Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, Duncan Pritchard (Editor) - Social Epistemology-Oxford University Press, USA (2010) PDF
Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, Duncan Pritchard (Editor) - Social Epistemology-Oxford University Press, USA (2010) PDF
Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, Duncan Pritchard (Editor) - Social Epistemology-Oxford University Press, USA (2010) PDF
Data available
Bibliography 326
Index 345
vi
List of Contributors
vii
Acknowledgements
We would like to extend warm thanks to the contributors to this volume for being willing
to have their work published in it. Several contributions are related to presentations given
at a conference on Social Epistemology held at the University of Stirling in late August-
early September 2007. We are grateful to those who were present for the stimulus they
provided. The conference was part of a project on the value of knowledge funded by the
UK's Arts and Humanities Research Council. We thank the Council for its generous
support.
Warm thanks are also due to Yvonne McClymont for assistance with the administration
of the project, to Nikki Leavitt for secretarial assistance, to Steinvr Thll rnadttir for
assistance in preparing the typescript, and to Tom Cunningham for producing the Index.
Their support has made the work of the editors very much easier.
Peter Momtchiloff has been an enormous support in relation to this and other published
work emerging from the value of knowledge project. We very much appreciate his
encouragement and assistance.
viii
Introduction
These are exciting times for the field of social epistemology, which has grown quite
dramatically in the last twenty-five years to become one of the mainstays of
contemporary philosophy. The aim of this volume is to offer a cross-section of the
excellent work that is currently being conducted on this topic. We feel that we have
succeeded.
The very idea of approaching epistemological concerns from a perspective that is both
social and philosophical (as opposed to sociological) is relatively new. As has often been
observed, the epistemological enterpriseindeed, arguably philosophy more generally
has for much of its history, and certainly since Descartes, been cast along egocentric
lines. Where a non-egocentric approach has been taken, as in the recent work of naturalist
epistemologists, the focus has been on individuals (not necessarily human) interacting
with their environment rather than on the significance of social interaction for an
understanding of the nature and value of knowledge. Indeed, until quite recently the only
kind of social topic discussed at any length by mainstream epistemologists was that of
testimony, and even then the issue tended to be largely understood from the perspective
of the consumer of the testimony rather than in terms of the complex social web in which
testimonial exchanges take place.
Things are very different today, with social epistemology now firmly lodged at the very
heart of a vibrant contemporary epistemological literature. For example, consider the
current discussion of testimony. From being a mainly peripheral part of the
epistemological canon, testimony is now centre stage, and as part of this transition the
very scope of the debate has altered to take in new topics.
This transition in the literature of testimony is well represented in the contributions to this
volume. On the one hand, the papers by Ram Neta and Frederick F. Schmitt are
specifically concerned with the work of a particular prominent figure in the literature
(Tyler Burge and Richard Moran, respectively), and thus in this sense constitute natural
extensionsand enrichmentsof the mainstream discussion. On the other hand, the
chapters by Jennifer Lackey, Michael P. Lynch, and Ernest Sosa explore a topic that is
relatively new to the epistemology of testimonythe epistemology of disagreement
while other chapters take the mainstream debate about testimony in new directions by
exploring the relevance of such notions as comprehension (Peter J. Graham), the social
norm of trust (Paul Faulkner), and recognitional abilities (Alan Millar).
ix
The real progress that has been made in the field of social epistemology is, however, best
reflected in how the literature in this area now covers issuesoften of a
metaphilosophical flavourwhich concern the topic of testimony only peripherally, if at
all. This is reflected by the range of topics covered by the papers collected in this volume.
At the metaphilosophical end of the spectrum there are the papers by Lorraine Code,
Alvin Goldman, and Miranda Fricker which raise wide-ranging issues about the nature of
social epistemology and what it can contribute to epistemology more generally. At the
other end of the spectrum we have the chapters by Sanford C. Goldberg and Jonathan
Kvanvig which examine particular epistemological issues that are salient to social
epistemology (respectively, the epistemology of silence and epistemic value). Lying
between these two camps are the chapters by Matthew Chrisman and Klemens Kappel,
which are concerned with the specific meta-epistemological issue of the social dimension
of knowledge ascriptions.
This volume thus captures the tremendous diversity and depth of the contemporary
debate in social epistemology. In doing so our hope is that it advances that debate still
further.
x
Analytical Table of Contents
xi
or elaborated, counted as the most reliable sources, with testimony ranking as a
distant, and usually compromised, third. In my view, social epistemology reverses
this ranking, granting a central place to testimony in the production of knowledge,
and interrogating assumptions about the replicability and homogeneity of
perception and memory. It thus generates a range of issues that had been hors de
question for traditional epistemologists. Drawing on the conceptual framework I
develop in my 2006 book, Ecological Thinking: The Politics of Epistemic
Location, I propose that epistemic enquiry socially reconfigured is more fully
naturalized than post-Quinean naturalized epistemology. Social epistemology
focuses on epistemic practices communally engaged by identifiable knowers in the
world (thus not principally in the laboratory), who are situated not just socially, but
ethically, politically, demographically, geographically, and ecologically, where
aspects of such situatedness' often count among the conditions that make
knowledge possible. This enquiry focuses on testimony and advocacy as practices
where these factors are particularly salient, and on ignorance not as a mere lack or
failure of knowledge, but as a modality of not-knowing, or knowing
inadequately/unjustly, which is itself situationally fostered, inhibited, or eradicated.
xii
4. ON SAYING THAT SOMEONE KNOWS: THEMES FROM CRAIG
In his book Knowledge and the State of Nature, Edward Craig proposes a new
methodological approach to one of the crucial questions in epistemology, the
question what knowledge is, or more precisely the question regarding the nature
and the concept of knowledge. The main aim of the chapter is to discuss and to
propose a distilled version of Craig's approach. The main issue is how to make
sense of questions such as What is the point of the concept of knowledge? and
Why do we attribute knowledge? In the chapter, I characterize and defend a
general way of understanding such questions, and contrast it to elements of Craig's
approach. On the basis of this, I offer some views about what, in Craig's
terminology, is the point of the concept of knowledge, and again I contrast this to
some of the claims put forward by Craig. Like Craig, I believe that understanding
the point of the concept of knowledge may yield some insights about knowledge
and the concept of knowledge, though space does not permit a discussion of these
further questions.
The Swamping Problem is one of the central problems in the new value-driven
approach to epistemology that has arisen recently. It arises from the fact that value
is not always additive, so if you begin with something valuable (true belief) and
add a further valuable thing (justification), there is no guarantee that the
combination is more valuable. The usual target of such concerns is reliabilism, but
such concerns plague approaches that are more conscious of value concerns as
well, such as functional accounts that aim at an account of knowledge in terms of
its social significance as a marker of dependable sources of information. Here I
investigate the fundamental nature of the problem and several recent attempts to
provide an escape route from the problem, concluding that none of them succeeds.
xiii
6. FROM EPISTEMIC EXPRESSIVISM TO EPISTEMIC INFERENTIALISM
Recent philosophical debate about the semantics of knowledge claims has largely
centred on the question of whether epistemic claims are plausibly thought to be
context sensitive. The default assumption has been that sentences that attribute
knowledge or justification (or whatever else is epistemic) have stable truth
conditions across different contexts of utterance, once any non-epistemic context
sensitivity has been fixed. The contrary view is the contextualist view that such
sentences do not have stable truth conditions but can vary according to the context
of utterance. This debate manifestly presupposes that the meta-epistemological
issue of accounting for the meaning of epistemic claims is to be settled by
determining the truth conditions of these claims. In the light of two observations, I
think this presupposition is under-motivated. First, many epistemologists see
epistemic claims as evaluative or normative, in some sense. Second, in the meta-
ethical debate most philosophers take alternatives to truth-conditional semantics,
such as expressivism, as live options when it comes to evaluative or normative
claims. As it turns out, I do not think expressivism provides a plausible account of
normative concepts across the board. But considering it as an alternative in the
meta-epistemological debate points the way to another alternative to truth-
conditional semantics. This is a form of inferentialism. In this chapter, I try to
motivate a move to epistemic inferentialism by showing how it overcomes worries
about expressivism and interacts with plausible ideas about the social function
epistemic claims play in our commerce with one another and the world.
7. NORMS OF TRUST
Should we tell other people the truth? Should we believe what other people tell us?
This chapter argues that something like these norms of truth-telling and belief
govern our production and receipt of testimony in conversational contexts. It then
attempts to articulate these norms and determine their justification. More fully
specified, these norms prescribe that speakers tell the truth informatively, or be
trustworthy, and that audiences presume that speakers do this, or trust. These
norms of trust, as norms of conversational cooperation, would then seem to be
justified on the basis of the interest that each has in the cooperative outcome. The
norms of trust would then be justified as Lewisian conventions. However, the joint
outcome prescribed by these norms is not a equilibrium
xiv
point: a speaker always does better to have an audience's trust and the liberty to tell
the truth or not, as it suits. In this way, testimony presents a problem of trust. The
justification of these norms of trust then starts from the recognition that any society
that did not resolve this problem of trust would be stymied as a society. The
resolution of this problem then requires securing the motivations characteristic of
trusting and being trustworthy, where to have these motivations is to have an
ethical outlook defined in terms of internalizing these norms of trust. This
justification is genealogical and it is one of value.
In his influential article Content Preservation, Tyler Burge argues for the highly
unorthodox thesis that, at least under some circumstances, when someone who is a
priori entitled to believe that p tells us that p, she thereby renders us a priori
entitled to believe that p. Anna-Sara Malmgren has argued against this thesis, and
raised objection to what she takes to be Burge's argument for it. After devoting the
first half of the present chapter to laying out precisely what Burge's thesis, and his
argument, amount to, I show that Malmgren's argument against Burge rests on a
misinterpretation. But I then go on to argue that, even when correctly interpreted,
Burge's argument still does not work: it rests on the premises that (a) what you're
entitled to believe is closed under modus ponens consequence, and (b) having an a
priori entitlement to believe that you're entitled to believe that p suffices for having
an a priori entitlement to believe that p. (a) and (b) appear plausible only if we
confuse the externalist kind of warrant that Burge calls entitlement with the
internalist warrant that he calls justification.
In this chapter I explore an analogy between our reliance on memory and our
reliance on news coverage. The analogy derives from a certain sort of
counterfactual reasoning that might be employed to support beliefs in either
domain, in cases involving the silence of a relied-upon source. Thus one might
form the belief that p on the grounds that if p were false one would have heard
about it by now (or would have remembered it). In another paper I develop an
account of the conditions under which counterfactual reasoning of this sort is
epistemically fruitful. Here I address a related matter: whether resources within the
epistemology of memory might be helpful in thinking about the epistemic
significance of silence from any relied-upon sourcewhether that source is one's
own memory, or the news groups on which one relies for coverage.
This chapter takes up one main question: when and how can a belief be sustained
reasonably in the face of known disagreement? On the answer to this question will
depend our prospects for sustaining cherished opinions in fields where controversy
abounds, such as religion, politics, history, morality, art, philosophy, and even
medicine and the law.
xviii
1. INTRODUCTION
Alvin I. Goldman
What is social epistemology? Or what might it be? According to one perspective, social
epistemology is a branch of traditional epistemology that studies epistemic properties of
individuals that arise from their relations to others, as well as epistemic properties of
groups or social systems. A simple example (of the first sort) is the transmission of
knowledge or justification from one person to another. Studying such interpersonal
epistemic relations is a legitimate part of epistemology. A very different perspective
would associate social epistemology with movements in postmodernism, social studies
of science, or cultural studies that aim to replace traditional epistemology with radically
different questions, premises, or procedures. Although these enquiries examine the social
contexts of belief and thought, they generally seek to debunk or reconfigure conventional
epistemic concepts rather than illuminate the nature and conditions of epistemic success
or failure. Under the first construal social epistemology is a bona fide part of the
mainstream, and hence real epistemology. Under the second construal, it is not part of
epistemology at all. If protagonists of the latter-day movements marketed their products
under the guise of epistemology, they would be imposters. Their products are not real
epistemology.
Is social epistemology real epistemology? is a question posed by William Alston
(2005). He raises it en passant, while noting that epistemology's boundaries are
controversial, drawn differently by different thinkers. To illustrate his point, he suggests
that much of the material in my book on social epistemology, Knowledge in a Social
World (Goldman 1999), would be rejected by many contemporary epistemologists as
not real epistemology (Alston 2005: 5). The epistemologists in question, says Alston,
would relegate much of this so-called social epistemology to sociology, social
psychology, or other social sciences, or perhaps to the philosophical foundations thereof.
1
What about this claim that Alston attributes to imagined readers of Knowledge in a Social
World? Would these readers be correct in saying that the material in question does not
qualify as real epistemology? Setting aside the specifics of Knowledge in a Social
World, which theoretical enterprises that flyor might flyunder the flag of social
epistemology deserve the label epistemology and which ones do not? Wherein does
social epistemology differ or diverge from traditional epistemology, and what differences
and divergences would carry social epistemology beyond the pale?
3. REVISIONISM
The writers subsumed under the heading of revisionism rarely employ the label social
epistemology.2 Nonetheless, since they typically study science and other forms of
knowledge-seeking, and they certainly emphasize the social character of these pursuits,
mainstream philosophers might view their approaches as aspiring forms of epistemology.
Under revisionism I include postmodernism, deconstructionism, social constructionism,
and various social studies of science, including the strong programme in sociology of
science. These movements share a staunch rejection of many if not all of the core tenets
of traditional epistemology. These rejections, moreover, are inspired by the social
character of the phenomena they study.
A few philosophers such as Richard Rorty fall into the same category, sometimes waxing
emphatic about the bankruptcy of traditional epistemology. Rorty (1979) declared the
death of epistemology and proposed a vague replacement for it in the form of a
conversation of mankind. His mantra was to keep the conversation going rather than to
find objective truth (1979: 377).
One strand of social constructionism holds that truths or facts are not in or of the world;
they are not out there to be discovered but are mere social fabrications or constructions
(Latour and Woolgar 1986). As Steven Shapin puts it, truth is a social institution (1994:
6). While revisionists often use the language of knowledge, they don't understand it to
be a truth-entailing, or factive, state. In their lexicon knowledge is simply whatever is
believed, or perhaps institutionalized belief. On the topic of rationality, we find
proponents of the strong programme rejecting objectivist rationality, declaring that there
are no context-free or super-cultural norms of rationality (Barnes and Bloor 1982: 27).
On the question of epistemic agents, at least a few revisionists deny that individuals are
epistemic agents at all. Only groups or communities qualify as knowers, according to
Lynn Hankinson-Nelson (1993):
In suggesting that it is communities that construct and acquire knowledge, I do not
mean . . . that what comes to be recognized or certified as knowledge is the result of
collaboration between . . . individuals who, as individuals, know in some logically or
empirically prior sense . . . [T]he collaborators, the consensus achievers, and, in more
general terms, the agents who generate knowledge are communities and subcommunities,
not individuals. (Hankinson-Nelson 1993: 124)
3
Thus, revisionists dispute many of the main tenets of traditional epistemology. They
might be called social epistemologists' by courtesy, but there is a wide gulf between their
questions and those that traditionally go by the name epistemology. Researchers in
these traditions are often absorbed with case studies in history and/or sociology of
science, with only scant attention to epistemic implications as mainstream
epistemologists would conceive of them. Several writers in the sociology of science
advance political-military accounts of science, aiming to displace the traditional notion
that science is a province of reason or rationality. Shapin and Schaffer remark that in
scientific disputes, [h]e who has the most, and the most powerful, allies wins' (1985:
342). Latour (1987: 31) offers a detailed analysis of how scientific controversies in
science are conducted by enlisting the support of forceful allies' such as prominent
journals, Nobel prize winners, or granting agencies. What does this show about the
epistemic properties of science? Latour's political-military account is intended to debunk
or undercut the alleged role of evidence and truth in science.3 This makes it natural for
mainstream epistemologists to deny that such approaches constitute genuine
epistemology, because little or no serious epistemic business gets conducted, as
mainstreamers see it.4
Our attempt to draw a firm boundary between revisionism and mainstream epistemology
may be a bit quick. Recent developments in epistemology and philosophy of language
may argue for greater nuance. Is it true, for example, that mainstream epistemology
firmly and definitively rejects relativism? Recently the scene has shifted a bit. There is a
New Age kind of relativismas Crispin Wright (2007, 2009) calls itthat has gained
popularity within analytic philosophy. Perhaps New Age relativism has much in common
with what revisionists like Barnes and Bloor have claimed. If so, there may be less
distance between revisionism and mainstream epistemology than suggested above.
However, we should not exaggerate the degree to which the popularity of New Age
relativism closes the gap between revisionism and mainstream analytic epistemology.
What Wright calls New Age relativism is a view championed by John MacFarlane
(2005), Max Kolbel (2003), and Peter Lasersohn (2005), among others, that says the
following: for a number of regions of discourse
4
the very same token claim can take different truth values when considered in different
contexts of assessment. This doctrine is a version of contextualism, except in holding that
an utterance's truth value depends on an index that varies with variable characteristics of
hypothetical assessments (rather than, say, contexts of use). In discussing predicates of
personal taste, Lasersohn suggests (at first pass) that in analysing a sentence like Roller
coasters are fun, we let the character (in Kaplan's sense) of the predicate fun yield
different contents in different contexts, depending on the speaker (or some other
referent). It might be claimed that the predicate fun has a hidden argument place, filled
by some sort of implicit indexical pronoun. Carrying this over to epistemology, New Age
relativism would be the thesis that the truth of statements about epistemic justification is
assessment-relative, with systems of standards providing the relevant assessment-
contextual parameter (Wright 2009: 384). This kind of relativism is attracting non-
negligible support among analytic philosophers.
However, as Paul Boghossian points out (2008: 414), New Age relativism is primarily a
semantical thesis, and as formulated above it does not express everythingor the most
important thingthat revisionist relativism means to assert. Revisionist relativism would
agree on a central presupposition of New Age relativism, namely, that multiple epistemic
systems are possible and justification claims can be assessed relative to any of these
different systems. Revisionist relativism, however, also endorses a further thesis, which
Boghossian sometimes calls epistemic nihilism. Epistemic nihilism says that there are
no facts by virtue of which one of these systems is more correct than any of the others'
(Boghossian 2006: 73, 2008: 413).5 This, I submit, is the core thesis of relativism that
revisionists advance and mainstream epistemologists dispute. So, even conceding the
respectability of New Age relativism, there remains a significant divide between
revisionist and mainstream views in the matter of relativism (in addition to other core
differences).
In short, with respect to a body of work in the social sciences and the humanities that is
sometimes dubbed social epistemology, epistemologists are well within their rights to
deny it the status of real epistemology. If one is in the demarcation business, there are
reasonable boundaries to be drawn.
4. PRESERVATIONISM
dimension.6 Suitable treatments of these questions would preserve the core assumptions
of traditional epistemology. So if SE is equated with the sector of epistemology that
scrutinizes these questions, SE is well within the realm of legitimate, genuine
epistemology. I shall illustrate preservationism by reference to three types of activity
studied by traditional epistemology, each of which has a social sector. Each social sector
of these parts of epistemology qualifies as real epistemology. The three types of
activity, in their social variants, are (1) doxastic decision-making with social evidence,
(2) gathering social evidence, and (3) speech and communication with an informational
purport (assertion, debate, argumentation, etc.).
I could not but wonder . . . what it would take to make my experience verifiable. The
testimony of an independent white bystander? . . . The blind application of principles of
neutrality. . . acted either to make me look crazy or to make the reader participate in old
habits of cultural bias.
(Patricia J. Williams 1991: 478)1
1. POINTS OF ENTRY
Much early twenty-first century Anglo-American epistemology is residually loyal to a
tradition for which perception, memory, reason, and testimony are the principal, most
reliable sources of knowledge, and the epistemically autonomous, self-reliant individual
is the presumptive knowing subject. Testimony's relegation to last place on this list
signals its lesser ranking in relation to perception, memory, and reason (or induction),
because reliance on testimony has long been thought to compromise epistemic self-
reliance. Social epistemology unsettles this ranking. In granting a central place to
testimony in knowledge production and circulation, it interrogates assumptions about the
homogeneity and universal replicability of knowers and the known, while contending
that epistemic self-reliance is at best an impossible dream, and contesting charges that
testimony amounts to nothing more substantial than hearsay, rumour, or gossip. Persistent
distrust of testimony is held in place by a tacit picture of the solitary epistemic agent
whose self-sufficiency and open receptivity ensure that her or his direct perceptions in
normal or ideal observation conditions will yield reliable knowledge. Memory enables
her or him to sort and match perceptions, which vary in reliability with the vividness of
the originating sensory experiences. Yet testimony, even in a (Russellian) restricted form
of knowledge by description,
29
is a risky affair even when it takes the form of corroborated oral or written reports.
This ingrained distrust of testimony is curious in view of how small a proportion of what
people reasonably claim to know, individually or communally, comes from or is
verifiable in appeals to first-hand experience. It is more puzzling still when enquiry
moves into the social register, away from the rarefied places where epistemologists
commonly work and the abstract, sanitized examples on which they tend to base their
conclusions: when it moves into places where testimony, in a richer than merely
information-reporting sense, becomes the stuff of which knowledge is made and on
which policies, practices, attitudes, and actions rely. There, the knower cannot be
represented as an isolated, self-sufficient being for testimony is, inherently, a form of
address: it is explicitly and intentionally interactive. Hence it is a place where epistemic
individualism cannot hold. Although formal perception- and memory-stating
propositional knowledge claims of the S-knows-that-p variety may (implausibly) pose
as monologic, as though no interlocutor(s) were required for their completion, a
testimonial communication looks to its hearer(s) for acknowledgement, contestation, and
uptake.
Social epistemology claims its title, in large measure, from the centrality it accords to
testimony and to knowledge-conveying exchanges in the real world. It is striking for the
attention many social epistemologists give to extended, situated examples of epistemic
negotiation and for the subtle, far-reaching effects of linguistic shifts from impersonal,
third-person propositional claims that S knows that p to the language of speakers and
hearers evident, to cite just two examples, in Edward Craig's (1990) Knowledge and the
State of Nature, and Miranda Fricker's (2007) Epistemic Injustice. Where the S-knows-
that-p rubric enabled formal early twentieth-century Anglo-American epistemology to
transcend the vicissitudes of the world in order to discern a priori necessary and sufficient
conditions for knowledge in general, social epistemologists return to and reclaim the
world, both human and other-than-human, with its incoherence and messiness, its
contradictions and specificities, to engage constructively and critically, descriptively and
normatively, with real epistemic interactions and negotiations. Hence the very idea of
knowledge in general is drained of content. Social epistemology generates a range of
issues that, for traditional epistemologists, counted merely as hors de question, many of
which blur the dividing lines that have separated epistemological enquiry from ethical
and political debate and influences. In social epistemology, ethical-political questions
such putatively extra-epistemological issues as trust, power, advocacy, negotiation, and
epistemic communityinevitably enter the discourse, and not to the detriment of
responsibly objective enquiry. Giving and receiving testimony commonly, if tacitly,
involves many of these issues.
In his essay Getting Told and Being Believed, Richard Moran argues persuasively in
favour of its being sufficient for bringing someone to know that
30
P that they were told by someone who knew, and they believed him . . . if this second
person is taken to know that P, he may tell another person, and so on (Moran 2006:
273).2 Moran's interest is less in conditions for the possibility of knowledge than in the
relation of believing, where its direct object is not a proposition but a person (Moran
2006: 273). His broader interest is in the relationships, the modalities of epistemic
dependence and, I would add, of epistemic vulnerability and risk, that follow from
reliance on testimony as a source of knowledge. In his view, the distinctive relation of
believing another person (Moran 2006: 274) is pivotal. This relation is quintessentially
social, if sometimes in a minimal sense when relatively trivial, punctiform informational
items are at issue. It is forged in communicative discourse, and hence in eschewing the S-
knows-that-p rubric where any knower, interchangeably, can occupy the S-place and any
object, the-p place. A certain particularity enters the scene, implying that, to a greater or
lesser extent according to the substance of the situation, it matters who that other person
is, for a responsible knower will not believe just anyone, unless for quotidian
informationabout the time of the train, the location of the bank. In invoking a
responsible knower, however, I am not suggesting that the responsibility is the hearer's
alone. Equally urgent, and more significant for Moran, is the responsibility of the speaker
in exchanges both trivial and complex: someone who tells me the meeting will take place
tonight is giving me her assurance, he maintains, that it will happen. My informant
participates as a kind of guarantor, provid[ing] me with a characteristic reason to
believe, different in kind from anything provided by evidence alone (Moran 2006: 279).
Here, ethical issues are integral to the appeals to assurance and responsibility invoked in
even the smallest moments of communicative action: introducing questions about
assurance and responsibility underscores the extent to which analyses of testimony
require a departure from epistemic individualism. Not only are giving assurance and
taking responsibility interactive and communal, but their centrality to testimonial
practices confirms that once the discourse of communicative engagement displaces the
discourse of autonomy and rights, the very idea of epistemic self-reliance is opened to
contestation. An epistemic stance for which responsibility is an overarching epistemic
virtue3 distinguishes itself, also, from reliabilism, which remains committed to
individualism in conceiving of reliability as a function of innate intellectual capacities,
and cognitive processes as quasi-mechanistic. On such a model, questions about
responsibility need not arise.4
Implicit in the assumptions that govern Moran's and Welbourne's positions is a specific
(if not specified) conception of the social for which participants in testimonial
knowledge-conveying and -receiving exchanges are situated on
31
a level playing field where these exchanges readily go through, and questions about
perceptual/experiential commensurability are unlikely to arise. There is an established
tradition in Anglo-American epistemology of beginning from the small and working
toward the more complex, from a conviction that complex amounts, in effect, to simple
multiples of the small: to the small writ large, so to speak. There is a certain plausibility
to such an approach, yet it is misleading in that it represents the social as less than fully
social, with none of the complexities of sociality. In glossing over the interactive
character of communication and failing to consider how it is often engaged across
intransigent social-conceptual differences where investigation and negotiation are
required for understanding to be achieved, it leaves open the question just how social its
operative conception of the social really is.5 It generates assumptions about the ease of
communication and understandingof uptake and acknowledgement (in Wittgenstein's
sense6 )fostering a conviction that we are so alike that our knowledge conveying (in
Welbourne's sense7 ) is a process of straightforward transmission and reception on the
model of a radio or television broadcast, where the speaker is a neutral medium through
which knowledge is transmitted, packaged, perhaps, and thus touched by her particular
rational (even creative) capacities, but untainted by her other idiosyncracies, biases,
predilections. The hearer is a passive, equivalently neutral receiver. Often, this state of
affairs prevails, but more rarely, I suggest, than Moran or Welbourne allows. Hence it is
unclear how they could address Patricia Williams's situation as she captures it in the
epigraph to this chapter.
Williams's question is prompted by, and exemplary for understanding, a common public
failure of acknowledgement and uptake, in this instance enacted in response to her
testimony about an incident at a New York Benetton's store, where a buzzer system
allowed sales personnel to refuse admission to undesirables. Intending to make a
purchase, she pressed her round brown face to the window and buzzed for admission. A
white, bubble-gum blowing teenager glanced her way, and mouthed We're closed, even
though several white people were shopping in the store. The question she poses was
prompted by the editors of a law review symposium on Excluded Voices who, after
making unacceptable (to Williams) cuts to her written analysis of the episode, indicated
they did not publish things that were unverifiable. In the final version of the essay
without consulting herthey sought to eliminate all references to race, contending that
naming it was just a matter of style. As a black professional woman in mid-1980s
America, Williams was well positioned to recognize how racism was germane to such an
incident, and acutely aware of how often charges of paranoia are levelled against racially
marked people who allege race as a determining factor in
32
their treatment. Since her testimony was to appear in a law review article, as an
established professor in a prestigious US law school whose credentials, by default,
become part of the tacit assurance she offers of the accuracy of her testimony, she might
without invoking these qualifications have anticipated a presumption in favour of her
credibility. Clearly, in this case, believing a person is at issue, and factors integral to the
sedimented social imaginary of a racist society override any expectation that telling and
hearing can suffice for testimony to establish its veracity.
In short, on Moran's criteria, Williams is disbelieved as a person. She may have been
mistaken in the substance of her testimony, and additional evidence might show this to be
so. She may have misread the Benetton situation, but this is not the issue for no attempt is
made to establish or discredit such a possibility; and in this situation as it played out, the
issue is less about logical possibilities of seeing otherwise than about the practical
possibilities that influenced how her knowledge claims acquired public standing.
Standards are in place before the fact to determine her credibility, and her perception is
that her race has overridden her professional status (which is presumably unknown to the
teenager, but not to her law review peers). It also might be thought, in the initial
encounter, to have overridden her class, which must have been legible from her
appearance and could have told in favour of her trustworthiness. These are details people
routinely take into account in information-seeking and testimony-evaluating activities.
When the editors insist that race should not be mentioned, in the interest of maintaining
an (illusory) neutrality, it is impossible to evaluate Williams's testimony on criteria that
address the specificities of the social climate: specificities integral to the very possibility
of such an event's taking place. These are public matters of credibility, incredulity, and
the politics of belief: they are missing from Moran's and Welbourne's accounts owing to
the kinds of example they rely on and the social imaginary within which their analyses
are conducted. The larger issue, then, is about how social situations and identities
influence processes through which testimony can yield knowledge good of its kind.
Principles of neutrality that prohibit taking specificities into account render Williams's
protests at best unreasonable, at worstas she puts itcrazy. Hence they prevent this
event and others like it from claiming a testimonial hearing on their own terms: no
assurance she offers can break the epistemic deadlock.
Miranda Fricker's (2007) work on epistemic injustice develops a rich conceptual resource
for thinking through such cases. Her analysis is grounded in a reading of virtue
epistemology and an engagement with the implications of prejudice, incredulity,
stereotypes, situated knowledge, and ethical-epistemological issues of trust, testimony,
and social conditions for establishing the status of a credible knower. Epistemic injustice,
in her view, has two principal modalities: testimonial and hermeneutical, each of which is
a source of harm to subjects as knowers or as knowable. Contending that testimonial
injustice necessarily
33
involves prejudice with the central case involving identity prejudice (2007: 41), Fricker
suggests that when the driving prejudicial stereotype involves the idea that the social
type in question is humanly lesser [a woman, a black, a member of a marginalized class
or group], the dimension of degradation qua human being is not simply symbolic; rather
it is a literal part of the core epistemic insult (2007: 445). She concludes: Testimonial
injustice denies one access to what originally furnishes status as a knower. . . [it] can
carry a symbolic weight to the effect that the speaker is less than a full epistemic subject
(2007: 145), incapable, then, of offering the tacit assurance Moran describes, that renders
a testifier appropriately believable as a person.8
Hermeneutical injustice is similar to and different from testimonial injustice. It is, I
suggest, also operative in the Williams example. It centres on the claim that relations of
power can constrain women's [and members of other marginalized social groups'] ability
to understand their own experience (Fricker 2007: 147). (Williams's testimonial
evidence suggests that she understands her own experience well, but is hermeneutically
blocked in attempting to persuade her interlocutors of the veracity of her understanding.
Hermeneutical injustice functions variously at different social layers.) For Fricker,
testimonial and hermeneutical modalities of epistemic injustice have an identity
constructive power in common, but they are structurally distinct in that testimonial
injustice is inflicted individual to individual, while hermeneutical injustice is not
inflicted by any agent, but . . . is caused by a feature of the collective hermeneutical
resource (Fricker 2007: 168). It draws on socially embedded interpretations and
understandings which are differentially available across relations of power and privilege.
Thus Fricker maintains:
relations of unequal power can skew shared hermeneutical resources so that the powerful
tend to have appropriate understandings of their experience ready to draw on as they
make sense of their social experiences, whereas the powerless are more likely to find
themselves having some social experiences through a glass darkly, with at best ill-fitting
meanings to draw on in the effort to render them intelligible. (Fricker 2007: 148)
As Williams's story shows, power and powerlessness are fluctuating signifiers: as a
relatively powerful member of her profession, Williams can make sense of her social
experiences; but in certain public situations and venues she is relegated all over again to
the powerlessness of her black American history.
According to Fricker, a collective social imagination functions as a repository for
stereotypes, some benign or neutral, others unequivocally malign, and many of which
shape our credibility judgements by stealth (2007: 389), unknowingly. Thus,
hermeneutical injustice can be systematic or incidental, but either way it inflicts harm to a
person's or a group's very sense of self. While agreeing with her in the main, I find
greater explanatory resources in the idea of a social imaginary to which I alluded earlier:
a conceptual-analytic resource analogous but not identical
34
to the social imagination. As it is enlisted by Cornelius Castoriadis, to whom I am
indebted, a social imaginary refers to implicit but effective systems of images, meanings,
metaphors, and interlocking explanations-expectations woven through a social-political
order, within which people in specific time periods and cultural-geographical situations
enact their knowledge and subjectivities, and craft their self-understandings.9 An
instituted imaginary carries the normative social meanings, customs, expectations,
assumptions, values, prohibitions, and permissionsthe habitus and ethosinto which
people are nurtured from childhood, which they affirm, challenge, internalize, or reject as
they make sense of their place, responsibilities, and options, within a social and physical
world whose nature and meaning are also instituted in these imaginary significations.
By contrast, an instituting imaginary is a locus of social critique and change: it refers to
the critical-creative activities of a society recognizing that it is incongruous with itself,
with scant reason for self-satisfaction, exhibiting its autonomy in exercising its capacity
to put itself in question. Imaginatively initiated counter-possibilities interrogate the social
structure to destabilize its pretensions to naturalness and wholeness, to initiate a new
making. In my view, a social imaginary carries greater explanatory and revisionary power
than the social imagination: it is more thoroughly systemic in a quasi-Foucauldian sense,
more explicitly power-infused and politically oriented, less presumptively cerebral, and
less conceptually contained than the idea of the social imagination. Where Fricker holds
ethics and politics apart, I think of them as co-constitutive in ways that the social
imaginary captures.
2. ECOLOGICAL THINKING
Diverse moves toward naturalizing epistemology that originate with W. V. O Quine
(1969b, 1994) have prepared the ground for the position I articulate in Ecological
Thinking10 where I am indebted to and critical of Quinean naturalism. In a pathbreaking
departure from the reductive abstraction and formal analysis that have held orthodox
Anglo-American epistemology aloof from the very knowledge it aims to explicate,
naturalized epistemology shifts the focus on to questions about the nature and scope of
real knowing. Constrained neither to analysing what ideal knowers ought to do nor to
silencing the sceptic, naturalists assume knowledge is possible and seek to explicate and
evaluate its real-world (natural) conditions. Hence some feminist and other postcolonial
theorists, and I among them, disenchanted with orthodox epistemology's incapacity to
engage with situated knowledges11 in the epistemologically and socially-politically
pertinent dimensions of their situatedness, have made common cause with them.
35
Many of these philosophers see social epistemology as a version of naturalized
epistemology, which aims to investigate the constitutive part specific social
circumstances play in the production and evaluation of knowledge: to examine how they
influence or even determine who can participate in epistemic projects and who can claim
a hearingcan expect acknowledgementin testimonial exchanges. Social
epistemologists investigate the structures and implications of the political, economic, and
social settings where enquiry is conducted, engaging critically with the ideological
commitments and the availability of models and narrative forms in the instituted
imaginary that shape and influence the structure and content of observation and enquiry.
They examine the socially conferred authority of diverse modes of investigation and
styles of reasoning and the patterns of scepticism and silencing that govern knowledge
construction. Analogously, and often practised as both socialized and naturalized,
feminist epistemology examines the effects of socially produced gender norms and
gender-specific interests and experiences in the production of knowledge.12 Such
investigations are continuous with inquiries into the effects of socially constructed ways
of knowing or ignoring race, class, ethnicity, and other Otherings from the neutral,
faceless, and unidentified knower who occupies the S place in standard epistemology. As
I argue in Ecological Thinking, they encompass investigations of the effects of place, of
situation, for the production and circulation of knowledge. Many such projects work with
elaborated case studies and proceed by analogical argument from case to case,
contending that standard attenuated one-liner examples are too limited in their
explanatory capacity to yield socially responsible knowledge and understanding.
Ecological thinking works across a range of subject matters and disciplinary territories,
often acting as a scavenger in its quest for viable epistemic resources. It requires knowing
the detail of place, population, politics, and particularity as enabling or constraining
factors in knowledge-gathering projects. It emerges from and addresses multiple
interwoven, sometimes contradictory social-epistemological positioningsfeminist,
postcolonial, racist, classist, environmental, sexistwith the result that its detail and
implications require multifaceted chartings. Yet ecological thinking is not just about
ecology or about the environment. It generates a revisioned engagement with
knowledge, subjectivity, politics, ethics, science, citizenship, and agency that pervades
and reconfigures theory and practice in multiple, intersecting projects. It does not reduce
to a set of rules or methods; it may play out differently from location to location; but its
operative principles are sufficiently clear, and it is sufficiently coherent to be interpreted,
enacted, and evaluated across widely diverse situations. It engages with events and
situations across the human and other-than-human world, in projects where the dividing
line between the (usually quantitative) Naturwissenschaften (natural sciences) and the
(commonly
36
interpretive) Geisteswissenschaften (human sciences) blurs, and epistemic and ethical-
political matters are reciprocally informative. In such projects, justification is more often
pragmatic than deductive-nomological, although not opportunistically so, and governing
principles are akin to those that govern virtue epistemology and ethics, enacted in media
res and by example, rather than on normative a priori principles. Hence, the evaluative
structure it yields is something of a hybrid.
