The Concept of The Political: Radical Identity: Love Your Enemies

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 30

Chapter 2

The Concept of the Political: Radical Identity

Love your enemies.1

It will be remembered from chapter one that the influence of liberal thought on

traditional IR theory is mirrored in the analyses of collective identity that realism and

liberal constructivism have developed. I argued in the previous chapter that these

approaches only show a partial picture of the process of collective identity formation

because the conceptions of politics that realism and liberal constructivism employ are

guided by a narrow account of state-centric forms of politics. In this chapter I develop a

view of identity and difference through an engagement with Carl Schmitts seminal

study on The Concept of the Political. This work, I will argue, offers a relevant

theoretical support to understand the activity of politics as the realm to establish and

protect collective identities. This is particularly so when examining some of Schmitts

ideas from a postmodern perspective which, among other things, employs an alternative

methodology grounded on discourse analysis to understand the formation of collective

identities. In line with the suggestion made in chapter one I consider postmodernism

give us a more prominent picture of political phenomena such as the construction of

collective identity and that classical international relations theory falls short in this task

for two reasons. First, many of its proponents rely on a limited political imagination

which sees little farther than state-centric forms of politics. Second, traditional

international relations theory very often tends to compromise its theoretical assumptions

with a western liberal culture.

1
Matt. 5:44; Luke 6:27.
My main objective in this chapter is to make a case for showing that Schmitts

concept of the political appears to throw fruitful theoretical insights upon the

construction of collective identity as a result of antagonistic relations. My contention is

that Schmitts work shows a more prominent image of the construction of identity as a

political phenomenon when engaged in a poststructuralist analysis of antagonism than

it does in the way it has been used under the auspices of traditional international

relations theory and Neo-conservative propaganda as an apologist of war.

This chapter lays the groundwork for a later analysis of the construction of

collective identity viewed as the result of the antithesis of the friend-enemy which I

term radical identity. I distinguish self/other relationships according to the degree in

which such relations of othering may turn into friend-enemy relations. The term

conflict therefore refers to the ontological relationship between identity and

difference, acknowledging that the intensity of conflict can vary.

Schmitts central argument is grounded on the belief that human relations

become organized via the distinction of friends and enemies. Schmitt conceptualizes the

political within the totality of human thought and action2 to highlight that the element

lying at the core of politics, in his antithesis of the friend and enemy, is precisely action.

Schmitts most important contribution to political theory has probably been his ground-

breaking and often stinging critique of liberal politics. In brief, he argues that liberalism

promotes a political system which eliminates the possibility of antagonisms in society,

replacing it with a moral discourse on the possibility of attaining a common good.

This chapter discusses Carl Schmitts peculiar understanding of the political as

the moment in which human groupings construct collective forms of identification in

relation to otherness-as-enmity. First, I introduce briefly Schmitts main ideas on the

2
Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).

51
political and the friend/enemy distinction. Second, I explore these notions and point out

some of the advantages over traditional IR theory that a non-state-centric version of the

political can offer. This section also considers the limitations of Schmitts thought in

this conceptual field. Third, I introduce the concept of antagonism and show how,

through a distinction I develop between difference, otherness and enmity, this can

provide an important basis not offered by traditional IR theories for understanding

collective identity formation. I continue the discussion on antagonism and contrast it

with more traditional understandings of conflict. I proceed to examine Schmitts

perceptive understanding of sovereignty as the moment of antagonism and show that

the links between this and drawing the limits of community make it possible to argue

that the relationship between sovereignty and identity is reciprocally interdependent.

Finally I present an example of some recent misreadings of Schmitt which can be seen

as showing the other side of the coin in the heated dispute over the usefulness of this

somewhat maligned German thinker. However, I show that such misreadings have very

frequently been biased and have been used for theoretical justifications which lack the

conceptual depth that the work of Schmitt necessarily deserves.

1. Rescuing Schmitts Concepts

Here I introduce three main concepts developed in the work of Carl Schmitt,

politics and the political, the state and sovereignty. These will be used to hightlight

several theoretical implications on the construction of identity and to elucidate how

dominant understandings of such terms affect the way IR scholars theorize political

phenomena. I employ a strategic reading of Schmitt through a poststructuralist lens for

two reasons. First, it intends to rescue the conceptual thought of Schmitt from the

52
misuses to which it has been frequently subject when read from more traditional IR

perspectives. Second, approaching Schmitts concepts from a postmodern approach

offers a powerful response to the contested notion of identity and its repercussions for

liberal democratic theory. The distinction Schmitt makes between politics as opposed

to the political produces important consequences for the conceptualisation of self/other

relationships. My broadest suggestion is that the political thought of Schmitt discloses

conceptual links between identity and difference, which provide a wider understanding

of the centrality of confronting views in the making of collective identities. These

identities, in my view, can be seen as being constituted to a large extent by the

discourses that constantly reinforce a sense of collective belonging through the practices

of political action they opt to employ.

Schmitt emphasises antagonism through the friend-enemy distinction as an

ineradicable core characteristic of human relations. This argument is often mistaken by

many liberals3 to be a reiteration of Hobbes assumption that man is evil by nature. This

error has led several commentators4 to understand both Schmitts work and the concepts

of antagonism and conflict found within it far too simplistically. In consequence, the

benefits of his work for scholars of international relations almost always go unnoticed.

Indeed, Schmitts work has never been used in the field of international relations as a

powerful source to theorise collective identity construction. This, in my view, is perhaps

not taking advantage of the scope of his ideas. A thorough and sensitive reading of

Schmitt shows that the condition for achieving collective identity, if it can at all be

achieved, is based on the premise that relations of antagonism need to be articulated

3
See particularly the interesting critique of Carl Schmitt by Heinrich Meier, Carl Schmit and Leo Strauss:
The Hidden Dialogue (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), and Pauline Johnson, Carl Schmitt,
Jrgen Habermas and the Crisis of Politics, The European Legacy 3, no.6 (1998): 15-32.
4
See Jan-Werner Mller, A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2003), 7. Also see Arash Abizadeh, Does Collective Identity Presuppose an
Other? On the Alleged Incoherence of Global Solidarity, The American Political Science Review 99, no.
1 (2005): 45-60.

