and managerial models. The attitudinal model focuses
on the ways in which judges make decisions that further their preferred policy
objectives (Segal & Spaeth, 1993, 2002). Strategic models incorporate con-
sideration of the ways in which judges seek to effectuate their goals in the long
term (Epstein & Knight, 1998; Maltzman, Spriggs, & Wahlbeck, 2000). The
managerial model emphasizes the increasing caseload pressures that judges at
all levels face (Resnik, 1982). Thus, as they make decisions, judges must
balance their desire to reach the right legal result, their preferences for
particular outcomes, their need to manage their workload, and many other
objectives.
To view these models as competitive accountsone more valid than the
othersis probably misguided. We argue that each model accurately cap-
tures some of what every judge does some of the time, and that no single
model is likely to describe any judge all of the time. A sophisticated under-
standing of judicial decision making should explicitly incorporate the notion
that judges simultaneously attempt to further numerous, disparate, and often
conflicting, objectives. In this chapter we attempt a preliminary account of a
more psychologically plausible account of judicial cognition and motivation.
amount of time they spend on aspects of their job they find less interesting in
favor of decision tasks (or cases) they prefer, or attempt to achieve control (or
a sense of control) over the nature and pace of their work.
One side effect of a focus on efficiency, coupled with the ability that
courts now have to collect more data on court operations, is increasing
opportunity for judges to attend to their statisticsfor example, the
number of cases they terminate, the number of motions they have ruled on,
or the number of days they have spent in trial (Resnik, 1982; see also Darley,
2001). Thus, judges may have goals that relate to improving their perfor-
mance on these types of measures.
Intertwined with the goals that are most central to legal, attitudinal,
strategic, and managerial models of judicial decision making, judges may
also be influenced by a range of additional objectives. For example, judges
may seek to make decisions that will not be overturned by a higher court or on
en banc review; they may seek to maximize their opportunities to exercise
discretion; they may seek to cultivate their reputation with their peers or
another constituency (e.g., the bar, academics, Congress, the press, particular
interest groups, or the public), aspiring to be respected, influential, and
frequently cited; they may seek to be reelected, to be promoted to a higher
court, or to move to another position beyond the court; they may seek to
build collegial relationships with their colleagues on the bench; they may seek
to make decisions that are consistent with their self-identity; and they may
seek to achieve a measure of consistency with their own past decisions (see
generally Baum, 1997, 2006; Cohen, 1991; Posner, 1993; Wrightsman, 2006).
While many of these disparate goals may be entertained consciously, others
may be adopted or pursued without conscious awareness (see, e.g., Bargh &
Chartrand, 1999; Shah, 2005; see also Guthrie, Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2007).
Furthermore, variations in the decision contextfor example, whether and
how the judge will be accountable for the decisioncan serve to make
particular goals temporarily operable or salient (see, e.g., Lerner & Tetlock,
1999).
While judges as a group may share this range of objectives to one degree
or another, judges sitting on different courts or across jurisdictions face
different sets of tasks and demands. Similarly, different decision tasks may
evoke different judicial goals. For example, trial and appellate court judges are
called on to make different kinds of decisions and face differing constraints on
their decision making. U.S. Supreme Court justices enjoy a greater degree of
control over their agenda and more discretion than do judges on other courts
and may seek to effect a somewhat different set of objectives. For trial court
judges, ruling on a pretrial motion may be subject to different constraints
than reaching a verdict in a bench trial. Judges who sit in jurisdictions in
which judges are elected may face different pressures than do judges who are
appointed. This divergence in decision tasks and in the range of demands
faced by judges sitting on different types of courts or across jurisdictions may
lead to different (though overlapping) sets of salient goals.
Multiple Constraint Satisfaction in Judging 31
Trial court judges wear many different hats, variously serving as finders of
fact, trial supervisors, and overall case managers. These judges decide some
cases on the merits, but they also manage the trial processruling on objec-
tions and motions and instructing juries about the law. Trial court judges may
hold Daubert hearings to determine the admissibility of scientific evidence,
make determinations about the appropriate amount of bail, and conduct
posttrial assessments of damage awards. In addition, trial court judges now
spend much of their time managing the pretrial and case settlement processes
as well as overseeing the implementation of remedies posttrial (Resnik, 1982).
As fact-finders, judges may struggle to simultaneously accomplish
myriad goalsmaking accurate factual determinations and reaching a verdict
consistent with the evidence (see Pennington & Hastie, 1993); accomplishing
optimal deterrence (see Becker, 1969; Cooter & Ulen, 2007); awarding appro-
priate compensation (Darley & Pittman, 2003;); accomplishing some mea-
sure of distributive justice (see Deutsch, 1975); punishing when appropriate
and to the extent that is fitting (see Darley et al., 2000); using the appropriate
rules to guide decision making (see Robbennolt, Darley, & MacCoun, 2003);
or expressing their values (see e.g., Sunstein, 1996; Robbennolt, Darley, &
MacCoun, 2003). Indeed, as with jurors, judges have been shown to have
difficulties with some of the decisions required by legal and economic models
of decision making. Specifically, judges have been shown to have trouble
ignoring inadmissible evidence (see e.g., Landsman & Rakos, 1994; Wistrich
et al., 2005) and evaluating scientific, expert, or statistical evidence (Gatowski
et al., 2001; Kovera & McAuliff, 2000; Redding & Repucci, 1999; Wells, 1992).
In addition, judges have been found to be susceptible to a variety of cognitive
heuristics such as anchoring, framing, hindsight bias, the representativeness
heuristic, and the egocentric bias (Guthrie et al., 2001; Rachlinski et al., 2006).
Trial court judges, however, spend much of their time engaged in tasks
other than presiding over trials. Indeed, judges are presiding over fewer and
fewer trials (Galanter, 2004). In their role as case managers, trial court judges
have different tasks and goals than they do in their role as fact-findersthey
must negotiate with parties pretrial to settle cases, plan litigation, and manage
discovery, and supervise the implementation of remedies posttrial (Resnik,
1982). In addition, trial court judges may be called on to manage complex
class-action or multidistrict litigation (see, e.g., Galanter, 2004; Walker &
Manahan, 2007).
As noted above, these case management responsibilities give rise to
incentives to get cases resolved and off the docket. Judges may even utilize
the symbolism of procedural justice to get cases settled. MacCoun (2005)
relates an anecdote in which a judge conducted a settlement conference in
which the attorneys negotiated a settlement in the clients absence. When the
plaintiffs attorney complained that his client might not accept the settlement
without getting her day in court, the judge put on his robe, called her into
32 Judges and Human Behavior
an empty courtroom, and sat her on the witness chair. After she told her story,
she assented to the settlement.
These case management pressures provide an additional set of goals with
which trial court judges, in particular, must contend.
Appellate Judges
Appellate judges face an overlapping, but somewhat different set of decision
tasks than do trial court judges. Rather than acting as fact-finders, appellate
court judges are primarily engaged in the business of judicial review.
Accordingly, they face decisionssuch as whether to grant cert to hear a
case or whether to grant en banc reviewthat trial court judges do not.
Similarly, appellate court judges must make decisions about whether to ask
questions at oral argument and what the nature of those questions will be.
Appellate court judges engage in more opinion writing and, in addition to
determining how they will vote in a particular case, must decide whether to
join a particular opinion, to write separately, or to author a dissenting
opinion. Appellate judges at different levels may face differently structured
decision tasks. For example, justices of the Supreme Court exercise more
control over their agenda than do intermediate appellate judges.
Elected Judges
Judges who face reelection or some form of retention election face additional
pressures attendant to such elections. There is evidence that judicial decision
making is influenced by such political concerns. For example, there is evi-
dence that in years in which they are up for reelection, judges are more likely
to sentence criminal defendants to death (see Brace & Hall, 1997; Brooks &
Raphael, 2003; see generally Bright & Keenan, 1995) or to sentence more
harshly in general (Huber & Gordon, 2004). Other hot button issues such as
tort reform also play a role in the politics of judicial elections and have the
potential to influence judicial decision making (see generally Champagne,
2005; Ware, 1999).
making that portray judges as pursuing single objectives and that do not
account for these intricacies are likely to miss important facets of the process.
We therefore propose a model, the parallel constraint satisfaction model, that
is explicitly designed to incorporate multiple objectives.
In an attempt to encourage the development of models of legal decision
making that capture these types of complexities, we have argued that legal
decision making might profitably be conceived of as a process of parallel con-
straint satisfaction that can be represented using connectionist models
(Robbennolt, Darley, & MacCoun, 2003; also see Simon, 2004). Connectionist
models endeavor to provide a framework for thinking about and modeling
decision-making tasks that require the integration of a range of disparate, and
potentially inconsistent, information and objectives (see Read & Miller, 1998;
Read et al., 1997). Accordingly, such models are well suited to modeling decision-
making by judges who must balance numerous, potentially inconsistent, goals.
Constraint satisfaction networks are made up of a set of nodes or
elements connected by links in a neural-like network. Each element comprises
a concept, item of evidence, legal proposition, or goal, and the links or
connections between elements vary in strength and valence (indicating the
degree of coherence or incoherence between elements) (Read et al., 1997).
The links that connect the elements represent the constraints faced by deci-
sion makerselements that are consistent, or mutually compatible, are said
to be coherent and are connected with positively valenced links, while ele-
ments that are negatively related or that inhibit each other are said to be
incoherent and are negatively linked (Read et al., 1997; Thagard, 2000). Such
models are sophisticated enough to take account of differential initial prio-
rities among goalsthis would be done by initially linking favored goals to
elements set to higher levels of activation and less favored goals to elements
with lower levels of activation (see Thagard, 2000).
Under this framework, decisions are made by finding the action that best
balances the constraints among the decision elements (Read & Marcus-
Newhall, 1993; Thagard, 2000). In a parallel constraint satisfaction model,
this balance is struck through a process of iterative updating of the model:
In a parallel constraint satisfaction connectionist model, each element
is assigned an equal initial activation value (e.g., .01). The central
aspect of the model is that the activation level of each element in the
model is then updated simultaneously based on four factors: (1) the
number of other elements connected to it; (2) the level of activation of
those elements; (3) the strength of the links to these other elements;
and (4) the valence of those links. This updating process is iterated
with activation of elements spreading through the network based on
the configuration of links between the elements until the activation of
each element stabilizes. Once the network settles, each element is
accepted or rejected based on its final degree of activation
(Robbennolt, Darley, & MacCoun, 2003, pp. 11491150).
34 Judges and Human Behavior
management principles that can describe the interrelations among the dis-
parate goals and actions pursued by legal decision makers:
Principle of equifinality: some goals may be alternately satisfied
through any one of a number of actions (see Kruglanski et al.,
2002; Anderson & MacCoun, 1999);
Principle of best fit: a particular action may better fulfill some goals
than others;
Principle of multifinality: a particular action may sometimes
accomplish multiple goals simultaneously (see Kruglanski et al.,
2002);
Principle of goal incompatibility: some goals will inevitably conflict
and, thus, be difficult or impossible to satisfy concurrently.
Connectionist models of parallel constraint satisfaction accommodate
these principles in various ways:
a goal might be connected by positive links to more than one action
(equifinality) and each possible action may be connected by positive
links to more than one goal (multifinality). At the same time, the
links between a goal and several different actions may have different
weights (best fit) and some of the links between two goals or two
actions may be negatively valenced (incompatibility). The
connectionist network updates activation of the elements (goals and
actions) in parallel until the network stabilizes. In this case, the final
activation of the elements represents the decision makers chosen set
of selected actions or goal valuations. (Robbennolt, Darley, &
MacCoun, 2003, pp. 11541155)
Thus, examining deliberative coherence through parallel constraint satis-
faction provides a way to formally model how decision makers such as judges
mediate among the influence of multiple, salient, and often conflicting goals
and do so in a way that results in reasonable behavior that is sensitive both to
the desires of the individual and the opportunities and constraints of the
environment (Read et al., 1997, p. 47).6 Judges may, for example, be able to
reach a particular desired outcome through two different analytic approaches
(equifinality), but one approach may be contrary to precedent (incompat-
ibility). A trial court judge may have at her disposal a number of case manage-
ment approaches (equifinality): one may be the most effective at speeding the
docket (best fit) but at the expense of party satisfaction (incompatibility),
while another approach may simultaneously move the docket and achieve a
good substantive result (multifinality). An appellate judge may weigh a desire
to write a detailed dissenting opinion against strategic objectives or against an
overwhelming workload (incompatibility).
Consider the following extended example as one illustration of how
parallel constraint satisfaction can be used to model the complexity of judicial
decision making.7 Imagine a judge who is considering a motion to suppress
36 Judges and Human Behavior
key evidence in a criminal trial that raises a somewhat novel, but not unpre-
cedented issue related to the exclusionary rule. The judge is faced with the
related tasks of determining the content of her ruling and deciding whether to
rule from the bench or to issue a written ruling. The judge, having reviewed
the evidence, is aware of its strong probative value and (again, having seen the
evidence) is of the opinion that the defendant quite likely committed the
crime with which he is charged and ought to be punished accordingly. Given
the nature of the other evidence in the case, the judge understands that it is
unlikely that the prosecution will be able to proceed without the evidence.
The judge is also aware of the public sentiment surrounding the case and
predicts a strong negative public reaction if the case were to be dismissed. At
the same time, the judge is strongly committed to the principles underlying
the exclusionary rule and believes, as an empirical matter, that following the
rule and excluding evidence in appropriate cases has had and continues to
have positive effects on police procedure. The judge is strongly committed to
following legal precedent. The relevant legal precedent in the judges jurisdic-
tion clearly requires that she find the evidence inadmissible. On the other
hand, the prosecutor is urging her to follow an exception that another
jurisdiction has recently carved out that would support the admission of
the evidence. While the judge believes that following the approach suggested
by this exception is analytically stronger than the approach currently followed
in her jurisdiction and may apply to the facts of this case, she does not think
that such an approach will be accepted in her jurisdiction and predicts that
any ruling admitting the evidence stands a relatively high chance of being
overturned on appeal. The judge enjoys writing opinions and would welcome
the challenge of crafting an elegant analysis of an important legal issue; she
views the appellate court as a more attractive audience for these scholarly
efforts than she does the general public. She feels some need to explain her
reasoning (particularly to the appellate court if she admits the evidence and to
the public if she chooses not to admit it). However, as a busy trial judge, she
does not have the luxury of spending a week or a month crafting a nuanced
scholarly exposition of the issue.
Figure 2.1 diagrams these goals and constraints in a connectionist parallel
constraint satisfaction network. Solid lines represent compatible links; dashed
lines represent incompatible relationships. In the model, ruling the evidence
inadmissible would be consistent with the judges understanding of the
relevant precedent and with the general purposes of the exclusionary rule,
would minimize the chance of a reversal, and would move the docket (as the
charges would most likely be dropped). Conversely, such a ruling would be
inconsistent with the judges own best legal analysis, would be inconsistent
with the judges view of just deserts by resulting in the release of a probably
guilty defendant, and would inflame public sentiment. While ruling the
evidence admissible would be consistent with the judges notions of analytical
rigor, would allow the prosecution of the defendant, and would comport with
public sentiment and, therefore, build public confidence in the judicial
Multiple Constraint Satisfaction in Judging 37
system, the judge believes that it is contrary to the relevant precedent, opening
the judge up to the possibility of reversal, and would be inconsistent with the
aims of the exclusionary rule. Drafting an opinion on the ruling would further
the judges goals in being analytically rigorous and in spending time engaged
in the intellectual enterprise of thorough legal analysis, and might catch the
attention of the judges judicial colleagues. However, the judge is simulta-
neously aware of the ever-present pressure to move the docket and spending
time drafting such an opinion will not further this goal.
The judges decisions, then, involve the elaborate interplay of these
myriad goals, and subjectively, such decisions can feel rather mysterious.8
One struggles and struggles with a decision, and then all of a sudden an
internal threshold is crossed and the judgment is made. Though much of the
deliberation is in the form of conscious internal dialogue, the cognitive
process by which the various constraints are reconciled is largely unconscious,
because serial consciousness cannot represent the kind of parallel processing
required to reconcile all the conflicting positive and negative activations
among elements. We experience the struggle, then we feel something settle,
and we then begin a secondary process of trying to rationalize in words what
we have decided.
Considering judges as decision makers who must reconcile numerous
objectives in carrying out a variety of different decision tasks provides an
avenue toward a more nuanced view of the cognitive complexity of judicial
decision making and may lead to increasingly sophisticated hypotheses about
judicial behavior. Identifying the distinctive constraints faced by judges with
38 Judges and Human Behavior
regard to particular decision tasks and settings can give rise to testable
predictions involving those constraints. For example, concern about being
overturned will be salient in some contexts and for some decisions, but not
others, and differences in the constraints faced may lead to predictable
differences in decision making across such contexts (e.g., differences in the
citation of precedent or in the scope of the decision). Alternately, one might
predict that alternate goals will have more influence on decision making when
legal precedent is unclear (i.e., less constraining). Or consideration of work-
load constraints might lead one to predict more intuitive processing by judges
facing greater workload pressures and more deliberation by those who are
relatively unconstrained by such pressures (see Guthrie, Rachlinski, &
Wistrich, 2007a). By guiding the generation of such predictions, conceiving
of judges as decision makers who attempt to simultaneously satisfy myriad
goals by engaging in a process of parallel constraint satisfaction offers a model
for incorporating the range of considerations that influence judicial decision
making and for understanding the interplay among them.
Notes
The authors would like to thank Matt Taksin for his helpful research assistance and
Margareth Etienne and Kevin Quinn for their helpful comments on parts of this
chapter.
1. The notion of ideal points has its origins in so-called spatial models of voting in
the political science literature on legislatures (see Downs, 1957; Enelow & Hinch,
1990; McCarty, Poole, & Rosenthal, 2006.
2. Martin and Quinn (2002) attempt to identify the dimensionality of Supreme
Court votes (to affirm or reverse) using a database of 3,450 cases from the 29
justices sitting on the Court during the 1953 through 1999 terms. They develop
an innovative Bayesian Monte Carlo algorithm to infer ideal points for each
justice. The details of the algorithm and its derivation are beyond the scope of
this chapter, but our concern is less with the method than with the available
data. In psychometric practice, the usual rule of thumb for fitting a latent
dimensional model is that one needs a minimum of 5 to 10 respondents per
measured item. The Martin-Quinn analysis reverses this inequality; with
between 41 (in 2003) and 108 (in 1972) decisions per term and only nine
seated Justices per term, there are far more items (41 to 108) than respondents
(9 for any given item).
It is difficult to correctly characterize an underlying multidimensional struc-
ture when the data are sparse (Fabrigar et al., 1999). For example, IQ tests are
carefully and painstakingly constructed from a very large set of items selected to
be homogeneous (high g loading), with thousands of respondents. Even so,
with factor rotation algorithms, or with a confirmatory factor analysis using
structural equation models, one can usually fit a multidimensional model to
these seemingly unidimensional datasets, and many psychologists believe there
are sound theoretical reasons to do so (see e.g., Cattell, 1963; Sternberg, 1999).
Multiple Constraint Satisfaction in Judging 39
Brandon L. Bartels
41
42 Judges and Human Behavior
law and ideology will exhibit greater or lesser impacts on judges choices. The
theoretical perspectiveand this essay in generalis primarily aimed toward
explaining decision making by justices on the U.S. Supreme Court. However,
the ideas have implications for judges at other levels of the judiciary.
murder case. The police may develop a theory early on about who the
murderer is, based on their prior knowledge about the particular type of
murder. For instance, if a child is killed inside the home, parents are typically
suspects. The police may develop a theory about how and why the parents
killed their child. In a top-down reasoning process, this theory would dom-
inate the investigation process, leading to a biased search for the truth. The
police will zone in on the parents, give less weight to alternative evidence
suggesting a different suspect, and exclude other suspects. They view all
evidence through the lens of the parent-centered theory they develop.
In contrast to top-down processing, bottom-up processing involves objec-
tive scrutiny of the information, facts, or evidence at hand. It involves objec-
tively assessing the relevant information and making a judgment based solely on
the facts, as opposed to predispositional biases. Bottom-up processing is usually
referred to as inductiveit is data driven. The theories or predispositions
people bring to the judgment context do not dominate the decision process.
Returning to the police investigation example, police would engage in bottom-
up reasoning if they are able suppress the biasing influence of a particular theory
that may develop during a murder investigation. They engage in an objective
search for the truth, considering all the relevant facts and evidence.
Fazios MODE model (1990; Fazio & Towles-Schwen, 1999), which
explains the processes by which and extent to which attitudes guide behavior,
sheds further light on top-down versus bottom-up processing. MODE stands
for Motivation and Opportunity as DEterminants, and these determinants
regulate whether people will enter into one of two attitude-behavior pro-
cesses: a deliberative process or a spontaneous process. The deliberative
process is a data-driven, bottom-up process, in which an individual closely
and systematically scrutinizes information, or the data, that is, the the
attributes of the behavioral alternative (Fazio & Towles-Schwen, 1999, p. 99;
see also Ajzen & Fishbein, 1980). Thus, it is an objective form of processing,
where attitudes may play a role in guiding behavior, but their influence is
diminished in the presence of the other attribute-based considerations.
A spontaneous attitude-behavior process is a top-down, theory-driven
process, where an automatically activated attitude is triggered, which then
biases how the individual processes the data and the attributes of the alter-
natives. In short, the attitude triggered by the immediate appraisal of the
decision context biases how one processes and perceives subsequent informa-
tion in an automatic, unconscious fashion. This strong attitude functions like
a theory, discussed above. The stronger the attitude, the more likely that
attitude will dominate the decision process at the expense of objectively
assessing the facts and evidence at hand.
Importantly, a mixed, controlled process may also occur whereby people
can overcome the potential biasing influences of even a relatively accessible
attitude when they [are] properly motivated; they can objectively process the
attributes of the alternatives instead of readily accepting the interpretation
implied by their attitudes (Fazio & Towles-Schwen, 1999, p. 102). Petty and
Top-Down and Bottom-Up Models of Judicial Reasoning 45
Wegeners (1993; see also Wegener & Petty, 1995) flexible correction model
is akin to this mixed model. Upon entering a judgment context, an attitude
may be automatically activated, but the activation of knowledge regarding
the normative requirements induces an individual to define the event as one
in which he or she needs to control and monitor impulsive behavior carefully
(Fazio & Towles-Schwen, 1999, p. 103). This controlled process means that
people will recognize their biases and, if motivated, will correct for those
biases, inducing one to engage in more data-driven processing, which will
attenuate the impact of the automatically activated attitude (Fazio &
Towles-Schwen, 1999, p. 103).
precedent(s) and legal doctrine, the arguments in the briefs, oral arguments,
and other legal considerations.
The top-down model is a theory-driven reasoning process whereby the
policy predispositions a justice brings to a decision context determine how
the justice will both process the information at hand and make the judgment.
In this process, predispositions, in the form of policy preferences, dictate how
the data will be processed. For a top-down processor, ones predisposition
provide a lens through which one views the data, therefore biasing the
reasoning process. Instead of letting the data guide the decision-maker, the
decision-maker finds the data that best supports his or her desired conclusion
(a la Segal & Spaeth, 2002). Akin to the MODE models spontaneous attitude-
behavior process, ideological predispositions condition the entire reasoning
process by determining how one appraises the cases, how one processes
relevant information, and ultimately, how one makes a decision.
The bottom-up model is a data-driven reasoning process whereby the
evidence, information, facts, and legal considerations objectively guide the
decision maker. Bottom-up processing is objective, unbiased processing of
the information and facts, untainted by the ideological predispositions one
may possess about the attributes in the decision context. Accuracy, fear of
invalidity, and accountability motivations drive one to engage in bottom-up
reasoning, to let the data determine how the decision is made, as opposed to
finding the evidence that best supports an ideological predisposition.
Therefore, given sufficient motivation, the impact of even a relatively acces-
sible attitude will be attenuated throughout the reasoning process, with the
justice instead focused on the facts and legal considerations.
Before moving on, a few caveats are in order. First, legal scholars and
political scientists recognize that facts, legal rules, and precedent are never
completely self-evident. The discovery of these factors can often involve sub-
jective choices based on differences of interpretation. Braman and Nelson
(2007), for example, report how the ascertainment of case similaritychoosing
which precedent most closely resembles the current casein legal reasoning
can be biased by policy preferences. Thus, rarely would we ever witness a judge
engaging in pure bottom-up reasoning. This leads directly to the second caveat.
I do not mean to depict judicial reasoning processes as either strictly top-down
or strictly bottom-up. Instead, I view these two processes as endpoints of a
reasoning continuum, with various hybrid processes falling in between. Social
cognition perspectives, and my own perspective, tend to focus on factors that
serve to reduce the amount of top-down processing or increase the amount of
bottom-up processing. These perspectives recognize that under certain condi-
tions, bias may not be completely eliminated, but instead reduced, with ones
predispositions and the data guiding the decision process. I recognize this
nuance and do not necessarily examine the conditions under which the effects
of policy preferences in the decision making process are completely eliminated,
which would suggest a purely bottom-up process, or are completely determi-
nant, which would suggest a purely top-down process.
Top-Down and Bottom-Up Models of Judicial Reasoning 49
Thus, while a pure bottom-up process would suggest that facts and legal
doctrine are essentially self-evident, recall that it represents an endpoint on a
continuum. Processes that move away from that endpoint can more realisti-
cally capture the subjectivity of interpretation that is inherent in legal rea-
soning. It is helpful, however, to depict and describe the full range of variation
in order to proffer a comprehensive explanation of judicial reasoning.
Collegial interaction
making, this has implications for explaining the relative impact of policy
preferences versus legal considerations.
Following this stage, justices must go through the legal reasoning process:
study the facts, read the parties briefs and amicus curiae briefs, examine past
precedents and legal doctrines, and engage in oral arguments. During this
data processing stage the justices sort through the information and attri-
butes associated with the case. The degree to which a justice is motivated to
control predispositional biases will determine how the justice processes the
data. It is at this stage that theory and data collidea justice begins reasoning
either in a more top-down, theory-driven process or a bottom-up, data-
driven process. In a top-down process, a justice assesses the data through
the biasing lens of his or her policy preferences. In a bottom-up process, a
justice suppresses this bias and assesses the data through a more objective
lens. In a hybrid process, a justice processes information via a mixed
processa weighted combination of top-down versus bottom-up processing,
where the weights are determined by the operative motivation(s).4
To summarize, I posit that there are two key stages in the sequence of a
justices decision process where there is variation crucial to explaining the
relative influence of policy preferences and legal considerations on justices
decisions. First, upon exposure to a particular case, a preference will be
activated to a certain degree, such that less than complete preference acces-
sibility will set the stage for a process where the biasing impact of policy
preferences in the decision process will be attenuated and the impact of
objective considerations will be elevated. At the second stage in the process,
a justices motivation to control bias is central. As this motivation increases,
bottom-up processing is more likely to occur, and the impact of policy
preferences in the decision process will be attenuated. Below, I construct
ideal types of justices decision processes based on combinations of these
two key factors. These ideal types provide predictions about the type of
reasoning process under various conditions, and predictions about the effects
of policy preferences and legal considerations.
The four ideal types summarized in Table 3.1 consist of all combinations
of whether or not a justices preference accessibility is high or low and
whether or not a justice is motivated to control an inclination to act solely
on the basis of policy preferences. As ideal types, these four models focus on
high and low values of both accessibility and motivation to control bias in
order to explore the full theoretical spectrum of processes of behavior. I begin
by discussing the two most extreme ideal types. The first ideal type encom-
passes a situation where a justices policy preference is highly accessible, and
moreover, the justice is not motivated to control biasperhaps the justice
does not feel accountable to another entity, possesses no fear of invalidity, and
is driven primarily by ideological goals. This motivational type produces a
52 Judges and Human Behavior
Predictions
Conclusion
In this essay, I have presented a broad cognitive perspective of judging. In this
section, I touch on some more tangible issues and obstacles, particularly with
respect to testing some of the empirical implications of the model. First, what
factors are associated with preference accessibility and motivation to control
predispositional biases? In other words, what situations or conditions would
induce the accessibility of policy preferences and what situations would
54 Judges and Human Behavior
Notes
I am grateful to Lawrence Baum, Eileen Braman, David Klein, and Howard Lavine
for extremely helpful feedback and suggestions on this essay.
1. I use the terms policy preferences, ideology, and attitudes toward legal
policy interchangeably.
2. Posner (1992) has distinguished between top-down and bottom-up legal rea-
soning processes. While there are some general similarities between his approach
and mine (e.g., emphasis on theory-driven reasoning), some key differences
exist. Namely, his conceptual framework is not psychologically oriented. My
focus is on the extent to which, and conditions under which, ideological predis-
positions bias legal reasoning processes.
3. The issue of whether this is a conscious or unconscious process would require a
more in-depth discussion, which is beyond this essays central scope of inquiry.
What is most important in this discussion is whether and to what degree justices
are motivated to control their biases. It is quite conceivable that such a process
could be either conscious or unconscious, a question I leave for future research.
4. I exclude from this discussion any collegial interaction that occurs in the opinion
drafting stage (e.g., Maltzman, Spriggs, & Wahlbeck, 2000). Incorporating small-
group dynamics (see Martineks essay in this volume) would offer a compelling
addition to the framework I have laid out.
5. I thank Pete Rowland for suggesting this idea in a conversation.
This page intentionally left blank
4
Persuasion in the Decision Making of U.S.
Supreme Court Justices
Lawrence S. Wrightsman
The purpose of this paper is to provide some thoughts about the role of
persuasion in judicial decision making. Herein, persuasion is treated broadly
as the process of influence, which covers not only overt attempts at influence
(by the media, by the advocates, and by other judges) but also the judges
responses to attempts at influence. Emphasis is on the question: What
influences how a judge forms an initial opinion about a case? The coverage
and examples refer to the United States Supreme Court, but the ideas are
applicable to other appellate panels and in some respects to trial judges.
Basic Assumptions
This paper assumes that justices are more susceptible to persuasion
depending on the nature of the case; some cases deal with matters to which
the justices have given much prior thought. Certain cases may reflect issues on
which they have developed strong views long in their past. Research on
persuasion certainly indicates that the nature of the material affects the will-
ingness to be responsive to an attempt to persuade. But individual differences
may exist in justices readiness to be persuaded on all issues; some may possess
personality characteristics that inhibit change. Thus, this paper reflects two
assumptions:
1. Persuasion operates differently depending on the type of case.
2. Persuasion operates differently depending on the particular justice.
57
58 Judges and Human Behavior
The body of the paper elaborates on these assumptions and presents some
data and examples to evaluate the papers claims.
rules. In 2001 the Court again sided with Kansas, including a judgment that
Colorado should pay interest on the damages accrued. While the question of
an interpretation of the Eleventh Amendment was part of the issue at hand,
the Supreme Court ruled unanimously in favor of Kansas in 2001, and the
basis appears to be simply what the law says. Thus the case appears to be free
of ideological triggers.
How does persuasion operate differently in ideological cases than in
nonideological cases? First, it is proposed that justices are aware of ideological
cases earlier than they are about nonideological cases. Well before their
conference to decide which cases to grant cert, even well before a petition is
submitted, the typical ideological case has generated publicity. A state passes a
law that critically restricts abortions, a universitys admissions program to
increase diversity is challenged in a lower court, the Bush administration
places prisoners of war at Guantanamo Bay and denies them rights to a trial
such decisions draw attention from the media, and the justices read the
newspapers and watch television news as many members of the citizenry
do. In contrast, for many nonideological cases, the first awareness may come
when the justice reads the recommendations from a law clerk who has
processed the case as part of the cert pool.
Second, at the point of granting cert, justices know more about the issues
in ideological cases than nonideological ones. Issues of search and seizure, for
example, are frequently before the Court; in the October 2003 Term the Court
dealt with ten cases involving claims of a violation of Fourth Amendment
rights. More often, nonideological cases deal with a relatively obscure federal
law, so that during the process leading up to the decision to grant cert, most
justices have to do more review. For example, a case during the October 2003
Term (BedRoc Limited v. United States) dealt with the terminology in the
Pittman Underground Water Act of 1919, a legislative decision probably not
on the forefront of each justices awareness prior to preparing for the cert
conference.
But the most important difference is what makes the case ideological
whether its issues generate a value-based predisposition. Many years ago
psychologist Fred Kerlinger (1967) proposed that in conceptualizing attitudes
and values, it was useful not to think of each as a bipolar continuum, but
rather to focus on what he called criterial referents. Certain objects, topics,
or issues may serve as anchors, or criterial referents, which define ones values.
For each justice, different issues may serve as criterial referents; for some,
abortion; for some, the death penalty; and for some, racial or gender dis-
crimination. These serve as triggers to at least a preliminary leaning in one
direction. Sometimes it is more than a leaning; it is an irrevocable response.
For example, toward the end of Justice Harry Blackmuns service on the
60 Judges and Human Behavior
Court, his position on any case coming before the Court that dealt with the
death penalty was clear. In 1994, his dissent in Callins v. Collins states:
From this day forward, I no longer shall tinker with the machinery of
death. . . . It is virtually self evident to me now that no combination
of procedural rules or substantive regulations can ever save the death
penalty from its inherent constitutional deficiencies. . . . The
problem is that the inevitability of factual, legal, and moral error
gives us a system that we know must wrongly kill some defendants, a
system that fails to deliver the fair. . . and reliable sentences of death
required by the Constitution. (p. 1145)
More recently, Justice Antonin Scalia has made it clear that on certain
matters before the Court, he had made his mind up before the process of
considering the issues had been completed. On one occasionthe issue was
the constitutionality of the words under God included in the Pledge of
Allegiancehe recused himself because of public statements he had made.
But in another notable case, that of Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, he did not. This
case required the Court to decide whether an enemy combatant who was
detained at Guantanamo Bay was protected by the articles of the 1949 Geneva
Conventions as a prisoner of war. In a speech a few weeks before this cases
oral arguments, Scalia ridiculed the suggestion that detainees captured on
the battlefield should receive a trial in civil courts; that proposition, he said,
was a crazy idea. He interrupted a subsequent question by claiming: If he
was captured by my army on a battlefield, that is where he belongs. I have a
son on that battlefield and they were shooting at my son. And I am not about
to give this man who was captured in a war a full jury trial. I mean its crazy
(Isikoff, 2006, p. 6).
Justice Scalias comments drew strong criticism and calls for recusal from
several sources (Isikoff, 2006). But Justice Scalia was not deterred; he participated
actively at the oral arguments and voted in the case. In fairness to Justice Scalia, he
is certainly not the only justice and this was not the only case in which a justices
eventual vote was fixed in concrete before the oral arguments; the matter came to
light because of his provocative style and willingness to express his opinion in
public. For him, if not every justice, this was an ideological case, and his actions
support the argument that in such cases, opinions are formed early and not
susceptible to persuasion. Thus, even though the focus of this paper is on
persuasion, it questions how much opportunity exists to persuade justices on
certain cases; their minds may be made up very quickly.
possibility is that in a particular case, the attitudinal model may describe the
reaction of some justices, while others may struggle to maintain a basis in the
legal model.
The wealth of empirical data used by adherents of the attitudinal model
(consistency in votes, correlation of votes of individual justices with their
ideological pronouncements in speeches, books, or articles) to support their
claim may apply in ideological cases, but in those cases where no personal
values are salient, the justices are more likely to examine the statutes, the
precedents, and, if applicable, the Constitution in a dispassionate manner.
(See, for example, the recent article by Lindquist and Klein, 2006, that revives
support for the role played by legal reasoning in Supreme Court decisions.)
Predictions
In summary, it is proposed that, compared to their response to nonideolo-
gical cases, individual justices in ideological cases are less responsive to the
persuasion expressed in merit briefs and oral arguments. Specifically, it is
hypothesized that they:
1. Form initial opinions more quickly.
2. Are less likely to change their opinions.
3. Have formed opinions by the time of oral arguments, so that their
questioning reflects their already-formed opinions.
4. Are less responsive to outside influences.
5. Are more predictable with regard to their final votes.
Furthermore, this paper suggests that the degree to which a case is ideolo-
gical can be reflected in several qualities of the dispensation of the case.
Specifically, in ideological cases, compared to nonideological cases:
1. The final vote will less often be a unanimous vote, because the
current composition of the Court is divided ideologically.
2. It will take longer for the Court to announce the decision in the case,
because the minority will more likely write dissents and the opinion
of the Court will go through more drafts.
As part of an ongoing project (see Wrightsman, 2008), data have been
collected from several recent terms of the Supreme Court that sometimes
directly and sometimes indirectly respond to these hypotheses.
For four recent terms each case has been classified as ideological, border-
line, or nonideological. The following variables have been determined:
1. In the oral arguments, the length of time (measured in words) that
the petitioner spoke and the respondent spoke before they were
interrupted by a justice.
2. The number of questions asked each advocate by the justices during
the oral arguments.
Persuasion in the Decision Making of U.S. Supreme Court Justices 63
sessions for the October 1980 Term and for the October 2003 Term, and
determined, for each case, the number of questions directed at the petitioner
and the number directed at the respondent. Then he examined which side
won. He reported: In the 28 cases I looked at, 14 from the 1980 Term and
14 from 2003, the most-questions-asked rule predicted the winneror,
more accurately, the loserin 24 of those 28 cases, an 86 percent prediction
rate (2005, p. 75). Then he drily added, The secret to successful advocacy is
simply to get the Court to ask your opponent more questions (2005, p. 75).
Like Shullman, Roberts did not define what a question was, and neither
study distinguished between ideological and nonideological cases. But the
methodology seemed to provide an entry into determining if any difference
related to persuadability existed. Does the more-questions-to-the loser rule
hold when all cases in a term are examined? Does it hold more strongly for
ideological cases?
It was also predicted that the justices would take longer to announce decisions
in ideological cases. Decision latency was measured by the number of days
between the oral argument and the announcement of the decision. For the
October 2002 Term, the average latency for ideological cases was 8l days, for
borderline ideological 75 days, and for nonideological 67 days. For the
October 2005 Term, these average latencies were 84, 78, and 66 days. In
both terms, ideological cases took longer to reach final resolution. But in
the October 2001 Term, the justices took less time to decide ideological
cases82 days versus 92 days for nonideological cases.
in the type of case to predict the votes and outcome. Experts were asked to
predict the outcomes of cases within only their areas of expertise. Like the
predictions from the statistical formula, all predictions by the experts were
made prior to oral arguments. Experts were provided a copy of the lower
court opinion and citations to the parties Supreme Court briefs, but they
were free to consider any sources of information they considered relevant.
Overall, the statistical model correctly predicted 75% of the decisions in
the October 2002 Term, while the experts, as a group, were correct only 59.1%
of the time (Ruger et al., 2004, Table 1, p. 1171). It was hypothesized that
decisions in the ideological cases would be more predictable than those in the
nonideological cases, and so a further analysis was done of data that were
available on the projects website (www.wusct.wustl.edu). Considering the
statistical model first, it was found that it was correct in 26 of 33 ideological
cases or 78.8%, correct in 11 of 15 borderline-ideological cases, or 73.3%, and
correct in 16 of 23 nonideological cases, or 69.6%. Thus the predicted
difference was obtained. For the experts, in ideological cases, 53 of 88 were
correct or 60.2%, while 18 of 35 were correct in borderline-ideological cases,
or 51.4%, and 32 of 55 were correct in nonideological cases, or 58.2%. For the
experts, the differences are not linear, as they are with the statistical model,
and the experts did not do appreciably better in the ideological cases than in
the nonideological ones.
Interim Summary
In summary, persuasion does appear to operate somewhat differently based
on whether the case is an ideological one or not. Data from several terms
indicate that:
1. In ideological cases, the final vote less often is unanimous.
2. In ideological cases, the time it takes to reach a decision is longer, at
least in the majority of terms.
3. In oral arguments in ideological cases, justices direct more questions
to the advocate or advocates who represent what later becomes the
losing side, implying that to some extent justices have already
formed an opinion in ideological cases before the oral argument.
4. In ideological cases, the decision of the Court is less often consistent
with the position of the Office of the Solicitor General, again
reflecting the power of the justices own ideologies in deciding such
cases.
Most of the empirical tests of the hypothesis produce small differences,
although the pattern is strongly in the expected direction. The smallness of the
differences is perhaps not surprising, given the rather broad means of distin-
guishing between ideological and nonideological cases. For example, abortion
cases were classified as ideological; in actuality, the topic of abortion triggers
68 Judges and Human Behavior
Conclusion
In the preface to The Puzzle of Judicial Behavior, Lawrence Baum expresses his
belief that we are a long way from achieving explanations of judicial behavior
that are fully satisfactory (1997, p. xi). That was more than10 years ago; this
chapter has presented a modest effort toward an explanation, by identifying
ways that persuasion operates differently on judges as they form their opi-
nions, depending on their biases and the nature of the case. Beyond this,
scholars are beginning the hard work of examining the files of several recent
justices, especially the detailed records of Justice Blackmun, to illustrate the
role of persuasion during the process of moving from the initial decision draft
to the final opinion of the Court. The recent article by Johnson, Spriggs, and
Wahlbeck (2007) is an excellent example. We can look forward to a greater
understanding of the role of persuasion at all stages of judicial decision
making.
5
Judges as Members of Small Groups
Wendy L. Martinek
Though most judges are trial court judges, and most judicial decisions are
made by trial court judges, appellate courts and the judges who populate
them have attracted a considerable (disproportionate?) share of scholarly
attention. This focus is perhaps lamentable but understandable given that
judicial policymaking falls more centrally in the province of appellate
courts rather than trial courts.1 In fact, some legal scholars have gone so
far as to suggest that policymaking is the primary function of appellate
courts (Landes & Posner, 1979).2 The importance of the decisions appellate
courts make is reflected in the fact that virtually all appellate courts use
groups of judges to render decisions. Sometimes this includes the full
complement of judges on a court (e.g., the U.S. Supreme Court) and
sometimes merely a subset of those judges (e.g., the South African
Appellate Division) but, with exceedingly rare exceptions, appellate court
decisions are group decisions. The logic underlying the use of groups of
judges at the appellate stage is straightforward: deliberation among a set of
judges is intended to enhance the likelihood of arriving at the correct
decision; that is, reduce the likelihood of erroneously reversing a correct
lower court decision or erroneously affirming an incorrect lower court
decision (Drahozal, 1998).
The fact that appellate courts are collegial (that is, multimember) courts
has not been lost on students of judicial behavior. In particular, those scholars
who approach judicial choice through the lens of strategic behavior explicitly
recognize that, to achieve their most preferred policy outcome, judges on
73
74 Judges and Human Behavior
collegial courts must consider the likely actions of their colleagues on the
bench to determine their best course of action:
[J]ustices may be primarily seekers of legal policy, but they are not
unconstrained actors who make decisions based only on their own
ideological attitudes. Rather, justices are strategic actors who realize their
ability to achieve their goals depends on a consideration ofthe preferences
of other actors, the choices they expect others to make, and the
institutional context in which they act. (Epstein & Knight, 1998, p. 10)
Though Epstein and Knight were writing about members of the U.S. Supreme
Court bench, their description of strategic behavior by members of that court
is equally applicable to judges on other appellate courts, both domestic (e.g.,
Hettinger, Lindquist, & Martinek, 2006; Langer, 2002) and foreign (Helmke,
2005; Vanberg, 2005).
Such scholarship takes seriously the fact that judicial decisions on collegial
courts are the product of group choices and, in that regard, takes into account
the small group environment of collegial court decision making. The focus of
the majority of this scholarship is unduly narrow, however, in that it almost
always presumes a single goal (policy) and neglects to consider nonstrategic
aspects of appellate court decision making (see Baum, 2006, pp. 68). But the
small group context of appellate court decision making has meaningful con-
sequences beyond serving as a venue for strategic calculations. This is where
psychology, especially the insights of social and organizational psychology
scholarship, focused on the behavior of small groups, can be profitably
deployed to further our understanding of how judges on collegial courts
behave. This is by no means the first time such an approach has been suggested.
Schubert (1964), Murphy (1966), and Ulmer (1971), among others,3 made this
same argument quite some time ago. But since then, researchers approaching
collegial court decision making as a type of small group behavior have been few
and far between.4 This is an unfortunate state of affairs.
Taking a small group approach to the study of judicial decision making is
very much an interdisciplinary activity. Sociologists, organizational behavior
researchers, social psychologists, and anthropologists have all applied small
group theory to their work.5 Regardless of the disciplinary context, however, a
key preliminary issue is determining what constitutes a small group. Levine
and Moreland offer a useful definition of a small group: a group of individuals
who interact on a regular basis, have affective ties with one another, share a
common frame of reference, and are behaviorally interdependent (1994,
p. 306). Notwithstanding their enormous institutional variation, this defini-
tion certainly fits the situation of virtually all appellate courts.6
First, judges serving on appellate courts must interact on a regular basis to
dispose of their caseloads. For example, many appellate court judges, such as
the justices of the U.S. Supreme Court and some members of state courts of last
resort, come together in conference to make decisions about which cases to
accept for review (Langer, 2002; Perry, 1991). And all members of an appellate
Judges as Members of Small Groups 75
court or appellate court panel must come together for oral arguments (Cohen,
2002, pp. 133136; Johnson, 2004) when they are held.7 Further, a written
opinion that formally disposes of a case may be the product of an intensive and
iterative process among the judges (Maltzman, Spriggs, & Wahlbeck, 2000) or a
less interactive process but, nevertheless, does entail at least some level of
interaction if for no other reason than a majority of the judges on an appellate
panel must sign off on an opinion to make it a majority opinion.