Within this conceptual frame, I am interested in how doing epistemic justice to people
silenced, ignored, or subjugated by received conceptions of knowledge, and to
circumstances and places that fall outside the purview of what is readily knowable in
spectator epistemologies, is complicated by incredulity, ignorance, and mistrust. Often, a
curious politics of unknowing silently contributes to how people recognize and respond to
difference: to judgements about whose knowledge matters or deserves a hearing, whose
putative knowledge warrants or fails to claim acknowledgement, in intransigent social
structures of scepticism and disbelief. It produces an epistemic inertia, a resistance to
looking beyond the instituted imaginings that hold received views in place and to taking
responsibility for their persistence. The Williams example is pertinent in this regard.
Although I call my position ecological naturalism. and situate it in the vicinity of Quine's
epistemology naturalized and its successors, I resist Quineans' adherence to a scientistic
model of knowledge and the unnaturalness of their conceptions of the natural, rather
as I resist the a-social conceptions of the social operative in Moran's and Welbourne's
analyses.13 Quinean naturalism is inhospitable to the social-political critique of
institutions of knowledge production and knowledge-producing practices which is
integral, in my view, to the very idea of social epistemology, and which figures centrally
in ecological thinking. Indebted methodologically and ideologically to the science of
ecology, environmentalism, and the ethical-political impetus that inspired the new social
movements in the second half of the twentieth century, ecological naturalism offers more
natural analyses of human epistemic practices and their products than formal
epistemology or Quinean naturalism can offer. Taking as given that human beings are
naturally, necessarily social beings, it proposes richer, less reductive possibilities for
socially responsible, transformative epistemology than are available in theories of
knowledge modelled on an idealized scientific method.
Eschewing the residual positivism whose traces linger in Quinean naturalism, for which
interchangeable observers leave their subjectivity and agency, interests and enthusiasms,
actions and interactions, prejudices and hopes outside the laboratory door, to isolate their
disinterested epistemic practices from what Bruno Latour (2004) aptly calls matters of
concern,14 ecological naturalism
37
looks to the new (contrasted with physics, chemistry, geology, astronomy) science of
ecology. It is politically engaged, accountable for the knowledge it produces, often
explicitly and unabashedly conducting its enquiries in the service of values,
commitments, agendas, and political programmes that have themselves to be kept open to
critical, deliberative evaluation. Its appeals to case studies where knowers are, by
definition, precisely situated as active participants in producing and testing knowledge
claims makes it implausible to imagine them isolated from the knowledge they produce,
even when they appeal to laboratory-derived and other forms of empirical/experimental
evidence for pieces of it. In these and other respects, ecological thinking is continuous
with and makes common cause with feminist theories of strong objectivity15 and situated
knowledges.
Rachel Carson's epistemic practice is exemplary for ecological thinking. Her method of
working back and forth from field studies to scientific analyses, experiments, and
explanations, to specifically located experiential (testimonial) evidence, and local (or
larger) histories of the sites and species she studies shows what I mean. The place she
accords to secular testimony is germane to this point. Carson's scientific world was
structured by hierarchical evaluative divisions between fact and anecdote, truth and
narrative, reason and feeling, with the first of each pair claiming a level of credibility and
authority to which the second could not aspire. Yet in her respect for testimonial
experientialevidence of the everyday, down-on-the-ground variety commonly relegated
to the merely anecdotal, epistemologically irrelevant, Carson contests and unsettles such
distinctions (and earns the epithet subversive in so doing).16 Denigrations of testimony
as evidence derive, if curiously, from the (lowly) status of experience in putatively
experience-based epistemologies which accord minimal evidential respect to
individuated, first-person accounts as they contrast with formal experience that is
everyone's and no one's. Its formality protects it from the confusion and bias of
particularity. Patricia Williams's experience, enacted within structures of power and
privilege which valorize some people's testimony and denigrate others' in the name of an
illusory neutrality, exemplifies this pattern, posing vexed questions about how experience
can stand as evidence in an epistemic climate where credibility is unevenly distributed
and testimony (again, contra Moran) is as often discounted because of whose it is as for
its content. The issue translates, with variations, into current feminist, anti-racist, and
other postcolonial theories of knowledge, and into the examples I will now discuss.
In Carson's scientific practice, as in biologist Karen Messing's research into women's
workplace health and in the epidemiological field work of a Canadian IDRC team in
Tanzania,17 local testimony and orthodox scientific enquiry confront one another in ways
that are instructive for understanding the place
38
of testimony in epistemic situations more elaborated, and more public, than one-on-one
exchanges or unidirectional transmissions. In each case, albeit differently in each,
advocacywhich is still more epistemologically suspect than testimonyis integral to
enabling testimonially derived knowledge claims to go through: to achieve
acknowledgement.
In her research into the effects of post-Second World War pesticides, Carson concludes
on the basis of wide-ranging local testimony that citizens often show a keener
understanding of the dangers and inconsistencies of spraying than do the officials who
order it done (Carson 1962: 113). Her investigations of massive insect-control spraying
expose an interplay between precise secular hypotheses and larger empirical-
experimental conclusions. Detailing a near-fanatical public resistance to knowing the
almost unparalleled wildlife destruction (Carson 1962: 92) that the eradication
programmes leave in their wake, Carson poses a question that is not only scientific but
moral . . . [W]hether any civilization can wage relentless war on life without destroying
itself, and without losing the right to be called civilized (1962: 99). In Silent Spring, she
cites scientific-observational evidence and anecdotal evidence. . . from nonexperts
suburbanites and ornithologists upset by the dead and dying birds they found on their
lawns. . . campers poisoned by DDT (Raglon 1997: 206, my italics). (Her conclusions
were based not only on the work of scientists on the cutting edge of their fields but on the
case histories that filled her file cabinets, her biographer notes [Lear 1977: 357].) For
Carson, testimony can set enquiry in motion and function as an ongoing corrective: it
generates precise local hypotheses, confirms or contests interim findings. Moving back
and forth between testimony and science, then, makes her (interim) empirical conclusions
possible. So, in Silent Spring, Carson recommends evaluating some of the major control
programs and learn[ing] from observers familiar with the ways of wildlife, and unbiased
in favor of chemicals, just what has happened in the wake of a rain of poison falling from
the skies (Carson 1962: 86). Presumably, standard epistemology has the capacity to
address routine failures to rely on scientifically uninformed lay testimony, but Carson is
working in a climate where such recognition rarely occurs, and it is with this down-on-
the-ground reluctance that she must contend to achieve credibility for her findings.
Noteworthy is the part testimony plays in enabling Carson to negotiate a hearing for
knowledge claims to which the scientific establishment in post-war United States was
stubbornly resistant. Much of this testimony is indeed anecdotally conveyed by testifiers
for whom the reported incidents (recalling Latour) are both matters of fact and matters of
concern. Carson evidently works from a presumption that the observers who report to her
are believable; that in testifying to the damage, they are offering the assurance of a
guarantor providing her with a characteristic reason to believe, different in kind from
anything provided by [scientific] evidence alone (cf. Moran 2006: 279). The sheer
accumulation of such reports, and their capacity to withstand empirical
39
scrutiny, lends credence to her presumption. But neither her credibility nor that of her
informers goes uncontested: one challenger, who declared she must be a communist, is
quoted as saying: As for insects, isn't it just like a woman to be scared to death of a few
little bugs! As long as we have the H-bomb everything will be OK.18 I cite the remark to
underscore the epistemic insult enacted by (gender) identity prejudice in
discounting/dismissing knowledge claims by discrediting their maker (Fricker 2007: 41),
and to point toward the complexity of epistemic negotiations required to establish the
veracity of testimony that goes against the grain of received opinion, in its substance or in
the persona of the testifier.
As Carson maps the local and wider effects of pesticides, Messing (1998) maps the
physiological effects of workplace conditions in the lives of poultry processors,
waitresses, bank tellers, telephone operators, and others. As Carson relies on scientific-
observational and testimonial anecdotal evidence, so Messing and her colleagues rely on
scientific-observational and experiential evidence culled from interviews with workers,
union members, and other ordinary folk, to investigate how women workers and
scientists can be brought together to make occupational health studies more accurate and
effective in improving working conditions (Messing 1998: xvi). When symptoms are
specific to small groups of workers, they afford insufficient (statistical) certainty either to
establish the reality of suffering, or to support workers' compensation claims. Hence
Messing investigates how minutely individuated complaints play out for specific people
(usually women) in the particularities of workplaces, habitats, governed by an ethos of
profit and efficiency, backed by an epistemology reliant on statistical certainty alone. Her
practice, like Carson's, is as subversive as it is respectful of the norms of scientific
enquiry and in the place it accords to testimony in knowledge production. Messing reads
statistical evidence against the elusiveness of certain symptoms to inclusion under law-
like descriptions, moving between the laboratory and the workplace floor as Carson
moves between the laboratory and the field or the ocean floor. Her work, too, exhibits an
interplay between local hypotheses and empirical generalizations, where analogies traced
and tested move enquiry forward, disanalogies initiate productive rethinking. At issue,
then, is an investigation of the traditional context of discovery, where questions about
how statistical significance is established need to be addressed. Statistics, too, are a
product of social judgement and deliberation: they are not self-announcing.
Frustrated by attempts to convince unions, employers, and workers themselves of the
factuality of correlations between workplace conditions and women's health, Messing
observes a vicious circle in which researchers do not think of looking for an
occupational cause . . . such causes are not demonstrated, so the
40
problems are attributed to women's biological or psychological nature (1998: 19). She
aims to undermine the injustices such stereotype-reliant naturalizing (1998: 25) enacts,
to show that women's workplace health is less about generic female incapacities, more
about standards of fitness based on fixed ideas about equipment, work environments and
attitudes derived from what is typical for men. Thus, she shows how work stations,
tools, and equipment designed for the average man place many women and some men
at a disadvantage, whose effects in pain, stress, and discomfort are rarely acknowledged
except in the language of failing to meet an abstract, one-size-fits-all criterion of fitness.
The politics are complex. Workers who turn to activism to protest their circumstances
meet with suspicions that they will fake symptoms to gain their point . . . even when the
patterns of physiological change are so specific to the toxic effect that the worker would
have to be a specialist . . . to produce them (Messing 1998: 69); a mail sorter reporting
extreme arm, shoulder, and elbow pain loses a compensation claim because an expert
witness quoted from the scientific literature purporting to show that repeated movements
could not produce injury below a specific weight manipulated . . . [and] described his
own laboratory tests, which . . . showed that this type of work was not dangerous'
(Messing 1998: xv). No one examined the sorter's situation (1998: xvi); yet without the
knowledge that only such an examination could provide, the reports claim dubious
validity. Hence Messing asks: how do scientists decide whom and what to study in the
occupational health field? (1998: xv). Adequate answers require attending to the
workers' testimony, with an initial presumption in favour of their believability; analysing
their interactions and situatedness ecologically, from a research stance informed and
vigilant to detect local, if minuscule, epistemic injusticestestimonial injustices
generated by the politics of knowledge (gendered, raced, classed, aged, ableist and other)
and the profit-driven interests that preserve invisibility and insignificance, credulity and
incredulity across populations and occupations.
In my third example, a 1990s IDRC project in Tanzania, local informants had been
ignored and their testimony denied acknowledgement in a climate of pervasive,
stereotype-derived scepticism. An epistemological reversal, initiated by the IDRC, turned
the health system around, moving it from ossified methods of gathering, evaluating, and
circulating knowledge and outmoded administrative practices and distributions of
epistemic power and authority, toward a responsible democratic complex of social-
natural epistemic interactions. Each stage required negotiations with intransigent
bureaucratic administrations and efficiency-driven multinational funding agencies, en
route to repairing lacunae in an intransigent hermeneutical repertoire.19 Here I sketch the
project's epistemic and moral-political trajectory.
41
By the 1990s, Tanzanians had endured a health crisis for most of a generation, even as
HIV/AIDS and recurrent infectious diseases were brutally rearrang[ing] the social
landscape. Nor was new, centrally administered funding the solution, for the problem,
according to the IDRC FIXING HEALTH SYSTEMs report,20 was an entrenched
epidemiological theory, rooted in statistically driven central planning, implemented from
afar. The putative knowledge informing this theory and the epistemic injustices it
produced are instructive. The project unsettled the power of conventional wisdom and its
practitioners in ways that are ecologically responsive to the detail of place and
demography and naturalized in a quintessentially down-on-the-ground fashion. Yet its
success can mask the intricate epistemic negotiations and advocacy without which it
could not have come about. My aim is to make them visible.
The IDRC'S simple recommendation was that monetary investments should be based on
evidence that targeted the local burden of disease . . . in a particular ecosystem:
administering aid from above, without such local understanding, was a principal source
of the crisis. Established epistemic practice in its relentless, quasi-automatic repetition
and rarely contested hegemony, had installed a screen of unknowing and not needing to
know between health care administrators and local practitioners, pathologies, and
places.21 Hence, new approaches to local circumstances, sensitive to their specificity,
were required: understanding the peculiarities and interconnections among diseases, and
learning to hear, interpret, and act upon testimonial evidence from sources commonly
denied authoritative voice under the Western eyes of development agencies and their
centralized bureaucracies. (As Fricker notes, testimonial injustice can be pre-emptive
when potential interlocutors are ignored; their testimony is not solicited. A speaker is
silenced by the identity prejudice that undermines her credibility in advance (Fricker
2007: 130).)
In Tanzania, fixed ways of presuming to know relations of identity and power had
produced a situation where local people could not dissent from distorted understandings
of their experiences and circumstances. In one-size-fits-all aid distribution practices,
funds were paid into a central administrative structure, on the assumption that appropriate
local allocations would follow. But appropriateness meant despatching equal sums of
money and identical packages of drugs to each district, without investigating the
specificity of populations and
42
health issues, which varied markedly across this vast country. A presumption of human
sameness and of the reliability of bureaucratic knowledge generated a reluctance to
engage directly with people who might be thought to know their situations and the
obstacles they faced, yet had no access to the discourse table, no status as knowledgeable
testifiers. All clinics received the same drugs regardless of whether the district's patterns
of disease and death showed those to be the right ones to maintain health and reduce
mortality there. Ignorance of the fit between local causes of mortality and resource
allocations saw non-malarious highland areas receiving a full complement of anti-
malarial drugs more suited to an endemic area. While malaria, responsible for 30 per cent
of life-years lost, was receiving 5 per cent of one district's budget, childhood diseases
such as diarrhoea, pneumonia, and malnutrition, responsible for 28 per cent of deaths,
were receiving 13 per cent, and tuberculosis, at 4 per cent of the burden of disease, 22 per
cent of the funds. People were sick and dying, and health-care workers, unable to offer
appropriate treatment, were demoralized. A sceptic might contest my proposal that a
dysfunctional epistemology is at work in this case with the counter-claim that no
epistemology would sanction such a system. But it is not so easy to gainsay the evidence,
first, that in the Tanzanian situation such an epistemology indeed informed and
sanctioned the operative system; and secondly, that the practical circumstances that
influence how certain misguided knowledge claims acquire public standing are the issue
here, for social epistemology. Logical possibilities have little to do with the case, and
standard epistemology is incapable of addressing it.
The IDRC's simple proposal was to study separate localities in their particularity, to
determine whether epidemiological detail varied sufficiently to discredit a one-size-fits-
all approach. Selecting two contrasting rural districtsRufiji, with a dry, flat interior and
a tidal delta on its coastline, and Morogoro, which is mountainous and lushresearchers
mapped diseases in their regionally specific manifestations. Yet, maintaining an
impressive level of local sensitivity, their aim was not to apply locally achieved
knowledge to other localities, but to work by analogy from district to district, testing
conclusions for their adaptability given the appropriate local statistical inputs (8/14).
The mapping model, described as evidence-based, differs sharply from Evidence-
Based Medicine (EBM) that has generated debate in the United States and elsewhere.
While textbooks praise EBM for eschewing such subjective practices as interpretation
and narrative,22 Tanzania had neither the statistical tools nor the scientistic approach to do
the investigations orthodox EBM requires, nor to perform Random Control Trials
(RCTs). Moreover, even with such assumptions and tools, it is unclear that interpretation-
free analysis could have filled the hermeneutical lacunae, for eighty per cent of
Tanzanian deaths
43
occur at home, and many fail to make their way into official documents or reports.
The epistemological issue is not about correcting isolated factual errors, but determining
how outworn templates could make room for ecosystem-specific evidence and
ecologically responsive practices. The questions are as political and ethical as
epistemological: the power/knowledge inequalities between NGOs and their beneficiaries
reinforced the screen of unknowing I have mentioned, preventing NGO personnel from
seeingindeed, excusing their not-seeingwhat their would-be beneficiaries needed, in
circumstances where their voices were rarely accorded the credibility owed to
presumptively reliable testifiers. Developing a solution required engaging with local
villagers and clinicians as believable informants, in respectful evidence-gathering
negotiations whose deliverances were perhaps less objectively accurate by first-world
standards than statistical analysis is imagined to be, yet were capable of withstanding
epistemic and practical-political scrutiny. The IDRC report confirms, when communities
are directly involved in identifying and solving their own problems . . . [their] members
become a powerful force in programs of social improvement.
As an exercise in naturalized-social epistemology with the respect it accords to
testimony, the IDRC's proposal was ingenious. When a death occurred, trained local
researchers travelled by bicycle, motorcycle, or boat to conduct verbal autopsies with
survivors. Because of the sensitivity required to interview bereaved families well, the
autopsies might take several hours and require repeated visits. Yet their meticulous,
respectful laboriousness is the source of their capacity to avoid or erase epistemic
injustice. Following the autopsies, findings were reviewed by three independent
physicians to produce an epidemiological picture by feeding the conclusions into a
computer according to a standardized international format. The investigators allow that
they rely on fairly accurate guesses such as EBM aims to avoid, yet follow-up analyses
confirm that, in aggregate, verbal autopsies provide a remarkably reliable picture of
disease in the population. Increasingly, such Demographic Surveillance Systems (DSS)
are used in Tanzania and elsewhere, both to compile health information, and to monitor
poverty levels, education, food security, and the environment.
An additional obstacle in this power/knowledge complex was a reliance on stereotypes
embedded in the Western colonial and postcolonial social imaginary, through which
administrators and other outsiders presume to know local populations. Such webs of
belief with their thinly veiled racist-colonialist tenor were informed and shaped by
conventional (outsider) wisdom for which death rates in these districts attested to
Tanzanians' stubborn preference for traditional healers over modern health care. The
assumption was reinforced by a claim that even more enlightened Tanzanians who seek
modern care for malaria associate convulsions of late-stage malarial feverdegedege
with evil spirits or changes in the weather. Hence, administrators had concentrated on
44
undermining local faith in traditional care, thereby compounding a virulent mix of
epistemic injustice enacted in observing the population from a distance as spectator
epistemologies do, drawing conclusions from actions arbitrarily selected to confirm a
prejudice-infused hypothesis kept alive by a colonial history of attributing naive
innocence to putatively pre-scientific people. It combines with the pre-emptive
hermeneutical injustice enacted in failing to work with or listen to indigenous people as
reliable informants.
The Demographic Surveillance System presents a different view. Testimonial evidence
shows Tanzanians who sought modern health care greatly outnumbering those who do
not. It vindicates the scepticism many researchers had voiced about reliance solely on
clinical attendance and government-compiled cause of death statistics as the knowledge-
base of health planning. When local informants testify to problems of access to health
care facilities and delayed responses to requests for treatment, or to the sheer inability of
modern facilities to prevent some patients from dying, the emphasis shifts to
understanding local circumstances and practices in and where they are and providing
accessible care, responsive to local specificity.
3. TESTIMONY, ADVOCACY, IGNORANCE
These examples highlight issues that acquire centrality once epistemology re-engages
with the complexities of the world. Moreover, in each, if differently, advocacy of some
kind counts among the conditions that enable knowledge claims to go through; and in
each, patterns of ignorance tacitly preserve an entrenched and silently operative social
imaginary, to generate a certain inertia in the face of imperatives to know better. In this
section I address some of these issues as they pertain to these examples and to testimony
and epistemic in/justice more generally.
In Ecological Thinking (2006) I propose that practices of advocacy often make knowledge
possible in hierarchical distributions of epistemic autonomy and authority and
institutional divisions of intellectual labour, in Western societies.23 The claim is
contentious, for advocacy is a tainted practice for epistemologists: it recalls Plato's
quarrel with the Sophists, and is one which positivists and their heirs were committed to
suppressing. Connotations derived from legal argumentation, where an advocate argues
someone's or some group's cause with the aim of winning the case represent advocacy as
a practice which sacrifices truth, factuality, to achieving that goal. Such contentions are
often justified: they prevail in the public and the philosophical imagination. But in the
extended meanings and modalities that inform my argument, advocacy moves into
epistemic lives and situations where it has to do with enlisting accredited expertise,
adducing
45
evidence to support silenced or discounted ways of understanding experiences and
phenomena.24 It contributes to knowing a cause, a policy, a point of view well; and often
to speaking on behalf of, supporting, a project or policy; to representing someone/some
group so as to counter silencing, incredulity, and other egregious epistemic, personal, and
social harms. It may be enacted in individual and communal practices: someone may
advocate on her/his own behalf or on behalf of (an)other person(s); advocate for or
against the significance, validity, credibility of someone's testimony, or of the testimony
of a group, an institution, or society. In this last range of practices, advocacy carries
epistemological force in the power and privilege structures of hierarchical societies,
where it can become a liberatory practice whose goal is to establish the credibility of, and
hence to (re)enfranchise epistemically marginalized Others.
Although advocacy often succeeds in opening epistemic space for the disenfranchised to
achieve a hearing and for challenging the limits of entrenched epistemologies of mastery,
advocacy advocates must be ever mindful of its perils: of its liability to the perversions
of interest group prejudices, coercive paternalism, manipulation and appropriation
(borrowing Peta Bowden's words),25 and of how its reliance on trust makes of it a fragile
process whose participants are peculiarly vulnerable (cf. 2006: 176ff). I retain my brief
for advocacy while acknowledging the seriousness of these charges, mainly because the
implied contrast is implausiblebetween epistemic projects where risk and vulnerability
do not figure because knowledge claims readily go through, leaving their claimants
untouched by the knowing, and advocacy practices where they are risky ventures.
Advocacy on both sidesfor the advocate or the advocated-forrequires ongoing
strategic scepticism, wariness;26 but the same is true, if differently, of most knowledge
producing practices beyond the abstract, formal structures of S knows that p; and
especially of those involving Latour's matters of concern.
Advocacy is vital to the (often partial) knowledge that issues from the epistemic
negotiations I have discussed. Patricia Williams had to advocate, not altogether
successfully or without risk, for her testimony to reach the public eye, to be evaluated
there. Rachel Carson's tireless efforts in advocating for recognition of, and action in
response to, local testimony about damage enacted by indiscriminate use of pesticides
were both successful in placing new knowledge before the public eye, and personally
damaging. Karen Messing's advocacy for the truth of women's workplace testimony,
and the IDRC's for the validity of local testimony, with the practical actions they went on
to inform, further support my claim in its strongest sense: practices of advocacy often
make knowledge possible. In short, without persistent advocacy, Williams might have
failed to make her experience
46
known; without persistent advocacy in writing, and in the public political forum, Carson
would not have achieved the acknowledgement (in Wittgenstein's sense) from the
Kennedy government that resulted in a ban on pesticides; Messing would not have
convinced public granting bodies to recognize the factual import of workers' statistically
insignificant testimonial reports; and the IDRC would not have succeeded in bringing
local Tanzanians to testify at the discourse table.
Advocacy practices, thenrepresenting, arguing for, recommending, acting or
engaging in projects of enquiry and intervention with, in support of, or on behalf of some
one or some groupanimate an instituting social imaginary capable of unsettling the
inertia of an entrenched imaginary, thence promoting social conditions of co-habitability
in the best sense, upheld by networks of responsible epistemic practice. Yet the risks are
real: advocacy plays into a politics of knowledge where advocacy research is a
derogatory label for research undertaken to serve special, contrasted with universal
(read: dominant), interests; and credibility is unevenly conferred or withheld in patterns
of epistemic injustice consequent upon discounting the experiences of some would-be
knowers, granting or refusing to grant their testimony a hearing, facilitating or blocking
their participation in communal epistemic practices. Claiming that advocacy can make
knowledge possible contests a false autonomy/advocacy dichotomy for which self-reliant
individual knowledge yields the only possible certainty, while advocacy inevitably
compromises that possibility and destabilizes the putative knowledge. Like any social-
epistemological project, advocacy requires ongoing vigilance, negotiation, openness to
the need for corroboration, contestation, revision. It maintains a certain fallibilism in
epistemic practice, yet it need not pervert the fundamental commitments of responsible
knowledge-seeking. Advocacy is a vexed and vexing process for epistemologies of
mastery with their adherence to the individualism of autonomous man and its attendant
image of monologic knowledge claims, uttered into a void. With social epistemology's
repudiation of individualism in favour of collaborative, interactive, deliberative knowing,
it is less fraught: it manifests openness to the counter-sentence, to negotiative processes
of listening and responding; to empirical-experiential testing and retesting for
confirmation or falsification. There are multiple modalities of advocacy, but charges
levelled against it tend, misguidedly, to generalize from places where its imagined
proximity to the worst rhetorical excesses expands to encompass all such practices.
Advocacy names practices such as those evoked in Marilyn Frye's phrase hearing each
other into speech (Frye 1996: 38). In such hearingwhich need not be unidirectional
these practices can inform collective action intended to further certain causes, contest
patterns of silencing, intervene in intransigent social orders on behalf of or in concert
with the disenfranchised, lend someone'sor some group'sexpertise and sometime
privilege to others less well positioned to know. None of these thoughts will undo
advocacy's negative implications or its dangers; but politically, these risks may have to be
faced. Thus Karen Messing
47
advocates for workers so disenfranchised by material-institutional structures that they
need help in speaking for themselves: advocacy whose credibility derives in part from
her credentials and social-professional positioning, yet is true to the specificities of their
situations, and available for acknowledgement or challenge from those prepared to hear
and qualified to advise. Carson advocates to President Kennedy's Science Advisory
Committee (PSAC) for knowledge about pesticides she has gained in field and laboratory
research, and from lay testimony.27 Hers was a long, bitter negotiation with and against
detractors whose vested interests were at risk, and the negotiations continue after her
death;28 but such will be true of many advocacy-driven and other such negotiations. In
short, contra Welbourne and Moran, giving and receiving testimony, privately (in one-
on-one exchanges) or publicly, is complicated by differences in privilege, credibility, and
understanding. Giving and receiving testimony is rarely a discrete event: it requires
negotiating differences in privilege and complexities, in the participants' ability to
communicate across differences of power, privilege, and articulateness. Messing's
enquiries, and those adduced by the IDRC are cases in point.
In its responsible modalities, advocacy strives to get at truths operating below the surface
of the presumed self-transparency of evidence. Al Gore's inconvenient truth is an apt, if
controversial, example.29 His is unashamedly an advocacy project, urging people to face
truths that are inconvenient because of the losses actively acknowledging them entails.
They demand radical life changes in the affluent Western/northern world with their
taken-for-granted materialities and the sense of entitlement that sustains them. It is easier
not to know. Precisely because of their social-political inconvenience, such truths
require sustained advocacy if they are effectively to infiltrate the social imaginary where
rhetorically fuelled counter-advocacy is actively devising strategies to gainsay them. Like
Carson, Gore has not had the last word: the controversy goes on. But his critics speak and
argue in a space he has made available. At their best, advocacy practices claim discursive
space for subjugated knowledges, putting them into circulation to negotiate
acknowledgement; working to promote informed, emancipatory moral-political-
ecological effects.30 At their worst, they can do untold damage.
In these examples, ignorance maintained and sustained is a powerful force of resistance
to testimonial knowledge going through. In each, there is much at stake for those
required to relinquish the ignorance on which their intransigence, variously, relies. Yet as
participants in the newly named agnotology discussions show,31 ignorance is more than
a simple lack of knowledge: it is a multifaceted social-political phenomenon produced or
sustained in ways that parallel but
48
do not replicate the production of knowledge: it is negotiated and held in place by
advocacy. Its power may be consequent upon a certain stasis: a resistance within a
community or group or a firmly instituted imaginary to entertain new epistemic
possibilities; a vested interest in maintaining a condition of not-knowing or pervasive
uncertainty about a particular subject matter; a paternalistic protectiveness against certain
truths entering public knowledge or the knowledge of particular segments of the
population. Ignorance thus sustained can perpetuate epistemic injustice, both testimonial
and hermeneutic, in the interests of sustaining a hierarchical social order. The politics of
unknowing manifests in the making and unmaking of ignorance.
In Patricia Williams's negotiations with the law review, principles of neutrality
entrenched within the going epistemic imaginary blocked possibilities of knowing the
salient specificitiesthe racial dimensionsof her situation. Moreover, presumed
neutrality protected the racially unmarked from confronting their ignorance about living
the differences racial difference makes, or acknowledging it in any but a blandly liberal
register for which we, whoever we are, are all alike beneath such allegedly insignificant
differences as skin colour, gender, race, ethnicity, disability, and other such
hermeneutical and testimonial injustice-fuelling specificities.32 Given the constitutive part
assumptions of universal human sameness play in the received epistemologies and moral-
political theories of Anglo-American philosophy, it is apparent that change can be
effected and multiple modalities of ignorance dislodged only at the level of the instituted
social imaginary. These are no individual, punctiform errors in perception, interpretation,
or judgement to be corrected with a simple dose of counter-evidence.
Forces of carefully preserved ignorance are at work in the epistemic climate where
Carson, Messing, and the IDRC workers sought acknowledgement for their findings. An
advisor warned Carson: Facts will not stand in the way of some confirmed pest control
workers and those who are receiving substantial subsidies from pesticides
manufacturers;33 Messing faced entrenched stereotypes of women's nature, invoked to
condone a systemic ignorance of the specificities of their situations which would have
required action, at some cost, by employers; the IDRC faced aid-distribution policies
based in sustained ignorance of local epidemiological facts, derived from policies not
tested in their ecosystem specificity. Curiously, in the light of resistance to advocacy,
received theory and practice are sustained and safe-guarded by persistent advocacy
against according acknowledgement to the local testimony that ultimately made
knowledgeable responses possible in each of these examples. I mention these issues not
to level a
49
facile tu quoque counter-argument against advocacy detractors, but to reinforce my
contention that, in social epistemology the autonomy/advocacy dichotomy is less readily
tenable than it has been in the rhetorical spaces where advocacy research is denigrated
for its alleged commitment to serving special interests, and is contrasted with
impersonal, universal truth-seeking enquiry which, too often, silently beneath its claims
to neutrality winds up serving dominant interests, after all. The epistemic injustices it
perpetuates would be impossible to catalogue.
50
3 Scepticism and the Genealogy of Knowledge: Situating Epistemology in
Time
Miranda Fricker
1. DIMENSIONS OF SOCIALIZATION
We tend to think of the socialness of social epistemology largely in terms of a lateral
expansion across social space. The expansion shifts the philosophical focus from the lone
individual of so much traditional epistemologythe individual who wonders whether he
really knows this is his hand before him, and so onto his relations with his fellow
subjects, his epistemic interactions with them, even his epistemic interdependence with
them. The interest in epistemic interdependence brings divisions of epistemic labour
centre-stage (as the explosion in the literature on testimony in recent years bears witness)
and further establishes a recognized theoretical space for insights about how justification
(for instance, justification for a scientific theory) might be dispersed across a whole
epistemic community, with the consequence that it makes sense sometimes to regard that
whole community as the subject of the knowledge, and perhaps no individual at all.1 This
kind of socialization of epistemology, then, brings with it a new, less individualistic
conception of epistemic subjects. No longer conceived as lone individuals whose
interactions with other individuals are epistemically incidental, we think of them as
fundamentally, naturally, placed in relations of epistemic interdependence. Let us call this
socialized conception of epistemic subjects, the Abstracted Social Conception. It marks
the anti-individualist moment in epistemology.
The conception is so labelled because it remains highly abstractedappropriately for
certain purposes. The social relations in which epistemic subjects are conceived as
standing are relations between finite knowers and enquirers conceived as bearers of
reasons, producers of evidence, seekers of information, conveyors of knowledge, and so
on. But these knowers and enquirers are
51
happens, it becomes part and parcel of the scientific enquirer's requisite epistemic
virtuespossessed either by individuals or possibly only by the communityto reliably
succeed in spotting research decisions that are too much driven by professional or
institutional power. When social epistemologists talk of experts and laypersons, then,
they are already flirting with a more fully socialized conception of epistemic subjects
than the Abstracted Social Conception itself allows for.
If we want epistemology to account for the human epistemic predicament, then we need
to have available a conception of epistemic subjects as required to overcome or negotiate
certain entanglements of reason and power, because it is an essential feature of human
enquirers that they operate in a context in which such entanglements can arise. This is the
source of the value of the Situated Social Conception, which conceives epistemic subjects
and their interactions as situated in a context of social identity and power, and so makes
visible the influence of these factors on our epistemic interactions. For any given project
in social epistemology, then, we need to be reflective about which conception suits our
philosophical purposesreflective, that is, about which degree of abstraction is
appropriate for the issues we want to bring out. Simply sticking to the standard
Abstracted Social Conception may occlude ethical and political aspects of epistemic
practice that are worth our attention; then again, sustaining a Situated Social Conception
will be pointless if relations of identity and power are irrelevant to the issue we are
pursuing. It's a judgement about horses for courses, so, as a matter of good philosophical
method, we need to have the different options reflectively available to the philosophical
imagination. The picture of epistemic subjects presented by the Situated Social
Conception is less abstract than that presented in the Abstracted Social Conception, but it
is still an abstraction, as befits the philosophical purpose. It represents epistemic subjects
not in their personal detailobviously notbut as variously instantiating one or another
more or less complex social type. If the Abstracted Social Conception marks the moment
of rebellion against excessive individualism in epistemology, the availability of the
Situated Social Conception marks our graduation beyond the naivety of compulsory
rational idealization.
I have argued elsewhere for the importance of the Situated Social Conception for certain
philosophical purposes, and in particular I have argued that there are issues of justice and
injustice in our everyday epistemic interactionsour testimonial interactions and our
practices of social interpretationwhich cannot come to light unless we adopt that more
fully socialized conception.3 For present purposes, however, the Abstracted Social
Conception is appropriate, as my aim is to show how expanding not only across social
space but also across time can be a powerful epistemological resource. We should
distinguish between two sorts of temporal expansion: expansion across real time
(including historical time), and
53
expansion across the quasi-fictional time that is at work in genealogical method. I shall
make a case for the philosophical fruitfulness of expanding over genealogical time, and
my specific aim will be to show how the genealogical method can support and augment
certain socializing arguments against scepticism. The genealogical story I shall use is that
given by Edward Craig (1990) in his book, Knowledge and The State of Nature (hence
the appropriateness here of the Abstracted Social Conception, for in so far as there are
any social types in the State of Nature, their social identities do not figure in the
explanatory purpose that this particular genealogy aims to achieve).
I shall make my case by reference to Michael Williams's diagnostic engagement with
scepticism, in which he crucially employs a Default and Challenge model of justification.
And I will develop three key aspects of Craig's practical explication of the concept of
knowledge so that they may be seen to resonate positively with Williams's
epistemological picture: the admixture of internalist and externalist features (3.1); the
proto-contextualism (3.2); and, finally, the distinctively genealogical anti-sceptical
impetus (3.3). In this way I aim to support and augment the socialized anti-sceptical case
mounted by Williams. I also aim thereby to illustrate the philosophical productiveness of
expanding epistemology not only laterally across the social space of other epistemic
subjects, but at the same time vertically in the temporal dimension.
2. DEFAULT AND CHALLENGE: SOCIALIZING JUSTIFICATION
In Responsibility and Reliability4 Michael Williams (2008) explores the anti-sceptical
impetus of a certain model of justification that is found in Robert Brandom's work under
the name of Default and Challenge. It is an entitlement conception of justification,
according to which we may assume our faculties are functioning correctly so long as
there are no reasons to suspect otherwise. Williams's paper has two aims. Firstly, he aims
to incorporate reliabilist insights within a fundamentally deontological framework, where
the key reliabilist insight he has in mind is that many accounts of knowledge incorporate
exaggerated, over-intellectualized conceptions of what it takes to be epistemically
responsible, which simply do not square with the spontaneous and unreflective character
of our most basic forms of knowledge, notably, perception. If there is to be a satisfactory
responsibilism that presents a unified account of knowledge, it will have to avoid such
intellectualism. And, secondly, he wants to show how such
54
a responsibilism can, by the same token, deflect scepticism. The problems of
intellectualism and sceptical challenge, he argues, have a common solution, for one and
the same excessively internalist, mentalistic conception of justification is their common
root.
Williams traces a dominant internalist conception of justification back to Chisholm, and
the model he finds in Chisholm's writing is one in which justification constitutes a kind of
positive authorization which, in Chisholm, is linked to a foundationalist structure with
error-proof sensory experiences at the bottom, so that the whole structure is designed in
the foundationalist style to stave off sceptical challenge. Looking to Sellars's critical
analysis of this sort of view and its dependence on notions of the Given, Williams argues
that the positive authorization conception seriously exaggerates what is needed to
vindicate the idea that epistemic subjects achieve justification by acting in the light of
epistemic rules, as opposed to merely conforming to them. We can achieve a picture of
subjects acting in the light of normative rules, without being compelled to add that rules
should be construed as imperatival in form, or that justification flows upwards in the
system from a foundation of error-proof self-addressed reports' of experience. Williams
continues in the Sellarsian idiom by taking up a distinction Sellars makes between
ought-to-do rules, which are imperatival in form, and ought-to-be rules, which are not.