53
through specific forms of political action that do establish difference and instead of

eradicate it. The production of identity and difference in turn conveys the existence of

conflict as something contingent, which Schmitt brings out as an omnipresent

possibility (reale Mglichkeit). For the purposes of this thesis, however, one of my

objectives is to show that the relevance of Schmitts conception of the political can put

forward an alternative theoretical approach to bring antagonistic concepts in

confrontation through adequate forms of political action.

I have chosen to develop a reading of Schmitt through a postmodern lens to

respond adequately to the conceptual challenges posed by the concept of identity in IR

theory. My main argument in this chapter indicates that a deeper analysis of the

conceptual linkages between two binary pairs: postmodernisms identity/difference and

Schmitts friend/enemy distinction uncovers a common ground between the two

approaches to understand the political. This common ground is a theoretical

touchstone that if taken in serious consideration it could begin to pave the way for the

development of more genuine democratic forms of identity than those notions of

identity commonly associated with associational theory. Conflict, in its ontological

manifestation is this similar ground, which if understood from both approaches can

explicate the tension existing between these binary pairs. Then a more compelling

explanation to use an alternative view to grasp the nature of the political is foreseeable.

This tension is obscured by the liberal preference for neutralising politics and thus the

antagonistic dimension of politics, and as a result the ontological dimension of conflict

is often greatly overlooked by IR theorists and liberal thinkers.

Schmitt grants political meaning to every realm of human life that can be

divided according to the category of the friend-enemy. While some of the elements in

Schmitts concept of the political appear far too radical at a first glimpse, the strength of

54
the his conceptual ideas lies in the scope that his category of the friend-enemy can

embrace. Schmitts theory of sovereignty and concept of the political do not need to be

accepted in their most radical tones to embody the alternative conception of identity I

present in this work. Nor is it my purpose to sustain that everything is politicisable only

for virtue of the criterion of the friend-enemy. I also do not offer a postmodernist

reading of Schmitts work as a justification to separate the Schmitt political philosopher

from the Schmitt legal theorist of the Nazi Machtergreifun. As I mentioned above,

Schmitts notion of the political exposes its usefulness in such a way that his

understanding of identity/difference reveals that its political character can transcend all

other types of collective sentiments of attachment. None of this should be taken to

suggest that culture and other collective feelings of belonging should be underestimated

or confined to the private sphere of life as in the case with liberalism. In contrast to

liberal thought, the conception of otherness developed by Schmitt is not reduced to the

private differences that cultural attachments entail. Schmitt presupposes a pre-cultural

state that gives more weight to the capacity to decide what otherness is. If any analysis

of Schmitts begins by misunderstanding the friend-enemy distinction, as a reiteration

of the realist vision in which man is deemed as evil by nature, the actual meaning of the

work of Schmitt is likely to be deferred. Expanding on this argument, Tracy Strong has

added that,

[t]here is here, however, a deeper claim, a claim that the political defines what it is to
be a human being in the modern world and that those who would diminish the
political diminish humanity. Schmitt lays this out as the "friend-enemy" distinction.
What is important about this distinction is not so much the "who is on my side"
quality, but the claim that only by means of this distinction does the question of our
willingness to take responsibility for our own lives arise. "Each participant is in a
position to judge whether the adversary intends to negate his opponent's way of life
and therefore must be repulsed or fought in order to preserve one's own form of
existence." 5

5
Carl Schmitt quoted by Tracy Strong, foreword to The Concept of the Political, xvi, Schmitt, The
Concept of the Political, 27.

55
Schmitt conceptualised the political with the fundamental antithesis of the

friend and the enemy because he considered this binary opposition to be the core

distinction to be found in any situation in which politics takes place. Ultimate

distinctions can be traced, according to Schmitt, in all other fields of life.6 For instance,

aesthetics derives its force form the distinction between the beautiful and the ugly and

likewise economics hinges on a distinction between profitable and unprofitable.7 In

particular, he separated politics from ethics as two different spheres of life, yet he

acknowledged that both realms of human endeavour are interconnected, as he explicitly

indicates,

[i]n contrast to the relatively independent endeavours of human thought and action,
particularly the moral, aesthetic, and economic, the political has its own criteria which
express themselves in a characteristic way. The political must therefore rest on its
own ultimate distinctions, to which all action with a specifically political meaning can
8
be traced.

Contrary to Machiavellis separation of ethics and politics, Schmitts claim finds

its uniqueness in specifying that politics and ethics are not atomistically distinct and,

therefore, to read it as such would be mistaken. By means of the friend-enemy

distinction, Schmitt promotes and understanding of politics as action which becomes

visible in the struggle to establish an us/them relationship. However, he insists on the

political meaning that action, in the form of struggle, should retain in order to transcend

the conflicting non-political antagonism. This means that the friend-enemy distinction

needs to remain valid in order to establish difference. When they consider him at all,

realist scholars have seen this theoretical move of Schmitt as a means to limit the scope

6
Friedrich G. W Hegel developed an analysis of the dialectic of human thought, that says that every
category in the universe has an opposite, every thesis is counterposed by an antithesis, for he considered
all things in the universe are constitutive parts seeking to find themselves in the whole. The thesis and the
antithesis get blended in a synthesis which is a higher phase of reality in which the lower contradiction is
overcome and transcended. See Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller. (Oxford: Oxford UP,
1977).
7
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 26.
8
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 26, [emphasis added].

56
of conflict in order to avoid a war of all against all.9 In my view, this is however,

rendering Schmitts notion of politics as action as a procedure to justify war as a

likelihood and not as a possibility. By contrast, Schmitt warned that should the friend-

enemy distinction develop into war, this would bring the friend-enemy distinction to an

end. This last observation has important repercussions for collective identity formation

and the inextricable link to the notion of otherness in postmodern thought. I will come

back to this point shortly.