Second, judges serving on appellate courts may squabble like children,
bond like family, or behave toward one another in a more detached, profes-
sional manner, but both anecdotal (Cooper, 1995; Hirsch, 1981; Schick, 1970)
and systematic (Cohen, 2002; Howard, 1981) evidence make clear that there
is an affective component to the interactions between and among judges
serving on appellate courts. The personal closeness between Chief Justice
Warren Burger and Justice Harry Blackmun, which devolved into a relation-
ship that could be called strained, at best, is one well-known example. Further,
Justices Brennan and Marshall were considered close colleagues, both on and
off the bench, while Justices Ginsburg and Scalia, though ideologically dis-
similar, are known to be personally quite friendly. Even in the absence of
personal affecteither positive or negativefor one another judges on
appellate courts share affective ties to the institutions on which they serve.
Third, colleagues on a given appellate bench possess a common frame of
reference provided by the institutional environment within which they
operate. That institutional environment includes rules regarding case selec-
tion, oral argument, opinion assignment, and the like. It also includes a
common body of law, which they are charged with interpreting and applying.
While nonjudges may recognize and acknowledge this common frame of
reference, they are viewing it as outsiders rather than partaking of it as judges
themselves do. In other words, colleagues on the bench function as a true
peer group, people who share the same position and work in the same
situation (Baum, 2006, p. 54).
And, fourth, appellate court judges are behaviorally interdependent by
definition. No single judge on an appellate court, not even the majority
opinion author, can individually determine the winner and loser in a given
case or dictate the content of the legal rule embedded in a particular written
opinion. Those are functions of the collective choices of the judges on that
appellate court. While it is true that some judges may be more influential than
others both as to the winners and losers in a case and as to the reasoning
subscribed to by an appellate court in determining those winners and losers,
no single judge can be determinative in the disposition of an appellate court
decision. In short, [a]ppellate court decisions are inherently collective pro-
ducts. The outcome for the litigants and the legal doctrine that a court
promulgates are determined by where a majority of judges stand (Baum,
2006, p. 51).
Though individual collegial courts may differ in their proximity to the
archetype of a small group as defined by social psychologists and
76 Judges and Human Behavior
that formal leaders such as chief justices have no punitive measures they can
impose. The opinion assignment authority of the Chief Justice of the United
States is an example of a power that could be used punitively through the
withholding of desirable opinion assignments, though the discretion to use
opinion assignment in this fashion is not infinitely elastic given efficiency
concerns (Maltzman & Wahlbeck, 1996). Compliance with or deference to
the wishes of an appellate court leader is secured in large part voluntarily or
not at all. The question remains, however: when can a person occupying a
formally defined leadership position on an appellate court effectively influ-
ence his colleagues? Small group theory can provide useful guidance in
answering this question.
Likewise, small group theory can profitably inform our work regarding
the behavioral effects of other types of roles. For example, the evidence to date
suggests that judges who are new to their positions are likely to face an
acclimation or socialization process (Alpert, Atkins, & Ziller, 1979; Hurwitz
& Stefko, 2004; Wood et al., 1998). Louis defines organizational socialization
as the process by which an individual comes to appreciate the values,
abilities, expected behaviors, and social knowledge essential for assuming an
organizational role (1980, p. 229). In other words, organizational new-
comers must gather a great deal of information about an institution before
they can become fully fledged members of that organization. A natural source
for that information is the other members of the organization. Freshman
judges, in effect, may cue off the behavior of their more senior colleagues.
Small group theory can guide our thinking about how freshman judges
determine which colleagues to rely on as cues for their own behaviors. Is
ideological proximity key or is it, perhaps, respect that comes from demon-
strated expertise? Alternatively, selecting a cue giver may be a function of
demographic and experiential similarities or the recognition of the status
accorded to a particular member of a court by other members of that court.
Research devoted to understanding conformity and status attainment in
small groups holds promise vis-a`-vis its utility for understanding when and
how new members of collegial courts select cue givers from among their
colleagues, as well as how more senior group members behave toward new
colleagues. Specifically, expectation states theory suggests that group mem-
bers have expectations for themselves and for other members of the group
regarding their ability to contribute toward the completion of the groups
tasks (Berger et al., 1977; Berger, Wagner, & Zelditch, 1985). These expecta-
tions are based on both external status characteristics and specific informa-
tion regarding task competency. External status characteristics include gender
and race, demographic characteristics that shape beliefs about task compe-
tence. For example, women are generally disadvantaged compared to men in
terms of their perceived competence in economics and foreign affairs but
advantaged when it comes to their perceived competence in social welfare
issues (Sapiro, 1983). Further, African Americans are seen as less able to
engage in abstract thinking compared to whites (Plous & Williams, 1995).
Judges as Members of Small Groups 81
small group constituted by a collegial court might matter for the quality of
adjudication. As noted at the beginning of this chapter, appellate courts consist
of more than one member on the presumption that groups of judges will be less
likely to err than single judges. In theory, each member of a collegial court will
engage in a deliberative process with his colleagues in which the decision-
making biases and other cognitive deficiencies of each judge will be compen-
sated for by his fellow judges on the bench. The end result will be adjudication
that, though a function of the decisions of individual judges on the bench, goes
beyond the mere sum of those individual decisions. Work by Gruenfeld
and Hollingshead suggests that a group cognition process such as this ideal
conception of adjudication is possible: [I]ndividuals in social interaction do
more than trade individually produced cognitions. They also engage in active
reconciliation and integration processes, leading to the emergence of unique,
collectively produced conceptualizationsincluding ideas, representations,
solutions, and argumentsthat no individual had to begin with (1993,
p. 385). As a consequence, the quality of a group decision has the potential to
exceed that of even the most skilled individual member of the group under
ceteris paribus conditions. Ceteris paribus conditions, however, are rare rather
than common.
There are a host of factors that can compromise the quality of adjudica-
tion, factors to which our attention is directed by the extant body of small
group research. One of these factors is undue deference on the part of some
members of a collegial court to other members. Such deference may result
from a status differential between and among judges. For example, the nature
of the judicial hierarchy implies that judges serving on appellate courts
occupy more prestigious positions than those serving on trial courts. This,
in turn, suggests that U.S. District Court judges serving temporarily by
designation on the U.S. Courts of Appeals or with circuit court judges on
three-judge district courts may defer to the circuit court judges with whom
they serve (Brudney & Ditslear, 2001; Walker, 1973). And, as previously
discussed, judges new to the appellate bench may similarly be deferential to
their more senior colleagues (Hettinger, Lindquist, & Martinek, 2003).
Certainly there are conditions under which such deference may be desirable,
as when neophyte judges pay heed to senior colleagues with more expertise.
Regardless, the roles group members occupy can result in less than the full-
throated deliberations among equals that the ideal of appellate adjudication
suggests.
Even assuming equal status among all members of an appellate court,
there are reasons to be concerned about the quality of the adjudication
process that derive from the fact that it is decision making by a small
group. Specifically, individuals participating in group decision making pro-
cesses are susceptible to conformity effects (Sunstein, 2003). Part of this may
be attributable to the fact that members of a group care about the evaluations
of their fellow group members and, all things being equal, prefer higher to
lower status within the group. And at least some research on organizational
Judges as Members of Small Groups 83
Notes
Special thanks are due to Paul M. Collins Jr. and Raymond V. Carman Jr. for their
thoughts about the utility of small group theories for understanding judicial
behavior on collegial courts and Harold J. Spaeth for his insights on this and related
projects.
1. There is also a very practical reason for the focus on appellate courtsand
appellate courts of last resort, such as the United States Supreme Court, in
particularthat has to do with the comparative ease of collecting the requisite
data to answer questions about how and why judges make the decisions they
make for appellate courts. The very fact that there are so many more trial courts
makes it a daunting task to gather information on a representative set of courts,
judges, and decisions sufficient for the purposes of inference.
2. Of course, trial court judges arguably make policy in the pattern of decisions
they render (Rowland & Carp, 1996).
3. Other notable work drawing on the psychology of small groups includes work
by Snyder (1958) and a series of articles by Walker (1973, 1974, 1976).
4. There is a similar dearth of recent political science scholarship that takes a small
group approach outside the context of judicial behavior, despite Kirkpatricks
(1976) exhortation and some promising work from the late 1970s and early
1980s (e.g., Dorff & Steiner, 1981; Fiorina & Plott, 1978; Hinckley, 1979).
84 Judges and Human Behavior
5. Hare, Borgatta, and Bales (1965) contains an excellent set of readings that nicely
illustrates the interdisciplinary history of small group theory.
6. This is consistent with Murphy: Collegial courts. . . use small groups in a face-
to-face relationship that interact under an obligation to solve a specific problem
or set of problems (1966, p. 1565).
7. Of course, not all appellate court cases are disposed of with the aid of oral
argument. On some appellate courts, in fact, a sizable proportion of the cases
are disposed of without oral argument (Cohen, 2002, pp. 6062).
8. One school of thought among the legal realists focused on the role of social
forces, while the other focused on the characteristics of individual judges.
9. The symposium appearing in the Spring 1994 issue of Law & Courts and the
symposium appearing in the Summer 2003 issue of that same newsletter offer a
representative sampling of the criticisms of the attitudinal model.
10. Issue 3 of volume 40 of the American Journal of Political Science (1996) was
specifically devoted to Segal and Spaeths empirical test of the influence of
precedent and critiques of that approach.
11. Certificated judges are retired judges who are certified to be both willing and
able to serve on a New York State court.
12. Designated district court judges serve for temporary periods of time on the
appeals court bench. Those coming from within the circuit are so designated at
the discretion of the chief judge of the circuit. Those coming from outside the
circuit are so designated only with the permission of the Chief Justice of the
United States. Similarly, circuit judges from one circuit may serve temporarily
in another circuit with the permission of the Chief Justice. Service by these
judges visiting the appellate bench from outside the circuit or from the
district court bench provides considerable service to the U.S. Courts of
Appeals (Cohen, 2002, pp. 194195).
13. There are notable exceptions, of course, such as the influence of Chief Justice
Warren Burger in President Richard Nixons selection of Burgers boyhood
friend Harry Blackmun for a spot on the Supreme Court.
14. The empirical evidence suggests that judicial reputations do have tangible
effects. For example, the reputations of United States Courts of Appeals
judges make a difference in the extent to which individual judges are influential
in the development of intra- and intercircuit law (Klein, 2002). Further,
Caminker (1994) makes the case that judges care about their reputations for
reasons of advancement.
6
The Supreme Court, Social Psychology,
and Group Formation
The justices of the Supreme Court function not only as individuals, but as
members of groups. One group of which they are part is the Court itself, as
discussed in Wendy Martineks chapter in this volume (ch. 5). But they can also
come together to form important subgroups. In this chapter, we examine a
particular type of subgroup that we refer to as a majority coalitiona group of
ideologically simpatico justices who are able to issue unambiguous, far-reaching
decisions, as opposed to fact-specific decisions of limited consequence. We
employ social psychology literature to better understand when the Court will
and will not function as a cohesive coalition. In so doing, we also comment on
the models political scientists use to describe Supreme Court decision making.
Our principal claim is intuitively obvious but in tension with much of the
political science literature. Political science models of Supreme Court deci-
sion making typically focus on the legal and policy goals of individual
justicesso that the key question concerns the legal policy preferences of
the median justice and the ideological gap between the median justice and
other members of the Court. We think the political science models focus too
much on the individual and not enough on the group (including the reasons
why individuals do or do not join groups). Specifically, when there is an
ideologically simpatico majority coalition, intragroup dynamics play a pro-
minent role in determining the reach of Supreme Court decisions. More to
the point, the individual preferences of the median justice are less consequen-
tial on a cohesive Courtsince the median justice will (up to a point) give in
to intragroup pressures to uniformity. In contrast, the preferences of the
median justice play a more prominent role on an ideologically diverse
85
86 Judges and Human Behavior
Court. At the same time, these preferences may not mirror the policy views of
the median justice. In refusing to join forces with an ideologically cohesive
coalition, the median justice is likely to place a high value on personal power
and reputation. In other words, median justices on ideologically diverse
Courts have comparatively weaker legal policy preferences and are willing
(up to a point) to sublimate those preferences in order to pursue other goals.
We begin with a brief tour of the chief political science models, high-
lighting the ways in which those models focus on individuated legal and policy
preferences. We then turn to social psychology to examine both the importance
of and obstacles to group formation. Finally, by comparing differences in
decision-making styles of the (largely simpatico) New Deal Court and the
(very diverse) Rehnquist Court, we illustrate how social psychology can con-
tribute to an understanding of Supreme Court decision making.
strategically and whether justices are pursuing legal or policy objectives. For this
very reason, the median justice plays a central role in all three models. All
models, for example, think that power resides at the medianso that the
most powerful justice is the Justice in the middle of a distribution of Justices,
such that (in an ideological distribution, for example) half the Justices are to the
right of (more conservative than) the median and half are to the left of (more
liberal than) the median (Martin et al., 2005, p. 1277). To pick a simple
example, if the Court is split 5 to 4, the median justice would be the weakest
member of the majority coalition. Under the attitudinal model, the median
justice would only sign an opinion she agreed with and, as such, the majority
might move closer to her position (so long as they too agreed with the final
opinion) or, alternatively, the median Justice might write a consequential
concurring opinion that would limit the reach of the majority or plurality
opinion. The strategic and institutional models likewise see the medians view
as controlling. Not only might the median write a consequential concurring
opinion, but other justices in the majorityfearing possible defectionmight
move their opinion closer to the medians preferred legal or policy position.
The power of the median justice is variable, and that variability will call
attention both to commonalities and differences between the political science
models and a model that makes use of social psychology. For the political
science models, medians are most powerful when there is substantial ideolo-
gical distance between the median and other members of the Courtso that
the median sits between one group of justices substantially to the right and
another group of justices substantially to the left (Epstein & Jacobi, 2008).
During the 2006 term, for example, Justice Anthony Kennedy was a super-
median; among other measures, he was a member of the winning coalition in
each case decided by a 5-to-4 vote. In sharp contrast, medians are least
powerful when their preferences overlap with the preferences of justices to
their right or left. This convergence of preferences, moreover, makes it more
likely that there will be an ideologically simpatico majority coalition of
justices. When this happens, the Court is likely to issue consequential opi-
nions, for a majority coalition sharing great unity of mind has the ability to
adopt whatever rule it would like (Staudt et al., 2008, p. 369).
We agree with these conclusions but nevertheless feel that the political
science models are incomplete because their policy-preference-driven focus is
too narrow and ignores basic psychological concepts. As we discuss below, the
power of the median is diminished on an ideologically simpatico Court
because the median justice is a member of a majority coalition and pressures
toward uniformity will diminish the preferences of any individual justice.
Correspondingly, although median justices are more likely to assume power
on an ideologically diverse Court, the unwillingness of a median justice to join
one or another group is not simply a matter of ideological or jurisprudential
divergence. Median justices do not join groups because they are less interested
in the pursuit of some ideological or legal vision and more interested in
competing values, most notably power and image.
88 Judges and Human Behavior
We are not the first to observe that justices think about more than their
legal and/or policy preferences. Lawrence Baum, both in his 2006 study Judges
and their Audiences and in his chapter in this volume, criticizes the leading
political science models for failing to take into account the desires of judges to
win approval from audiences they care about. Noting that the Spock-like
judges of the dominant models have no interest in public approval as an end
in itself, Baum argues that political scientists need to take into account the
commonsense notion that judges, like other people, care a great deal about
what people think of them (Baum, 2006, p. 22). We agree and will discuss
how impression management figures into the willingness of a justice to be
part of a coalition of justices. Unlike Baum, however, the approach taken in
this chapter also applies social psychology to describe the interplay between
the justices themselves.
should also be more likely to go along with the coalition without issuing a
consequential concurrence. This should be especially true when the issue at
hand is particularly important or salient to the groups core beliefs. And, the
opinions issued by a majority coalition of justices will not reflect the prefer-
ences of the median justice on the Court. Instead, it will be the product of the
group dynamics of the majority and may be a more extreme position than
some members of the group would have preferred on their own.
Finally, depending on the cohesiveness of the coalition, there may be a
willingness among the members to vote together on other issues, provided the
votes on those issues are not central and opposed to a justices personal
beliefs. The more group members see the group as significant, important,
the more likely it is that the group will bond together and stick together
(Stangor, 2004, PIN/24). With respect to Supreme Court justices, norms of
independence (which typically cut against the formation of a cohesive
majority coalition) are likely to limit the willingness of group members to
form a group that cuts across all issues. It is far more likely that the group will
coalesce around a set of core issues and that the justices will act in a more
disparate way on issues that are not central to the groups identity. For
example, the New Deal Courtas we will soon discusswas formed
around the core issue of governmental power to regulate economic condi-
tions. Civil rights and liberties issues were not core to the formation of this
coalition and, not surprisingly, the majority coalition broke apart on civil
liberties questions.
Indeed, the bitterness that subsets of New Deal justices expressed about
each other in connection with civil rights and liberties issues backs up the
central point of this chapter: Although justices can come together to act as a
coalition on one set of core issues, at the same time, the social psychology
barriers that stand in the way of group formation also make it likely that these
justices will splinter on issues that are not central to the groups mission. We
turn to a discussion of those barriers now.
justices, there are countless opportunities to take into account their standing
with various audiencesoral argument, opinion writing, the giving of
speeches and interviews, attending social gatherings, so on and so forth. In
other words, judging on the Court is in many ways an exercise in self-
presentation, and the behavior of the justices is shaped in important ways
by the opinions of outside groups that the justices care about. More than that,
the very process by which we select justices tends to favor those with an
especially strong interest in the esteem of other people (Baum, 2006, p. 32).
Accepting a judgeship entails accepting relatively significant constraints on
personal activities and behaviors as well as a significant reduction in monetary
compensation. The inducement for accepting these losses is an increase in
prestige (and an increase in potential power). As a result, the types of people
who end up with judicial positions tend to be those who care a great deal
about the esteem of others.
Impression management figures prominently in the willingness of a
Supreme Court justice to join forces with others and forge a majority coali-
tion. To start, a justice will not join a coalition if that will harm her reputation
among groups that are important to her. Just as a justice will not join a group
that would require her to vote in ways not in sync with her personal beliefs, a
justice will not hurt her standing with groups she cares about. And while some
of these groups may have identifiable ideologies (Federalist Society, American
Constitution Society), externally focused justices are well aware that the norm
of judging in the United States is that the judge is a neutral, impartial arbiter
of disputes. For some (but not all) justices, this norm tends to act as a
disincentive to be part of a unified, ideologically identifiable subgroup of
justices, because people try to project images of themselves that are consis-
tent with the norms in a particular social setting and with the roles they
occupy (Leary, 1996, p. 67). In this way, justices have incentives to act like an
independent judge and not a member of an ideologically identifiable group.
As such, an externally focused judgeespecially as compared to public
officials whose status is tied to political battles that play out in public
viewhas little reason to curry favor with one or another ideologically
identifiable constituency. Justices with strong ideological precommitments,
however, will place a higher value on winning the esteem of some ideologi-
cally identifiable group. For these justices, approval by such groups may
matter more than engaging in self-presentation that is aimed at reinforcing
the norm of neutral, impartial arbiter.
Consider again our so-called swing justice. If all she cared about was
power, she would pay no mind to her reputation. Her decision to join one or
another side of a dispute would simply be an exercise in powerher efforts to
wield as much as influence as possible (either by filing a consequential
concurring opinion or by joining one or the other side of a dispute). In
particular, she would want to maintain her swing justice statusso that her
vote would be critical to the resolution of any dispute. Along these lines, she
would want to locate herself at the Courts median (and, to the extent
The Supreme Court, Social Psychology, and Group Formation 93
possible, distance herself from justices to her immediate right and left)
(Epstein & Jacobi, 2008, p. 7481). An externally focused swing justice,
instead, would focus on how others perceive her. Perhaps she would cultivate
a reputation of neutrality; perhaps she would want to be known as the critical
vote; perhaps she would want groups with disparate ideologies to view her
vote as gettable. Whatever her methodology or motivation, the externally
focused swing justice will place a high value on cultivating a positive image
with groups that do not demand ideological conformity.
Indeed, the desire to appear independent may prompt some justices to
engage in a type of behavior known as reactance. Reactance speaks to the
desire of individuals to resist challenges to their autonomy (Brehm & Brehm,
1981). In particular, when people feel their independence is threatened, they
will take steps to demonstrate that they are in control of their own behavior.
For example, the Supreme Courts 1992 reaffirmation of abortion rights in
Planned Parenthood v Casey may well be tied to the desires of Justices
OConnor, Kennedy, and Souter to demonstrate that they were not the
political lackeys of the presidents (Reagan and Bush I) who appointed them
to the Court. Proclaiming that the Courts legitimacy is tied to its ability to
withstand political attacks, these justices made clear that they would not
facilitate efforts by the Reagan and Bush administrations to push for the
overruling of Roe v. Wade. Taken together, these psychological concepts
illustrate some of the difficulties of forming a majority coalition on the
Court. A justice, of course, will not choose to join a coalition if doing so
means they have to cast a vote on a core issue that does not match her central
beliefs. In addition to legal and/or policy preferences, the desire for power,
impression management, and reactance may all contribute to a justices
refusal to join a coalition. In other words, even if a justices legal policy
preferences are largely in sync with an existing subgroup on the Court, a
justice might not join it. Put another way: Without strong ideological pre-
commitments to a particular group, Supreme Court justices are likely to value
power and image in ways that make them resistant to forging a majority
coalition.
On the other hand, justices with strong ideological precommitments may
be especially likely to join coalitions. Members of ideologically simpatico
coalitions will agree with each other on issues of high salience to coalition
members; consequently, they will more likely seek to assume power by
forcefully advancing a shared agenda. In other words, members of such a
group have less interest in exercising individualized power by casting the
decisive swing vote; for them, the pursuit of a shared agenda is the most
important manifestation of power. Likewise, justices with strong ideological
precommitments may be less interested in fostering the norm of an impartial,
independent jurist. Rather, when it comes to impression management, the
outside groups they care about are those who share their values and objec-
tives. Compare, for example, Justices Anthony Kennedy and Clarence
Thomas. Kennedyconsistent with swing justice behaviorplaces a high
94 Judges and Human Behavior
value on the opinions of the news media and other elites; Thomas identifies
closely with ideologically conservative groups (Baum, 2006, pp. 132, 142
144). If there are 5 or more ideologically simpatico justices, a majority
coalition may form. The key variable, as noted above, is whether these justices
have sufficiently strong ideological precommitments to overcome the basic
obstacles to group formation. For example, in determining whether a justice
will join a group, it may require more than the justice agreeing with other
members on the preferred outcome and legal reasoning in any given issue
space. A justice not strongly precommitted to the groups agenda may place a
higher value on the exercise of individual power or cultivating a reputation
for judicial independence. Perhaps for this reason, Justice Anthony Kennedy
broke ranks with the Rehnquist Courts conservative bloc by switching his
initial conference votes in high visibility school prayer and abortion cases.
(Greenburg, 2007, pp. 145160).
The appointments-confirmation process also stands as a substantial
obstacle to the formation of an ideologically simpatico majority coalition,
especially with regard to controversial, highly salient issues. Because justices
have life tenure, it is very unlikely that appointments to the Court will be
clustered closely together. Such clustering of appointments facilitates group
formation (Arrow et al., 2000, p. 69). In the case of the Court, this is both
because people who join an existing organization tend to identify with others
who join at the same time and because such clustering means that the same
president and Senate will be making the appointments, increasing the like-
lihood of clustered appointees being relatively closely aligned ideologically.
For example, as we will discuss near the end of this chapter, President
Roosevelts clustering of Supreme Court appointments from 1938 to 1943
figured prominently in the New Deal Courts dramatic expansion of govern-
ment power over the economy. At the same time, this perfect storm of closely
clustered appointments and other factors that would help overcome the
barriers to group formation rarely occurs.
tasked to write the decision, initially drafted an opinion that would have
remanded the case so that a trial court could make additional factual findings
(Cushman, 2000, p. 1138). Jackson nevertheless backed away from his ori-
ginal opinion and wrote a decision that effectively granted Congress carte
blanche power to regulate anything arguably economic. In private correspon-
dence, Jackson signaled his discomfort with his handiwork. Recognizing that
we no longer have legal judgment upon economic effects which we can
oppose to the policy judgment made by the Congress in legislation,
Jackson observed: I really know of no place . . . where we can bound the
doctrine (quoted in Cushman, 2000, pp. 1143, 1145).
Wickard exemplifies what a coherent Court can do. Committed to a
shared agenda, group members can work together to advance an expansive
vision of the law. Wickard also stands in sharp contrast to New Deal Court
decisions on individual rights. Unlike economic issues (which were core to
the groups formation), civil and individual rights were irrelevant to the
formation of the New Deal Court. Roosevelt wanted justices who would
validate the regulatory state; he was not especially interested in constitutio-
nalizing civil liberties and civil rights. At the time of Court-packing, the
Courts docket had almost no cases implicating civil and individual rights.
But with the Courts approval of sweeping legislative power over economic
issues, the Court inevitably turned its attention to other matters. Reflecting
both changing social conditions and their personal interest in asserting
power, judges created for themselves a new role in the political system, one
that involved identifying those preferred freedoms or suspect classifica-
tions that might provide a basis for trumping the otherwise unrestrained
power of the modern legislature (Gillman, 1993, pp. 202203). Here, the
New Deal Justices dividedreflecting the fact that groups organize around
clusters of core issues, that justices will not vote against their legal policy
beliefs on issues of consequence, and that the norm of impartiality pushes
justices away from groups that do not share their core beliefs. In other words,
just as social psychology helps explain why the New Deal Court acted as a
coherent group on economic questions, social psychology is also useful in
understanding why the justices were unwilling to forge a majority coalition
on issues involving civil and individual rights.
noting that in any given year, we make more important decisions than the
legislative branch does (quoted in Rosen, 2007b, p. 17).
For her part, Justice OConnor made extensive use of fact-specific con-
curring opinions to keep her options open in future cases and, more impor-
tantly, to tell litigants that the outcome of a case goes through herso
much so that litigants spoke about writing for an audience of one when
crafting Supreme Court briefs (Brust, 2005, p. 37; Estrich & Sullivan, 1989,
p. 119). As Justice Sandra Day OConnor votes, so goes the Court, wrote
one commentator, and it is undeniable that OConnor was aware of both the
power she wielded and her legacy as the Courts first women justice (Lazarus,
2000). OConnors flexible, context specific approach was most pro-
nounced in cases implicating civil and individual rights (Maveety, 1996,
p. 31). In a prominent voting rights case, OConnor filed a concurrence to a
decision she authored (Bush v. Vera, 1996, pp. 990995). When concurring to
a decision rejecting a constitutional right to physician assisted suicide,
OConnors reasoning fundamentally limited the majority opinionso
much so that Justice Stephen Breyer joined the concurrence except insofar
as it joins the majority(Washington v. Glucksberg, 1997, p. 789). Whatever
her motivations, OConnor did not want to be pinned down. She wanted to
make her mark through individuated fact-specific decisions of limited reach,
decisions that would make her the focal point of subsequent cases.
Without a solid coalition of five ideologically simpatico justices, the
Rehnquist Courts civil and individual rights legacy was inconsequential.
The Court did not make a single move that would radically change or
unsettle existing constitutional doctrine (Friedman, 2002, p. 146). The
Rehnquist Courts federalism revival, for the most part, tells a similar story.
Unlike civil and individual rights, the Rehnquist Court did pursue doctrinal
innovations on federalism (Merrill, 2003, p. 58486). More than that, com-
mentators initially labeled a group consisting of Justices OConnor, Kennedy,
Scalia, Thomas, and Chief Justice Rehnquist as the federalism five. But the
federalism revival, ultimately, was more bust than boom; the Court over-
turned only one significant precedent and, ultimately, backed away from its
campaign to limit congressional power under the Commerce Clause and
section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. In cases decided in 2003, 2004,
and 2005, four of the five so-called federalism five distinguished earlier
Rehnquist Court rulings in order to back up congressional power. The only
justice to consistently vote in favor of limits on Congress was Clarence
Thomas.
The failure of the federalism revival is tied to the simple fact that feder-
alism-qua-federalism was never a core issue to the so-called federalism five.
Presidents Reagan and Bush never used federalism as a measuring stick
when screening candidates; the Senate paid no mind to federalism during its
confirmation hearings. The focus, instead, was on first-order policy issues
race, privacy, religion. Unlike the New Deal era (where Court limits on
congressional power frustrated Roosevelts pursuit of a fundamental
100 Judges and Human Behavior
restructuring of the regulatory state), elected officials neither pushed for nor
resisted Rehnquist Court efforts to place some federalism-based limits on
congressional power (Devins, 2004). Against this backdrop, it is not sur-
prising that a core group could not form around this low salience issue and,
in so doing, invalidate laws that they otherwise supported.
For our purposes, the Rehnquist Court highlights the various roadblocks
that stand in the way of group formation on the Supreme Court. Groups form
around core issues and, in part, that requires the appointment and confirma-
tion of justices who are precommitted to the pursuit of some agenda.
Otherwise, median or swing justices will resist banding together with
other justicesfor these swing justices are likely to place a high value on
power and/or their image. Indeed, the Reagan administrations embrace of
the social conservative agenda may well have boomeranged, in that, swing
justicesconsistent with reactancefelt that their independence was threa-
tened by the administrations assault on the Court.
Conclusion
Social psychology provides important insights into group formation on the
Supreme Court. In particular, unlike political science models, which emphasize
the pursuit of legal and policy preferences, social psychology highlights the
importance of group processes and how issues of power and reputation also
contribute to group formation on the Supreme Court. In so doing, social
psychology suggests that political scientists overemphasize the median justice
benchmark. When a majority coalition forms, intragroup dynamics define the
scope of the Courts ruling. Those dynamics reflect group preferences, not
the preferences of the median justice. And when there is no majority coalition,
the median justice may well be influenced by concerns of power and reputa-
tionconcerns that may lead the median justice to vote in ways that do not
necessarily reflect her true legal policy preferences. Through limited case studies
on the New Deal and Rehnquist Courts, there is reason to think that justices
like other humansoperate within the boundaries of group dynamics. That, of
course, is not to denigrate the profoundly important role of legal policy
preferences. Justices, according to the social psychology model, will never cast
votes that do not jibe with their core beliefs. At the same time, the dominant
political science models offer a too simplistic picture of Supreme Court deci-
sion making.
Note
Thanks to David Klein, Greg Mitchell, Lee Epstein, Larry Baum, and especially John
Nezlek.
Part II
JUDGING AS SPECIALIZED ACTIVITY
This page intentionally left blank
7
Is There a Psychology of Judging?
Frederick Schauer
103
104 Judging as Specialized Activity
authorities from the way in which the man on the Clapham omnibus7 deals
with similar inputs into and constraints on his decision-making processes.
And if it is a mistake to move too quickly from what we know about how lay
people perform certain tasks to conclusions about how judges perform some
of those same tasks, it certainly would be a mistake to draw conclusions about
how judges perform a range of judge-specific tasks from what we have found
about how lay people perform quite different tasks.
Thus, one questiona question and not a conclusionis whether the
experience of studying to be a lawyer and then of practicing law causes
decision making in law, especially about legal (as opposed to factual) matters,
to diverge in deep and cognitively substantial ways from the decision making
of human beings who do not possess such training and experience.8 And a
further question is whether those who self-select to be judges, who are selected
as judges, and who have the experience of serving as judges make decisions
differently from nonjudge lawyers, thus causing further gaps between judicial
decision making and the decision making even of similarly trained and
experienced people holding different roles.9 Consequently, there are hypoth-
eses worthy of investigation about whether in law-focused decision making
there are divides between lawyers and people in general, between judges and
nonjudge lawyers, and consequently even larger divides between judges and
people in general.
Indeed it is likely that multiple phenomena are at work. Self-selection
into law, subsequent legal training, subsequent legal experience, self-selection
into judging, and then finally serving in the judicial role may all interact with
each other to produce considerable differences between how judges and lay
people reason and decide. To the extent that this is so, the interaction among
legal training, legal acculturation, legal experience, and the judicial role may
even generate process- and not just content-based differences between the
cognitive mechanisms of judges and those of nonjudge humanity. If so, there
may be differences, at least with respect to some highly important judicial
tasks, between how judges and lay people think and not merely differences in
what they think about.
The battery of possibilities offered in the previous paragraphs is no more
than an array of testable hypotheses. If even some of these hypotheses turn out
to be true, however, then there actually may be a genuine psychology of
judging. But if on the other hand these hypothesized differences between
judges and lay people turn out not to exist, and if instead the assumptions and
premises of judge as human being lying behind most of the existing research
are sound, then research into the psychology of judging will be an interesting
application of larger psychological issues, but will not in any fundamental way
constitute a discrete area of inquiry. If the most important or only determi-
nant of judicial decision-making characteristics is the fact that the judge is
human, after all, then a psychology of judging will be little different from a
psychology of dentistry or a psychology of plumbing. It would be interesting
and possibly even important to know what psychology could teach us about
106 Judging as Specialized Activity
how dentists and plumbers think, but the application of research findings
about human beings generally to the human beings who fill these socially vital
roles is a long way from saying that there is a psychology of dentistry or
plumbing. Perhaps the psychological dimensions of judging are different
from those of dentistry or plumbing, but we will not know that unless we
depart from the assumption that what we know about people is necessarily
applicable to judges. And because I suspect that there might be more to the
psychology of judging than there is to the psychology of dentistry or
plumbing,10 and because I suspect as well that there are reasons to believe
that legal and judicial attributes may cause judicial decision making to depart
in relevant ways from the decision making of lay people, my aim in this paper
is to examine in a preliminary and nonempirical wayhypothesis offering
but not hypothesis testingwhat a genuine psychology of judging might
look like, and why, most of the existing literature on the psychology of
judging notwithstanding, we ought to take this possibility seriously.11
often mandate a result other than the one that is optimally fair or maximally
wise, all things considered, in the particular casea result that will some-
times be wrong for the particular dispute (Sherwin, 1999). It may seem
unfair on the balance of all reasons to deprive a person of property (United
States v. Locke, 1985) or a place on a ballot (Hunter v. Norman, described in
Schauer, 1988a) just because he has missed a statutory deadline for under-
standable, innocent, and ultimately inconsequential reasons, but the law
characteristically even if not universally enforces the literal meaning of
authoritative language even when such an action produces a bad outcome
in the particular case (Manning, 2003; Schauer, 1992). And it may seem
equally unfair to take the existence of clear precedent as commanding a
suboptimal result, especially from the vantage point of a decision maker
who thinks the precedent mistaken, but following even a precedent perceived
to be erroneous is what, under the traditional understanding, the law expects
its decision makers to do.21
The second-order reasoning I describe here is not about what is, but
instead about what to do. The law must frequently engage in factual inquiry to
determine who fired the gun, how much toxic waste was discharged into the
river, whether someone was in possession of inside information when they
purchased a quantity of securities, or whether the driver of some car had
consumed alcohol prior to being involved in an accident. But in the law such
factual determinations are typically precursors to a judgment about what the
law requires to be done on the basis of these facts; and what the law requires to
be done may be something other than that which a nonlegal decision maker
would decide, all things considered, should be done. So although the legal
system engages in factual inquiry, it is precisely in moving from factual
inquiry to action-producing consequence that legal reasoning potentially
differs in fundamental ways from the reasoning of other action-producing
agents. These other agents, we typically think, are focused on producing the
right decision for this decision making event, but if the characteristic deci-
sion-making modality of law is different from the decision-making modal-
ities of other domains, than legal reasoning and decision making may be
different as well. Legal reasoning, on this widespread account, is artificial
not only because of the way in which it is deliberately not focused on reaching
the best for just this case, but also because decisions having legal consequences
differ for just this reason from the practical reasoning in which nonlawyers
ordinarily engage.
At the very least, the contrast between the traditional and Realist
accounts of legal reasoning suggests that a research agenda could be aimed
at answering the precise question of the extent to which, if at all, judges
actually do engage in second-order reasoning and actually do refrain from
reaching what they believe to be the correct outcome in this case because of
the perceived (or actual) constraints of precedent, rule, or authoritative
source. Moreover, such a research agenda need not be limited to examining
the hypothesis that judges engage in second-order reasoning. It could also
usefully test the hypothesis that judicial second-order reasoning is substan-
tially different from, more frequent than, or more effective than the second-
order reasoning of nonjudge decision makers, even assuming that nonjudge
decision makers engage in second-order reasoning at all.
Even the foregoing sketch of a research program is far too crude. In
addition to attempting to control for intelligence, education, motivation, and
other attributes that judges likely possess to a greater degree than the popula-
tion at large, such a program would attempt to disaggregate the components
of second-order legal reasoning in order to determine whether there was a gap
between judges and lay decision makers for each of those components.
When judges are expected to make a decision consistent with a previous
decision with which they disagreethe central case of decision according to
precedentwill they follow precedent and reach what they think is the wrong
result more often than ordinary people assigned the same task? If judges are
told that the only sources on which they may rely are part of an artificially
constricted array of sources that in this instance might support an erroneous
result (Schauer, 2004c), will they limit their attention to this suboptimizing
and error-producing (from their lights) array to a greater extent than the
nonjudges? If commanded to follow a bad rule or a good rule which in this
instance produces an unfortunate outcome, will judges more than others
simply follow the rule and swallow the unfortunate outcome? And if
instructed to refrain from doing the right thing because doing the right
thing is in someone elses jurisdiction or is someone elses responsibility,27
will judges more than others remain passive in the face of an opportunity to
do the right thing, or will they, like most others, treat jurisdictional and
similar limitations as inconsequential?28
Even if such research were to indicate that judges really were different
from lay people for some or all of these tasks, additional research would still
be necessary to determine whether it was simply legal training that produced
the difference, or whether it was something about the role of judge as judge.
We can imagine a research design that might, for example, assign similar tasks
to judges, practicing lawyers, and law students, in order to determine whether
an identified difference between judges and lay people was explained by some
difference between judges and lawyers, or was explained instead by a differ-
ence between judges and lawyers and (advanced) law students, on the one
hand, and those without legal training, on the other. And even more fine
grained research could attempt to locate differences even among classes of
Is There a Psychology of Judging? 113
what expert fact-finders do that novice fact-finders do not, just as we could ask
what expert judges do that novice judges do not. But if we are interested in
testing the hypothesis that there is a psychology of judging that differs from the
psychology of decision making simpliciter, then we want to see whether there
are some tasks that judges perform differently just because they are judges. We
know from the existing research on judging that in some tasksmany aspects
of fact-finding, principallyjudges do differ less from nonjudges and non-
lawyers than the conventional wisdom has appeared to suppose. But to take
these findings, important as they are, as answering the central question about
the psychology of judging is like imagining that because auto mechanics
approach the finances of their own small business in the same way that
psychiatrists approach the finances of their own small businesses that auto
mechanics are importantly similar to psychiatrists. That the two are similar
with respect to accounting says nothing about whether they are similar with
respect to fixing cars and fixing heads, and similarly the discovery that judges
and jurors (or people generally) are similar with respect to fact-finding skirts
the question whether there is something else that judges do for which their
training and expertise might actually produce important differences.
If I am right that an important component of judging is something other
than fact-findingarguably true for trial judges and self-evident for appellate
judgesthen we can understand the importance of focusing on law-finding,
law-applying, law-interpreting, and, yes, law-making, for these are a large part
of the judicial task. But when judges perform these tasks, do they perform
them in the same way that those without legal or judicial training or experi-
ence would approach them, which is what many of the Realists argued, or do
they employ a different skill set, to use an infelicitous and fashionable but not
inappropriate term from contemporary management-speak? When it comes
to tasks other than fact-finding, do judges think like human beings, or like
lawyers, or like judges? Addressing this question should be one of the central
items on a research agenda for the psychology of judging, but it is, surpris-
ingly, an item that up to now has been almost completely absent.
Conclusion
Jerome Frank understood the traditional claim about legal reasoning, but he
argued that judges were psychologically unable to do what the traditional
theory demanded.31 Frank is treated nowadays as a bit idiosyncratic, but the
psychological lens through which he viewed judging points to the importance
of distinguishing three questions about second-order reasoning. The first, the
answer to which is embodied in Franks own point of view, is whether people
are naturally particularistic. When engaged in decision-making tasks, do
people just because of the makeup of the human mind think in terms of
this task, thus being psychologically averse to making the wrong decision on
this occasion in the service of larger or more distant goals?
Is There a Psychology of Judging? 115
import. But before we can intelligently decide what judges should do, we need
to see both what they are doing and what they can do. This inquiry can be
usefully informed by serious empirical inquiry into the psychology of judging,
but little progress will be made even on this dimension until the research
agenda begins to take seriously the possibility that there might actually be a
psychology of judging, a possibility that is surprisingly absent from almost all
of the existing literature.
Notes
An earlier version of this chapter was presented at the Workshop on the Psychology
of Judging, University of Virginia, Charlottesville, Virginia, March 2931, 2007.
I am grateful for the comments of the participants on that occasion, for thoughtful
and challenging written comments from Barbara A. Spellman and Dan Simon, and
for research support from the Harvard Law School and the Joan Shorenstein Center
on the Press, Politics and Public Policy, Harvard University.
1. For a useful analysis of the research that is genuinely focused on judges and
judging, see (Robinson & Spellman, 2005).
2. There are numerous logistical and ethical impediments to research using real
judges as experimental subjects, and thus the conclusion that nonjudge and
nonlawyer research subjects are representative of judges is facilitated by the ease
of locating the former and the obstacles to doing serious experimental work on
the latter.
3. Fact-finding is not to be confused with fact-locating or fact-discovering. Fact-
finding is the legal term of art for determining what actually happened based
solely on the evidence presented in court by the parties.
4. Indeed, the preoccupation with the jury in much of the psychological research is
itself curious in light of the fact that the institution of the jury does not much
exist in civil law countries, is not used outside of criminal cases (with the
occasional exception of libel trials) in any common law country other than
the United States, and is a rapidly declining institution even for criminal cases
in the United States and elsewhere (Guthrie, Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2001;
Schauer, 2006b).
5. On the implications for social science research of the distinction between the
tasks typically performed by trial judges and those typically performed by
appellate judges, see (Rowland & Carp, 1996).
6. The statement in the text is not intended to express even the slightest sympathy
with the hoary but misguided cavil that experiments on university under-
graduates are of limited value in learning about the behavior of people who
are not undergraduates. In the absence of identifiable and germane differences
between undergraduates and people in general, there is no good reason to
doubt the generalizability of findings about undergraduates to conclusions
about people as a whole. But when we are drawing conclusions about the
decision-making characteristics of individuals who are in theory specially
trained to make decisions of a certain kindas are judgesit is far more
appropriate to question whether research using people without that special
Is There a Psychology of Judging? 117
training can tell us much about the way in which people with special training
make the very decisions for which they are supposedly specially trained and for
which they are specially selected by virtue of possessing the requisite training
and skills.
7. The man on the Clapham omnibus being the quaint British equivalent of the
American reasonable man (Hall v. Brooklands Racing Club).
8. Those who become lawyers may self-select, or may be selected, on the basis of
their possession of attributes that are relatively rare in the general population
but that are not only germane to success as a lawyer, but are also germane to
success as a judge even among the class of lawyers.
9. Or it may be that the causal mechanism operates in a different direction, with
lawyers being selected for the judiciary, or self-selecting into the judiciary,
because they possess skills or proclivities to forms of reasoning and decision
making that are different from those of the mine-run of practicing lawyers.
10. This says nothing about the respective abilities or intelligence of judges, den-
tists, and plumbers. One need not be smarter (or dumber) than the average of
humanity in order to engage in a cognitively specialized task.
11. It is worth emphasizing that nothing I say here denies that judges share some or
perhaps even many decision making psychological characteristics with ordinary
people (Simon, 1998, 2002, 2004), and that many of those shared characteristics
are useful in understanding what judges do. My concern is that by focusing so
heavily on the shared characteristics, researchers have slighted the nonshared
characteristics to the detriment of a fuller understanding of what judges do.
Tiger Woods and I both play golf, and I am reasonably sure that Woods and
I share some number of decision making pathologies on the golf course, such as
exaggerating the probability of making (for our skill level) low probability
shots, or taking the most recent (and thus most cognitively available) shots as
more representative of the array of outcomes on shots of that variety than they
in fact are. But to focus only on these shared characteristics and to ignore the
numerous ways in which Woods and I differ as golfers, mentally as well as
physically, is to ignore something seemingly quite important. Without investi-
gating the ways in which judges might be able to do things that lay people
cannot, we run the risk of overgeneralizing from the ways in which judges
assuredly have decision-making characteristics they share with lay people.