These so called ought-to-be rules effectively set conditions of entitlement in the Default
and Challenge mould. In Williams's example:
For me to see, and not merely think that I see, that there is a rabbit in the garden, all sorts
of conditions must be met. Some concern me: I must be of sound mind, paying attention,
capable of recognizing what is going on, and so forth. Others concern the object and its
situation: the animal has to be a rabbit and not a stuffed toy, the light must be good
enough to make out the shape of the dark patch in the middle of the lawn, and so on. If
these conditions are not met, I won't be in a position to see that there is a rabbit in the
garden. (Williams 2008: 1213)
What Default and Challenge achieves for us is the desired admixture of internalist and
externalist insights. In order to count as acting in the light of a rule (in order to count as
epistemically justified) the well-trained subject might, depending on the context, need
only to be counterfactually sensitive to lapses in the conditions required for taking the
deliverances of her faculties for granted. As Williams puts it, Our acceptance of an
ought-to-be rule consists principally in our disposition to acknowledge the exceptions,
and to respond appropriately (2008: 21). In sum, the well-trained subject may take her
sensory experiences at face value, so long as there are no reasons not to. In doing this she
is following rules of justification, acting in the light of them but not self-consciously.
Thus the externalist aspect of Default and Challenge that sets it apart from any positive
authorization model. Yet if appropriately challenged, she does have a standing
obligation to produce a justification, and if she cannot, then she is revealed as
55
5
lacking entitlement to her belief. Thus the internalist aspect of Default and Challenge
that qualifies Williams's position as a form of responsibilism.
Williams also argues that seeing justification as conforming to a Default and Challenge
structure can help fend off scepticism. He invokes the distinction between Agrippan and
Cartesian forms of sceptical challenge. Agrippan scepticism imposes an endless demand
for further justifications, so that it threatens to expose either regress or circularity in the
series of justifications we may offer, or else a plainly unjustified assumption somewhere
in our reasoning. Cartesian scepticism is characterized as exploiting issues of
underdetermination by positing sceptical scenarios which he claims, for all we know, we
might be in.6 Williams's focus, however, is on the Agrippan style sceptic, and he argues
that the Agrippan is implicitly committed to the familiar, mentalistic and so excessively
internalist model of justification that conceives being guided by norms or rules as always
a matter of self-conscious obedience to self-addressed imperativespositive
authorization. What the Default and Challenge model furnishes is an account of
justificationentitlementthat makes no such requirement. By contrast, what Default
and Challenge obliges the individual subject to do is something negative: don't take your
experiences at face value if the default condition is lapsed. A subject who is entirely
successful with respect to that negative task may well not be able to answer the Agrippan
scepticbut so much the worse for the sceptic. The standing obligation to come up with
reasons when challenged only holds for challenges to which one's interlocutor is entitled.
Brandom, introducing the label Default and Challenge, puts the point like this:
Claims such as There have been black dogs' and I have ten fingers' are ones to which
interlocutors are treated as prima facie entitled. They are not immune to doubt in the form
of questions about entitlement, but such questions themselves stand in need of some sort
of warrant or justification. Entitlement is, to begin with, a social status that a performance
or commitment has within a community. . . The model presented here has what might be
called a default and challenge structure of entitlement.
(Brandom 1994: 177)
The Agrippan sceptic, then, is presenting inappropriate challenges, and so our failure to
meet those challenges signifies nothing. The sceptic is thus revealed as missing the point,
for she tries to compel the individual subject to dig deeper and deeper into his individual
epistemic resources, furnishing reason upon reason for his beliefbut this is simply the
wrong place to look for his status as justified in
56
believing what he believes. The Agrippan demands to be shown a justificational stopping
point somewhere in the depths of the individual subject, and her mistake is that
justification is not to be found deep in the individual but rather on the surface of
something irreducibly social, namely, the subject's ability to meet the challenges properly
brought in that context by others in the epistemic community.
Williams focuses on the mentalistic nature and extreme internalism of the model of
justification that both polarizes reliabilism and responsibilism and hands the sceptic a
stick to beat us with. But I think we should most of all emphasize its individualism, for it
is the individualism that underpins both the mentalistic and the excessively internalist
character of the mistaken model of justification that Williams rightly diagnoses in the
sceptic. Given a general assumption of epistemic individualism, one easily sees how it
can seem natural to assume that the individual is the source of all justification for her
belief, and that the place to look is (where else?) in her mental states. Thus the
mentalism. Further, if even the subject herself cannot find a justification in her
psychology, then how can she count as possessing a justification at all? Thus the extreme
internalism. I think, then, that once we focus on the anti-sceptical energy that Default and
Challenge clearly contains, we find that energy to be derived most fundamentally from its
sociality (and so, to relate back to the terminology I introduced earlier, from its implicit
insistence on the Abstracted Social Conception of epistemic subjects). For it is the
sociality that effects the crucial shift in rational obligation away from the lone individual
and into the epistemic social body as a member of which the individual subject must
function. It is of course individuals who bear the responsibility of justification for their
beliefs, but the point is they can only live up to this responsibility in virtue of their
participation in a social practice of proper challenge. (I alone bear the responsibility for
paying my bills; but the question of what I owe is settled as a matter of social practice.) It
is this social dispersal of justificatory labour that relieves the individual believer of the
burden of accessing the kind of justification that the Agrippan sceptic demands.
The Agrippan, who presses and presses for ever more justifications, is thus revealed as
making a profound mistake at both the level of epistemic practice and the level of
epistemology. She fails to adhere to socially established norms of challenge, a mistaken
practice that exposes her false theory of justification. But what of the Cartesian sceptic?
Williams thinks the Cartesian, whose signature is of course the sort of madcap sceptical
scenarios we all know and love, cannot be confined in the same way, but only indirectly
by way of showing how we can legitimately set sceptical problems aside (Williams
2008: 26). Why is this? If the context sensitive norms of challenge can reveal Agrippan
challenges as mistaken, then why not Cartesian challenges too? Now that we have
identified the sociality of Default and Challenge as fuelling the anti-sceptical work, is it
not evident that the Cartesian invocation of sceptical scenarios is a style of challenge
every bit as inappropriate as the Agrippan? The Cartesian, too, seems to press
57
his case to the individual knowledge-claimant in a way that is not sanctioned by socially
established norms of Default and Challengethe demand to rule out that one is a brain in
a vat, or whatever it may be, is obviously outrageous. I think this does have some bite as
an argument against the Cartesian. He, no more than the Agrippan, can just assume that
his challenges are appropriateon the face of it they certainly are not.
It remains true, however, that the Cartesian has a card up his sleeve that the Agrippan
lacks, in as much as the Cartesian's challenge plays specifically on the idea of
underdetermination in order to spook us with the possibility that our beliefs are not
justified at all, on the grounds that they are no more justified than the alternative
theories' of the world cooked up in the sceptical scenarios. This means the Cartesian can
be construed as making a challenge not necessarily to the individual knower in any way
that violates the insights of Default and Challenge, but rather as making a higher level
challenge in respect of what we think we achieve by adhering to our precious norms of
appropriate challengenot knowledge, he exclaims, not even justified beliefs!
Admittedly, then, revealing the Cartesian as having an excessively individualistic theory
of justification that should be replaced by Default and Challenge still leaves the spooky
radical sceptical possibility rather as it is, which is why other arguments (against
epistemological realism and for an antidote contextualism) need to be brought in.
Nothing in Default and Challenge, after all, directly addresses issues of
underdetermination; whereas, by contrast, the favourable identification of Default and
Challenge as a rival account of justification reveals the Agrippan as entirely driven by the
mistaken assumption that justification requires an individual capacity to respond to an
indefinite series of challenges, without lapse into regress, assumption, or circularity. Even
while I want to insist that the socializing move inherent in Default and Challenge does
win a trick against the Cartesian sceptic, then, still it is clear that it cannot on its own beat
the Cartesian's hand in the way it beats the Agrippan's.
Accordingly, in respect of the Cartesian challenge, Williams looks to the central anti-
sceptical argument of Unnatural Doubts (1991), namely, the argument that the Cartesian
sceptic is committed to epistemological realism and epistemological realism is false. The
Cartesian sceptic's challenges concern something called knowledge of the external
world or empirical knowledge, as if these were respectable theoretical categories; but
they are not. They are far too internally diverse to be so regarded, and in fact have no
more integrity than a category such as knowledge of things done on a Wednesday.
Crucially, they are too internally diverse in terms of the kind of justification that is
requiredsomething we may express in terms of the Default and Challenge model by
saying that the norms of appropriate challenge vary from context to context. The
Cartesian sceptic may possibly go in for his peculiar style of challenge in the strictly
epistemological context, but not in other contexts. To do so would, as ever, constitute a
mistake at the level of norms of Default and Challenge governing our epistemic practice,
58
but more importantly perhaps, it would be an enactment of the false piece of theory that
is epistemological realism. The Cartesian sceptic wants to move from (i) discovering that,
in context C, knowledge is impossible, to (ii) discovering (in context C) that knowledge
is impossible7 , but if he can only make that move by way of the false doctrine of
epistemological realisma staging post which would effectively privilege the so-called
epistemological context over all othersthen the move is blocked and, qua sceptic, he
is confined to the study. That is, his eccentric style of justificational challenge is confined
to the context of enquiry that is peculiar to a certain style of epistemology.
Thus Williams's fascinating anti-sceptical case. I have so far discussed (and slightly
elaborated) the use he makes of Default and Challenge against scepticism in
Responsibility and Reliability; and I have recalled (as he does) the contextualist
position he first argued for in Unnatural Doubts, where it functions as the antidote to the
sceptic's epistemological realism. My chief purpose here, however, is to make a case for
the expansion of our philosophical conception of epistemic subjects and their activities
along a certain temporal dimension, namely, the genealogical temporal dimension. So
how might a genealogy of knowledge help bolster and augment Williams's anti-sceptical
case?
3. EXPANDING ALONG THE TEMPORAL DIMENSIONGENEALOGICAL TIME
In his Knowledge and The State of Nature Edward Craig gives what I'm calling a
genealogical account of knowledge. That is, he tells a State of Nature story about why we
have the concept of knowledgea practical explication of that concept. He envisages a
minimally social epistemic communityan abstraction of any real human community,
though one that non-accidentally resembles what a real early human community might
have been like in respect of its social simplicity and its hand-to-mouth relation to basic
human needs and dangers. The basic epistemic needs that define the State of Nature are,
first, the need for enough truths (and not too many falsehoods) for other sorts of basic
needsprincipally survival needsto be met. A community that survives in the State of
Nature must operate with sufficient truths to hunt and/or forage for food, take care of the
young, avoid predators, deal with the dead, and so on. That first epistemic need
immediately gives rise to a second: the need to realize the epistemic and practical
advantages of pooling information. Why rely only on one's own eyes and ears when you
can benefit from the eyes and ears of others? From where you're standing you may not be
able to see if the predator is coming, but that person up in the tree might, and this
exemplifies the
59
fundamental practical pressure to stand in cooperative epistemic relations with fellow
enquirers. Finally, this second epistemic need spontaneously gives rise to a third: the
need to distinguish good from bad informants, so that it is indeed information that gets
shared and not misinformation or disinformation. Human beings, however described, are
falliblehence the risk of misinformation. And human beings in the State of Nature, as
anywhere else, operate under pressures (such as competition for resources) that create
motivations for deceptionhence the risk of disinformation. Distinguishing good
informants is indeed an essential capacity.
This trio of fundamental epistemic needs generates a certain point of view for our social
epistemological project: the point of view of the enquirer. This is notably different from
the point of view normally taken up in epistemology, namely that of the examiner; a point
of view typified by the epistemologist's remove from the actual business of enquiry in
order to debate about whether some candidate knower really qualifies.8 The particular
need to distinguish a good informant as to a given question whether p is a need had only
by someone who doesn't know whether p but wants to. Accordingly, as we construct the
epistemic State of Nature, we find that ignorance and the desire to make it good with
good information emerge as our basic epistemic state. In this sense, Who knows whether
p? is our most basic epistemological question, a question that presupposes the possibility
of knowledge. How far this broad anti-sceptical presupposition has any argumentative
force depends upon how convincing the overall story is in terms of its explanatory power.
In so far as the State of Nature construction provides a convincing explanatory story
about why we have, of necessity, the concept of knowledge, then so far may it turn out to
give genuine independent support to the idea that sceptical questions are parasitic on
there being a functional epistemic practice in which knowledge is possessed and, in
particular, shared or commoned9 in an epistemic community. (I shall return to this in
section 3.3.)
So how does Craig's genealogy explain the advent of the concept of knowledge? We have
seen that the enquirer needs to distinguish good informants. A good informant is someone
who: (1) is likely enough in the context to be right about whether p, (2) is
communicatively available and open (including sincere), and (3) bears indicator
properties so that you can reliably recognize that (1) and (2) are satisfied.10 In Craig's
story, indicator properties will be a mixed bag, but might standardly include properties
such as having been looking in the right direction at the time, or having a good track
record.11 Craig's thesis is that the
60
constructed concept of the good informant constitutes the core of our actual concept of a
knower. As we might put it, the status of being a knower starts life as the status of being a
good informant. The two concepts are not coextensive of course: there can be knowers
who are not good informants, for instance because they lack the requisite indicator
properties, or because the indicator properties (being only reliable) unluckily mislead on
that occasion. But Craig's proposal is that the functional origin of the concept of
knowledge is to identify good informants; and that thereafter the constraints of
recognizability and communicative openness gradually become relaxed, as certain more
sophisticated uses we come to make of the concept (such as referring to knowers we
cannot ourselves recognize) pressurize it in the direction of objectificationthat is, of
referring to something that exists independently of our powers of recognition. Such
pressures explain how we come to think of knowledge as something another person can
possess, even if we can't recognize it, or they aren't coming out with it.12
3.1. The Original Synthesis of Internalist and Externalist Insights
According to Craig's genealogy, then, we start to operate with the concept of knowledge,
of necessity, because at the core of that concept is something that meets the absolutely
basic epistemic need to pick out good informants. Now how does all this help the
socializing anti-sceptical case that Williams builds on Default and Challenge? One of the
key anti-sceptical features of Default and Challenge is that it achieves a desirable
combination of internalist and externalist features. I think we can see how this is
explained and so reinforced if we look closely enough at epistemic practices in the State
of Nature. In the first instance, the practice of pooling information in the State of Nature
features people spotting others as good informants before asking them for information.
But we can see how the basic need for good information also drives a modification of that
practice; namely, asking candidate good informants the question to which we want the
answer, and then, once they have responded, quizzing them as to their reasons. The
capacity to give reasons for what one asserts is a supremely important indicator property,
not discussed by Craig. The person who asserts but does not know may be suspiciously
fuzzy on her reasons; the person who asserts what he knows to be false may be
suspiciously
61
unconvincing when he presents purported reasons for his pretend belief. The ability to
satisfy this kind of challenge is a key indicator property of good informants.
Being able to supply a justification when challenged is not, however, a necessary
condition of being a good informant. Rightly not, for what primarily matters to the
enquirer is simply that the good informant comes out with the truth on demand; not that
he comes out with his reasons as well. Given that the enquirer can spot a good informant
to her own satisfaction, she will just take the information and not bother to quiz him
further about his reasons. However, this basic practice established, we can immediately
see how quickly an informant's capacity to give reasons assumes importance, for it is
highly desirable in a good informant that he be able to produce reasons when challenged,
owing to the fact that this may be by far the best indicator property available to the
enquirer. The same point applies individualistically too, for enquirers in the State of
Nature will often be relying on the deliverances of their own faculties, and are best
construed as entitled to trust them unless they have some reason not toa foggy day; a
foggy memory.13 (Here we glimpse the nascent Default and Challenge structure of
justification emerging.) On these occasions, a certain challenge to self is in order, which
amounts to a demand for an after-the-fact indicator property that one is likely enough in
the context to be right about p. The ability to produce a satisfying reason is the prime case
of such an indicator property.
The importance of this capacity to come out with reasons when appropriately challenged,
combined with the fact that it is not one of the conditions of qualifying as a good
informant, explains what underpins the desired admixture of internalist and externalist
features that Williams aims to achieve. The picture in the State of Nature is
fundamentally externalistwhat matters is simply that good informants come out with
the truthbut then we quickly come to see the origin of internalist intuitions about
knowledge. On the story I am urging here, we agree with Craig that the good informant's
capacity to access his reasons is not at the core of the concept of knowledge. But, we add,
nor is it a merely peripheral feature, resulting from some historical accident in how we
use the concept. Rather, the capacity to access one's reasons features in a layer of content
that is close to the core of the concept of knowledge. The importance of the capacity to
produce reasons in support of what one believes flows immediately from the basic
method of identifying good informants that does constitute the core. I think this is a good
way of substantiating the two-sided thought that it is close to conceptually impossible
that a human being who lacked the general capacity to come out with reasons for her
beliefs could count as a knower (or even a believer); but being able to come out with
one's reasons is not thereby required in every instance of knowledge, and so not a
necessary condition.
62
This combining of externalist and internalist features of the practice of justification on the
part of good informants in the State of Nature echoes and substantiates the internalist-
externalist combination we find in Default and Challenge. On that model of justification,
the subject can have knowledge even if she has taken the deliverances of her faculties
entirely at face value and cannot produce any positive reason for her belief. If faced with
an eccentric challenge, she may only be able to assert that it never occurred to her to
wonder; she may even be a bit thrown by the fact of the challenge and by her own
bewildered reaction. And yet, according to Default and Challenge, the fact that the
default did indeed hold is sufficient. The kind of responsibilism Williams's arguments are
designed to achieve, I think, is one that allows externalism vis--vis the question whether
the default of entitlement holds, so that there is no blanket requirement that the subject be
reflectively aware that it holds; yet a modest internalist constraint when it comes to the
subject's obligation to respond to contextually appropriate challenges. My suggestion has
been that a responsibilism of that combinatory sort finds explanatory support in the
genealogical approach, owing to the non-core yet close-to-core role that an ability to
produce reasons plays in the State of Nature.
3.2. Practical Origins of Contextualism
What about contextualism?a basic version of which might be considered part and
parcel of the Default and Challenge model of justification.14 I suggest that this too finds
an origin in the State of Nature. We have seen that the enquirer is looking for someone
who is crucially likely enough in the context to be right as to whether p. This presents an
explicitly contextualist picture of its own, according to which what it takes to be a good
informantwhat it takes to play the social role at the core of knowingalters from
context to context. For instance, if the stakes are very high, the good informant will be
almost certainly right about p; if they are not so high, and/or if one needs to act sooner
rather than later, she might count as likely enough to be right about p just by having a
half-decent track record and being the only candidate good informant in the vicinity. The
State of Nature, then, explicitly imposes the aspect of contextualism that Williams has
elsewhere labelled economic:
If it is important to reach some decision, and if the costs of error are fairly low, or if we
gain a lot by being right and lose little by being wrong, it is reasonable to take a relaxed
attitude to justificational standards. If the costs of error are high, more demanding
standards may be in order. The opportunity costs of further inquiry can also be relevant.
(Williams 2001: 161)
63
The proto-contextualism contained in the State of Nature not only signifies a constraint
on who can be a good informant, it imposes a constraint on the enquirer too. If, in our
imagined scenario in which the enquirer has already asked a candidate good informant
for information, the informant has told her something, and she is challenging him for his
reasons, then her challenges must be appropriately geared to the context. She is looking
for an after-the-fact-of-utterance indicator property, and this means that if she were to
press him for a justification that exceeded the contextually required level of probability,
this would mark a dysfunction in her epistemic conduct from her own point of view as an
enquirer. Basic practical concerns generate the context sensitive norms of Default and
Challenge in the State of Nature, so that enquirers who demand reasons above and
beyond those appropriate to the context are making a mistake at the level of the
(emergent) norms of proper challenge. All in all, the State of Nature presents us with a
range of practical contexts such that in some contexts the enquirer will demand very little
by way of an informant's likeliness of being right, whereas in other contexts she will
demand a good deal more, according to her practical needs and interestsaccording, that
is, to what it takes for the informant to be likely enough in the context to be right about p.
This aspect of context is the only one we find explicitly stated in the formulation of our
State of Nature scenario, as a condition of being a good informant, though the other
determinants of epistemic context can be built in if one is so inclined. Besides the
economic, Williams cites four other aspects of context: (1) the intelligibility of errorwe
cannot make sense of the possibility of error except against a backdrop of getting it right;
(2) issues of methodological necessityin order to pursue any question we must take
some others for granted; (3) dialectical issuesdefault entitlements are lost and gained
according to the ongoing movement of evidence; and (4) situational issuesclaiming
knowledge commits us to the objective well-groundedness of our beliefs (either a default
entitlement holds or it doesn't). Taking as an example the issue of methodological
necessity, people in the State of Nature definitively don't do history, so they don't have to
set aside questions about the reality of time in order to do it; but they may well have to
establish whether a certain water source is clean or not, and so they do have to set aside
questions about the reality of the external world.
I believe something similar can easily be said in relation to the other aspects of context
that Williams argues for, but I do not want to set much store by it. I dare say an advocate
of another style of contextualism could construct a similar support in the State of Nature
for his particular brand of the view too. Only the contextualism we find explicit in the
formulation of the State of Nature scenario should define the proto-contextualism we
regard as proper to it, and that is the condition of being a good informant that requires her
to be likely enough in the context to be right about p. My point is that the practical
pressures that generate this proto-contextualism lend genealogical explanatory support to
the
64
contextualism that Williams embraces, even while we can see that they might also be
able to support distinct forms of contextualism in which the economic element was
differently embedded. That is entirely as it should be, for the State of Nature scenario
purports to contain only the necessary features of our practices. We should not try to find
anything besides the core elements of our actual justificatory practices represented in the
State of Nature scenario, and so should not hope to extrapolate anything more than a
generic proto-contextualist commitment.
3.3. The Un-Originality of Sceptical Challenge
In this exploration of the practical pressures that generate contextualism in the State of
Nature, we already begin to see how the genealogy of knowledge provides independent
support for the anti-sceptical purpose to which Williams puts his own contextualist
position. There are no sceptics in the State of Naturesurvival requires taking some
people as knowing things one needs to know, and that entails accepting the possibility of
knowledge. This underpins my earlier suggestion that Williams's charge against the
Agrippan scepticthat he behaves in a contextually inappropriate mannerdoes have
some force of its own against the Cartesian sceptic. In the State of Nature, it doesn't
matter in which style sceptical challenges are made. The fact that any such challenges
make demands that exceed what it takes for the informant to be likely enough in the
context to be right about p means the sceptic will fail to identify good informants that are
staring him in the face, and will lose out on knowledge as a result. This means that not
only the Agrippan demand for ultimate justification but also the Cartesian demand that
we meet the challenge of underdetermination can only be a mistake.15 The State of
Nature, then, explains the commonsense idea that no one can basically be a sceptic. They
must be enquirer first, and sceptic second; someone committed to the practical possibility
of knowledge first, and committed to undermining that possibility second. This of course
leaves room for the idea that there may yet be a context in which it is appropriate to
mount sceptical challenges. The present argument shows only that there is no such
context in the State of Nature.
This accommodating thought prompts exposure of the other respect in which we can see
the genealogy of knowledge lending independent support to Williams's anti-sceptical
strategy. The point of extending our philosophical conception over the semi-fictional time
in which genealogical narratives are set, is
65
that it provides an invaluable way of relating core features of a concept to non-core and
peripheral features. I know of no other philosophical method that provides the
opportunity to relate original, necessary features of a concept to less basic, more
contingenthistorically contingentfeatures.16 Accordingly, it delivers an entirely
different image of concepts than that issued by the analytical method. The analytical
ambition and attendant philosophical imagination generates an image of concepts as like
molecules, ready for their different elemental components to be separated out by the
philosopher acting in his capacity as conceptual chemist. Genealogical method, by
contrast, brings with it an image of core and periphery, or kernel and outer layersthe
kernel presents necessary features of the concept, and the outer layers increasingly
contingent historical features. These layers may be separated out from the kernel by the
philosopher acting in his capacity as something more like conceptual historian. The
necessity of the core features stands or falls with how convincingly the story passes
muster as a pure construction out of nothing but absolutely basic needs. If, however
unwittingly, one includes a contingent feature in the State of Nature scenario, perhaps to
suit one's philosophical purpose, then, clearly, the story will lack force. No doubt every
story of origins should be accompanied by something of a health warning, for it surely is
all too easy to portray the State of Nature in one's philosophically preferred image. As
Foucault scoffingly warns us, echoing what he takes to be Nietzsche's own warning about
the philosopher's fantasy of the origin:
History is the concrete body of a development, with its moments of intensity, its lapses,
its extended periods of feverish agitation, its fainting spells; and only a metaphysician
would seek its soul in the distant ideality of the origin. (Foucault 1984: 80)
But Foucault is wrong if he equates all origins stories with ahistorical fantasy. One of the
great virtues of the State of Nature method is precisely its separation of features of a
concept that bear the necessity of the origin, from features that are more or less
contingent matters of history. Far from demanding some dubiously metaphysical faith
in the necessity of any given practice, it gives us a concrete way of assessing the
plausibility of any such claim. When confronted with a genealogical claim that such-and-
such a practice is humanly necessary or original, we must ask, Does this practice really
qualify as an indispensable feature of human life? Is it really required to meet absolutely
basic human needs? Can we not imagine a recognizably human society without it?
Genealogical claims of necessity, then, are grounded not on dubiously metaphysical
ideas or articles of analytical faith, but rather on something fundamentally practicalthe
practical human necessity of the materials used to construct the State of Nature
66
scenario. If we can find nothing contingent about the posited original human need to pool
informationif, that is, we cannot make sense of the idea that there could be a
recognizably human society absent this most basic form of epistemic cooperationthen
the thesis that identifying good informants comprises the kernel of the concept of
knowledge possesses significant force. Foucault seems to regard it as a misuse of the
genealogical method ever to use it to identify human necessities. But if it were in the very
nature of genealogical method that it could only properly be used to find contingency and
never necessity, then it would be a lousy, because undiscriminating, method. Foucault's
blithely expressed wisdom that when it comes to concepts, all is history and nothing
origin, is mere prejudice.
Craig's State of Nature story reveals that if there is a context of enquiry in which sceptical
challenges are appropriate, still there are nonesuch in the State of Nature. And from this
we have drawn the inference that sceptics must be enquirers first and sceptics second (or,
basically enquirers, and sceptics only superficially). This, in its own right, blocks the
sceptic's colonizing move from (i) discovering that, in context C, knowledge is
impossible, to (ii) discovering (in context C) that knowledge is impossible. What blocks
scepticism here is the genealogical primacy of practical, knowledge-permitting, contexts
of enquiry. These knowledge-permitting contexts are the contexts in which the core of the
concept of knowledge is dramatized in practices of good informing. In this sense,
knowledge-permitting contexts figure at the core of the concept of knowledge; indeed
they exhaust it, for there are no other contexts in the State of Nature. Thus the possibility
of knowledge is prior to the possibility of sceptical challenge in the special sense that can
only be supplied by imaginatively stretching our concepts of knowledge and justification
across genealogical time: even the sceptic cannot escape the cognitive functionality of the
origin, for that scenario is still with us, still supplying the core of what it is for us to
know.
As in Williams's irenic anti-sceptical strategy, this may still leave some room for a
confined practice of sceptical challengeit is only in the exclusively practical contexts
provided by the State of Nature that sceptical challenge is obviously never a proper
challenge. In the real-time practices of Default and Challenge there may possibly remain
a context in which sceptical challenge is appropriate, so that knowledge is not possible in
that context. But such an epistemological context, if there be such17 , exploits only
aspects of the concept of knowledge that are way out on the periphery. And our
genealogy has exposed the historical contingency of merely peripheral practices, so that
the sceptic may at any time find the locks to his study have been changed and that it is
now being put to a different philosophical use. In this way genealogical time
67
has implications for historical time: while the diagnosis of the sceptical urge goes deep in
philosophy, our genealogy of knowledge reveals that the question of the propriety of
sceptical challenge does not go deep. It simply rests on how much nurturance we
continue to give to the context of enquiry in which sceptical challenge is deemed
appropriate. That is, it rests on something social within the philosophical community:
namely, how far we continue to respond to sceptical challenge in the epistemological
context as justified challenge, how long we continue to sustain something called the
epistemological context. Perhaps only a satisfactory theoretical diagnosis can catalyse
and justify the historical shift that would render sceptical challenges inappropriate in all
contexts; and that is surely something to which Williams's arguments make a significant
contribution. For my part, I have tried to show that the genealogical approach contributes
an independent diagnostic strategy, which can be seen to support and augment the main
strands of Williams's anti-sceptical case, and also to provide its own distinctive style of
directly anti-sceptical argumentone that affirms the genealogical primacy of
knowledge-permitting contexts. Most generally, I hope to have thereby shown how social
epistemology may be fruitfully expanded not only across social space but also across
time.18
68
4 On Saying that Someone Knows: Themes from Craig
Klemens Kappel
In his book Knowledge and the State of Nature, Edward Craig (1990) proposes a new
methodological approach to one of the crucial questions in epistemology, the question
what knowledge is, or more precisely the question regarding the nature and the concept
of knowledge. We should, urges Craig, start by asking what we have the concept of
knowledge for, what the point or purpose of this concept is. Craig thinks that we can
answer this question, and that the answer will illuminate the concept of knowledge. The
reason we have the concept of knowledge, according to Craig, is that we use it to flag
approved sources of information (Craig 1990: 11). In part, Craig defends his view about
the point of the concept of knowledge by providing a detailed genealogical account of
how the concept of knowledge evolved out of a more primitive concept of the good
informant, which in turn arose in a state of nature. Moreover, Craig endeavours to show
how this throws light on a range of otherwise puzzling features of knowledge and our
practice of epistemic appraisals, including perennial issues debated in epistemology, such
as scepticism, the Gettier problem, and the controversy over externalism and internalism.
Craig's book strikes one as rich and suggestive. Indeed, it seems very compelling that
understanding what we have the concept of knowledge for, and how this concept
developed, will help us understand features of the concept of knowledge. And it certainly
does seem plausible that this in turn will cast light on the nature of a range of disputes
that relate to the question of what knowledge is. Indeed, Craig has many interesting
things to say about the point of the concept of knowledge, the development of this
concept, and how this explains certain features of our practice of epistemic appraisals,
and certain debates in epistemology.
Nonetheless, it is far from straightforward what it is to understand the point of a concept,
or how a genealogical story or considerations of a state of nature help us to understand
this. How, if at all, does understanding the point and the genealogy of the concept of
knowledge contribute to understanding the content of this concept, or the nature of
knowledge? On the other hand, one should not dismiss
69
this sort of project out of hand, and certainly not do so merely on the ground that it
deviates somewhat from mainstream epistemology in the analytical tradition.
It is, therefore, worth exploring whether a robust understanding of the kind of approach
devised by Craig can be provided. Proposing a distilled version of Craig's approach is the
main aim of this chapter. Thus, the issue before us is how to make sense of questions
such as What is the point of the concept of knowledge? and Why do we attribute
knowledge? Below, I shall characterize and defend a general way of understanding such
questions, and contrast it to elements of Craig's approach. On the basis of this, I offer
some views about what, in Craig's terminology, is the point of the concept of knowledge,
and again I contrast this to some of the claims put forward by Craig. Like Craig, I believe
that understanding the point of the concept of knowledge may yield some insights about
knowledge and the concept of knowledge, though space does not permit a discussion of
these further questions.
1. PRACTICAL EXPLICATION
Often philosophy, particularly in the Anglo-American tradition, proceeds by way of
conceptual analysis in some broad sense. This is no less true in epistemology, where
much work aims to analyse our concepts of knowledge and justification, and other
epistemic concepts.1
Clearly, however, there may be other ways of elucidating our concept of knowledge. One
apparent way would be by starting with trying to understand the general point of having
the concept of knowledge, the function it serves, or the purposes we pursue in making
knowledge attributions, or the point of institution of knowledge attributions. This is the
approach favoured by Craig, and in his book he offers a rather detailed account of what
he takes to be the point of knowledge, backed up by a genealogical story about how the
concept evolved.
As a general strategy in philosophy, this is not new, of course. Nietzsche pursued a
similar strategy with respect to certain moral concepts, and related themes are found in
Wittgenstein. More recently, as Kusch (2009) points out, Kripke, inspired by
Wittgenstein, urged us to ask: What is the role, and the utility, in our lives of our
practices of asserting (or denying) [meaning attributions] under these conditions? In
epistemology, approaches similar to Craig's have been taken up by Bernard Williams
(2002) and a number of epistemologists have been directly inspired by Craig's work, and
they have to some extent modified or applied Craig's work.2
70
These efforts notwithstanding, the kind of approach favoured by Craig has not been
widely adopted in recent epistemology. This, I believe, is in part due to the fact that it is
often not fully transparent what the approach recommended by Craig really amounts to.
Despite a longstanding tradition in philosophy for embarking on just these kinds of
enquiries, one may reasonably be somewhat hesitant about our capacity as philosophers
to answer questions such as What is the point of the concept of knowledge? or How
did the concept of knowledge evolve from earlier, more primitive concepts? The reasons
for being cautious are not hard to come by. How does one read off what the point or
purpose of a concept is? How does one gain epistemic access to facts about the
evolutionary process that lead, or could have lead, to our having a concept with the
content of the concept of knowledge?
The aim of this section is to suggest that there is nonetheless a robust interpretation of
these What is the point of X?-questions', as one may term them. Moreover, it is an
interpretation of this type of question that points to a way they can be answered even by
armchair philosophers. I shall use the expression practical explication to refer to a
successful answer to What is the point of X?-questions' interpreted as outlined below.
So, answering the question What is the point of knowledge? when the question is
interpreted in the way I outline below issues in a practical explication of knowledge.
Note that also Craig uses practical explication to refer to the results of his investigations
of the concept of knowledge, though he employs such diverse terms as genealogical
explanation, state of nature explanation, and contractarian explanation. In what
follows, however, I shall use practical explication to refer to the kind of explanation I
outline here, and not to whatever practical explication refers to in Craig's writings. This
act of linguistic appropriation is at least partly justified by the fact that the sound core of
the approach proposed by Craig just issues in the kind of practical explication that I
outline here, or so I shall suggest at any rate.
Let me first exemplify what I take a practical explication to be. Consider the question
Why do we have cars? or What is the point of cars? When read in a very familiar way,
the answer is obvious. The reason we have cars is that we have a need for transport, and
cars meet that need. More specifically, we have important things to do in different
geographical locations, while time and native resources available for transport are scarce.
Hence, there is a need for fairly quick and efficient transport. Cars are our chosen means
of meeting that need, and that is the reason we have them. So, in this sense we can say
that fulfilling a certain need for transport is the point of cars.
Of course, it is correct to point out that people acquire cars for many other reasons as
well. For example, people may acquire cars to display their wealth, or to participate in
certain life forms. While this is no doubt true, it does not undermine the explanation just
offered. There is no reason to deny that items such as cars serve several purposes, though
perhaps it is questionable if cars could
71
serve these more symbolic purposes in the way they do, if they didn't serve as means of
transport for so many people. At least, it is very unlikely that we would have cars if we
never had had the need for transport that they serve to meet.
A practical explication is a kind of explanation, but this explanation is not meant to
explain why we have an extensive traffic system based on privately owned vehicles
rather than, say, a very elaborate system of public transport. Like many other
explanations, the practical explication of cars depends on contrast classes. Roughly,
saying that we have cars in order to meet a need for transport is meant to explain why we
have cars, rather than, say, no means of transport apart from our natural ability to walk
and run. It is not meant to explain why we have cars rather than some other equally
efficient system of transport.
Having exemplified what I take a practical explication to be, I now want to make three
observations about practical explications, all of which should be fairly uncontroversial.
First, obviously, nothing hangs on cars. We can provide similar practical explications of
many other things or kinds of things, say social phenomena such as monetary systems,
laws, educational systems, or devices for communication, conventions of etiquette or
moral norms. And we can, as is our concern here, try to devise practical explications of
various concepts, including the concept of knowledge. Just as we can ask why we have
cars, we can ask why we have the concept of knowledge. This is not to insist that any
item, or even any artefact, does have a practical explication. Perhaps not every concept
has a practical explication of the kind exemplified. Yet, practical explications do make
sense, and some concepts do seem to have practical explications, or so I shall suggest at
least.
Second, a practical explication of a certain phenomenon proceeds by stipulating first,
certain facts about us, such as facts about our physical environment, our biological set-up,
our social organization, and second, certain aims or interests that we typically have, or
have in certain more specific circumstances. Against the background of such stipulations
we can see that there is a certain need, and we can stipulate that the phenomenon to be
explained fulfils that need. This is a practical explication of the phenomenon in question.
So, the format of a practical explication is roughly this. To provide a practical explication
of some explanandum E, two sorts of claims are advanced:
(1) Given a set of facts F, and a set of aims or interests I, we have a certain need N.
(2) E is what actually fulfils the need N.