Theoretically speaking, the concept of the political poses a challenge to both

essentialist and liberal constructivist theories of identity in the discipline of IR. The

political is a concept that surpasses the often simplistic essentialist understanding of

identities grounded on the categorical distinctions inherent in every group, such as

religious affiliation, race, gender and so forth.10 The instability of identity categories

prohibits serious analyses on the subject matter from examining the evolution of a

collective experience. This renders essentialist theorists incapable of dealing with

difference, and thus overlooks the political aspect of identities. As I argued in chapter

one, constructivists of the liberal camp such as Wendt and Ruggie, do not leave enough

room in their theories for that possibility that difference and identity require each other

in an ever-present possibility of conflict. Wendts statement that collective identity

brings the relationship of self and other to its logical conclusion11 reveals his belief that

identity may either incorporate difference into sameness or that friend-enemy groupings

9
See Eckard Bolsinger, Carl Schmitts and Lennins Political Realism. (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press,
2001).
10
An example of this type of theorizing is found in R. Sooknanan, The politics of Essentialism:
Rethinking Black Community, in Rude: Contemporary Black Canadian Cultural Criticism, ed. R.
Walcott (Toronto: Insomniac Press, 2000), and H. Bhabha, Introduction: Narrating the Nation, in
Nation and Narration, ed. H. Bhabha (New York: Routledge, 1990).
11
Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999), 227.

57
can be transcended. Both of which appear to be objectives of arch-liberal Rawls

overlapping consensus, for example.12

The concept of the Political decides the degree of separation which compels the

members of a human grouping to associate in a critical situation. Understanding

Schmitts thinking in this way helps us build a strong theoretical base to understand

political identity as less of an associational character than Rawls would have it. By

aligning collectivities under the friend-enemy distinction, categories are entirely

transcended without transcending the different kinds of identities inherent in each

category. The concept of the political

does not describe its own substance The real friend-enemy grouping is existentially
so strong and decisive that the non-political antithesis, at precisely the moment in
which it becomes political pushes aside and subordinates its hitherto purely religious,
purely economic, purely cultural criteria and motives to the conditions and conclusion
of the political situation at hand.13

A superficial reading of Schmitts words here might suggest that there are no

grounds for locating the specificity of the political outside the conditions which appear

to shape an antagonism. However, his elaboration of antagonism as a theoretical tool to

examine political conflict succeeds in that it overcomes the essentialism entailed by

reliance on categorical oppositions. Schmitt subsumes all other spheres of life into the

friend-enemy distinction in order to raise consciousness about the contexts in which all

other spheres of life become political.

The postmodern approaches to antagonism developed by Ernesto Laclau and

Chantal Mouffe are useful in disclosing the conceptual properties inherent albeit if

latent in the Schmittian concept of the political. Antagonism, in this view, is

approached in the discourse-theoretical conditions in which it develops. Laclau and

12
John Rawls, Political Liberalism, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 12
13
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 38.

58
Mouffe examine antagonism beyond the logical incompatibility of ideas and interests.

Antagonism is seen as constitutive of the processes in which identification emerges. In

this respect Laclau and Mouffe think of antagonism beyond the logical structures which

situate two opposing views in conflict. For instance, Laclau and Mouffe see the

opposition between empiricism and rationalism as a historically specific discursive

construct.14 What lies at the core of antagonism is the fact that social subjects15 are

understood to be relationally constituted by creating subject positions which come to

be conceived in terms of the discursive practices associated with the relationship

between two or more subjects. Subject positions are seen, in this view, as incomplete in

themselves without the articulation of the discourse formulated by other subject

positions.

So what is exactly antagonism? Laclau and Mouffe, as well as Slavoj Zizek16

agree on the notion of impossible full identification as a step towards understanding

the incomplete character of the subject and its dependence upon the consequential

experience of not ever finding identity in the other.

While Laclau and Mouffe do not put it in quite his Hegelian way, the basic

stages in the argument for antagonism are as follows. Premise 1: The subject seeks its

own objective realization. So, for example, during the Cold War, the U.S. strove to

the single objectively realized superpower. Premise 2: the other stands in the way of

this objective realization (represented in this brief example by the Soviet Union).

Premise 3: the subject desires to annihilate the other who stands in its way. Premise 4:

But the subject requires the existence of the other for the existence of its own identity

14
Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe, Hegemony and Social Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic
Politics (London: Verso, 1985): 125.
15
The term subject position seeks to capture the idea of what enables the identity of a given subject is not
self-generated but its given through its subject position (i.e. its relations with other subject positions).
16
Slavoj Zizek, appendix Beyond Discourse Analysis, in New Reflections on the Revolution of Our
Time, by Ernesto Laclau (London: Verso, 1990): 249-260.

59
hence antagonism is the constant oscillating desire to crush the other, but repeatedly

drawing back from doing so lest its own identity be eclipsed at the very moment of its

realization.

For Laclau and Mouffe this model related most strongly to the struggle between

the proletariat and the bourgeoisie. However, the end of the Cold War also seems to

bear out the use of antagonism as a very explanatory concept. Once the Other had

disappeared, the identity of the U.S. has been placed in serious question, both internally

and externally, and another other subsequently had to be found to balance the

inescapable tension identity entails. This point can be used to illuminate the scope that

Schmitts friend-enemy distinction can bring to understanding collective identity

formation and rearticulation in a way not captured by traditional IR theory.

In this sense, Schmitts friend-enemy distinction oscillates before and after the

decision to nominate the enemy has been reached. So far, I have shown the

compatibility of the Schmittian notion of antagonism with that offered by postmodernist

thinkers like Chantal Mouffe and Ernesto Laclau. The strength of this approach should

serve us as an indicator of how liberal thought has underestimated the ontological

presence of conflict in its own debates. From this point it should be clear that the liberal

avoidance of conflict brings as an initial consequence the privatization of differences. In

this way, my argument that the strategy of liberal thought to universalize metanarratives

shows that liberalism constantly locks itself in the conceptual impossibility of

developing a non-universalistic concept of difference that recognizes that difference, be

it in conceptual otherness or in collective forms of identification is particularistic.

60
2. Historical Context and Discourse-orientated interpretations of Schmitt

While it is important to recognize that Schmitt condemned those liberal practices

of the Weimar state he happened to live in, it is even more important to acknowledge

the usefulness we can find in this thought to correct present mistakes, or

depoliticisations, as he would put it. His critique of depoliticisations and neutralisations

in The Concept of the Political17 against the narrowing down of the field of the political

was the result of the practices of liberal democracy in the nineteenth century which gave

rise to the total state of the interwar years. In the words of Paul Hirst, [t]he [liberal]

state provided a legally codified order within which social customs, economic

competition, religious beliefs, and so on, could be pursued without becoming 'political.'