12. Outside of North America, the study of law takes place largely at the under-
graduate level, although additional and postgraduate law study is common.
A potentially valuable research project, although not my focus here, would be to
examine whether studying law from the age of eighteen or nineteen, and in
place of some other undergraduate specialization, produces a significant dif-
ference in reasoning and decision making from that which exists in those who
do not commence the serious study of law until at least the age of twenty-two,
and who already have as undergraduates studied another field.
13. And if they do, they shouldnt.
14. To forestall a potential objection, I signal here (and address at somewhat greater
length below, and see also Schauer, 2007) that I do not take the use of analogy
and the constraints of precedent as being especially similar. Lawyers use analogy
frequently, but so do other professionals and most lay people. Feeling obligated
to follow a previous decision that one believes to be erroneous, however, is
arguably far less prevalent outside of law than in, and may thus comprise part of
118 Judging as Specialized Activity
fellow travelers advanced a cluster of different claims all in the name of Legal
Realism, it is uncontroversial that the particular part of Realism I stress in the
text is at least among the positions advocated by some of the more prominent
Realists.
25. It is fashionable these days to marginalize Franks contribution to Realism
because of his belief that the judges personal idiosyncrasies were a significant
determinant of judicial outcomes (Dagan, 2007; Leiter, 1997). But although
Franks (and Hutchesons) views about the source of the judges decision may be
unrepresentative of so-called mainstream Realism, he remains a seminal figure
for the view that the judges determination of the right outcome precedes the
judges consultation of formal legal doctrinal sources, and also for the view that
judicial decision is substantially particularistic, both being central tenets of the
broad Realist program.
26. For a modern and sophisticated version of this form of Realism, see Kennedy
(1986).
27. See Blanchflower v. Blanchflower (2003), concluding that same-sex adultery
ought to constitute grounds for at-fault divorce, but that such a change was
for the legislature and not the courts.
28. Consider the question of federalism. Although lawyers and judges spend much
time wrestling with the respective jurisdictional competences of the federal
government and the states, there is little indication that either the public or
the political world that caters to that public takes the principles of federalism as
constituting an independent second-order constraint on either the states or the
federal governments adopting what the public believes to be a desirable first-
order policy.
29. I bracket here the important debates about whether patterns of reasoning falling
short of optimal or perfect rationality are better understood as desirable
adaptive strategies (Gigerenzer, 2000; Gigerenzer & Selten, 2001) or instead as
potentially correctable errors whose correction would, in general, be desirable
(Kahneman & Tversky, 1981, 1984; Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982).
30. For an introduction to the psychological literature, see Ericsson et al. (2006)
and Chi, Farr, & Glaser (1998).
31. It is interesting that when Frank became a federal judge, a role he occupied from
1941 until his death in 1957, he wrote opinions that hardly differed in style from
those of other judges. Much better examples of Realist judging can be found in
the opinions of Justice William O. Douglas.
32. This is a good place to point out the important difference, off-hand remarks in
the psychology analogy literature notwithstanding, between analogical rea-
soning and the legal constraint of precedent. When people, including lawyers
(Levi, 1948; Weinreb, 2005), seek to persuade others, or seek guidance in
making a decision, they often rely on analogies. They think it is good to take
some action now because it is similar to some action in the past that has worked
out successfully, or they think it wise to avoid some decision because the
circumstances resemble circumstances of the past. But in such cases the deci-
sion-maker is using the analogy (Spellman & Holyoak, 1996) to help reach the
right decision now. The analogy is a tool, and in theory a friend. The constraint
of precedent in law, however, which is not coextensive with lawyers use of
analogical reasoning, is more foe than friend. Having concluded that the right
thing to do now is f, the lawyer or judge will sometimes find that f is precluded
120 Judging as Specialized Activity
by some previous decision, often a decision that the present judge thinks
mistaken. But insofar as the constraint of precedent actually constrains
(which it likely does outside of hard Supreme Court cases far more than it
does in the Supreme Court (Segal & Spaeth, 1996, 2002), then the judge is not
looking for the analogy that helps, but instead seeking, often unsuccessfully, to
avoid the analogy that hurts. Whether such constraint by precedent is desirable
is itself debatable, as is the empirical question about its frequency in legal
decision making. But the importance of these questions should not lead us to
think that being bound by a similar but erroneous decision from the past is
similar to choosing to be guided or persuaded by analogous circumstances from
an earlier time (Schauer, 2008).
8
Features of Judicial Reasoning
Emily Sherwin
121
122 Judging as Specialized Activity
to suppress reason in order to give authoritative effect to rules. How judges can
achieve the mental state necessary for this purposea mental state consisting of
abstinence from reasoningis one of the great psychological mysteries of law.
What I say in this essay is nothing new. In particular, the analysis of rule-
based decision making I provide is much indebted to Schauers excellent work
on the subject. Nor do I provide independent psychological insights: I write as
a legal theorist without expertise in the field of cognitive science.
Rule Making
One prominent institutional circumstance of judicial decision making is that
judges make rules of law as they adjudicate disputes. Judges may decide cases
124 Judging as Specialized Activity
fairly narrowly, but in a legal system such as ours, in which judges commonly
explain their decisions in opinions, some degree of generalization is unavoid-
able and generality leads to rules.3 Moreover, in a system in which the out-
comes of adjudication are accessible to the public, judicial decisions are
studied by an audience of potential actors, who naturally generalize from
past decisions to probable legal treatment of their own activities.
One might imagine a system in which judges say nothing about their
decisions and the conclusions they reach are understood to have no prece-
dential effect. Only legislative rules would have implications for future deci-
sions. In our own legal system, however, this is not the case. The public
expects a fairly high degree of consistency in judicial decision making over
time and judges respond to this expectation by recognizing, to some extent,
the authority of prior decisions. Moreover, the publics expectation of con-
sistency has social value, because it enables the members of society to coordi-
nate their actions and to treat controversies as settled (Postema, 1982,
pp. 172186; Raz, 1986, pp. 4950; Hurd, 1999, pp. 214221).
Thus, implicitly or explicitly, judges announce rules of decision as they
decide cases. It follows that the complete set of reasons for or against a
particular decision includes the future effects of the decisional rules on
which it rests. To reach a fully reasoned decision in any case, the judge
must generalize from the specific problem at hand to the class of problems
governed by the operative decisional rule.
Research on cognitive bias, as described above, is pertinent to this aspect of
second-order reasoning. Assessing the future effects of a decisional rule typi-
cally requires a calculation of statistical probability over a range of possible
cases, some of which may be remote from the case before the court. At the same
time, the judge must attend to the immediate task of achieving a fair outcome
for the parties to the current dispute. These simultaneous demands on the
judges attention implicate at least two of the biases documented in cognitive
studies: the availability bias and the affect bias, which lead reasoners to err in
assessing probabilities when their attention is focused on salient or emotionally
charged facts (Devins & Meese, 2005; Rachlinski, 2006; Schauer, 2006a). As a
consequence of these biases, the facts of current cases are likely to appear more
representative than they are of the class of cases covered by a proposed decision
rule, causing judges to miscalculate the overall effects of rules.4
Rule Following
Following rules is more complicated analytically, and perhaps psychologi-
cally as well. Suppose a judge is called on to decide a case that falls
indisputably within the terms of a rule announced by a prior court. One
possible approach for the judge is what Schauer (1991) has termed rule-
sensitive particularism. Simple particularism is the process of deciding
what outcome is best in a particular case, all things considered. The reasoning
involved is ordinary reasoning (empirical observation, induction, and moral
Features of Judicial Reasoning 125
not the ideal judicial response to rules. This may seem odd: rules are blunt,
and as a consequence are likely to require the wrong result in some of the cases
they cover. In a world of perfect reasoners, therefore, it might be best if rule-
followers were rule-sensitive particularists who sometimes decided not to
follow applicable rules. Judges, however, are not perfect reasoners: they lack
the perfect information required for perfect reasoning5 and, as noted, they are
subject to cognitive biases that may cause them to systematically undervalue
the long-term costs of deviating from rules. Consequently, rule-sensitive
particularists will sometimes deviate from rules when they should not. In a
community of rule-sensitive particularists, each judge will anticipate that
some other judges will miscalculate in this way, and accordingly will discount
the benefits of the rule. Each such discount, by each rule-sensitive particu-
larist judge, means a corresponding decrease in the judges estimate of the
harm that will result from a decision to defect from the rule. Ultimately, the
rule has no value at all, and rule-sensitive particularism collapses into simple
particularism.6
Rule sensitive particularism may be more meaningful when some judges
consistently follow rules. Yet it is still less than ideal from the rule makers
point of view. Imagine that within a given legal system, some judges are rule-
sensitive particularists and others are rule followers. In this situation, a
decision to deviate from a rule has adverse consequences that the rule-
sensitive particularist must take into account. Specifically, other judges
who observe the deviation will know that not all judges are consistent
rule-followers. As a result, rule-followers may change their attitude, and
rule-sensitive particularists may discount the benefits of the rule. These
possibilities give the decision maker a reason to be cautious about deviating
from the rule. Nevertheless, although rule-sensitive particularist judges now
have some reason to follow the rule when it produces an outcome they
believe to be wrong, they may still err in calculating the balance of harms,
and, because of cognitive bias, their errors will tend systematically to favor
deviation from the rule.
Because rule-sensitive particularism is unstable in this way, a rational
legal rule maker would prefer that judges follow rules according to their
terms. A well-designed rule, consistently applied, will prevent errors of judg-
ment more often than it generates errors of overinclusion.7 From the point of
view of rule makers, therefore, a rule applied without reflection is preferable
to case-by-case judicial reasoning, even if judges are sensitive to the value of
rules. At the same time, when a judge believes that, in a particular case, the
harm to substantive values from following the rule is greater than the harm to
rule-based values from disregarding the rule, the only rational course is to
disregard the rule. The result is a logically unbridgeable gap between the way
in which rational rule makers would want judges to approach rules and the
approach that is rational for judges.8
This leads to the second possible judicial response to rules, which is to
follow them without further reflection about the justification, or lack of
Features of Judicial Reasoning 127
justification, for the particular results they require. Legal rules, on this
approach, operate as the exclusive reasons for judicial decision in cases to
which they apply (Raz, 1979, 1986).9 If the terms of the rule call for a certain
result, that result is correct.
In ordinary life, rules appear to function in this way, at least at times. For
example, we may set schedules for ourselves to fend off procrastination,
although the schedules will never control our actions if we pause to think
about whether the time designated for each action is in fact the best time to act
(Fumerton, 1990, pp. 178188). Somehow, we manage not to think, and thus
to follow the schedule. Judicial rule-following, in the manner necessary to
avoid the pitfalls of rule-sensitive particularism, is similar in nature. Judges
may in fact follow rules, but they can do so only by abstaining from thought
about what is best, all things considered.
Thus, rule-following in the true sense presents a psychological enigma: in
what circumstances, and by what processes, do human decision makers
suspend their powers of reason and instead defer to authority?10 This is not
a phenomenon unique to adjudication: it occurs in daily life when people
follow nonlegal rules, and it occurs whenever nonjudges follow legal rules.
Nor is it something judges are especially likely to be good at: there is no reason
to think that selection (or self-selection) as a judge corresponds to a heigh-
tened capacity to suspend reason. Yet, if in fact there are psychological
mechanisms that permit blind rule-following, they have special social sig-
nificance in the context of law because they enable judges to give serious effect
to legal rules.
A further point is that when judges follow rules without reflection, they
must suspend reason in a special way. Judges typically do not decide legal
questions in the abstract; they resolve live disputes and enter judgments that
penalize or impose liability on the losing parties. This means that when a rule
calls for a result that the judge deems to be wrong in the case before the court,
the judge not only must decide the case against his best judgment, but also
must impose a penalty on a party he believes has acted correctly and does not
deserve to suffer harm (Hurd, 1992, 1999, pp. 253293; Alexander & Sherwin,
2001, pp. 7886). Even when the judge believes the result of the rule is correct,
enforcing the rule may sometimes entail penalizing a party who did not act
culpably, but simply misjudged. Thus, following rules according to their
terms requires judges to suppress both reason and moral censorship of their
own actions toward others. This aspect of adjudication adds to the signifi-
cance of the normative questions about rule following. We have reason to
prefer that judges enforce legal rules as written, but we also have reason to
question the morality of full enforcement of rules.
Assuming that blind rule-following is at least sometimes desirable from a
social point of view, a further psychological question is whether the capacity
to suppress reason can be taught or cultivated. Research indicates that to
some extent, reasoners can learn to curb some forms of cognitive bias. The
studies conducted by Guthrie, Rachlinski, and Wistrich (2001) confirm that
128 Judging as Specialized Activity
this holds true for judges: certain common types of cognitive bias are less
pronounced in experienced judges addressing legal problems. It seems unli-
kely, however, that absence of reason is a mental state that reasoners could
develop deliberately in themselves. By definition, abstaining from reasoning is
an unthinking, if not unconscious, process. It is possible that reasoners could
become accustomed by force of habit to reaching decisions without reflection,
but it is difficult to see how a propensity to decide without reflection could be
instilled in a reasoner with the reasoners conscious assent.
I have mentioned two second order judicial tasks that play an important
part in the psychology of judging. First, judges must formulate rules of
decision and calculate the effects of those rules will have when applied to
future cases. In making this calculation, judges are subject to cognitive biases
that can lead them to undervalue statistical probabilities. Second, judges are
expected to treat established legal rules as authoritative. To give authoritative
effect to rules, judges must decide cases mechanically, without reflecting on
the relationship between the outcomes the rules require and the values the
rules are supposed to promote.
The states of mind necessary to perform these two judicial tasks effec-
tively are quite different. Designing sound rules is a highly deliberative
process involving empirical observation, induction, and moral reasoning.
Judges engaged in rule making must, among other things, remain alert to
background probabilities and guard against the biases that might prevent
them from accurately assessing the future effects of potential rules. Thus, for
the purpose of rule making, the more judges know about their own psycho-
logical proclivities the better they will do. When judges are called on to follow
rules, the opposite is true. To follow rules consistently, they must suppress
their own judgment about the outcomes of the cases before them. The more
judges reflect on the process of decision, the more difficult this will be.
The tasks of rule making and rule following are distinct. Judicial rule
making, and the empirical and inductive reasoning it entails, come into play
when no rule applies. Rule following, of course, is reserved for cases governed
by rules. Accordingly, there is ordinarily no need to perform both these
functions at once. Yet, judges must frequently shift from one mode of
decision making to the other from case to case, or even in the course of a
single litigation. This will not be easy: rationality and self-awareness, which
conduce to good rule making, are naturally at odds with a habit of unre-
flective obedience that will enable judges to follow rules.
A further complication is that if a legal system hopes both to maintain
effective rules and to command public respect, it must provide some relief
from rules. Rules may be misconceived, and even well-conceived rules may
become obsolete as conditions change. Legislatures can intervene to repeal
unsound rules, but for various reasons they may fail to respond. When this
Features of Judicial Reasoning 129
occurs, the only avenue of relief is judges own power to overrule judicial
rules.
In our own legal system, the power of judges to overrule precedent rules
established in prior judicial decisions is widely recognized. Ideally, however,
judges should overrule rules only when the rules are unjustified as rules.11
Rules are justified as rules if their benefits (settlement, coordination, and
preemption of faulty judgment) outweigh their costs (errors of overinclu-
sion) over the range of cases to which they apply. When a rule passes this test,
it is best, from a societal perspective, that judges leave the rule in place and
enforce it according to its terms, even when they believe that a particular
outcome of the rule is a mistake. When a rule does not pass the test of net
benefit over the full range of its applications, it should be overruled.
The difficulty is that when rules are justified, judges must combine the
two types of mental tasks I have described to solve a single legal problem. To
determine whether a rule is justified as a rule, the judge must calculate the
future consequences of the rule. This requires both careful reasoning and
attention to cognitive biases that may make a current bad outcome appear
more representative than it is (Schauer, 2006a, 906912). Then, if the balance
of error favors the rule, the same judge must cease reasoning and follow the
rule, whether or not the judge believes the outcome is correct. This is a
difficult psychological feat.
Conclusion
The authoritative nature of law generates some psychological puzzles that,
although not limited to law, take on special social importance in the context
of adjudication. One set of questions relates to the rule-making role of judges:
what sorts of errors are judges prone to make in designing or evaluating rules
of common law and what mechanisms, if any, can a legal system use to control
their errors? A second set of questions relates to judicial compliance with
rules: do judges follow legal rules against their own best judgment, and if so,
how do they disengage from the process of deliberating about the relationship
between purposes and outcomes of rules? The mystery deepens when the
functions of rule making and rule following are closely juxtaposed.
Of course, theoretical analysis of the type presented here can at best
provide a map of the problem. As Schauer observes, the challenge is to find
some means of empirical access to legal reasoning. Judicial opinions provide
an immense source of information, but as Legal Realists are happy to point
out, they are written after their authors reach decisions. Opinions also may be
products of negotiation that do not reflect any single individuals process of
decision. Experiments involving judges may be more promising, but they
require heroic efforts and even then it may be difficult to recreate the moral
pressures of adjudication in an experimental setting.
130 Judging as Specialized Activity
Notes
Thanks to Jeffrey J. Rachlinski and Frederick Schauer for helpful comments.
1. For present purposes, I am adopting a broad definition of empirical reasoning
as the process of reaching conclusions about the world through observation or
experiment. A cautionary point is that empirical observations may incorporate
elements of induction, and both empirical and inductive judgments may be
intertwined with normative judgment. There is no perfect line of demarcation
between judgments of fact and judgments of law or between empirical and
moral reasoning.
2. For explanations of the method of reasoning to wide reflective equilibrium, see
Rawls (1971, pp. 1421, 4353, 578582) and Daniels (1979).
3. For discussion of the generality of rules, see Schauer (1991, pp. 1734).
4. Studies focusing specifically on judges, while they do not address the particular
problem of rule making, confirm that judges are not immune to these biases.
See Guthrie, Rachlinski, and Wistrich (2001, pp. 807811) .
5. Part of the problem is lack of coordination: even a very wise judge cannot know
with certainty what other, less wise, judges will decide and how many errors
they will make.
6. For extended analysis of this problem, see Alexander and Sherwin (2001,
pp. 6168).
7. Of course, rule makers can also make mistakes, and judicial rule makers are
susceptible to mistakes for the reasons mentioned above. My analysis, however,
assumes sound rules. Overruling unsound rules is a separate, although not
unrelated, question.
8. Larry Alexander and I have written in considerable detail about this gap,
concluding that it cannot be reasoned away. See Alexander and Sherwin
(2001, pp. 5695). For similar analyses, see Alexander (1991); Schauer (1991,
pp. 128134).
9. For an analytical (as opposed to psychological) argument against the view that
rules have an exclusionary effect, see Hurd (1999, pp. 6294).
10. Stanley Milgrams (1974) famous experiments demonstrate that people cer-
tainly are capable of obeying authority, either contrary to reason or without
engaging in reason. Interestingly, there are indications that Milgrams subjects
did not follow authority thoughtlessly, but rather struggled with the problem
(Milgram, 1974, pp. 4143).
11. For extended discussion of this point, see Alexander & Sherwin (2008,
pp. 6163, 115).
9
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism: Pitfalls and
Opportunities in the Psychology of Judging
Dan Simon
131
132 Judging as Specialized Activity
the laboratory, which are starkly different from worldly human practices in real
life. The concern pertains to the external validity of experimental findings, that
is, their generalizability to settings outside the laboratory. Psychologists, who
are ever so sensitive to situational effects on human behavior (e.g., Lewin, 1935;
Ross & Nisbett, 1991), are the first to acknowledge that results obtained in any
given study could have come out quite differently under different variations of
their experimental design. It is not hard to see why critics question the relevance
of findings obtained by testing a relatively small group of lay subjects (say, sixty
psychology undergraduates at a midwestern university), performing hypothe-
tical tasks, with limited knowledge, and under specific instructions.
Psychological studies have been criticized for the nonrepresentativeness
of the subject samples, the artificiality of the experimental setting, the dis-
connectedness from institutional contexts, the glossing over of individual
differences, the lack of appropriate incentives, the inconsequentiality of the
tasks, and more (e.g., Konecni & Ebbesen, 1986; Mitchell, 2002; Sears, 1986;
Yuille & Cutshall, 1986). These reservations warrant a healthy dose of skepti-
cism toward even cautious applications of experimental findings to real world
situations (see Mitchell, 2003). This concern seems doubly warranted when
applying the findings to specialized domains such as judicial decision making.
Concerns over the external validity of psychological research appear to
have animated Fred Schauers discerning and provocative essay in this
volume (ch. 7). The core of his essay is a call for a unique and genuine
psychology of judging. The proposal starts with an appealing proposition
that a psychology of judging ought to be what it claims to bean examina-
tion of judging, as performed by judges. Explanations that rely on cognitive
processes that are performed also by nonjudges and in nonjudicial domains
might make for an interesting application of psychological research, but they
do not constitute a discrete area of inquiry. Merely applying basic findings
to the work of dentists and plumbers is a long way from saying that there is a
psychology of dentistry or plumbing.
Schauer proposes to distinguish decision making by judges from decision
making by other people, even lawyers, for the same reason that one ought not
to equate the mathematical reasoning of a Harvard mathematics professor
with that of ordinary folks balancing their checkbooks. He contends also that
the field ought to concentrate on decision making in domains that are unique
to judging, such as finding, interpreting, and making law. Even if auto
mechanics and psychiatrists approach the finances of their small business in
similar fashions, it does not follow that they do the same when they fix cars or
provide psychiatric care. The underlying intuition is that judicial training,
acculturation, experience, and role may lead to deep cognitive effects that
generate process- and not just content-based differences between the cogni-
tive mechanisms of judges and those of nonjudge humanity.
Schauers proposal is constructive in that it actually suggests an experi-
mental project to test his proposition. The central hypothesis focuses on the
role of second-order reasoning in judicial decision making. Second-order
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 133
reasoning stands for higher order decision rules that are supposed to trump
reasons that would otherwise provide a sufficient basis for a decision. Second-
order reasoning is deemed central to the judicial function in that it forces
judges to abide by a hierarchy of reasons, and specifically, to yield to higher
order considerations even when they feel that doing so leads to suboptimal or
unwise outcomes for the case at hand. Schauer intuits that judges engage in
second-order reasoning differently, more effectively, and with greater fidelity
than nonjudges. Specifically, the studies would test whether judges are more
inclined to follow a precedent or rule with which they disagree, and to limit
their attention to a narrow range of permissible sources even when other
sources lead to what they consider to be superior results. The studies are
designed to compare judicial decisions with decisions made by lawyers and
law students, and to compare decisions made by different classes of judges,
such as elected and appointed judges, trial and appellate judges, and judges
with different personal backgrounds. Undoubtedly cognizant of the com-
plexity of the issues involved, Schauer emphasizes the tentative and explora-
tory nature of his proposal, characterizing it as a set of hypotheses, an
invitation to consider a possible line of research.2
Schauers proposal also has a distinctive critical component. He addresses
extant research that tests real judges in a variety of experimental tasks that have
previously been tested with lay subjects. These studies tend to demonstrate that
judges are indeed prone to most of the same biases and errors as people in
general (Guthrie, Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2001; Wistrich, Guthrie, &
Rachlinski, 2005). Schauer considers this research to be of marginal interest
to his project because it focuses on the fact-finding and verdict-rendering
dimensions of the judicial role, which are performed also by lay jurors.
Because the studied tasks are not performed exclusively by judges, this research
fails to meet the proposed standard of uniqueness. Schauer is far more critical
of the literature that applies basic psychology to judging.3 This research fails on
both dimensions of the proposed uniqueness in that it uses ordinary people as
subjects in the performance nonjudicial decisions. In other words, the external
validity gap is seen to render this work invalid. Schauer briskly dismisses the
application of this work for being axiomatic, unargued, and unresearched.4
Schauers chapter provides a fortuitous opportunity to closely examine
the concerns over external validity that hamper application of psychological
research to legal theory. This chapter will focus on both the prescriptive and
critical approaches of his approach. First, it suggests that the design of
psychological experiments can be far more complex and subtle an endeavor
than it appears. Along these lines, it should be appreciated that the intuitively
appealing proposal to run experiments with judges is burdened by methodo-
logical pitfalls. External validity is just one piece of a larger set of validity
issues, which tend to be intricately intertwined. Attempting to fix one aspect
can be overwhelmed by greater compromises elsewhere, thus resulting in
a net loss in validity. To prevent this, one needs to adopt a pedantic approach
to the design of the study.
134 Judging as Specialized Activity
At the same time, the concern with external validity should not be
exaggerated. The discrepancy between the experimental environment and
real world settings does not automatically bar all applications of findings
from the former to the latter. It does, however, require cautious work and
oftentimes also more data. When experimental findings meet the heightened
demands of external validity, they can be applied safely to real world domains,
including specialized ones. This possibility opens up the field of judging to a
wide range of methodological approaches and thus offers the benefit of
insights originating from eclectic perspectives. To demonstrate the possibi-
lities in this regard, the discussion will center on the application of a particular
body of researchcoherence based reasoningto judging.
In Praise of Pedantry
Before expending the limited experimental resources on the proposed studies
(there is no abundance of judge-subjects), one ought to ensure that the
studies are capable of providing the insights they aim to discern. In this
vein, a brief methodological detour would be helpful.5 It is imperative to
acknowledge that external validity does not exhaust the validity challenges
facing experimental research. The foremost criterion of the validity of any
psychological experiment is that it be internally valid, which stands for the
degree to which the experimental treatment explains the observed results.
Studies are said to be internally valid when they demonstrate that the variables
that were set up or manipulated by the experimenter (independent vari-
ables) were indeed the cause of variation in the focal point of the hypothesis
(the dependent variables). Internal validity rests heavily on the researchers
ability to design the study so that it provides maximal control over the
experimental environment. Control is necessary for the restraining of unin-
tended factors that might affect the dependent variable.6 There seems no
reason to believe that Schauers proposal would be lacking in internal validity.
A finding of differences in decisions made by judges and nonjudges in a well-
controlled environment could be fairly understood to be related to differences
in the manner in which the respective groups make decisions.
Detecting differences, however, can be a far cry from understanding their
underlying mechanisms at work. To bridge this explanatory gap, studies need
to be shown to have construct validity, which stands for the degree to which
one can correctly identify and explain the operative psychological constructs.
This important and somewhat neglected facet of validity stands for the degree
to which studies accurately operationalize their theoretical constructs, which
is essential for the correct explanation of the relationship between the experi-
mental treatment and the observed phenomena. Absent this validity, one
cannot draw reliable inferences from the observed results.7
It should be acknowledged that the various forms of validity are often in
tension with one another. Notably, the high levels of experimental control
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 135
that are essential for ensuring internal and construct validity cut against the
generalizability of the findings. Likewise, tests that are designed to have a large
degree of external validity, such as archival research and field studies, typically
lack important aspects of control, most notably, random assignment of
subjects to the various conditions. Herein lies the tension in Schauers
proposal. Recall that the proposed research seeks to discern differences in
the underlying cognitive processes between judges and nonjudges. This
aspiration can be problematic, especially since such deep constructs are
most difficult to study. Even if the proposed studies yielded the expected
resultsnamely, that judges decisions were better aligned with second-order
principles than decisions by nonjudgesthe underlying operative
mechanism would remain unknown. A finding that judges show greater
deference to a precedent might or might not be indicative of superior
second-order reasoning. It could also be due to the fact that lay people lack
a sense of the judicial conventions and practices involved in assessing case
similarity, distinguishing precedents, and more. By the same token, a finding
that judges display a heightened respect for jurisdictional limitations need not
stand for the proposition that judges engage in different cognitive processes.
It could be readily interpreted as standing for the proposition that lay people
lack familiarity with the constitutional principles that underlie the rules of
federalism,8 lack the nuanced knowledge of how to weight them against
competing considerations, and the like.9 Lay people are bound to be unfami-
liar with the professions conceptions of the hierarchy of reasons, the reputa-
tional damage of being overturned, and the personal commitment to the
judicial role.10
One plausible alternative explanation for hypothesized findings of judi-
cial superiority is that judges are experts at judging, whereas lay people are
novices. Psychological research on expertise shows that experts perform
differentlyin certain ways, betterthan novices (Chi, 2006; Ericsson &
Ward, 2007). The possibility that judges have a better grasp of the conven-
tions and practices of the judicial role, and are better in weighting and trading
off the competing rules is consistent with the advantages of expertise.11
Moreover, the determinants of judicial uniqueness noted by Schauer
namely, selection, training, and experienceclosely resemble the factors
that have been found to develop expertise (Feltovich, Prietula, & Ericsson,
2006).12 While Schauer explicitly rejects the explanation based on expertise,13
the proposed studies do not seem to provide a way to discriminate between
the two explanations.14
Underlying the proposed hypothesis is the belief that judges are consid-
erably superior to lay people in following second-order rules. Schauer is
skeptical of lay peoples ability to abide by second-order rules, and goes so
far as to suggest that they might not know how to engage in this form of
reasoning at all.15 The explanation offered for lay peoples low capabilities is
that they have little experience making decisions of this kind. Yet, there is
reason to doubt whether second-order reasoning is rare or undeveloped in
136 Judging as Specialized Activity
In Praise of Eclecticism
This brings us back to the ubiquitous concerns over the external validity
of basic psychological research. With so many degrees of freedom separating
the laboratory environment from real world contexts of human action, one
might wonder how experimental research can ever be deemed to bear any
practical relevance to real life. Yet, an array of experimental findings are
notably present outside the confines of the laboratory. As it turns out, the
gathering of intelligence by the CIA in preparation for the Iraq War21 bears
an eerie similarity to various forms of biased reasoning generated in the
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 137
laboratory (e.g., Frey, 1986; Klayman, 1995; Kunda, 1990; Nickerson, 1998).
The behavior of nations and ethnic groups entangled in real conflicts corre-
sponds closely to the behavior of arbitrarily formed groups in the laboratory
(e.g., Brewer, 1979). Marketers and political consultants routinely exploit
human judgment processes gleaned from the laboratory (e.g., Rozin &
Royzman, 2001; Nisbett & Wilson, 1977). Prejudicial behavior by employers
(Bertrand & Mullainathan, 2004) mirrors behavior observed in experimental
settings (e.g., Dovidio, Kawakami, Johnson, Johnson, & Howard, 1997).
Likewise, jury decisions to send convicted inmates to their death (Eisenberg,
Garvey, & Wells, 2001) appear to be influenced by the same attitudes that affect
mock jurors decisions in hypothetical cases (Thompson, Cowan, Ellsworth, &
Harrington, 1984). A meta-analysis of experimentation is social psychology has
shown a rather strong correspondence between findings obtained in the
laboratory and in the field.22
Thus, it seems that applying psychological research to capture real world
phenomena is a complicated feat, which can be neither accomplished nor
controverted offhandedly. As discussed below, subject to a careful and meth-
odical examination, psychological research can be safely applied to some real
life situations, but not to others. Applications to the stylized domain of
judicial decision making require a heightened level of scrutiny.
For the research to be deemed useful outside the confines of the con-
trolled laboratory setting, it must first be shown that the observed phenom-
enon is not an artifact of the specific experiment. One important way to allay
this concern is by replicating the finding under similar and different experi-
mental settings. Validity increases when the same finding is observed using
different populations of subjects, stimulus materials, instructions, and tasks.
It increases also if replications are conducted in different laboratories.
Validity is further increased by the robustness of the finding, that is, its
recurrence under various manipulations, across wide ranges of values, and
in the presence of counterforces.23
Still, external validity does not guarantee that the findings apply equally
to every domain of human behavior. To be deemed applicable to a particular
real world practice, the finding must not be trumped, weakened, or distorted
by particular features of the domain, as these were not present in the experi-
mental setting and their potential influence on the finding is unknown to the
experimenter. This last link in the applicability chain has been coined con-
textual attentiveness (Arlen & Talley 2008), which stands for the degree to
which the experimental findings map onto the rich context of the real world.
Contextual attentiveness can be deemed an additional layer of external
validity. A threshold criterion for establishing contextual attentiveness is the
facial similarity between the behavior captured by the laboratory finding and
the behavior observed in real life. It is enhanced by the extent to which the
psychological theory that underlies the phenomenon is deemed germane to
the domain, particularly in the absence of competing theories. Strong support
can be derived from corroborative evidence derived from sources other than
138 Judging as Specialized Activity
the experiment itself, such as when archival or field data reveal behaviors that
are consistent with the experimentally observed phenomenon. Finally, one
might also look, with caution, to self-reports by people working in the
domain, particularly to those who are considered to be introspective.
It is important to note that there is no established gold standard for
determining external validity. None of the abovementioned features can carry
the day by itself, nor can any body of research be expected to fit them all. The
guiding principle is convergent validity: the more of the noted features that
converge toward validity, the more reliable the conclusion.
With these methodological guidelines in mind, we can return to assess
Schauers objection to the application of basic psychological findings to
judging. It is beyond the scope of this chapter to examine the merits of this
charge with respect to the various bodies of work Schauer mentions (in which
he candidly includes his own previous work, Schauer, 2006a, 2006b; see also
Arlen, 1998; Hanson & Yosifon, 2004). It is, however, feasible to assess the
objection as it pertains to the applicability of one of the bodies of work,
coherence based reasoning.24 To do so, it would be helpful first to review this
line of research.
Coherence based reasoning seeks to explain an enigmatic, yet prevalent
mode of reasoning in judicial opinions. Even the casual reader of judicial
opinions is likely familiar with the experience of being strongly persuaded by
an opinion, with all of its components converging to provide overwhelming
support for the outcome. The facts of the case, authoritative texts, governing
precedents, legal principles, public policies, as well as sheer logic and common
sense, all come together in a coherent whole to make for the inevitable and
undeniably correct result. The sense of correctness is bolstered by the dearth
or absence of arguments to the contrary. By the culmination of the opinion,
one might wonder how the decision could be considered to have been any-
thing but obvious in the first place. This sense of obviousness, however,
quickly dissolves upon turning to the opinion of the dissenting judges.
Dissenting opinions too tend to be strongly coherent and persuasive in
defending their conclusion, which is invariably antithetical to the majoritys
conclusion. Thus, while the opinions are exceedingly coherent internally, they
are radically inconsistent with a slew of seemingly plausible arguments con-
tained in the opposing opinion. The divergence between opposing judges
views of a case can lead them to stake remarkable positions. For example,
when interpreting statutes, it is not unusual for judges to deny outright that
the there is any ambiguity in the statutory text, notwithstanding the fact that
similarly positioned judges read the text to mean the very opposite.25 This
mode of reasoning is apparent in almost every appellate case.
As a matter of legal policy, this phenomenon has mixed effects that
exceed the scope of this chapter.26 As a theoretical matter, it offers an
opportunity to peer into the judicial decision-making process and better
understand the extent to which it is constrained by the law, as judges routinely
claim it to be. If indeed the coalitions of reasons mustered by judges
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 139
accurately represent the state of the law, one ought to infer that judicial
decision making is indeed tightly constrained by the law, and more impor-
tantly, that the law is determinative of single right answers. If, however, we
find an alternative explanation for this mode of reasoning, one might call into
question the professed constraint and, by implication, the binding nature of
the legal materials.
There are good reasons to suspect that the legal materials are considerably
less determinant than they are portrayed in judicial opinions. For one, most
cases decided by appellate courts are truly complicated and difficult, as they
contain sound arguments supporting each side of the issue (Schauer, 1988b).
The suspicion intensifies once opinions are dissected and stripped down to
their constitutive arguments. Relatively short U.S. Supreme Court opinions
typically contain a handful of core issues, each of which is supported by an
array of arguments, which can easily total fifty arguments or more.27
A notable feature of the opinions is that virtually every one of the dozens of
arguments supports the corresponding conclusion and contradicts the oppo-
site one.28 This perfect alignment of reasons is plainly implausible. Assuming
that the soundness of the opposing arguments are roughly similar, the
mathematical probability that each of the fifty or more arguments line up
perfectly is astronomically minute. This observation suggests that the overall
conclusion of the case plays a role in determining which arguments are
endorsed and which are rejected. While judicial decisions are most likely
affected by their underlying reasons, there appears also to be an effect in the
opposite direction, by which decisions affect the reasons that are claimed to
support them. This calls into question the avowed unidirectional relationship
between reasons and conclusions, namely that the former should affect the
latter, but not the other way round. Judicial reasoning, it would seem,
operates bidirectionally, from reasons to decisions, and back in reverse.29
This feature of judicial reasoning cannot be explained by the conven-
tional theories of decision making (e.g., von Neumann & Morgenstern, 1944;
Edwards & Newman, 1982), which seem ill suited to handle complex
decisions of the kind that judges facewhere the variables are numerous,
conflicting, ambiguous, and incommensurable. The phenomenon could,
however, be consistent with a body of psychological research that shows
that certain cognitive tasks are driven by coherence-maximizing processes.30
This line of research follows the tradition of cognitive consistency theories
notably balance theory (Abelson & Rosenberg, 1958; Heider, 1946, 1958) and
cognitive dissonance theory (Festinger, 1957)which are based, in turn, on
Gestalt psychology (Wertheimer, 1923/1938). Cognitive consistency theories
were animated by principles of structural dynamics, which posit that relevant
cognitive processes are determined holistically, rather than elementally. The
holistic structural properties are deemed to be dynamic, so that interrelated-
ness of the elements generates forces that determine the configuration of the
structure. Some things go together, that is, they are related by cohesive
forces, whereas other things tend to disperse. These forces determine the
140 Judging as Specialized Activity
overwhelming support for the emerging decision, and the other providing
depressed support for the rejected decision choice. This process is understood
to be adaptive in that it enables people to make decisions and conduct their
affairs even in the face of stifling complexity. It follows, then, that the state of
coherence is not a property of the arguments themselves, but rather an
artificial cognitive state imposed by the decision-making process. In other
words, attaining a state of coherence entails a certain distortion of the factors
involved in the decision.
Though inspired by judicial decision making, these experimental find-
ings were borne by a basic-psychological research program, and thus cannot
automatically be said to pertain to the domain of judging. To support the
claim of applicability, the research must be shown to withstand the test of
external validity.31 Coherence effects have been replicated repeatedly, without
fail, in a wide range of studies (Simon, Krawczyk, & Holyoak, 2004; Simon,
Krawczyk, Bleicher, & Holyoak, 2008; Simon, Pham, Le, & Holyoak, 2001;
Simon, Snow, & Read, 2004. For reviews, see Simon, 2002, 2004). The studies
have been replicated also by other researchers in the United States, Canada,
and Europe. One study replicated the findings using the same materials as
used in the original research (Glockner, 2007), while others tested a variety of
different tasks including financial auditing decisions (Lundberg, 2004, 2007;
Phillips, 2002), judgment and decision making (Glockner, Betsch, &
Schindler, under review), legal-economic behavior (Landeo, under review),
and evidence evaluation (Lundberg, 2004). Across the various studies, the
subjects have role-played young judges, jurors, arbitrators, auditors, and job
applicants, while other studies involved no role-playing at all. In all, the
studies have been tested with some 3,000 subjects, including undergraduate
students, graduate business students, a general sample of Internet users, and
experienced professional auditors.32 The studies have tested a wide range of
reasoning tasks, including high level inferences, analogies, rule application,
policy decisions, factual judgments, social judgments, probability assess-
ments, and personal preferences. The robustness of coherence effects is
further bolstered by the fact that they have been manipulated in numerous
ways, always yielding the hypothesized results.33
Recall that to apply a body of research to the real world, it must be shown
also that the research is contextually attentive to the particular domain.
Support for the applicability of coherence based reasoning to judging is
derived from the close resemblance between the coherence that is present in
judicial opinions and the coherence that is found in the laboratory: complex
and taxing decision tasks are resolved successfully, resulting in lopsided and
coherent sets of arguments, accompanied by high levels of confidence.34 The
theory underlying the laboratory resultsnamely, that the cognitive system
imposes coherence to facilitate choiceis consistent with the judicial func-
tion of producing compelling decisions even for the most close and contested
of cases. It is noteworthy that key components of coherence based reasoning
appear in the theorizing of the some of the notable commentators on
142 Judging as Specialized Activity
the judicial practice, including Holmes (1881, 1897), Cardozo (1921), and
Llewellyn (1960).35 Furthermore, the effect of coherence based reasoning on
appellate judging has been supported by a study that examined data from
actual court decisions (Beebe, 2006).
There are three additional ways in which the research on coherence based
reasoning maps onto judicial decision making. First, the research shows that
coherence-maximizing processing operates mostly at a low level of awareness.
People do not consciously manipulate their mental representation of the task.
Their views of the task shift toward coherent states spontaneously and
imperceptibly.36 This lack of awareness offers a plausible retort to the
Realist charge that judges consciously misrepresent the law by stacking their
opinions with whichever arguments support their preferred choices. The
research indicates rather that the excessive coherence is a natural by-product
of the decision-making process.37
Another overlap with judging emanates from a recent study that shows
that coherence can dissipate soon after the decision has been completed
(Simon et al., 2008). Coherence seems to be an ad hoc construct that appears
around the time of making the choice but does not linger on to limit
the decision maker in future cases where the constellation of variables will
not necessarily align in the same manner. Thus, while coherence tends to be
very strong within each decision, it can be rather weak across cases. This
finding suggests that people are capable of applying a particular rule or
principle in one case, and not following it in the next. This observation is
consistent with the view that judges apply differenteven opposingrules,
policies, and interpretive principles from case to case (Llewellyn, 1950, 1960;
cf. Schauer, 2007).
The research also seems to provide insight into the enduring question of
freedom and constraint in judicial decision making, that is, why critics view
the law as replete with indeterminacy and room for judicial discretion, while
judges persistently describe the legal materials as constraining. Coherence
based reasoning indicates that even though the legal materials in hard legal
cases are not constraining, they can be experienced as such once the judges
cognitive system has imposed coherence on them and shifted the vying
conclusions apart. Thus, the judicial characterization of constraint is best
understood not as a reflection of the legal materials, but as an artifact of the
cognitive process that people employ in the making of complex decisions,
judicial and otherwise.
In conclusion, Schauer is of course correct in objecting to facile applica-
tions of basic research to judicial decision making. Yet, there seems good
reason to conclude that coherence based reasoning meets the requisite stan-
dards of applicability. Whether one is persuaded by it or not, this application
ought not to be regarded as unargued, axiomatic, or unresearched. Moreover,
given the difficulties involved in understanding the judicial process, one
ought not rush to discard a body of valid and pertinent basic-psychological
research. Rather, what is needed is an eclectic stance, based on any valid and
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 143
Conclusion
The psychology of judging is poised to benefit much from a call for more
experimentation, especially when it comes from a scholar of Schauers stature.
Schauers essay provides a good opportunity to force people working in the
field to think hard about the strengths and limitations of their methodological
choices. Hopefully, it will also attract others to engage these issues and
contribute to the development of the field.
Still, the specifics of Schauers critiques and the proposed research are not
free of objections. The attempt to increase the external validity of the experi-
mentation does not come without costs. The insistence on uniqueness ends
up compromising the proposed studies construct validity, and thus muddies
up the conclusions that could be drawn from them. Methodological tradeoffs
of this kind hound experimental psychologists on a regular basis.38 It is
possible also that like many other important aspects of human behavior,
the hypotheses posed by Schauer simply do not lend themselves to experi-
mental testing. The insistence on uniqueness might also undermine the
contributions from nonunique research, especially basic psychology.
Instead of uniqueness, the field has most to gain from a pedantic attention
to the experimental design coupled with open-mindedness to the range of
useful methodologies.
The answer to the question posed in the title of Schauers essay ought to
be: yes, there is a psychology of judging. Admittedly, it is underdeveloped. To
foster its growth, the field should be guided by the understanding that the
practice of adjudication comprises a wide and diverse range of decision-
making processes. In some facets of their work, judges exert judicial expertise,
in others they behave just like ordinary people, and it is possible that in some
facets they engage in processes that are unique to them. Researchers should
opportunistically employ whichever methods are best suited for the subject of
inquiry. Looking forward, the field stands to be enriched by carefully vali-
dated findings from all strands of psychology: basic psychology, applied
144 Judging as Specialized Activity
Notes
1. In this chapter, the term psychological research refers to research based on
experimental studies.
2. Note that the proposal bridges two ingredients of external validity, namely, the
population of participants and the type of decision tested. It does not bridge
other aspects, such as realism, consequentialism, and the like.
3. Basic psychology focuses on phenomena that are relatively generalizable across
people, situations, tasks, and contexts. Basic psychologists research phenomena
like memory, reasoning, and persuasion. Applied psychology research focuses on
testing psychological phenomena as they are performed in particular contexts.
For example, applied psychology tests memory performance in the context of
witness testimony, reasoning in police investigations, and persuasion in poli-
tical campaigning.
4. Specifically, the essay states that the premise underlying this literature is an
undocumented and unargued premise that lurks in the background (p. 2). It
is described as something that researchers merely assume (p. 2); an unex-
pressed and typically unresearched outlook (p. 14); and a viewpoint that is
taken as axiomatic but hardly based on systematic research directed precisely
at that question (p. 20).