Note that a practical explication does not attribute intentions or teleological purposes to
anyone or anything, apart from what is involved in the attribution of general aims and
interests to people. Thus, it is not part of a practical explication that we somehow have
the intention to use E in a certain way, though the existence of such intentions may be
consistent with a practical
72
explication of E. And the practical explication does not attribute the teleological property
of having a certain purpose. Neither does a practical explication posit a developmental
history, or make appeals to some primitive state. It is not part of the practical explication
to hold that E developed in certain stages, though it is clearly consistent with a practical
explication that it did.
Practical explications appeal to facts, typically facts about the physical world, our
biological or psychological constitution, or our social organization. And practical
explications invoke facts about our general aims and interests, or the aims and interests
we have in more specific situations. Generally, practical explications thus depend on
empirical, contingent facts. However, this need not invalidate the use of practical
explications in epistemology or in philosophy more generally, since the practical
explications we are interested in as philosophers may rely on trivial facts. When this is
so, philosophers can appeal to these trivial facts and offer plausible practical explications,
even without leaving the armchair, though of course not without running the risk of being
wrong even about the trivial facts. Clearly, however, practical explications may also
proceed at more detailed levels where no trivial facts can be appealed to, and where
proper empirical investigation therefore is necessary. And in many cases, the practical
explications of various phenomena may be hard to come by, for example, because the
underlying facts are not easily accessible, even with the best of empirical investigations.
Third, at least in some cases, practical explications elucidate the phenomena explained. In
the case of cars, we can understand a range of features of cars by seeing how they relate
to the practical explication of why we have cars. Cars have wheels, for example, and can
carry a number of passengers, and these features of cars makes obvious sense against the
background of the practical explication suggested. Similarly, one might hope to discover
features or properties of a concept on the background of a practical explication, or show
how such features make sense given a practical explication of the concept.
2. PRACTICAL EXPLICATION OF THE CONCEPT OF KNOWLEDGE
Having now what is, I hope, a tolerably clear idea of what a practical explication is,
consider the question: why do we have the concept of knowledge? What is the point of
the concept of knowledge? We can now rephrase this question as follows: what is the
practical explication of the concept of knowledge?
The suggestion I shall elaborate is that we can answer this question by noting a set of
features of our cognitive capacities and practical ends, which indicate that we have a
certain need, a conceptual need, as I will call it. Next, the suggestion is that our concept
of knowledge fills the void defined by that conceptual need. As will be clear, it is actually
the first stepthat of delineating the contours of
73
a particular conceptual needthat is the most important. And it is here that the practical
explication is most likely to go wrong. Nonetheless, the proposed practical explication of
the concept of knowledge might also fail at the second step: it might correctly identify the
shape of a conceptual need, yet the conceptual need is not met by deploying our concept
of knowledge, but in some other way. I regard this possibility as unlikely, though not as
unthinkable, but I don't offer specific arguments against it.
As one might expect, much of the practical explication of knowledge that I wish to put
forward is encapsulated in this quotation from the beginning of Craig's book:
Human beings need true beliefs about their environment, beliefs that can serve to guide
their actions to a successful outcome. That being so, they need sources of information
that will lead them to believe truths. They have onboard sources, eyes, and ears, powers
of reasoning, which give them a primary stock of beliefs. It will be highly advantageous
to them if they can also tap the primary stocks of their fellowsthe tiger that Fred can
see and I can't may be after me and not Fredthat is to say, if they act as informants for
each other. On any issue, some informants will be better than others, more likely to
supply a true belief. (Fred, who is up a tree, is more likely to tell me the truth as to the
whereabouts of the tiger than Mabel, who is in the cave.) So any community may be
presumed to have an interest in evaluating sources of information; and in connection with
that interest certain concepts will be in use. The hypothesis I wish to try out is that the
concept of knowledge is one of them. To put it briefly and roughly, the concept of
knowledge is used to flag approved sources of information. (Craig 1990: 11)
However, before turning to the main idea suggested in this passagethe idea that the
concept of knowledge is used to flag approved sources of informationI want to
consider another important matter. Neither in the passage quoted nor in his book, does
Craig consider the special role the concept of knowledge may have for enquiry,
independently of whatever need we might have for identifying sources of information.
Yet there seems to be a very distinct role for the concept of knowledge in enquiry, or this
is what I want to suggest at any rate. Consider what we might call our need for an
enquiry-stopper. The need for an enquiry-stopper arises out of the following three trivial
observations about our interest in truth and certain limitations in our cognitive capacities.
The first is that truth matters. For a range of important propositions we generally benefit
prudentially from treating them as true just in case they are true. Here I assume that what
makes a proposition important is its relation to our practical or prudential concerns.
Treating an important proposition as true, while it is in fact false, is generally worse in
prudential terms than treating it as false. And, conversely, failing to treat a relevant
proposition as true, when fact it is, is generally less optimal in prudential terms. Some
propositions, of course, are not important for our practical
74
concerns, so at best we gain nothing by treating them as true and do not incur the risk of a
loss by treating them as false. In certain special cases, propositions are really important
for our practical concerns, yet because of unusual circumstances, we are better off not
believing a true proposition, or firmly believing a false one. My quality of life may be
much enhanced if I falsely believe that the medication will cure my life-threatening
disease, or if I do not believe the truth that I have failed in my life's most important
project. While there are such cases, it is still true that we generally benefit from treating
as true all the important propositions, and this is the claim I wish to make.
Many epistemologists suggest that at least some true propositions matter in the sense that
knowing them is in some sense epistemically better than merely believing them, or not
believing them, where this sense of betterness is entirely unrelated to prudential goodness
or prudential concerns. I wish to ignore issues about this sense of epistemic goodness,
however, and just rely on the obvious ways in which the truth of propositions may be
important for our practical concerns.
The second observation is that without some form of enquiry, we cannot have truth. But
enquiry is always costly. At any stage in enquiry, continuing the enquiry comes with
certain costs in terms of time and resources. Though facts may sometimes be said to be
directly observable, beliefs about facts are nonetheless always acquired by some method
of enquiry in a particular set of circumstances. A method of enquiry whether p may be
viewed as a process or mechanism that serves to rule out various possibilities. If the
method delivers the result that p, then the method does so in virtue of ruling out certain
non-p possibilities, and vice versa a method that delivers the result that non-p.
Moreover, we need to worry not only about the error-possibilities that are ruled out by the
method we use, but also about those that are not. For any belief, method, and particular
set of circumstances, there are undetectable error-possibilities, that is, ways in which
things might have gone wrong such that the subject in question would have ended up
with a false belief about the relevant subject matter, despite relying on a generally
reliable method of enquiry. One's chosen method may malfunction, or there may be
unexpected features of the circumstances to prevent it from being reliable under the
circumstances at hand. Ruling out error-possibilities by using a method of enquiry and by
securing that the conditions for its application applies, generally requires resources in the
form of time, energy, and attention. In this sense, enquiry is always costly, and can, from
the point of view of the individual, be considered a kind of risky investment.
The third observation is that enquiry, in a sense, has no natural stopping point.
Imagination may always reveal further conceivable but as yet uneliminated error-
possibilities. Of course, the more resources one has invested into enquiry into some
question, the more remote the remaining conceivable error-possibilities may be.
Nonetheless, there are always further ways in which things might have gone wrong. As
we know all too well in epistemology, it only takes a sceptical mind to realize what such
options might consist in. Contrary to what Moore
75
suggested, agents are never in an epistemic position such that they can reasonably infer
that any further conceivable error-possibility simply does not obtain. Or, at least it takes
considerable philosophical sophistication to discern that one is in a position to rule out
any conceivable error-possibility. It is not, of course, that any sound mind would always
worry about any remote as yet uneliminated error-possibility. But this is precisely the
point that I wish to make. The sound mind will be in need of a way of expressing the
attitude that enquiry has now taken one far enough, and that one shouldn't worry about
remaining as yet uneliminated error-possibilities.
Perhaps a way of putting the point is this. At any given point in enquiry we face a
decision task, which consist in weighing the risk of being wrong about p against the risk
of wasting time and resources on further enquiry whether p in the event that p is true. If
one's belief that p is true it would be better just to treat it as true, rather than continue
enquiry. But, of course, if one is inclined to think that p is true, but p is in fact false, it
may be better to spend extra resources in the effort of discovering that it is false. Now,
clearly, often it will be very difficult for enquirers to solve this decision problem by
calculating the expected utility of the two options. In addition, there will be a point where
even beginning to calculate in this way risks being a waste of time and energy, though for
obvious reasons it may be even more difficult to decide when this point has been reached.
This suggests that we have a particular conceptual need. As a first approximation, we
may describe it as a need to express a certain kind of judgement about the beliefs we
acquire during enquiry: that enquiry has now gone on long enough. Or as one might
perhaps put it in more detail: in the nature of the case, we always regard the propositional
content of our beliefs as true. Yet we often believe a certain proposition p, and still regard
it as a live possibility that p might be false, despite the evidence in favour of p that made
us believe it. In such cases, there is always a pro tanto reason to enquire further into the
question whether p. But often, in such cases, we nonetheless benefit from treating a belief
as true, full stop, despite the remaining pro tanto reason to continue enquiry. So, we need
a kind of device to express the attitude that our epistemic position with respect to a
particular proposition p is now so good that we should stop further enquiry whether p.
We need a way to command a switch of our attention away from further uneliminated
non-p possibilities, a way to urge that we simply take the truth of p for granted in our
practical deliberation, as well as in our enquiry into other questions. Or, as I shall say, we
have a need for an enquiry-stopper.
In his book, Craig doesn't discuss the role of knowledge in enquiry, and so he does not
make claims analogous to what I have said about the need for an enquiry-stopper.
Instead, he suggests, as we have seen, that we use the concept of knowledge to identify
good informants, and Craig offers a genealogical story about how our concept of
knowledge has evolved in response to a need to identify good informants that arose in a
state of nature. The basic idea is plausible, I
76
think, but the case for it could be made using the notion of a practical explication that I
proposed above, and without resorting to genealogy or state of nature explanations. This
is what I shall now do.
Again, the basic approach is to identify a set of facts concerning our cognitive capacities
and basic interests, in the light of which we can see that we have a conceptual need of a
certain structure. As before, assume that truth matters to us for prudential reasons, and
assume that truth is available only through methods of enquiry, the exercise of which are
costly, and in some cases not possible. Now, there are two new elements to consider.
First, subjects differ with respect to their cognitive capacities, their decisions about how
to employ these capacities, and the circumstances under which they do so. That is,
individuals may differ with respect to the cost and possibility of acquiring beliefs with a
certain epistemic strength within certain domains, and at particular times they may differ
with respect to the propositions they have chosen to adopt as targets for their
investigative efforts. This results in a great variability in the strength of epistemic
position that various subjects have with respect to many propositions. This variability
may be due to differences between subjects regarding how they are located in time and
space, and it may be due to variation in internal cognitive capacities and cognitive
history, or their ability to exercise these capacities, and their choices about targets of
enquiry.
Second, because of this variability, it may be the case that some subject S1 is not in a
position to rule out error-possibilities relevant for some proposition p, while S1
nonetheless has evidence that some other subject S2 is in such position. Or more
generally, it may be less costly in terms of time and resources for S1 to acquire the belief
that S2 is in a certain desirable epistemic position with respect to some target proposition
p than to get in such position herself. Given that such cases are not too rare, it is
obviously useful for subjects to be able to identify other subjects who assert p while
being in a position to rule out relevant error-possibilities. Hence, we have a general need
to be able to identify properly positioned informants, or good informants, as Craig says,
though there are some important differences between Craig's view about what it takes to
be a good informant and mine, to which I shall return.
More carefully, what is useful for us to have is a range of predicates that serve to express
a variety of epistemic evaluations of the epistemic position of other subjects. If I register
that some subject S believes some proposition p, I clearly need to assess S's epistemic
position with respect to p in order to make any use of that observation in my own
cognitive economy. Without this epistemic assessment it is simply indeterminate how the
proposition should fit into my own theoretical and practical deliberation. Now, for much
the same reasons as I noted above concerning the need for an enquiry-stopper, one useful
evaluative epistemic predicate would express a permission (or obligation) to foreclose
further enquiry and a permission (or obligation) to rely unconditionally on a proposition
in one's practical deliberation. Thus, we have a need for a predicate to express
77
the judgement that we should take the truth of a transmitted proposition for granted.
We can say that it is useful for us to be able to receive or transmit fully trusted
information, information that p conjoined with the evaluation that, because of the origin
of the information that p, there is no point in questioning p, no point in investing
resources in further enquiry whether p, and such that the information that p should be
taken for granted in practical deliberation. Thus, we have a conceptual need to express
the judgement that some proposition p delivered by an informant I is to be considered
fully trusted information.
As before, the need for transmitting fully trusted information, and the conceptual need
that this generates, relies on basic and trivial facts about our cognitive capacities, the
physical environment, and the different distribution and application of diverse subjects'
cognitive capacities. We benefit from transmitting information from one individual to
another, and the reason this is a benefit, of course, has to do with the fact that we occupy
different epistemic positions, combined with the fact that our own epistemic position is
often not as good as we would like. Denying these facts would require holding either that
we rarely have an interest in truth, that enquiry comes for free, that cognitive capacities
are not unevenly distributed or applied, or that one is never in a position to register that
some other subject is better situated than oneself with respect to some subject matter.
None of this is plausible, of course.
2.1. Outline of a Conceptual Need
I have now indicated the contours of two conceptual needs: the need for an enquiry-
stopper and the need for transmitting fully trusted information. We can characterize these
conceptual needs in more detail by characterizing the content of the predicate or the
judgement that we would need to express the attitude in question. I shall do so for each of
the conceptual needs, and then indicate the obvious way in which the two needs may be
considered two instances of one slightly more general conceptual need.
Consider first the need for an enquiry-stopper. This is the need for a predicate that
permits us to express a judgement (about a subject S and a proposition p) with the
following kind of content:
(1) p, and S is in a sufficiently good epistemic position with respect to p, such that S
ought to take the truth of p for granted in her practical and theoretical deliberation.
We can add more flavour to what it means to take a proposition for granted by saying that
taking a proposition for granted includes that one believes p with confidence, or perhaps
better that one should believe that p with considerable confidence, that one shouldn't
gamble on p being false, that one shouldn't spend time and resources amassing further
evidence for p, and that one should not spend time looking for evidence against p, and so
on.
78
Consider then the need for transmitting trusted information. What we need is a predicate
that in its basic form permits us to express the following type of judgement (about two
subjects S1 and S2, and a particular proposition p):
(2) p, and S1 is in a sufficiently good epistemic position such that, given the right
circumstances of transmission, S2 ought to take the truth of p for granted in her
practical and theoretical deliberation.
I haven't here said what counts as a right circumstances of transmission; this is obviously
an important question, and it is likely to be a very delicate matter, but my intention here
is only to describe certain structural features of a conceptual need, not to try to identify
the exact circumstances under which information can be transferred as fully trusted from
one individual to another.
Clearly, the kind of judgement exemplified in (1) may be viewed as a special case of the
judgement exemplified in (2): it is the special case where the informant is the same
individual as the recipient. Moreover, the judgement exemplified in (2) is a special case
of a more general class of judgements that concern a group of subjects rather than only
one as in (2). Hence, while the need for an enquiry-stopper and the need for transmitting
trusted information may seem two very different things, they are in obvious respects very
similar. Thus these two needs may be viewed as instances of the same slightly more
general conceptual need.
Let us introduce the term K-predicate as a name for the predicate we would use to
express the kind of judgement corresponding to this slightly more general conceptual
need. So, the K-predicate would be partly characterized as follows:
K(S1, S1-Sn, p) iff p, and S1 is in a sufficiently good epistemic position such that S1-Sn,
given right circumstances of transmission, ought to take the truth of p for granted in their
practical and theoretical deliberation.
In enquiry, the enquiring subject may apply the K-predicate to herself to express the
judgement that enquiry has now gone far enough, and in this case right circumstances of
transmission almost always obtain. In transmission of information, a subject S1 may
judge that some other subject S2 is in a strong enough epistemic position with respect to
some information that p, such that S1 should take the truth of p for granted in her
theoretical and practical deliberation. Or one may use the K-predicate to recommend
someone as a source of information regarding a particular subject matter. Thus, S2 may
express the judgement that S1s epistemic position with respect to p is such that some
larger group should take the truth of p for granted, given the right circumstances of
transmission.
The point of introducing the K-predicate is only to provide a convenient way of
characterizing and referring to the particular conceptual need that I am interested in. The
word need should not be understood in the strong sense according to which S has a need
for X in order to do F only if S cannot do
79
F without X. In this sense, humans have a need for water, for example, since without
water humans die. When I here speak of a conceptual need I have a less dramatic sense of
the word need in mind; my suggestion is only that, other things being equal, we are
better off if we can meet this conceptual need in some way. We are better off meeting the
need, though we might also get along without doing so.
It is now convenient to expand the terminology a little. Let's call a state of a subject to
which the K-predicate applies a K-state, and let us say that the concept thus expressed by
the K-predicate is the concept of a K-state. I haven't yet said that the conceptual need
defined by the K-predicate is actually met by our possession of the concept of a K-state,
or that this need could not be met in other ways. Having the K-predicate and the concept
of a K-state as a part of one's linguistic and conceptual inventory would meet the need in
question, of course, but there might be other predicates and concepts that would address
the same conceptual need in a different way. For example, one might imagine rational
enquirers who are always willing to consider the possibility that some proposition is in
fact false. These would be subjects who never take any proposition for granted in the way
I have suggested, but rather attribute some degree of confidence, or say in terms of
subjective probabilities approaching but always less than 1.
Neither have I said that we use the concept of knowledge to meet the conceptual need
identified by the K-predicate. This would be a further claim about the concept of
knowledge, and as I see it, it is in part a contingent, empirical claim. Finally, I haven't
said that the concept expressed by the K-predicate just is the concept of knowledge.
This notwithstanding, it seems clear that the concept of a K-state has a range of features
in common with the concept of knowledge, as we would usually understand this concept,
and it might be worth briefly outlining some of these parallels. Clearly, just like states of
knowledge, K-states are factive, they involve belief conditions, and they require some
degree of justification or warrant, however understood. Moreover, being in the K-state
entails being subject to certain norms concerning enquiry and practical deliberation:
being in the K-state with regards to some proposition p entails both that one shouldn't
continue one's enquiry whether p, and that the proposition that p should enter into one's
practical deliberation in a very specific way. So, at least we can say that K-states are in
many important ways just like states of knowledge.
Moreover, I do believe that our concept of knowledge is what actually serves to meet the
need identified, though I haven't argued this further point explicitly. The point of the
concept of knowledge is to accomplish the task delineated by the K-predicate. Thus, the
role of the concept of knowledge in our cognitive ecology, as Kaplan says, is this: in
enquiry, when we believe some proposition p, we say that we know that p in order to
express the judgement that p is indeed true, and that our epistemic position with respect
to p is strong enough
80
to merit taking the truth of p for granted. In transmission of information, we say that
some informant S knows that p in order to express the judgement that S's epistemic
position with respect to p is strong enough to warrant our taking the truth of p for
granted.3
3. GENEALOGY, STATE OF NATURE, CONCEPTUAL SYNTHESIS, AND THE
POINT OF A CONCEPT
Having now outlined what I hope is a workable notion of practical explication, and begun
outlining the practical explication of knowledge, it is worth pointing out how this
approach differs from that of Craig and related approaches. One important element of
Craig's work is that he proposes a genealogy of the concept of knowledge, a genealogy
that traces the concept back to a predecessor concept employed in a state of nature.
But what is a genealogy of a concept? Bernard Williams writes:
a genealogy is a narrative that tries to explain a cultural phenomenon by describing a way
in which it came about, or could have come about, or might be imagined to have come
about. (Williams 2002: 20)
In the words of Martin Kusch, the method proposed by Craig is genealogical, in that it
seeks to illuminate knowledge by providing a hypothetical historical narrative of the
process in which this concept was put together (Kusch 2009).
A practical explication of knowledge, as I understand it, is not a genealogy in this sense.
This is a major advantage, I think, for fairly obvious methodological reasons.
Genealogical explanations may, as Williams says, seek to chart the actual history of some
item. If so, they require an input of empirical observations that may be very hard to get in
the case of the concept of knowledge. It is simply very difficult to know with any
confidence how our actual concept of knowledge, or predecessors to this concept,
evolved in pre-historic times, or even in more recent times. Of course, we can study the
epistemological tradition and learn how philosophers at different times has invested the
word knowledge and its cognates with somewhat different meanings, but this may
obviously be a very unreliable guide to the relevant fact about the concept of knowledge
as it features in our actual conceptual inventory.
The methodological obstacles are no less formidable when we turn to hypothetical
genealogies. If we assume, for the sake of argument, that the content or other features of
knowledge to some extent reflects the hypothetical historical narrative of the process in
which this concept was put together, as Kusch says it, then it is obviously quite
important to know which hypothetical story to adopt. Clearly, there will be many
hypothetical stories to choose between, and it is far
81
from obvious how we would identify the relevant hypothetical story among the many
possible stories.
By comparison, the practical explication of knowledge that I have proposed relies only on
trivial observations of actual facts as they are now; it does not posit a developmental
history, and neither is it a hypothetical narrative.
Genealogical explanations sometimes take the form of state of nature explanations, that
is, explanations that contrast some actual state of affairs with a state of nature, where the
state of nature may be an actual historical state, or a hypothetical one. State of nature
explanations are, of course, familiar in political philosophy, where they are usually
invoked for normative purposes. They usually employ the strategy of showing that some
state of affairsa distribution of resources or whateveris just (or unjust) in virtue of
the fact that it could (or could not) have evolved from the state of nature in the right way.
In a related version, a state of nature explanation may seek to offer a story about how we
might form a collective intention to adopt a certain convention or social institution, such
as the institution of property rights (Hume's example). In other versions the ambition is
more like explaining why we have an individual reason to adhere to certain social
institutions, such as certain norms of morality (Hobbes's example).
Craig talks about a state of nature, and it even figures in the title of his book. For Craig,
however, the point of invoking a state of nature is not to justify any normative stance.
The state of nature is a kind of hypothetical primitive human society that contrasts with
our actual and presumably more complex and sophisticated social organization, and the
state of nature figures only as part of an explanation of how our concept of knowledge
evolved from a more primitive predecessor-concept.
The practical explication of knowledge outlined above is, of course, entirely different
from all this. It does not invoke a state of nature, either for normative or explanatory
purposes. Again, this is a major methodological advantage for the reasons already
rehearsed: we know too little about the actual primitive life forms and the concepts that
figured in these life forms. And there are too many hypothetical primitive states to choose
between.
In many places Craig writes as if a concept may inherit certain properties or features from
its predecessor-concepts. Craig, for example, writes:
The concept of the informant will then leave its mark, so to speak, on the concept of
knowledge, and the hypothesis is that for this reason an approach via the former concept
will be likely to provide a more illuminating account of the concept of knowledge than
will any other method. (Craig 1990: 95)
Indeed, if a concept is not subject to some form of hereditary influence of some sort, it is
hard to see how a genealogical explanation can illuminate features of the concept.
However, one might reasonably doubt whether there can be the relevant kind of
hereditary mechanisms between (tokens of?) concepts, except
82
in some metaphorical sense. In particular, it may be very hard to understand how a purely
hypothetical narrative can involve the relevant kind of hereditary influence. Why does
some story about how a concept could have evolved, but did not actually evolve, leave
any marks on our actual concepts? To make sense of this, one would have to posit causal
mechanisms that cross modal boundaries in the most astonishing way.
At any rate, the practical explication of knowledge put forward above does not assume
any process of conceptual inheritance; it is not part of the story that the concept of
knowledge carries certain traits that stems from predecessor-concepts. But practical
explications are not for that reason bound to be static. Obviously, the conceptual needs
generated by facts about the environment, our cognitive capabilities, our general or
specific aims and so on, might evolve for the simple reason that the underlying facts
change over time.
In various places Craig writes as if the concept of knowledge is constructed out of the
concept of the good informant, or some similar concept or set of concepts. If taken
literally, this idea is rather different from what is no doubt Craig's settled view, namely
that the concept of knowledge somehow evolved out of a more primitive conceptual
device serving to identify good informants. This is not the same as claiming that the
concept of knowledge is constructed out of the concept of the good informant. Indeed,
the view that the concept of knowledge evolved out of something like the concept of the
good informant through some evolutionary process is consistent with the view that the
concept of knowledge is primitive, that is, not constructed at all out of any more primitive
parts. Anyway, the practical explication that I offer neither affirms nor denies that the
concept of knowledge is constructed out of other concepts.
Yet a third idea floated in Craig's book is that we can fairly easily advance plausible
hypotheses about the role of the concept of knowledge. As he says:
We take some prima facie plausible hypothesis about what the concept of knowledge
does for us, what its role in our life might be, and then ask what a concept having that
role would be like, what conditions would govern its application. (Craig 1990: 2)
And, in a similarly optimistic tone:
One doesn't have to commit oneself to a great deal of epistemology or semantic theory, as
the standard approach evidently does, to presume that there is such a thing as the point of
this concept [the concept of knowledge], what it does for us, the role it plays in our lives.
(Craig 1990: 3)
It has already been made clear, of course, what Craig takes to be a prima facie plausible
hypothesis concerning the point of the concept of knowledge: the concept of knowledge
is used to flag approved sources of information (1990: 11). No doubt, Craig's settled
view is that the genealogical story does offer some additional support to his view about
the point of the concept of knowledge. Still, it is noteworthy that in these passages Craig
advances his views about the point of knowledge without mention of any state of nature
or genealogy. He seems to
83
suggest that we can fairly directly see what would be a plausible hypothesis about the
point of the concept of knowledge, and then we can move to the question what a concept
having this purpose would have to be like.
Craig's assumption that we can fairly easily discern the point of the concept of knowledge
is questionable for familiar reasons. In general, we should not assume that the point of a
concept is part of its conceptual content, and indeed Craig does not rest his case on this
assumption. Hence, while it might be that conceptual analysis can reveal something about
the content of the concept of knowledge, it is not really suited for discovering anything
about the point of that concept.
It might be tempting to assume that the point of the concept of knowledge can somehow
be gleaned from our linguistic practice featuring know or knowledge and their
cognates, or by studying the intentions we manifest when using these words in their
ordinary meaning. However, there are familiar reasons why this is not plausible.
Compare the question: Why do we say that things are on fire? Well, sometimes to scare
people, sometimes to encourage people to escape the burning house, sometimes to
celebrate (if we are resistance fighters having just succeeded in putting the enemy's
property on fire). Something similar may hold for our use of the words know and
knowledge. So, strictly speaking, the set of aims manifested when saying that someone
knows may be uninformative about the point the concept of knowledge, and this is of
course due to the fact that once we have the concept, we may use it for a rather broad
variety of things. The actual intentions manifested in our use of the concept of knowledge
may therefore constitute a bewildering array that doesn't permit any simple inference to
any view about the point of the concept of knowledge.4
This is of course not to deny the possibility that our various uses of the concept of
knowledge and the word knowledge are unified by the fact that they all involve
assertions of propositions of the form S knows that p. Similarly, whether your utterance
of the house is on fire is intended to scare someone or to encourage someone to
celebrate, this utterance normally asserts the proposition the house is on fire. For all I
have said, the same may hold for utterances of the form S knows that pthey all assert
propositions of the form S knows that p. It should be quite clear, though, that this type of
unity in our use of the concept of knowledge does not permit any interesting conclusion
about the point of the concept. It is true, but not informative, to be told that the point of
the concept of knowledge is to enable us to assert propositions of the form S knows that
p.
Finally, there is, of course, a metaphysical problem about what we should even mean by
the point of a concept, an issue that Craig does not address. We should, for familiar
reasons, be quite wary of the assumption that talk of the point of a concept refers to
genuine teleological properties of concepts.
84
It is an obvious advantage of the notion of a practical explication proposed here that
epistemological and metaphysical difficulties pertaining to talk of the point of a concept
are avoided. We can fairly easily see how certain conceptual needs arise in response to
trivial facts about our aims, circumstances, and cognitive capacities. And we can explain
how we have some epistemic access to these facts.
It is interesting to note that in some places Craig actually characterizes his own approach
in very similar terms:
We are attempting a state of nature explanation of a number of facts of conceptual or
linguistic practice. Such explanations work by identifying certain human needs and
arguing that the practices are a necessary (or at least highly appropriate) response to
them. (Craig 1990: 89)
This passage may be read as endorsing precisely what I mean by a practical explication,
provided that the passage is read as referring to our actual needs, the needs underlying
our actual conceptual practice, not some need we would have in a hypothetical state of
nature. On this reading, there is nothing genealogical about the account, and no reference
to a state of nature different from our actual state. Be this as it may, I want to suggest that
the sort of practical explication of knowledge proposed here is a plausible candidate for a
purified version of what Craig actually does in his book, despite his own different
characterization of his approach.
4. CRAIG ON THE CONCEPT OF THE GOOD INFORMANT
Let us now turn to Craig's views about the concept of the good informant and the concept
of knowledge. As mentioned, Craig thinks that the concept of knowledge somehow
evolved out of the concept of the good informant, in part through a process of
objectivization, as he says. I shall now add some comments to these parts of Craig's view,
mostly to compare it to the practical explication of knowledge that I have suggested.
Consider first what Craig says about the concept of the good informant:
We begin by considering it at its most subjective. I am seeking information as to whether
or not p, and hence want an informant who is satisfactory for my purposes, here and now,
with my present beliefs and capacities for receiving information. I am concerned, in other
words, that as well as his having the right answer to my question,
(1) He should be accessible to me here and now.
(2) He should be recognisable by me as someone likely to be right about p.
(3) He should be as likely to be right about p as my concerns require.
(4) Channels of communication between him and me should open. (Craig 1990: 845)
85
This gives an approximate indication of what we should understand by the concept of the
good informant, at its most subjective, as Craig says (1990: 84). Craig's idea is that this
concept of the good informant is a concept belonging to a state of nature, and that our
current concept of knowledge evolved from this, in part through a process of
objectivization, in which certain features of the concept of the good informant are
diluted, transformed, or left out:
What remains [of the process of objectivization] will not be identifiable with the concept
of a good informant [. . . ] but it may still bear certain marks of its origin, and if it does
then the concept of the good informant may be the key for drawing them to our attention
and making their presence comprehensible to us. It will also bear the marks of the
objetivisation. Some of the marks may obscure some of the others. (Craig 1990: 97)
I have three main comments on these parts of Craig's view. First, the process of
objectivization is obviously quite crucial in these and similar passages. Objectivization is
simply the backbone of the genealogical process that takes us from the state of nature to
our present situation. However, it is not easy to get a firm grasp of the process that Craig
refers to. The driving assumption seems to be that objectivization is a response to certain
pragmatic pressures that arise. For example, Craig asserts that as objectivisation
proceeds', the requirement of the detectability of the property will be diluted (1990: 90).
So, the idea is that while the primitive or most subjective version of the concept of the
good informant includes a requirement of detectability, as is stated in (2) above, this
requirement is abandoned as the concept evolves towards our mature concept of
knowledge. This is why our concept of knowledge doesn't include any such requirement:
someone S can know that p though no detectable property of S correlates with S's reliably
believing that p, just as S can know that p despite being unwilling to tell.
Craig here trades on assumptions about how our concepts would develop in response to
certain pragmatic pressures. But it is obviously quite hard to assess the plausibility of this
line of thought, and consequently an explanation of features of the concept of knowledge
depending on views about objectivization is bound to be very fragile. By comparison, the
practical explication of knowledge that I have suggested does not depend on anything
like a process of objectivization.
Second, note that perhaps the most striking feature of Craig's way of characterizing the
concept of the good informant is that a range of features necessary for identifying and
making use of others as informants is built into the very concept of a good informant, viz.
the conditions listed in (1) to (4). So, the concept of the good informant comes with a
range of epistemic and pragmatic features that enables us to identify individuals in
possession of the right answer, and enables us to utilize this capacity of these individuals.
It is far from obvious why such epistemic and pragmatic features would have to be built
into the concept of the good informant itself. According to Craig, we need the concept of
the good informant because, as enquirers, we benefit from being able to identify
86
individuals whom might have the right answer to our question. Nonetheless, the concept
of the good informant is not simply the concept of someone having the right answer to
some question, according to Craig. But why not? Why not simply stick to the simpler
idea that we need the concept of someone being in a good enough epistemic position with
respect to some proposition, and then letting the question of the detection of this property,
and other questions pertaining to the use we can make of this, be further questions? It is
not at all clear why these epistemic and pragmatic features would have to be built into the
concept we need. What Craig suggests about the concept of the good informant is rather
like the claim that the concept of a good car is the concept of a car that I own and which
is parked nearby, and where the keys are presently in my pocket. Clearly, this is odd.
One should note, of course, that Craig is not offering an analysis of our actual concept of
a good informant. Rather, his concern is to identify a concept that we possessed in some
state of nature, and which later evolved into our concept of knowledge. So, while Craig is
suggesting a concept that we would need in some state of nature, our discomfort with
Craig's notion of the good informant may at least in part be due to the fact that this notion
fails to match our current concept of the good informant. Clearly, any discomfort in
having this source might not be well placed. Nonetheless, we are still in need of an
explanation of why the state of nature concept of the good informant has the odd features
that Craig assumes. In comparison, the practical explication proposed above does not in
similar ways rest on assumptions that prima facie seem peculiar.
Third, the issues just raised bear an interesting similarity to an objection that Craig
responds to. This is what he calls the cart before the horse objection: Shouldn't being a
good informant be explained in terms of knowing whether p, rather than the other way
around? (Craig 1990: 94). Or, as Craig states the assumption behind the objection:
knowing seems to be that central state of the subject which fits him to be a good
informant, other circumstances concurring (1990: 93).
On the one hand, it appears obvious why one would consider something like the cart
before the horse objection. Clearly, we should worry that our actual concept of the good
informant is something like the concept of someone who knows. On the other hand, as I
have just argued, Craig's concern is not to propose an analysis of our actual concept of
the good informant. Neither is his concern, one can add, to propose an analysis of
knowledge in terms of the concept of the good informant. Rather, his concern is to
identify a particular state of nature concept that later developed into the concept of
knowledge. Against this background, it is actually not so clear what the point of the cart
before the horse objection would be, or why Craig even devotes it any attention.
It is even more striking to note Craig's considered response to the cart before the horse
objection:
knowing is best understood in terms of the idea of a potential informant, that we get at its
nature by first considering the business of being a good informant and then subtracting
87
something from the result, or modifying it in some way. The concept of the informant
will then leave its mark, so to speak, on the concept of knowledge, and the hypothesis is
that for this reason an approach via the former concept will be likely to provide a more
illuminating account of the concept of knowledge than will any other method.
(Craig 1990: 95)
Now, what Craig seems to be saying here, at least in the most obvious and
straightforward interpretation, is that the concept of knowledge is best understood with
reference to the role it plays in our notion of the good informant. What is striking is that
this is very different from saying that the concept evolved out of the concept of the good
informant through a process of objectivization. Clearly, one can hold that the concept of
knowledge is partly shaped by the role this concept plays in our efforts to identify good
informants, and yet deny that the concept of knowledge evolved out of the concept of the
good informant.
What we have seen, then, is that there really are two very different themes in play in
Craig's discussion. One is the idea that the concept of knowledge evolved through a
genealogical process, the process of objectivization of the concept of the good informant.
The other and entirely different idea in Craig's thinking about these issues is that we
might think of the concept of knowledge as being partly shaped by the role this concept
has in the concept of the good informant. This latter idea is plausible, I think. It seems to
be just an instance of the sort of practical explication of knowledge that I have proposed.5
88
5 The Swamping Problem Redux: Pith and Gist
Jonathan Kvanvig
The Swamping Problem is one of the central problems in the new value-driven approach
to epistemology. Issues concerning epistemic value, however, are not new. We can find
them first in Plato's dialogue Meno, where Socrates and Meno have a discussion about
what type of guide one should prefer if one wants to get to Larissa. The first suggestion is
that one should want a guide who knows the way, but Socrates notes that a guide with
true opinions will work just as well. Meno's response to Socrates' objection raises
precisely the correct worries: he wonders about the nature of knowledge (whether it
differs from true opinion) and about the value of knowledge (why we prize it over true
opinion). The point of view of value-driven epistemology is that a myopic focus on the
former question is a mistake and that questions about the value of knowledge and other
epistemic phenomena are important in their own right. Addressing them explicitly can
help evaluate the adequacy of proposals concerning the nature of knowledge and other
epistemic phenomena.
The natural suggestion in response to Socrates' objection is to look for something
valuable to add to true belief so that the composite is more valuable than mere true belief
and where the composite is identical to knowledge. Here is one such suggestion:
knowledge is justified true belief. This suggestion is appropriate since justification is
itself valuable. Sober reflection reveals that one should prefer justified beliefs to
unjustified beliefs. So justified true belief should be more valuable than true belief alone,
and thus if knowledge is justified true belief, we can explain to Socrates and Meno why
we prefer guides who know the way to Larissa: not because they are better at getting us
there, but because knowers are in a preferable state to mere true believers.
Sometimes simple explanations arouse legitimate suspicion and such is the case here.
Note first that the above explanation may rely on a principle of value additivity: take
anything valuable, add something of value to it, and you get something even more
valuable. Yet, this principle is false: if a little salt adds flavour and hence value, multiple
iterations do not continue to add value.
It is this failure of additivity, I will argue, that it is the pith and gist of the Swamping
Problem. This account of the problem has not been properly
89
appreciated, as can be seen by examining some recent proposals for escaping the
problem. We will turn to such proposals after first clarifying what we are trying to
explain when we attempt to explain the value of knowledge, and how the issue of
additivity is central to such explanations. In particular, we will see that though a social
approach to the value of knowledge has a significant role to play in addressing the value
problem, its role is partial and incomplete, requiring supplementation by some more
general solution to the Swamping Problem.