'Politics' as such ceases to be exclusively the matter of the state when 'state and society

penetrate each other.18 It is difficult not to agree with Hirsts interpretation when

examining Schmitts text. For Schmitt, [t]he concept of the State presupposes the

concept of the Political.19 While the most salient features of the concept of the political

have been spelled out in this chapter, it is important to investigate what is the concept

of the state that Schmitt has in mind. For him the state is nothing else than the legal

order itself,20 Schmitt recognizes the political dimension that involves the creation of

the state, that is, the potentially antagonistic relationship between those who govern and

those who are governed. Gopal Balakrishnan begins to query this statement by asking

17
See Carl Schmitt, The Age of Neutralisations and Depoliticisations, Telos 96 (1998): 130-42.
18
Paul Hirst, Carl Schmitts Decisionism, in The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, ed. Chantal Mouffe
(London: Verso, 1999), 23.
19
Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, l.
20
Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans. George Schwab
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985), 19.

61
what was meant by Schmitt with the word presuppose.21 To say presuppose however

also indicates that the political is a fundamental feature of human behaviour that

includes the organization of a particular form of order yet is not limited to state-related

endeavours. In consequence this presupposition logically implies that the political can

occur also within and beyond the spectre of the state.

The challenge Schmitt poses does not intend to eradicate the function of the state

as an analytical unit for the study of the constructions of identities. However, this idea

begins to suggest how state-based theories of identity might fail to account for, or to

explain the emergence of, collective identities within the state and outside of it as

consequences of the contested notion of politics. Since, as Yosef Lapid points out, the

spectre of the state is still very much with us,22 it is important to recognize that

concepts such as sovereignty (in its liberal form) and the state still play a fundamental

role in the construction of identities.

It is worthy of mention that Schmitts critique of the liberal state corresponds

exclusively to the liberal state of the Weimar Republic. He envisioned a substantial

fissure in the body politic of societies embracing individualism, fearing that political

unity would not be achieved once the demos was left without the possibility of a

determinate decision in the case of conflict between the series of these many bonds.23

Although it can be objected that his critique is determined by the historical conditions

that prevailed in the Weimar Republic, what it is intended here is to show that the

substantial evolution of the liberal state between the interwar years and our current

liberal democracies render Schmitts critique of the liberal state useful only insofar as

21
Gopal Balakrishnan, The Enemy: An intellectual Portrait of Carl Schmitt (London: Verso, 2000): 21
22
Yosef Lapid, Cultures Ship: Returns and Departures in International Relations Theory, in The
Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory, eds. Y. Lapid and F. Kratochwill (Boulder: Lynne Rienner,
1996), 10.
23
Carl Schmitt, Ethic of State and Pluralistic State, in The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, ed. Chantal
Mouffe (London: Verso, 1999), 196.

62
the concepts of the state and sovereignty are analyses as the result of discursive

practices and open to change.

Schmitts version of antagonistic politics should not be regarded as a deliberate

effort to create hostility, however. Rather, he suggests that some degree of antagonistic

conflict is an ineradicable feature of human behaviour that purports to preserve

particular characteristics with which every human grouping acknowledges to be fully

identified. Mouffe provides a promising argument on how antagonism can be situated at

the core of the creation of identities. She argues that in the domain of collective

identifications, where what is in question is the creation of a we by the delimitation of

a them, the possibility always exists that this we/them relations will turn into a relation

of friend/enemy type.24 Accordingly, the discussion here concerns the extent to which

relations of identity/difference can be translated into the friend/enemy arguing that such

a transposition of terms is required in order to construct a radical identity. Radical

identity needs to be seen more as a methodological tool and less as a necessary

condition to understand collective identity formation. I hope the following argument

demonstrates that this process does not conflate difference, otherness and enmity, as has

been claimed by Arash Abizadeh.25

The notion of otherness in the development of identities has long been present

in the history of political thought. A prominent account of particularist identities is

found in Hegels argument.26 The so-called recognition argument states that [s]elf-

consciousness requires recognition by an other who is also a self-consciousness

another human being. And this recognition must be a mutual recognition.27 Contrary to

the particularist understanding inherent in Hegels argument, Abizadeh claims that the

24
Mouffe, The Return of the Political (London: Verso, 1993), 2.
25
Abizadeh, Does Collective Identity Presuppose an Other?, American Political Science Review, 99.1
(2005): 45.
26
It is the Master-Slave Dialectic in F.W.G. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, 166.
27
I have borrowed this phrase from Abidazeh, Does Collective Identity Presuppose an Other?, 6.

63
delimitation of an us/them relationship understood at the conceptual level can be

established in relation to a we referring to all human beings.28 Such an interpretation

of the term humanity involves both a masked conceptual fallacy and an intrinsic

liberal understanding of universal values. Schmitt famously charged that whoever

invokes humanity wants to cheat29 in allusion to the universalising concepts launched

by the liberal machinery. While this form of universalism under the term humanity

attempts to enhance the common aspects that could create a common membership to a

world community in terms of humanity, it fails to account conceptually for particular

cultures, ways of life and for the distinctiveness of political communities with different

needs and self-perception of how they came into being. Moreover, Abizadeh contends

that [t]here is nothing incoherent about an identification that goes beyond humanity, to

include, for example, sentient beings.30 Thus, Abizadehs claim that otherness need not

be human fails to grasp the fundamental axiom of the Hegelian argument whereby one

other self-consciousness is indeed required to mirror the selfs desire for self-

consciousness only through another human being. My suggestion here is therefore that

this mutual identification applies for both individual and collective identity formation

and that it does require an external other which must be human as well.

Alternatively, Schmitt offers a powerful critique of the liberal notion of

humanism, his assertion that [t]he concept of humanity excludes the concept of the

enemy, because the enemy does not cease to be a human being,31 obliterates the

possibility of relying on non-human objects to attain collective identity on a world

scale. Schmitt tries to convey the relevance of an external other against which one

human grouping can reflect its own particular identity. That is, the reflecting other

28
Abidazeh, Does Collective Identity Presuppose an Other?, 46.
29
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 54.
30
Abizadeh, Does Collective Identity Presuppose an Other?,47.
31
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 54.