5. For useful discussions on methodological aspects of experimental psychology,
see Aronson, Wilson, and Brewer (1998) and Mitchell and Jolley (2007).
6. In the following examples, imagine a jury simulation that is intended to test the
effect of gruesome photographs from the crime scene on verdicts in the murder
trial. The hypothesis in this example is that the exposure of the fact finders to
the photographs will result in an arousal of negative emotion, which will
increase their tendency to convict.
A typical violation of internal validity is the failure to control for alternative
potential causal effects, also known as confounds. In this example, assume a
comparison between one group that receives a case that contains gory photo-
graphs and another group that receives a different case that does not contain
photographs. Given the discrepant stimuli, different rates of conviction (if
obtained) could not be explained as driven necessarily by the exposure to the
gory photographs. They could readily be explained by the fact that the two
groups received different cases. The evidence in the former case might have
been more incriminating.
7. In the abovementioned example of the study testing the effect of gruesome
photographs on jury verdicts, observing the heightened conviction rates in the
presence of gruesome evidence does not in itself provide a satisfactory under-
standing of the effect. While it is possible that the effect was driven by the
arousal of emotion (the hypothesized cause), it is also possible that it was driven
by the fact that the photographs contained incriminating information that tied
the defendant to the crime.
Construct validity is needed, first, to overcome the fact that human cognition
is notoriously multidetermined. Thus, to reliably interpret experimental
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 145
findings, studies need to be able to isolate the hypothesized mechanism and rule
out alternative explanations. Studies designed to have this capability are said to
have discriminant validity. Second, the experimental design needs also to over-
come the fact that psychological phenomena are generally not directly obser-
vable. To attain construct validity, the design needs to be able to identify the
psychological mechanisms that drive the observations. Studies designed to be
capable of identifying the correct construct are said to have content validity.
Content validity is enhanced also by the extent to which the construct fits into a
broader underlying theory. Theories are particularly useful when they are
capable of explaining other related constructs. The content validity in the
study testing the effect of gruesome photographs could be enhanced by showing
that the finding can be explained by a theory that explains other effects of
emotional arousal, such as in judgments of tort liability (Lerner, Goldberg, &
Tetlock, 1998) and aggressive behavior (Bushman, 1995).
8. Schauer actually discusses the potential problem with lay understandings of the
concepts of federalism and jurisdictions (fn. 29), but does not treat it as a
potential methodological problem with the study.
9. For an insightful demonstration of evaluating and weighting judicial goals see
Robbennolt, MacCoun, and Darley (this volume, ch. 2).
10. A tempting solution to these difficulties would be to provide lay subjects with
special training about these matters in preparation for the experiment. To the
extent that the training would be feasible and effective, it could jeopardize the
studys internal validity. For example, lay subjects might interpret the instruc-
tion as a cue for a desired decision.
11. It must be noted, however, that expertise is also characterized by subpar
functioning. Experts tend to display overconfidence, fail to notice details, and
are less agile in adapting to change. Expertise is also no guarantee against the
effects of bias (Chi, 2006; Koehler, Brenner, & Griffin, 2002). It is also important
to note that expertise is typically narrow in scope. While experts perform
differently on one type of task, the do not necessarily perform differently on
adjacent tasks, even within the domain of their expertise.
12. The expertise explanation would also explain the examples Schauer uses to
illustrate the uniqueness of judging: the difference in the mathematical skills of
a Harvard professor of mathematics and lay people, and differences between a
psychiatrist and a mechanic when it comes to providing psychiatric care or to
fixing cars.
13. See section 4, The Question of Expertise.
14. The proposed comparison of judges to nonjudges parallels what researchers in
the field of expertise call the relative line of inquiry. A different type of research
takes an objective approach, namely, focusing on how well the experts perfor-
mance stacks up against predetermined measures of excellence (Chi, 2006). By
adopting the former approach, the proposed studies will, at best, indicate that
judges are somewhat better at some aspects of judicial decisions than lay people.
But that finding falls short of answering what is arguably the crucial questions:
whether judges are good enough relative to some objective expectation, and
whether they fulfill their constitutional role satisfactorily.
15. Referring to second order reasoning, Schauer characterizes judges as people
who know how to x and contrasts them with lay people who do not know how
to x at all (p. 20).
146 Judging as Specialized Activity
16. For example, human resource personnel are habitually confronted with
considerations such as employment laws, company policies, maintaining con-
sistency with prior cases, and setting an example for future ones. It should be
noted that the article by Sunstein and Ullman-Margalit (1999) cited by Schauer
pertains to second-order decisions made in nonjudicial contexts.
17. This body of research is a good example of the productive use of cross-
disciplinary research. While the constructs underlying these findings are psy-
chological, much of this research has been performed by political scientists, in
nonexperimental settings.
18. A recent experiment conducted with law students demonstrated how second-
order rules are distorted by the ideology of the participants. See Furgeson, J. R.,
Babcock,. L., and Shane, P. M. 2008a), Behind the mask of method: Political
orientation and constitutional interpretive preferences. Law & Human Behavior.
19. True, the tasks involved in these studies were more akin to fact-finding and
rendering of verdicts, but there is no obvious reason to believe that the
performance would be better in appellate-like decision making.
20. Llewellyn, K. N. (1950), Remarks on the theory of appellate decision and the
rules or canons about how statutes are to be construed. Vanderbilt Law Review,
3, 395.
21. See Senate Report 108-301. Report of the Select Committee on Intelligence on
the U.S. Intelligence Communitys Prewar Intelligence Assessments on Iraq.
July 7, 2004 (http://intelligence.senate.gov/pub108thcongress.html).
22. The correlate coefficient of the findings was found to be about 0.73. See
Anderson, A. A., Lindsay, J. L., and Bushman, B. J. (1999), Research in the
psychological laboratory: Truth or triviality? Current Directions in Psychological
Science, 8, 39. The similarity between laboratory findings and field findings
does not ensure that the findings are applicable to real world applications, but it
does allay some of the concerns about the artificiality of the laboratory setting.
Another aspect of validity is ecological validity, which captures the similarity
between the experimental setting and the real life domain. It is undeniable that
the bulk of basic psychological research has little ecological validity with respect
to the practice of judging, or to any other real world practice for that matter.
Still, external validity ought not be confused with ecological validity. High
ecological validity naturally increases external validity, but the latter is not
dependent on the former.
23. To follow the abovementioned example, the external validity of the study of the
effect of gruesome photographs will be increased by showing that the same effect
is observed in other experimental variations, such as using different photographs,
media, populations, factual patterns, judicial instructions, and the like.
24. Schauer criticizes the application of coherence based reasoning to judging
(Simon, 1998, 2002, 2004), and also singles out some of the underlying
empirical work, namely Holyoak and Simon (1999) and Simon, Krawczyk,
and Holyoak (2004).
25. See Simon (1998), p. 71.
26. While it can be said to increase the acceptability of the opinions, this mode of
argument can be deemed detrimental to adjudication in that it obscures the
complexity of the issues involved, blunts the thoroughness of judicial analysis,
and unduly devoids the validity of the losing side. For a discussion, see Simon
(1998), pp. 129134.
In Praise of Pedantic Eclecticism 147
27. There is of course more than one way to break down a case and to enumerate its
components. Alternative ways will always be possible, though the differences
should not bear on the substantive conclusions of the analysis.
28. This form of inquiry was first demonstrated in the analysis of Ratzlaf v. United
States, 510 U.S. 135 (1994), a relatively mundane case chosen almost at random.
See Simon (1998, pp. 6172, and 73102 passim). For another example, ana-
lyzing Rogers v. Tennessee, 532 U.S. 451 (2001), see Simon (2002). The Bush v.
Gore case provides a more familiar manifestation of the phenomenon (draft on
file with author).
29. One explanation for the excessive coherence of judicial reasoning is that the
strong alignment of arguments is a product of padding of opinions (Posner,
1995a). The concept of padding implies that not all reasons play the same role
in the decision, as some are deemed to actually exert power on the decision
maker, whereas others merely serve as ex post justifications. This seems true,
though it is doubtful that padding could fully account for the observed
coherence (see Simon, 1998, pp. 3536). To illustrate, even if all but the
handful of core issues served as mere justifications, one would still need to
explain how the handful of core arguments lined up to cohere with the
decision. For example, in the Ratzlaf case there were six core issues.
Assuming that they were about equally plausible, the probability of all six
lining up to support the respective conclusion is one in sixty-four. A precise
assessment of likelihoods would depend on the degree to which the issues and
arguments are independent of one another.
30. The processes include vision (McClelland & Rumelhart, 1981), social reasoning
(Read & Miller, 1998; Read, Vanman, & Miller, 1997), analogical reasoning
(Holyoak & Thagard, 1989; Spellman & Holyoak, 1992), relational inference
(Hummel & Holyoak, 2003), text comprehension (Kintsch, 1988), and more.
These strands of research are based on a connectionist architecture, and are
resolved via Parallel Constraint Satisfaction Mechanisms (Holyoak & Thagard,
1989; Read, Vanman, & Miller, 1997).
31. The studies internal validity and construct validity are beyond the scope of this
chapter. Concerns over internal validity can be put to rest in light of their
salience in the extensive peer review that the studies have undergone.
32. The professional auditors were tested performing an actuarial task (Lundberg,
2007).
33. Manipulations can be found in Holyoak and Simon (1999), studies 1, 3;
Simon et al. (2001), studies 1, 2, 3; Simon et al. (2004a), study 1; Simon et al.
(2004b,) studies 1, 2, 3, 4.
34. See Simon (1998), pp. 61102.
35. See Simon (1998), pp. 102121.
36. Holyoak and Simon (1999), study 2. This lack of awareness further enables the
endurance of this type of reasoning in the judicial practice (Wilson & Brekke,
1994).
37. See Simon (1998), pp. 134137.
38. A key to the success of research projects is the critical examination that takes
place in lab meetings at the early stages of experimental design. Of the many
seemingly good ideas proposed at these meetings, only a small fraction make it
to the phase of experimentation, not to mention onto the pages of scientific
journals.
This page intentionally left blank
10
Judges, Expertise, and Analogy
Barbara A. Spellman
149
150 Judging as Specialized Activity
your client as the business traveler, the cruise ship as the train, and handbag as
the cell phone. Alternatively, you might think of your client as the man on
vacation, the ship as the hotel, and the handbag as the wallet.
If you think your case is most like that of businessman on the train (who
lost), you will expect the same outcome as in that case; if you think it is most
like that of the vacationing man in the hotel (who won), you will expect that
result. But despite the fact that the third case involves a woman, a cruise ship,
and a handbagjust like your ownit probably doesnt seem very similar to
your case because the objects that are the same dont stand in the same
relations to each otherand relations are the key to analogy.
Note that the difference between attribute and relational similarity is key
in the use of analogical reasoning in the law. A useful precedent is not usually
one in which the parties themselves (or the property in question) are similar
but rather one in which similar (legal) relations hold between the relevant
parties or property.
So, in the earlier example of the theft on the ship, the relevant similarities
are not whether the victim was a woman or man, whether it was a business or
pleasure trip, or what was stolen;3 rather what matters is the relation between
the victim and the owner of the ship, train, or hotel. And although most
people believe that a ship is more similar to a train than to a hotel, the court
in Adams v. New Jersey Steamboat Company (1896) ruled that for liability
purposes a ships cabin is more like a hotel room, where there is an expecta-
tion of privacy and protection, than like an open berth in a sleeping car, where
there is not.
Developing expertise in law is (at least in part) learning to ignore
irrelevant attribute similarities, learning what counts as a relational similarity,
and understanding which relational similarities are likely to matter in a given
case.
What Is an Expert?
(Chi, 2006; Glaser & Chi, 1998). These qualities are thought to reflect not just
that experts have more knowledge but also that experts have a qualitatively
different representation and organization of knowledge (Ericsson, 2006).
A potentially important characteristic of experts for the law is that, in a
variety of domains, being an expert means seeing past attribute similarities
to underlying relational similarities. For example, when shown index cards
depicting different physics problems and asked to sort them into piles, novice
physics students sort them based on the type of objects involved in the
problems (e.g., pulleys, inclined planes) whereas expert physicists sort them
based on the underlying principles involved (e.g., conservation of
momentum) (Chi, Feltovich, & Glaser, 1981). When using analogies, experts
are more able to retrieve previous analogs based on structural similarity and
avoid interference by those exhibiting only surface similarity (Novick, 1988).4
Thus, someone who is legally trained is less likely to be distracted by the hit-
by-a-handbag-on-a-cruise-ship case than someone who is not.
Another general characteristic of expertise is that it only develops given
specific conditions. One is that the person spends a lot of time at itbut, of
course, time itself is not sufficient. We all know people who have played golf
or bridge for years, and who seem to enjoy it, but who arent any better than
they were years ago. More important than just the amount of time is how that
time is spent: expertise develops out of a process called deliberate practice
which involves thousands of hours of specific types of practice and training.
Deliberate practice requires focused programmatic study with appropriate
feedback about performance. It includes identifying errors and working on
procedures to eliminate them (Ericsson, 2006; Horn & Masunaga, 2006).
Although the psychology literature is fairly glum about peoples ability to take
what they have learned in one domain and use analogy to transfer that
knowledge to another domain (see Barnett & Ceci, 2002, for a review),
there are, in fact, ways to improve peoples performance on analogical
reasoning tasks. In the laboratory, bad performance on analogical reasoning
tasks is often to due a failure to retrievesubjects trying to solve a problem do
not find relevant analogs in memory; however, once they are told that a prior
experience might be relevant, they are good at mapping.
Judges, Expertise, and Analogy 155
adults is sparse, the idea is consistent with various kinds of developmental and
anecdotal evidence. People tend to use the same labels for objects (e.g., car,
tow truck) but different labels for verbs and relations (e.g., pulls, tows,
drags)making it easier to use objects/attributes in retrieval and also
making relations more difficult to learn (Gentner & Kurtz, 2007; Gentner &
Loewenstein, 2002). Relational categories seemed to be learned by progres-
sive alignmentby first comparing examples that are similar, then com-
paring more distant ones (Gentner & Kurtz, 2007).
Law students learn the names of many legal relations: contracts, torts,
negligence, standing, jurisdictionall are about the relations between parties
and/or actions that create legal rights or obligations. Certainly, there are some
legal categories that are attribute-based: there are laws that apply only to
people over 18 years old and there are laws that apply only to ships. However,
much of law school is about learning, by contrasting many examples, the
requirements and limits of legal relations.
The best way to think of what judges may have developed is that it depends on
both process and content: it is using analogy in a domain in which they have
158 Judging as Specialized Activity
Planet 1:
Afflu ! aids ! Barebrute ! aids ! Compak
(economically (economically weak; (militarily
strong) militarily strong) weak)
Planet 2:
Grainwell ! aids ! Hungerall Millpower ! aids ! Mightless
(economically (economically (militarily (militarily
strong) weak) strong) weak)
Which (of many potential) analogs one regards as best may depend on how
much of the abstract analogical structure one incorporates (Hofstadter &
Mitchell, 1994). Consider the following question:
If the string of letters abc is changed to abd, how would you change kji in
the same way?
This question is, in effect, a four-term analogy question (like lawyer:
client :: doctor:patient): find the relations in the first pair of letter strings, map
abc to kji, and then apply the relations to create the fourth term.
The following two solutions are based on superficial features and are very
literaland people find them very unsatisfying: kji could be turned into abd
or into kjd. The first ignores all internal properties of both abc and kji (and
ignores how kji might be similar to abc); the rule is: turn any letter string into
abd. The second also ignores all internal properties of kji but does consider the
relation between abc and abd; the rule is: change the rightmost letter to d.
A less literal solution is to turn kji into kjj. That solution means con-
sidering the relation between abc and abd and also understanding that c is part
of an alphabetical sequence and that d is one step lower in the sequence; the
rule is: change the rightmost letter one step lower.
People generally prefer the two analogical solutions that incorporate the
internal relational structure of the letter strings. Generating the answer kjh
means seeing that abc is a downward sequence from which the rightmost letter
is moved one more step down; however, kji is an upward sequence, therefore,
the rule is: move rightmost letter one step more in the direction of the sequence.
Generating the answer lji also means seeing that abc is a downward sequence
and kji is an upward one. Then abd means changing the lowest (rightmost)
letter down one; lji means changing the lowest (leftmost) letter down one.
One of the fascinating things about the Hofstadter letter-string analogies
is how many different ones can be sensibly generated from such seemingly
simple stimuli. Legal cases are similarly complicated in that they may contain
relations that are or are not incorporated into the litigants arguments and
that analogies may be drawn at very literal or abstract levels. For example, the
same case may be viewed as being about the right to engage in homosexual
sodomy or the right to be let alone (Bowers v. Hardwick, 1986).
Coherence
The selection of a particular analog, or relevant precedent, might also (unin-
tentionally) emerge out of a general pressure for cognitive coherencethat is,
the tendency for people to be consistent in their reasoning. As a consequence,
peoples views of the applicability of a source analog change in line with other
changes in their opinions (for overviews of this research see Simon, 2004;
Simon & Holyoak, 2002). In the basic study (Holyoak & Simon, 1999),
subjects (undergraduates) read a semifictional legal case. The plaintiff, a
Judges, Expertise, and Analogy 161
software company named Quest, sued Jack Smith, an investor in the com-
pany, for libel. Smith had posted a negative message about the company on an
electronic bulletin board directed at investors, and soon after the stocks price
dropped drastically and the company went bankrupt.
Before reading the case, subjects were asked whether they thought mes-
sages posted on electronic bulletin boards should be treated like items pub-
lished in newspapers or like messages sent over a telephone network. Later, as
part of the case, subjects learned that defamatory messages published in a
newspaper could give rise to a cause of action for libel whereas those trans-
mitted by telephone could not.
Subjects were about equally divided in verdicts. But whereas before
reading the case, subjects found the newspaper and telephone analogies
equally compelling, after rendering their verdicts, they widely diverged.
Those who found for Quest believed that the newspaper analogy was much
better than the telephone analogy; the opposite was true for those who found
for Smith. Thus, belief in the quality of an analogy shifted coherently along
with other beliefs that led them to their decision.
Legal Knowledge
An experiment comparing law students to undergraduates demonstrates how
legal knowledge can affect analogical reasoning (Braman & Nelson, 2007, Exp.
2). Subjects (96 undergraduates and 77 law students) read an article summar-
izing the target case facts (but not the result) of Wazereud-Din v. Goodwill
Homes and Mission, Inc. (1999) in which the plaintiff, an Islamic man, was
denied admission to a Christian-administered drug treatment program. They
also read about a potentially relevant previously decided case. The precedent
case varied in its similarity to the target case and involved one of three
different plaintiffs: Islamic man, gay man, or black man; one of three different
types of defendant: religious treatment program, community service organi-
zation, or insurance company; and one of two holdings: discrimination or
not. Subjects rated how similar the precedent was to the target case. They had
also previously been asked whether they agreed that faith-based organizations
should have the right to exclude people who did not share their beliefs from
receiving their services.
Several findings demonstrate the effects of legal knowledge: (1) overall,
undergraduates rated the precedents as more similar to the target case than
did the law students, and (2) undergraduates treated precedents involving
Islamic and gay plaintiffs similarly whereas law students tended to treat
precedents involving Islamic and black plaintiffs similarly. These results
suggest that the law students were using their prior knowledgeof the
difference between strict scrutiny and rational basis testsin their
judgments.8
But Braman and Nelson (2007) want to go further than merely stating
that knowledge matters to analogy use; they argue that there was (sometimes)
162 Judging as Specialized Activity
evidence that subjects prior beliefs mattered: in general, those who opposed
exclusion based on religion were more likely to rate the target case as similar
to the precedent when the holding was that there was discrimination, but
those who favored exclusion were more likely to rate the target case as similar
to the precedent when the holding was that there was no discrimination. This
pattern was stronger and more consistent for the law students.
Therefore, Braman and Nelson (2007) also conclude in favor of moti-
vated reasoningthat peoples policy preferences (e.g., regarding exclusion)
influence legal decision making (p. 954). However, the causal conclusion
that preferences influence reasoning, and, especially, that it might have influ-
enced reasoning in a consciously motivated way, is not justified. Subjects are
not randomly assigned to favor or oppose exclusionthus, subjects who start
out holding different beliefs may differ from each other in other systematic
ways (creating a so-called third variable problem). For example, subjects
who are more tolerant of different groups and less likely to see differences
between them might both (1) be more likely to oppose exclusion and (2)
more likely to see similarities between the cases. Other types of preexisting
knowledgenot necessarily directly related to the casecould have similar
effects.
Note that the authors hasten to add that nothing we have found suggests
a conscious effort to twist the law to serve ones preferences (Braman &
Nelson, 2007, p. 954). It is easy to see how these results could emerge
simply from different knowledge and from the (unconscious) pressure for
coherence in reasoning.
What can we conclude? Judges have had lots of practice using analogy; yet,
they might not actually be experts because just as there is no real generalized
expertise in problem solving it is not clear that there can be a generalized
expertise in analogy use. More important, however, judges (like laypeople)
know that when using analogies it is important to look for relational simila-
rities andbecause of their specialized training in legal contentthey know
which relational similarities matter within their domains of expertise.
Many of the limitations on using analogies described above have to do
with finding or retrieving the proper analogs to use. Judges dont have to try
to retrieve from memorythey have briefs and law clerks to find the relevant
sources. Yet, as the WWII/Vietnam study shows, unconscious remindings of
known analogs that are not present can affect judgments even though, when
made explicit, the analogs are not viewed as any better or worse than other
ones. In addition to this automatic retrieval of analogies, judges knowledge
and interests may influence how they mentally represent and use different
analogs. When judges know more about some issues than others, or, in the
past, have drawn analogies to one kind of outcome, they might be more likely
to unintentionally find in a direction consistent with past judgmentsin part
Judges, Expertise, and Analogy 163
because of what they see as more (or less) similar, in part because of the level
of abstraction (i.e., how deep the relations) they use, and in part because of an
effort to maintain coherence in their beliefs.
Thus, although judges might decide consistently with predictions, it is
possible that they do so not for any of the intentional (and sometimes
seemingly nefarious) reasons suggested by legal realism. Regression ana-
lyses can reveal that it happens but understanding how analogical reasoning
works, and how judges might use it, is necessary for understanding why it
might happen.
Notes
1. This position is the most extreme version of the legal realist view. A more
nuanced view is that they are sensitive to both attitudinal and jurisprudential
concerns (Lindquist & Klein, 2006).
2. The terms surface and superficial are often mixed both within and across
articles.
3. Note that although irrelevant in this case, such factors could be relevant in other
types of cases.
4. When acquiring analogical skills, children parallel this development (Ratterman
& Gentner, 1998).
5. But see Lawrence (1988) for an early study of how Australian magistrates impose
sentences; and, Dhami (2003), with a larger data set showing that British judges
bail decisions can be well described by a simple heuristic model.
6. In a sense, when lawyers write briefs, and when judges read and rule on them,
they are engaged in a similar activity. Of course, the kind of feedback that
lawyers and, especially, judges get is much more erratic and sporadic than that of
the law student.
7. Other potential factors include context effects (see Hunter, 2001); whether
people set out to look for similarities or differences between cases (see Gentner
& Markman, 1994; and Medin, Goldstone, & Gentner, 1990); and beliefs about
the causal structure of relevant legal categories (see Kim & Ahn, 2002).
8. Under current constitutional doctrine, actions that treat people differently based
on race and religion merit strict scrutiny, whereas those based on sexual orienta-
tion do not.
This page intentionally left blank
11
Thresholds for Action in Judicial Decisions
Many decisions that people are called on to make can be thought of as involving
thresholds for action. Should one buy a new computer, attempt a left turn into
oncoming traffic, excuse a late submission from a student? In each case, we can
understand the decision maker to be answering two questions: (1) How strong
are the arguments in favor of taking this action? (2) How strong must the
arguments be in order for me to take the action?
Decision makers in court cases, whether judges or jurors, are commonly
required to make this kind of decision. Take a hypothetical, but fairly typical,
drug trafficking case in a U.S. court, where the police uncovered one piece of
evidence by stopping the defendant on the street for questioning, subjecting
him to pat-down search, and finding a bulky packet of marijuana in his coat
pocket. In one of several motions to the judge, the defendants lawyer argues
that the marijuana should not be allowed into the trial as evidence because the
search was unconstitutional. The judge must decide, among other things,
whether the police reasonably suspected that the defendant was, at the time of
the search, armed and presently dangerous.1 Her decision will depend on
both her assessment of the evidence available to the police at the time and her
understanding of reasonable suspicion. At the end of the trial, the jury (or
judge, if a jury trial has been waived) must decide whether the prosecution
proved the defendants guilt beyond a reasonable doubt. Again, the decision
will require judgments about both the evidence itself and the threshold the
evidence needs to cross.
These are just two examples of a great many. Appellate judges may have
to decide whether a decision made by a trial judge constitutes an abuse of
165
166 Judging as Specialized Activity
HIGH
Factors
Factors Influencing
Influencing Assessment Threshold
Assessment.
Information from
Information from Experiences and
Current situation History of
being Judged Yes Decision Maker
(The Past)
Threshold
No
LOW
Assessment Dimension
e.g. Strength of Evidence
Decision Rule:
If the Assessment of the current situation is above the threshold, decide Yes.
If the Assessment of the current situation is below the threshold, decide No.
Figure 11.1 A general model for assessment and decision making (GADM).
taught them to give more weight to certain types of evidence than others. The
case factors and to some extent their weight are reasonably easy to articulate.
Cooksey (1996) reviews how to elicit and analyze the factors influencing the
assessment. This chapter focuses on how to make explicit the factors influen-
cing threshold placement. Since they are not case or situation factors, they are
less easy to articulate.
An implication of the model is that it points to two different explanations
for why different people when presented with the same evidence come to
different decisions. Consider two judges presented with the same information
in a motion hearing, where one chooses to grant the motion and the other
denies it. According to the model, the difference in outcomes might come
from differences in the assessment of the strength of evidence, but it may also
arise from divergent thresholds for action, or from both causes combined.
This chapter focuses on the implications of variation across people in their
personal thresholds for action.
The left hand side of the model derives from Signal Detection Theory
(SDT) (McNicol, 2004), which has had wide influence beyond its initial
development for the interpretation of sensory processes in the 1950s. In the
example above, the judges task is to discriminate between two states: the
motion should be granted and the motion should be denied. For a juror in a
168 Judging as Specialized Activity
Table 11.1 The Four Categories of Response in the Context of Juror Decision
Making in Criminal Trials
criminal case, the task is to discriminate between two states: the defendant is
guilty and the defendant is innocent. The signal the juror has to detect is
the guilt of the defendant. This decision is made under uncertainty.
Hammond (1996) argued that in all decision making there is irreducible
uncertainty. This means that no matter what decision is made, deny or
grant, convict or acquit, there is always the possibility of an error. The
fourfold table makes explicit that there are two types of error. Table 11.1
illustrates this for the jurors task. The two types of error are Wrongful
Acquittals, or misses, where the juror has missed the signal, and Wrongful
Convictions, or false alarms. For the judges motion hearing example, the
two types of error are wrongful denial of the motion and wrongful
granting.
There has been much interest in the relationship between the two types
of errors. Volokh (1997) demonstrated that people have expressed a great
many opinions about what the ratio of Wrongful Acquittals to Wrongful
Convictions is or should be. One of those opinions is by the English jurist
William Blackstone, who said, Better that ten guilty persons escape than that
one innocent suffer (cited in Volokh, 1997). The ratio 10:1 has become
known as the Blackstone Ratio (BR).
There has been considerable debate on the meaning of the numbers in
the BR (Dekay, 1996). One view is that the numbers in the BR indicate
frequencies in a population of cases. Assuming that jurors assess the like-
lihood of guilt as a probability, the numbers in the BR can be used to
establish a beyond reasonable doubt probability against which they com-
pare their assessed likelihood of guilt. Another view of the BR is that it
captures the worth, utility, or value of one persons being wrongly con-
victed. Signal Detection Theory (SDT) combines these two views. In SDT,
the decision maker is assumed to maximize the percentage of correct
decisions and to maximize the utility of the decision. Using Bayes theorem
and Subjective Expected Utility theory, Coombs, Dawes, and Tversky
(1970) give the formula for threshold placement in terms of the prevalence
of signals and the utilities for the four possible outcomes in Table 11.1.
Thresholds for Action in Judicial Decisions 169
Dekay (1996), in the context of juror decision making, points out that the
merit of SDT is that it separates two aspects of decision performance. These
are the ability of the person to discriminate between the two states in Table
11.1 and the persons willingness to take action, their threshold placement.
It can be equally helpful in analyzing judges decisions on which side to err
in considering a motion.
Identifying Thresholds
The first study to be discussed was designed to test whether giving different
definitions of the standard of proof shifted the threshold for beyond reason-
able doubt, but we ignore that element of the study here.3 Participants were
given general information about a particular murder trial from South
Australia, Pfennig v. The Queen (1995). This case was chosen because it was
largely based on circumstantial evidence and was appealed through to the
High Court of Australia. Table 11.2 gives a brief summary of the case.
Briefly, Pfennig v The Queen involved Peter Pfennig being charged with the murder of a
10-year-old boy named Michael Black. At trial, the Crown prosecutor argued that Pfennig had
abducted Michael for sexual purposes and then killed him. Michaels body was never found.
The Crown presented the court with much circumstantial evidence, including evidence of
Pfennig talking to Michael at the last place that Michael was seen alive. The Crown also
provided evidence that Pfennig had pleaded guilty to abducting and raping a 13-year-old boy
almost one year after Michael disappeared. In that case Pfennig had placed his victims
belongings at the top of a cliff to encourage speculation that the victim had accidentally fallen.
Similarly, Michaels belongings were found arranged neatly beside a river so as to suggest an
accidental drowning.
170 Judging as Specialized Activity
EVIDENCE
Strength of Evidence
low high
0 20 40 60 80 100
Cuel: degree of match
between the description of 1
the man and Pfennig
detection where the experimenter defines which stimuli are the signals and
which are no-signals (Ryder, Pike, & Dalgleish, 1974). The important thing
about this procedure is that it enables measurement of the threshold.
Three groups of 10 students from the University of Queensland partici-
pated as part of their course requirements. All participants were registered on
the electoral roll as required by s.4 of the Jury Act 1995 (Queensland).
Each participant received information on the general case, definitions of
the evidence cues, and practice cases. Each also received one of three different
definitions of reasonable doubt. For each of the 100 hypothetical cases they
made a judgment of the overall strength of evidence on a nine-point rating
scale and made a decision whether to convict or acquit.
Table 11.3 shows a cross tabulation of the decisions made by two partici-
pants, chosen because they were given the same definition of reasonable doubt
and their evaluations of the strength of evidence in different cases were quite
similar. Despite these similarities, Juror C made 79 convict decisions whereas
Juror A made 25 convict decisions. Their rates of Wrongful Convictions and
Wrongful Acquittals differ considerably. Juror C is a Convictor because for a
given case they need little evidence before they convict. On the other hand Juror
A is an Acquitter and for a case needs much more evidence before they
convict. Calculations from a Signal Detection Theory (SDT) analysis, Stainslaw
and Todorov (1999), indicate that the index of threshold placement, ln(b), is
1.5 for Juror C and 1.2 for Juror A. Note that ln(b) is the natural logarithm of
the threshold (or response criterion, to use SDT terminology). This index is
useful because it is symmetrical around zero and is independent of the accuracy
of the decision maker. It is negative when the participant has a decision
tendency toward convicting. The differences in the decisions of these two
Juror C Juror A
High
Threshold JA
Acquit
JA JC
Assessment. Assessment.
Convict
Threshold JC
Low
Assessed level of Strength of
Evidence for Guilt
Figure 11.3 Conflict in decision making when there is agreement on the
evidence.
Thresholds for Action in Judicial Decisions 173
be known. For the criminal trial, the proportion of truly guilty defendants is
also not known. However, decision makers have beliefs about these propor-
tions based on their experiences and history either directly or vicariously
gained. That is, they have in mind a perceived prevalence that is their prior
beliefs about the need to take action. This influence on the threshold is in
place before the decision maker has any information about the current case or
situation. Let p(Na) be the proportion of cases for which the decision maker
believes they need to take action for a particular type of decision. If a decision
maker has a high p(Na) then given the knowledge that they are about to see a
case, they need less strength of evidence to decide yes than someone with a
low p(Na).
The second theoretical influence on the threshold is a function of the
utilities the decision maker has for each outcome in the fourfold table, Table
11.1. These utilities are subjective in that each decision maker has their own
set of utilities and these derive from their experiences and history either
directly or vicariously gained. If a decision maker wishes to avoid misses
(Wrongful Acquittals), then they need less strength of evidence to decide yes
than someone who wants to avoid False Alarms (Wrongful Convictions). In
SDT both these influences are combined mathematically and captured in an
index of threshold placement, ln(b).
In the next three studies to be briefly reported we attempt to measure the
relative utilities and beliefs about the need to take action directly by eliciting
peoples prior beliefs about the prevalence of guilt. One view of the Blackstone
Ratio is that it reflects the value people put on a Wrongful Acquittal com-
pared to a Wrongful Conviction, that is, 10:1. We wanted to find out how
people replied when we asked them for their own version of the BR directly
and to look for variation in the elicited BR.
Thirty-six undergraduate Psychology students at Kansas State University
participated. They were randomly assigned to three groups that received
different labels for the standard of proof. Each participant was given a careful
instruction individually. Participants were asked to imagine themselves on a
jury, given a case to read, shown in Table 11.4, and asked to make a decision
about whether to convict or acquit.
A 32-year-old, Paul, was shot to death in his car outside Brooklyn, New York, at 11:30 pm on
November 15, 2005.
The witness saw a man wearing black clothing who walked up to Paul and shot him several
times as he was entering his car.
Paul was a restaurant manager. According to colleagues, he was friendly and successful.
However, he had financial problems with his ex-wifes boyfriend, John.
Police accused John of the murder, and a shoeprint matching one of Johns shoes was found
near the crime scene.
However, John said he was in bed with Pauls ex-wife at the time, and she confirms the fact.
174 Judging as Specialized Activity
Think of 1000
defendants on trial
for murder
Of these, how
Of these, how many
many are
are convicted?
acquitted?
Of these, how
Of these, how Of these, how Of these, how
many are
many are Guilty? many are Innocent? many are Guilty?
Innocent?
They were then asked to think about murder cases in general and asked
this question to elicit their Blackstone Ratio, HOW MANY truly guilty
defendants charged with murder do you believe should be acquitted to
avoid ONE truly innocent defendant being convicted? To elicit their prior
beliefs about guilt, they were asked to think about 1000 defendants before the
court charged with murder. They filled out the boxes in Figure 11.4 by first
thinking how many of the 1000 were convicted or acquitted. For those that
were convicted they were asked to state how many did they think were truly
guilty and how many were truly innocent. They did the same for those they
thought were acquitted.
Frequency 19 9 2 2 1 2 1
Percentage 53 25 5.6 5.6 2.8 5.6 2.8
Frequency 10 4 10 4 4
Percentage 31 12.5 31 12.5 12.5
from Study 2 with a sizable percentage not wanting to let any guilty people to
go free, see Table 11.6. As in the other studies, there is wide variability.
The key message from a Blackstone Ratio of 10:1 is that the interests of
the defendant are paramount. However, Volokh (1997, p. 211) cites the story
of a Chinese law professor listening to a British lawyer state it is better that 99
guilty men go free than that one innocent man be executed. The Chinese
professor asked Better for whom? This may help with an explanation for
the number of participants who wanted no guilty men to go free and the
participants who wanted to avoid a Wrongful Acquittal. It may be that some
participants have the defendants interests as paramount but others may focus
on the interests of society. Study 4 explores this explanation.
Consider the situation of a judge deciding to grant or deny a motion. For
a particular type of motion, perhaps a frequently encountered type of motion,
they will have beliefs about the prevalence with which such a type of motion
should be granted. They will also have beliefs similar to those expressed in the
BR. For example, how many motions should be wrongfully granted to avoid
one wrongfully denied motion? Further, apart from the two adversaries
before the judge, there are other stakeholders in the decision to grant or
deny a motion, for example, the judge, society, and the law.
There are many stakeholders in the criminal court, for example, the
defendant, the lawyers, the judge, the jury members, the victims and their
families, and society, to name some of them. The decisions made in court will
have different consequences for different stakeholders. We think that when
participants focus on the defendant as stakeholder, more will want to avoid
Wrongful Convictions and that when focusing on society as stakeholder
more will want to avoid Wrongful Acquittals. This could explain some of
the variability in our studies reported so far. Further, using the idea that
people with a conservative approach to justice would focus on the society as
the main stakeholders and that those with a liberal approach would focus on
the defendant as the main stakeholder, (Tetlock & Mitchell, 1993), we suggest
that those who want to avoid Wrongful Convictions would identify them-
selves as more liberal.
Thirty-four students from an intermediate-level forensic psychology
course in 2007 at Kansas State University participated. Prior beliefs were
elicited as in Studies 2 and 3. The fourfold table was explained as in Study 3,
Thresholds for Action in Judicial Decisions 177
and participants were asked to think about the defendant as stakeholder and
write out the consequences for the two types of error. They were then asked to
think about society as the stakeholder and wrote out the consequences for the
two types of error, Wrongful Acquittal and Wrongful Conviction. Following
this, we asked them which error they wanted to avoid the most with the
defendant as stakeholder and then with society as stakeholder. They were also
asked which stakeholder they thought was more important. We asked them to
place their political views on a scale from 1 to 100 labeled liberal at the low
end and conservative at the high end of the scale. We then elicited their
Blackstone ratio as in Studies 2 and 3.
The results for prior beliefs for guilt were very similar to those from
Studies 2 and 3. The mean was .623 with a standard deviation of .18 and a
range from .13 to .91. This range does not seem to be a function of being an
undergraduate student because it matched the range of prior beliefs elicited
from seminar attendees at seminars given by Dalgleish for faculty and grad-
uate students at some universities in the United States and the UK.
Table 11.7 presents the frequency with which participants wanted to
avoid the two types of error by stakeholder. When considering the defendant,
76% wanted to avoid a Wrongful Conviction, whereas 26% wanted this when
considering society. These two proportions are different using a McNemars
test, w(1) = 73.5, p < 0.001. Thus, the consideration of different stakeholders
matters. The most important stakeholder was society for 21/34 (64%) of parti-
cipants. The majority, 18/34 (53%), wanted to avoid Wrongful Convictions
when considering the defendant and avoid Wrongful Acquittals when consid-
ering society.
What is the relationship between self-reported political views and the
value placed on the consequences for different stakeholders? There were some
weak relationships but all were in the expected directions. When thinking of
the defendant as stakeholder those that wanted to avoid WCs had a more
liberal political view (N = 8, M = 52.2) than those who wanted to avoid WAs
Table 11.7 Frequency of Desire to Avoid the Two Types of Error Depending
on Stakeholder
Society as Stakeholder
Wrongful Wrongful
Convictions Acquittals Total
Defendant Wrongful 8 18 26
as stakeholder Convictions
76
Wrongful 1 7 8
Acquittals
Total 9 25 34
26
178 Judging as Specialized Activity
(N = 26, M = 62.3), t(30) = 1.42, one-tail p = .08. This test has low statistical
power because the sample sizes are small and the measure of political views
was a simple one-item scale. It would be interesting to see if this effect
is stronger if better measures of political views were used, such as those
developed by Evans, Heath, and Lalljee (1996) and Mehrabian (1996).
Those participants who said the defendant was more important had more
liberal views, (M = 50.2 versus M = 55.2, t(32) = 1.07, one-tail p = .15) but,
while in the expected direction, this difference was not statistically significant.
The pattern for Blackstones Ratio is similar to those for Studies 2 and 3.
However, it is useful to tabulate the elicited BRs by which stakeholder was
considered more important. Table 11.8 does this. There were 5 participants
who stated their BR as not wanting any guilty defendants being free. We
believe this category is separate from BRs that state that the participant wants
at least one guilty defendant to go free. The participants with a BR of 0:1 may
not have understood the question eliciting the BR or they have a particular
interpretation of WA or WC or they really wanted no guilty defendants free.
We calculated the mean political view for these 5 participants (M = 72.3,
SD = 21.8) and tested it against the mean for those 25 who said they wanted
at least one guilty defendant free, (M= 48.24, SD = 23.26). This difference is
statistically significant, t(29) = 2.36, p = .025) showing that those who had a
0:1 BR rated themselves as more politically conservative. Combined over our
2nd, 3rd and 4th studies, 35 out of the 100 participants had an elicited BR of
0:1. The implication is that these people would be more conservative in their
political views. Another implication is that in future research, the BR should
be elicited using a different question that allows participants to state the ratio
of WC to WA. For some of the participants who stated a 0:1 BR, their BR
elicited using a different question may have been 1:10 or some ratio opposite
to the direction of the ratio stated by Blackstone.
Excluding the 0:1 group, there were no differences in political view for
those participants whose BR were <10:1 and for those with BRs 10:1.
However, for those 10 participants with BRs 10:1 seven of them (70%)
stated that the defendant was more important while for those that favored
Defendant 2 1 2 5 2
Society 3 2 9 4 1
Equal 1 0 0 0 0
Total (N = 32) 6 3 11 9 3
Percentage 18.8 9.4 34.4 28.1 9.4
Thresholds for Action in Judicial Decisions 179
society 5/16 (31.3%) had BRs 10:1. These proportions were close to being
significantly different, w2(1) = 3.72, p = .054.
So when participants consider either the defendant or society, this influ-
ences their threshold since the relative costs of WC and WA change. However,
which stakeholder is more important is not related to prior beliefs but is
related to their Blackstone Ratio. From these results we could infer that the BR
is more about values of consequences than about frequency (prior beliefs)
(cf., Dekay, 1996).
From the GADM model there is the prediction that if two members of a
jury have different thresholds, for example, one considers the defendant as a
more important stakeholder and the other favors society, and they assess the
strength of evidence as being the same in the case, then they will disagree
about the verdict. Going back to the case evidence will not resolve this
disagreement. There is a further implication of the GADM model from
these findings. Consider a person from the group who wanted to avoid WC
when considering the defendant and wanted to avoid WA when considering
the society as stakeholder (the majority of participants). Let us assume one of
them has a prior belief of guilt of 0.50 (neutral) and let them consider a case
that does not have clear-cut evidence of guilt. Figure 11.5 illustrates this
example with two possible thresholds for this juror. When considering the
defendant the threshold is Tdef and the assessment of the evidence is not
sufficient to convict. When considering the society the threshold is Tsociety
and the evidence is sufficient to convict. This juror would be in a state of
internal decisional conflict and would vacillate while trying to reach a
verdict. This may be seen as indecision but searching the evidence is not
going to resolve this internal conflict. The person needs to go with the
stakeholder they evaluate as the most important and use the threshold for
that stakeholder.
What are the implications of these findings for judges ruling on motions
or other judicial decisions? The link between judicial decisions and political
orientation, given the tentative evidence from Study 4, seems to lie not with
High
Threshold TDef
Acquit
J
Assessment.
Convict
Threshold TSociety
Low
Assessed level of Strength of
Evidence for Guilt
Figure 11.5 Internal decisional conflict within a juror.
180 Judging as Specialized Activity
the assessment of the evidence but with the relative importance of different
stakeholders and the relative values of Wrongful Convictions and Wrongful
Acquittals to the judge. The relative influence of the assessment of the
evidence and prior beliefs about prevalence, the values of the two types of
errors and the importance of the different stakeholders could be tested using a
vignette study similar to our Study 1 together with the elicitation of the other
factors developed for Studies 2, 3 and 4. More robust measures of political
orientation would need to be used.
Conclusion
The data from the four studies indicates a tremendous amount of variation in
(1) measured thresholds, and (2) measures of the influences on threshold.
These were the prior beliefs about guilt and the error they wanted to avoid the
most. Further there was considerable variation in the elicited Blackstone
Ratios. Some of this variation was related to which stakeholder they thought
most important or were considering and their self-reported political views.
From the GADM model this variation in threshold for guilt, implies that,
within jury trials, there will be considerable differences in verdicts reached
that are not due to differences in the interpretation and assessment of the
evidence.
While the data presented in this chapter has been with undergraduate
students in simulated jury decision making, the aim has been to show that
the methods could be generalized to judicial decision making. Whether the
results of our studies generalize to other judicial decision making tasks is an
empirical question. Throughout this chapter we have drawn parallels between
the judicial task of deciding to deny or grant a motion and the jury task of
deciding whether to convict or acquit a defendant. Further, we have suggested
that our convict/acquit decision tasks could be used with judges and lawyers.
The aim of these proposed studies would be to investigate the amount and
variability in their thresholds for beyond reasonable doubt and in the theore-
tical influences on thresholds among judges and among lawyers and between
judges and lawyers.
Similarly, the aim of the proposed studies on the judicial decision to deny
or grant motions would be to investigate and document variation in the
thresholds for action. If, for example, both trial judges and appellate judges
did the same tasks, we could compare thresholds between pairs of judges.