TASK 1: WHAT NEEDS TO BE EXPLAINED
One way to proceed here is to notice different levels of suspicion concerning the value of
knowledge, beginning with fully general suspicion that knowledge has little or no value
at all. One may respond to such suspicion either in terms of the nature of knowledge or in
terms of its function in ordinary life. On the former score, one might point out aspects of
knowledge, such as true belief, that are valuable, and defend the value of knowledge
indirectly in this way. Such defences, however, are likely to have been anticipated by the
iconoclasts in question, since the relationship between knowledge and true belief is such
an obvious one. Perhaps a more promising strategy is through appeal to the function of
knowledge in ordinary life.1 Such an explanation of the value of knowledge will almost
certainly be a social explanation. For example, it is of central importance for us to be able
to keep track of information and sources of information that can be trusted, and one of the
functions of attributing knowledge to sources is for such tracking purposes.
Such an explanation latches onto something important and significant about the social
function of the concept of knowledge. Whatever else we might wish to say about the
value of knowledge, there is no question that a good part of the value of knowledge needs
to be explained in precisely this way. We can gain a great deal of insight into the value of
knowledge by attending to the functional role the concept of knowledge plays in our
lives, and we might even try the tack of attempting to understand knowledge, not in terms
of necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of some concept expressed by
ordinary language, but rather in terms of whatever plays the knowledge-role in ordinary
thinking. Initial suggestions along these lines have played an important role in recent
epistemology, as epistemologists have suggested that knowledge is necessary for
appropriate assertion and sufficient for practical reasoning.2 The former principle
90
is already social in nature because of the social function of assertion, and the role of
knowledge in practical reasoning should be conceived in social terms as well if we want
the principle to state both necessary and sufficient conditions. If I know that my sources
of information know of what they speak, that is perhaps ordinarily sufficient for me to
know as well, but my legitimate reliance on that information in practical reasoning is not
determined by my own epistemic state in such cases. If you know that the bridge is safe,
but for some reason I don't know that the bridge is safe, it can still be acceptable for me
to cross it on your word in spite of my lack of knowledge. The epistemic division of
labour involved in trusting engineers, doctors, lawyers, priests, pastors, and social policy
gurus is not held hostage to the vagaries of the precise epistemic state of the one who
trusts. Individual knowledge, for example, is undermined by exaggerated doubts and by
subjective defeaters, but reliance on the knowledge of the authorities in question is not
automatically undermined by the presence of such idiosyncrasies.
Such a theoretical approach to epistemology might go farther, attempting not only to
account for the value of knowledge in terms of such guiding principles, but also claiming
that the resulting theory is all the theory of knowledge we need. Such an extension would
count as a Lewisian approach to epistemology, wherein one's concern is not so much with
the nature of knowledge itself but with whatever plays the knowledge role in ordinary life
and thought, much as Lewis attempts to understand the role of the idea of chance in
ordinary thought in terms of the Principal Principle (and its successors).3 I will not here
explore this project, but it is a worthy one indeed, one fully deserve of the title of being a
Lewisian theory of knowledge, one designed from the beginning as a social theory of
knowledge that aims first at accounting for the value of knowledge by focusing on its
function in ordinary life and thought. Such a theory would be a substantive and original
contribution to contemporary epistemology, even though it would likely be at odds with
the only extant Lewisian theory elicitable from his idea that knowledge is a quite elusive
thing (since the more elusive and contextual a theory goes in epistemology, the less
important knowledge seems to become).4 Whatever the guiding principles of the role that
the concept of knowledge plays in everyday life, the social function is certain to be
central to that role. In such a theory, then, the social function that knowledge plays would
be highlighted and the resulting theory would be able to explain the value of knowledge
at least in part in terms of this social role.
It is important to note, however, that whatever the merits of a social epistemological
account of the value of knowledge, such an account has no capacity to solve or address
the Swamping Problem, absent some really excessive
91
Procrustean manoeuvres. The Swamping Problem attacks a very special and unique kind
of value that knowledge seems to have, that involved in being preferable to true belief
and any other combination of its proper parts. Whatever role is played by the notion of
knowledge in ordinary life is not likely to be sensitive to this feature, unless we claim that
it is part of the role from the start. Such a claim has much to be said against it, however.
Whatever role knowledge plays in ordinary life is more likely to involve the value of
knowledge rather than the special or unique value it has over its proper parts. A more
fitting explanation here is that the factors involved in the role in question are more
coarse-grained than that, and that the fine-grained special and unique value in question
will be tramped under foot in the process of providing an account of the role, rather than
the nature, of knowledge. In slogan form, such a role, or functional, theory of knowledge
is better suited to providing an account of the value of knowledge than it is to providing
an account of the special value knowledge has over it subparts.
Such a conclusion fits well with some rather sceptical thoughts John Greco (2009) has
voiced about the special value in question. Greco doubts that ordinary thinking ascribes
any such special value to knowledge, but should be understood instead to involve the
more simple attitude that knowledge is valuable or that knowledge matters. I agree with
this sentiment: the issues that threaten the special value of knowledge do not threaten the
value of knowledge, and the assumptions that give rise to the problem concerning the
special value of knowledge are not present in any direct or immediate way in ordinary
thought about knowledge. Assumptions and presuppositions of thought are too far below
the surface to sustain any such general claim, and may not be mental states at all. But
what follows from this point is that a theory of the value of knowledge designed for use
in a functional theory of the sort indicated is not likely to need any account of the special
value of knowledge, whereas a theory that attempts to say what the nature of knowledge
itself is will require such an account.
This point raises important issues in meta-epistemology and meta-philosophy more
generally, and the functional role theorists will insist that anything beyond a functional
role theory would be suspect from the start. I do not believe this for a moment, and view
such attitudes as excessively procrustean. A focus on this issue will take us too far afield,
but it is worth mentioning here since everything that follows is predicated on this point of
view. In what follows the guiding principle will be about the nature of knowledge itself,
not some substitute designed to play the role that knowledge actually plays, and the
presupposition of such a project is that reality cannot be delimited in the way imagined
by theories that attend only to roles in ordinary thinking.
Whether or not I'm right about such meta-philosophical issues, the point remains that a
large part of value-driven epistemology will involve the social aspects central to such a
functional account. But the nature of knowledge itself may remain untouched by such an
account, and if so, the special value
92
of knowledge may remain unexplained. For the special value is discovered only by
comparing the value of knowledge with the value of its parts, and such a comparison
plays no role in the functional approach. The point that bears emphasis, then, is this: the
Swamping Problem is, at its core, a problem concerning the special and unique value of
knowledge over that of its parts, rather than a problem concerning the value of
knowledge itself.
In order to see how the Swamping Problem threatens this special and unique value, we
need a clearer understanding of the scope of this value, and here some distinctions are
needed to see precisely what the Meno problem is. We can begin by noting what the idea
that knowledge is more valuable than true belief doesn't involve. It doesn't involve the
claim that all things considered, it is always better to know than to merely believe truly.
Suppose my entire family will be killed immediately if it is discovered that I know, rather
than merely truly believe, that they are in Dallas today. Then, all things considered, it is
not better to know. But such a conclusion shouldn't be thought to show anything about
the universality or necessity of the value of knowledge. What it shows is that we
shouldn't think of the value of knowledge in terms of all-things-considered value. Instead,
the obvious reply is to distinguish between prima facie and ultima facie value.
We might put this point by saying, rather uninformatively, that all else being equal,
knowledge is more valuable than true belief. For some approaches to value, this
distinction between prima facie and ultima facie can be put in the language of defeasible
reasoning. On these approaches, when reasoning about preferences and values in general,
finding out that a given state is a state of knowledge is a defeasible reason for preferring
that state or concluding that the state is all-things-considered valuable, and finding out
that two states differ in that the first is a state of knowledge and the second of mere true
belief is a defeasible reason to prefer the first to the second and to conclude that the first
has more value than the second.
On some more particularist understandings of value, the value of the parts will depend on
the value of the whole, so that knowledge will have prima facie value in this way only
when it is part of a whole which is ultima facie valuable. On such approaches,5 it is false
that knowledge always and necessarily has more value than mere true belief, even when
the kind of value in question is prima facie value. But even these approaches to value had
better not deny a global supervenience thesis about value, to wit, that there cannot be two
worlds that differ at the value level without differing in some way at the non-value level.
Given the global supervenience thesis, if we find a case where knowledge is not more
valuable than true belief, there will be a reason we can cite that is independent of the
mere fact that the state in question is a state of knowledge rather than a state of mere true
belief to explain why knowledge isn't more valuable in that case, and this
93
explanation will give us a factor that we can control for and hold fixed in order to explain
the nature of the claim that knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief.
It is also important to distinguish the question of the value of knowledge from the related
issue of our valuing of it. Valuings are things done by persons, and it is a thoroughly
prosaic fact to note that people sometimes value things that have no value at all. When
we ask questions about the value of knowledge, we are asking about matters that go
beyond individual preferences and valuings. Though there may be some ultimate
connection between objective value in this sense and our subjective valuings, the
connection will not allow us directly and immediately to read off claims about the value
of knowledge from claims about the way in which we value it.
Those convinced that objective value can only find a place in the natural world by being
definable in terms of subjective valuings will be tempted to specify counterfactual
conditions for the identity of value with valuings. For example, one might think that
value could be identified with valuings by fully rational individuals apprised of all
relevant facts. Such counterfactual accounts find grave difficulty avoiding the conditional
fallacy,6 and give way quickly in the face of these problems to better self theories,
theories that identify objective value with what our better selves would view as
appropriate valuings on our part.7 Whatever the connection posited, however, the
important point to note is that the kind of value in question concerning the value of
knowledge is a kind of value that requires the same treatment as other objective values.
The value of human life, for example, cannot be explained sufficiently in terms of what a
fully informed individual might value, or what our better selves might attach significance
to; instead, the only hope for such accounts would be to refine the idea that the value of
human life involves the valuing a fully informed individual or a better self would make.
Anything weaker would have no hope of explaining the value in question. Just so, the
value of knowledge cannot be explained either in terms of value judgements a well-
placed individual might make, but must rather advert to valuings such an individual
would make. In the light of the difficulties presented by the conditional fallacy, it is
doubtful that such a theory can be successful, but we need not enter that fray here, since
the only point needed for present purposes is one concerning the kind of strength such an
account must employ to have any hope of success. The special and unique value of
knowledge is thus a special truth-related, prima facie value that it possesses necessarily if
at all, and it is a value explicable in terms of valuings only to the extent that the
individual doing the valuing is idealized and the valuing in question is a valuing that such
an idealized individual would do rather than simply might do.
94
This way of putting the point allows a nice analogy with the theory of probabilistic
causation. An initial idea concerning probabilistic causes is to think of them in terms of
probability enhancers, but such a proposal founders on the fact that causal factors often
interact. Taking birth control pills causes thrombosis even though women taking such
pills decrease their chances of getting thrombosis (because they decrease their chances of
getting pregnant which also causes thrombosis). Just as a causal factor can be present but
masked by other factors, so can the value of knowledge be present but masked. And just
as we should expect to uncover probabilistic causes by finding probabilistic enhancement
in circumstances in which we have the right controls for interference in place, just so we
should expect to uncover the value of knowledge when we impose the relevant controls
here as well. So, to claim that knowledge has special value only sometimes and in some
places is not to account for its special value, but rather would be like resting content with
the claim that causation sometimes involves probabilistic enhancement and sometimes
doesn't when faced with counterexamples involving interaction to the persuasive initial
suggestion that probabilistic causes are probability enhancers. The right response to the
initial counterexamples is a refining of the initial idea, not a revisionary conception that
remains complacently comfortable with the opinion that there is no deeper explanation
than that the original account is true sometimes and in some places. The hard task of
stating precisely the controls that are needed I have not done here, but the idea of doing
so is just as plausible here as it is with the notion of probabilistic causation.
TASK 2: THE TWO-TIERED VERSION OF THE SWAMPING PROBLEM
Given this understanding of the claim that knowledge has special value in terms of the
idea of a defeasible value that is always and necessarily present, we are now in a position
to state more clearly the nature of the Swamping Problem for this special value. The
problem, at bottom, arises when a theory tries to explain the value of knowledge over that
of true belief by citing a property that is not always and everywhere additive in value.
Once we notice that true belief is valuable, and one identifies knowledge with a property
that does not always add value to true belief, we smell the scent of a problem. Of course,
the problem can disappear if the cases where value is not added can be explained away in
terms of the other kinds of things that must be controlled for in order to reveal the special
value of knowledge, as noted above. But such explaining away offers little hope for the
usual kinds of theories the Swamping Problem plagues. What is needed is to avoid non-
additive properties: properties that, once the relevant controls are in place, do not add to
the value of true belief. One of the most obvious of such properties is the property of
statistical likelihood of truth.
95
My preferred formulation of the Swamping Problem employs this property and proceeds
in two steps. It begins with an example in which it is clear that such a property adds no
value whatsoever, and then treats the example as an instructive analogy about one
particular epistemological theory that clearly succumbs to the Swamping Problem. After
seeing what a theory cannot be like if it is able to avoid this problem, a challenge can be
issued to the reliabilist (as well as other theories) to explain what value-adding feature
their theory possesses that is lacking in the theory that succumbs to the problem.
First, then, the example. Suppose I want chocolate. I Google to find places close to me. I
get two web pages: one titled places that sell chocolate in Waco; the other places likely
to sell chocolate in Waco. We may assume accuracy for both lists, and that the second
list is generated from correlations: places that sell food are likely to sell chocolate, places
that sell sweets are too. We do not assume, for purposes of the example, that the accuracy
in question is known to obtain, though we do assume that no special doubts are present
regarding accuracy. We assume, simply, that Googling gives us the means to achieve the
goal of getting chocolate, one a list of probabilistic means and the other a list of means
simpliciter. We also assume that there is no evaluative dimension to our appraisal of the
lists other than in terms of the goal of getting chocolate: categorization of means in terms
of better or worse is restricted to their capacity to serve the goal of getting chocolate. We
exclude all other values from consideration, values such as having fancier names for a
place of business, finding a business run by an acquaintance, proximity to my present
location, and so on.
So I have two lists relevant to the goal in question. We then note four important facts
about these lists. The first fact is that the second list is better than nothing, given that the
only relevant goal is the goal of getting chocolate. If I want chocolate, rather than
choosing randomly from all the businesses in Waco, it would be better to select randomly
from the list of places likely to sell chocolate in Waco. The second fact is that, for the
purpose in question, the first list is more valuable than the second. I do not wish to say
that it would be irrational to rely on the second list, given only the purpose of getting
chocolate, but it would certainly be better to rely on the first list. The third and fourth
facts arise from introducing a third list, which is the intersection of the first two lists:
places that both sell chocolate and are likely to. The third fact is that the intersection list
is also preferable to the second list: it would be better to rely on a list that included places
that both sell chocolate and are likely to than to rely on a list that included only places
likely to sell chocolate. The final fact, however, is the swamping fact: the intersection list
is no more valuable than the first list, given the interest in question. If all I care about is
chocolate, it would be no better to use the list of places that both sell chocolate and are
likely to than to use the list of places that sell chocolate. Choosing a place of business
from the intersection list may be no worse for purposes of getting chocolate than
choosing from the first list, but it is certainly no better. Someone who adopts the practice
96
of selecting from the intersection list rather than the first list does not adopt a superior
means of securing the goal in question, given the assumption that the first list is an
accurate list.
One may start to follow red herrings of decision theory to try to avoid this conclusion by
claiming that it is not enough to assume that the first list is accurate. Instead, it might be
claimed, one will need to assume that one believes with certainty, or knows, that the list
is accurate. The second claim is surely false: one can reasonably act on the basis of
assumptions that do not constitute knowledge. It is plausible to think that the same point
holds for the claim that subjective certainty is needed: one can reasonably act on the basis
of full belief with no need to adopt further strategies to take into account the possibility or
chance of error, even if one resists subjective certainty about one's beliefs. Some chances
of error need not be taken into account when acting, and the case as imagined is of this
sort. What we have is a low-stakes situation in which the loss of securing the goal is not
important enough to get anxious about the chance of failure. So, the lists are taken at
face-value, assumed to be accurate in what they represent, and a choice of means to
getting chocolate ensues. In such a case, the intrusion by a friend who insists on
constructing an intersection list and counsels its use over the first list would be a case of
inapt advice. By my lights, it doesn't cut my chances of missing out on chocolate and I
have no interest in practising set-theoretic operations for their own sake. I just want
chocolate, and the intersection list does not present any improvement for purposes of
getting chocolate over the first list.
I belabour the obvious here because there will be a temptation to niggle about the
example once one sees its implications. For those still inclined in this direction when the
consequences are observed, I recommend a small experiment: present the case as I did
originally to undergraduate classes, and see what response is elicited. I predict your
experience will match mine: students think the idea of constructing an intersection list
and claiming that it is a better list to use for purposes of getting chocolate is just crazy.
What I do not claim, it should be noted, is that it is impossible for a person to value the
intersection list over the first list. Someone could begin to worry about the accuracy of
the Google search engine, about the methods used to generate the lists, and could
rationally judge that more research is required before embarking on a trip to get
chocolate. Such a person could feverishly seek to calm the anxieties present, and view
finding many different web pages mentioning a place of business together with chocolate
as a sign that the chance of error was being reduced of losing out on chocolate whenever
intersection lists are constructed in this way. The more web pages from which to create
intersection lists, the better the resulting intersection list, so our anxious friend reasons.
My claim is not that it is impossible to imagine an individual who values the intersection
list over the first list, or that it is impossible for such valuing to be rational. My
inclination is to think that such individuals are making a mistake
97
of a certain sort: they show too much anxiety about the chance of missing out on
achieving a rather low-stakes goal. But even if they are not making a mistake, even if
their valuing of the intersection list is rational, it is still optional. It is at most a kind of
valuing of the intersection list that a fully informed person might make, but it is certainly
not true that it is a valuing that any fully informed person would make or needs to make.
In such cases, it is a mistake to take the valuing in question as implying any objective
value of the intersection list over the first list, as we noted earlier when discussing the
relationship between values and valuing. The intuitive point thus stands that the
intersection list is no more valuable than the first list for the purpose in question.
This last fact is the first tier in the structure of the Swamping Problem. The second tier is
the analogy between the arena of action and the arena of belief. Instead of thinking in
terms of actions based on lists, we think in terms of beliefs that correspond with items in
the book of truth and in the book of claims likely to be true. Just as actions corresponding
to items on the first list (the list of places that sell chocolate) are preferable to random
actions, so are beliefs corresponding to items in the book of truth preferable to random
beliefs. Moreover, just as actions corresponding to items on the second list (the list of
places likely to sell chocolate) are preferable to those that correspond to items not on the
second list, so are beliefs that correspond to items in the book of claims likely to be true
as compared with beliefs that correspond to items not in this book. Moreover, just as in
the case of action, beliefs that correspond with items in the book of truth are preferable to
those corresponding with items in the book of claims likely to be true. Furthermore, if we
create a new book which is the intersection of the two books already mentioned, we get a
further fact, the fact that a belief corresponding to items in the intersection book is
preferable to ones that correspond to items in second book, the book of claims likely to
be true. Finally, we also get the swamping fact: there is no advantage to having a belief
that corresponds to some item in the intersection book over having a belief that
corresponds to some item in the book of truth. In short, truth plus likelihood of truth is
not preferable to truth alone.
The analogy thus presents an argument for four claims about epistemic value, if our
theory of justification identifies it with statistical likelihood of truth: first, true belief is
better than false belief; second, justified belief is better than unjustified belief; third,
justified true belief is better than justified belief; but fourth, and most important in our
context, justified true belief is not better than true belief. These claims about preferability
and value are, of course, claims about epistemic preferability and epistemic value,
specifiable in terms of the epistemic goal as usually formulated, in terms of getting to the
truth and avoiding error.
This much of the Swamping Problem is, I think, untouchable. It is untouchable in the
initial case that adding statistical likelihood alone doesn't add value, and
98
it is untouchable that the analogy shows that one had better not identify justification with
statistical likelihood of truth. It is also clear that substituting some other notion of
objective probability for the statistical notion won't be much help either. For example,
suppose one's theory of objective probability is a propensity theory. It still remains true
that a list of places that sell chocolate is better than a list of places with a propensity to
sell chocolate, and that there is no advantage relative to the pursuit of chocolate in favour
of a list of places that both sell chocolate and have a propensity to do so over a list of
places that sell chocolate. The lesson here is that objective probability alone had better
not define one's theory of justification if one hopes to solve the Swamping Problem.
Hardly any theories of justification, and certainly none of the major players in the
contemporary scene, rely on such an identification, however, so the question arises how
we are to extend this result to raise any problem for ordinary accounts of justification. In
typical presentations of the Swamping Problem, the target is externalist theories of
justification, most especially the quite popular process reliabilist version of externalism.
So how do the results achieved so far cause a problem for process reliabilism?
I have argued with others that there are versions of externalism that have such resources
but that process reliabilism does not cite features with such resources.8 After all, if
objective probability itself succumbs to the Swamping Problem, why would the fact that
there is an etiological relationship to a process or method responsible for that probability
relieve the theory of the problem? Such a causal relationship to methods or processes
does not seem to be the kind of feature that adds value beyond the value of true belief, so
there is no apparent reason here to think that ordinary process reliabilism is in a better
condition with respect to the Swamping Problem than is the simple objective probability
theory. Resistance to this claim can be found in recent literature on the subject, but I will
argue that these defences of process reliabilism fail to come to grips with the real
Swamping Problem as described above, and instead only succeed at blocking certain
other versions of the problem that are much easier to avoid.
TASK 3: THE PROPOSALS OF GOLDMAN AND OLSSON
In a recent article, Alvin Goldman and Erik Olsson (2009) propose two different ways to
try to respond to the Swamping Problem. Both approaches go beyond
99
the identification of justification with objective likelihood of truth, and thus provide some
hope of avoiding the Swamping Problem. The first approach is the conditional
probability approach:
What is this extra valuable property that distinguishes knowledge from true belief? It is
the property of making it likely that one's future beliefs of a similar kind will also be true.
More precisely, under reliabilism, the probability of having more true belief (of a similar
kind) in the future is greater conditional on S's knowing that p than conditional on S's
merely truly believing that p. Let's call this proposed solution to the EVOK problem the
conditional probability solution. Probability should here be interpreted objectively.
(Goldman and Olsson 2009: 28)
The claim here is that if we condition on knowing versus truly believing, the likelihood of
being correct in the future goes up. But obviously not for just any old kind of belief, but
for a special kind. Which kind is that? Well, for beliefs of a similar kind, the probability
goes up when conditioning on knowledge rather than on mere true belief.
Once we appreciate the nature of the Swamping Problem as a problem concerning
properties of belief that are non-additive of value in the presence of true belief, it
becomes hard to see how the above proposal is helpful at all. In the analogy involving
chocolate, I don't even know how to begin thinking about applying this idea to new
businesses of the same type, conditional on the first list (places that sell chocolate) and
the third list (places that both sell chocolate and are likely to).
There is an answer to my perplexity, however. The proposal is not really the proposal
above involving conditioning only on the two lists in question, but a rather more complex
proposal involving several contingencies. Goldman and Olsson note that the proposal
depends on contingent regularities in order to derive the conclusion that one of the
conditional probabilities is higher than the other, and they say,
To see what roles these regularities play, suppose S knows that p. By the reliabilist
definition of knowledge, there is a reliable method M that was invoked by S so as to
produce S's belief that p. By non-uniqueness, it is likely that the same type of problem
will arise again for S in the future. By cross-temporal access, the method M is likely to be
available to S when this happens. By the learning assumption, S is likely to make use of
M again on that occasion. By generality, M is likely to be reliable for solving that similar
future problem as well. Since M is reliable, this new application of M is likely to result in
a new true belief. Thus the fact that S has knowledge on a given occasion makes it to
some extent likely that S will acquire further true beliefs in the future. The degree to
which S's knowledge has this value depends on how likely it is that this will happen.
This, in turn, depends on the degree to which the assumptions of non-uniqueness, cross-
temporal access, learning and generality are satisfied in a given case.
(Goldman and Olsson 2009: 2930)
So the claim is not that the conditional inequality explains the value of knowledge over
that of true belief. The claim is, rather, that when certain contingent
100
features are in place, we should expect the conditional probability of future true beliefs to
be higher, given that one knows rather than that one merely truly believes.
This response, however, fails to come to grips with the core of the Swamping Problem.
As we have seen, once the relevant controls are in place, we should expect, always and
necessarily, for knowledge to be a value-enhancing characteristic of a state of true belief,
not just such a characteristic when the person is likely to use the same method in the
future and the world hasn't changed so that what was reliable in the past is no longer so.
To uncover the special value of knowledge, we have to control for interaction by values
outside the purely cognitive sphere, but once we do so, we should find that knowledge is
special. It is not only special when the future resembles the past and when people retain
their dispositions across time of how to find out what the world is like. Perhaps we are
stuck having to adopt such a revisionary account of the value of knowledge, but we
shouldn't offer such an account and pretend that it is not radically revisionary.
Why do I insist that this account is revisionary? I spent some time on this issue in my
book,9 and here I will offer a brief reminder. There are worlds in which my coming to
know one more thing makes certain that the world will end. So suppose I just now have
come to know one more thing. In such worlds, the likelihood of my having any future
beliefs at all, true or otherwise, conditional on knowing versus truly believing, is the
same: zero. But this probability does not undermine the fact that I ended my cognitive
career on a high note. I learned something, and that is a good thing. There may be other
more important things on which to end a life: bringing about world peace, for example.
And certainly, from an all-things-considered perspective, it would have been better had I
not achieved this additional learning. But merely acquiring a true belief wouldn't have
been as good from a purely cognitive point of view, and we deserve an explanation of
that. In this way, and in others discussed in my book, the conditional probability of the
future offers no hope of being able to explain the special value of knowledge.
Goldman and Olsson have another proposal. It involves a main idea and what they term a
subsidiary part. The main idea is that reliable processes come to possess autonomous'
value, value that is not dependent on the value of the resultant true beliefs. The subsidiary
part arises because they believe that the Swamping Problem assumes that, according to
reliabilism, the value of a token reliable process derives from the value of the token belief
it produces' (2009: 31) and they thus wish to argue that a token of a reliable process has
value even when it does not produce a token true belief. I think they are mistaken in this
concern. Nothing in the account of the problem described above assumes that reliable
process tokens have value only when they produce true beliefs. Perhaps there is a need
for an explanation as to why reliable false beliefs are more valuable than
101
unreliable false beliefs, but a defender of the Swamping Problem need hold no brief on
this question in order to show concern about the non-additive character of whatever value
accrues to reliable processes in the presence of true belief. We can thus stipulate for
present purposes that token reliable processes have value whether or not they cause token
true beliefs, in order to focus on the main part of the proposal.
Regarding the main point, they say,
The crucial feature of our proposed explanation is an elucidation of the psychological
mechanisms whereby reliable belief-forming processes come to be accorded
autonomous' value. Although the ascribed value of reliable processes is initially
derivative from the ascribed value of the true beliefs they cause, reliable processes
ultimately acquire autonomous valuevalue that isn't dependent, on a case-by-case
basis, on the value of resultant true beliefs. (Goldman and Olsson 2009: 31)
Goldman and Olsson thus claim a special value for reliable processes, what they term
autonomous' value.
How could this proposal help solve the Swamping Problem? I think the idea is that it is
supposed to show how a reliable process can have a kind of value that is not wholly
derivative on the value of true belief itself, and thus provides some hope of adding special
value on top of whatever value true belief has in virtue of being true. They write,
The main possibility we suggest is that a certain type of state that initially has merely
(type-) instrumental value eventually acquires independent, or autononomous, value
status. We call such a process value autonomization. (Goldman and Olsson 2009: 33)
And regarding the crucial notion of autonomy at work in the proposal, they say,
Value autonomization is a psychological hypothesis, which concerns our practices of
ascribing or attributing value to various states of affairs.
(Goldman and Olsson 2009: 34)
So the idea is that, though processes that produce true beliefs initially acquire all of their
value from this instrumental relationship to truth, these processes come to be valued in an
autonomous way or a way independent of this relationship to truth. In this way, a
different kind of value is present in reliable true belief than is present in true belief alone.
Goldman and Olsson immediately notice the objection that the kind of value to be
explained is objective value and that their proposal only involves an appeal to subjective
valuings by individuals rather than some objective value itself. They rightly point out that
it is methodologically reasonable to assume a connection between the two, on the same
grounds that it is reasonable to construct theories with some (defeasible) reliance on
intuitions. But this response does not address the heart of the problem. As we noted
earlier, one can't read off objective
102
value from the mere possibility of some subjective valuing, nor can we infer the objective
value of some item from the fact that some people rationally value it. Instead, something
stronger is required, something like the claim that a fully informed individual not only
might value the item in question (in a special way) but that such an individual would
value it in this special way.
It is crucial to note that nothing in the proposal by Goldman and Olsson provides any
basis for the stronger claim. All they have is a story about how reliable processes might
come to have a special kind of autonomous value. It is worth pointing out that a similar
story could be told about mere statistical likelihood itself: we can imagine the process of
value autonomization applying to statistically likely beliefs so that they came to have
autonomous value. Doing so would force us into the position of claiming, in the original
chocolate example, that the third intersection list has more objective value than the first
list, the list of places that sell chocolate. Since that conclusion is mistaken, we should
look for an explanation of the mistake, and the explanation is not hard to find. The
explanation is that it isn't sufficient just to note that there is some psychological
mechanism that could easily lead to some independent value for some property added to
true belief. Instead, one needs an explanation of why a fully informed individual would
autonomize in the way imagined or why one's better self, fully informed, would prefer
that one autonomize in that way.
In this respect, the approaches of Goldman and Olsson are best thought of as in need of
supplementation in order to provide any hope of success. As we will see in the next
section, there is in the literature a proposal that provides just such an extension, and so we
can complete our evaluation of the GoldmanOlsson proposal by turning to the appeal to
final value by process reliabilists to avoid the Swamping Problem.
TASK 4: THE APPEAL TO FINAL VALUE
The appeal to final value arises by noting recent work in the theory of value that is
ignored by those who raise the Swamping Problem. Those who raise the Swamping
Problem distinguish between intrinsic value and extrinsic value, but fail to take account
of the distinction between instrumental value and final value. For example, Duncan
Pritchard says,
One problem with this argument is that it appears to rest on a failure to recognise an
important distinction that is common currency in value theory. In particular, the value
distinction that this argument ignores is that between intrinsic value, where an object's
value is determined by its intrinsic properties, and final value, where we value an object
for its own sake (i.e., non-instrumentally). The Swamping Problem in effect presupposes
that the only way that the relational properties of a true beliefin particular, the way that
the belief was formedcould contribute value would be instrumentally. But that is to
103
simply ignore the possibility that the relational properties of a true belief could contribute
final value. (2007a: 6)10
Here I will put aside any concerns that there may be no such value as final value and will
assume with Pritchard and others that there is a distinction needed between final value
and the more familiar notions of intrinsic and extrinsic value. Since the notion of final
value is a relatively new discovery, it will be useful to have some examples of such, and
Pritchard is helpful on this point:
Consider, for example, a book printed on the first ever printing press and an exact replica
produced by lasers. We would undoubtedly value the former more than the latter even
though we can accept, for the sake of argument, that these two objects have the same
relevant intrinsic properties. Moreover, we would value the former for its own sake, quite
apart from what instrumental value it had (e.g. its monetary value). The difference in
value, however, is clearly due to the relational properties of the objects concerned. The
reason for this difference in value is that a book printed on the first ever printing press,
unlike an exact replica, has final valueit is valuable for its own sake because of how it is
produced (i.e. its relational properties). (2007a: 6)
The key claim here, as far as argument goes, is the first two sentences of the first quoted
passage above. The first sentence notes that usual formulations of the Swamping Problem
ignore a distinction between final and intrinsic value. That point is certainly true, but by
itself no more telling than noting that the argument also ignores present diplomatic
tensions in the Middle East. The key argumentative move is in the second sentence: In
order to see that the Swamping Problem turns on a failure to recognise this distinction,
one only needs to note that the problem in effect presupposes that sameness of intrinsic
properties entails sameness of value. So ignoring the distinction between intrinsic and
final value differs from ignoring certain diplomatic tensions. Why is that? Because the
Swamping Problem in some way depends on a Moorean conception of value: that
sameness of intrinsic properties entails sameness of value.
I want to pursue two separate lines of response to this complaint. First, I want to show
that the Swamping Problem does not depend on a Moorean conception of value, and
second that the distinction in question offers no hope to the process reliabilist in replying
to the Swamping Problem.
So first, about the argument itself: I think it is instructive to note that as I developed the
problem above, it never mentions distinctions in value at all except to distinguish purely
cognitive values from other values such as those deriving from practical concerns. Given
such distinctions among types of value deriving from different ends or goals, the problem
as I developed it focuses on an additivity failure. Take whatever purely cognitive value is
found in true belief and add statistical likelihood of truth to it, and you are guaranteed no
added value.
104
The rest of the argument can be put in the form of a challenge to reliabilists: tell us what
features beyond statistical likelihood your theory involves and how these additional
features add value to the value of true belief. The first step of this argument, concerning
the additivity failure for statistical likelihood surely presupposes no Moorean conception
of value. Moreover, there is no reason I can see to think that the Moorean conception is
involved in denying that the challenge to process reliabilists can be met. Of course, if the
Moorean thesis were true, we could explain why the non-additivity feature occurs, but we
could do the same if value nihilism were true, and nobody is accusing the argument of
presupposing that.
So I don't think the claim that the Swamping Problem presupposes a Moorean conception
of value is correct. What is true is that some presentations of the problem have endorsed
the Moorean conception, but that is not sufficient to show that an appeal to final value
will somehow undermine the Swamping Problem. The Swamping Problem doesn't
presuppose the Moorean view, and thus attacking the Moorean view won't allow any
view to escape the Swamping Problem even if the attack on Mooreanism is successful.
Even if the Swamping Problem does not disappear on grounds of presupposing
Mooreanism, however, the distinction between final and intrinsic value may yet provide
the resources for escaping the problem. If we attend to the usual examples of the
distinction between final and intrinsic value, things do not look promising, though. The
primary example in the literature is Princess Diana's dress as opposed to a mere duplicate
of it, while Pritchard's preferred example is the first book off Gutenberg's press versus a
duplicate of it. Such examples take us in a direction wholly unhelpful to reliabilists. The
final value involved in these cases is clearly dependent on the uniqueness of the items in
question, and value depending on uniqueness of method or process is clearly a dead end
in attempting to reply to the Swamping Problem.
Uniqueness, however, is not essential here, since other examples can be found where
uniqueness is absent. Instead of focusing on Guttenberg's first offering or Diana's dress,
we might want to focus on paintings by great artists, untouched wildernesses, first-edition
books, Wedgwood china over mass-produced reproductions, and artefacts from ancient
civilizations. Such examples involve rarity, but not uniqueness.
The move from uniqueness to rarity is not enough, however. While it may be true that
certain pieces of knowledge are more prized than others because of their rarity, this value
is not the kind threatened by the Swamping Problem. It may be true that we find
wondrous and precious and fascinating the special knowledge found in theoretical
physics, but this value does not generalize to our legitimate valuing of comparatively
mundane knowing, such as knowing where to find a good set of tires at a decent price.
The solution to the Swamping Problem has to have a kind of generality that doesn't
depend on the rarity of knowledge, and perhaps we can put this point starkly by noting
that it doesn't take closer and
105
closer approximations to the truth of radical scepticism to uncover a solution to the Meno
problem. To the extent that the examples of final value depend on the rarity, there is little
of comfort for reliabilists to be found in the distinction between final and intrinsic value.
But can't the reliabilist appeal here to the relative rarity of knowledge compared with the
much larger class of belief itself? Such an appeal is surely correct: knowledge is rarer
than belief, and rarer than true belief as well. But such a response contains the seeds of its
own destruction, for imagine a world in which knowledge is coextensive with true belief
(or even belief itself). In such a world, knowledge would have no final value over and
above the value of true belief or belief itself, given the assumption that final value is tied
to rarity. The appeal to final value thus could not account for the special value of
knowledge for such worlds, and would have to adopt the procrustean and revisionary
strategy of fitting the phenomena to the theory instead of providing a theory adequate to
the phenomena.
The only way to avoid this difficulty is to insist that rarity is just an artefact of the usual
examples chosen, rather than an essential feature of the notion of final value. Reliabilists
might note that the examples involve not only rarity, but an etiological component as
well. Perhaps it is this etiological component, rather than rarity, that is the key. If such an
etiological component is the key, and an etiological feature is what distinguishes justified
true beliefs from unjustified true beliefs, then perhaps the final value of the former
exceeds that of the latter.