64
ought to be one other which is not a constituent part of the collectivity because such

constituent elements do not relate in an antagonistic fashion to one another so as to

delineate the limits of collective identity. Only in reflection with an external other can

radical difference be established. In the words of Walker, [c]laims about some

common identity convey a great deal about our capacity to imagine particular identities,

for a common identity is precisely what we do not have, at least in any politically

meaningful sense.32 It is not difficult to notice that Abizadeh falls into a conceptual

pitfall by unnecessarily relating global solidarity, which for him requires a common

global identity based on humanity, to the concept of the friend.

In this context, the concept of the enemy appears to unfold gradually from

both difference and otherness, yet it is possible to come across literature which

posits these concepts to be interwoven or even conflated, as is the case of Abizadeh.33

They are nevertheless, distinct in their conceptual meaning. Yet it is possible to arrive at

enmity, in the Schmittian understanding of it, when departing from difference and

otherness. David Campbell, as a postmodern constructivist, concedes that in so far as

identity requires difference, the potential for the transformation of difference into

otherness always exists.34 Consequently, the possibility of otherness turning into

enmity is also omnipresent in the political and this possibility is contingent upon the

struggle which makes human action so fundamental to the activity of politics.

Relationships of othering are a contingent outcome of difference, yet othering in

itself cannot fully account for the construction of identities. Othering must be perceived

as a threat to ones identity, in other words, that not only the very visibility of its being

other will establish the groups identity, but also the possibility of the other to become

32
R. B. J. Walker, Inside/Outside International Relations as Political Theory (Cambridge & New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 161.
33
Abizadeh, Does Collective Identity Presuppose an Other?, 45.
34
David Campbell, Writing Security: United Status Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity
(Manchester: Manchester University Press: 1992), 23.

65
an enemy. This fine distinction is both profound and crucial to Schmitts thought. I

interpret Connollys statement that [t]he threat is not posed merely by the actions the

other might take to injure or defeat the true identity but by the very visibility of its mode

of being other35 to be fairly consistent with Schmitts portrayal of the enemy in his

claim that it is sufficient for his nature that he is, in a specially intense way,

existentially something different and alien, so that in the extreme case, conflicts with

him are always possible.36 The conceptual differences between otherness and enmity

will necessarily be reflected in the intensity of the conflict. The presence of antagonism

is a necessary condition, therefore, to carry out the process of identification, which in

postmodernist approaches is a process that never achieves a full identification so long as

the enemy stops us from reaching our identity. However, should the enemy disappear it

would be impossible to reflect our own form of identification. We would turn from

subject to object, which makes otherness the condition of possibility and impossibility

of identity, in Derridean terms.

The significance of integrating Schmitts concept of the political for theorising

the construction of identities resides in its ability to comprise a wide range of identity

categories so long as political meaning can be granted. Schmitt explains that every

concrete antagonism becomes that much more political the closer it approaches the most

extreme point, that of the friend-enemy grouping.37And by moving towards the friend-

enemy distinction and thereby becoming political, human groups actively constitute

their identities even if the awareness of the extreme case has been entirely lost.38

These theoretical insights are equally useful for locating the political in discussion of

concepts and methodologies for example. The confrontation of concepts as well as the

35
William E. Connolly, Identity/Difference. Democratic Negotiations of Political Paradox (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 1991), 66.
36
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 27, [my emphasis].
37
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 29.
38
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 30.

66
confrontation of collective systems of belief is a necessary condition for reinforcing and

establishing a sense of identity. Thus identity operates first and foremost from the other,

by distinguishing and identifying the features that are not the concept or collectivity.

2. Ethical Considerations of the Political

One point to be made at this stage refers to the ethical burden that such concepts as

enmity and conflict bear in contemporary liberal debates. Schmitts friend-enemy

distinction has received numerous criticisms39 because, in my opinion, the content of his

political thought has not been sensitively read as a conceptually valid option to shed

light on how potential collective identities come to be constituted. It is important to

reiterate that the friend-enemy distinction need not be taken in its most radical way, as

variously a life-and-death struggle, full-blown physical and/or psychological

violence or out-and-out war, to be able to grasp the distinction between identity and

difference. Rather, I proceed to examine Schmitts brand of antagonism in way similar

to the concept of antagonism developed by the poststructuralists Chantal Mouffe and

Jacques Derrida.

By enemy and conflict, Schmitt is not intending to introduce a language of

hostility in politics but to address the issue that it cannot be denied that nations

continue to group themselves according to friend and enemy antithesis, that the

distinction remains actual today, and that this is an ever present possibility for every

people existing in the political sphere.40 It remains then to address the question of

whether a different analysis of the manifestation of political identities is possible by

means of exploring the discursive practices of translating difference as enmity.

39
A recent critique of Schmitt though can be found in Lon Troyer, Couterterrorism, Sovereignty, Law,
Subjectivity, Critical Asian Studies 35, no.2 (2003): 262.
40
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 28.

67
Insofar as analyses of the processes of collective identity formation are situated

within the analyses of the multiple forms in which difference emerges, questions about

how to approach the concept of conflict start to arise. It is not difficult to trace back in

the history of IR how conflict, has been overemphasized as is the case with realists or

weakened to a point of denial as with the case of institutional liberals.41 However, it is

the ontological value of conflict that has been underexamined and taken for granted.

This brings us to the point where the conceptualisation of conflict has to be addressed.

Poststructuralist thinkers have been concerned with explaining how the establishment of

difference results in the outcome of conflicting structures, stressing particularly the

preservation of the ontological value of conflict by not attempting to overcome its

possibility. Thus conflict comes to constitute the very essence of difference. William

Rasch elaborates as follows,

[c]onflict is possible as a structure of difference, and such a structure is only possible


as a differentiation of unities, a differentiation, that is, of bundled differences. Thus,
the specific nature of politics is determined by the specific constitution of opposed
unities, making the origins of politics already political, already a battle about what
constitutes a politically legitimate unity.42

I stated earlier in this chapter that the relationship of constitutive difference

between self and other necessarily posits a friction of disagreement, namely, an aspect

of non-identification. What is relevant about this relationship is that it demands social

exclusion and simultaneously reassures the members inclusion into their respective

group. Mouffe supports her own claim about the underpinning role of antagonism with

the Derridean notion of constitutive outside which explains [t]he antagonism inherent

in all objectivity and the centrality of the us/them distinction in the constitution of
41
For an account of the treatment of conflict in IR see Jeffrey W. Taliaferro, Security-Seeking Under
Anarchy: Defensive Realism Reconsidered, International Security 25, no. 3 (2000/2001): 152-86; and
John J. Mearsheimer, Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: W.W. Norton, 2002).
42
William Rasch, Conflict as a Vocation. Carl Schmitt and the Possibility of Politics, Theory, Culture
& Society 17, no.6 (2000): 2.