What are the implications of this? Let us consider a trial judge who has a
tendency to deny motions of a particular type. Let us assume that some of the
decisions are contentious enough to provide grounds for appeal. Now con-
sider an appellate judge who reads the original submissions and decides
against the original decision. Within the GADM model approach to the
assessment of the original submissions and the decision to take action, the
Thresholds for Action in Judicial Decisions 181
trial judge and the appellate judge may differ in their assessment or in their
thresholds or both. It is important to isolate whether such differences in
decisions are due to differences in the interpretation of the law or to differ-
ences in the values attached to the consequence of the decisions or to the
judges prior beliefs about the need to take action. In addition to the studies
reported in this chapter, there seems anecdotal evidence, for example on
websites such as Decision of the Day4 that such differences of opinion
exist. Investigating whether there is variation in the influences on the
threshold is important because making such influences explicit to people
enables discussion about them and provides ways of devising training to
reduce the effects of decisional conflict. One of our studies found links
between the relative importance of different stakeholders and political orien-
tation and if such effects were found among judges and lawyers, it may inform
and extend debate on the role of political orientation and judicial decision
making. The GADM model and its associated methodologies provide a way to
empirically study such issues.
Notes
Preparation of this chapter was supported by funds provided by the Scottish
Funding Council to HealthQWest; A research consortium for the West of Scotland.
1. U.S. v. Terry, 392 U.S. 1 (1968).
2. Similarly, in applying the GADM model to verdicts, it is assumed that an
assessment of the strength of evidence is made and a decision to convict is
made if the assessment exceeds their threshold for action. This threshold
depends on the level of proof needed to convict; for example, beyond reason-
able doubt would be higher than the preponderance of the evidence.
3. Anna Rickard (1998) completed the study as an honors project at the University
of Queensland.
4. http://www.enotes.com/blogs/decision-blog/
This page intentionally left blank
12
Every Jury Trial Is a Bench Trial: Judicial
Engineering of Jury Disputes
For decades virtually every scholarly work on civil trial courts and trial judges
began by lamenting the unfortunate tendency of students of judicial behavior
to concentrate almost exclusively on appellate courts generally and on the
U.S. Supreme Court in particular. Fortunately, although this imbalance is still
present to a degree, a nascent body of research has ameliorated the disparity
and enhanced greatly our understanding of civil trial courts, trial judges, and
the psychology of trial judging over the last decade.
This growth in attention to trial courts has, of course, included tradi-
tional legal analysis and over 25 years of sophisticated, multidisciplinary
attention to all levels of criminal courts (Jacob, 1983; Gibson, 1980); how-
ever, studies of civil trial judges behavior have, generally speaking, either
pursued a political track, which studied trial judges as political actors by
reference to appellate judicial behavior (Baum, 2007), or a juror track
marked by explicit or implicit comparisons with juror behavior
(Robbennolt, 2005).
Political studies, especially judicial comparisons have, not surprisingly,
been primarily (but not exclusively) conducted by political scientists, and
have borrowed heavily from the study of appellate judicial behavior and the
influence of extralegal factors on that behavior (Rowland & Carp, 1996;
Buchman, 2007). Relying almost exclusively on federal trial judges published
opinions (but see Rowland & Carp, chap. 4 re unpublished opinions), judicial
scholars have found that for politically salient issues, such as abortion-related
disputes, federal trial judges published decisions can be predicted to an
impressive degree by extralegal factors, such as the appointing president
183
184 Judging as Specialized Activity
As suggested by the title of this essay, every civil trial is in important ways a
bench trial, with evidence and, to some degree, outcomes engineered by the
trial judge. Yet, with notable exceptions discussed below, most recent research has
devoted little attention, especially in natural settings, to judicial participation
in the resolution of civil disputes in which litigants demand a jury trial.
Indeed, unlike students of the criminal justice process, who have for years
focused on judges as participants in a courtroom workgroup whose members
186 Judging as Specialized Activity
Pretrial
outcome of the trial itself. Not surprisingly, many cases settle shortly after
these rulings are made.
7. Motions regarding admissibility of expert witnesses and testimony. There are a
multitude of preliminary decisions, leading up to the courts ultimate ruling, that
can determine how the court will handle its gate-keeping function as it relates to
expert testimony, all of which may dramatically alter the course of the trial. The
judge has within his or her power to decide whether to hold a hearing at all,
whether the hearing is evidentiary in nature and should include witness testimony,
and which factors to employ in determining reliability of testimony. Because the
motions are usually filed by defendants seeking to exclude plaintiffs expert
testimony, the rulings often define at an early stage which party has the higher
evidentiary ground. Given the influence of these admissibility rulings for both
parties, it is no accident that they are usually hotly contested, with extensive
briefings and adversarial argumentation.
During Trial
1. Jury Selection. There can be little dispute that the demographics, back-
ground, education, experience and attitudinal bent of each individual juror is
a critical component of how a jury dispute will eventually be resolved. The
judge exercises great power and influence over the jury selection process, the
ultimate makeup of the jury, and therefore, the verdict they will likely render
by deciding: whether or not to strike jurors for cause; the number of per-
emptory challenges allowed to each side; the reasons accepted or rejected for
hardship excuses; whether multiple plaintiffs or defendants are treated singly
or as a group for peremptory challenges; how many strikes each side gets
when the dispute involves multiple plaintiffs and/or defendants; whether a
supplemental juror questionnaire is allowed, and, if so, what questions and
what response options are permitted; whether attorneys can conduct their
own voir dire or not; how much discretion is given to attorneys in conducting
voir dire regarding scope of questions and latitude to introduce case themes
and facts. These jury-selection judgments, virtually untouchable at the appel-
late level, define the right to a jury trial in practice perhaps more than any
other exercise of judicial discretion.
2. Evidentiary Rulings. Evidentiary rulings do not stop once the trial begins.
Interpretation of the rules of evidence and the amount of leeway given on issues
like hearsay, laying proper evidentiary foundations, relevance, prejudicial
effect, and to what extent, if at all, an expert witness can testify beyond the
material contained in the four-corners of his/her report are judicial opportu-
nities to impinge on the province of the jurors to decide a dispute, by limiting
or expanding what it is those jurors will hear as evidence in the case.
3. Rulings on the Use of Demonstratives and Graphics. Another arena for
judicial engineering is in the area of visual evidence: whether graphics or
190 Judging as Specialized Activity
American Bar Association, is warranted and can alter the language of the
charge in subtle but important ways that determine the likelihood of a verdict
or a mistrial.
Posttrial
Through posttrial motionsJNOV (Judgment Notwithstanding the
Verdict), Motions for a New Trial, and Motions to Modify Damagesthe
trial court can nullify the jurys conclusion or alter it substantiallyfor
example, by significantly reducing damages. At the extreme, such decisions
have the potential to nullify not only the jury decision, but also to nullify the
litigants right to a jury trial.
It is obvious from this partial listing of discretion points that most of the
decisions made in this context offer the trial judge a great deal of discretion to
engineer process, content, and outcome probabilities with limited appellate
guidance or threat of appellate reversal, a condition that maximizes the
potential for variation in judges behavior and the extralegal correlates of
this behavior and demonstrates the importance of research that helps us
understand judicial behavior in this context. We next propose a theoretical
framework that we believe will most effectively guide inquiry into judicial
engineering of jury trials.
Theoretical Framework
In this section we outline a proposed theoretical framework for a research
program that focuses on the behavior of trial judges in jury disputes and the
extralegal influences on that behavior. At first blush, one would expect our
proposal to focus research on judicial behavior in natural settings to rely on
theories of judicial behavior associated with political inquiry into extralegal
influences on federal judges in natural settings. Unfortunately, with a few
notable exceptions (Baum, 2006a; Rowland & Carp, 1996; Braman, 2006b),
most of these studies have been either atheoretical or have relied rather
uncritically on adaptation of preference-based theories and rational-choice
models of strategic decision making (Epstein & Knight, 2000; Baum, 2006)
developed in the context of appellate judicial behavior (Carp & Rowland,
1983; Buchman, 2007). Although political scholars have engaged in a healthy
debate regarding the extent to which judges voting their preferences may
be bounded by institutional constraints (Baum, 2006; Epstein & Knight,
1998), their common assumption is that, to the extent possible under institu-
tional constraints, judges are motivated by their policy preferences and their
votes are strategic reflections of these preferences. Indeed, two of the leading
scholars in the field have speculated that when judges explain their decisions
192 Judging as Specialized Activity
Rowland and Carp (1996) took a first step in this direction a decade ago. We
started with the premise that any useful theory of trial judging had to
reconcile the anomaly outlined abovethat is, how trial judges decisions,
at least in their published opinions, could be predicted with remarkable
accuracy by extralegal, ideology-driven variables when these same judges,
including judges who acknowledged and were sensitive to their own policy
predilections, insisted that their decisions were based on unbiased legal
reasoning subject to the constraints imposed by the law and the facts before
them (Baum, 1997). To accommodate this apparent anomaly, we turned to
social psychology and adapted concepts from social cognition and social
judgment theory to create an eclectic, rather primitive, general model of
trial judging based on the assumption that trial judges, like jurors, are
cognitive misers who, when faced with ambiguous decision criteria that
exceed their cognitive capacity to resolve episodically, must process the
evidence via existing schemata and rely on judgment heuristicsfor example,
the availability heuristic. Motives, according to this formulation, were essen-
tially irrelevant in the context of judgment tasks whose complexity and
ambiguity forced trial judges, like all human judges, to rely on cognitive
Every Jury Trial Is a Bench Trial 193
strike plaintiffs scientific evidence and witnesses than are the appointees of
Democratic presidents.
In sum, models of motivated reasoning predict that when human judges,
with or without robes, are faced with difficult decisions and discretionary
decision criteria, the interface between accuracy and directional goals, and
cognitive illusion is complex and situational. Moreover, these goals and the
interface between them should be especially salient where, as in the case of
jury disputes, well-defined alternative accuracy and directional outcomes are
often argued in briefs or motions and verbally in open court, as in the court
should do (directional) because (accuracy). However, to maximize the
utility of these models for trial judging in jury disputes, we propose an
extension of motivated reasoning in trial judges to include a third potential
set of goals and an elevated attention to the audiences associated with trial
judges and trial judging.
Administrative Goals
As with many political actors, all trial judges are subjected to important
time constraints on their discretion as gatekeepers and judicial engineers,
and on their pursuit of accuracy goals. All are expected by their appel-
late and administrative principals to manage their docket, and to
achieve a case disposition rate that does not overburden their peers or
deny a speedy trial to litigants. Indeed, since many states have adopted
unified systems of judicial administration, federal and state judges case
disposition records are published and evaluated annually (Administrative
Office, annual). The most important and obvious incentive created by
administrative goals is the incentive to settle cases. Nothing wreaks more
havoc with a trial judges case backlog than a long jury trial, or series of
jury trials, each of which is recorded at the end of the trial as one case
resolution. Nothing alleviates this problem more than a settlement or
dismissal, both of which are typically also recorded as one case disposi-
tion. Therefore, if models of Motivated Reasoning are adapted to studies
of participation of trial judges in jury trials, we believe they should direct
specific attention to the relative influence of administrative as well as
accuracy and directional goals. Having said this, we recognize that admin-
istrative goals could in theory be accommodated by a judges directional
goal setthat is, rapid case disposition as desired direction. However, this
is qualitatively different from motivation to arrive at a particular sub-
stantive conclusion. Moreover, as with plea bargaining in the criminal
context, these administrative goals are, of course, shared by judges of
diverse policy predispositions and may dominate other directional goals
and accuracy goals, especially when judges are faced with external case-
disposition pressures. These administrative goals may conflict with sub-
stantive directional goals because the desire to move his/her docket may
conflict with a judges desired substantive outcome, and with accuracy
196 Judging as Specialized Activity
Audience
In our adaptation of motives to jury disputes, we expect that the trial judge
involved in a jury dispute will have multiple motives, and that the absolute
and relative salience of the three motive sets will vary significantly among
jurisdictions, among judges within jurisdictions, and among dispute categories.
Moreover, we believe that the relative saliency of each motive will be influenced
by the relative importance of multiple audiences to the judge. Larry Baum
has introduced this important concept of audiences to the general study of
judicial behavior (Baum, 1997, 2006).
Borrowing heavily from psychological models of self-presentation, Baum
assumes, axiomatically:
1. People want to be liked and respected by others who are
important to them;
2. The desire to be liked and respected affects peoples behavior;
3. In these respects, robes notwithstanding, judges are people.
For Baum, potentially important judicial audiences are numerous, ran-
ging from appellate justices, to the general public, to members of the
executive and legislative branches, to social and professional groups, to
the media. Thus, some audiences, which we will label task audiences,
may be important for professional validation, while others, which we will
call expressive audiences, may be important for elevating the individuals
self-esteem. For our purposes, audiences may be divided analytically into
accuracy, administrative, and directional audiences. However, the
distinction among these audience types is frequently blurred, and all three
types of audiences may be important influences on judicial engineering of
jury disputes.
Baums adaptation of a multiple audience perspective to judicial set-
tings is particularly helpful for inquiry into the behavior of trial judges in jury
disputes. Because judicial decisions are a special case of expressive choice
their decisions link judges to particular values and to others who share those
values. . . . By taking positions, judges align themselves implicitly with groups
whose positions are consistent with theirs (2006, p. 47). Moreover, trial
judges at jury trials arguably have more potential audiences than do judges
higher in the judicial hierarchy. Second, the importance of audience and
audience approval may be more important for trial judges than for their
appellate brethren. For example, the importance of audience is most apparent
Every Jury Trial Is a Bench Trial 197
in jurisdictions where judges are elected, where the electorate and sources of
campaign support are crucial audiences. Indeed, in the course of a jury trial,
representatives from multiple audiences, including sources of electoral
success or failure, are present in the courtroom and are eyewitnesses to
many of the crucial public decisions that make a jury trial a bench trial.
Finally, the context of jury disputes also enhances the potential importance
of audience relative to appellate settings. Whether at pretrial hearings or
during trial, the judge must make judgments and justify those judgments
face-to-face with audiencesranging from law-school classmates, to impor-
tant donors, to officers in the state bar associationswhose success or failure
may depend on those judgments.
In our adaptation of audience to judicial engineering of jury disputes,
we expect that the trial judge involved in a jury dispute will have multiple
audiences; that the quantity and qualitative importance of these audiences
will vary significantly among jurisdictions, among judges within jurisdic-
tions, and across disputes. We expect that this variation in audience will
help explain variation in jury-dispute judgments, including the reasons
given for these judgments, and we expect that variation in audiences will
interact with variation among accuracy, directional, and administrative
goals in ways that help us understand variation in judicial behavior in jury
disputes.
Methodological Opportunities
Although the juror track has produced more methodological sophistication
and variety than has the judicial/political approach to the study of judicial
behavior, both tracks have relied almost exclusively on quantitative methods
of analyzing their data, whatever the datas source. Indeed, this emphasis on
quantification is an important part of what distinguishes social science
scholarship in this area from traditional legal analysis. In this section we
propose an extension of quantitative methods to the study of judicial engi-
neering in jury disputes; however, we also outline some important opportu-
nities created for a sophisticated application of underutilized qualitative
methods.
Qualitative Methods
Applications of quantitative methods in current scholarship have established at
high levels of confidence that, for disputes that are politically salient and offer
judges sufficient discretion, trial judges can vary significantly in their responses
to similar disputes and that this variation correlates significantly with key
value-based background variation, such as the judge and his/her appointing
presidents support for, or opposition to, a womans right to choose. The most
198 Judging as Specialized Activity
recent efforts in this area have included logistic regression models, which have
helped us understand the relative influence of value-based variables and other
variables, including institutional variables (Buchman, 2007). Scholars working
in the law and psychology tradition have appropriately quantified findings
ranging from descriptive analysis of survey responses (Gatowski et al., 2001) to
aggregative comparison of judge-juror decision proclivities (Hersch & Viscusi,
2004), to multivariate analysis of data from experimental designs (Robbennolt,
2005). Each of these methodologies, including quantification of results, has
obvious and potentially productive application to studies of judicial engi-
neering of jury disputes. For example, one particularly intriguing possibility
is an experimental design reversing aspects of judge-jury comparisonsfor
example, how do retired judges rule on Daubert motions when viewing alter-
native argumentation or offered alternative information regarding the identi-
ties of the parties. However, we believe that the research program proposed
here also creates some important opportunities to benefit from underutilized
qualitative approaches.
A research program that examines judicial behavior in the context of jury
disputes, especially if framed in ways that respect judges own descriptions of
their judgments and the reasoning underlying those judgments, creates a rich
set of unmined opportunities for harvesting insights available via qualitative
analysis. Three exemplar avenues of opportunity are:
Eileen Braman
This essay is about constraint in legal decision making: how we should con-
ceptualize it, how we should study it, and why psychological theory and
methods provide such a promising avenue for doing so. I treat constraint as a
democratic good, necessary to justify the distributional decisions of unelected
judges and as an empirical question: Does meaningful constraint exist? If so,
where are we likely to find it? What are the potential sources of constraint in
legal decision making? Asking these questions should lead to what I hope will be
the next generation of empirical research on legal reasoning involving a wealth
of theoretically based questions of interest to scholars in numerous disciplines.
Constraint itself is defined as something that limits the freedom to act
spontaneously; or some physical, moral or other force that compels some-
body to do something or limits their freedom of action. When legal types talk
about constraint they are usually referring to professional norms and/or
obligations that require judicial actors to use legal presumptions, rules and
authority in reaching decisions.1 Traditional legal approaches hold that the
reasoned use of these tools will often compel particular outcomes.
The argument for requiring that decision makers use and cite accepted
sources of authority is at least twofold. First, where judges use their training to
apply the logic set forth in sources of legal reasoning, they are encouraged to
think about specific disputes in light of generally applicable rules and larger
societal values that legislative actors and other judges have deemed applicable
in similar circumstances. In this way referencing legal considerations helps
imbue judicial decisions with continuity and predictability. Second, judges
utilizing tools of legal reasoning are prevented from calling on their own
203
204 Judging as Specialized Activity
are studies employing content analyses (Tetlock, Bernzweig, & Gallant, 1985;
Gruenfeld, 1995) and experiments (Guthrie, Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2001;
Braman, 2006a; Furgeson, Babcock, & Shane, 2008b; Braman & Nelson,
2007) to understand aspects of legal decision-making behavior.
Also, we may have to move away from analyzing final case votes toward
discrete choices judges make in the process of legal reasoning in order to get a
realistic idea of how and where constraint operates in their decision making.
For instance, judges make many component decisions in the context of
deciding a case: what issue is determinative? Does a particular statute
govern? Is a cited precedent applicable or can it be distinguished from the
current case? Understanding how the law shapes these discrete choices seems
an important aspect of investigating how decision makers are or are not
constrained by controlling authority.
could imagine that decision makers are more able to comply with this
presumption in some types of cases (i.e., white collar vs. violent crime) or
more skeptically, with regard to some type of individuals (class or race based
differences in ability to apply the presumption). Experimental techniques
might help us understand if decision makers fall short of making required
assumptions and where they are especially likely to do so.
Prospect theory, especially as it relates to status quo bias, can help us
theorize about the application of presumptions in legal decision making.8
Psychological research reveals that the price at which people are willing to sell
things that already belong to them is typically higher than the price they
would be willing to pay to acquire them. This endowment effect (Knetch,
2000) seems especially important to the aspect of constraint requiring deci-
sion makers to apply presumptions in the context of thinking about legal
disputes. For instance, one of the most famous axioms in legal academia is the
Coase Theorem: in the absence of transaction costs it does not matter to
whom a right is initially assigned because the parties will be able to bargain
efficiently and it will wind up in the hands of whoever values it most (and is
therefore willing to pay to get it). Introducing endowment effects may
complicate matters significantly. If sellers attribute some unstated value to
simply possessing an objectbuyers who actually value that item more
may not be able or willing to meet their terms to acquire it. This endowment
effect is kind of a surcharge not adequately encompassed by the theory.
Moreover, it is not clear if the endowment effect for owning some objects (for
example, real property) is greater than the endowment effect for owning other
objects (for example, cups and penswhich is what much of the experi-
mental research on this topic has involved). One could hypothesize that the
endowment effect could be more of an obstacle for some types of Coasean
transactions than others.
Also, it is not clear whether there are third-party, observer, endowment
effects that might be relevant for judges adjudicating disputes concerning the
allocation of rights and resources. Are judges able to do the mental acrobatics
required of them if presumptions call for them to consider counterfactuals
that are at odds with the status quo? How, if at all, does who currently possesses
a right or resource influence their seemingly objective decision processes? For
instance, law students commonly study water rights in Property classes. In
western states, where water is scarce, a common presumption in this area of
the law is prior appropriation, the first person to use water from some
natural source acquires priority rights to that source against later users.
Often junior appropriators divert water from the beneficial use of land
owners with superior right to a particular source for several years before such
conflicts become the subject of litigation. How does the current state of affairs
influence the decisions of judges and/or juries in such matters?
Finally, presumptions are especially important in motion practice. As
discussed more fully in the essay by Rowland, Traficanti, and Vernon in this
volume (ch. 12), motions represent a highly significant aspect of legal
Searching for Constraint in Legal Decision Making 211
with respect to the degree of attitudinal influence and variance across decision
makers. If conventional wisdom is right, decision makers in the rule condi-
tion should be less influenced by their attitudes and there should be less
variance across decision makers within that condition.9 Regardless of what
the findings show, this sort of experiment would tell us something very
interesting about the confining influence of different decision criteria that
have been a subject of substantial interest in legal discourse.
Conclusion
This is an exciting time in the development of our knowledge of legal decision
making and the constraints that act on judges engaged in the task. Part of this
excitement is because of the important implications these findings have for
216 Judging as Specialized Activity
Notes
1. There are, of course, also contextual sources of constraint in our legal system
including the group nature of appellate review and accountability mechanisms.
I will deal with these more fully later in the essay.
2. See Braman and Nelson (2007) for a detailed critique of extant operationaliza-
tions of the constraining influence of precedent:
For a variety of reasons, the Supreme Court is perhaps the least likely
place to detect the powerful gravitational pull of cited authority.
Because the Supreme Court sits atop our judicial hierarchy, justices
are not subject to the constant threat of review that may serve to
heighten accuracy goals for lower court judges. Moreover, the
Supreme Court has the ability to overrule itself. Lower court judges
must follow binding authority without explicit license to change or
ignore higher court rulings. Many of the justices on the Supreme
Court see themselves as high-profile representatives of a specific
jurisprudential approach (Baum 2006), and are thus unlikely to back
away from public statements about how the law should be applied in
prior dissenting or concurring opinions. Thus, tests of constraint that
have been applied to the Supreme Court set an exceedingly high bar,
and may not be appropriate to assess the influence of precedent more
generally.
3. See Braman (2004, pp. 4552) Braman and Nelson (2007, p. 942) regarding top
down versus bottom up theories of attitudinal influence in legal decision
making on why this is important distinction. See also Bartels (this volume, ch.
3) Top-Down and Bottom-Up Models of Judicial Reasoning.
4. Gillman (2001) writes, [I]f some contemporary positivists are willing to make
empirical claims about the determinate influence of rules, then it is not unrea-
sonable for scholars such as Spaeth and Segal to ask them to formulate those
claims in ways that allow for hypothesis testing (Gillman 2001, p. 486). That is
what I attempt to do here.
5. I do not mean to imply that empirical studies have been blind to the influence of
legal factors in models of decision making (Segal, 1984 [search and seizure];
Songer & Haire, 1992 [obscenity cases]; Gryski, Main, & Dixon, 1986 [sex
discrimination]) but where such factors are treated as control variables that
improve our attitudinal predictions (i.e., Segal & Spaeth, 1993) their influence
tends to be obscured.
Searching for Constraint in Legal Decision Making 217
6. Significantly, altruism (as I have defined it) may be less of a motivating factor at
the Supreme Court, where researchers have actually looked at this question
especially if one assumes that litigants who get to our highest court are likely to
be relatively well represented.
7. See also, Nelson, Maruska, and Braman (2002) for an analysis of how alternative
argument frames can influence lay perceptions of important issues in litigation.
8. The challenge Kahneman and Tverskys (1979) theory of decision under risk
poses to purely rational models of decision making has been realized and
acknowledged across multiple disciplines. Legal scholars have shown through
their own experimental techniques that magistrate judges, like ordinary people,
can be subject to framing effects in choosing between settlement options
(Guthrie, Rachlinski, & Wistrich, 2001).
9. I have yet to come up with a psychological theory to express this expectation
that seems almost intuitive to legally trained individuals. It might be an example
of the kind of decision domain where there is no psychological theory that
neatly corresponds with conventional legal wisdom.
10. For instance, decision makers who will be held accountable tend to overem-
phasize the importance of irrelevant information; this is commonly referred to
as the dilution effect.
11. Moreover, where judges have a prior record of deciding cases in a certain way,
memorialized in written opinions accounting for prior decisions, consistency
motives (Abelson et al., 1968) are likely to kick in and act as a further constraint
on decisional behavior.
This page intentionally left blank
Part III
EVALUATING AND IMPROVING JUDGING
This page intentionally left blank
14
Evaluating Judges
Gregory Mitchell
221
222 Evaluating and Improving Judging
experts in the administration of law takes the sting out of arguments to limit
judicial review and give greater power to the legislature and executive.
Likewise, to the extent that the legitimacy of the courts and their ability to
motivate voluntary compliance with the law derives from the popular view of
the courts as detached from ordinary political processes (Tyler & Mitchell,
1994), evidence that judges are just political actors in robes should undercut
the legitimacy of the courts. However, these arguments should lose steam if
existing studies into the descriptive-normative gap are far from compelling,
as I contend they are.
From a prescriptive perspective, reliable knowledge about the descriptive-
normative gap is needed to understand where judicial incompetence exists so
that we may attempt to correct it.3 If judicial behavior systematically deviates
from legal norms in some domains, then steps may need to be taken to rein
in this predictably unlawful behavior. If judicial behavior commonly, but
randomly, deviates from legal norms in other domains, then steps may need
to be taken to eliminate chance influences in these domains.4 If judicial
behavior proves unresponsive to prescriptive interventions in these domains,
then the legal norm, or the task to which the norm is to be applied, should be
reconsidered on grounds that ought implies can. If some types of judges
perform better than others under consensual norms, then we can evaluate
whether our preconceptions of the personal qualities and training associated
with competent judging are correct and gain valuable information about
whether the judicial selection process should be altered.
By suggesting the many different standards that may be used to examine
judicial competence and by suggesting the limits of the usual comparison
focused on law versus politics (between attitudinal-type models and simple
legal models of judicial behavior5), I hope to encourage the debate to move
beyond characterizations of judges as driven primarily by ideology or law (for
a more comprehensive effort in this regard, see Baum, 2006). At all levels of
the judiciary, judges political attitudes undoubtedly play some role in their
judgments and decisions, but many other aspects of a judges psychological
make-up and of the social-psychological setting in which a judge acts will be
influential as well, with some of these influences pushing the judge toward
idealized normative behavior and some pushing the judge away from judicial
ideals. Gaining a more sophisticated understanding of when and why judges
deviate from various judicial norms should provide a better understanding of
potential sources of judicial legitimacy or illegitimacy and aid in the important
task of developing prescriptive models of judicial behavior.
treat deviation from judicial social norms as a reason in and of itself for
criticizing a judges behavior.8
Moral norms, as I use the term here, encompass any norm derived from a
theory of justice or ethical obligations. Legal scholars often use moral norms
to evaluate individual judicial decisions (see Posner, 1999), but these studies
typically dispute the normative status of the law by recourse to moral arguments
rather than describe judicial behavior. Several empirical studies examine the
degree to which parties or citizens in general perceive judges and the courts to
be acting justly or to be allocating outcomes justly (e.g., Tyler & Huo, 2002;
Tyler & Mitchell, 1994). Procedural justice norms are an important source for
evaluation, but they typically are used in connection with efficacy norms as
discussed below. Other than procedural and distributive justice norms, few
empirical studies of judging evaluate judges against moral norms as defined
here (except with respect to selected decisions).
Legal norms for present purposes are norms established by an author-
itative governmental body, including constitutional, statutory, and adminis-
trative law and judge-made common law, to bind public and private
institutions and the persons running and governed by these institutions.
The power of courts to clarify, establish, or alter legal norms complicates
matters from an empirical perspective, for it means that in some instances it is
legitimate for a court to ignore, alter, or invalidate one norm to resolve
conflict with another norm (as may occur through judicial review or
common law development) or to embellish a norm (as may occur through
legislative or constitutional interpretation). Uncertainty about what counts as
law or binding legal norms likewise complicates matters (e.g., Hart, 1961), as
we have seen with recent disputes about the role of foreign law in U.S. courts
(e.g., Rahdert, 2007; see generally Shapiro, 2007).
Accordingly, a secondary set of legal norms has developed to govern
interpretive practices and to establish a hierarchy of precedent and deference
to guide superior and inferior courts, future panels of the same court, and
branches of the government as they sort out the content of legal norms and
the obligatory status of these norms. For instance, the norm of rationality
review within constitutional law provides that a legislative act with some
conceivable purpose behind it should be upheld by the courts.9 It is often this
secondary set of interpretive and role norms that serve as the primary legal
norms in comparisons of actual to ideal judicial behavior (e.g., Segal &
Spaeth, 2002, operationalize the legal model of judicial behavior as
requiring fidelity to the plain meaning of statutory or constitutional text, to
the legislative or constitutional drafters intent, and to precedent).
Coherence norms, including norms of rationality, require logical consis-
tency and coherence in the formation and ordering of beliefs and preferences,
whatever those beliefs or preferences may be:
technical discussions of rationality generally adopt a logical
conception, in which an individuals beliefs and preferences are said
Evaluating Judges 227
General Complications
The process of choosing a normative standard and applying it to judicial
behavior presents predictable complications, some more difficult than others.
First, the researcher must decide whether to take an internal or external
normative perspective. From an internal perspective, the researcher asks the
judge (or otherwise determines, perhaps through the judges opinions) what
goal he or she was trying to achieve, selects the proper evaluative norm given
that goal, and compares behavior to the norm to measure degree of success or
compliance with the norm.13 An external perspective asks what goal the judge
should be trying to achieve and applies norms proper to those goals; no effort
is made to gain judicial input on proper normative standards. An external
perspective may be justified from a metatheoretical stance about the proper
role of judges within the legal hierarchy or from the perspective of interested
parties subject to the authority or influence of the courts (e.g., litigants may
hope that judges decisions are legal, just, and accurate). Or the external
perspective may be chosen simply to test some theory about the degree to
which judicial behavior, whether intentionally or not, accords with particular
normative standards.
The choice of norms is crucial, because different norms will often point
to different conclusions about competence. A judge presented with inadequate
evidence at trial may irrationally convict the truly guilty defendant, while
another judge presented with this inadequate evidence may rationally acquit
the truly guilty defendant. The first judge did a good job under the corre-
spondence standard but a poor job under the coherence standard, and
conversely with respect to the competence of the second judge. Hence, the
choice of normative criteria controls the assessment of the judges competence
on particular tasks.
It may be that the judge was capable of providing the normative response
the researcher is testing for, but the judge had different values or concerns than
the researcher assumed or intended and these other concerns overwhelmed
the judges interest in applying the norm of the researchers choice. In such a
230 Evaluating and Improving Judging
case, it is not that the judge has misunderstood her task or role nor that biases
drove the judges behavior, but rather that there is a mismatch between the
task or role as the researcher perceives it and as the judge perceives it. In some
instances, being perceived as logical, consistent, legally principled, or fair-
minded may be less important to the judge than achieving some other goal
(e.g., moral and public policy concerns may override base rate information in
determining liability14), and, in other instances, the researcher may have
mistaken beliefs about the judges goals or beliefs in light of the larger social
setting. In these latter cases, where the researcher simply misconstrues the
judges beliefs or goals but the judges behavior is logical in light of her true
goals or beliefs, then we cannot say that the behavior is irrational under a
coherence standard if that is our normative perspective of choice.
Unifunctionalist tunnel vision blinds the research community to empirical
and normative boundary conditions on basic effects. Inconvenient though it is,
people are multifunctional entities that demand cumbersomely complex expla-
nations (Tetlock, 2002, p. 469).15 Even within the confines of a theory of the role
of a judge, much room exists for different conceptions of the judges proper
functions. Thus, a narrow view of behavior may reveal departures from the
coherence definition of rationality, but a broader view of the same behavior may
reveal a larger purpose that makes this lack of coherence look instrumentally
rational and that confounds conclusions that the irrationality was due to
cognitive bias.16
Existing discussions of judicial competence typically employ externally
determined measures of competence, rather than internally determined mea-
sures based on the judges self-chosen goals or norms. Because we are usually
interested in how judges fulfill their roles within the larger legal-institutional
setting, it is fair to impose values and goals on the judge that he or she might
not endorse or that might even be contrary to the judges own goals or
valuesalthough sharp disparities between internal and external normative
perspectives should be rare if the judge deems her legal system legitimate
and the researcher accurately perceives the goals of the legal system.17
Nevertheless, a finding of external incompetence does not necessarily mean
that the judge was incompetent from an internal perspective; it only means
that the judge failed to meet an externally imposed normative standard.
Indeed, a judge may be judged externally incompetent precisely because the
judge is quite competent at achieving a goal that is internally desirable but
undesirable from an institutional, external standpoint.
Second, because there may be dispute about the goals that should be
served by certain tasks or because the judge may need to serve multiple goals,
the researcher may need to employ multiple, possibly conflicting normative
criteria or justify her choice of some normative criteria to the exclusion of
others (for more on this topic, see the chapter by Robbennolt, MacCoun, &
Darley in this volume).18 Otherwise, the research may be dismissed as irrelevant
or be disputed on grounds of incompleteness.19 Absent an agreed ranking of
values and norms, however, contending factions may exalt or impugn judicial
Evaluating Judges 231
Legal Norms
Many empirical studies of judicial competence employ perfect lawfulness
as the normative standard: Do extralegal factors affect judicial decisions that
ideally should turn solely on what the law and legally relevant facts of the
case dictate? The numerous studies by political scientists into the correla-
tion of Supreme Court justices political attitudes with the direction of case
votes on judicial decisions employ this normative standard (e.g., Unah &
Hancock, 2006). Most prominently, Segal and Spaeth (2002) contrast
their attitudinal model of Supreme Court judicial decision-making with
what they call the legal model, which is supposed to represent how a
law-bound ruling would be made (through fidelity to text, drafters intent,
or existing precedent), and they find that justices political attitudes relate
significantly to patterns of votes on cases.20 They conclude that the legal
model and its components serve only to rationalize the Courts decisions
232 Evaluating and Improving Judging
and to cloak the reality of the Courts decision-making process (Segal &
Spaeth, 2002, p. 53).
There are considerable limitations to the use of perfect lawfulness as the
normative standard. First, the norm is typically just in the air and does not
serve as a source for direct comparison. In these studies, the normative
position of perfect lawfulness at best serves as the null hypothesis, and any
measured extralegal variable that is statistically related to case outcomes leads
to a rejection of the null hypothesis. In Segal and Spaeths (2002) main tests of
the attitudinal model of judicial decision making, there is no direct comparison
between judicial decisions and the predictions of any specific instantiation of
the legal model. Rather, Segal and Spaeth, after finding that ideology can
explain some significant percentage of variance in judicial decisions, simply
assume that this finding contradicts what a legal model would predict.
Of course, to the extent a legal model would predict absolutely no
influence of justices attitudes, then the legal model is contradicted, but I
am aware of no legal model that would predict that liberals and conservatives
would perfectly agree on the controlling legal norm in all Supreme Court
cases. Indeed, I am aware of no single legal model or set of coherent legal
norms that all conservative scholars and judges would agree on as the correct
approach, nor that liberal elites would similarly agree on, and I suspect that
many politically conservative and politically liberal elites would disagree over
the proper outcome in many Supreme Court cases from even a narrowly self-
interested, purely political perspective.21 In other words, Segal and Spaeths
support for the attitudinal model certainly casts into doubt perfect lawfulness
as an accurate description of judicial behavior, but the degree of deviation
from this vague standard goes unspecified, and, given competition over
what perfect lawfulness requires across cases, interpretations of a particular
outcome as reflecting inappropriate policy preferences or principled disagree-
ments between liberals and conservatives as to what the law requires in
particular cases will often be contestable.22
This last point is not a minor quibble with political science studies of the
Supreme Court. If a conservative judge can choose among legally principled
courses C1, C2, and C3 to reach the conservative result that he politically
prefers, but if the judge feels constrained by legal norms to choose C1 over the
other two options, then this constraint is significant if writing the opinion
pursuant to C1, as opposed to pursuant to C2 or C3, has effects on the lower
courts and later Supreme Court decisions (see Richards & Kritzer, 2002; see
also Friedman, 2006; Hansford & Spriggs, 2006).
Second, because these studies almost invariably test for an extralegal
influence rather than compliance with a legal norm, a finding that the variable
of interest is not significantly related to judicial behavior tells us little about
judicial competence other than that this variable, in this study, did not exert
any influence. It may be the case that judges were acting pursuant to the
normative standard, that the wrong extralegal influences were investigated, or
that some other norm or feature of the institution or situation other than the
Evaluating Judges 233
the legal norm not existed?). How an opinion is written may have more
lasting influence on the behavior of other courts as well as that of lawyers and
parties than the particular outcome of a case (Hansford & Spriggs, 2006); so it
is no small matter if norms constrain opinions without altering outcomes
(Richards & Kritzer, 2002). Whereas legal scholars may give too much
explanatory weight to the reasons stated in opinions, the tendency to ignore
the reasons stated and focus on case outcomes and external motives greatly
restricts the usefulness and acceptance of empirical judicial studies by judges
and lawyers.
Stated another way, if one of the goals of empirical judicial studies is to
predict how judges will act and rule under specified conditions rather than
assess normative compliance (see Leiter, 1997), then disregard of the text of
statutes and cases constitutes a curious omission unless the prediction game is
confined only to how a particular courtmost notably the Supreme Court
will rule on a case once the judges hearing the case are known. Attorneys
cannot play the prediction game in that truncated manner because they must
often advise clients before the ideology of the whole series of judges who may
ultimately hear a case is known. Accordingly, attorneys must look to existing
case law and the text of statutes and regulations to predict how a generic judge
would rule and advise their clients accordingly. Until studies demonstrate
convincingly that looking to these documentary sources of the law is pointless
to predict judicial behavior outside the Supreme Court, attorneys will continue
to do so for lack of any better guidance on predicting how the law will be
applied. Furthermore, when the prediction game is really a multilevel predic-
tion game with tremendous uncertainty (trial judge A will rule this way, but
appellate judges X, Y, & Z are likely to rule that way assuming X, Y, & Z are
assigned to the case. . . ), it is unclear whether any rational attorney, ex ante,
should look more to judicial ideology than the law to advise her client.
Coherence Norms
There are, of course, many coherence norms other than legal norms that we
may want judges to follow. Axioms of rational choice, rules of logic and
probability, hypothesis-testing rules, and Bayes formula for updating beliefs
are the most common coherence norms employed in behavioral decision
theory studies.26 Many legal norms, such as interpretive rules and the rules of
Evaluating Judges 237
evidence, clearly allow room for other coherence norms to operate. In general,
the more closely a judge follows norms of rationality, logic, and probability,
the more consistent and predictable her behavior should be and the more
likely the judge will maximize the values she deems most important.
In the abstract, the notion that judges and jurors should act rationally
when evaluating the law and evidence in a case is uncontroversial, and
therefore proof from psychology of apparently rampant irrationality under-
standably commands the attention of legal scholars (as Saks & Kidd, 1980,
noted many years ago). In some ways, this evidence should be more troubling
to positive political theorists and others who advocate rational choice models
of judicial decision-making as explanatory models of actual judicial behavior
(e.g., Epstein & Knight, 1998; Schanzenbach & Tiller, 2006) than to scholars
examining judicial behavior for the size of the descriptive-normative gap. For
there are a host of other norms that we may care equally about from an
external perspective that do not require strict compliance with norms of
rationality. Indeed, to the extent that systematic deviations from rationality
are caused by cognitive and motivational mechanisms that have evolved or
are used to serve alternative goals than those served within the closed rationality
system under observation (e.g., efficiency in processing at acceptable levels of
accuracy [Hammond, 2000b] or attributing greater causal responsibility to
persons than rationally justified to encourage care and deter excuse-making
[Tetlock, 2000]), then we should expect deviations from rationality to accom-
pany satisfactory performance under alternative normative standards.
Nevertheless, whether judges, given their experience, training, and the
decision aids available to them, comply with norms of causal hypothesis
testing, probability and rationality is of interest from an external normative
perspective because this information may lead to prescriptive models of
judging. We now know that several predictable judgmental biases can be
debiased (Heath et al., 1998; Larrick, 2004), and we know that the structure of
some environments ameliorates or exacerbates some biases (see Mitchell,
2002b, 2003b). We also know that there are individual differences in ration-
ality, a topic addressed in other chapters in this volume (see generally
Mitchell, 2003b; Stanovich, 1999). Identifying the norms that judges have
the greatest difficulty following and identifying the characteristics of more
and less rational judges may lead to feasible prescriptive models for legal
reform.
Tests of norms of rationality and probability will look like many of the
tests of legal norms, because all are coherence norms. Thus, if a norm of
rationality directs the judge to ignore outcomes and focus only on ex ante
information available to the parties to assess their behavior, we will test
whether the judge can ignore these improper influences (see Rachlinski,
1998). Where the norm directs that certain information should be consid-
ered, such as base rate evidence in assessing the probative value of evidence,
we will test whether the judge properly uses this information. Experimental
tests allow the cleanest tests of judges abilities to engage in analytical thought
238 Evaluating and Improving Judging
and comply with norms of rationality, but testing judges outside their natural
environments may lead us to worry more than we should about the harms
associated with laboratory normative deviations (Gigerenzer, 2006). Thus,
experimental tests should be seen as providing an important first step toward
understanding the rationality of judges and identifying possible normative
deviations, but that step should be followed by studies assessing how institutions
and individual judges adapt, if at all, to correct for such deviations.
Efficacy Norms
idea, see Goldberg, 2005; WERL, 2004). Traditional judicial studies, which
examine justices for ideological voting and typically contrast behavior to perfect
legality (or rather a norm of no ideological voting), often have data that can be
reported in tournament format (e.g., Segal & Spaeth, 2002, report the relative
influence of values on different justices votes), but the emphasis is on testing for
deviations from a specified norm or finding confirmation that some extralegal
factor influences judicial behavior. The emphasis in judicial tournaments is on the
relative ranking itself and, at least in Choi and Gulatis judicial tournaments, on
relative rankings derived from objectively measurable variables. This emphasis on
relative performance gives rise to a fundamental criticism of the tournament
approach: a relative ranking of judges fails to provide compelling evidence of
judicial competence absent some independent normative benchmark (e.g.,
Solum, 2005a): the winner may simply be the best judge in a tournament of
bad judges.
The skeptical response to this criticism is that relative standing on weakly
diagnostic objective measures of performance is the best we can do given the
contested nature of the concept of good judging and given the difficulties of
translating judicial votes and opinions into data. Under this view, any eva-
luative study of judges yields at best a relative ranking of judges according to
the researchers flawed theory or methodology, and hence we avoid at least
the problems of subjective judgment by employing objectively determined
rankings.
The ecumenical response is that relative standing yields useful information
about judicial competence along dimensions that may hold relevance for a
variety of conceptions of good judging, and perhaps provides definitive
information for some norms. A well-theorized selection of objective measures
can provide good, if imperfect, proxies for testing abstract norms of judicial
competence (e.g., some of Solums [2003, 2005a] thin judicial virtues may
be captured roughly by objective measures of ethics compliance, opinion
clarity, educational achievement, and productivity), and a number of objective
measures may approximate widely accepted conceptions of good judging
(e.g., most theorists would place a judge who writes her own opinions
above one who does not; Choi & Gulati, 2005). When the tourneys results
converge across multiple measures designed to get at the same qualities, then
we should have confidence that the tournament meaningfully and reliably
assesses qualities related to differential effort or ability at judging.
Furthermore, understanding how judges compare on objective measures
moves debate away from the mechanics of operationalizing independent and
dependent variables to a debate about the relevance of these and other
measures to notions of judicial competence (Choi and Gulatis tournaments
certainly motivated much fruitful debate in this regard; see Gey & Rossi,
2005). When objective measures identify sets of judges as high versus low
achievers, and alternative approaches to judicial competence yield different
outcomes, then understanding why the divergence occurs can only improve
theorizing about what constitutes good judging and how to identify it
Evaluating Judges 241
(e.g., Farber, 2005; Goldberg, 2005; WERL, 2004). For instance, on what
objective dimensions do Democrats and Republicans agree, and is such
agreement consistent with the attitudinal model of judges? Along what
objective dimensions other than voting behavior are liberal and conservative
judges predicted to act in an ideological fashion, and do they behave as
predicted (for one example along these lines, see Law, 2005)? And of
course, the judicial tournament need not involve only objective measures.
Many states systematically collect data on judicial performance, including
attorney and juror surveys of judicial demeanor and performance, and this
wealth of data, if made available to empiricists, could be readily adapted for
academic research and judicial tournaments in particular (see Kourlis &
Singer, 2007, on judicial performance evaluation programs).