This is not exactly a compelling argument: it's more like a wish and a hope. Moreover,
once we think a bit more carefully about the notion of final value, we will see why the
appeal to etiological features doesn't really help. We should begin by noting that final
value begins with valuing in a particular way. The usual distinction between intrinsic and
extrinsic value is a distinction involving the objects of value themselves, but the
distinction between valuing for its own sake and valuing for the sake of something else,
the distinction involved in the notion of final value, is a distinction between two types of
valuing. We may want to construct some more objective notion of value out of the notion
of valuing for its own sake, but we need first to notice that the fundamental notion is one
concerning something we do as evaluators. The idea here is that we should focus first on
different types of valuings rather than different types of values. Viewed in this way, we
have two orthogonal sets of distinctions: we have things that are intrinsically valuable
and things that are extrinsically valuable, and we can value such things either for their
own sakes or for the sake of something else. We thus have the possibility of something of
merely extrinsic value that is nonetheless valued for its own sake.11
106
Once we get clear in this way about the notion of final value, we can see a danger lurking
along this path of appeal. In more cynical moments, we can ask ourselves what difference
it really makes to the value of a thing whether Princess Diana wore it. We can understand
the human desire for identification with celebrities, the associational connotations of it
all, while at the same time knowing that this is all a way of coping with the lack of
recognition that is part of almost everybody's mundane existence. And Guttenberg's first
book is a relic, to be sure, but our interest in historical artefacts need not indicate
anything really important at all, but may just be a typical over-generalization from the
usefulness that attending to some of history plays in our practical lives. More generally,
we know of things that have purely instrumental value that end up being valued for their
own sake by distorted souls. Money is the classic example. Lovers of money of this sort
abound. They value money for its own sake, even though the only value it really has is
instrumental in character. So travelling down the path of distinguishing what we value
from what is valuable is worth doing, but if the kinds of valuing that would help avoid the
Swamping Problem all turn out to be nothing more than all too human foibles, the appeal
to final value will leave us with an unsatisfactory response to the Swamping Problem. We
would have to admit that knowledge is no more important than true belief, even if we
typically treat it as being so.
I do not wish to rely on such cynicism here, however, for there is a deeper worry. This
deeper worry can be seen once we recognize that the fundamental notion concerning final
valuing involves a way of valuing things, and then remind ourselves of what would be
needed to turn this subjective notion into something objective enough to account for the
special and unique value of knowledge or the special value of reliable true belief over
that of true belief. For this valuing to yield any conclusion about the value of knowledge
or reliability, the valuing must not be some idiosyncratic feature of some individual or
group of individuals. It is, of course, possible for process reliabilists to so cherish their
magnificent theory that they value the beliefs that result for their own sake on the basis of
the etiology of such beliefs in processes or methods that make for objective likelihood of
truth. As noted earlier, more is needed for valuings to provide the resources to explain the
value of knowledge. What is needed is some way to leap the chasm from subjective
valuing to objective value. We may grant to the defender of the final value of knowledge
that knowledge is valued in the final way at least by some people, but how do we get
from this claim to the claim that there is a value found in knowledge that is not found in,
say, true belief? The point here is not the items of comparison, but rather how we get
from a point that is fundamentally about a subjective state to one that is about something
not subjective.
The only available answer is that some values are response-dependent values, that some
things have value because they are the kind of thing that a fully
107
informed individual (in the right kind of circumstances) would value. So, the defender of
the final value proposal might claim that a fully informed individual in the right
circumstances would value reliable true belief in this final way, and that it is this
response-dependent value that provides a solution to the Swamping Problem for
reliabilism.
It is fairly easy to see how such an individual might value reliable true belief in this final
way, but nothing in the story about reliability itself yields any basis for concluding that
such an individual would value reliable true belief in this way. My scepticism here
derives from comparing this claim with the simple statistical likelihood proposal with
which we began. Adding mere statistical likelihood of truth to true belief was obviously a
non-starter in explaining the value of knowledge over that of true belief itself. But there is
no reason to suppose that an individual might not value statistical likelihood of truth in
the final way. Such a possibility, however, is not enough. What is needed is some account
of why ordinary folk would value reliability in the final way, if fully informed and in the
right circumstances, whereas they would not value statistical likelihood in that way even
though fully informed and in the right circumstances. Failure to produce an account that
discriminates between reliability and statistical likelihood leaves the defender of final
value still susceptible to the Swamping Problem, since it was obvious from the start that
the statistical likelihood proposal succumbs to the Swamping Problem.
Moreover, I doubt we have the kinds of responses needed to give any hope to this final
value proposal. We simply don't have the responses predicted by the final value proposal
to cases in which statistical likelihood with the specific etiological features central to
reliability is added to true belief, responses that are obviously present in other cases of
response-dependent value. When I look at a shard of earthenware and act uninterested,
you can urge me to change my attitude by saying, But that's from the Mayan
civilization! My eyes light up, I'm now impressed, and I treat the shard with much
greater care. When you show me a first-edition Jane Austen, I'm more reverent than
otherwise. But when you tell me about a statistically likely opinion that is true, and note
with appropriate fervour that its statistical likelihood is the causal result of a process that
is reliable, I wonder what point you are trying to make. Why should I care about that? I
just don't get it.
Of course, you can retort that there's lots of stuff I don't get. But I don't think you get it
either. Think of the untouched wilderness compared to the parts of the world on which
humans have already intruded, first-edition books and all the rest, Picasso paintings, and
perfect replicas. When learning the final-value-imputing fact, there is an aha! response
(when the example is a good example of final valuenothing here turns on whether the
particular contrasts I've listed really are good examples or whether other examples are
more appropriate). When learning
108
that likelihood is caused by a reliable process, there is a ho-hum response. It would be
advantageous to the defender of the idea that there is response-dependent, anti-realist
value of the sort needed to address the Swamping Problem if ordinary human beings such
as we are had the aha! response. But we don't, and the fact that we don't provides some
evidence against the claim that the needed response-dependent value is present.
We have to be careful here, however. You may have the aha! response when you
compare a belief with a reliable belief, but that is the wrong comparison. Remember that
the Swamping Problem is a value problem that arises once truth is in the picture. So the
comparison has to be this: start with a true belief, and then add statistical likelihood of
truth and then the etiological component as well. It is this comparison that, I claim,
generates no systematic or uniform aha! response. Once truth is in the picture here,
adding reliability fails to impress.
A final point is worth making as well. The value of things is sometimes the result of
features of those things themselves and sometimes the result of our caring about them.
Put somewhat differently, sometimes the direction of explanation goes from features of
things to our valuing them, and sometimes the direction of explanation goes from our
caring about them to the value that they have. Perhaps unspoiled wildernesses have the
value they have because we care about such things, but the order of explanation goes the
other way when it comes to matters involving fundamental human rights. The appeal to
final value to solve the Swamping Problem presupposes that the explanation of the value
of knowledge over that of true belief should be explained in one of these directions, and it
is the wrong direction. I value this particular watch because it was my grandfather's, and I
care about him. But I don't value knowledge like that. Knowledge is a wonderful thing,
and it is because of what it is that I value it. The direction of explanation goes from
knowledge and its features to my caring about it, not the other way around. Any
explanation that starts the explanatory story from the way in which we value knowledge
gets the order of explanation wrong.
One may resist at this point by noting the popularity of response-dependent accounts of
all value, of whatever sort, according to which values always depend on what our
responses are or would be.12 Such accounts face the burden of avoiding the conditional
fallacy,13 but I will not rely on such difficulties in order
109
to respond to this point. For whatever the merits of response-dependent accounts of
value, the point above is not a theory-driven point, but rather a datum that must be
explained by any adequate theory of value. Final value is, at the initial stage, a matter of
the way we value things, and the reification of this phenomenon into an item that is
useful for solving the Swamping Problem involves an appeal to the ubiquity or
uniformity of valuing certain things in this final way, at least in idealized conditions. The
things valued in the final way fall into two classes. Some such valuings are idiosyncratic
(such as treasuring one's collection of spent cartridges from some weapon) or unusual
enough in some other way, so that no reification from valuing to the presence of a value
is legitimate. In other cases, there is ubiquity or uniformity enough to the valuing, as with
unspoiled wildernesses, relics of various sorts, and the like. There is enough uniformity in
these latter cases that it is legitimate to reify, so long as we note that the value present is
explanatorily dependent on the valuing in question. Even if all value is response-
dependent, there is much that is valuable that does not fit this pattern, for much that is
valuable is not treasured or respected enough (or is easily imagined to be so). In such a
case, the nature of the explanation of value given by defenders of the response-
dependence of value will be different. The explanation will need to appeal to what would
be appreciated if the people in question were better informed or in different
circumstances. Such an explanation is not an explanation that reifies valuing into values,
but rather explains value as response-dependent without undermining the point that
sometimes the order of explanation runs from caring to importance and other times it runs
the other way. We might put the point this way, if we assume that a response-dependent
account is acceptable. Given this assumption, sometimes the counterfactuals involved in
the objective value in question are true independently of what people actually value, and
sometimes they are true because of what people value in the actual circumstances in
which we find ourselves. Sometimes, that is, things would be valued in idealized
circumstances because of the way they are valued in actual circumstances, and sometimes
this order of explanation is unavailable or incorrect.
So, even if all value is response-dependent in some way, the datum cited remains:
sometimes the explanation of value runs from features of things to our valuing them and
other times from our valuing things to their value. The general difficulty raised by this
datum for the final value proposal thus remains. The special and unique value of
knowledge over that of true belief is a value in which the order of explanation goes from
the nature and function of knowledge to our valuing it rather than the other way around.
The appeal to final value explicitly reverses this order of explanation, and thus cannot
give an adequate account of the value of knowledge or a solution to the Swamping
Problem.
110
CONCLUSION
The lesson to learn here is that the Swamping Problem is a much deeper problem than
these solutions appear to recognize. Probabilities concerning the future don't help, an
appeal to the type/token distinction is a non-starter, and appeals to final value are not
successful either. The conclusion to draw is that if there is a successful defence of process
reliabilism against the Swamping Problem, we have yet to see it.
111
6 From Epistemic Expressivism to Epistemic Inferentialism
Matthew Chrisman
1. INTRODUCTION
Ordinary people often make epistemic claims. For example, they claim to know the
whereabouts of a misplaced book, or that someone else knows whether Jones will be at
the party, and they might even do something reconstructable as claiming that Suzy's
belief is justified even though false or claiming that Henry's belief is justified and true
though not a case of knowledge. Insofar as they make such claims, presumably they are
at least somewhat concerned to do so rightly. Epistemologists make such epistemic
claims too and are, of course, also concerned to do so rightly. However, they often give
priority over these epistemological issues to what I think can only be viewed as meta-
epistemological issues. These are issues not about whether this or that epistemic claim is
correct but about things like the standard for knowledge, the nature of epistemic
justification, the possibility of rational response to sceptical arguments, and the meaning
of epistemic claims.
Concerning this final issue, recent philosophical debate has largely centred on the
question of whether epistemic claims are plausibly thought to be context sensitive. The
default assumption has been that sentences that attribute knowledge or justification (or
whatever else is epistemic) have stable truth conditions across different contexts of
utterance, once any non-epistemic context sensitivity has been fixed. The idea, for
instance, is that sentences of the form S knows that p have stable truth conditions once
the values of S and p (plus any implicit temporal elements) are fixed. The contrary view
is the contextualist thesis that such sentences do not have stable truth conditions but can
vary depending on the context of utterance. So, for instance, even once we've fixed the
values of S and p the sentence S knows that p could still be true when tokened in one
context, while false when tokened in another context, since the truth conditions of this
sentence depend in part on some
112
contextually varying element such as the strength of evidence required for knowledge.1
This debate manifestly presupposes that the meta-epistemological issue of accounting for
the meaning of epistemic claims is to be settled by determining the truth conditions of
these claims. I think this presupposition is probably false and, in any case, way too quick.
This is for two interlocking reasons. First, many epistemologists see epistemic claims as
evaluative or normative, in some sense.2 However, in the meta-ethical debatewhich has
really become a meta-normative debatemost participants take alternatives to truth-
conditional semantics, such as expressivism, as live options. Second, from a pragmatist
view on meaning (that I think makes contact with the remit of social epistemology) a
natural way to approach the meaning of epistemic claims would be to ask not about their
truth conditions but about what practical function they serve in our commerce with one
another and other aspects of the world. It could be that, even if we agree about the truth
conditions of knowledge attributions, there's still an important meta-epistemological
question to be settled about their linguistic and conceptual role.
These two reasons correlate with two moments in a line of thought whose name I have
taken for the title of this chapter. My purpose in it is to flesh out this line of thought and
then indicate how I think it could help to enrich meta-epistemological theorizing in a way
that appreciates the specially social character of epistemic claim-making.
2. ETHICAL EXPRESSIVISM AND EPISTEMIC EXPRESSIVISM
In the meta-ethical debate, ethical expressivists encourage us to ask not about the nature
of ethical facts or values but instead about the nature of ethical evaluations. They do so
because they think we can satisfactorily answer the latter question without ever
countenancing some sui generis kind of thingethical facts or valuesto answer the
first question. Their idea is that ethical evaluations are not representations of how the
world is; rather, they are expressions of our attitudes towards the way we represent the
world to be. Specifically, ethical claims are seen not as descriptions of the world but as
expressions of our ethical attitudes
113
towards things like actions, agents' characters, systems of rules, social structures, and so
forth.
From the perspective of a truth-conditional semantics, which takes notions like truth and
reference as its master concepts, the semantics for ethical claims that results from the
standard sort of expressivism will appear quite radical.3 In effect, it is the view that
ethical sentences mean what they do in virtue of the state of mind that they express,
rather than in virtue of the facts they purport to represent.
However, this semantical idea is not without at least some historical inspiration and
contemporary allies in the philosophy of language. A rich alternative semantic
programme, which is at home with this idea across the board, traces back through Grice
at least to Locke. This is the ideationalist or psychologistic approach to meaning,
which is inspired by Locke's view that Words in their primary or immediate
Signification, stand for nothing, but the Ideas in the Mind of him that uses them (1975:
405). In its contemporary manifestation, the project is to understand semantic content in
terms of conventional regularities linking overt use of a sentence with a particular idea or
state of mind.4 Accordingly, all sentences are thought to mean what they do in virtue of
the state of mind that they express. And, if we embrace this idea in our philosophy of
language, it then opens up room for the expressivist to argue that the conventional
regularities of our language are such that descriptive sentences mean what they do in
virtue of expressing specific beliefs while ethical sentences mean what they do in virtue
of expressing specific desire-like moral attitudes. Because of this, I think expressivism is
naturally married to an ideationalist alternative to truth-conditional semantics.5
But what exactly does the expressivist say is the desire-like moral attitude expressed by
ethical sentences? The details won't matter much here, but to have a toy expressivist
theory on the table, we can use a simplification of Gibbard's (1990) leading idea. That is,
we can think of the sentence X is good as meaning what it does in virtue of the fact that
it express one's acceptance of a system of ethical norms which one believes to encourage
the promotion of X.6 Expressivist
114
views like this one purport to carry at least two theoretical advantages, which I'll now try
to characterize in a rough and ready way.
First, expressivist views claim to have a very simple and intuitive explanation of the
apparent practicality of ethical discourse. The rough idea is that the making of ethical
claims seems to be intimately and causally linked with motivation to action; if, for
example, one judges that giving to charity is good but displays no motivation to give to
charity, then something seems to be amiss. And on a popular Humean view7 motivation
to action always requires the agent to have some desire-like attitude. Expressivism gives
us just such an attitude in its account of what is expressed by ethical claims, which
generates its explanation of the intuitive practicality of ethical claim-making.
Second, expressivist views claim to avoid queerness/placement problems for ethical facts
and values. This is initially an ontological issue, but it is closely related to a conceptual
issue having to do with a different sense in which ethical discourse is intuitively practical.
The initial idea is that ethical facts, conceived as judgement-independent facts in the
world, seem to be neither ontologically reducible to other facts whose existence is not in
question nor locatable in the spatio-temporal world governed by empirically discoverable
physical laws. Why? Because ethical judgements seem to have a special connection to
motivation to action. Roughly, they seem to commit their author to a reason to act in a
particular way, irrespective of any desire to do so. For example, if one judges that giving
to charity is good, then one seems to be committed to thinking that there is a reason to
give to charity. If we view such judgements as representing the world, then they purport
to describe facts which, if they existed would seem to have the power to attract our wills
irrespective of our desires. This can make ethical facts appear queer in the sense that they
purport to have a reason-giving power not had by any other kind of fact.8 Now, there is
plenty of room for debate about whether this is the only plausible conception of ethical
concepts and facts or whether the reduction of ethical facts to less queer facts is after all
possible. However, because of the very controversies involved in this debate, any meta-
ethical view ontologically committed to ethical facts or values bears a theoretical cost not
borne by views that do not. Expressivism claims to avoid this cost in its contention that
ethical concepts (and perhaps normative concepts more broadly) have their distinctive
function in making claims that express desire-like attitudes rather than describe or
represent the world.9
115
This is a brief outline of what ethical expressivism is and two reasons for endorsing it. It's
a curious fact that very few philosophers have sought to defend or even recognized the
theoretical possibility of a meta-epistemological analogue to ethical expressivism.10 This
is in spite of several obvious parallels. First, it's now commonplace (even if still
controversial) for philosophers to insist that epistemic notions like knowledge and
justification are normative, and many epistemologists are interested in norms of
belief.11 Second, some epistemologists have become quite puzzled about the nature and
location of epistemic values, thinking now that if the value of knowledge were merely
instrumental value for the goal of truth that it would be swamped once one has the truth
by whatever means.12 Third, several pragmatist-inspired philosophers have asked about
the social role of epistemic concepts such as knowledge and come up with an account
according to which this concept is not used directly to describe people but rather to do
something like compliment (Rorty 1979, 1995), tag (Craig 1990), or keep the books on
the ways in which various people track, process, and transmit information (Brandom
2000a: ch. 3; Rosenberg 2002: ch. 5).
In an earlier paper (Chrisman 2007), I provisionally argued for a version of epistemic
expressivism not on the basis of these parallels but on the basis of the fact that it
addresses two pervasive objections to epistemic contextualism while retaining the
advantages of that view. I want to leave this argument to the side here, except to say that
what resulted was a view that encourages us to ask not about the nature of epistemic facts
and values but instead about the nature of epistemic evaluations. It did so with the typical
hope of expressivist views to answer the latter question without ever needing to
countenance some sui generis kind of thingepistemic facts or valuesto answer the
former question. The idea is the same as before: epistemic evaluations are not seen as
representations of how the world is; they are seen as expressions of our attitudes towards
the way we represent the world to be. In particular, they involve expressions of our
distinctively epistemic attitudes towards things like believers, beliefs, and types of
evidence and justification.
As before, from the perspective of truth-conditional semantics, the resulting semantics for
epistemic claims is apt to seem quite radical. However,
116
epistemic expressivists seem to have at least some support from ideationalist or
psychologistic approaches to meaning on their side (as well, of course, ethical
expressivists) in arguing that epistemic sentences could mean what they do in virtue of
the state of mind that they express, rather than in virtue of what they represent.
The epistemic parallel to the toy version of ethical expressivism above would hold
something similar about attributions of justification and knowledge. For example, it
might hold that to say S is justified in believing that p is to express one's acceptance of
a system of epistemic norms which one believes to positively value S's belief that p. And,
sloughing over a few details, we might extend this by claiming that to say S knows that
p is to express one's acceptance of a system of epistemic norms, which one takes to
positively value S's true belief that p. In addition to retaining advantages of contextualism
while overcoming two of its problems (if the argument of my previous paper is correct),
this view would carry at least one of the same theoretical advantages as ethical
expressivism.
This is the second advantage mentioned above: Epistemic expressivism would avoid
queerness/placement problems for epistemic facts and concepts. Philosophers have been
less concerned about the ontological status of epistemic facts and values than ethical facts
and values; however, arguably, whatever naturalistic inclinations motivate concern about
the queerness/placement of ethical facts or concepts, the same naturalistic inclinations
should motivate the same concerns about epistemic facts and concepts, insofar as we're
conceiving of these as genuinely normative (whatever, exactly that means). If that is
right, then epistemic expressivism would avoid an ontological/conceptual cost in its
contention that epistemic concepts function like ethical concepts to make claims that
express attitudes rather than describe or represent the world.
The other advantage typically claimed for ethical expressivism was its intuitive
explanation of the practicality of ethical discourse, and it is perhaps because epistemic
discourse isn't seen as similarly practical that epistemologists have ignored that accounts
of the meaning of epistemic claims that don't turn on the truth conditions of these claims,
such as expressivist accounts. After all, claiming, for example, that Plato knew nothing
about Google does not seem to be as tightly connected to being motivated to act in a
particular way as claiming, for example, that charity is good. However, although I think
it's probably correct that epistemic discourse is not practical in exactly the same way that
expressivists claim that ethical discourse is practical, I suspect that epistemic discourse is
interestingly practical in another sense that encourages rethinking the pervasive
presupposition in epistemology about how best to approach an account of the meaning of
epistemic claims.
More on this in 4, but first I want to discuss anotherto my mind, better and more
generalreason for being wary of epistemic expressivism as an account
117
13
of the meaning of epistemic claims. A brief and somewhat dogmatic discussion of the
notorious FregeGeach problem in meta-ethics will help to expose this reason.
3. EXPRESSIVISM'S DISCONTENTS
There are other views going under the label expressivism on the meta-normative scene14
, but one of the main challenges for views, which hold that normative claims mean what
they do in virtue of the type of desire-like attitude that they express, is to explain, in a
systematic way, the logic of normative concepts in all of their uses. Normative concepts
are clearly used not only atomically but also in logically complex contexts. We say things
not only like X is good but also like If X is good, then Y is good; not only like S's
belief that p is justified but also like If S's belief that p is justified, then S's belief that q
is not justified. If expressivists say that the atomic claims mean what they do in virtue of
expressing a desire-like attitude, what will they say about the logically complex claims?
It seems that one could endorse these claims without expressing a desire-like attitude
(towards X or Y, or towards S's belief that p or S's belief that q). This is the FregeGeach
problem (Geach 1965).
In my view, ethical expressivism in its early forms suffered the FregeGeach problem
because, in effect, it treated the meaning of normative predicates as given completely by
the expressive force of applying them in making an atomic normative claim. This is why
Ayer suggested that atomic moral claims like Stealing money is wrong have no factual
meaning and express no proposition. But such a view is hopeless when it comes to
explaining the semantic properties of normative predicates embedded in force-stripping
contexts such as conditionals. There must be some stable content between Stealing
money is wrong and the antecedent of If stealing money is wrong, then it will be good
thieves are punished, if we're to view a modus ponens inference proceeding from these
premises to be innocent of the fallacy of equivocation.
Interestingly, Ayer's view of complex normative sentences of another type may, if
suitably generalized, provide some traction against this problem. For the case of a
complex normative sentence, he suggested that the sentence has descriptive content that
is presented in a particular way. His example is the claim Your stealing that money was
wrong, and he suggests that it expresses the proposition that you stole that money, but it
presents this proposition in a special way that
118
could in principle be replaced by a special form of exclamation marks indicating a
speaker's contempt for the action mentioned. What is interesting is that this can help to
capture some stable content across unembedded and embedded contexts for such
complex claims. For Ayer can say that the same proposition is the content of the
antecedent of If your stealing that money was wrong, then you will be punished.
A problem with this, of course, is that we need to explain the content of not only complex
moral claims but also atomic moral claims. But many latter-day expressivists have sought
to overcome this problem by also holding that atomic claims have both descriptive and
evaluative aspects.15 It is highly controversial whether any of these enriched expressivist
views work, but, rather than get into the trenches of that debate, I want to point out that,
insofar as these views continue to operate within the general ideationalist approach to
meaning, they can still be fit into Ayer's heuristic at least this far: normative sentences are
still viewed as having a particular descriptive content that is presented in a special
normative way that could in principle be replaced with a special set of exclamation marks
expressing the relevant desire-like attitude.
For example, we can already see how this is the case with our toy version of ethical
expressivism above. The idea was that a sentence of the form
X is good
expresses the acceptance of a set of norms N, which one takes to encourage promoting X.
Here the descriptive content is that
N encourages promoting X
and it is presented, so to speak, in the mode of one who accepts N. Thus, on the view, it
seems that we could in principle replace the claim X is good with N encourages
promoting X!!, where the !! indicates that the speaker accepts
119
N. When the normative predicate is embedded in a force-stripping context, the point
remains the same. For instance, the sentence
If X is good, then Y is good
might be thought to have the descriptive content that
if N encourages promoting X, then N encourages promoting Y
which is presented in the mode of one who accepts N. Thus, it could, in principle be
replaced with If N encourages promoting X, then N encourages promoting Y!!, where
the !! indicates that the speaker accepts N.
No mature version of expressivism deploys Ayer's heuristic tactic so baldly, but I think
most can be fit into the general model.16 Because of this, however, I worry that they trade
on an impoverished view of what a normative concept could be. To appreciate this, let
me contrast two conceptions of concepts.17
There is a strong tradition in cognitive science of viewing concepts, especially those often
deployed in observation, as asymmetrically dependent labels or classificatory devices. On
this view, concept possession is a discriminatory ability: to possess the concept C is to be
reliably disposed to respond differentially to things in a particular class, the C-things. For
instance, the concept red is, on this view, a classificatory device for the red things; to
possess this concept is to be reliably disposed to respond differentially to red things
(under normal circumstances and with the right sort of prompting) with the word red (or
some suitable analogue), that is, to be able to classify things as red or non-red.18
Another tradition dominates the philosophy of logic, where concepts are seen as logically
articulable functions or nodes of inferential (evidential and/or justificatory) relations. On
this view, concept possession is a rational ability: to possess the concept C is to be able to
draw the right sorts of inferences to and from applications of the concept C. For instance,
the concept of conjunction is, on this view, the node of the inferential relations between
judgements deploying this and other concepts; to possess this concept is to have the
ability to make
120
(some substantial portion) of these inferencesfor example, from P and Q to Q and
from P and Q to P and Q.19
Which conception of concepts is correct? I think both conceptions capture something that
is important about at least some concepts, so I'd say neither is correct if it is meant to
capture all that there is to concepts and concept possession. However, when it comes to
the nature of human concepts and especially our normative concepts, I think the
inferentialist conception has some claim to being more illuminating and fundamental. For
one thing, it doesn't have to deny that concepts sometimes serve as classificatory devices,
it just claims that there is more to human concepts. For another, when concepts have a
richer logic than is captured by their possible use as classificatory devices, this view can
explain this logic. This seems to be especially apt when it comes to logical concepts such
as necessary, but it may extend to other concepts such as normative concepts too. Even
those concepts that are unquestionably observational might be thought to embody
inferential nodes. For example, it's plausible to think X is red implies X is colored and
X is crimson implies X is red. And this could be relevant for determining their
classificatory function.
I mention this distinction between the two views of concepts because I suspect that
expressivists are, to put things somewhat crudely, tacitly conceiving of normative
concepts as classificatory devices rather than as nodes of inferential relations. It's not that
they think that a normative concept such as good is analogous to an observational
concept such as red in bearing an asymmetric relationship to all and only the good
things. That would be a form of realist cognitivism. Rather, it seems to me that they treat
ethical concepts such as good as partially second-order devices for classifying the
things towards which we (the concept-users) have a certain desire-like attitude in virtue
of certain descriptive properties of the things.
In other words, although, on the expressivist view, X is good clearly does not describe
X as something the speaker approves of, it does classify X as one of the things to which
the speaker has a specific desire-like attitude of approval. The same is true even in
logically complex contexts such as a conditional. For example, on the expressivist view
of the sentence If X is good, then Y is good, neither X nor Y is classified as
unconditionally good. But they are classified as standing in a certain relation with respect
to the things the speaker approves ofbasically, if X is in the class of things the speaker
approves of then so is Y. This is why we can reconstruct the expressivist's view of
normative sentences as one according to which they have descriptive content that is
presented in a special way, which we could in principle replace with a certain kind of tag
or label, for example, the special exclamation marks from Ayer.
121
On this way of thinking of things, to possess a normative concept is to be disposed to
respond differentially to the things towards which one has a certain desire-like attitude
(under normal circumstances and with the right sort of prompting) with the word good
(or some suitable analogue). This is why the expressivist has such an easy time
explaining the intuitive practicality of normative discourse, as explained above. However,
just as I think the general conception of concepts as classificatory device will have a hard
time explaining, in general, the logic of human concepts, I think the view of ethical
concepts which seems to be tacit in expressivism, is likewise bound to have a hard time
explaining the logic of ethical concepts.
There may be a structurally adequate expressivist response to the FregeGeach problem.
That is to say that there may be a version of the expressivist idea that normative claims
express desire-like attitudes, which is capable of assigning different mental states to
different sentences as a way of giving their meaning at whatever degree of logical
complexity. However, as long as the aspect of normative sentences that makes them
normative is conceived as a second-order desire-like classificatory device, I think
expressivists will be stuck with an impoverished view of normative concepts. This is not
to say that it is wrong to view normative concepts as (partially) second-order
classificatory devices, for that idea may very well capture an important aspect of these
concepts. However, especially in the normative case, it seems to me that this cannot be
the most illuminating or fundamental story, since it does not explain the inferential
(evidential or justificatory) relations in which normative concepts stand.
This is, I think, a better reason for being wary of expressivism, and it may seem to be
even more pressing in the case of epistemic expressivism than in the case of ethical
expressivism. For perhaps philosophy is still influenced by positivist undercurrents
enough to take seriously the idea that ethical concepts are somehow attitudinal
classificatory devices rather than inferential nodes. However, positivism's influence hasn't
extended far enough to make the idea that epistemic concepts are attitudinal classificatory
devices rather than inferential nodes equally acceptable. Epistemic concepts clearly have
a robust logic, and it seems to be one entirely parallel to other non-normative concepts.
This is something that I think any view of normative concepts, which turns implicitly on
the cognitive science conception of concepts rather than the philosophy of logic
conception of concepts, is bound to fail to explain.
4. INFERENTIALISM AS A NEW META-ETHICAL AND META-
EPISTEMOLOGICAL VIEW
Summing up before moving on: meta-epistemology has largely presupposed that debates
about the meaning of epistemic claims will be settled by determining the truth conditions
of these claims. I have claimed that this obscures meta-normative
122
views like expressivism which explain the meaning of the target claims in terms other
than truth conditions. However, in both meta-ethics and meta-epistemology, although
expressivism claims certain theoretical advantages, it also seems to tacitly assume a view
of normative concepts that will not be taken to be the most fundamental story in the
epistemic case and, anyway, is impoverished enough to wonder whether it should be
taken as the most fundamental account of any concepts at all.
In the light of the distinction between the two views of concepts, I now want to suggest a
way to retain the advantages of expressivism without incurring the problem I've raised for
it. The strategy will be to pick up on the idea of concepts as inferential nodes and to
sketch the rudiments of a new meta-normative view with this at its heart. As a first pass,
this view can be seen as involving three related elements.
First, it says that we should think of normative concepts not (merely) as classificatory
devices (even at the second-order) but as nodes of inferential relations. Which inferential
relations? It is difficult to say in general and exhaustively, but these will comprise all of
the standard logical relations (like modus ponens and modus tollens inferences) and the
conceptual connections between these concepts and other concepts (e.g. ought implies
can, knowledge implies truth, etc.).20
Second, it says that we should recognize the distinctively practical kinds of inferential
relations in which some normative concepts are caught up. For example, while S ought
all things considered to do A may have the theoretical implication that S can do A,
from the first-person, I ought all things considered to do A may have the practical
implication I shall do A (where this is not the expression of a prediction but rather the
expression of an intention). Likewise, while S knows that p may have the theoretical
implication S believes that p; from the first person, I know that p may have the
practical implication I shall act as if p is true and/or I shall stop enquiring as to whether
p (where this is not the expression of a prediction but rather the expression of an
intention). In effect, here we get a distinction between two different sorts of inferential
roles: the theoretical inferential roles that normative concepts may share with descriptive
concepts and the practical inferential roles that mark them out as different.
Third, it says that we should retain, if only provisionally, the popular idea that intention
and belief have different directions of fit with the world, such that, if two people believe
incompatible propositions to be true, their disagreement presupposes some fact of the
matter about who is right, whereas, if two people intend to make different propositions
true, their disagreement does not by itself presuppose some fact of the matter about who
is right.
123
Now, if we hold that normative predicates and the sentences in which they figure mean
what they do in virtue of their inferential role, so construed, I think we get an alternative
to both truth-conditionalism and expressivism, as accounts of the meaning of normative
claims. We might call this view normative inferentialism (with ethical inferentialism and
epistemic inferentialism as two species).21 Its attractiveness depends on its ability to
retain the advantages of expressivism while enriching the conception of normative
concepts in a way that avoids expressivism's problems. I've just said how it enriches the
conception of normative concepts by moving beyond classificatory devices to inferential
nodes. I'll illustrate separately how it might retain the advantages of ethical expressivism
and then turn to epistemic expressivism.
In the meta-ethical debate, expressivists claim an easy explanation of the intuitive
practicality of ethical discourse. However, above, I distinguished two senses in which
ethical discourse is distinctively practical. There is an issue in, so to speak, the order of
causes: those who make certain sorts of ethical claims tend to exhibit correlated
motivations. By contrast, there is an issue in the order of reasons: one can, it seems, make
ethical claims to justify actions. I think ethical inferentialism is consistent with many
different explanations of the first sense in which ethical discourse is practical. Indeed, it
is consistent with the idea that ethical claims express desire-like attitudes that serve, in
the order of causes, to motivate the expected action (although, it will not put this idea to
the same work in the theory of meaning that the expressivist does). However, ethical
inferentialism offers a novel explanation of the second sense in which ethical discourse is
distinctively practical. By treating ethical predicates as standing in inferential relations
with the predicates that serve in the expression of intentions, we can explain more than
just why ethical claim-making tends to cause certain motivation, we can explain why it
can be used in an attempt to justify it. The idea is that it is by standing in inferential
relations to intentions (to action) that ethical claims are of the right inferential category to
be made in response to demands for justification of an action. For example, if you give
some money to charity, and then someone asks you, Why did you do that?, you can
typically say, Because giving to charity is a good thing to do. That is, you can answer,
in the order of reasons, by making an ethical claim. Ethical inferentialism explains why
this is so.22
The other main advantage of ethical expressivism was its claim to avoid
queerness/placement worries generated by the practicality of ethical concepts.
124
Here, it's difficult to assess the relative merit of inferentialism because it's difficult to say
when the inferentialist semantic idea, viz. that claims mean what they do in virtue of their
inferential roles, commits one ontologically. Some inferentialists (e.g. Dummett) seem
attracted to anti-realism across the board, in which case ethical inferentialism would
obviously be just as ontologically parsimonious as ethical expressivism, but only on pain
of deconstructing the whole issue of ontology. Other inferentialists (e.g. Sellars, Harman)
seem willing to reconstitute the notion of representing the world within the inferentialist
framework. However exactly they do this, as long as there is room for viewing some
claims as not completely representational because of their inferential relations to
expressions of intentions, ethical inferentialism can argue that ethical claims fit into this
latter category and thereby retain the advantage of ontological parsimony claimed by
ethical expressivists. The idea would be to think of some concepts as bearing no direct
inferential connection to intentions, and so not having a distinctively practical inferential
role. These concepts could be viewed as the descriptive or representational concepts,
whose deployment in basic assertions commits the speaker to the existence of the
corresponding fact.23 For example, X is red could then be viewed as committing one to
the fact that X is red. By contrast, other concepts could then be thought of as lacking this
commitment precisely because of their distinctively practical inferential role (and the
corresponding difference in directions of fit). Assuming that ethical concepts belong in
the latter category, ethical inferentialism would have a parallel way to avoid
queerness/placement worries to the ethical expressivist.24
The ostensible advantages of an expressivist approach have not seemed as weighty in the
meta-epistemological debate about the meaning of epistemic claims as they may seem in
the meta-ethical debate. However, in the case of queerness/placement worries, I think this
may have resulted from mere oversight. If we conceive of them as normative, epistemic
facts and values seem to me to be just as difficult to locate in the natural world as ethical
facts and values. For one thing, epistemic concepts seem to resist analysis in non-
normative terms. For another, epistemic norms seem to be categorical and not
hypothetical, in the sense that their normative force does not depend on the contingent
and personal aims or desires of the agents to whom they apply.25 In any case, to the
extent that ethical inferentialism retains resources for claiming ontological parsimony
over truth-conditionalist views of the meaning of ethical claims, epistemic inferentialism
125
will do so as well. So, if epistemic facts and values are queer enough to make ontological
commitment to them a theoretical liability, epistemic inferentialism will retain some of
the advantage of epistemic expressivism.
As I mentioned above, the expressivist's easy explanation of the motivational force of
ethical discourse, does not seem to carry over to epistemic discourse. We can, of course,
make some pretty reliable predictions about what someone who affirms certain epistemic
claims will do. For example, there may be a tight connection between claiming I know
that p and being motivated to act as if p is true. However, it seems that this has nothing
specifically to do with the claim's being an epistemic claim. We can just as well make
such predictions from someone who asserts that p.26
Nonetheless, it seems to me that epistemic discourse is practical in a different sense. As
with ethical claims, I think epistemic claims can be made in the attempt to justify certain
actions. Which epistemic claims can be used to justify which actions is a matter of
considerable debate. Some epistemologists think knowing that p justifies asserting that p
or acting as if p is true, while others think being justified in believing p is enough to
justify these actions.27 Whatever exactly the correct account is, if some epistemic notions
serve as the norm of some kinds of actions, then epistemic discourse exhibits a sort of
practicality in the order of reasons that demands explanation. Epistemic inferentialism
provides this explanation by construing epistemic predicates as inferentially related to the
predicates by which we express intentions.
Thus, it seems to me that normative inferentialismwith its ethical and epistemic
specieswill be at least as well off as normative expressivism vis--vis the alleged
advantages of the latter view. And, since normative inferentialism is based on a view of
concepts, including especially ethical and epistemic concepts, as inferential nodes rather
than classificatory devices, it will overcome one of the core drawbacks of normative
expressivism: its impoverished conception of normative concepts.