68
political identities. This arises when this us/them relation, which until then was only

perceived as simple difference, began to be seen as one between friend and enemy.43

To make sense of these theoretical assumptions, I reiterate that Schmitts central

argument lies precisely in the intrinsic value of conflict as a delineator of collective

identities. Because liberal constructivists like Wendt downplay the role of conflict in the

construction of identities and therefore in the making of politics, Schmitt has often been

misrepresented as an defender of the intensification of conflict whose conception of

enmity could ostensibly generate violence and war.44 Schmitts conceptualisation of the

enemy does presuppose a possibility whereby conflict itself has the potential to turn into

war. Nevertheless, he insists that [w]ar is neither the aim nor the purpose nor even the

very content of politics. But as an ever present possibility it is the leading

presupposition which determines in a characteristic way human action and thinking and

thereby creates a specifically political behaviour.45 The key word for Schmitt is

possibility and its theoretical implications need to be approached from perspectives that

can embrace the undecidability it entails. This is an aspect that liberal thought and IR

theory attempt to set aside by negotiating procedures to overcome the possibility of

conflict when in fact, procedures are needed to allow for conflict in ways that permit a

ongoing disclosure of the political character of identity without permitting that conflict

turns into war. This is possible I argue through a deep reformulation of how we

understand forms of political action that I examine in detail in chapter three.

This analysis precedes and justifies the assertion that the very possibility of

conflict embedded in the concept of the political serves as parameter to set limits on the

scope of conflict, assuming that there is a boundary beyond which uncontrolled conflict

43
Chantal Mouffe, The Democratic Paradox (London: Verso, 2000), 13.
44
One of major critics includes Jurgen Habermas. I will approach the repercussions of these
misinterpretations in chapter 3.
45
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 35.

69
would necessarily terminate the very purpose of the political. War follows enmity. War

is the existential negation of the enemy But it must nevertheless remain a real

possibility (reale Mglichkeit) for as long as the concept of the enemy remains valid.46

In order to defend the argument that only the possibility of war can bring about

politically meaningful associations, it is important to stress that the point Schmitt tries

to get across materializes in the stakes involved for identity when the enemy is lost.

The emphasis is thus placed on the possibility of establishing a friend-enemy grouping,

the moment in which the peoples sense of belonging is tested by being prompted to

take sides. Derridas reading of Schmitt suggests that the notion of possibility acquires a

reified conceptual value insofar as the struggle for reaching a final decision about who

the enemy is also derives the construction of identities.

[a]s soon as war is possible, it is presently in process .as soon as it is characterised as


eventual (that is, announced as a non-excluded event in a sort of contingent future).
And it is eventual as soon as it is possible. Schmitt does not wish to dissociate the
quasi-transcendental modality of the possible and the historico-factual modality of the
eventual. He names now the eventuality (weningstens eventuell), now the possibility
(Mglichkeit) as soon as war is possible/eventual, the enemy is present the
concept of the enemy is thereby deduced or constructed a priori, both analytically and
synthetically.47

The disappearance of the enemy results in the absence of a constitutive outside

against which any collective subject can reaffirm what their identity is not. Thus conflict

on the one hand cannot be brought to a halt, and simultaneously it ought not to develop

into a war of mutual annihilation. In other words, without the enemy identity ceases its

course of construction and culmination. The poststructuralist reading of Schmitt offered

by Derrida and Mouffe have so far served us as an indicator of the similar grounds that

the Schmittian approach and the poststructuralist conception of conflict share. In both

46
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 33.
47
Jacques Derrida, Politics of Friendship (London: Verso, 1997), 86.

70
instances we are told that the concept of the enemy is a construction that almost always

informs a crucial component of the discourses that make identity possible.

3 The Schmittian Conception of Sovereignty

Now my suggestion extends to indicate that Schmitts concept of the political

decision, which reads sovereign is he who decides on the exception

[Ausnahmezustand],48 is not difficult to integrate into the constellation of postmodern

thinking which challenges the traditional notion of sovereignty by giving it an

interpretation of a fiction of discourse. The state of emergency is tied to sovereignty by

way of a decision which parallels Schmitts notion of the political with that of

poststructuralist thinkers such as Slavoj Zizek, Derrida and Laclau: the moment of the

political is a period where a new social order is founded it institutes that which will

henceforth count as political community.49 Sovereignty is thus seen as the diving line

between chaos and order and its force lies precisely in the decision to designate friends

an enemies for Schmitt. Sovereignty as a concept brings about the necessary distinction

between antagonistic views and concepts. For the purposes of this thesis I sustain that

sovereignty can bring that distinction in cases where, similar to collective systems of

belief, at least two concepts are held in tension, without either being broken apart or

completely elided.

Sovereignty is thus seen as the moment of antagonism.50 Bearing in mind that

the friend/enemy opposition deconstructs itself as a figure of discourse, neither the

48
Schmitt, Political Theology, 5.
49
Jenny Edkins, Poststructuralism and International Relations: Bringing the Political Back in.
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 7.
50
Laclau cited in Edkins, Poststructuralism, 5. This is not to say that Laclau and Mouffes notion of
antagonism corresponds exactly to Schmittian enmity. See for instance Mouffe, The Democratic Paradox,
102.

71
friend nor the enemy is ontologically prior to each other. Hence, it implicates a decision

which is necessarily political because it decides the undecidible.51 In other words, the

state of emergency demands succinctly the construction of a new social order which

brings about the circumstances in which collective identity can be ideally formed. The

sovereign decision is performed in the way that it places itself above the ordinary course

of action, the general norm or the ordinary legal prescription, because as Schmitt puts it,

such an ordinary situation can never encompass a total exception.52 This links

smoothly with my earlier statement in the introduction of this thesis and chapter one

that points at the constant flux of concepts. If concepts are analysed as discursive

constructions that in most cases mutate or evolve, then it is likely that when they enter

the battle of confrontation there will necessarily be a state of exception to establish a

sense of order from which to establish a sense of temporal fixity.