The relative ranking approach to judicial competence may also proceed
in an atheoretical fashion to explore courts and areas of law for unexpected
patterns. For instance, are there consistent sets of characteristics associated
with judges on particular courts who perform well versus poorly on mundane
measures of productivity, influence, or reversal rates? Judicial tournaments
can identify the high and low achievers on such measures, who can then be
systematically studied for similarities and dissimilarities in their backgrounds
and situational settings that may account for these differences. Areas of law
that provide objectively determinable outcomes allow for the use of judicial
tournaments based on a correspondence norm: for instance, courts that
randomly assign criminal cases, and hence provide a natural control on
factual differences across cases, and that collect data on probation and
parole violations provide a setting for a judicial tournament involving the
ability of judges to discriminate between good and bad risks.
The judicial tournament, in short, presents a host of research opportunities
and should be seen as a necessary, but not sufficient, part of the judicial
competence research repertoire. The relative ease of conducting tournaments
based on objective measures compared to labor-intensive and debatable
coding of opinions and outcomes makes this tool a particularly valuable
one as judicial researchers seek to expand knowledge about judicial competence
beyond the U.S. Supreme Court.
The second popular alternative to traditional political science studies of
judicial competence is to focus on the possession of certain traits or qualities
rather than particular behaviors to determine judicial competence (e.g.,
Farber & Sherry, this volume, ch. 18). This dispositional approach risks
converting intuition into unproven tautology: wise judges will issue wise
decisions (because the desirable trait of wisdom means acting wisely). To
move beyond tautology, some justification needs to be provided for giving a
dispositional theory normative weight. Normative authority could arise from
agreement, as with a thin theory of judicial virtue, in which only uncon-
troversial traits that are desired in all judges are chosen (Solum, 2003). Or its
normative status could arise from showing that the dispositional theory of
judging derives from another theory that already enjoys normative status
242 Evaluating and Improving Judging
(e.g., Solum derives his virtue-centered theory of judging from virtue ethics),
or from empirical studies showing that other types of judges with particular
characteristics perform better and worse on various normative tests (for a
discussion of the concept of expertise and its application to judicial studies,
see the chapter in this volume by Shanteau & Dalgleish, ch. 16). Or the theory
could be justified through empirical observation (which appears to be the
basis for Sherrys [2005, 2006] views on the traits and experiences that
appellate judges should have or should not have; namely, in this last respect,
experience as an academic): if empirical observation reveals that judges who
possess qualities X, Y, and Z reliably produce excellent decisions, then these
qualities should be favored. The problem with this last approach is that it
simply moves the normative question to another point in the equation: we
will need justified normative standards for deciding whether the decisions of
these judges were indeed excellent.27
One interesting feature of character-based approaches to evaluating
judges is that, if one accepts the character traits chosen, then the evaluative
focus shifts to whether judges possess these traits and away from perfor-
mance. The task becomes measuring the traits of existing and potential judges
to evaluate them for good and bad judicial character.
From an empirical perspective, the measurement problems associated
with dispositional approaches to judicial evaluation are severe for judicial
traits of the kind Solum advances (abstract virtues and vices),28 but much less
so for judicial traits of the kind Sherry advances (at least for the experience-
based factors she argues for as proxies for the more abstract character traits
she ultimately favors). Consider a popular judicial trait within some disposi-
tional approaches: good judgment, which may go by a variety of labels, such
as wisdom or pragmatism (see Sherry, 2003).29 There is no single theory of
judicial pragmatism or judicial wisdom, and certainly no well-validated
measure of pragmatism or judicial wisdom. It may be difficult to distinguish
a pragmatic from a textualist outcome in a particular case (because, as Posner
[2005] notes, at times the pragmatic judge will adopt the textualist outcome),
but it will be near to impossible to distinguish a pragmatist from a textualist
from biographical material about judges (though Solum [2005b] disputes this
with respect to his proposed virtues and vices) (and, in any event, clinical
assessments of character are considerably less reliable than those based on
validated assessment tools, none of which exist for pragmatism). If a judges
opinions serve as the source for making determinations about the judges
pragmatic character, then we return to our tautology problem.30
Another interesting feature of these theories, and the most problematic
feature from a social-psychological perspective, is the assumption that judges
with ideal judicial character are more likely to follow the law strictly, wisely
interpret and apply the law, or, perhaps, do justice (whatever those terms
imply) than those without this character. While it is certainly the case that
individuals differ in important ways that may relate to judicial behavior (e.g.,
Tetlock et al., 1985), it is also the case that these individual difference variables
Evaluating Judges 243
Conclusion
Empirical evaluative studies of judges have historically been dominated by a
focus on the U.S. Supreme Court and a narrow debate about the degree to
which Supreme Court justices allow their personal preferences or political
values to influence their decisions. I have argued that these studies fail to
provide compelling evidence on the law versus politics debate as applied to
the Supreme Court, much less other courts, and these studies distract attention
from a host of other possible normative comparisons that judicial scholars
should care about, and from alternative empirical approaches that may be
more easily, or at least less controversially, implemented.
A diverse and robust literature on the normative-descriptive gap in
judgment and decision-making exists within psychology, and this literature
contains much healthy debate about the size, contours, and meaning of this
gap (see, e.g., Krueger & Funder, 2004). The insights and methods of this
literature are just starting to filter into empirical studies of judicial compe-
tence, and by explicating some of the norms utilized in this literature and
some of the methodological issues that evaluative studies present, this chapter
is meant to accelerate the rate of interdisciplinary exchange and encourage
diversification in evaluative studies. Trite though it now is to suggest that
judicial researchers should let a thousand empirical flowers bloom (given the
long history of invocation of this dictum within judicial studies; Maveety,
2003), this recommendation may have no more apt application within the
244 Evaluating and Improving Judging
Notes
1. I use the term competence to refer to a judges (degree of) compliance with a
normative standard (see Stein, 1996, for a similar usage). The term is meant to
have the same meaning here as the terms rational or irrational do in
psychological studies of the concordance of actual judgment and choice with
norms of rationality.
2. My primary and modest goal is to provide a framework for organizing empirical
questions about judicial competence, but I do venture some predictions and offer
some critical assessments of existing evaluative studies. For an extended discus-
sion of the difficulty in operationalizing good judgment for assessing the quality
of real world judgments, see chapter 1 in Tetlock (2005).
3. Within psychology, prescriptive models are distinguished from normative and
descriptive models of judgment and decision making. Normative models
supply the standards or rules for evaluating judgments; descriptive models
compare judgments to the normative models; prescriptive models specify the
conditions under which judgments can be brought more into line with the
normative models (see Baron, 2004).
4. These random deviations constitute mere performance errors, whereas sys-
tematic deviations would suggest an underlying incompetence (Stein, 1996).
Both may need attention, but likely different sorts of attention.
5. Of course, not all political scientists embrace the strict attitudinalist view and
very few legal scholars embrace a strict legalistic view. Segal and Spaeths
influential framing of the debate in this way, however, surely has framed the
larger debate, for better or worse, and their strongly worded skeptical view of
the power of the law to constrain (e.g., Segal & Spaeth, 2002), or the modified
strategic view in which other political institutions but not the law constrain
judges (e.g., Epstein & Knight, 1998), now regularly serves as the starting
position within empirical quantitative studies of judicial behavior.
6. Segal and Spaeth (2002, pp. 289292) assimilate Casey to their attitudinal model
and thus do not treat it as dissonant evidence.
7. Others may parse the norms differently; this particular categorization is used for
organizational purposes only and holds no special importance in the chapter.
8. The few works that do evaluate judges in relation to social norms usually involve
norms of secrecy and civility (e.g., Gaffney, 1994). Baum (2006) argues for greater
attention to collegiality as an important judicial motive, which might lead to a
greater emphasis on social norms and the degree to which judges comply with
them. Fischman (2008) presents interesting evidence that a norm of consensus
may significantly moderate individual judges policy preferences. For further
discussion of collegiality as an important influence on appellate judges behavior,
see the chapter by Martinek in this volume (ch. 5).
Evaluating Judges 245
9. See, e.g., FCC v. Beach Communications, Inc., 508 U.S. 307, 315 (1993): On
rational-basis review, a classification in a statute such as the Cable Act comes to
us bearing a strong presumption of validity, and those attacking the rationality
of the legislative classification have the burden to negative every conceivable
basis which might support it. Moreover, because we never require a legislature
to articulate its reasons for enacting a statute, it is entirely irrelevant for
constitutional purposes whether the conceived reason for the challenged dis-
tinction actually motivated the legislature (citations omitted). Whether
rationality review actually operates in this minimal, deferential form is the
subject of debate (see Farrell, 1999), but the standard does serve as a normative
baseline.
10. Technically, legal norms are a subcategory of coherence norms because they
constitute a closed system of rules to be followed without regard to some
independent measure of the quality of system outputs. The goals are deter-
mined by the body that promulgates the legal norms, and the legal norms are
designed to produce outputs in line with the desired goals. Legal norms are thus
analogous to scientific norms: scientific principles for conducting empirical
research, if followed, should lead to reliable empirical knowledge; the scientific
status of research is determined by its fidelity to scientific principles rather than
the reliability or truth of the knowledge produced (Kitcher, 1993). Likewise,
fidelity to legal norms should lead to the kinds of outcomes lawmakers desire. I
treat legal norms separately from other coherence norms because of their
special importance for judicial evaluations.
11. Alexander George (1980) and Irving Janis (1982) developed their important
models of good political decision-making through historical studies of flawed
and successful executive decision making.
12. In addition to moving selection away from political litmus tests and irresolvable
debates about merit, Choi and Gulati (2004b) also hypothesize that tourna-
ments with implications for selections for higher courts may provide positive
incentives to judges.
13. We may question the sincerity of judges stated goals, and the possibility of
insincerity does complicate the interpretation of results obtained from an
internal perspective: if empirical tests reveal a large gap between actual and
ideal behavior under the judge-chosen norm, then the gap may be due to
insincerity or incompetence.
14. Windschitl and Wells make this argument:
Consider . . . the general implication of a system of justice that could
find people liable, based on the balance of probability that derives
merely from membership in a group or class. Would it be good social
or legal policy, for instance, to consider a man to have harassed female
coworkers merely because he is a member of a corporate organization
in which 80% of the males have harassed female coworkers. Our point
is that it would be inappropriate to use such base rates for these types
of judgments. (Windschitl & Wells, 1996, p. 41)
15. As an alternative way to understand the possible problem of confounding
between seemingly biased behavior and underlying values and beliefs, consider
how the interplay between cognitive bias and different aversions to the types of
verdict errors may play out at trial. Imagine a criminal case with Judge 1 who
246 Evaluating and Improving Judging
mention a host of more mundane motives and influences (see Baum, 2006;
Schauer, 2000). Of course, how to measure these other extralegal factors can
create large new problems.
21. To the extent that ideology and normative perspectives are confounded (e.g., if
conservatism is positively correlated with acceptance of textualism as a legal
process norm and liberalism is positively correlated with purposivism as a legal
process norm), the correlation between outcomes and ideology does not compel
the conclusion that legal norms fail to constrain decisions. Correlation cannot
establish causation: the conservative may conveniently favor textualism to
advance desired policy ends, or the conservative may endorse textualism as part
of a sincere set of beliefs about the proper role of the judiciary; partial correlations
can suggest the proper causal model but cannot establish that ideology causes a
strategic choice of normative perspectives.
22. A direct comparison would compare actual votes to the votes predicted by a
legal norm. Very few studies undertake this direct comparison, perhaps because
it is very difficult to operationalize a quantitative empirical test with legal
variables (Cross, 2004, p. 31). For instance, Spaeth and Segal (1999) have only
directly tested compliance with the follow precedent norm within their
simplified legal model.
23. As I discuss below, when testing legal proscription norms, which forbid con-
sideration of some specific factor(s), a finding of no influence from these factors
may vindicate the judges conduct relative to the legal norm. But tests for
extralegal influences will often not provide a direct test of compliance with
other types of norms, as I discuss below.
24. In some domains, process norms dominate legal scholars normative discus-
sions. For instance, process norms dominate discussions of constitutional
interpretation (i.e., norms for how to make constitutional decisions rather
than norms about the specific decisions that should be made), making their
relative neglect within empirical studies all the more unfortunate given the great
interest in constitutional cases within judicial behavior studies.
25. Arguably the central mediating variable in studies of extralegal influences is the
degree of discretion or subjectivity permitted or perceived with respect to any
given judgment or decision, yet this variable typically goes unmeasured in
judicial studies.
26. Although probability and hypothesis-testing rules ultimately serve the purpose of
making accurate and reliable judgments, they are still types of coherence rather
than correspondence norms, just like the rules of logic or rationality, because they
do not guarantee correspondence to reality. If one complies with rules of prob-
ability and hypothesis testing, one is more likely to reach reliable conclusions
about probabilistic and causal relations, but compliance is measured by fidelity to
the rules rather than the correspondence of judgments with reality.
27. Or we might ask what kinds of judges seem to act in ways that are contrary to
existing normative theories, using the character of these judges as negative
evidence. For instance, the attitudinal model research would suggest that
judges who hold less extreme ideological views should rule very differently
than ideologues, and, if moderates are more constrained by the law (i.e., if
their decisions are less predicted by ideology), then political moderation should
be favored to the extent legal constraint is desired.
248 Evaluating and Improving Judging
28. Solum accepts that virtues of the kind he advocates are not easily quantified
(Solum, 2005a). He offers templates of the judicial qualities to look for (Solum,
1988, 2003) and offers some specific ideas on how to screen out those with
judicial vices (Solum, 2005a). But on the more abstract judicial virtues, Solum
offers little specific guidance on how exactly to identify these qualities in
particular judicial candidates and is largely content to rely on recommendations
of persons who know the judges, with those recommendations proceeding from
vague standards.
29. Posner (1995b) provides one of the more explicit defenses of pragmatism, even
if the content remains somewhat vague, though Posner seems to argue less that
some are predisposed to be pragmatic judges and more that all judges should
strive to be pragmatists.
30. The point here is not that looking to opinions to find pragmatic judges is
wrongheaded; the point is that the character of pragmatism is, at this point,
doing no independent work except serving as a label for how this judge ruled. It
will be impossible to identify pragmatic judges and predict their rulings if we
can only identify pragmatic judges from their rulings. In this approach, prag-
matism may be seen as a proper norm for judging judicial acts, but it is now just
another of our normative standards rather than part of some character-based
theory of good judging. Of course, this may be the sense most advocates of
pragmatic judging intend; few scholars advance as explicitly as Solum does a
dispositional theory of good judging.
15
Defining Good Judging
Andrew J. Wistrich
When Supreme Court Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr. was quite old, he
took a trip by train. During the trip, a conductor asked him for his ticket.
After unsuccessfully searching through one pocket after another, Holmes
became flustered. The conductor recognized the famous jurist and tried to
reassure him: You dont need to find your ticket now, Mr. Holmes. Im sure
you bought one. Just send it to the railroad office when it turns up. Holmes
replied with impatience: The problem is not that I cant find my ticket, the
problem is I dont know where Im going!1
Some have suggested that we must define good judging before we begin
studying, evaluating, and reforming judicial decision making.2 That plausible
suggestion flows from the same intuition as the one expressed in the story about
Holmes; that is, before we embark on a journey, it would be nice to know where
we are going. While I agree that it might be nice, I am not sure that it is possible,
or necessary, or even that it would be helpful. Therefore, when we are thinking
about what research should be done concerning judges and judicial decision
making during the next decade, and what improvements to our justice system
might result from that research, perhaps what seems like the most logical place
to start is actually not the best place to start. In fact, beginning by trying to define
good judging might delay our departure and lead us in the wrong direction.
249
250 Evaluating and Improving Judging
The Old Testament, dating back to the twelfth century B.C., teaches
judges, Thou shalt not wrest judgment; thou shalt not respect persons,
neither take a gift: for a gift doth blind the eyes of the wise, and pervert the
words of the righteous (Deuteronomy 16:19).
Several hundred years later, the Greek philosopher Socrates said, Four
things belong to a judge: To hear courteously, to answer wisely, to consider
soberly and to decide impartially(Sampson, 2004). Writing at about the
same time, and in the same place, Plato argued that the good judge must
not be young but old (Plato, 2006, bk. 2 div. 409).
St. Augustine, who served not only as Bishop of Hippo, but also as a civil
and ecclesiastical judge during the 4th and 5th centuries A.D. (Schaff, 1954),
said that [a] good judge does nothing according to his private opinion but
pronounces sentence according to the law and the right.3
Not surprisingly, many definitions of good judging have been authored
by judges. Often their definitions consist of a mixture of personal qualities a
judge should possess and ways in which a judge should act or behave while
doing his job.
In 1612, Sir Francis Bacon, philosopher, statesman, and Lord Chancellor
of England, wrote: Judges ought to be more learned than witty, more
reverend than plausible, and more advised than confident. Above all things,
integrity is their portion and proper virtue. . . . Let judges also remember that
Solomons throne was supported by lions on both sides: let them be lions, but
yet lions under the throne (Montagu, 1850, pp. 5859).
Defining Good Judging 251
judge exerts in approaching her job and the willingness to decide cases
impartially and independent of political ideology, are considered (Choi &
Gulati, 2004b).
Whatever its value with respect to appellate judges, however, citation
analysis is of little use with respect to trial judges. In most states, trial court
decisions are not published. In the few states where they are published, or in
the federal courts, published decisions by trial courts are usually of negligible
importance as precedent (except as to issues that are rarely litigated on
appeal), and most are seldom cited.
The results of these laudable efforts to define good judging make inter-
esting reading. They also possess some practical value. Reviewing them occa-
sionally can remind judges of the abstract ideals to which they should aspire.
Some of the definitions conceivably could be used as a crude measuring stick to
assess the quality of judicial performance. As the basis for scholarly research or
judicial reform, however, they are inadequate (Frankel, 1976).
While a handful of traits have persisted over the centuries and appear
to be universally accepted as desirable, no clear consensus has emerged
regarding the criteria that should be employed to determine whether
someone is a good judge or whether a particular decision embodies good
judging (Fennell, 1999). Moreover, widely accepted criteria such as integrity,
impartiality, dignity, and patience are subjective or immeasurable, making it
difficult to determine whether a judge did or did not display them in making a
particular decision (Minow & Spelman, 1989, p. 50).
Modern definitions of good judging are more detailed than their pre-
decessors, and tend to emphasize more practical judicial qualities or goals.
They also acknowledge that judges do more than simply decide cases, and that
judges ancillary responsibilities should be reflected in the definition of good
judging as well. Although those newer definitions may be slightly more
realistic when compared to the lofty and often superhuman standards of
good judging emphasized in the past, they still contain many terms that are
vague or subjective (Schaefer, 1960).
The failure of so many sincere efforts by so many capable people leads me
to believe that defining good judging in the abstract is infeasible. Others have
reached the same conclusion (e.g., Posner, 2008, p. 12; Champagne, 1986, pp.
104, 110; Farthing-Capowich, 1985, p. 23; Dubois, 1980, p. 17). Gregory
Mitchells understandable failure to offer such a definition in his fine essay
on evaluating judges in this volume (ch. 14), coupled with his ingenious and
exhaustive account of the difficulty and complexity of doing so, only confirms
that attempting to define good judging in the abstract is a fools errand.
Conceptual Difficulties
In addition to the difficulty of crafting a meaningful definition of good
judging, attempting to do so creates conceptual problems. One such problem
Defining Good Judging 257
would be misleading. In todays courts, there is no one size fits all descrip-
tion of what judges do, and therefore no single, all-encompassing definition
of what they should do.
The role of trial court judges in performing nontraditional tasks such as
mediation and case management creates especially challenging problems of
quality evaluation or measurement. What counts as bad judging in a media-
tion setting? Is it any behavior that either coerces or discourages settlement in
the particular context presented? Or is it conducting a settlement conference
in a manner that is more evaluative than transformative regardless of the
outcome? Similarly, how should an error in case management be defined? Is it
setting a schedule that is too strict, so that the facts cannot be developed
adequately or the lawyers are severely stressed? Or is it setting a schedule that
is too lax, so that a case languishes rather than being disposed of promptly and
inexpensively? Might it also consist of sequencing motions in a way that gives
one party an unfair tactical advantage over the other? Defining and measuring
quality in these dimensions of judicial performance would be difficult indeed.
Perhaps for that reason, few attempts have been made. Even the ABAs
judicial performance guidelines, which go further than just about any defini-
tion of good judging in accounting for the varying roles that judges play, fail
to address these sorts of questions in a meaningful way. Yet these sorts of
decisions and actions comprise a large chunk of what many trial court judges
do (see, e.g., Otis & Reiter, 2006; Parness, 2006).
The nature of judging in collaborative or nontraditional trial court
contexts makes it especially difficult to evaluate quality in those contexts.
For example, consider child custody determinations, the appropriate
response to juvenile delinquency, or public law cases involving structural
relief. As one scholar has noted, in these types of assignments,
what is important is not to mete justice, but to help the parties design
an arrangement which will be least destructive and vindictive,
especially when children are involved. The prime commitment of the
decision maker should not be justice or the application of (legal)
norms, but a viable resolution of the dispute. For this commitment,
legal education is neither necessary nor clearly desirable.
Similarly, for cases in which intervention is needed to supervise
a complex administrative agency structure, such as a company or a
prison system, judges must have the skills to help them identify the
right and the feasible arrangement, and design the supervision
mechanism which might be most effective and least demanding of
constant review. I know of no law school which seeks to provide its
students with such skills, nor of a [judicial] selection criterion which
reflects them. (Gavison, 1988, p. 1625)
A third problem is that attempting to formulate a definition of good
judging encourages the misperception that the judicial role is fixed. Judges
jobs, however, evolve over time. The mix of tasks judges perform has changed
Defining Good Judging 259
during the past few decades (Parness, 2006, pp. 18921898), as has our
perception of the relative importance of those tasks. For example, as the
role of case management has waxed and the role of presiding over trials has
waned (Galanter, 2004), our assessment of the skills judges should possess, as
well as our vision of good judging, has begun to shift. As one law professor has
pointed out,
the claim that the more dispositions, the better raises difficult
valuation tasks; decisionmaking must be assessed not only
quantitatively, but also qualitatively. On any given day, are four
judges who speak with parties to sixteen lawsuits and report that
twelve of those cases ended without trial more productive than
four judges who preside at four trials? (Resnik, 1982, p. 422)
Questions such as this, which no one would have thought to ask a few decades
ago, must be addressed today.
Today, excellence at presiding over jury trials, which remains a valuable
skill, arguably has become less important relative to excellence at the now
far more common tasks of mediating, scheduling, and ruling on pretrial
motions. While the personal qualities and skill sets that judges need to excel
at the wide range of tasks they are assigned undoubtedly overlap, they are not
congruent. Historical wish-lists of judicial qualities and guidelines for how
judges should do their jobs need to be revised to take this into account. Any
definition of good judging we develop today will have to be updated as judges
jobs continue to evolve. Thinking that we can settle on oneor even
severaldefinitions of good judging that are capable of providing a stable
platform for research over a decade or more is unrealistic.
from interviews of the nurses and physicians involved exactly how and why
each mishap occurred (Cooper et al., 1978; see also Cooper et al., 1984).
Based on Coopers work, the American Society of Anesthesiologists
brought together anesthesiologists, surgeons, nurses, human factors engi-
neers, equipment manufacturers, and others at an international conference.
The combination of a willingness to acknowledge mistakes, careful empirical
study, and the consideration of interdisciplinary and cross-cultural perspec-
tives proved fruitful. Sources of error were identified, and strategies to
mitigate or eliminate them were implemented. Hours on duty for anesthe-
siology residents were shortened so that fewer slips or lapses would be caused
by fatigue. Manufacturers redesigned their machines, standardizing dials to
turn in a uniform direction, adding a mechanism to prevent the accidental
administration of more than one type of anesthetic gas simultaneously, and
changing controls so that oxygen delivery could not be turned off. Where an
error could not be eliminated, methods for detecting it before irreparable
harm was done to the patient were developed.
These efforts paid off. Within a decade, anesthesia-related deaths fell
from 1 in every 5,000 operations to just 1 in every 200,000 operations.9
What does this inspiring story about anesthesiology have to do with
judges? A lot. It suggests how judicial decision making might be improved
if the justice system adopted a similar approach.
Law is different from medicine in a variety of respects, of course, so it may
not be possible to replicate in the justice system the remarkable success
achieved in anesthesiology. It may be easier to identify errors in medicine
than in law, where the standards of correctness may be more subjective
(Posner, 2008, p. 3). Also, physicians may be more accountable for poor
performance than judges, because they can be sued for malpractice while
judges generally are immune from civil liability or criminal prosecution for
judicial acts.10 There already is at least one example, however, of the use of
empirical research in psychology to improve the quality of decisions in trial
courts.
Psychologists have known for decades that the traditional way of con-
ducting lineups in which an eyewitness is shown six photographs or six
people simultaneously under the supervision of a law enforcement officer
involved in investigation is likely to result in mistaken identifications
(Behrman & Davey, 2001; Steblay et al., 2001). There is a much better
technique that significantly reduces false positive identifications without
significantly increasing false negative identifications, and without signifi-
cantly increasing the cost of conducting lineups. That method is to show
the eyewitness one person or photograph at a time, and to ask the eyewitness
to make a decision about that individual before moving on to the next person
or photograph. If the eyewitness wants to view a particular person or photo-
graph again, he is allowed to do so, but only after he has first seen all of the
individuals separately, and only after the order in which the individuals are
presented has been reshuffled. In addition, the live or photographic lineup
Defining Good Judging 261
should be conducted by a law enforcement officer who does not know which
individual is the suspect and which individuals are not.
These two changes improve the accuracy of identifications because
research has shown that when confronted by a simultaneous array, witnesses
tend to assume that the perpetrator is included, and then to compare the
individuals in the array to determine which one best matches their recollec-
tion of the perpetrator. Also, having the lineup supervised by an officer who is
not involved in the investigation reduces the danger that something might tip
off the eyewitness as to who the suspect is.
Although the advantages of this new method of conducting lineups have
been known for a long time, law enforcement agencies have been slow to
adopt it. Recently, however, New Jersey decided to require that this new
method of conducting lineups be used throughout its criminal justice
system (Kolata & Peterson, 2001). Other jurisdictions are following suit.11
This is a good example of how social science research can be used to improve
the accuracy of the justice system by strengthening the quality of the evidence
available to judges and juries. It also demonstrates that not all clearly bene-
ficial changes to our justice system necessarily require expensive, unpalatable,
or dramatic changes to existing procedures.
Improving Judging
Assuming that we want to follow in the footsteps of anesthesiologists, and
skip or defer the step of defining good judging, how should we proceed?
Probably by continuing some of the research we already are conducting, and
by trying a few new tacks as well. One approach would be to begin with a few
existing criteria of good judging we can all agree on (e.g., Klein, 2005; Farber
& Sherry, this volume, ch. 18). For example, no one would argue that the
length of a federal criminal sentence should be based on the race or gender of
the defendant rather than the relevant factors specified by statute. Nor is that
something that is likely to change over time, or even to vary depending on
whether the sentence is a conventional one imposed by a traditional criminal
court or a disposition implemented by an innovative collaborative court. One
thing we could do without first defining good judging would be to determine
whether judges have been imposing racially biased sentences by carefully
analyzing past decisions. Several scholars already have done this. I discuss
just one example, notable for its thoroughness and perceptiveness.
David Mustard (2001) examined the sentences imposed on 77,236 fed-
eral offenders during 19911994. His analysis revealed large disparities in the
length of sentences based on race, gender, education, income, and citizenship.
On average, white offenders received shorter sentences than black or Hispanic
offenders, and female offenders received shorter sentences than male offen-
ders. After controlling for a myriad of factors, the difference in sentence
length amounted to about six months in both instances. Significantly, most
262 Evaluating and Improving Judging
of the difference occurred when the sentencing judge departed from the
guidelines promulgated by the United States Sentencing Commission.
Mustard started with a criterion of good judging we can all agree on
judges should not determine sentences based on statutorily forbidden
characteristics like the defendants race or genderand simply tested how
well judges were doing. His research revealed that judicial discretion for
individualizingwhich seems desirable in the abstractcontinued to create
the risk of forbidden discrimination even under the then tighter control of the
guidelines.12 This suggests that, whatever their other shortcomings, tight
sentencing guidelines may not be so bad after all.
Another approach is the one that Jeffrey Rachlinski, Chris Guthrie, and I
have taken in our work.13 We have tackled the problem experimentally rather
than archivally. We began by examining the psychology literature to identify
mistakes people commonly commit when making decisions. Assuming that
judges should avoid cognitive error while ruling on cases, we then attempted
to discern which of those mistakes plausibly might occur in situations in
which judges work. Our next step was to test judges, eliciting from them
responses to hypothetical cases or other sorts of problems to determine if,
when faced with choices similar in content and structure to those they
confront when doing their jobs, they would be vulnerable to the same sorts
of cognitive biases or illusions that cause ordinary people to make mistakes in
experiments conducted by psychologists.
This approach possesses some advantages. There is an extensive literature
concerning flaws in judgment and decision making on which one can draw,
rather than starting from scratch. That made it possible for us to start
identifying nonobvious potential sources of error immediately. If judges are
susceptible to committing particular types of errors, then we can think about
the situations in which judges act and try to identify solutions. It is not
necessary to have a comprehensive definition of good judging to know that
judges should not consider evidence they themselves have correctly decided is
inadmissible under the rules of evidence, be wildly influenced by an arbitrary
number mentioned by a litigant, make rulings based on a litigants attrac-
tiveness rather than the merits of the case, and so on. If it turns out that judges
are not susceptible to a particular type of error across a range of situations,
then we can cross that type of error off the list, at least provisionally, and move
on to others on the list.
Of course, this approach is not perfect. There may be questions about its
external validity,14 and it may be that some of the problems in human
decision making that have the most serious consequences for judges have
not been identified or systematically studied by psychologists. Cognitive
biases, however, are things we can identify, and in many instances, do some-
thing about, right now.
Careful study of reversals in the aggregate would be another way of
identifying potential sources of error. There are many studies of reversals,
of course, but most seem to focus on reversal rates, either overall or in
Defining Good Judging 263
particular categories of cases (e.g., Guthrie & George, 2005). Others explore
the impact of reversals on subsequent trial court decisions (e.g., Gellis, 1985;
Liberato & Rutter, 2003; Smith, 2005). There do not seem to be any, however,
that attempt to determineas Cooper did in his study of anesthesia mishaps
the types of errors lower courts are making. That is something that can, and
should, be tried.15
Another criterion of performance could be developed from studying the
appellate records of individual lower court judges. It is well known that the
judgments of some judges are more frequently appealed than are judgments
of others. It is likewise recognized that some lower courts conform more
closely to the law as interpreted by the higher courts than do other lower
courts. The extent to which a trial judge should attempt to conform to the
opinions of her appellate court superiors may be debatable in some cases, but
regardless of the side one takes in that debate, both the frequency of appeal
and the frequency of reversal are objective criteria of judicial performance of
considerable significance (Mott, 1948, p. 276).
Even if an appellate court finds that the trial court erred, it will only
reverse the decision if it concludes that the error was not harmless. We should
study cases in which error was found to be harmless very carefully. Not only
may the error have affected the outcomedespite the appellate courts
determination to the contrarybut if it did not that may have been a fortuity.
Like the situation in which a doctor makes a mistake, but subsequently
notices it and fixes it before it harms the patient, the error occurred and
might have had injurious consequences in a different case, so we ought to
figure out how to prevent it. These near misses could be a valuable source of
information about needed reforms that may be overlooked by focusing only
on reversals.
We also could go a step further and review a sample of cases that were not
appealed to determine whether errors were made that escaped appellate
review entirely. For example, a confidential peer review process could be
implemented, in which respected judges would periodically visit other
courts and study a few randomly selected cases in which no appeal was
taken. The judges under study could be given feedback on their performance
to help them improve. This would help us to determine whether the errors
that are appealed are representative of those that are not appealed. It also
would help us to ascertain whether errors that are likely to be harmful are
escaping appellate review.
Of course, reversals provide noisy signals of error. Appeals are infrequent,
particularly in civil cases, and reversals are rare (Guthrie & George, 2005, pp.
359363). Some interim decisions are isolated from appellate review, and
final judgments are reviewed deferentially. Further, some reversals result from
disagreements over policy, or occur in cases that are extremely close. These
arguably cannot be characterized as errors in any meaningful sense. Despite
these shortcomings, however, studying the causes of reversal might be
fruitful.
264 Evaluating and Improving Judging
Conclusion
Like the talented and hard-working anesthesiologists, judges (and others,
such as scholars and legislators) possess both the abilityand, I would
argue, the responsibilityto try to reduce the frequency and the magnitude
of error in trial court decision making. What we need is the dedication and
the courage to do what anesthesiologists did: openly pursue a painstaking
interdisciplinary inquiry into the question of how best to structure the
process of judicial decision making, and then implement reforms based on
what we learn. And we need to get started right away.
It is significant, I think, that anesthesiologists did not begin by trying to
define a good anesthesiologist or good anesthesiology. Instead, they
rolled up their sleeves and collected data. Then, viewing the delivery of
medical care as a system of which anesthesia and anesthesiologists were
merely a part, they attacked the most common and serious problems, leaving
the philosophizing for later. That is exactly what judicial reformers should do.
If, on the other hand, defining good judging is made a prerequisite to
empirical research concerning judicial decision making, then I doubt we will
progress very far anytime soon. We will have missed the opportunity to make
rapid progress like the anesthesiologists did, and that would be a terrible shame.
My respectful disagreement with those who contend that we must begin
our efforts to achieve judicial reform by defining good judging reminds me of
a story about two clerics who were debating the finer points of theology. After
they had been at it for awhile, one put his arm around the others shoulders
and said: Brother, why do we argue? After all, we both serve God. You in your
way, and I in His.
Appendix
American Bar Association Committee On Judicial Performance Evaluation,
Black Letter Guidelines for the Evaluation of Judicial Performance with
Commentary, 5-1 to 5-6 (2005)
Guideline 5-1. A judge should be evaluated on his or her legal ability,
including the following criteria:
Defining Good Judging 265
Notes
1. Differing versions of this story have been recounted. See, for example, Reed
(2005).
2. See Gregory Mitchells essay in this volume and Schauer (1988b). See generally
Dworkin (1986).
3. Quoted in St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, pt. 2, question 67, art. 2,
objection 4.
4. Reprinted in In re Code of Judicial Conduct (1994), 103738 n.2. See also
Campbell (2005).
5. For a fine example of this, consider the following:
I venture to believe that it is as important to a judge called upon to
pass on a question of constitutional law, to have at least a bowing
acquaintance with Acton and Maitland, with Thucydides, Gibbon
and Carlyle, with Homer, Dante, Shakespeare and Milton, with
Machiavelli, Montaigne and Rabelais, with Plato, Bacon, Hume and
Kant, as with the books which have been specifically written on the
subject. For in such matters everything turns upon the spirit in which
he approaches the questions before him. (Hand, 1930, pp. 1213)
6. See also Solum (2005a).
7. Stephen J. Breyer, quoted in Toward Active Liberty: A Supreme Court Justice
Offers a View from the Top, Harvard Law Bulletin, 57:14, 17 (Spring 2006).
8. To put these anesthesia-related death rates into perspective, consider the error
rate in adjudication. Perhaps the best measurealbeit an imperfect oneof
whether a decision is mistaken is whether it is reversed on direct appeal or set
Defining Good Judging 267
Even a casual glance at papers on the expertise of court judges reveals wide-
spread disagreement about the quality of judicial decisions. Consider the
following recent articles:
Playing Dice with Criminal Sentences, by Englich, Mussweiler, and
Strack (2006)
Judicial Decision Thresholds for Violence Risk Management, by
Monahan and Silver (2003)
Conditional Bail Decision Making in the Magistrates Court by
Dhami (2004)
The first article implies a deficiency in judicial decision making, whereas the
second implies competence. The position taken here is consistent with the
third article: the expertise of court judges is tied to the particular domain in
which judges are asked to make factual or probabilistic assessments in the face
of uncertainty or ambiguity.
We believe that expert performance is not best understood and assessed
in terms of general characteristics applying across all domains. Rather, it
should be analyzed in the context of the specific tasks that experts in a
particular domain are called on to accomplish. Drawing on a substantial
line of research from psychology, we will argue that considerable empirical
evidence supports this domain-specific view of expert competence, that there
are reasons to believe this view holds with respect to court judges, and that, to
be as fair and useful as possible, assessments of judicial performance should
incorporate this view.
269
270 Evaluating and Improving Judging
The paper is organized into five sections as follows. First, there is a review
of the literature on expertise in general. Second, the implicit theory behind
expert decision making (judges are either good or bad decision makers) is
described. Third, the role that domain differences play in disagreement
between experts across a wide variety of domains is considered. Fourth, an
alternate theory of expertise is proposed that posits that decision quality
depends on domain differences. Finally, the paper concludes with implica-
tions for judicial decision making and future research directions.
Background
Since the start of systematic analyses of skilled performance in the 1950s,
investigators have expressed surprise and dismay at the extent to which
experts make poor or inconsistent decisions. For example, if we ask two
court judges to assess a court case, the expectation of most analysts is that
they should come to the same conclusion. If they arrive at different conclu-
sions, then we wonder whether they are as skilled as they claim to be.
In a seminal paper, Einhorn (1974) argued that consensus or between-
expert reliability is a necessary condition for expertise.1 He found, however,
significant differences in diagnoses made by three expert medical pathologists.
The average between-expert correlation (r) was .55 (where .0 is chance and 1.0
is perfect). In comparison, weather forecasters were reported to have high
consensus values, r .95, for short-term predictions (Stewart, Roebber, &
Bosart, 1997). Thus there is widespread variability in the agreement of experts.
It is also possible to examine internal consistency, the extent to which an
expert makes the same decision for the same case if repeated. For pathologists,
Einhorn (1974) reported an average within-expert consistency r of .50. For
weather forecasters, on the other hand, the average internal consistency is
near perfect, r .98 (Stewart, Roebber, & Bosart, 1997).
In a study of livestock judges, four professionals were asked to evaluate
overall breeding quality of swine (Phelps, 1977). Despite a high level of
internal consistency (average r .96), the consensus agreement was much
lower, r .50. Apparently, livestock experts have internally consistent strate-
gies, but they disagree with each other about what those strategies should be.
Comparable results have been reported for other types of experts. For
instance, grain inspectors were found to have a consensus value between
judges of r .60, with internal consistency of r .62 (Trumbo, Adams,
Milner, & Schipper, 1962).
In other domains, the correlations are often lower. For example,
Hoffman, Slovic, and Rorer (1968) and Goldberg and Werts (1966) reported
consensus values of less than .40 for judgments by professional stockbrokers
and clinical psychologists. The internal consistency values were slightly
higher, with correlations of just over .40.
Expertise of Court Judges 271
Experts-Should-Be-Perfect Argument
The less-than-impressive results from most studies of expertise have led many
analysts to question the abilities of experts in general. Following Einhorns
logic, these investigators assumed that agreement on the correct answer is a
necessary condition for expertise. The lack of agreement, therefore, suggested
that experts are no damn good (Gettys, personal communication, 1980).
This interpretation apparently derives from an implicit five-part argument
about experts:
(1) In expert domains, there is an assumed gold standard or unique
ground truth. If this truth is readily accessible, then we dont
need expertsanyone can obtain it. In most cases, however, it
requires an expert, such as court judges, to access truth. In these
cases, the answer is outside the realm of common knowledge of
most people. That is why we need experts.
(2) Because of their special skills and experience, the experts job is to
tell the rest of us about this ground truth. That is because experts
should be able to access answers that others cannot access. Put
another way, experts should have a unique ability to know the
truth.
(3) Since by definition there can be only one ground truth, all
experts should arrive at the same (single) correct answer. The
special abilities of experts thus allow them to arrive at the ground
truth correct answer.
(4) If experts disagree, then someone is wrong. Since there is one and
only one correct answer, some (or all) of them must not be real
experts. Thus, disagreement about the correct answer is a
reflection of incompetence within the group of would-be experts.
(5) Since lay people do not know which of the so-called experts is
correct, the only safe course of action is to distrust all (or at least
272 Evaluating and Improving Judging
Domain Differences
It is common knowledge that experts in different domains perform different
tasks. Yet, many decision analysts persist in treating all fields of expertise alike,
that is, the term expert is used generically. For instance, Kahneman (1991)
concludes, there is much evidence that experts (in general) are not immune
to the cognitive illusions that affect other people (parenthesis in the ori-
ginal). Of course, this may be true for some, or even many, domains. But there
are domains, such as weather forecasting, where experts show little sign of
biases or cognitive illusions (Lichtenstein, Fischhoff, & Phillips, 1982;
Murphy & Winkler, 1977; Stewart, Roebber, & Bosart, 1997). Thus, despite
the broad generalizations of incompetence drawn about experts, there are a
number of exceptions to the rule.
In an effort to account for these domain differences, Shanteau (1992a,
1992b) constructed a table to differentiate those domains where experts do
well from those where experts do not. Table 16.1 is an updated version based
on a continuum from high to low competence. In the left column are those
domains where experts make aided decisions using Decision Support Systems
(DSS) or other computerized tools, for example, weather forecasters. The
next column contains domains where experts make skilled, but largely
unaided decisions, for example, livestock judges. The third column lists
domains where experts show limited competence, for example, clinical psy-
chologists. The behavior of experts in the last column is close to random, for
example, stockbrokers and, unfortunately, court judges.
It should be noted that assignment of domains within the table was based
on our review of the conclusions of the authors of each study. That is, the level
of competence is categorized from the assessments of the researchers who
studied each domain.
There are many ways to describe the differences in this table (Shanteau,
1992a, 1992b). For present purposes, it is sufficient to observe that domains to
the left (more competent) side involve stable (static) properties. That is, the
stimuli and the problem hold still for experts to evaluate. The domains to
the right (less competent) side involve more changeable (dynamic) proper-
ties. Thus, the stimuli and problem are less stable, more difficult to specify
more like moving targets.
Another way to view this distinction is to note that most domains to the
left side of the table involve physical or natural properties, whereas most
domains to the right involve human or social behavior. This may reflect the
fact that natural sciences in left-side domains have a longer history of devel-
opment. In contrast, the domains to the right have relatively young social
sciences. Given this difference, it makes sense that, as a general rule, expert
competence will tend to be higher to the left side and lower to the right side.
The question remains whether this distinction between domains is pre-
dictive of different levels of agreement. To examine this proposition, Table 16.2
summarizes consensus values reported by the author(s) for a variety of domains.
Two specialties are listed under each category, with the between-expert agree-
ment (consensus) given as average correlations. As can be seen, the mean
consensus r value for weather forecasters is .95, whereas the average value for
livestock judges is .50. The consensus values for clinical psychologists, and
stock forecasters are .40, and .32, respectively. Comparable results for other
domains appear in the second line. The trend supports the prediction outlined
weather forecasters and livestock judges are skilled professionals. Yet, there is
a major difference for these two fields in the level of disagreement between
experts. The former is based on a well-developed science, whereas the latter is
based more on informed judgment. It should not be surprising, therefore,
to find livestock experts disagreeing more with each other about their judg-
ments than weather forecasters.
Nonetheless, judgment and decision researchers continue to view experts
as extensions of the flawed decision making typically seen in undergraduates
(Kahneman, 1991). That is, the characteristics of flawed decision making
associated with the biases and heuristics tradition are generalized to skilled
professionals (Gigerenzer, 1993; Klein, Orasanu, Calderwood, & Zsambok,
1993; Yates, 1990).
Importance of Domains
The position taken here is that previous analysts have unknowingly adopted
the experts-should-be-perfect view of expertise. As argued above, this view
implies that disagreement between experts is taken as a sign that something is
wrong. That in turn leads to the conclusion that experts are not as skilled or as
competent as they claim. In this section, we propose an alternative perspective
based on a domain-dependent view of expert performance. This perspective is
based on a five-part argument:
(1) The primary job of an expert is not to make decisions but to help
others reach a broadly defined target state. For example, the goal may
be to help policy makers design better strategies to reduce recidivism
or to increase the efficiency (i.e., reduce the cost) of the court system.
These goals do not involve single answers, but instead require
something more elaborate from the expert, such as strategic plans.
(2) To reach these goal states requires dealing with multiple,
constantly changing, and dynamic factors. As noted by Klein et al.
(1993), the situations faced by experts are different and more
complex than the simplified situations considered by most
analysts. Thus, experts work on problems that are much more
complex than those studied in idealized settings with
undergraduates making decisions.
(3) Using their knowledge and experience, the role of the expert is to
recognize patterns and find consistencies in a dynamic problem
space. The experts job is to clarify the issues and to identify
alternative approaches. In other words, the challenge for an expert
is to make sense out of chaos. This is certainly a description of
what many court judges have to do.