5. TOWARDS A VIABLE SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY IN PRAGMATISM
In many ways, the sort of epistemic inferentialism for which I have been arguing here is
inspired by a sort of pragmatism about words and concepts that encourages us to look for
their social-practical roles rather than referents in
126
order to understand their meaning. However, it's a pragmatism which makes a distinction
between normative concepts like knows' or good and descriptive concepts like water
or heat. The difference will be not in which concepts have inferential connections but in
the inferential connections between these concepts and action. In my view, normative
concepts embed the concept ought and this we should understand in terms of its
inferential connections to intentions to action. I think this allows us to view normative
concepts as playing some essentially non-descriptive social-practical role.
Because other pragmatists sometimes say things sounding roughly like this, I'd like to
conclude by distinguishing the pragmatist social epistemology an epistemic inferentialist
should allay himself with from some other similar ideas.
As I mentioned above, pragmatists often challenge the standard approach to doing meta-
epistemology. For example, Rorty (1979, 1995) suggests that epistemic concepts are
primarily terms of praise. This allows him to cast the endless debate about the nature of
knowledge as stemming from a failure to recognize that knows', like good, is not a
word that picks out something with a nature. In a somewhat different vein, Craig (1990)
proposes to approach the concept of knowledge by investigating what role the
introduction of such a concept would have served in human coordination in community,
much like Hobbes tried to understand the concept of justice by investigating what role the
introduction of such a concept would have served in human coordination in community.
Thus, Craig's account of knows' construes it as (initially) a way to tag reliable
informants; what it takes for someone to be deserving of such a tag will largely be down
to the varying specific information tracking and transmitting needs of different groups of
people and not some underlying nature of knowledge.28
Both of these approaches to understanding epistemic concepts have met significant
resistance, which is I think due to the vague sense that they undermine the objectivity of
epistemic concepts and discourse. If epistemic terms are used merely to praise people's
beliefs in a special epistemic way, and different people find different sorts of things to be
worthy of epistemic praise, then there will be no objective answer to first-order epistemic
questions. Similarly, if epistemic terms are used to tag reliable informants, but there is no
specific measure of reliability one must achieve to deserve such a tag, then there will be
no objective standard for our epistemic claims.
Despite this worry, I think it would be wrong to doubt that epistemic concepts are used to
praise and tag; it's just that they seem to do or be something more. If the view of
epistemic concepts as devices of praise or tagging encourages something like the
expressivist semantics for epistemic claims that I discussed
127
earlier, I think the inferentialist semantics that I have proposed to view as expressivism's
successor (both in meta-ethics and meta-epistemology) offers a more nuanced view of the
essentially social function of epistemic concepts and, thereby, a way to view them as
doing more than merely praising and tagging.
The idea would be to treat epistemic concepts as nodes of inferential relations, which are
ossified and perpetuated by the social-linguistic practice of users of these concepts in
human linguistic community as they faced certain needs. Thus, there will be good
pragmatic reasons to explain why it is better for us to use concepts embodying these
inferential roles rather than some other concepts embodying some other inferential roles.
However, once we are using the concepts we have good reason to use, since they embody
specific inferential roles, there is an objective answer to questions about when they can
be correctly applied and what follows from such an application. (Compare: an
inferentialist about logical concepts usually holds that there is an objective answer about
the correct application of, and what follows from, a conjunction or negation.) This is why
I have taken my inspiration from other pragmatists about knowledge, like Brandom
(2000a: ch. 3) and Rosenberg (2002: chs. 56) who embed their pragmatism about
epistemic concepts in a broader pragmatism about concept possession and use more
generally that underwrites an inferentialist treatment of these concepts.
The objectivity for which this move makes room is not the objectivity of some sort of
realism about the relevant kinds of predicates and concepts that they express (e.g. moral,
epistemic, logical, etc.). Rather, it's the kind of objectivity sought by Kant's discussion of
pretty much all of the concepts that interested him. His idea is that we can establish our
unconditional right to use the concepts without needing to establish access to properties
in the world that these concepts purport to represent. The value I see in treating this as
stemming from the social function of epistemic discourse is that it encourages
investigation into why it is useful to use epistemic concepts the way that we do. And this
is the sort of investigation that single-minded focus on the truth conditions of epistemic
claims (invariantist or contextualist) or even on the expressive role of epistemic claims
(representationalist or expressivist) is likely to hinder rather than help.29
128
7 Norms of Trust
Paul Faulkner
1.
Norms are instructions how to act. Their form is the imperative or hypothetical
imperative: Do X, Don't do X, or if Y, then do X. There are moral norms, epistemic
norms, norms of practical rationality, and social norms. In following norms we come to
believe truths, to be justified in our belief, act rationally, lead a virtuous life, and act in
morally permissible ways. In following social norms we come to lead a life that is
acceptable to a given society, a life that conforms to this socially established way of
living. Social norms thereby differ from other norms in that their prescriptions are
relative rather than universal. At the most trivial level these norms can be no more than a
matter of etiquette: they are a matter of adopting the right register, wearing the right
clothes, or, for instance, using the outermost knife and fork first. In these matters most
would accept that when in Rome one should do as the Romans do. But this easy-going
relativism towards the prescriptions of social norms is not always so easy: social norms
can be strongly felt. And nor are all social norms trivial: adopting the right register, for
instance, can shade into treating someone the right way and thereby engage moral norms.
Similarly, prescriptions of politeness can overlap with epistemic prescriptions. Believe
people might be a matter of politeness, but it could also be an epistemic norm if truth-
telling were the norm. Is tell the truth a social norm, and so the norm? Should we
believe people? This chapter aims to argue that, roughly speaking, we have these social
norms. It aims to offer an explanation of these social norms and an account of how this
bears on epistemological theories of testimony as a source of knowledge.
2.
The attitudinal hallmark of social norms, Jon Elster suggests, is that they are associated
with, and sustained by, feelings of embarrassment, anxiety, guilt and shame that a person
suffers at the prospect of violating them, or at least at
129
the prospect of being caught violating them. Social norms have a grip on the mind that is
due to the strong emotions their violations can trigger.1 Where the social norm concerns
the behaviour of one party towards another, there are three attitudinal dimensions that
could be individuated. Violation of the norm will provoke emotions of shame or guilt in
the wrongdoer; it will provoke the reactive attitude of resentment in the wronged; and
it will provoke punitive attitudes of disapproval or anger in third parties. These hallmark
emotions are found in our attitudes towards truth-telling and believing others. This might
be illustrated for truth-telling as follows. A native to this city you are approached by
someone who is visibly a tourist and asked directions to the train station. Most would
think it would be the wrong thing to do to misdirect the tourist, and that it would be
shameful to misdirect the tourist for the fun of it. A friend X has confided in you. The
matter is of some delicacy. Another friend Y is curious about what is going on with X,
you try to avoid the issue but Y is persistent and asks about the matter directly. With no
room to manoeuvre you choose to maintain X's confidence and lie to Y all the while
chaffing at being put in this position. These cases illustrate, at the very least, that in the
context of being quizzed for information we feel that we should give the audience the
information needed. Equally, we would be susceptible to guilt-like emotions were we to
mislead the audienceeven if for good reason as in the case of the nosey friend. And we
feel it would be appropriate for the misled audience to resent being misled. These
hallmark emotions then suggest that we have some kind of norm of truth-telling. That
there is a parallel norm of believing others is then illustrated by imagining things from
the other side. Suppose that you look like the kind of person whose directions would be
authoritative but after having given clear and confident directions to the train station you
witness the tourist walk off in the opposing direction and promptly ask someone else for
the same set of directions. This manifest distrust has something of an insult to it.2 If
humour did not intervene, it would be liable to provoke something like resentment: what
reason could he have had for not believing you? And one would expect the tourist to be
embarrassed if he sees you watching him. This set of emotional responses equally
suggests that we have something like a norm of believing others. So the first question is
what is the content of these two norms?
The norm of truth-telling, I think, is less one of truth-telling, and more one of being
cooperative in conversation. Suppose that as an audience you need to know whether p
and engage a speaker in conversation with the purpose of finding this out. Ideally, you
want to engage with a speaker who will tell you that p if p and tell you that not-p if not-p.
Ideally you want a speaker who makes her conversational contribution one that is true.
But since it is not always plain
130
what is true, the most one can really expect is for a speaker not to say what she believes is
false or for which she lacks adequate evidence. But this is not all. Williams gives the
example of being told Someone's been opening your mail, when it is the speaker who
has been doing so. This speaker has said something true, but what she has said is
misleading because it implies the falsehood that someone else has been opening the mail.
To communicate a truth, she would have to say more: Someone has been opening your
mail and that someone is me (or I've been opening your mail). So if you want to know
whether p, then, in addition to wanting a speaker to try and say what is true, you also
want the speaker to be as informative as is required for your not being misled. Ideally the
speaker's contribution would also be appropriately relevant and lucid. And if it is all of
these things, the speaker's contribution has been guided by Paul Grice's maxims of
Quality, Quantity, Relation, and Manner respectively. Given our conversational goal of
learning whether p, a reply that is guided by these maxims is cooperative.
On the other side, the norm of believing others is less one of credulity and more the
paired norm of presuming cooperation.3 Grice's claim is that we can presume
conversation to be cooperative; we can expect it to be guided by the Cooperative
Principle:
We might then formulate a rough general principle which participants will be expected
(ceteris paribus) to observe, namely: make your conversational contribution such as is
required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk
exchange in which you are engaged. One might label this the Cooperative Principle.
(Grice 1967: 26)
For Grice, it is the presumption that participants are following this principle that makes a
talk exchange a conversation rather than a succession of disconnected remarks'. This
presumption, his point was to observe, can be needed to work out what a speaker means
by what she says. For example, a speaker S states You're a fine friend on learning that
her close friend A has divulged her secret to a business rival. In knowing that S knows of
his actions, A knows that S believes that what she says is false. So S appears to be
flouting the maxim of Quality and with it the Cooperative Principle. But they still seem to
be having a conversation: S appears to be telling him something. So A must presume that
S is following the Cooperative Principle and is telling him the opposite of what she says.
There is little cooperation between A and S but A's receiving the information from S's
telling that he is a poor friend requires the conversation be a cooperative endeavour.
Now, not all talk exchanges are cooperative: not all talk exchanges are conversations in
Grice's sense. We might expect our interlocutors to cooperate in conversation, but they
need not. This is illustrated by the mail case. The speaker
131
S purportedly tells the audience A something. Since the conversation thereby has the
seeming purpose of S giving A some information, A will expect S's utterance to be such as
is required, and to be true and appropriately informative. On the presumption that S is
following the cooperative principle, A will thereby understand S to be telling him that
someone else has been opening his mail. And there is room here for S to say truthfully
that she didn't say that, and so has been misunderstood. She has been misunderstood
because the presumption of cooperation is false; it turns out that they are not having a
conversation in Grice's sense: A thinks that he is being told something when in fact he is
being manipulated. But A was right to presume that they were having a conversationA
was right to presume the Cooperative Principle was being followednot merely because
this is how things seemed, but also because the Cooperative Principle is a normative
principle amounting to the prescription that if you want to have a conversation which has
a certain understood purpose, then you'd better make your conversational contribution
such as is required by this accepted purpose. If the accepted purpose is the giving and
receiving of information, then you'd better try and say what is true and be appropriately
informative.
When a speaker satisfies these maxims, let me say that the speaker is trustworthy. Grice's
proposal that participants in a talk exchange should follow and be presumed to follow the
Cooperative Principle is then the proposal that we expect speakers to be trustworthy
when the talk exchange has the accepted purpose of giving and receiving information.
The idea that conversation be seen as a cooperative endeavour thereby yields a pair of
social norms. The prescription that speakers follow the Cooperative Principle and its
maxims describes a social norm of trustworthiness. And the paired prescription that as
audiences we presume this of speakers and act as if we believe that they are following the
Cooperative Principle and its maxims describes a social norm of trust. Together this pair
of norms describes a standard that we expect interlocutors to live up to when engaged in a
certain practice: that of having a certain type of conversation. On this standard if another
depends on you for information, then other things being equal you should try to say what
is true and try to be appropriately informative; and if another purports to tell you that
something is so, then other things being equal you should explain this in terms of their
trying to be appropriately informative. The fact that the presumption that speakers follow
the Cooperative Principle reveals what speakers mean by what they say so in a way that
naturally describes how we understand others I then take to be good evidence that this
pair of norms describes our conversational practices. Grice's definition of a conversation
is not meant to be a mere term of art. This answers the first question of the content of the
norms of truth-telling and belief: they are actually norms of trustworthiness and trust. The
next question is what explains our having these social norms? What explains the fact that
talk exchanges tend to have the civility of conversations?
132
3.
An influential account of social norms is provided by David Lewis (1969). Lewis's
starting point is the idea of a coordination problem. The resolution of this problem, Lewis
argues, gives rise to conventions which then define social norms. We often need to
coordinate our actions. A simple case: if we live in the suburbs on opposite sides of the
city and decided to meet for a drink after work in the city we need to arrange a time and a
place. Supposing neither of us cares whether we meet at six or seven or at The Lion or
The Lamb, then we have what Lewis defines as a coordination problem: we have a
coincidence of interests in that of the four possible time and pub combinations it doesn't
matter to either of us which pair is chosen but each likes one pair best given the other's
choice. The problem is settling on a choice. If you choose seven at The Lamb that is fine
by me and best for me, and we could reach this arrangement by declaration and
agreement. However, another possibility is coordination by precedence. If you get cut off
just as you were about to make this suggestion, one arrangement may remain salient and
this is a repeat of last week's meeting. If this arrangement then successfully repeatswe
both turn up at the same time and placeit will establish an expectation of future
conformity and we will have an embryonic convention: to meet at The Lamb at seven
after work on Wednesdays. This gives Lewis's first approximation:
A regularity R in the behaviour of members of a population P when they are agents in a
recurrent situation S is a convention if and only if, in any instance of S among members
of P,
(1) everyone conforms to R;
(2) everyone expects everyone else to conform to R;
(3) everyone prefers to conform to R on condition that the others do, since S is a
coordination problem and conformity to R is a proper coordination equilibrium in S.
(Lewis 1969: 42)
This definition does not contain any normative terms, however social norms, Lewis
suggests, can be defined as regularities to which we believe one ought to conform
(1969: 97), and conventions are norms in this sense. This ought Lewis explains in two
ways. First, conformity to a convention is in everyone's interest: the regularity is a proper
coordination equilibrium or a combination that each likes better than any other, given the
others' choices. And, on Lewis's refinement, it is common knowledge that this is so (1969:
52 ff). Consequently, everyone will recognize two reasons why one ought to conform:
one ought to do what is in one's interests; and one ought to do what others expect one to
do when this expectation is reasonable. And this expectation is reasonable given that
conformity is to a regularity that everyone knows is in everyone's best interest.
133
The ought of social norms then carries the force of these two reasons on Lewis's
account. It also has further force, which is detailed by Lewis's second explanation: the
ought of social norms is attached to feelings of approval and disapproval. If others are
confronted by an action that fits with their reasonable expectations, then they are likely to
approve; and if others confront an action that runs counter to these expectations, then
they are likely to explain it discreditably. So a failure to conform to a convention elicits
disapproval, and this constitutes a sanction. This makes conventions by definition, a
socially enforced norm: one is expected to conform, and failure to conform tends to
provoke unfavorable responses from others' (Lewis 1969: 99). Sanctions offer additional
motivation for compliance. So conventions are social norms because they have normative
force: one has reasons to comply with them and there are sanctions on one's compliance.
This explains why the regularities that constitute the norm persists. What explains there
being regularity in the first place is that norms as conventions are proper coordination
equilibria, and so in everyone's best interest.
4.
In order to give this Lewisian explanation of the Cooperative Principle, and more
specifically the norms of trust and trustworthiness, these norms must prescribe courses of
action in a situation whose outcome is determined jointly by the actions of two or more.
This they do. This situationcall it the testimonial situationis a conversation whose
ostensible purpose is the giving and receiving of information. The prescribed outcome is
for the speaker to be trustworthy and so to try to tell the truth in an informative way and
for the audience to trust and so to act as if he believed the speaker is doing just this. In
order for these norms to have the status of conventions, this outcome must be a proper
coordination equilibria: it must be an outcome that each likes best given the other's
choice. Now, in any particular case this could be true. But conventions and norms must
hold independently of the particularities of any given case. And it is easy to imagine
cases where this outcome is not a proper coordination equilibria. Holding the audience's
trust constant, a speaker might have preferred the outcome where he was untrustworthy.
Suppose the speaker has just made a kill in a hunt and would rather keep this kill for
himself and his family. In this case, if another hunter asks him whether he had any luck
hunting, he might well tell the other hunter the truth, but he would prefer the outcome
where there is trust but he keeps the fact that he has made a kill concealed. So in this
particular case the prescribed outcome is not a coordination equilibria. Moreover, if the
testimonial situation is considered in abstract there is no reason to think that this case is
peculiar. The recurrent situation is that of a conversation whose ostensible purpose is the
giving and receiving of information, wherein the audience ostensibly needs to know
whether p, and the speaker ostensibly tells the
134
audience what he needs to know. The choices for the audience are to trust or notto
accept what the speaker tells him on the presumption that the speaker is trustworthy or
not; and for the speaker to be trustworthy or notto try to tell the audience the truth
informatively or not. Given the assumptions that a false belief would leave the audience
in a worse position than ignorance and that the audience's interest is what it appears to be
and that is being informed, the best outcome for the audience is to trust when the speaker
is trustworthy and not to trust when the speaker is not trustworthy. Call the first outcome
the cooperative outcome. Whilst, in any particular case, it may lie in the speaker's interest
to tell the truth, what explains this lie of interest will be the more basic interest of
influencing the audience. A conversation whose ostensible purpose is the giving and
receiving of information will be of interest to a speaker because it is a way of getting an
audience to believe something and is thereby a way of exerting an influence on the
audience. And we have a basic interest in exerting an influence on others. Telling the
truth could further this interest but only telling the truth expediently, or telling the truth
conditional on one's other interests. Being bound to give an audience the information
soughtbeing trustworthywould not be in a speaker's interest. So whilst the
cooperative outcome would be the best-case outcome for an audience, the commitment of
trustworthiness would not be best for a speaker. The best outcome for a speaker would be
to receive an audience's trust yet have the liberty to tell the truth or not given the shape of
interest in the particular case. However, telling the truth merely when it suits one is a way
of being untrustworthy. So the best outcome for a speaker would be the trust and
untrustworthiness combination. Since this is the worst case scenario for an audience, the
testimonial situation has a structure of pay-offs that resembles the prisoner's dilemma.4
As such the testimonial situation could be said to present a problem of trust: the rational
thing for an audience to do seems to be to not trust another for information in the first
place.5 Since the testimonial situation is thereby not one in which coincidence of interest
predominates', it is not a coordination problem in Lewis's sense. So it seems that Lewis's
explanation of social norms cannot be given for the norms of trust and trustworthiness.
5.
Nevertheless, Lewis's explanatory strategy can still be pursued. This strategy is to explain
the cooperative outcome in terms of the interests of the parties
135
producing it. Ultimately, what explains a convention is the fact that it is a proper
coordination equilibrium. The problem is that in prisoner's dilemma type cases non-
cooperation is the dominant option, in that it is the rational thing to do whatever the other
party does. However, this all changes given a couple of assumptions about the recurrent
situation that presents the dilemma. The first assumption is that individuals have a
sufficiently large chance of meeting again so that they care about future interactions, and
the number of these future interactions is indefinite. I might depend on you for
information on this occasion but you will depend on me on some future occasion and
there is the mutual expectation that we will find ourselves in an indefinite number of
these testimonial situations. As such there is no final interaction where the trusted party
might hope to secure extra benefit by behaving untrustworthily. The second assumption
is that each party can make it clear to the other that they will behave in a tit-for-tat
manner, which is cooperating at the start but responding to any non-cooperation with
retaliation. If the hunter concealed the fact that he made a kill on this occasion and was
found out, he would lose the benefit of sharing on another occasion. So whilst non-
cooperation could potentially pay dividends on any given occasion, this would be offset
by future losses. Given these two assumptions, the cooperative outcome is a coordination
equilibrium: no one benefits from unilateral non-cooperation. And it is a proper
coordination equilibrium: there is no better strategy. That the cooperative outcome then
comes to describe a convention and so be prescribed as a social norm follows on Lewis's
account once it is added that everyone expects and prefers conformity. This expectation is
delivered by the second assumption: it is clear to all that each is behaving in a tit-for-tat
manner and so will conform by default. And the preference for conformity follows given
that another's non-cooperation results in loss of the benefits of the cooperative outcome
for two rounds, this and the next when retaliation is due. So it is possible to give Lewis's
explanation of how the cooperative outcome becomes a matter of convention, where this
explanation appeals to little more than rational self-interest.6
Philip Pettit (1990: 735) develops a particular implementation of this strategy for
explaining norms of cooperation. He starts with three criticisms. First, what this strategy
explains is not a norm prescribing a certain behaviour but one prescribing that one behave
in this way in a tit-for-tat manner. So it does not offer an explanation of the norm of
trustworthiness, or telling the truth reliably, so much as one of the norm of truth-telling in
a tit-for-tat way. However, Pettit does not regard this as a significant matter because these
norms should be extensionally equivalent in that general tit-for-tat truth-telling would
result in the same behaviour as reliable truth-telling. Second, this explanation only works
for certain norms. It only works for what Pettit calls type B prisoner's dilemmas':
In a type B dilemma, defection by even a single individual plunges at least one
cooperator, and perhaps many more, below the baseline of universal defection. In a type
A dilemma
136
this is not so and, at limit, the lone defector may have only an imperceptible negative
effect on cooperators. (Pettit 1990: 737)
The problem for this explanatory strategy is then that lots of many-party prisoner's
dilemmas are type A. However, this is not a problem in this case: the problem of trust is
type B because defection by a speaker in the testimonial situation will plunge an audience
below the baseline; that is to say, it is worse for the audience to have a false belief than
remain ignorant. The real problem, third, is that behaving in a tit-for-tat way requires that
people be willing to retaliate. And if the norm being explained is a norm of
trustworthiness as opposed to tit-for-tat trustworthiness, then being trustworthy in a tit-
for-tat way requires that people will break norms punitively in order to punish those who
break them for convenience. . . . And this disposition is not genuinely manifested among
those who honor norms' (Pettit 1990: 737). Pettit's key observation then follows this third
criticism and pursues Lewis's thought that sanction can come by way of others'
disapproval. It is that whilst people might not be given to retaliationsuch behaviour is
costly and risks an escalation of retaliation rather than a return to cooperationpeople do
retaliate after a fashion: a violater can be punishedor of course a conformer
rewardedby the attitudes of others' (Pettit 1990: 739). And once these approbative
costs and benefits are put into the equation, Pettit hypothesizes, we can see our way to
explaining why the emergence and persistence of otherwise puzzling norms may be
unsurprising (1990: 742). That is, once these costs and benefits are put into the equation
we can make good the tit-for-tat implementation of Lewis, (except we now understand
tatting as holding a disapproving attitude). What is assumed here is that people care
about others' approval and disapproval. If it is also assumed that these feelings are
automatic and costless, then one gets sanctions for free and one has an explanation of
compliance with the norm: the sanction which ensures compliance is not the threat of
retaliation but the fear of disapproval and desire for approval. So we can regard
trustworthiness as the best preference given trust, and the cooperative outcome as a
coordination equilibrium given the approval it elicits. Thus starting with Lewis's
suggestion that conventions are norms because they specify regularities which everyone
recognizes that one ought to conform to. And making it explicit that the feeling that one
ought to conform underwrites approval and disapproval and plays a causal sustaining role
gives Pettit's Lewisian account of social norms:
A regularity, R, in the behaviour of members of a population, P, when they are agents in
a recurrent situation, S, is a norm if and only if, in any instance S among members of P,
(1) nearly everyone conforms to R;
(2) nearly everyone approves of nearly anyone else's conforming and disapproves of
(1) nearly everyone conforms to R;
nearly anyone else's deviating; and
(3) the fact that nearly everyone approves and disapproves on this pattern helps to ensure
that nearly everyone conforms. (Pettit 1990: 731)
137
In short, norms are regularities in behaviour that we approve of where this approval and
corresponding disapproval enforce the regularity. The approval and disapproval are
rationally intelligible because the norm specifies the cooperative outcome in some
situation of collective action. And this outcome can be seen to be a proper coordination
equilibrium once our concern for approval is factored into the equation.
6.
Pettit distinguishes two different ways of explaining norms of cooperation. Behavioural
explanations' show how certain patterns of behaviour are a matter of self-interest. The tit-
for-tat explanation of cooperation is behavioural; it shows how cooperation can emerge
in a world of egoists without central authority (Axelrod 1984: 3). Pettit contrasts his
attitude-based explanation which shows first why certain attitudes of approval are
intelligible . . . [before] then showing how they might generate the patterns of behaviour
required for norms' (Pettit 1990: 733). Now, suppose that agents S and A are in a joint
action situation T and there is a norm stating that S should in T. Pettit's account as to
why disapproval of breach of a norm like this is intelligible is that the norm prescribes a
cooperative outcome that is a proper coordination equilibrium. So were S not to , A
would disapprove of S's failure to because it is to his, A's, detriment, and A thinks that S
has a reason to . This renders A's attitude of disapproval intelligible after a fashion: it
renders it intelligible from the perspective of what lies in A's rational interest. However,
this is not intelligible from A's perspective in that it does not detail A's reason for his
attitude of disapproval. The judgement of wrongness made when a norm is breached does
not consist of a judgement of consequence: A's disapproval does not stem from the loss
that will follow from S not -ing. Rather, A's judgement is no more than that S should
have -ed, or should have -ed given that he was in situation T. Consider the question,
what exactly do people disapprove of when they disapprove of others breaking a norm?
Or, what makes disapproval intelligible to those making a disapproving judgement?
These questions will be answered by appeal to the norm: the norm that one should in T
describes a standard of conduct that is appealed to when making an approving or
disapproving judgement. What this means is that one cannot see the attitudes of approval
and disapproval as intelligible independently of acceptance of the norm that articulates
these judgements and that is appealed to in order to justify them. Consequently, these
judgements do not have the kind of independent intelligibility necessary for Pettit's
attitude-based explanation. That is, unless intelligibility is really just a matter of rational
self-interest. But then patterns of behaviour are ultimately approved of because they are
in everyone's best interest, and the distinction Pettit draws between styles of explanation
is not substantive. But this is just to say
138
something that Pettit (1990: 725) otherwise acknowledges, which is that his account is
game-theoretical.
On Pettit's definition of social norms, general attitudes of approval and disapproval help
to ensure conformity to the regularity in behaviour that is the outward part of the social
norm. This is undoubtedly true, but the question is what is the right reading of helps to
ensure. The right reading for Pettit's attitude-based explanation is a strong one like is
the cause of. The idea is that conformity is explained once people's preferences are
suitably adjusted to take into consideration the fact that we care about others' opinions of
us. The problem for this explanation starts when we take seriously the question, what
exactly do people disapprove of when they disapprove of others' breaking a norm? In
terms of the schematic scenario just described, what A disapproves of when A
disapproves of S not -ing in T is just the fact that S didn't when S should have done.
The norm itself articulates A's reason for disapproval. Social norms are thereby held as
standards of behaviour that justify both attitudes of approval and disapproval. To use a
sociological term of art, people internalize social norms, which is to say that social norms
describe patterns of behaviour that people are motivated to follow for no other reason
than that these patterns of behaviour are valued in themselves or held as ultimate ends.
Let me describe this kind of motivation as intrinsic.7 The idea that we internalize social
norms is the idea that we are instrinsically motivated to behave in the way the norms
prescribe. This aspect of social norms, the fact as Elster says that they have a strong grip
on the mind, is not represented by game theory, which is not concerned with
intelligibility from the inside or intelligibility in terms of the norm. So returning to the
issue of A's disapproval of S not -ing, this disapproval is the kind that is meant to
explain, on Pettit's account, general conformity with the norm to in action situation T.
But if A's disapproval stems from the fact that A has internalized this norm then it is this
fact and not others' disapproval that should explain A's compliance. But what goes for A
goes for S; these are just agent role placeholders. This is to say that whilst others'
disapproval can cause conformity, the reason for others' disapproval will also centrally be
their reason for conformity. Returning to Pettit's criticisms of the tit-for-tat behavioural
explanation of social norms, these criticisms can now been seen to be more substantial
than Pettit acknowledged. If peoples' reason for conformity is their having internalized
the norm they conform to, then we have an explanation as to why people tend not to
break the norm punitively. To break the norm punitively is still to break the norm and so
fall short of the standard of behaviour prescribed. And if the norm articulates peoples'
reason for conformity, then it matters whether the norm is to or to in a tit-for-tat way.
Even if these two norms are extensionally equivalent, they give different reasons for
action. So the tit-for-tat explanatory strategy is limited from the start.
139
The idea that social norms articulate reasons for action and figure in justifications of
attitudes of approval and disapproval allows for a very simple explanation as to why
people conform to social norms. We obey social norms because these norms describe
what we believe that we ought to do. We obey social norms because we have internalized
them. This is more properly an attitude-based explanation of social norms, and can be
labelled the social account (since talk of internalizing social norms is commonplace in
the social sciences). However, whilst it provides a very simple answer to the question of
why people conform, the social account raises two further questions. First, we might have
a rudimentary explanation of why people comply with social norms, but can this be filled
out? Second, game-theoretical or Lewisian accounts of social norms make good sense of
why norms exist in that they provide an explanation not merely of compliance but also of
the norms themselves. So one might also hope for an answer to this question: why do
particulars norm exist? In the next section I consider this question, and its particular
form: why is it that we have social norms of trust and trustworthiness?
7.
In Truth and Truthfulness Bernard Williams offers an imaginary genealogical account of
what he calls the virtues of truth: Accuracy and Sincerity. These are the dispositions to
care about the truth of one's beliefs, and to come out with what one believes. Williams's
genealogy offers an explanation of our valuing these dispositions or virtues of truth. It is
because we value these dispositions that we try to get things right in belief and utterance.
However, our valuing Sincerity is not a matter of the crude prescription: always tell the
truth. The mail opener, referred to above, does not manifest the disposition of Sincerity
in Williams's sense, even though she is sincere in believing what she says. When the
conversation is one of giving and receiving information, Sincerity is a matter of being
appropriately informative: it is a matter following the Cooperative Principle and its
maxims, which define the social norm of trustworthiness. So Williams's genealogical
justification of Sincerity offers a way of explaining why it is that we have this social
norm, and the paired social norm of trust. Moreover, Williams's genealogical justification
focuses on the joint action situation that is the testimonial situation which presents the
problem of trust.8
Williams's genealogy starts by imagining a State of Nature consisting of a primitive
social group with limited technology and no writing. Although primitive, this social
group is imagined to be a real society whose members have projects and interests, and are
related to one another in various ways and via various roles. As with any society, the
society imagined in the State of Nature will
140
involve cooperative engagements which demand information be communicated between
individuals. Given that an individual can only be at one place at one time, individuals will
often gain what Williams (2002: 42) calls purely positional advantage; that is, by virtue
of their location at a time, one individual can come to possess information that another
individual needs. It follows that even in the State of Nature, thus minimally characterized,
Accuracy and Sincerity are desirable from the social point of view; they will be socially
valued because pooled information is a social good and necessary for many cooperative
endeavours. However, possessing the disposition of Sincerity need not always be in an
individual's best interest. Williams gives the example of the hunter who has found prey
that he would rather keep for himself and his family. This raises the problem that:
The value that attaches to any given person's having this disposition [Sincerity] seems, so
far as we have gone, largely a value for other people. It may obviously be useful for an
individual to have the benefits of other people's correct information, and not useful to him
that they should benefit of his. So this is a classic example of the free-rider situation.
(Williams 2002: 58)
The problem is that the collective valuing of Sincerity does not itself give an individual a
reason to value Sincerity, or be sincere. Whilst it is always in an audience's interest to be
informed, Sincerity needn't best serve a speaker's interest and as audiences we know that
this is the case. The problem that Williams thus identifies is the problem of trust; and
since the State of Nature represents a basic society, the possibility that a conversation as
to the facts could be stymied by this problem shows that no society can get by . . . with a
purely instrumental conception of the values of truth (Williams 2002: 59).
What any society requires is that individuals have internalized Sincerity as a disposition,
where this is to say that individuals are motivated to act in a sincere way simply by the
description of this way of acting as sincere. Where this is true, Sincerity will have
intrinsic value (or intrinsic value in the society). Something's having intrinsic value,
Williams then goes on to argue, can be understood in terms of the satisfaction of two
conditions. For something, X say, to have intrinsic value in a society: first X must be
necessary, or nearly necessary for basic human purposes and needs'; and second X must
make sense to them [the society members] from the inside, so to speak (Williams 2002:
92). The first of these desiderata is established by the imagined genealogy. If Sincerity is
not given intrinsic value, then any conversation that purports to be one of giving and
receiving information will generate the problem of trust. This threatens to stymie both the
conversation and any further cooperation. However, we do cooperate in conversations as
to the facts. We tell one another what we know and we have a way of life wherein
testimony is a source of knowledge. So whatever needs to be in place to avoid the
problem of trust must be in place and that is that we intrinsically value Sincerity. We
must be motivated to be sincere as an end in
141
itself. The second desiderata is then giving an account of how this motivation is made
sense of.
Since any value is made sense of through its connection to further values, how a society
gives intrinsic value to Sincerity can be philosophically unearthed through conceptual
analysis. What conceptual analysis shows about our social history is that we understand
Sincerity through its relation to trust and our valuing trustworthy behaviour. Sincerity is
trustworthiness in speech. This is more than the avoidance of lying; our being trustworthy
can require our lying. Equally, it is not simply the disposition to say what one believes;
one can implicate falsehoods by saying what one believes and so be untrustworthy by
doing this. The mail opener implicates that someone else has been opening your mail.
What Grice's discussion of implicature then shows is that:
Implicature do not presuppose language as simply a practice involving semantic and
syntactic rules, together with the norm that certain kinds of utterances are taken to be
true; they look to the use of language under favourable social conditions which enable it
to be indeed co-operative. They are conversational implicatures, but not everyone who is
talking with someone else is engaged, in the required sense, in a conversation. What is
required for that to be so are certain understood levels of trust. (Williams 2002: 100)
We have achieved these levels of trust because we intrinsically value trustworthiness in
speech, which is the disposition of Sincerity. And this is just to say, I suggest, that the
norm of trustworthiness, which is the prescription that speakers follow the Cooperative
Principle and its maxims, is internalized as a social norm. In learning to have
conversations one learns this norm, and the presumption that things are as the norm
prescribes then allows us to uncover implicatures or what people mean by what they say.
Since we can tell people what we know by implication as much as by bald statement, our
norm of trustworthiness is then necessary for testimony being the source of knowledge
that is. The genealogical justification that Williams offers in Truth and Truthfulness for
our having the disposition of Sincerity can then be presented as a genealogical
justification of the norm of trustworthiness, and with it the paired norm of trust. This
addresses the challenge of explaining why we have these particular norms.
8.
The problem, as Williams is aware, is that the claim that X has intrinsic value faces a
dilemma. Left like this it is mysterious as a claim. Why should the description of an act
as X be a motivation to act this way? But if the mystery is explicated, then the account of
the value threatens to become reductive with X being merely instrumentally valuable.
Williams's two-condition account is meant to address this dilemma; genealogy is meant
to achieve explanation without reduction (2002: 90). A similar problem faces social
accounts of social norms. The explanation of
142
behaviour that states that people act a certain way because they have internalized a
certain norm is not fully satisfactory issuing in the question: but why should they be
motivated to act in this way? This is the first challenge noted in section six, and here
game-theoretical, or Lewisian, accounts of social norms seem to be genuinely
explanatory since they have self-interest as the final appeal, which does not seem to just
raise further questions. The problem with this, I argued, is that if social norms are
rationalized in terms of rational self-interest, then what is left out is the sense that we find
in acting in the way that the norm prescribes. What is left out is our understanding of the
value that motivates our action. However, to make good the claim that this genuinely
impoverishes these explanations, what is needed is a fuller account of how our
understanding of value motivates action. Moreover, the need to meet this challenge is
sharp in this particular case because, on the face of it at least, we do find trust
problematic. That this is so can be easily reinforced by considering a testimonial situation
but stripping away all the factors that could be used in a game-theoretical solution to the
problem of trust. One must imagine that there is no sanction on untrustworthy behaviour
and that the speaker does not care for the good opinion of others, or at least that the
audience cannot have the assurance of believing either of these things. That is, one must
imagine a case where an audience is engaged in a conversation as to the facts with a
speaker whose particular motivations and preferences the audience is ignorant of. In this
case, the worry that the speaker will not tell the truth, or will only do so if it suits them is
a natural worry. Thus the idea that it is reasonable to trust if we know absolutely nothing
about someone, Williams describes as simply a bad piece of advice (2002: 111). He
then adds that
[i]t may be said that a hearer never has a reason for believing that P which lies just in the
fact that a given speaker has told him that P. He has to believe also that the speaker (on
such matters, and so on) is a reliable informant. (Williams 2002: 778)
So our intrinsically valuing Sincerity is not sufficient, according to Williams, to ground
reasonable acceptance testimony as to the facts. What is also needed is the belief that a
bit of testimony is reliable or that a speaker is manifesting the disposition of Accuracy.