One theoretical limitation in the work of Schmitt is presented by Charles E.

Frye. He critically observes that such a proposition may lead Schmitt to fall into a state

of nihilism.53 If there are absolutely no norms or laws that define or limit the

possibilities open to him, then the sovereign is in a state of mind in which he cannot

possibly decide.54 But such an accusation relies tacitly on Schmitts detachment of any

ethical codes which could exert an influence on the sovereign decision. This is precisely

part of Schmitts possible and highly significant contribution to international relations

theory: he raises questions pertinent to the anarchic nature of our international system

and its institutional forms of politics dominated by liberalism. The displacement of the

political in modern politics places ethics and morality above struggle which, for

Schmitt, meant inhibiting the agency of deciding on a particular situation. But the

51
Jacques Derrida, Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority, in Deconstruction and the
Possibility of Justice, eds. D. Cornell et al. (New York: Routledge, 1992), 15.
52
Schmitt, Political Theology, 5.
53
Charles E. Frye, Carl Schmitts Concept of the Political, The Journal of Politics 28, no.4 (1966): 828.
54
Frye, Carl Schmitts Concept, 828.

72
accusations his notion of sovereignty faces ignore the fact that Schmitts theory of

identity is indeed a theory of limits.

If acknowledging the limits of the community entails the recognition of

homogeneity, it follows that the sovereign act simultaneously leads to the exclusion of

heterogeneity qua difference. Thus, the arrangement of limits appears conceptualisable

in Schmitts theory of identity. Using the lexicon of Laclau, members of a community

generate chains of equivalence55 and not of identity, when this chain closes via the

sovereign act; it does so by excluding that which escapes the scope of the decision.56

Sovereignty, in the Schmittian understanding of it, accounts for an existing

human agency capable to set the limits on the scope and intensity of conflict. Douglas

Bulloch pertinently inquires when decisions are taken on behalf of a collective, what

makes the members of the collective abide by those decisions? .the decision must be

understood as a decision by the members of the collective.57 The constitution of

identity is dependent upon a decision to nominate otherness as enmity and thereby

setting up the conditions to distinguish friends from enemies. Ellen Kennedy expands

this argument by affirming that Schmitt transformed the Hobbesian notion of

sovereignty as a person or instance into a moment of existential intervention in a

process over which the sovereign does not reside as a creator and controller.58 The

particularity of the Schmittian understanding of sovereignty is that it empowers the

collective will with a capacity to decide on an unprecedented situation which exceeds

55
Laclau means by chains of equivalence the presence of signs or concepts that can be associated in a
single discourse. This association is not a form of cooperation but it entails that a mutual enemy is a point
for mutual identification.
56
See Ernesto Laclau, Identity and Hegemony (London: Verso, 2000).
57
Douglas Bulloch, Carl Schmitt and the Theory of the Partisan: Articulating the Partisan in
International Relations (paper presented at the SGIR Conference, The Hague, September 2004),
http://www.sgir.org/conference2004/papers/Bulloch%20-%20Articulating%20the%20Partisan.pdf
(accessed on June, 2005).
58
Ellen Kennedy, Carl Schmitt and the Frankfurt School: A Rejoinder, Telos 73 (1987): 101-116.

73
the moral, economic or aesthetic realms, a decision in the true sense of the word.59

Further, if politics is viewed as a result of struggles in the quest for achieving identity, it

follows that politics derives its force from its capacity to deal with contingency. Rather,

sovereignty, understood in this way seeks to reclaim the agency of human collectives to

decide its own telos. As it has become clear, the relationship between sovereignty and

identity is reciprocally interdependent.

The limitations of Schmitt work are therefore methodological in the sense that

his concepts are equally contestable and subject to change. My position here is to

vindicate that the concepts of the political and sovereignty are located in the place

that semiotics would call signified although inevitably connected with the sign (or

signifier) they represent, their meaning remains discursively constructed as an image of

thought. Although this can bee seen as a weakness, the concept of sovereignty presented

here portrays a more coherent tool to grasp the nature of identity and its strength needs

to be seen in the ways it explains the logic of self/other relationships.

Schmitts limitations for international relations theory remain to be seen mostly

from realist perspectives and international law studies. I agree with his critics that in

practice, much of his work was inspired by the need to salvage Germany from liberal

imperialism.60 This strategy in the end aimed at contributing to the creation of a total

state however, I must insist on the value that his concepts have as analytical instruments

to disclose the close, so far concealed, connection between politics and collective

identity. From this perspective Schmitts thought has not been widely explored and the

real limitation would be for IR theory if his ideas are not seriously taken into account.

On the theoretical level Schmitt can also be charged for not giving sufficient attention to

the issue that causes the opposition between two collectivities. While this issue is a

59
Schmitt, Political Theology, 5.
60
Johnson, Carl Schmitt, Jrgen Habermas, 15-32.

74
necessary component of antagonistic relations, the political reflects the possibility of

antagonism regardless of the conditions in which this develops. In fact, it has been

suggested by Arditi that the issue in dispute makes the political a triad instead of a

binary.61 These three poles connect identity with sovereignty as a result of the decision

and sovereignty with the political as the end of the struggle (temporarily) to achieve

identity.