(4) Based on their experience and insights into the nature of problems,
experts try to help others (such as jury members) clarify their
276 Evaluating and Improving Judging
Conclusion
Dawes (personal communication, 1987) offered an insightful observation
about an earlier version of Table 16.1. The performance standards expected
by clients are different for the left and right sides. Weather forecasters are
allowed to make occasional mistakes. However, court judges and managers
are expected to be correct almost all the time. That is, in the less predictable
(right-side) domains, experts are held to higher standards of performance.
This is important for court judges, since with increased computerization
and media coverage, there has been a shift in skills needed. Traditionally, a
judge needed to be a jack-of-all-trades, with general skills in many areas.
Today, modern courtrooms place more demand on cognitive (thinking)
abilities. For example, with the trend toward more complex legal cases,
there is a greater need for judges with management abilities. These are
precisely the psychological skills associated with right side of the table (as
opposed to the more technical skills on the left side).
278 Evaluating and Improving Judging
Note
1. Preparation of this chapter was supported by funds provided by the Scottish
Funding Council to HealthQWest; A research consortium for the West of
Scotland.
17
Cognitive Style and Judging
279
280 Evaluating and Improving Judging
to judicial activism, might suggest that judicial foxes should be favored over
judicial hedgehogs (e.g., Farber & Sherry, this volume, ch. 18, advocate giving
preference in judicial selections to foxes), the attractiveness of hedgehog-like
or fox-like tendencies will depend on the interests of the audience. The judge
who appears to some to be a wise judicial fox, deciding only what is necessary
to resolve the case at hand, will appear to others as an unprincipled, timid
judge who fails to provide necessary guidance to future legal actors
(cf. Tetlock et al., 1993; Waldron, 2007).
Fox-like tendencies are likely to be especially valued in public law
domains, which preoccupy many legal scholars, where the issues presented
in cases often implicate many contentious trade-offs and implicate debates
about the relative competency of courts versus legislatures versus executives
to make these trade-offs. Thus, a humble, incremental approach will often be
seen as the least likely to lock-in-place bad guesses about future conditions
and unpopular resolutions of trade-offs (see, e.g., Sunstein, 2007). In the
domain of private law, however, where parties can often contract around
undesirable legal rules or choose from competing legal regimes, we suspect
that judicial hedgehogs, with their more sweeping, definitive, and predictable
approaches to cases, will fare much better in the eyes of the key attendant
audiencesbusinesses and business lawyers.
If we are right that the hedgehog-fox cognitive style dimension can
illuminate how judges go about their business, then researchers should
naturally be concerned with issues of measurement and testing of our
hypotheses on judges, for it is perilous to assume that findings from
Tetlocks research on forecasting experts holds with respect to judges, who
inhabit unique institutional positions and generally have similar educational
backgrounds that may greatly affect the expression of individual differences in
cognitive style. The most straightforward approach would be to recruit judges
to complete Tetlocks (2005) hedgehog-fox scale and then examine these
judges with respect to their opinion-writing and other behaviors consistent
with the different cognitive styles.4 Alternatively, observers may score a
sample of judges opinions for hedgehog- versus fox-like perspectives and
examine the consistency of these tendencies across cases and the ability of
these scores to predict other judicial behaviors. Unfortunately, no content-
analytic protocol for the placement of writers on the hedgehog-fox conti-
nuum presently exists.
However, given the potential gains from cognitive styles research on
judges, we believe that investments in the development of empirical tools to
measure judicial cognitive styles would be well-rewarded. Because interest in
the hedgehog-fox variable supplements rather than supplants traditional
political-science interest in the judicial ideology variable, and offers a way
to explain more of the non-law-related variance in judicial behavior, political
scientists should find this research perspective congenial to prevailing attitu-
dinal theories of judicial behavior. Because the hedgehog-fox distinction
mirrors existing legal discussions of judicial philosophy, and offers a way to
Cognitive Style and Judging 283
explain the bases for these philosophies and to focus on elements of judicial
behavior largely ignored by political scientists, legal scholars should find this
research perspective congenial to prevailing theories of legal interpretation
and the development of the common law. We thus see cognitive style research
as offering an empirical bridge between the political science and legal litera-
tures. Most provocatively, cognitive style research may show that traditional,
competing positions of the political scientist and the legal scholar are both
correct, but only for subsets of judges: judicial hedgehogs may allow their
personal beliefs and values to drive their legal decisions, thus supporting
many political scientists views of judging, but judicial foxes may be much
more sensitive to the facts and law of particular cases and much less willing to
inject their own beliefs and values into cases, thus supporting many legal
scholars views of judging.
Notes
1. Scope itself can be seen as multidimensional. For instance, Sunstein (1999)
distinguishes between the width and depth of an opinion, with the former
referring to the reach or breadth of the legal ruling announced and the latter
referring to the nature of the doctrinal or theoretical foundations for the
opinion.
2. In this brief discussion, we focus only on one area of cognitive style research.
For reviews of this large body of research, see Kozhevnikov (2007), Suedfeld
(2000), and Suedfeld & Tetlock (2001). We focus here on individual differ-
ences in cognitive style because of their potential for differentiating among
judges and their opinions. There are, however, situational differences in
cognitive style as well, and these situational differences may cause convergence
across judges who otherwise would exhibit different individual styles (see
Tetlock, 2005).
3. This distinction follows from Isaiah Berlins now classic essay, The Hedgehog and
the Fox, in which he describes the distinction as one of the deepest differences
which divide writers and thinkers, and it may be, human beings in general:
For there exists a great chasm between those, on one side, who relate
everything to a single central vision, one system less or more coherent
or articulate, in terms of which they understand, think and feela
single, universal, organizing principle in terms of which alone all that
they are and say has significanceand, on the other side, those who
pursue many ends, often unrelated and even contradictory,
connected, if at all, only in some de facto way, for some psychological
or physiological cause, related by no moral or aesthetic principle;
these last lead lives, perform acts, and entertain ideas that are
centrifugal rather than centripetal, their thought is scattered or
diffused, moving on many levels, seizing upon the essence of a vast
variety of experiences and objects for what they are in themselves,
without, consciously or unconsciously, seeking to fit them into, or
exclude them from, any one unchanging, all-embracing, sometimes
284 Evaluating and Improving Judging
We have spent much of our academic careers arguing that judicial decision
makingeven in constitutional casesis a specialized craft, not merely an
exercise in politics (Farber & Sherry, 2002; Farber, 1992, 1995; Farber &
Adams, 1999; Sherry, 2003, 2005, 2007). We have suggested that good judging
requires both expertise and a certain set of dispositional traits, and that it can
be enhanced or hindered by both personal traits and situational character-
istics. In a recent book, we describe and defend our vision of the process of
constitutional adjudication, provide examples of good and bad judicial opi-
nions, and identify existing and proposed structural supports conducive to
good constitutional decision making. (Farber & Sherry, 2008).
Our task in this essay is to translate our theorizing into concrete sugges-
tions for further research. Anyone who has read this far in the current volume
is probably persuaded that the task is hopeless. In constitutional cases, there
seems to be no hope of reaching agreement on an appropriate normative
standard. Certainly there is no consensus on outcome-based norms: If
everyone agreed about the ultimate meaning of constitutional provisions,
the Supreme Court would have no docket. Decisional norms fare no better,
insofar as judges and scholars disagree about both the appropriate method of
constitutional interpretation and the role of the judiciary in our constitu-
tional democracy. As for our claim that certain dispositional traits can lead to
better judging, the empirical testing of such a claim would prove difficult if
not impossible.
Being legal academics as well as pragmatists, however, we remain
undaunted by philosophical dilemmas and empirical gaps. The reader will
285
286 Evaluating and Improving Judging
have to judge whether our optimism is warranted. Mindful of the fate of Gaul,
we nevertheless divide this essay into three parts: In the first part, we describe
what judges do when they decide constitutional questions, concluding that
they are primarily exercising the same legal expertise that judges and lawyers
utilize in all of their professional decisions. In the second part we focus briefly
on the personal and contextual characteristics that have been shown to
produce or interfere with expert decision making in general. Finally, we
turn to our main focus: the legal structures that might enhance the positive
characteristics and minimize the negative ones.
ambiguous text (Farber & Sherry 2002, pp. 1028). Given that professional
historians themselves disagree about such issues, and that judges are not
trained in historical analysis, originalism cannot effectively constrain judicial
discretion. Indeed, it is likely to prove less effective in constraining discretion
than the common law method, with which judges have years of professional
training and experience to guide them (Farber & Sherry, 2002, pp. 153154).
So how do judges make decisions in constitutional and nonconstitutional
cases? What distinguishes a reasonable answer from an unreasonable one, a
legitimate decision from an illegitimate one? As we argue in our book, we can
look to administrative law to help us answer these questions. Legislatures
often delegate broad but not unlimited discretion to administrative agencies,
and courts are frequently called on to review agency action to determine
whether it is a legitimate exercise of the agencys discretion. In doing so,
courts focus on two aspects of the agencys decision: They ask whether the
agency considered all of the relevant factors and only the relevant factors, and
they ask whether the decision was arbitrary and capricious.1
Administrative decision making also helps us see how sound judgment
and expertise can play a key role in decision making even in situations where
politics and ideology matter. Clearly, it matters whether the administrator
of EPA is appointed by a Republican or a Democrat. But science, law, and
economic analysis also matter. Two good professional EPA administrators
appointed by presidents of different parties (say, William Ruckelshaus and
Carol Browner) have more in common with each other, and their decisions
have more similarity, than either has with a political ideologue like Anne
Burford. The exercise of discretion leaves room for a variety of factors, but not
all of those factors are political. Good administrative decisions are also shaped
by legal directives, prior practice, and rigorous analysis. So it is with consti-
tutional interpretation.
When good judging is described in this way, it should be apparent that it
is not very different from good decision making in other contexts. Expert
decision making, judicial and otherwise, is the ability to identify and take into
account all of the relevant information and then draw reasonable conclusions.
Lawyers rely on this sort of expertise all this time: when advising a client about
whether a proposed course of action is likely to lead to legal liability, when
drafting a contract designed to have a certain legal effect, or when deciding
whether a particular legal argument might persuade a court. Of course,
lawyers do not always agree about the right answer, and these disagreements
may relate in part to broader differences in personal experience and perspec-
tive, but there is a core of shared skills in these tasks. Interpreting the
Constitution may have more political salience than interpreting a statute, a
contract, or a body of precedents, but it is fundamentally analogous. Judicial
expertise is simply legal expertise in a different context.
Once we conclude that judicial decision-making is the exercise of legal
expertise, we can turn to the field of psychology and expert decision making
more broadly to help us understand what personal and situational factors
288 Evaluating and Improving Judging
Legal Characteristics
With these personal and situational characteristics in mind, we can now
examine which aspects of the American legal landscape are likely to be
conducive to good judicial decision-making, which might be in need of
improvement, and what changes we might want to make.
Building a Better Judiciary 289
federal judges, should be appointed rather than elected. The public has no way
to evaluate a candidates judgment or expertise, so it is no surprise that elected
judges are only coincidentally good decision makers.
One further factor should guide the selection process. Since heteroge-
neity has been shown to improve collegial decision making, we should try to
maintain a diversity of viewpoints on the bench. This often happens naturally,
as presidents and senates with different perspectives have a chance to nomi-
nate and confirm new judges. But long periods of single-party rule, random
fluctuations in the judicial vacancy rate, and particular commitments to
ideological nominees can sometimes produce a largely homogeneous judi-
ciary. When this seems likely, senators of both parties should take seriously
our constitutional ideal of an independent judiciary, and insist on greater
diversity. (We can dream, cant we?) To the extent that presidents focus on
expertise and open-mindedness rather than ideology, of course, deliberately
creating diversity will be less necessary.
Moving from individual character traits to the institutional context, a
number of existing structural features enhance judicial decision making. The
two most important are the collegial and hierarchical structure of the judi-
ciary, and the tradition of issuing written opinions to explain judicial deci-
sions. A less important but still significant factor is the influence of multiple
nonjudicial actors on judicial decision making.
All American appellate courts make their decisions collegially, on
multimember panels. Since virtually all important constitutional questions
get to the appellate level, we need not be overly concerned about constitu-
tional adjudication by single judges at the trial level. Additionally, all judges
save the nine on the Supreme Court are subject to oversight by other
judges. Thus all judges must persuade others in order to prevail, and all
except the nine justices are directly or indirectly accountable to some other
court. Both collegiality and accountability, the two most important situa-
tional characteristics for good decision making, are therefore already
present.
The heterogeneous nature of the judiciary contributes two further ben-
efits. First, collegial decision making by a heterogeneous group injects mul-
tiple perspectives and limits the problem of self-reinforcement within the
members of the group. Second, because judges often know neither the
identities nor the perspectives of those who will be reviewing their decisions,
the beneficial effect of accountability is increased. This will always be true for
decisions by trial court judges. It can also be true for judges on three-member
federal appellate panels, whose decisions might be scrutinized by other
members of their court via a petition for en banc review, by the Supreme
Court, or by both. These judges may also be concerned about how their
decisions will be received by colleagues in different circuits, who are not
bound by their decisions and are free to criticize them.
Even more important is the fact that in the United States (as in most
countries whose legal systems are primarily derived from the English
Building a Better Judiciary 293
common law regime), judges routinely issue written opinions explaining and
justifying their decisions. Judicial decision making is therefore relatively
transparent. This transparency enhances decision making by subjecting deci-
sions to public scrutiny and thereby increasing accountability. It also forces
judges to confront counterevidence and counterarguments. Many judges
recount the experience of having reached a particular decision, only to have
a change of heart after finding that the opinion wont write. A judicial
career spent deliberating with colleagues and writing opinions is also likely to
lead to greater open-mindedness and critical thinking over time, further
improving the quality of decision making in life-tenured judges. It is well-
known that judges can grow on the bench, and the psychological literature
on decision making may offer a partial explanation.
Unfortunately, opinion-writing is declining in the federal appellate
courts, as more and more cases are decided by perfunctory unpublished
decisions. The recent adoption of Fed. R. App. Proc. 32.1, which bars courts
from prohibiting the citation of unpublished opinions, should help alleviate
this problem; since most unpublished opinions are easily located through
electronic databases, it was only the courts prior ban on citation that allowed
such decisions to escape scrutiny. Now that judges know that all their
opinions are subject to citation, they are more likely to take them all seriously.
But the underlying problem is one of time and resources: As long as the
federal appellate docket is overloaded, judges will not be able to devote
sufficient time to each case. Increasing the number of courts or judges
might help, but is not a panacea, because it could create more inter- and
intracircuit conflicts. In the end, we have to decide which cases are most in
need of federal judicial resources, and cut back on the others. Our own view is
that Congress has been acting irresponsibly by increasing federal jurisdiction
in diversity cases (which do not need federal adjudication in the first place)
and by enacting too many federal criminal statutes that simply criminalize
behavior that is already punishable under state law. In part, this trend is
driven by a sense that federal judges are more capable of handling complex,
major cases, but a better solution would be federal funding to help state courts
develop this capacity. In any case, we cannot expect good decisions from
judges whose dockets are bloated with cases unworthy of their attention.
Finally, although judges are ultimately responsible for their own deci-
sions, they are subject to multiple influences and thus to multiple perspec-
tives. The adversary system ensures that all interested parties will have a say.
Most appellate judges have law clerks, whose short tenure and youthful
perspective can complement the judges experience. And to the extent that
judicial opinions are subject to critical scrutiny by law professors, journalists,
politicians, and the public, judges may have to refine their views over time.
We also have some improvements to suggest, especially at the Supreme
Court level. First, the problem of insufficient attention to each case is not
limited to the lower courts, although the problem is somewhat different in the
Supreme Court. It is not that they have too many casesindeed, we think
294 Evaluating and Improving Judging
they decide too fewbut that they place unnecessary artificial limits on the
amount of time for each case. Two small changes could have a great effect:
Routinely allow more than one hour for oral argument, and permit cases to
carry over into the next term if some number of justices think more time
should be devoted to deliberation or to opinion writing.
Another problem is that the Courts focus on constitutional and other
politically salient cases has a tendency to make its job seem more exceptional,
and less like ordinary legal decision making. To the extent that the justices
themselves believe this, it might interfere with their judgment. Again, two
changes could help alleviate the problem by exposing the justices to a greater
number of more routine (albeit legally difficult) cases. The Supreme Courts
mandatory jurisdiction might be expanded, so that it is required to decide
more cases: for example, cases in which the circuit courts disagreein mid-
twentieth century the Court tried to resolve almost all circuit splits, but now it
ignores most of them. Another possibility would be to reinstate the justices
circuit-riding duties, requiring them to sit regularly with courts of appeals
and hear the gamut of cases (Sherry, 2005). Some appellate judges, including
Richard Posner on the Seventh Circuit and the late Chief Justice William
Rehnquist, have voluntarily chosen to sit as trial judges, and we suspect the
experience was good for them.
We also think that it is useful for judges to be exposed to other view-
points. The problem is that most people with whom they associate have every
reason to cater to their viewsfew lawyers will tell a sitting judge that his
views are wrong, and lower courts judges are equally unlikely to provide
challenges to the intellectual viewpoints of their reviewing courts. It is useful
for high court judges to meet with their peers: state supreme court judges with
colleagues in other states; U.S. Supreme Court justices with colleagues from
foreign constitutional courts. To encourage this, Congress should provide
funding to assist in meetings of state court judges and to finance travel to
foreign conferences, as well as funding to hold conferences with foreign jurists
on U.S. soil.
A final proposal would be to encourage peer review, especially at the
Supreme Court level. A panel of eminent retired judges, lawyers, and academics
might be created, on the understanding that subgroups of those with relevant
expertise would be selected to give feedback on Supreme Court opinions before
they are issued. A particularly noncontroversial form of this review would be to
require the circulation of opinions to retired justices for comment. Playing this
peer review role might make retirement more attractive to some justices,
increasing turnover and therefore potentially diversity on the Court. Retired
solicitors general and attorneys general might also be recruited with minimal
controversy. A more modest, and less controversial, program would be to
appoint a nonpartisan commission with the charge of issuing assessments of
the Courts performance on a regular basis.
Considered individually, it is possible that none of these proposals would
have a substantial effect. They might, however, have a significant cumulative
Building a Better Judiciary 295
impact. They might also have some effect on the recruitment and retention of
judges, making the job more attractive to the kind of people we wish to have
as judges: those who enjoy being exposed to different viewpoints and who like
engaging in legal analysis rather than political rhetoric.
None of these existing or proposed structural features, of course, guar-
antees good decision making. A judge who is dogmatic and closed-minded or
whose hedgehog-like devotion to certainty or to an abstract theory is unshak-
able will not be swayed by colleagues or critics nor dissuaded by the impos-
sibility of writing a coherent opinion. In the end, then, it is the character traits
that are most important. Former Attorney General Nicholas Katzenbach put
it most eloquently when he told the Senate Judiciary Committee deliberating
on the nomination of Robert Bork: Were I in your position . . . the central
question I would be asking is this. Is Judge Bork a man of judgment? . . . Is he a
wise person? (Lewis, 1987). It is our hope that the project begun with this
book will eventually help us answer that question about future nominees.
Note
1. The leading case is Citizens to Preserve Overton Park v. Volpe, 401 U.S. 402
(1971).
This page intentionally left blank
References
297
298 References
Aliotta, J. M. (1988). Social backgrounds, social motives, and participation on the U.S.
Supreme Court. Political Behavior, 10, 267284.
Alpert, L., Atkins, B. M., & Ziller, R. C. (1979). Becoming a judge: The transition from
advocate to arbiter. Judicature, 62, 325335.
Altman, S. (1990). Beyond candor. Michigan Law Review, 89, 296.
American Bar Association Committee on Judicial Performance Evaluation. (2005).
Black Letter Guidelines for the Evaluation of Judicial Performance with Commentary.
Anderson, A. A., Lindsay, J. L., and Bushman, B. J. (1999). Research in the
psychological laboratory: Truth or triviality? Current Directions in Psychological
Science, 8, 39
Anderson, M. C., & MacCoun, R. J. (1999). Goal conflict in juror assessments of
compensatory and punitive damages. Law & Human Behavior, 23, 313.
Arlen, J. (1998). The future of behavioral economic analysis of law. Vanderbilt Law
Review, 51, 17651788.
Arlen, J. H., & Talley, E. L. (in press). Introduction. In J. H. Arlen & E. L. Talley (Eds.),
Experimental Law and Economics, pp. 156. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar
Publishing.
Aronson, E., Wilson, T. D., & Brewer, M. B. (1998). Experimentation in social
psychology. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The Handbook of
Social Psychology, Vol. 1 (4th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Arrow, H., McGrath, J. E., & Berdahl, H. L. (2000). Small Groups as Complex Systems:
Formation, Coordination, Development, and Adaptation. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Asch, S. (1955). Opinions and social pressure. Scientific American, 193(5), 3135.
Asch, S. (1956). Studies of independence and conformity: A minority of one against a
unanimous majority. Psychological Monographs, 70(9), Whole Number 416.
Asch, S. E. (1940). Studies in the principles of judgments and attitudes: II.
Determination of judgments by group and by ego standards. The Journal of
Social Psychology, 12, 433465.
Ashwander v. Tennessee Valley Authority, 297 U.S. 288 (1936).
Atkins, B. M., & Zavoina, W. (1974). Judicial leadership on the court of appeals: A
probability analysis of panel assignment in race relations cases on the Fifth
Circuit. American Journal of Political Science, 18, 701711.
Austin, J. (2006). Do the Supreme Court Justices Questions during Oral Arguments
Predict their Decisions? Honors Thesis, Department of Psychology, University of
Kansas, Lawrence.
Bainbridge, S. M., & Gulati, G. M. (2002). How do judges maximize? (The same way
everyone else doesboundedly): Rules of thumb in securities fraud opinions.
Emory Law Journal, 51, 83151.
Bales, R. F. (1950). Interaction Process Analysis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bandstra, R. A. (2005). Looking toward Lansing: Could you be a lawyer-legislator?
Michigan Bar Journal, 89, 2829.
Barber, J. D. (1965). The Lawmakers: Recruitment and Adaptation to Legislative Life.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Barberis, N., & Thaler, R. (2003). A survey of behavioral finance. In G. M.
Constantinides, M. Harris, & R. M. Stulz (Eds.), Handbook of the Economics of
Finance. Amsterdam: Elvesier.
Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being.
American Psychologist, 54, 462479.
References 299
Berger, J, Wagner, D. G., & Zelditch, M. Jr. (1985). Expectation states theory. In
J.M. Berger & M. Zelditch (Eds.), Status, Rewards, and Influence. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Berlin, I. (1953). The Hedgehog and the Fox: An Essay on Tolstoys View of History.
Chicago, IL: Ivan R. Dee.
Bertrand, M., & Mullainathan, S. (2004). Are Emily and Greg more employable than
Lakisha and Jamal? A field experiment on labor market discrimination. The
American Economic Review, 94, 9911013.
Bickel, A. (1986). The Least Dangerous Branch. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Biskupic, J. (2004, June 8). June is often the time of compromise in court. USA Today,
p. 2A.
Biskupic, J. (2005). Sandra Day OConnor. New York: HarperCollins.
Black, H. C. (1912). Handbook on the Law of Judicial Precedents. St. Paul, MN: West
Publishing Co.
Blair, I. V., Judd, C. M., & Chalpeau, K. M. (2004). The influence of Afrocentric facial
features in criminal sentencing. Psychological Science, 15, 674679.
Blanchette, I., & Dunbar, K. N. (2001a). The inVivo/inVitro approach to cognition:
The case of analogy. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5, 334339.
Blanchette, I., & Dunbar, K. N. (2001b). Analogy use in naturalistic settings: The
influence of audience, emotion, and goals. Memory & Cognition, 29, 730735.
Blanchflower v. Blanchflower, 834 A.2d 1010 (N.H. 2003).
Blanck, P. D. (1991). What empirical research tells us: Studying judges and juries
behavior. American University Law Review, 40, 775, 777.
Blanck, P. D., Rosenthal, R., & Cordell, L. H. (1985). The appearance of justice:
Judges verbal and nonverbal behavior in criminal jury trials. Stanford Law
Review, 38, 89.
Boot, M. (1998). Out of Order. New York: Basic Books.
Borchard, E. M. (1932). Convicting the Innocent: Sixty-five Actual Errors of Criminal
Justice. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Bork, R. (1990). The Tempting of America. New York: Touchtone.
Bowen, T., & Scheb, J. M. (1993). Freshman opinion writing on the U.S. Supreme
Court, 19211991. Judicature, 79, 239243.
Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986).
Brace, P. R., & Hall, M. G. (1997). The interplay of preferences, case facts, context, and
rules in the politics of judicial choice. Journal of Politics, 59, 1206.
Braman, E. (2004). Motivated Reasoning in Legal Decision Making. Doctoral
dissertation, Ohio State University, Columbus.
Braman, E. (2006a). Reasoning on the threshold: Testing the separability of
preferences in legal decision making. Journal of Politics, 68, 308321.
Braman, E. (2006b, February 15). Exploring discretion in legal decision making: An
experimental approach. Paper prepared for Presentation at Law & Society
Workshop, University of Indiana University Law School.
Braman, E., & Nelson, T. E. (2007). Mechanism of motivated reasoning?: Analogical
perception in discrimination disputes. American Journal of Political Science,
51(4), 940956.
Brandeis, L. D. (1916). The living law. Illinois Law Review, 10, 461.
Breasted, J. H. (2001). Ancient Records of Egypt: Volume Two. The Eighteenth Dynasty.
Urbana-Champaign: University of Illinois Press.
References 301
Brehm, S. S., & Brehm, J. W. (1981). Psychological Reactance: A Theory of Freedom and
Control. New York: Academic Press.
Brenner, S., & Hagle, T. M. (1996). Opinion writing and acclimation effect. Political
Behavior, 18, 235261.
Breyer, S. (2005). Active Liberty. New York: Vintage Books.
Brenner, S., & Spaeth, H. J. (1995). Stare Indecisis. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Brewer, M. (1979). In-group bias in the minimal intergroup situation: A cognitive-
motivational analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 86, 307324.
Brewer, M. (1991). The social self: On being the same and different at the same time.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 17, 475482.
Brewer, S. (1996). Exemplary reasoning: Semantics, pragmatics, and the rational force
of legal argument by analogy. Harvard Law Review, 109, 9251028.
Bright, S. B., & Keenan, P. J. (1995). Judges and the politics of death: Deciding between
the bill of rights and the next election in capital cases. Boston University Law
Review, 75, 759.
Brooks, R. R. W., & Raphael, S. (2003). Life terms or death sentences: The uneasy
relationship between judicial elections and capital punishment. Journal of
Criminal Law and Criminology, 92, 609.
Brudney, J. J., & Ditslear, C. (2001). Designated diffidence: District court judges on the
courts of appeals. Law & Society Review, 35, 565606.
Brust, R. (2005, September). Balancing act. American Bar Association Journal, 37.
Buchman, J. (2007). The effects of ideology on federal district judges decisions to
admit expert testimony. American Political Science Review, 35, 671.
Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393 (1932).
Burton, S. (2005). An Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning (3d ed.). Frederick,
MD: Aspen Publishers.
Bush v. Vera, 517 U.S. 952 (1996).
Bushman, B. J. (1995). Moderating role of trait aggressiveness in the effects of
violent media on aggression. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 950960.
Buthe, T. (2002). Taking temporality seriously: Modeling history and the use of
narratives as evidence. American Political Science Review, 96, 481494.
Byrne, M. D. (1995). The convergence of explanatory coherence and the story model:
A case study in juror decisions. In J. D. Moore & J. F. Lehman (Eds.), Proceedings
of the 17th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Mahwah, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Caldeira, G. A. (1977). Judicial incentives: Some evidence from urban trial courts.
Iusticia, 4(2), 128.
Caldeira, G. A., & Wright, J. R. (1990). The discuss list: Agenda building in the
Supreme Court. Law & Society Review, 24, 807836.
California Supreme Court. (n.d.) Internal Operating Practices and Procedures of the
California Supreme Court. Retrieved August 27, 2007, from http://
www.courtinfo.ca.gov/courts/supreme/documents/sc082504.pdf
Callins v. Collins, 510 U.S. 1141 (1994).
Caminker, E. H. (1994). Why must inferior courts obey superior court precedents?
Stanford Law Review, 46, 817873.
Campbell, J. (2005). The Lives of the Chief Justices of England: From the Norman
Conquest Till the Death of Lord Mansfield. London: Elibron Classics.
302 References
Cardozo, B. N. (1921). The Nature of the Judicial Process. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Carp, R. A., & Rowland, C. K. (1983). Policymaking and Politics in the Federal District
Courts. Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press.
Cartwright, D. (1968) The nature of group cohesiveness. In D. Cartwright & A.
Zander (Eds.), Group Dynamics: Research and Theory(3d ed.). New York: Row,
Peterson, & Co.
Cartwright, D., & Zander, A. (1968). Origins of group dynamics. In D. Cartwright &
A. Zander (Eds.), Group Dynamics: Research and Theory(3d ed.). New York: Row,
Peterson, & Co.
Catrambone, R., & Holyoak, K. J. (1989). Overcoming contextual limitations on
problem-solving transfer. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning,
Memory, and Cognition, 15, 11471156.
Cattell, R. B. (1963). Theory of fluid and crystallized intelligence: A critical
experiment. Journal of Education Psychology, 54, 122.
Chaiken, S. (1980). Heuristic versus systematic information processing and the use of
source versus message cues in persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 39, 752766.
Chaiken, S., Giner-Sorolla, R., & Chen, S. (1996). Beyond accuracy: Defense and
impression motives in heuristic and systematic information processing. In
P. M. Gollwitzer & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The Psychology of Action: Linking
Cognition and Motivation to Behavior. New York: Guilford Press.
Chaiken, S., Liberman, A., & Eagly, A. H. (1989). Heuristic and systematic
information processing within and beyond the persuasion context. In J. S.
Uleman & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), Unintended Thought. New York: Guilford Press.
Chaiken, S., & Trope, Y. (Eds.). (1999). Dual-Process Theories in Social Psychology.
New York: Guilford Press.
Champagne, A. (1986). The selection and retention of judges in Texas. Southwestern
Law Journal, 40, 53.
Champagne, A. (2005). Tort reform and judicial selection. Loyola of Los Angeles Law
Review, 38, 1483.
Chapman, G. B., & Bornstein, B. H. (1996). The more you ask for, the more you get:
Anchoring in personal injury verdicts. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 10, 519, 527, 531.
Chapper, J. A., & Hanson, R. A. (1990). Intermediate Appellate Courts: Improving Case
Processing. Williamsburg, VA: National Center for State Courts.
Chen, S., & Chaiken, S. (1999). The heuristic-systematic model in its broader context.
In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-Process Theories in Social Psychology. New
York: Guilford Press.
Chi, M. T. H. (2006). Two approaches to the study of experts characteristics. In
K. A. Ericsson, N. Charness, P. J. Feltovich, & R. R. Hoffman (Eds.), The
Cambridge Handbook of Expertise and Expert Performance. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Chi, M. T. H., Farr, M. J., & Glaser, R. (Eds.). (1988). The Nature of Expertise. Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Chi, M. T. H., Feltovich, P. J., & Glaser, R. (1981). Categorization and representation
of physics problems by experts and novices. Cognitive Science, 5, 121152.
Choi, S. J., & Gulati, G. M. (2004a). Choosing the next supreme court justice: An
empirical ranking of judge performance. Southern California Law Review, 78,
23117.
References 303
Cross, F. B. (2004). Explaining U.S. Circuit Court Decision Making. Judicature, 88,
3135.
Cross, F. B. (2007). Decision Making in the U.S. Courts of Appeals. Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Cross, F., & Tiller, E. (1998). Judicial partisanship and obedience to legal doctrine:
Whistleblowing on the Federal Courts of Appeals. Yale Law Journal, 107,
21552176.
Cross, F. B., & Nelson, B. J. (2001). Strategic institutional effects on Supreme Court
decisionmaking. Northwestern University Law Review, 95, 14371493.
Cross, F. B., & Lindquist, S. A. (2007). The scientific study of judicial activism.
Minnesota Law Review, 91, 17521784.
Cross, R., & Harris, J. W. (1990). Precedent in English Law (4th ed.). Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Cushman, B. (2000). Formalism and realism in Commerce Clause jurisprudence.
University of Chicago Law Review, 67, 1089.
Dagan, H. (2007). The realist conception of law. University of Toronto Law Journal, 57,
607660.
Dalgleish, L. I. (2003). Risk, needs and consequences. In M.C. Calder (Ed.),
Assessments in Child Care: A comprehensive Guide to Frameworks and Their Use.
(pp. 8699). Dorset, UK: Russell House Publishing.
Dalgleish, L., & Weiss, D. (2007). Evidence-based expertise: A theoretical framework and
some data. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Brunswik Society, Long
Beach, CA.
Dancy, J. (1993). Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.
Danelski, D. J. (1960). The influence of the Chief Justice in the decisional process. In
W. M. Murphy & C. H. Pritchett (Eds.), Courts, Judges, and Politics. New York:
Random House.
Daniels, N. (1979). Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance. Journal of
Philosophy, 76, 256.
Darley, J. M. (2001). The dynamics of authority influence in organization and the
unintended action consequences. In J. M. Darley, D. M. Messick, & T. R. Tyler
(Eds.), Social Influences on Ethical Behavior in Organizations. Mahwah, NJ:
L. Erlbaum.
Darley, J. M., Carlsmith, K. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2000). Incapacitation and
just deserts as motives for punishment. Law and Human Behavior, 24,
659683.
Darley, J. M., & Pittman, T. S. (2003). The psychology of compensatory and
retributive justice. Personality & Social Psychology Review, 7, 324336.
Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, 509 U.S. 579 (1993).
Dekay, M. L. (1996). The difference between Blackstone-like error ratios and
probabilistic standards of proof. Law & Social Inquiry, 21(1), 95132.
Denniston, L. (2005, November 27). Court to rule on military tribunals. Web site:
http://www.scotusblog.com/movabletype/archives/2005/
Denzau, A., Riker, W., & Shepsle, K. (1985). Farquharson and Fenno: Sophisticated
voting and home style. American Political Science Review, 79, 117134.
Deutsch, M. (1975). Equity, equality, and need: What determines which value will be
used as the basis of distributive justice. Journal of Social Issues, 31, 137.
Devins, N. (2004). The judicial safeguards of federalism. Northwestern University Law
Review, 99, 131.
References 305
Devins, N., & Fisher, L. (2004). The Democratic Constitution. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Devins, N., & Meese, A. (2005). Judicial review and non-generalizable cases. Florida
State University Law Review, 32, 323.
Devitt, E. J. (1979). Ten commandments for the new judge. American Bar Association
Journal, 65, 574.
Dhami, M. K. (2003). Psychological models of professional decision making.
Psychological Science, 14, 175180.
Dhami, M. K. (2004). Conditional bail decision making in the magistrates court.
Howard Journal of Criminal Justice, 43(1), 2746.
Dhami, M. K. (2005) From discretion to disagreement: Explaining disparities in
judges pretrial decisions. Behavioral Sciences & the Law, 23(3), 367386.
Dobie, A. M. (1951). A judge judges judges. Washington University Law Quarterly,
1951, 471.
Dorff, R. H., & Steiner, J. (1981). Political decision making in face-to-face groups:
Theory, methods, and an empirical application in Switzerland. American Political
Science Review, 75, 368380.
Dovidio, J. F., Kawakami, K., Johnson, C., Johnson, B., & Howard, A. (1997). On the
nature of prejudice: Automatic and controlled processes. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 33, 510540.
Downs, A. (1957). An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper & Row.
Drahozal, C. R. (1998). Judicial incentives and the appeals process. Southern Methodist
Law Review, 51, 469503.
Druckman, J. (2001). The limits of framing effects: Who can frame. Journal of Politics,
63(4), 104166.
Dubois, P. L. (1980). From Ballot to Bench: Judicial Elections and the Quest for
Accountability. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Duckworth, K. L., Bargh, J. A., Garcia, M., & Chaikin, S. (2002). The automatic
evaluation of novel stimuli. Psychological Science, 13, 513519.
Duncker, K. (1945). On problem-solving (L. S. Lees, Trans.). Psychological
Monographs, 58(5), Whole No. 270.
Duxbury, N. (1995). Patterns of American Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Dworkin, R. (1986). Laws Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The Psychology of Attitudes. Fort Worth, TX:
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Edwards, H. T. (1985). Public misperceptions concerning the politics of judging:
Dispelling some myths about the D.C. Circuit. University of Colorado Law Review,
56, 619.
Edwards, H. T. (1998). Collegiality and decision making on the D.C. Circuit. Virginia
Law Review, 83, 13351370.
Edwards, H. T. (2003). The effects of collegiality on judicial decision making.
University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 151, 16391689.
Edwards, W. (1983). Human cognitive capacities, representativeness, and ground
rules for research. In P. Humphreys, O. Svenson, & A. Vari (Eds.), Analyzing
and Aiding Decision Processes. Budapest, Hungary: Akademiai Kiado.
Edwards, W., & Newman, J. R. (1982). Multiattribute Evaluation. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Einhorn, J. (1974). Expert judgment: Some necessary conditions and an example.
Journal of Applied Psychology, 59, 562571.
306 References
Eisenberg, M. A. (1988). The Nature of the Common Law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Eisenberg, T., Garvey, S. P., & Wells, M. T. (2001). Forecasting life and death: Juror
race, religion, and attitude toward the death penalty. The Journal of Legal Studies,
30, 277311.
Eisenberg, T., Hannaford-Agor, P. L., Hans, V. P., Waters, N. L.; Munsterman, G. T.,
Schwab, S. J., et al. (2005). Judge-jury agreement in criminal cases: A partial
replication of Kalven and Zeisels The American Jury. Journal of Empirical Legal
Studies, 2(1), 171207.
Eisenberg, T., LaFountain, N., Ostrom, B., Rottman, D., & Wells, M. T. (2002). Juries,
judges, and punitive damages: An empirical study. Cornell Law Review, 87, 743,
747749.
Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972).
Eisler, K. I. (1993). A Justice for All: William J. Brennan, Jr., and the Decisions That
Transformed America. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Ellsworth, P. C., & Mauro, R. (1998). Psychology and law. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske
& G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of Social Psychology (4th ed., pp. 684732). New
York: McGraw-Hill.
Elster, J. (1989). The Cement of Society. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Enelow, J. M., & Hinch, M. (1990). Advances in the Spatial Theory of Voting. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Englich, B., Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (2006). Playing dice with criminal sentences:
The influence of irrelevant anchors on experts judicial decision making.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32(2), 188200.
Epstein, L., & Jacobi, T. (2008). Super medians. Stanford Law Review, 61, 37.
Epstein, L., & Knight, J. (1998). The Choices Justices Make. Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Epstein, L., & Knight, J. (2000). Toward a strategic revolution in judicial politics: A
look back, a look ahead. Political Research Quarterly, 53, 625661.
Epstein, L., Knight, J., & Martin, A. (2003). The political (science) context of judging.
St. Louis University Law Journal, 47, 783.
Epstein, L., Segal, J. A., & Johnson, T. (1996). The claim of issue creation on the U.S.
Supreme Court. American Political Science Review, 90(4), 845852.
Ericsson, K. A. (2006). The influence of experience and deliberate practice on the
development of superior expert performance. In K. A. Ericsson, N. Charness,
P. J. Feltovich, & R. R. Hoffman (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Expertise and
Expert Performance. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Ericsson, K. A., Charness, N., Feltovich, P. J., & Hoffman, R. R. (Eds.). (2006). The
Cambridge Handbook of Expertise and Expert Performance. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Ericsson, K. A., & Ward, P. (2007). Capturing the naturally occurring superior
performance of experts in the laboratory: Toward a science of expert and
exceptional performance. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 16, 346350.
Eskridge, W. N., Jr. (1991). Reneging on history? Playing the court/congress/president
civil rights game. California Law Review, 79, 613684.
Estrich, S. R., & Sullivan, K. M. (1989). Abortion politics: Writing for an audience of
one. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 138, 119.
Ettenson, R., Shanteau, J., & Krogstad, J. (1987). Expert judgment: Is more
information better? Psychological Reports, 60, 227238.
References 307
Evans, G., Heath, A., & Lalljee, M. (1996). Measuring left-right and libertarian-
authoritarian values in the British electorate. British Journal of Sociology,
47(1), 93112.
Fabrigar, L. R., Wegener, D. T., MacCallum, R. C., & Strahan, E. J. (1999). Evaluating
the use of exploratory factor analysis in psychological research. Psychological
Methods, 4, 27299.
Farber, D. A. (1992). The inevitability of practical reason: Statutes, formalism, and the
rule of law. Vanderbilt Law Review, 45, 533559.
Farber, D. A. (1994). Missing the play of intelligence. William & Mary Law Review,
36, 147171.
Farber, D. A. (1995). Reinventing Brandeis: Legal pragmatism for the 21st century.
University of Illinois Law Review, 1995, 163190.
Farber, D. A. (2005). Supreme Court selection and measures of past judicial
performance. Florida State University Law Review, 32, 117596.
Farber, D. A, & Adams, E. (1999). Beyond the formalism debate: Expert reasoning,
fuzzy logic, and complex statutes. Vanderbilt Law Review, 52, 12431340.
Farber, D. A., & Sherry, S. (2002). Desperately Seeking Certainty: The Misguided Quest
for Constitutional Foundations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Farber, D. A., & Sherry, S. (2008). Judgment Calls: Principle and Politics in
Constitutional Law. New York: Oxford University Press.
Farrell, R. C. (1999). Successful rational basis claims in the Supreme Court from the
1971 term through Romer v. Evans. Indiana Law Journal, 32, 357.
Farthing-Capowich, D. P. (1985). Designing programs to evaluate judicial
performance: Participation is key to success. Supreme Court Journal, 9, 22.
Fazio, R. H. (1986). How do attitudes guide behavior? In R. M. Sorrentino & E. T.
Higgins (Eds.), Handbook of Motivation and Cognition. New York: Guilford Press.
Fazio, R. H. (1990). Multiple processes by which attitudes guide behavior: The MODE
model as integrative framework. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in Experimental
Social Psychology. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Fazio, R. H. (1995). Attitudes as object-evaluation associations: determinants,
consequences, and correlates of attitude accessibility. In R. E. Petty & J. A. Krosnick
(Eds.), Attitude Strength: Antecedents and Consequences. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Fazio, R. H., Jackson, J. R., Dunton, B. C., & Williams, C. J. (1982). Attitude
accessibility, attitude-behavior consistency, and the strength of the object-
evaluation association. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 18, 339357.
Fazio, R. H., & Towles-Schwen, T. (1999). The MODE model of attitude-behavior
processes. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual Process Theories in Social
Psychology. New York: Guilford Press.
Fazio, R. H., & Williams, C. J. (1986). Attitude accessibility as a moderator of the
attitude-perception and attitude-behavior relations: An investigation of the 1984
presidential election. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 505514.
FCC v. Beach Communications, Inc., 508 U.S. 307, 315 (1993).
Feigenson, N. R. (2003). Can tort juries punish competently? Chicago-Kent Law
Review, 78, 239.
Feltovich, P. J., Prietula, M. J., & Ericsson, K. A. (2006). Studies of expertise from
psychological perspectives. In K. A. Ericsson, N. Charness, P. J. Feltovich, & R. R.
Hoffman (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Expertise and Expert Performance.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
308 References
Fennell, L. A. (1999). Between monster and machine: Rethinking the judicial function.
Southern California Law Review, 51, 183.
Fenno, R. M. (1973). Congressmen in Committees. Boston: Little, Brown.
Festinger, L. (1957). A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Evanston, IL: Row, Peterson.
Festinger, L. (1968). Informal social communication. In D. Cartwright & A. Zander
(Eds.), Group Dynamics: Research and Theory (3d ed.). New York: Row,
Peterson, & Co.
Festinger, L., Schacter, S., & Back, K. (1968). Operation of group standards. In D.
Cartwright & A. Zander (Eds.), Group Dynamics: Research and Theory (3d ed.).
New York: Row, Peterson, & Co.
Fiorina, M. P., & Plott, C. R. (1978). Committee decisions under majority rule: An
experimental study. American Political Science Review, 72, 575598.
Fischman, J. B. (2008). Decision-making under a norm of consensus: A structural
analysis of three-judge panels. Unpublished manuscript.
Fishburn, P. C. (1991). Decision theory: The next 100 years? Economic Journal, 101, 27.
Fisher, W. W., III, Horwitz, M. J., & Reed, T.A. (Eds.). (1993). American Legal Realism.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Fiske, S. T. (2003). Five core social motives, plus or minus five. In S. Spencer, S. Fein,
M. P. Zanna, & J. M. Olson, Motivated Social Perception. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Fiske, S. T., and Taylor, S. E. (1991). Social Cognition. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Fong, G. T., Krantz, D. H., & Nisbett, R. E. (1986). The effects of statistical training on
thinking about everyday problems. Cognitive Psychology, 18, 253.
Forgas, J. P. (Ed.). (2000). Feeling and Thinking: The Role of Affect in Social Cognition.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Foroni, F. & Mayr, U. (2005). The power of a story: New, automatic associations from
a single reading of a short scenario. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 12, 139144.
Forsyth, D. R. (1999). Group Dynamics (3d ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Foucha v. Louisiana, 504 U.S. 71 (1992).
Frank, J. (1930). Law and the Modern Mind. New York: Brentanos.
Frankel, M. E. (1975). The search for truth: An umpireal view. University of
Pennsylvania Law Review, 123, 1031.
Frankel, M. E. (1976). The adversary judge. Texas Law Review, 54, 465.
Frankfurter, F. (1953). Chief justices I have known. Virginia Law Review, 39, 83.
Frey, D. (1986). Recent research on selective exposure to information. In L. Berkowitz
(Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology (vol. 19). New York: Academic
Press.
Frickey, P. (1996). The fool on the hill: Congressional findings, constitutional
adjudication, and United States v Lopez. Case Western Law Review, 46, 695.
Fried, C. (1981). The artificial reason of the law or: What lawyers know. Texas Law
Review, 60, 3558.
Friedman, B. (2006). Taking law seriously. Perspectives on Politics, 4, 261276.
Friedman, L. (2002). The Rehnquist court: Some more or less historical comments. In
M. Belky (Ed.), The Rehnquist Court: A Retrospective. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Fumerton, R. A. (1990). Reason and Morality. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Funder, D. C. (1999). Personality Judgment: A Realistic Approach to Person Perception.
San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Funder, D. C. (2001). The Personality Puzzle. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
References 309
Furgeson, J. R., Babcock, L., & Shane, P. M. (2008a). Behind the mask of method:
Political orientation and constitutional interpretive preferences. Law and Human
Behavior, 32, 502510.
Furgeson, J. R., Babcock, L., & Shane, P. M. (2008b). Do a laws policy implications
affect beliefs about its constitutionality? An experimental test. Law and Human
Behavior, 32, 21927.
Gaeth, G. J., & Shanteau, J. (1984). Reducing the influence of irrelevant information
on experienced decision makers. Organizational Behavior and Human
Performance, 33, 263282.
Gaffney, E. M., Jr. (1994). The importance of dissent and the imperative of judicial
civility. Valparaiso University Law Review, 28, 583646.
Galanter, M. (2004). The vanishing trial: An examination of trials and related matters
in federal and state courts. Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 1, 459.
Gardner, H. (1985). The Minds New Science: The History of the Cognitive Revolution.
New York: Basic Books.
Garrett, B. (2008). Judging innocence. Columbia Law Review, 108, 55142.
Gatowski, S. I., Dobbin, S. A., Richardson, J. T., Ginsburg, G. P., Merlino, M. L., & Dahir,
V. (2001). Asking the gatekeepers: A national survey of judges on judging expert
evidence in a post-Daubert world. Law and Human Behavior, 25, 433, 442.
Gavison, R. (1988). The implications of jurisprudential theories for judicial election,
selection, and accountability. Southern California Law Review, 61, 1617.
Gawande, A. (2000). When doctors make mistakes. In J. Gleick & J. Cohen (Eds.), The
Best American Science Writing 2000. New York: HarperCollins.
Gellis, S. L. (1985). Reasons for case reversal in Texas. St. Marys Law Journal, 16, 299.
Gelman, S. (2001). The hedgehog, the fox, and the minimalist. Georgetown Law
Journal, 89, 22972350.
Gentner, D. (1983). Structure-mapping: A theoretical framework. Cognitive Science, 7,
155170.
Gentner, D. (1989). The mechanisms of analogical reasoning. In S. Vosniadou & A.
Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and Analogical Reasoning. London: Cambridge
University Press.
Gentner, D. (1998). Analogy. In W. Bechtel and G. Graham (Eds.), Companion to
Cognitive Science. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Gentner, D., & Kurtz, K. (2006). Relations, objects, and the composition of analogies.
Cognitive Science, 30, 609642.
Gentner, D., & Kurtz, K. (2007). Relational categories. In W. Ahn, R. L. Goldstone, B.
C. Love, A. B. Markman, & P. Wolff (Eds.), Categorization Inside and Outside the
Laboratory: Essays in Honor of Douglas L. Medin. Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association.
Gentner, D., & Loewenstein, J. (2002). Relational language and relational thought. In E.
Amsel & J. P. Byrnes (Eds.), Language, Literacy, and Cognitive Development: The
Development and Consequences of Symbolic Communication. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Gentner, D., & Markman, A. B. (1994). Structural alignment in comparison: No
difference without similarity. Psychological Science, 5, 152158.
Gentner, D., Rattermann, M. J., & Forbus, K. D. (1993). The roles of similarity in
transfer: Separating retrievability from inferential soundness. Cognitive
Psychology, 25, 524575.
George, T. E. (1998). Developing a positive theory of decisionmaking on the U.S.
Courts of Appeals. Ohio State Law Journal, 58, 1635.
310 References
George, T. E. (1999). The dynamics and determinants of the decision to grant en banc
review. Washington University Law Review, 74, 1635.
George, T. E., & Yooh, A. H. (n.d.). Chief judges: The limits of attitudinal theory and
possible paradox of managerial judging. Available at Social Science Research
Network: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1001247.
George, A. (1980). Presidential Decisionmaking in Foreign Policy: The Effective Use of
Information and Advice. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
George, T. E. (2001). Court fixing. Arizona Law Review, 43, 962.
George, T. E., & Epstein, L. (1992). On the nature of Supreme Court decision making.
American Political Science Review 86, 323337.
Gerber, S. D., & Park, K. (1997). The quixotic search for consensus on the U.S.
Supreme Court: A cross-judicial empirical analysis of the Rehnquist Court
justices. American Political Science Review, 91, 390408.
Gey, S. G., & Rossi, J. (2005). Empirical measures of judicial performance: An
introduction to the symposium. Florida State University Law Review, 32, 10011014.
Gibson, J. L. (1980). Environmental constraints on the behavior of judges: A representational
model of judicial decision making. Law and Society Review, 14, 343370.
Gibson, J. L. (1991). Decision making in appellate courts. In J. B. Gates & C. A. Johnson
(Eds.), The American Courts: A Critical Assessment. Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Gibson, J. L. (2006). The Legitimacy of the United States Supreme Court in a Polarized
Polity. Working paper.
Gick, M. L., & Holyoak, K. J. (1980). Analogical problem solving. Cognitive Psychology,
12, 306355.
Gick, M. L., & Holyoak, K. J. (1983). Schema induction and analogical transfer.
Cognitive Psychology, 15, 138.
Gigerenzer, G. (1993). The superego, the ego, and the id in statistical reasoning. In G.
Keren & C. Lewis (Eds.), A Handbook for Data Analysis in the Behavioral Sciences:
Methodological issues. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Adaptive Thinking: Rationality in the Real World. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Gigerenzer, G. (2006). Heuristics. In G. Gigerenzer & C. Engel (Eds.), Heuristics and
the Law. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2001). Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gillman, H. (1993). The Constitution Besieged. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Gillman, H. (1997). Placing judicial motives in context: A response to Lee Epstein and
Jack Knight. Law and Courts, 7 (Spring), 1013.
Gillman, H. (1999). The Court as an idea. In C. W. Clayton & H. Gillman (Eds.),
Supreme Court Decision-Making. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gillman, H. (2001). Whats law got to do with it? Judicial behavioralists test the legal
model of judicial decision making. Law & Social Inquiry, 26, 465504.
Gilovich, T. (1981). Seeing the past in the present: The effect of associations to familiar
events on judgments and decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
40, 797808.
Gilovich, T., Griffin, D. W., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Heuristics and Biases:
The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Ginossar, Z., & Trope, Y. (1987). Problem solving in judgment under uncertainty.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 464474.
References 311
Glaser, R., & Chi, M. T. H. (1998). Overview. In M. T. H. Chi, R. Glaser, & M. J. Farr
(Eds.), The Nature of Expertise. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Glockner, A. (2007, August). Solving complex legal cases using the intuitive system.
Paper presented at the Subjective Probability, Utility, and Decision Making
Conference, Warsaw, Poland.
Glockner, A., Betsch, T., & Schindler, N. (n.d.). Construction of probabilistic inferences
by constraint satisfaction. Unpublished manuscript.
Goffman, E. (1959). The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. New York: Doubleday.
Goldberg, L. R., & Werts, C. E. (1966). The reliability of clinicians judgments: A
multitrait-multimethod approach. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 30, 199206.
Goldberg, S. (2005). Federal judges and the Heisman trophy. Florida State University
Law Review, 32, 12371244.
Golde, R. A. (1969). Can You Be Sure of Your Experts? New York: Award Books.
Golding, M. P. (1963). Principled decision-making and the Supreme Court. Columbia
Law Review, 63, 3558.
Gollwitzer, P. M., & Bargh, J. A. (2005) Automaticity in goal pursuit. In A. J. Elliot &
C. S. Dweck (Eds.), Handbook of Competence and Perception. New York: Guilford
Press.
Graber, M. A. (2006). Dred Scott and the Problem of Constitutional Evil. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Graber, M. L., Franklin, N., & Gordon, R. (2005). Diagnostic error in internal
medicine. Archives of Internal Medicine, 165, 14931499.
Granberg, D., & Bartels, B. (2005). On being a lone dissenter. Journal of Applied Social
Psychology, 35, 18491858.
Greenawalt, K. (1978). The enduring significance of neutral principles. Columbia Law
Review, 78, 9821021.
Greenburg, J. C. (2007). Supreme Conflict: The Inside Story of the Struggle for Control of
the United States Supreme Court. New York: Penguin Press.
Greenhouse, L. (2002, April 18). U.S. joins inmate in prison discipline case. New York
Times, p. A23.
Greenhouse, L. (2004, June 2). Teenagers murder conviction is reinstated after
challenge. New York Times, p. A17.
Greenhouse, L. (2005). Becoming Justice Blackmun: Harry Blackmuns Supreme Court
Journey. New York: Times Books.
Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965).
Groopman, J. (2007). How Doctors Think. New York: Houghton Mifflin.
Groscup, J. L. (2004). Judicial decision making about expert testimony in the aftermath
of Daubert and Kumho. Journal of Forensic Psychology Practice, 4(2), 5766.
Gruenfeld, D. H. (1995). Status, ideology, and integrative complexity on the U.S.
Supreme Court: Rethinking the politics of political decision making. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 68, 520.
Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003).
Gruenfeld, D., & Hollingshead, A. B. (1993). Sociocognition in work groups: The
evolution of integrative complexity and its relation to task performance. Small
Groups Research, 24, 383405.
Gruenfeld, D. H., & Preston, J. (2000). Upending the status quo: Cognitive complexity
in Supreme Court justices who overturn legal precedent. Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin, 26, 10131022.
312 References
Gryski, G. S., Main, E. C., & Dixon, W. J. (1986). Models of high court decision
making in sex discrimination cases. Journal of Politics, 48(1), 143155.
Gulati, M., & Choi, S. J. (2005). Which judges write their opinions (and should we
care?). Florida State University Law Review, 32, 10771122.
Gulati, M., & Choi, S. J. (2007). Ranking judges according to citation bias. Notre Dame
Law Review, 82, 12791309.
Gulati, M., & Sanchez, V. (2002). Giants in a world of pygmies? Testing the
superstar hypothesis with judicial opinions in casebooks. Iowa Law Review, 87, 1141.
Guthrie, C., & George, T. E. (2005). The futility of appeal: Disciplinary insights into
the affirmance effect on the United States Courts of Appeals. Florida State
University Law Review, 32, 357.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., & Wistrich, A. J. (2001). Inside the judicial mind. Cornell
Law Review, 86, 777830.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., & Wistrich, A. J. (2002). Judging by heuristic: Cognitive
illusions in judicial decision making. Judicature, 86, 44.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., & Wistrich, A. J. (2007a). Blinking on the bench: How
judges decide cases. Cornell Law Review, 93, 1.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., & Wistrich, A. J. (2007b). Inside the bankruptcy judges
mind. Boston University Law Review, 86, 1227.
Guthrie, C., Rachlinski, J. J., & Wistrich, A. J. (2009). The hidden judiciary: An
empirical examination of executive branch justice. Duke Law Journal, 58,
14771530. Hagerstrom, A. (1953). Inquiries into the Nature of Law and Morals
(C. D. Broad, Trans.). Stockholm: Almquist & Wiksell.
Hagle, T. M. (1993). Freshman effects for supreme court justices. American Journal of
Political Science 37, 11421157.
Hall v. Brooklands Auto Racing Club, K.B. 205 (1933).
Hall v. Brooklands Auto-Racing Club, 1 KB 205 (1933).
Hall, M. G. (1992). Electoral politics and strategic voting in state supreme courts.
Journal of Politics, 54, 427446.
Hall, M. G. (1995). Justices as representatives: Elections and judicial politics in the
American states. American Politics Quarterly, 23, 485503.
Hall, R. L. (1996). Participation in Congress. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, 126 S.Ct. 2749 (2006).
Hammond K. R. (1996). Human Judgement and Social Policy: Irreducible Uncertainty,
Inevitable Error and Unavoidable Injustice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hammond, K. R. (2000a). Coherence and correspondence theories in judgment and
decision-making. In T. Connolly, H. R. Arkes, & K. R. Hammond (Eds.),
Judgment and Decision Making: An Interdisciplinary Reader. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Hammond, K. R. (2000b). Judgments Under Stress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hammond, T. H., Bonneau, C. W, & Sheehan, R. S. (2005). Strategic Behavior and
Policy Choice on the U.S. Supreme Court. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Hand, L. (1930). Sources of tolerance. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 79, 1.
Hansford, T. G., & Spriggs, J. F., II. (2006). The Politics of Precedent on the U.S.
Supreme Court. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hanson, J., & Yosifon, D. (2004). The situational character: A critical realist
perspective on the human animal. Georgetown Law Journal, 93, 1177.
Hare, A. P., Borgatta, E. F., & Bales, R. F. (Eds.) (1965). Small Groups: Studies in Social
Interaction, Revised Edition. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
References 313
Harman, G., & Kulkarni, S. R. (2006). The problem of induction. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 72, 559575.
Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Haslett, D. W. (1987). What is wrong with reflective equilibria? Philosophical
Quarterly, 37, 305.
Hastie, R. (2001). Problems for judgment and decision making. Annual Review of
Psychology, 52, 653.
Hastie, R., Schkade, D. A., & Payne, J. W. (1999). Juror judgments in civil cases: Effects
of plaintiffs requests and plaintiffs identity on punitive damage awards. Law &
Human Behavior, 23, 445.
Hausegger, L., & Baum, L. (1999). Inviting congressional action: A study of Supreme
Court motivations in statutory interpretation. American Journal of Political
Science, 43,162185.
Hausegger, L., & Haynie, S. (2003). Judicial decisionmaking and the use of panels in
the Canadian Supreme Court and the South African Appellate Division. Law &
Society Review, 37, 635657.
Haynie, S. L. (1992). Leadership and consensus on the U.S. Supreme Court. Journal of
Politics, 54, 11581169.
Heath, C., Larrick, R. P., & Klayman, J. (1998). Cognitive repairs: How organizational
practices can compensate for individual shortcomings. Research in Organizational
Behavior, 20, 137.
Heider, F. (1946). Attitudes and cognitive organization. Journal of Psychology, 21,
107111.
Heider, F. (1958). The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations. New York: Wiley.
Helmke, G. (2005). Courts under Constraints: Judges, Generals, and Presidents in
Argentina. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Henderson, L. (1987). Legality and empathy. Michigan Law Review, 85, 1574.
Hersch, J., and Viscusi, W. K. (2004). Punitive damages: How judges and juries
perform. Journal of Legal Studies, 33, 1.
Hettinger, V. A., Lindquist, S. A., & Martinek, W. L. (2003). Acclimation effects on the
United States Courts of Appeals. Social Science Quarterly, 84, 792810.
Hettinger, V. A., Lindquist, S. A., & Martinek, W. L. (2006). Judging on a Collegial
Court: Influences on Federal Appellate Decision Making. Charlottesville: University
of Virginia Press.
Higgins, R. W., & Rubin, P. H. (1980). Judicial discretion. Journal of Legal Studies, 9,
129138.
Hinckley, B. (1979). Twenty-one variables beyond the size of winning coalitions.
Journal of Politics, 41,192212.
Hirsch, H. N. (1981). The Enigma of Felix Frankfurter. New York: Basic Books.
Ho, D. E., & Quinn, K. M. (2007). Assessing political positions of media. Stanford Law
and Economics Olin Working Paper No. 343.
Hoffman, P., Slovic, P., & Rorer, L. (1968). An analysis of variance model for the
assessment of configural cue utilization in clinical judgment. Psychological
Bulletin, 69, 338349.
Hofstadter, D. R., & Mitchell, M. (1994). An overview of the copycat project. In K. J.
Holyoak & J. A. Barnden (Eds.), Advances in Connectionist and Neural
Computation Theory: Vol. 2. Analogical Connections. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Hollander, E. P. (1960). Competence and conformity in the acceptance of influence.
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 61, 365369.
314 References
Jacavone, J., & Dostal, M. (1992). A descriptive study of nursing judgment in assessment
and management of cardiac pain. Advances in Nursing Science, 15, 5463.
Jacob, H. (1983). Trial courts in the United States: The travails of explanation. Law
and Society Review, 17, 407423.
Janis, I. L. (1982). Groupthink (2nd ed.). Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Johnson, T. R. (2004). Oral Arguments and Decision Making on the United States
Supreme Court. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Johnson, T. R., Spriggs, J. F., II, & Wahlbeck, P. F. (2007). Supreme Court oral
advocacy: Does it affect the justices decisions? Washington University Law
Review, 85, 457.
Jost, J. T., Glaser, J., Kruglanski, A. W., & Sulloway, F. J. (2003). Political conservatism
as motivated social cognition. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 339375.
Judicial Council of California. (2007). The Strategic Plan for Californias Judicial
Branch 20062012. San Francisco: Judicial Council of California, Administrative
Office of the Courts.
Kahneman, D. (1991). Judgment and decision making: A personal view. Psychological
Science, 2, 142145.
Kahneman, D. (1997). New challenges to the rationality assumption. Legal Theory, 3, 105.
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment Under Uncertainty:
Heuristics and Biases. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979) Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under
risk. Econometrica, 47, 263291.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of
choice. Science, 211, 453458
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1984). Choices, values, and frames. American
psychologist, 39, 341350.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (2000). Choices, Values, and Frames. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Kalman, L. (1986). Legal Realism at Yale, 192760. Chapel Hill: University of North
Carolina Press.
Kalven, H,. & Zeisel, H. (1966). The American Jury. Boston: Little, Brown.
Kansas v. Colorado, 121 S.Ct. 2023 (2001).
Kassin, S. M., Meissner, C. A., & Norwick, R. J.(2005). Id know a false confession if I
saw one: A comparative study of college students and police investigators. Law
and Human Behavior, 29, 211227.
Kennedy, D. (1986). Freedom and constraint in adjudication: A critical
phenomenology. Journal of Legal Education, 36, 518547
Kerlinger, F. N. (1967). Social attitudes and their criterial referents: A structural
theory. Psychological Review, 74, 110122.
Kerr, N. & Tindale, R. S. (2004). Group performance and decision making. Annual
Review of Psychology, 55, 623.
Kerr, N. L., Atkin, R. S., Stasser, G., Meek, D., Holt, R. W., & Davis, J. H. (1976). Guilt
beyond a reasonable doubt: Effects of concept definition and assigneddecisionrule on
judgments of mock jurors. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 34, 282294.
Kida, T. (1980). An investigation into auditors continuity and related qualification
judgments. Journal of Accounting Research, 8, 506523.
Kim, N. S., & Ahn, W. (2002). Clinical psychologists theory-based representations of
mental disorders predict their diagnostic reasoning and memory. Journal of
Experimental Psychological: General, 131, 451476.
316 References
King, G., Keohane, R. O., & Verba, S. (1994). Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific
Inference in Qualitative Research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kintsch, W. (1988). The role of knowledge in discourse comprehension: A construction-
integration model. Psychological Review, 95, 163182.
Kirkpatrick, S. A. (1976). Introduction to the special issue on small group theory.
American Behavioral Scientist, 20, 59.
Kitcher, P. (1993). The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Klayman, J. (1995). Varieties of confirmation bias. The Psychology of Learning and
Motivation, 32, 385418.
Klein, D. E. (2002). Making Law in the United States Courts of Appeals. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Klein, D. E. (2005). Unspoken questions in the Rule 32.1 debate: Precedent and
psychology in judging. Washington & Lee Law Review, 62, 1709.
Klein, D. E. & Morrisroe, D. (1999). The prestige and influence of individual judges on
the U.S. Courts of Appeals. Journal of Legal Studies, 28, 371391.
Klein, G. A., Orasanu, J., Calderwood, R., & Zsambok, C. E. (1993). Decision Making in
Action: Models and Methods. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Corp.
Knetch, J. C. (2000). The endowment effect and evidence of irreversible indifference
curves. In D. Kahneman and A. Tversky (Eds.), Choices Values and Frames. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Koehler, D. J., Brenner, L., & Griffin, D. (2002). The calibration of expert judgment:
Heuristics and biases beyond the laboratory. In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D.
Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kolata, G., & Peterson, I. (2001, July 21). New Jersey is trying new way for witnesses to
say, Its Him. New York Times, p. A1.
Konecni, V. J., & Ebbesen, E. B. (1986). Courtroom testimony by psychologists on
eyewitness identification issues: Critical notes and reflections. Law and Human
Behavior, 10, 117126.
Kornhauser, L. A., & Sager, L. G. (1993).The one and the many: Adjudication in
collegial courts. California Law Review, 81, 159.
Kourlis, R. L., & Singer, J. M. (2007). Using judicial performance evaluations to
promote judicial accountability. Judicature, 90, 200207.
Kovera, M. B., & McAuliff, B. D. (2000). The effects of peer review and evidence
quality on judge evaluations of psychological evidence: Are judges effective
gatekeepers? Journal of Applied Psychology, 85, 574.
Kozhevnikov, M. (2007). Cognitive styles in the context of modern psychology:
Toward an integrated framework of cognitive style. Psychological Bulletin, 133,
464481.
Kozinski, A. (1993). What I ate for breakfast and other mysteries of judicial decision
making. Loyola Los Angeles Law Review, 26, 993.
Kritzer, H. M., & Richards, M. J. (2003). Jurisprudential regimes and Supreme Court
decisionmaking: The Lemon regime and Establishment Clause cases. Law &
Society Review, 37, 827840.
Kritzer, H. M., & Richards, M. J. (2005). The influence of law in the Supreme Courts
search-and-seizure jurisprudence. American Politics Research, 33, 3355.
Krueger, J. I., & Funder, D. C. (2004). Toward a balanced social psychology: Causes,
consequences, and cures for the problem-seeking approach to social behavior
and cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 313376.
References 317
Lerner, J. S., Goldberg, J. H., & Tetlock, P. E. (1998). Sober second thought: The effects
of accountability, anger, and authoritarianism on attributions of responsibility.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 24, 563574.
Leuchtenburg, W. E. (1995). The Supreme Court Reborn: The Constitutional Revolution
in the Age of Roosevelt. New York: Oxford University Press.
Levi, E. (1948). An Introduction to Legal Reasoning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Levine, J. M., & Moreland, R. L. (1994). Group socialization: Theory and research. In
W. Stroebe & M. Hewstone (Eds.), European Review of Social Psychology.
Chichester: Wiley.
Lewin, K. (1935). A Dynamic Theory of Personality. New York: McGraw Hill.
Lewis, A. (1987, September 27). Abroad at home: Question of judgment. New York
Times, p. D23.
Liberato, L., & Rutter, K. (2003). Reasons for reversal in the texas courts of appeals.
South Texas Law Review, 44, 431.
Lichtenstein, S., Fischhoff, B., & Phillips, L. D. (1982). Calibration of probabilities:
The state of the art to 1980. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.),
Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Liebman, J. S. (2000). The overproduction of death. Columbia Law Review, 100, 2030.
Linder, D. O. (1985). How judges judge: A study of disagreement on the United States
Court of Appeals for the Eighth Circuit. Arkansas Law Review, 38, 479560.
Lindquist, S., & Klein, D. (2006). The influence of jurisprudential considerations on
Supreme Court decisionmaking: A study of conflict cases. Law and Society
Review, 40, 135161.
Lithwick, D. (2004). A high court of one. In N. Devins & D. M. Douglas (Eds.), A Year
at the Supreme Court. Durham, NC: Duke University Press
Llewellyn, K. N. (1930). The Bramble Bush: Law and its Study. New York: Columbia
Law School.
Llewellyn, K. N. (1950). Remarks on the theory of appellate decision and the
rules or canons about how statutes are to be construed. Vanderbilt Law Review,
3, 395.
Llewellyn, K. N. (1960). The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals. Boston: Little,
Brown.
Lodge, M., & Taber, C. (2000). Three steps toward a theory of motivated political
reasoning. In A. Lupia, M. D. McCubbins, & S. L. Popkin (Eds.), Elements of
Reason: Cognition, Choice, and the Bounds of Rationality. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Loewenstein, G., & Elster, J. (Eds.). (1992). Choice Over Time. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.
Loewenstein, J., Thompson, L., & Gentner, D. (1999). Analogical encoding facilitates
knowledge transfer in negotiation. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 6(4),
586597.
Lord, C. G., Ross, L., & Lepper, M. (1979). Biased assimilation and attitude
polarization: The effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence.
Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 37, 2098.
Louis, M. R. (1980). Surprise and sense making: What newcomers experience in
entering unfamiliar organizational settings. Administrative Science Quarterly,
25, 226251.
References 319
Radin, M. (1925). The theory of judicial decision: Or how judges think. American Bar
Association Journal, 11, 357362.
Rahdert, M. C. (2007). Comparative constitutional advocacy. American University
Law Review, 56, 553.
Randazzo, K. A., Waterman, R. W., & Fine, J. A. (2006). Checking the federal courts:
The impact of congressional statutes on judicial behavior. Journal of Politics,
68(4), 10061017.
Raskin, D. C., & Podlesny, J. A. (1979). Truth and deception: A reply to Lykken.
Psychological Bulletin, 86, 5459.
Ratterman, M. J., & Gentner, D. (1998). More evidence for a relational shift in the
development of analogy: Childrens performance on a causal-mapping task.
Cognitive Development, 13, 453478.
Ratzlaf v. United States, 510 U.S. 135 (1994).
Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Raz, J. (1979). The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Raz, J. (1994). Ethics in the Public Domain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Read, S. J., & Marcus-Newhall, A. (1993). Explanatory coherence in social
explanations: A parallel distributed processing account. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 65, 429.
Read, S. J., & Miller, L. C. (1998). On the dynamic construction of meaning: An
interactive activation and competition model of social perception. In S. J. Read &
L. C. Miller (Eds.), Connectionist Models of Social Reasoning and Social Behavior.
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Read, S. J., Vanman, E. J., & Miller, L. C. (1997). Connectionism, parallel constraint
satisfaction processes, and Gestalt principles: (Re)introducing cognitive
dynamics to social psychology. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 1,
2653.
Redding, R. E., & Reppucci, N. D. (1999). Effects of lawyers socio-political attitudes
on their judgments of social science in legal decision making. Law and Human
Behavior, 23, 31.
Redelmeier, D. A. (2005). The cognitive psychology of missed diagnoses. Annals of
Internal Medicine, 142, 115120.
Reed, J. W. (2005). Theyre playing a tango. Michigan Bar Journal, 84, 18.
Reeve, J. (2005). Understanding Motivation and Emotion. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Resnik., J. (1982). Managerial judges. Harvard Law Review, 96, 374.
Resnik, J. (2002). Mediating preferences: Litigant preferences for process and judicial
preferences for settlement. Journal of Dispute Resolution, 2002, 155.
Richards, M. J., & Kritzer, H. M. (2002). Jurisprudential regimes in Supreme Court
decision making. American Political Science Review, 96, 305320.
Rickard, A. (1998). Juror Judgment and Decision Making: Prior Convictions Evidence,
Instructions to Disregard and Different Standards of Proof. Unpublished honors
thesis, School of Psychology, University of Queensland.
Ridgeway, C. L. (1978). Conformity, group-oriented motivation, and status
attainment in small groups. Social Psychology, 41, 175188.
Ridgeway, C. L., & Berger, J. (1986). Expectations, legitimation, and dominance
behavior in task groups. American Sociological Review, 51, 603617.
Ridgeway, C. L., Johnson, C., & Diekema, D. (1994). External status, legitimacy, and
compliance in male and female groups. Social Forces, 72, 10511077.
References 325
Shapiro, S. (2007). The Hart-Dworkin Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed.
University of Michigan Public Law Working Paper No. 77.
Sherif, M. (1936). The Psychology of Social Norms. New York: Harper and Row.
Sherry, S. (2003). Judges of character. Wake Forest Law Review, 38, 793812.
Sherry, S. (2005). Politics and judgment. Missouri Law Review, 70, 973987.
Sherry, S. (2006). Logic without experience: The problem of federal appellate courts.
Notre Dame Law Review, 82, 97154.
Sherry, S. (2007). Democracy and the death of knowledge. University of Cincinnati
Law Review, 75, 10531069.
Sherwin, E. (1999). A defense of analogical reasoning in law. University of Chicago Law
Review, 66, 11791197.
Shoemaker, P. J. H. (1982). The expected utility model: Its variants, purposes,
evidence, and limitations. Journal of Economic Literature, 20, 529.
Shullman, S. L. (2004). The illusion of devils advocacy: How the justices of the
Supreme Court foreshadow their decisions during oral argument. Journal of
Appellate Practice and Process, 6, 271293.
Simon, D. (1998). A psychological model of judicial decision making. Rutgers Law
Journal, 30, 1142.
Simon, D. (2002). Freedom and constraint in adjudication: A look through the lens of
cognitive psychology. Brooklyn Law Review, 67, 10971139.
Simon, D. (2004). A third view of the black box: Cognitive coherence in legal decision
making. University of Chicago Law Review, 71, 511586.
Simon, D., & Holyoak, K. J. (2002). Structural dynamics of cognition: From
consistency theories to constraint satisfaction. Personality and Social Psychology
Review, 6, 283294.
Simon, D., Krawczyk, D. C., & Holyoak, K. J. (2004a). Construction of preferences by
constraint satisfaction. Psychological Science, 15, 331336.
Simon, D., Krawczyk, D. C., Bleicher, A., & Holyoak, K. J. (2008). The transience of
constructed preferences. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 21, 114.
Simon, D., Pham, L. B., Le, Q. A., & Holyoak, K. J. (2001). The emergence of
coherence over the course of decision making. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 27, 12501260.
Simon, D., Snow, C. J., & Read, S. J. (2004b). The redux of cognitive consistency
theories: Evidence judgments by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 86, 814837.
Simon, J. F. (1980). Independent Journey: The Life of William O. Douglas. New York:
Harper & Row.
Simon, R., & Mahan, L. (1971). Quantifying burdens of proof: A view from the bench,
the jury, and the classroom. Law and Society Review, 5(3), 319330.
Simonson, I., & Staw, B. M. (1992). Deescalation strategies: A comparison of
techniques for reducing commitment to losing courses of action. Journal of
Applied Psychology, 77, 419426.
Sisk, G. C., & Heise, M. (2005). Judges and ideology: Public and academic
debates about statistical measures. Northwestern University Law Review, 99,
743803.
Slotnick, E. E. (1979). Judicial career patterns and majority opinion assignment on the
Supreme Court. Journal of Politics, 41, 640648.
Slovic, P. (1969). Analyzing the expert judge: A descriptive study of a stockbrokers
decision processes. Journal of Applied Psychology, 53, 255263.
References 329
Starr, K. W. (2002). First Among Equals: The Supreme Court in American Life. New
York: Warner Books.
Staudt, N., Friedman, B., & Epstein, L. (2008). On the role of ideological homogeneity
in generating consequential decisions. University of Pennsylvania Journal of
Constitutional Law, 10, 361.
Steblay, N., Dysart, J., Fulero, S., & Lindsay, R. C. L. (2001). Eyewitness accuracy rates
in sequential and simultaneous lineup presentations: A meta-analytic
comparison. Law & Human Behavior, 25, 459.
Stein, A. (2005). Foundations of Evidence Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stein, E. (1996). Without Good Reason: The Rationality Debate in Philosophy and
Cognitive Science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Sternberg, R. J. (1999). The theory of successful intelligence. Review of General
Psychology, 3, 292316.
Stewart, T. R., Roebber, P. J., & Bosart, L. F. (1997). The importance of the task in
analyzing expert judgment. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
Processes, 69, 205219.
Stith, K. (2008). The arc of the pendulum: Judges, prosecutors, and the exercise of
discretion. Yale Law Journal, 117, 1420.
Stone Sweet, A. (2002). Path dependence, precedent, and judicial power. In I. Shapiro
& A. Stone Sweet (Eds.), On Law Politics and Judicialization. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Suedfeld, P. (2000). Cognitive styles: Personality. In A. E. Kazdin (Ed.), Encyclopedia of
Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 166169). Washington, DC and New York: American
Psychological Association and Oxford University Press.
Suedfeld, P., & Tetlock, P. E. (2001). Individual differences in information processing.
In A. Tesser & N. Schwarz (Eds.), Blackwell International Handbook of Social
Psychology (pp. 284304). Boston, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Sullivan, K. M. (1992). The Supreme Court 1991 Term: The Justice of Rules and
Standards. Harvard Law Review, 106, 22123.
Sunstein, C. R. (1993). On analogy in legal reasoning. Harvard Law Review, 106, 741789.
Sunstein, C. R. (1996). On the expressive function of law. University of Pennsylvania
Law Review, 144, 2021.
Sunstein, C. R. (1996). Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Sunstein, C. R. (1999). One Case at a Time: Judicial Minimalism on the Supreme Court.
Cambridge, MA; Harvard University Press.
Sunstein, C. R. (2000). Deliberative trouble? Why groups go to extremes. Yale Law
Journal, 110, 71119.
Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Why Societies Need Dissent. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Radicals in Robes: Why Extreme Right-Wing Courts Are Wrong
for America. Cambridge, MA: Basic Books.
Sunstein, C. R. (2007). If people would be outraged by their ruling, should judges care?
Stanford Law Review, 60, 155212.
Sunstein, C. R., Hastie, R., Payne, J. W., Schkade, D. A., & Viscusi, W. K.
(2002). Punitive Damages: How Juries Decide. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sunstein, C. R., Schkade, D., Ellman, L. M., & Sawicki, A. (2006). Are Judges Political:
An Empirical Analysis of the Federal Judiciary. Washington, DC: Brookings
Institution Press.
References 331
Thagard, P., & Kunda, Z. (1998). Making sense of people: Coherence mechanisms. In
S. J. Read & L. C. Miller (Eds.), Connectionist Models of Social Reasoning and
Social Behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Thagard, P., & Millgram, E. (1995). Inference to the best plan: A coherence theory of
decision. In A. Ram & D. B. Leake (Eds.), Goal-Driven Learning. Cambridge, MA:
Bradford Books.
Thaler, R. H. (1991). Quasi Rational Economics. New York: Russell Sage.
Thompson, W. C., Cowan, C. L., Ellsworth, P. C., & Harrington, J. C. (1984). Death
penalty attitudes and conviction proneness: The translation of attitudes into
verdicts. Law and Human Behavior, 8, 95113.
Tindale, R. S., Meisenhelder, H. M., Dykema-Engblade, A. A., & Hogg, M.A.
Shared cognition in small groups. In M. A. Hogg & R. S. Tindale (Eds.),
Blackwell Handbook of Social Psychology: Group Processes. Malden, MA:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Time Magazine. (1975, November 24). The Courts uncompromising libertarian,
p. 69.
Tinsdale, R. S., Meisenhelder, H. M., Dykema-Engblade, A. A., & Hogg, M. A. (2000).
Shared cognition in small groups. In M. A. Hogg & R. S. Tinsdale, (Eds.),
Blackwell Handbook on Psychology: Group Practices. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Toobin, J. (2007). The Nine: Inside the Secret World of the Supreme Court. New York:
Doubleday.
Toward Active Liberty: A Supreme Court Justice Offers a View from the Top. (2006,
Spring). Harvard Law Bulletin, 57(14), 17.
Trumbo, D., Adams, C., Milner, M., & Schipper, L. (1962). Reliability and accuracy in
the inspection of hard red winter wheat. Cereal Science Today, 7, 6271.
Tushnet, M. (1992). Thurgood Marshall and the brethren. Georgetown Law Journal,
80, 21092130.
Tushnet, M. (2005). A Court Divided: The Rehnquist Court and the Future of
Constitutional Law. New York: Norton.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and
biases. Science, 185, 11241131.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1982). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency
and probability. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment
under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Twining, W. (1973). Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Tradition. London: Weidenfeld &
Nicolson.
Tyler, T. R., & Huo, Y. J. (2002). Trust in the Law. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Tyler, T. R., & Mitchell, G. (1994). Legitimacy and empowerment of discretionary
legal authority: The United States Supreme Court and abortion rights. Duke Law
Journal, 43, 703815.
Ulman, J. N. (1933). A Judge Takes the Stand. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Ulmer, S. S. (1971). Courts as Small and Not So Small Groups. New York: Basic Books.
Unah, I., & Hancock, A. M. (2006). U.S. Supreme Court decision making, case
salience, and the attitudinal model. Law & Policy, 28, 295320.
United States v. Locke, 471 U.S. 84 (1985).
United States v. Terry, 392 U.S. 1 (1968).
Vanberg, G. (2005). The Politics of Constitutional Review in Germany. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
References 333
West, A., Desdevises, Y., Fenet, A., Gaurier, D., & Heussaff, M. (1992). The French
Legal System. London: Fourmat Publishing.
Whittington, K. E. (2000.) Once more unto the breach: Post-behavioralist approaches
to judicial politics. Law & Social Inquiry, 25, 601634.
Wickard v. Filburn, 317 U.S. 111 (1942).
Wilkerson, J. D. (1990). Reelection and representation in conflict: The case of agenda
manipulation. Legislative Studies Quarterly, 15, 263282.
Williams, F. V., III. (2007). Reinventing the courts: The frontiers of judicial activism in
the state courts. Campbell Law Review, 29, 591.
Wilson, T. D., & Brekke, N. (1994). Mental contamination and mental correction:
Unwanted influences on judgments and evaluations. Psychological Bulletin, 116,
117142.
Windschitl, P. D., & Wells, G. L. (1996). Base rates do not constrain nonprobability
judgments. Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 19, 40.
Winter, D. G. (2002). Motivation and political leadership. In L. O. Valenty & O.
Feldman (Eds.), Political Leadership for the New Century: Personality and Behavior
among American Leaders. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Winter, D. G. (2003a). Measuring the motives of political actors at a distance. In J. M.
Post (Ed.), The Psychological Assessment of Political Leaders. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Winter, D. G. (2003b). Personality and political behavior. In D. O. Sears, L. Huddy, &
R. Jervis (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Political Psychology. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Wissler, R. L., Hart, A. J., & Saks, M. J. (1999). Decisionmaking about general
damages: A comparison of jurors, judges, and lawyers. Michigan Law Review,
98, 751.
Wistrich, A. J., Guthrie, C., & Rachlinski, J. J. (2005). Can judges ignore inadmissible
information? The difficulty of deliberately disregarding. University of Pensylvania
Law Review, 153, 1251.
Wold, J. T. (1978). Going through the motions: The monotony of appellate court
cecisionmaking. Judicature, 62, 5865.
Wood, S. L. Keith, L. C., Lanier, D. N., & Ogundele, A. (1998). Acclimation effects
for Supreme Court justices: A cross-validation, 18881940. American Journal of
Political Science, 42, 690697.
Wright, D. B., & Hall, M. (2006). How a reasonable doubt instruction affects
decisions of guilt. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 29(1), 8592.
Wrightsman, L. S. (1999). Judicial Decision Making: Is Psychology Relevant? New York:
Kluwer Academic.
Wrightsman, L. S. (2006). The Psychology of the Supreme Court. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Wrightsman, L. S. (2008). Oral Arguments Before the Supreme Court: An Empirical
Approach. New York: Oxford University Press.
Yarborough v. Alvarado, 124 S.Ct. 2140 (2004).
Yates, J. F. (1990). Judgment and Decision Making. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Yuille, J. C., & Cutshall, J. L. (1986). A case study of eyewitness memory of a crime.
Journal of Applied Psychology, 71, 291301.
Index
accountability, 16, 25, 45, 48, 50, Blackmun, Harry, 11, 5961, 75, 84 n13
5254, 205, 21416, 236, 288, Blackstone Ratio, 168, 17380
29293 Brennan, William, 15, 60, 6869, 75,
Alito, Samuel, 70 291
analogical, analogical reasoning, xii, Burger, Warren, 69, 75, 84 n13
107, 11819, 147, 14950, 152,
15461, 163, 205, 212 cognitive illusion(s), 187, 19395, 198,
analogy, 104, 111, 11720, 14952, 272
15455, 15762, 281 cognitive style, xii, xiii, 27983
attitudinal model, 48, 10, 2830, 42, coherence based reasoning, 134, 138,
46, 50, 52, 54, 6162, 7677, 8384, 14042, 146
8687, 150, 158, 163, 189, 204, 209, competence, 7981, 119, 22223,
21113, 216, 22325, 23132, 241, 22932, 23941, 24346, 25354,
244, 24647, 282 269, 27173, 27678, 291
audience(s), 13, 18, 2022, 25, 3637, constraint(s), 27, 2930, 3339, 46, 52,
88, 9192, 96, 99, 124, 187, 192, 76, 92, 105, 112, 117, 11920, 131,
19597, 199200, 215, 282 139, 142, 147, 184, 186, 19193, 195,
203207, 20910, 213, 21517,
bias, 31, 4348, 5055, 58, 72, 82, 23132, 236, 247
104, 113, 12224, 12630, 133, 136, construct validity, 13435, 14345,
145, 154, 184, 187, 19294, 210, 215, 147
227, 230, 235, 237, 24546, 251,
253, 257, 26162, 272, 27576, descriptive-normative gap, 22224,
288, 290 22829, 233, 237
335
336 Index
discretion, 14, 17, 27, 30, 52, 80, 84, 142, 4748, 5052, 5455, 5868, 70,
166, 184, 18693, 195, 197, 200, 206, 7477, 80, 8587, 9096, 9899,
212, 23536, 247, 262, 267, 28687 146, 184, 192, 200, 204205, 207,
dogmatism, 7172, 288 209, 21213, 215, 223, 232, 234,
Douglas, William, 15, 68, 69, 24041, 24647, 256, 28182, 287,
119 n31 29192
impression management, 18, 88,
election(s), 15, 18, 20, 24, 32, 187, 9193, 98
291 incompetence, 223, 230, 24446, 254,
emotion(s), xv, 60, 122, 12425, 27172, 27778
14445 internal validity, 134, 14445, 147
expectation states theory, 8081
expertise, xii, 29, 67, 80, 82, 11314, judicial review, 32, 22223, 226
122, 13536, 14345, 149, 15255, judicial selection, 187, 223, 258, 282,
157, 162, 242, 26972, 27476, 278, 288, 291
280, 28587, 28992, 294 juries, 31, 39, 104, 210, 222, 235, 261
expert(s), xii, 31, 50, 6667, 11314, juror(s), 31, 39, 104, 114, 131, 133, 137,
125, 135, 145, 149, 15254, 156, 158, 141, 16569, 17172, 175, 179,
162, 186, 189, 200201, 216, 223, 18385, 18890, 192, 19798, 237,
23536, 239, 26978, 28082, 241, 246
28687, 28990
external validity, 13238, 141, 14344, Kennedy, Anthony, 71, 87, 9394,
146, 224, 262 9899
extralegal factors, 183, 18586,
19192, 198, 23133, 235, 240, leadership, 7980, 91, 265
24647 legal considerations, 45, 7, 25, 41, 43,
4748, 5153, 203204
fox(es), 72, 28084, 28889, 291 legal model(s), 4, 7, 6162, 76, 204, 223,
Frankfurter, Felix, 68, 212, 253 226, 23132, 234, 247
freshmen effects, 54, 81 legal realism, legal realists, 45, 28, 76,
84, 10910, 113, 11819, 129, 163,
Ginsburg, Ruth Bader, 70, 75 204
group decision making, 78, 8182, 89,
205, 21314 majority coalition, 85, 8797, 100
group formation, 8586, 88, 9091, 94, managerial model(s), 28, 30
9798, 100 Marshall, Thurgood, 75
Martin-Quinn ideology scores, 2829,
hedgehog-fox, 280, 282 38 n2
hedgehog(s), 72, 28084, 28889, 291, median Justice, 8587, 90, 95, 100
295 MODE attitude-behavior model,
heuristic(s), 14, 1721, 23, 31, 43, 163, 4445, 46, 48
192, 194, 275 Multiple Constraint Satisfaction, 27
heuristic-systematic model, 1720
New Deal Court, 86, 90, 9497
ideological cases, 19, 5868
ideology, ideological, xii, 6, 8, 10, 12, OConnor, Sandra Day, 11, 69, 71, 93,
14, 1920, 24, 2829, 39, 4143, 9899
Index 337