As a conclusion, while the terms of the debate revolving around collective

identity formation have shifted considerably with the influence of postmodernism, less

attention has been given to Schmitts concept of the political as a useful conceptual

support to theorise identity. I have suggested that Schmitts thought throws promising

insights in the development of a coherent reformulation of identity if it is viewed

through the lens of a postmodern approach. The limitations of discourse analysis as a

methodology also need to be acknowledged in that there is always the risk of denying

the role of socio-economic factors in explaining political motivation. Likewise, the

appeal to linguistics and the context-dependent nature of discourse analysis make

discourse analysis appear a little less than flexible, and as John Torfing has warned, it

could develop into a totalizing master methodology.62

It must be made clear at this stage that the decision to employ the work of Carl

Schmitt over other thinkers can be justified on several grounds. In contrast to Hobbes,

who sees the creation of the Leviathan to offer protection to the life, and therefore the

identity of individuals, Schmitts poltical agent is a collective body and as such the

conceptualization of the enemy remains part of the constitutive outside of the body

politic. In a distinct fashion to Max Weber, who sees politics as a vocation, and for

whom the development of disputes into violence continues to be political, Schmitt limits

61
Arditi, Tracing the Political, Angelaki, 1, No.3, (1995): 16
62
Jacob Torfing, New Theories of Discourse, Laclau, Mouffe and Zizek (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999): 49

75
the content of politics to the possibility of conflict and war. While the approaches of

Arendt and Schmitt have been studied together as being compatible or complementary

in many ways,63 I focus only on Schmitt because he offers a model of antagonism that

can be transformed into agonism in the sense that Arendt depicted it. Arendts work

goes underexplored in this thesis because her approach to politics requires physical

presence to make genuine politics flourish, although this shortcoming could be

transcended if taken conceptually, her approach lacks the presence of antagonism that

this thesis proposes as an ontological necessity of the principle of identity. Some of her

ideas are tacked in chapter three and four where the focus is more on action than on

concepts. The list could go on, but it must be remembered by now that for the length of

the project one of my objectives is to introduce Schmitts concept into current debates

in IR about the nature of concepts such as politics and collective identity.

Schmitt has been subject to conceptual criticism by Leo Strauss64 and Heinrich

Meier65 in a way that goes deeper than other superficial readings of Schmitt that are

circulating around. I consider Strausss and Heinrichs critiques of Schmitt as the most

congruent in the literature whose objections to Schmitts ideas must definitely be

approached with the conceptual scrutiny the work of Schmitt also deserves. Meier

accuses Schmitt for drawing his concepts significantly from theology, the content of

which principally appeals to a transcendental concrete order as opposed to the belief in

an absolute immanent world as proposed by Hegel. Schmitts concept of the political is

in this sense transcendental and counterposes immanence in the sense that the friend-

enemy distinction is conceptually dependent on a constitutive outside to exist. Mika

Ojakangas suggests that Meiers accusation of Schmitt too quickly misinterprets the

63
See Emma Norman, The Political Self, 130-142.
64
See Leo Strauss, Comments on Carl Schmitts Der Begriff des Politischen in Schmitt, Carl, The
Concept of the Political. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1976
65
Heinrich Meier The Lesson of Carl Schmitt: Four Chapters on the Distinction between Political
Theology and Political Philosophy, (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2004), 204

76
political character of Schmitts theology only for the resemblances it could bear to

Christian theology. Ojakangas discusses that this move in Schmitts thought against the

Hegelian immanent world has its roots in Schmitts desire to illuminate humans

freedom to act politically outside its own self-immanent world.66

Schmitt has also been the target of Strauss who famously denounced Schmitt for

proposing a concept of the political too separate from a particular conception of the

good, the major consequence of which is to give this concept ontological neutrality. In

contradiction to himself, this is a principle Schmitt attacked liberals of using with

procedures. However, in my view the decision to designate and distinguish the enemy

from the friend has an already ethical content to it. This moral decision is not ultimately

abided by any liberal conception of the good but can be attributed to Schmitts own

personal interpretation of a decision between good and evil, which as Sergei Prosorov

appropriately proposes, this a-moralism of Schmitts concept of the political is a vital

component of its ethical dimension.67 My criticism of Schmitt is his reductionism of

human relations into the friend-enemy distinction as containing a radical view of what

can only be political. This is in part one of the capital reasons why I chose to offer a

poststructuralist reading of Schmitt in conjunction with some exegetical work. I

interpret this move of Schmitt to encompass all of what lies within the variety of radical

antagonisms in human thought. The consequences of his concept of sovereignty as the

act that emanates from nothingness and cannot be subsumed68 may suggest certain

degree of nihilism but also could convey a sort of a mystical element in his thought. His

conception of human sovereignty appears as a direct reproduction of Christians god

66
Mika Ojakangas, A Terrifying World Without An Exterior: Carl Schmitt and the Metaphysicis of
Word (dis)order, Conference on: The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt. September 2004.
available at: http://www.sgir.org/conference2004/papers/Ojakangas. (Accesed on 23 Jan 2006).
67
Sergei Prozorov, The Ethos of Insecure Life: Schmitt, Kundera and Foulcault and the Point of the
Political. Conference on The Political Thought of Carl Schmitt, Septermber 2001. available at:
http://www.sgir.org/conference2004/papers/Prozorov. (Accessed on 3 May, 2006).
68
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 32.

77
sovereignty. In this sense, collective identity and politics are ultimately related by a

human sovereign act that I have shown is dependent on human action.

In applying Schmitts concept of the political to support a theoretical framework

of identity, I focus on the relevant aspects of his thought which deserve a deeper

assessment and are often overlooked along with other aspects of his theory which

convey a rather more radical tone. Nonetheless, what is intended in this chapter is to

provide a reconstructive theoretical framework69 which may incite to raise questions

about why it is important to understand collective identity in relation to difference

acknowledging the conflicting reality such a process entails. The significance of identity

depends to a certain extent on our ability to identify the structures of power inherent in

the politics of identity which will significantly affect our life chances. Such structures of

inequality abound at the international level as well as within the state. The lack of

substantial non-ethical approaches in the area accounts for why identity has been a

fundamental element of social liberation as well as in social oppression.

The benefit of using a postmodern approach can be honestly assessed to the

degree in which the methodology employed interrogates the nature of cultural and social

identities as fictions of discourse. However, my intention is not to discard the existence

of collective forms of identifications as merely fictitious creations translated into facts.

Rather, Schmitts challenge for identity theory is just as liberating in that it allows a

collective will to take their own stand, their own Gestalt beyond the structures already

produced. In the next chapter, I examine two contemporary approaches to develop

alternative forms of political action. These are the deliberative democratic approach and

agonistic pluralism. These forms of political action reveal useful in providing elements

to contest and discuss collective systems of belief. However, I show that the agonistic

69
Lapid and Kratochwil, The Return of Culture, 23.

78
pluralist approach succeeds in providing adequate mechanisms for antagonistic

confrontation of concepts, which in turn allows for an deeper analysis of the connection

between politics and identity.

79

You might also like