Now, I think that this is the wrong way to go, and the wrong way for Williams to go: the
attitude of trust can suffice for reasonable acceptance of testimony. And I think that this
is what is delivered by considering how our valuation of Sincerity makes sense to us
from the inside. However, leaving this argument until the next section, the point to be
made here is that the temptation to require more than trust for reasonable belief is an
expression of finding the problem of trust genuinely problematic. So if this problem of
trust is meant to be solved by our giving intrinsic value to Sincerity, then a fuller
statement is needed as to how this locus of value motivates our acting in certain ways.
This is the first challenge facing social accounts: filling out how the internalization of
social norms explains conformity with them.
143
What is needed, in the case of the norms of trust, is recognition of how trust figures in our
explanations and justification of action. These explanations and justifications are rather
straightforward. Asked why we took the risk of depending on someone we often answer
simply that we trusted them, and asked why we put ourselves out to do something we
answer that someone trusted us to do this thing. Suppose that one person A trusted
another S to do something, to . And suppose that A trusted S to in the thick sense that A
depended on S -ing and expected this to be at least part of S's reason for -ing.9 Such an
attitude of trust is quite common and might be found in the coordination problem
described in section three. In this case, A trusts S to turn up at the The Lamb at eight and
A trusts S to do this in the sense that A thinks that at least part of S's reason for turning up
at this pub at this time is the fact that A depends on S's doing so. In this case if S were
asked why he was going to this pub at this hour he might reply to meet A or A's waiting
for me and if pushed to take another course of action, S could emphasize the reason this
gives by making it explicit: A trusts me to turn up.10 So we can use the fact that another
has trusted us to do something to explain why we did this thing. And we can use the fact
that we trust someone to explain why we showed a willingness to depend on them in
certain ways: asked why he was bothering to get to the pub on time, A might reply that he
trusts S to show up at this time. So the attitude of trust, in this thick sense, figures in
justificatory explanations of action. This, I suggest, is what the claim about intrinsic value
amounts to: we credit these kinds of ways of making sense of things. Since we use the
attitude of trust to explain and justify acts of trust and trustworthiness, our having the
dispositions that follow from internalizing norms of trust and trustworthiness makes
sense to us from the inside. However, to say that we use the terms of these norms to
explain and justify, is to say that we are motivated to act in the same terms. This is what
the idea of internalization delivers: the prescription of the norm captures the way the
subject thinks about the action prescribed. The idea that we have internalized the norms
of trust and trustworthiness then offers a genuinely explanatory account of action because
if it is true that we have these dispositions to trust and be trustworthy, then the
prescriptions these norms make will outline good descriptions of our reasons for acting.
9.
Williams's official solution to the problem of trust found in the State of Nature is that this
problem is resolved by finding someway to give Sincerity intrinsic value.
144
We then give Sincerity intrinsic value by taking it to be a form of trustworthiness and
valuing trust and relations structured by trust. If this claim about how we give Sincerity
intrinsic value is understood as a claim about our finding certain descriptions and
justifications of action persuasive, then the shape of the solution to the problem of trust
Williams's genealogy offers is revealed.
The problem of trust presupposes an account of the kinds of reasons people have for
acting. On this account, action is explained in terms of the agents' beliefs and desires.
Epistemic rationality demands that an audience desires to believe the truth and avoid
falsehood and so has a preference for ignorance over error. Then absent any belief about
a speaker's motivations, or any grounds for predicting the probable truth of utterance, and
the result can only be that it is not reasonable for the audience to accept what he is told.
Game-theoretical solutions to this problem add grounds for belief. A concern for others'
good opinion in Pettit's case. With the problem situation then reconfigured, a
coordination equilibrium is found and the norms of trust and trustworthiness emerge.
Williams recognizes the extent of the problem, offers the basis of a solution in terms of
giving intrinsic value to Sincerity, but then feels compelled to add that some belief about
the truth of utterance is still necessary. However, his idea that Sincerity be intrinsically
valued suggests an alternative solution. On this solution, what goes wrong with the
problem of trust, why trust is seen as problematic, is that the only explanation of
acceptance allowed is one that proceeds in terms of an audience's belief and desires.
However, we can act out of trust: our trusting a speaker for the truth can give us sufficient
reason to accept what the speaker tells us. An audience can explain why he accepted what
a speaker told him, and so detail his motivations and justify his acceptance, by saying that
he trusted the speaker for the truth. However, an explanation of action that is couched in
terms of trust cannot be translated into one couched in terms of belief and desire. This is
because the attitude of trusting someone to do something involves placing an expectation
on that person: that they will act in a certain way and for a certain reason. And this
expectation of them is not the expectation that something will happen. The difference
between these kinds of expectation is marked by the fact that when we expect things of
people we are susceptible to various reactive attitudes if they do not act as we expect. So
given a conversation as to the facts and an audience who trusted the speaker for the truth
and was misled, this audience will be liable to resent the speaker's actions. The
susceptibility to such a feeling of resentment defines the expectation as one that is placed
on a person or held of them and distinguishes it from the expectation or belief that
something will happen. And this feeling of resentment involves commitment to the norm
of trustworthiness as an objective standard: any resentment felt will not be mollified by
the knowledge that the trusted individual had no inclination to tell the truth because what
is felt is that the trusted individual did have such a reason and should have acted on this
reason. This is the reason described by the norm of trustworthiness, which is meant to
prescribe behaviour irrespective of subjective
145
motivation or personal interest. So the norms of trust and trustworthiness define standards
of behaviour within which explanations in terms of trust make sense and are accordingly
good explanations. This is what is missed when trust is seen as problematic.
Where norms of trust and trustworthiness are internalized, the social background will be
one of certain understood levels of trust. It will be such that if an audience A trusts a
speaker S for information, this will give S a reason to tell A what he needs to know; and if
S tells A something, this gives A reason to accept what S tells him. The idea that
conversation can be structured by presumptions of trust then allows for the following
explanation of what goes on, or should go on, in a conversation as to the facts. A
speaker's reason for telling an audience what he doesthe explanation of the speaker's
testimonywill be the speaker's perception that the audience depends on him for this
information. In this case, if the speaker S tells the audience A that p, it will be because S
believes himself to know that p, and assumes responsibility for letting A know that p in
the following sense: S takes it on himself to tell A that p if and only if he, S, knows that p.
In this way S is trustworthy. And in recognizing that the speaker S intends that A come to
believe that p and trusting S, A will then take S's telling him that p as something like a
promise that p is true. Testimony then functions to transmit knowledge from speaker S to
audience A because it transmits the responsibility for justifying belief from audience A to
speaker S. This explanation is offered by Richard Moran (2006) and following his lead
call it the assurance explanation. On this explanation A doesn't need the belief that S is
reliable to have a reason to accept what S tells him. Rather, A's trusting S gives him a
reason through delivering the presumption that S is trustworthy. Moreover, for A to seek
further reason to believe that p would be to reject S's assurance that p is true. This would
be as likely to provoke S's resentment as straight disbelief since, Moran argues, it
amounts to a refusal to accept S's assumption of responsibility in telling A that p (see
Moran 2006: 301). And this feeling of resentment, I suggest, is parallel to that a misled
audience would experience in that it equally involves commitment to a social norm as an
objective standard, in this case the norm of trust. Supposing A did seek the support that S
was reliable prior to belief, S's resentment at not being believed would not be appeased
by the knowledge that A had no inclination to belief because what is felt is that A did
have a reason for belief, given by S's telling, and should have believed for this reason. So
violations of either norm of trustdisbelieving a speaker or misleading an audience
will engender resentment and other punitive attitudes. So let me drop the demand for a
belief about Accuracy or reliability from Williams's genealogy: it is better to see the
problem of trust confronted in the State of Nature as resolved by the establishment of
levels of trust that allow the giving and receipt of testimony as assurance.
How does the existence of social norms of trust and trustworthiness bear on
epistemological theories of testimony? It is now possible to give a brief
146
answer to this question. One implication is that non-reductive theories are correct to
describe our attitude towards what others tell us as trusting. However, non-reductive
theories, I suggest, are wrong then to hypothesize that we are default justified in trust; the
norm of trust is a social norm and not a general or universal epistemological principle.
Whilst every society confronts the problem of trust, since it is confronted in the State of
Nature, securing the necessary motivations through a valuation of trust is but one solution
to this problem. Other norms are possible. Another implication is that insofar as these
social norms do operate in our society, there should be plenty of scope to give a reductive
theory of testimony: we should have good evidence that tellings will prove generally
reliable even if evidence of particular reliability is hard to come by.11 However, the
possibility of this defence of reductive theory should not constitute a justification of this
position because the norm of trustworthiness is associated firstly with testimony being a
source of knowledge that can be explained in assurance terms. And this, I think, is the
central implication. Our having the social norms of trust and trustworthiness is a function
of our having a way of life wherein we have conversations as to the facts and tell one
another what we know. The epistemology of testimony cannot be synonymous with the
epistemology of tellings: there are too many messy and varied cases, which determine
that the assurance can only be part of the story. But if we have these norms of trust and
trustworthiness, then the assurance explanation of how another's telling can put us in a
position to know something must be an essential part of our epistemological story.12
147
8 Testimonial Entitlement and the Function of Comprehension
Peter J. Graham
Why do you think it will rain tomorrow? Because, you say, it always rains this time of
year; you can see dark clouds for miles; and besides, you read the weather report. The
reasons you offer justify your belief; they comprise a justification for your prediction
about the weather. Justifications are commonplace. Justifications involve reasons or
evidence you often cite when asked how you know. Justifications support your ability to
justifyto argue in favour ofyour belief, to show that your belief is (likely to be) true
(Unger 1968; Audi 1988; Kornblith 2008).
Justification is one kind of positive epistemic status or standing. Positive epistemic
standings are goods, successes, fulfilments, or achievements understood in terms of
promoting true belief and avoiding error (Alston 1985, 2005).
Epistemic justification is not the only kind of positive epistemic standing. Perceptual
beliefs paradigmatically enjoy positive epistemic status, but higher non-human animals,
human infants, children, and ordinary adults often lack evidence or reasons in support of
their perceptual beliefs, and even more often, if not always, lack the ability to cite
evidence or reasons in support of their perceptual beliefs. Ask a small child why he
believes the ball continues to exist as it passes behind the screen, and at best you'll get a
gurgle or a burp. Ask a chimpanzee trying to open a crate why she believes there are
bananas inside, and you won't get any answer at all. Well-formed, garden-variety
perceptual beliefs enjoy positive epistemic status, but that status does not depend on
reasons or evidence, and it especially does not depend on the subject's ability to offer
reasons or evidence (Goldman 1979).
I use the term warrant for positive epistemic statuses that provide epistemic support or
grounding in favour of holding the belief. Justifications are a familiar kind. Evidentialism
arguably captures the contours of this kind of warrant. But justification is clearly not the
only kind of warrant. I use entitlement for positive epistemic support or grounds in
favour of belief when the support or grounding
148
does not involve or depend upon evidence or reasons, especially evidence or reasons the
subject might cite in favour of his or her belief (cf. Burge 1993, 1996). Entitlements are
goods, successes, or fulfilments in the way of promoting true belief and avoiding error
that do not depend on evidence or reasons available to the subject. Though many
perceptual beliefs enjoy justifications, paradigmatically they enjoy entitlements.
What about so-called testimony-based beliefs? These are beliefs based on our capacity
to comprehend assertive speech acts. What kind of warrant do they enjoy? When you tell
me the rain won't let up and I comprehend and accept your assertion, what kind of
warrant does my comprehension-based belief enjoy, justification or entitlement?1
On the traditional view, warrants for comprehension-based beliefs rely exclusively on
entirely first-hand justifications. This tradition has fallen on hard times. For though
comprehension-based beliefs are by and large warranted, it is now widely thought that
fully adequate, entirely first-hand justifications are in short supply (Coady 1992; Fricker
1995).
Though comprehension-based beliefs sometimes enjoy fully adequate, entirely first-hand
justifications, and very often enjoy partially adequate, partially first-hand justifications
(cf. Faulkner 2002), I shall argue that comprehension-based beliefs formed though a
process of filtering generally enjoy prima facie pro tanto entitlement.2 We thus need not
worry over the paucity of fully adequate, entirely first-hand justifications. Though
justifications clearly play an important role in a complete account of the epistemology of
comprehension-based beliefs, they do not play the only role.
Why should beliefs based on comprehension-via-filtering enjoy entitlement? I shall first
argue for an account of (a kind of) entitlement and then apply it to comprehension-based
beliefs. A belief enjoys (a kind of) prima facie pro tanto entitlement when based on a
normally functioning belief-forming process that has
149
forming and sustaining true beliefs reliably as a function.3 And comprehension-with-
filtering has that function. Beliefs based on comprehension-with-filtering thus enjoy (a
kind of) entitlement when our capacity to comprehend and filter functions normally, for
our capacity has forming and sustaining true beliefs reliably as a function. When
functioning normally, comprehension-with-filtering confers prima facie pro tanto
entitlement on the beliefs it causes and sustains.
In the first section I say a few words about our psychological capacity to comprehend and
filter. In the second I explicate function, normal conditions, and normal functioning. In
the third I put these notions to use to argue for my first main thesis, that (a kind of)
epistemic entitlement derives from the normal functioning of the belief-forming process
when the process has forming true beliefs reliably as a function. In the fourth I argue
indirectly for my second main thesis by first arguing that assertion has causing and
sustaining true hearer beliefs as a function. In the fifth I defend this claim against four
counter-arguments. I then argue directly in the sixth for my second thesis that
comprehension-with-filtering has causing and sustaining true beliefs reliably as a
function. Though I have tried to be concise, the paper is not short enough to be easily
read without taking a break. A natural place to pause would be at the end of section three.
Taking a moment to digest the first main thesis may help prepare the palette for the
second. Taking a break after the fifth section might not be a bad idea either.
1. COMPREHENSION-WITH-FILTERING
For the most part, we automatically, quickly, and reliably comprehend speech.
Comprehension involves a number of factors: standing abilities to comprehend shared
meanings of words, shared awareness of relevant features of the context of utterance, and
standing expectations of conformity to cooperative principles or maxims governing
speech behaviour, not to mention the rest of the language suite: syntax, morphology,
phonology, and speech perception.
150
Usually we correctly comprehend what people say. But sometimes we make mistakes: we
sometimes miscomprehend and thereby misrepresent the content or force of a speech act,
or both.
Comprehension states are exercises of our capacity to comprehend. Since my focus is
assertive communication, I shall use comprehension state throughout for
comprehension states that purport to represent assertions.
I use assertion broadly to cover the whole range of constative speech acts: affirm,
allege, avow, certify, concur, declare, describe, disclose, inform, predict, recount, report,
say, state, submit, tell, and testify, among others.4
Comprehension-based beliefs are beliefs caused or sustained by taking comprehension
states at face value. In the ordinary case, a speaker (sender) asserts that P. The hearer
(receiver) represents P as asserted.5 The representation of the speech actthe hearer's
comprehension statedisposes the hearer to believe that P. In the default case,
comprehension prompts belief in the propositional content of the assertion as represented.
Being so moved constitutes taking comprehension at face value. My topic is the
epistemology of beliefs so formed. I thus use testimonial entitlement to refer to the
entitlement that beliefs based on comprehension enjoy.
151
Our developmental starting point is not a broadly Humean, sceptical stance, where we
withhold belief until sufficiently strong supporting reasons come along. Rather our
developmental starting point is a broadly Reidian, credulous stance (Harris 2002; Koenig
and Harris 2005). Very young children nearly automatically accept whatever they
comprehend. We are built to take comprehension states at face value; credulity is the
default.6
That said, we obviously do not believe everything we hear or read. Filtering soon
develops. If you label something right before a child's eyes when she already confidently
believes the opposite, she is less apt to believe you. If you call a cup a dog right before
a 16-month-old, the child will direct more attention to you than she will to speakers who
correctly label the object. If you do the same thing before an 18-month-old, she may even
correct you (Koenig, Clement, and Harris 2004).
Another filter involves manner of presentation. Three- and four-year-olds are sensitive to
how confident an assertion is. An unsure, less committal tone of voice sometimes makes
acceptance less likely. Conversely, more confident assertions make acceptance more
likely (Moore, Bryant, and Furrow 1989; Jaswal 2004).
Young children acquire track record information, either first hand or from others. On the
basis of this information, they tend to selectively accept assertions. When children have
information that a speaker is reliable, that speaker tends to prompt belief more often than
the speakers which children know are less reliable. Again, it is three- and four-year-olds
that display this ability, with four-year-olds showing more sensitivity to such information
(Koenig, Clement, and Harris 2004). This stands to reason, for only after children acquire
the concepts of belief and truth are they in a position to form beliefs about which of their
interlocutors are reliable, beliefs they can then rely upon in blocking or supporting the
transition from comprehension to belief. (I have in mind the false belief task.)7
Coherence-checking, a fourth form of filtering, emerges later. I will have more to say
about coherence checking further along. As we mature, we rely on these filters and more.
152
Filtering need not involve explicit awarenessbelief or judgementthat counter-
considerations are absent. Filtering need not involve reasons and reasoning. The subject
need only respond by dampening, if not entirely suspending, the normal force of
comprehension (Goldberg and Henderson 2006).
In sum, filtering involves sensitivity to counter-considerations: were there are counter-
considerations of a certain sort, acceptance would be less likely. Different filters involve
different sensitivities. We obviously do not believe whatever we are told; credulity as
default does not imply unalterable gullibility. We're no fools.
Sometimes filtering blocks the normal force of comprehension, but we still come to
believe what we were told. Consider Nick and Oscar. Nick correctly comprehends
Oscar's assertion. But Nick is suspicious of Oscar's credibility. Perhaps Nick antecedently
doubts that Oscar will tell the truth. Perhaps Oscar's story does not fit with other things
Nick believes. Perhaps Oscar's report contains internal contradictions. Or perhaps Oscar
is alarmingly fidgety. If this were the end of the matter, Nick would not believe what
Oscar just said. But on reflection Nick thinks Oscar can be relied upon. Taking as a
premise that Oscar asserted that P, Nick comes to believe that P. Nick's warrant is a
justification, an argument from Oscar's assertion that P as premise (and other believed
propositions) to the conclusion that P. Nick's belief is, as it were, from comprehension
without being through comprehension (cf. Audi 1997).
Once we mature, comprehension involves a default-trigger-and-evaluate structure. Peter
Lipton explains:
[I]n most contexts the hearer simply accepts what is [taken as] said, without engaging in
any conscious evaluation or inference . . . [But] there are diverse conditions that may
trigger the hearer to switch into evaluative mode, where he pauses to consider whether he
should believe what he has been told. . . . The obvious triggers include cases where what
is claimed obviously contradicts firmly held beliefs, cases of contradictory testimony, and
cases where there is reason to worry about incompetence or insincerity. (2007: 241)
Comprehension states dispose belief, but not willy-nilly. Though credulous, we do not
believe everything we are told. We filter and, on occasion, evaluate.
2. ETIOLOGICAL FUNCTIONS
I now turn from psychology to teleology. In this section I explicate the notions of
function, normal functioning, and normal conditions. There are at least three kinds of
functions. My account of entitlement employs the third.
First, there is the familiar category of intended (consciously assigned) functions for items
we design to produce certain effects. Artefacts (tools) have many of their functions
because of what we have in mind when making them. Usually an artefact's function is
what it was consciously and intentionally designed to do. Belts were designed to hold up
trousers. Watches were designed to tell the
153
time. Cars were built to take us from point A to point B. The artefact was made, shaped,
arranged, composed, manufactured, in order to produce a certain effect. The effect is
what the designer had in mind that explains why she made, shaped, arranged, composed,
or manufactured the artefact. Call these d-functions.
Second, there are functions fixed by one-off, occasion specific intentions. Intentions are
goals, aims, or purposes. Like function, intention is a teleological notion. An intention on
an occasion explains why someone does something, or what he or she is using an item
for. I went out to get a breath of fresh air. I put the stapler in the doorway to keep the
door ajar. Call these functions i-functions.
A third kind of function applies paradigmatically to biological organs and systems,
though it has a much wider application. It even applies to some functions of artefacts; not
all functions of artefacts are d-functions. I have in mind etiological functions, where the
function of an item essentially depends on certain explanatory features of its history. Call
etiological functions e-functions.8
An e-function of an item is the effect of ancestors of the item that explains why the item
was replicated, and so why the item exists now, where the item (or the system of which it
is a part [Buller 1998, 2002]), underwent some form of selection (natural, artificial,
cultural, or some other form). Take the heart. Its function is to pump blood. Hearts now
exist because ancestors of hearts pumped blood, and in so doing contributed to survival
long enough for new hearts. The eye is for seeing. Eyes now exist because ancestors
provided information about the spatial array of objects in the environment. For most
animals, sexual reproduction is the mechanism of copying where later hearts are
produced on the model of past hearts. But other methods of copying will do. E-functions
arise when certain effects of ancestors of an item explain why the item persists.9
E-functions are real features of biological kinds. When evolutionary biologists
taxonomize according to function, they look for effects that played an important role in
explaining why the organs, systems, or activities of animals persist.
But as I have already said, e-functions are not simply biological functions. E-functions
are effects of ancestors of any item that played a role in explaining why reproductions of
that item exist, no matter what the item is, or
154
how it was reproduced. Learned behaviours, linguistic devices, conventions, cultural
practices, games, and so on, may all have etiological functions (Millikan 1984).
The logic of e-functions comes with an informative account of what counts as normal
conditions and normal functioning (Millikan 1984: 334). When an item has an
etiological function, there is an explanation in terms of that function for why the item
exists. It exists now, in part, because its ancestors, when working or operating a certain
way in certain circumstances, produced the effect that contributed to the item being
replicated. That effect becomes the item's etiological function. The way the item operated
according to that explanation counts as normal functioning. If the current item works or
operates that way (or in relevantly similar ways; there are borderline cases), then it
functions normally; it operates the way it is supposed to operate. And the conditions
according to that explanation (or conditions of similar type; there are borderline cases),
fix normal conditions. Take the heart. It beat (worked, functioned) a particular way in an
organism's body in a particular environment. By beating that way, it pumped blood and
thereby contributed to the survival and reproduction of the organism. Pumping blood
thereby became the function of the heart. Normal functioning is then just beating or
working the way it did that contributes to the explanation of the heart's acquiring the
function of pumping blood.10
This explanatory, individuative interconnection (between function ascription, function
fulfilment, normal conditions, and normal functioning) means that for any item with an e-
function, ceteris paribus it will fulfil its function, often enough, in normal conditions
when functioning (operating, working) normally. If it did not, then the item would not
have been replicated because of that effect; it would not have that e-function. This falls
out of the logic of e-functions.
155
This fact marks an important difference between e-functions, on the one hand, and d-
functions and i-functions, on the other. You can design something to produce a certain
effect, but it may fail to ever do it. Think of the dustbin of failed inventions. You can also
intend to do something but not succeed. If only life were so easy. Not so for etiological
functions. No type of item with an etiological function can have tokens that fail across the
board.
We now have an important explanatory fact to rely upon for items with etiological
functions: ceteris paribus normal functioning in normal conditions leads to function
fulfilment. We can then partially individuate and explain normal functioning in terms of
normal conditions and function fulfilment. If you know the etiological function of an
item, functioning normally just is working or operating in the way that, according to the
historical, normal explanation for the item, fulfils that function often enough ceteris
paribus in normal conditions. Normal functioning is thus individuated and understood in
terms of function fulfilment.
You can fulfil your function without functioning normally, and function normally without
fulfilling your function. Stimulate a diseased heart artificially and it may pump blood,
though not because it is working the way it is supposed to. You can also take a heart out
of someone's chest and put it in a sterile dish; it may still function (work, operate)
normally for a time, but no blood is passing through it. Put a car up on a lift for
inspection, and it may function just fine, even if it is not hurtling you down the highway
at 65 miles per hour. Fulfilling a function is one thing, functioning normally is another,
despite their explanatory relation.
Different items fulfil their functions at different rates, even in normal conditions when
functioning normally. The function of spermor the sperm-producing deviceis to
fertilize eggs.11 But sperm hardly ever do that, even in normal conditions, functioning as
normally as can be. Sperm need only fertilize eggs often enough. And often enough, for
sperm, is not very often. But at the other end of the spectrum some devices fulfil their
functions all of the time when functioning normally in normal conditions. The heart
provides a good illustration; it pumps blood all the time. Less reliable hearts were
selected out. Some items thus have reliability vis--vis a certain effect as their function.
The heart clearly does; the heart is for reliably pumping blood.
Functional items often have a plurality of functions. One item may be intended, designed,
or selected to do many things. It may have more than one causal-role capacity. Most do.
It is thus misleading to speak of the function of an item. When it comes to etiological
functions and biological items in particular,
156
there is often a plurality at horizontal levels on the vertical dimension. An example
will show what I mean. The tongue is for eating; it moves food around as we chew, and
also assists in swallowing. But the tongue is also for talking; it helps form word sounds in
conjunction with other parts of our mouth and vocal tract. These are all functions of the
tongue at the same horizontal level. By doing all of these things, the tongue assists in
fulfilling other functions, such as getting enough food and nutrients into the bloodstream
so as to nourish other parts of the body, so as to remain healthy and fit, so as to assist in
dealing with the creature's natural habitat, so as to find more food, avoid predators, find
mates, and so on, so as to live long enough to survive to reproduce. All of these other
more distal effects of the tongue are among its functions. On this vertical dimension, the
tongue has many functions. (And so my title is a bit misleading. I argue for a function of
comprehension and not for its one and only function.)
Items also lose e-functions over time (the appendix), acquire additional e-functions over
time (feathers), and even lose one e-function only to acquire another (limbs). When we
speak of the e-functions of an item, we often mean current functions (Millikan 1984,
2002; Godfrey-Smith 1994; Schwartz 2002). Origins are one thing; functions
(sometimes) are another.
To sum up, there are (at least) four kinds of functions: designed, intention-determined,
causal-role, and etiological functions. They all differ notionally and extensionally, though
in particular cases two or more may overlap. When it comes to items with etiological
functions, ceteris paribus they fulfil their functions in normal conditions when
functioning normally. Normal functioning is thus operating or working in a manner that,
in normal conditions, leads to function fulfilment. If you know an etiological function of
an item, you can thereby partially individuate and explain normal functioning in terms of
that function. And some itemslike the hearthave reliability vis--vis an effect as a
function. Normal functioning, for the heart, is thus individuated and understood, in part,
in terms of reliably pumping blood.
3. EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT
I now use the etiological notions of function and normal functioning to explicate (a kind
of) epistemic entitlement (cf. note 3). I argue that entitlement attaches to beliefs in virtue
of the normal functioning of the belief-forming process when the process has forming
true beliefs reliably as an etiological function.
First, positive epistemic standings are goods, successes, fulfilments, or achievements
understood in terms of promoting true belief and avoiding error. Warrants are positive
epistemic standings that epistemically support or ground beliefs. Warrants are positive
epistemic standings, and so are themselves goods, successes, fulfilments, or achievements
understood, at least in part, in terms
157
of promoting true belief and avoiding error. Any explication of a kind of warrant must
explain why the warrant is a success, good, fulfilment, or achievement understood in
terms of promoting true belief and avoiding error.
Second, function fulfilment is a success or good. The function sets a standard or norm.
Fulfilling the function achieves that standard. Meeting the standard is success or
fulfilment, and as such is a good for the item with the function. And failure to fulfil the
norm is just that, failure. Normal functioning is also a fulfilment. Functioning normally is
functioning (operating, working) the way the item is supposed to operate. Think of the
heart. Beating normally is the way the heart is supposed to beat. In beating that way, it
pumps blood. Beating normally fulfils a standard for the heart. And failure to operate
normally is just that, a failure. Normal functioning is a success or fulfilment for the
functional item, and as such is a good for the item. Using achievement broadly, function
fulfilment and normal functioning are both achievements for functional items.
Despite their explanatory interrelation, function fulfilment and normal functioning are
distinct achievements. Recall that you can fulfil your function without functioning
normally, and vice versa. A heart in a sterile dish may function (work, operate) normally
without blood passing through. A car up the lift may function just fine without taking you
where you want to go.
Third, for any belief-forming system or process whose etiological function is to form true
beliefs reliably, ceteris paribus it will form true beliefs reliably in normal conditions
when functioning normally. This follows automatically from the logic of etiological
functions. Normal functioning for such a process is thus functioning in a way that, in
normal conditions, reliably produces true beliefs. Normal functioning for any such
system is then individuated and understood in terms of reliability and truth. Again, all of
this follows from the logic of e-functions, as just explained.
Putting two and two together, we arrive at an account of epistemic entitlement.
Entitlement is a kind of warrant that does not depend on reasons or evidence available to
the subject. Entitlements are psychologically and developmentally more primitive kinds
of warrants. Warrants generally are fulfilments, successes, or goods understood, at least
in part, in terms of promoting true belief and avoiding error that ground or support belief.
Normal functioning is an achievement, success, or good understood in terms of function
fulfilment. So for any belief-forming process whose e-function is reliably producing true
beliefs, normal functioning for that process is an achievement understood, at least in part,
in terms of promoting true belief and avoiding error. When the belief-forming process
functions normally, it epistemically grounds or supports the belief it thereby causes or
sustains. A kind of warrant thus attaches to belief when formed on the basis of a normally
functioning belief-forming process whose function is to form true beliefs reliably. Since
this warrant does not depend on reasons or evidence
158
available to the subject, it is (a kind of) entitlement. A normally functioning belief-
forming process that has forming true beliefs reliably as a function confers entitlement on
the beliefs it normally causes and sustains. I have established my first thesis, an account
of (a kind of) entitlement.
What does this account imply about the massively deceived brain-in-a-vat? In such a
case, the standard belief-forming processes are all functioning normally, but they are not
reliable. Envatted, the subject's belief-forming process may all function (operate, work)
normally, even while not in normal conditions. They thus enjoy (a kind of) entitlement
just as if the subject were not envatted. The brain is like a car up the lift for inspection.
The subject's belief-forming processes are operating just fine, even though they are not
producing and sustaining true beliefs at, so to speak, sixty-five miles an hour.
And what does this account imply about the beneficiary of an accidentally acquired,
merely reliable belief-forming process, a process the subject knows absolutely nothing
about (that he has it, that it is reliable, and so on)? Merely accidentally acquired, the
process has no function. It's just a mutation. Nothing then counts as normal functioning
for the process. Though the subject's beliefs so caused enjoy the epistemic good of being
mostly true, they lack the achievement conferred by function fulfilment, for it lacks a
function, and they lack the achievement conferred from normal functioning, for nothing
counts as normal functioning.
Space does not allow me the luxury of responding to familiar objections to etiological
accounts of epistemological properties. I hope I have said enough here to make my
account of entitlement prima facie plausible. Elsewhere I answer some of the more
prominent objections.12
Perceptual beliefs paradigmatically enjoy entitlement, for (most) perceptual belief-
forming systems have reliably forming true beliefs as an etiological function. I argue that
comprehension-with-filtering-based beliefs enjoy entitlement for the very same reason;
comprehension with filtering has forming true beliefs reliably as an e-function. When our
capacity to comprehend and filter functions normally, it meets a standard understood in
terms of promoting true belief and avoiding error. That is why our comprehension-with-
filtering based beliefs enjoy prima facie pro tanto entitlement. (As I noted, this a good
place to take a break.)
4. AN ETIOLOGICAL FUNCTION OF ASSERTION
But before arguing that comprehension-with-filtering has reliably causing and sustaining
true beliefs as an e-function, I first argue that assertion has inducing (and sustaining) true
hearer belief as an etiological function. (Recall I am using assertion broadly.) I take up
assertion first for two reasons. Making the
159
case for assertion practically makes the case for comprehension-with-filtering; if the
argument is plausible for assertion, it will be even more plausible for comprehension-
with-filtering. And most of the relevant discussion in the literature so far has focused on
assertion instead of comprehension.13 As a result, the question whether comprehension-
with-filtering is for reliably forming true beliefs is apt to be confused with whether
assertion has that function. Discussing assertion first should head off potential
misunderstanding.
To show that assertion has inducing true hearer beliefs as one of its etiological functions,
I begin with an argument from C. A. J. Coady intended to demonstrate the reliability of
any practice of reporting. Though Coady's argument unsurprisingly falls short, it reveals
an important fact about assertion.
Coady conducted a thought experiment involving a community of Martians. Let us
suppose for the moment, he writes,
that they have a language we can translate (there are difficulties in this supposition . . . )
with names for distinguishable things in their environment and suitable predicative
equipment. We find however, to our astonishment, that whenever they construct
sentences addressed to each other in the absence (from their vicinity) of the things
designated by the names, but when they are, as we should think, in a position to report,
they seem to say what we (more synoptically placed) can observe to be false. (1992: 85)
Coady then asked whether any hearer would have any reason to rely on what a speaker
says in such a situation. He replies that
any Martian has four powerful reasons for not relying on what others appear to be telling
him: (i) he finds their reports' false whenever he checks personally on them, (ii) he finds
reliance upon them consistently leads him astray in practice, (iii) he finds himself utterly
unreliable in what he tells others and it is, at least in part, possible that he is not atypical,
(iv) others often give chaotically different reports on those matters beyond his checking.
(1992: 87)
Coady inferred there would then be no practice of making and accepting reports. Given
what each Martian can expect of the other,
it is . . . very hard to imagine the activity of reporting in anything like its usual setting
with the Martians, for there would surely be no reliance upon the reportive utterances of
others. [T]he Martain community cannot reasonably be held to have the practice of
reporting . . . (1992: 87)
Coady concluded that any practice of reporting must be reliable.
I think Coady missed a premise. With the premise he needs, Coady's argument goes like
this:
(1) If everyone in a community, when making reports, always makes false reports, then
no one will have any reason for relying upon and accepting those reports. They have
four powerful reasons not to do so.
160
(2) A central reason (motive) for making reports is to get others to believe them.
(3) But if no one accepts those reports, then speakers will have no reason to think that
making those reports will lead hearers to believe them. (This is the missing premise.)
(4) So if no one accepts reports, speakers will stop making them.
In short: if all falsehoods uttered, then no acceptances; if no acceptances, then no reason
to report; if no reason to report, no reporting. Contraposed: if reports, then not all reports
are false. Hence: if reports, then truths.
In The Reliability of Testimony (Graham 2000c) I showed that this argument falls short
of establishing the reliability of any practice of reporting. At best it shows that reporting
practices exist because not all of the reports made are false. And not all are false surely
does not entail most are true.
Though this argument does not show what Coady hoped, it does bring out a very
important fact about linguistic practices: speakers and hearers both need some reason
(motive) to participate. Speakers, presumably, benefit in some way by affecting hearers.
If hearers receive no benefit from being so affected, they will probably stop responding in
the desired way. So unless hearers get something out of accepting reports, they will not
accept them. And if they will not accept them, speakers will not benefit by making them.
Then they will not get made. Hearer benefits (partly) explain speaker production.
Ruth Millikan exploits this very fact when arguing that various linguistic devices have
etiological functions. She has argued in general that (i) language devices produce effects
that interest speakers often enough to encourage continued replication by those speakers
only if hearers produce hoped-for responses often enough, and (ii) that hearers will
continue to produce those hoped-for responses often enough only if the results are of
interest to hearers (Millikan 2004: 25). Language devices exist, as a matter of fact, only if
their use benefits both speakers and hearers.
Applied to (declarative sentences in) the indicative mood, the device we paradigmatically
use to make assertions, she has argued that one of its central functions is to produce true
beliefs in the propositional content(s) of the utterance, for it is the effect that, often
enough, benefits hearers. Truth about relevant subject matters clearly benefits hearers.
Dan Sperber says that:
From the point of view of receivers, communication, and testimony in particular, is
beneficial only to the extent that it is a source of genuine (and of course relevant)
information. Just as in the case of individual cognition, there may be cases where biases
in communicated information are beneficial (think of exaggerated encouragement or
warnings, for instance), but these cases are marginal. (2001: 404)
Though inducing false beliefs sometimes benefits speakers, and it may also sometimes
benefit hearers, if hearers never got true information from assertive utterances of
declaratives in the indicative mood, they would quit forming beliefs
161
in response. And then speakers could not even get across false information when they
wanted to. (This is what Coady's thought experiment brings to the fore.) And if hearers
quit forming beliefs in response, then speakers would quit making those utterances. There
would be no point. True hearer belief thus explains why the indicative mood persists.
True hearer belief is thus a function of the indicative mood:
If no true beliefs ever resulted from hearer interpretations of indicative sentences, it is
clear that indicative syntactic patterns would cease to be used first by hearers and, as a
result, by speakers in the ways they now are. . . . The focused stabilizing function of the
indicative mood is thus the production of a true hearer belief. The function of the
indicative mood is to convey information. (Millikan 1984: 589)14
Millikan calls this function a stabilizing one, for it encourages speakers to keep using the
device and hearers to keep responding to it with the same (with a stable) response (2005:
94).15
Since the default, standard use of a declarative sentence in the indicative mood is to
assert, and since the same reasoning Millikan offers applies to assertive communication
generally, I conclude that an etiological function of assertion is to induce true belief in
hearers. Truth is a price speakers pay that keeps assertion in play. Though Coady failed to
establish the necessary reliability of any practice of reporting, he unearthed an important
fact that helps show that inducing true belief in hearers is an etiological function of
assertion.
5. ALTERNATIVE FUNCTIONS
Some will resist; assertions may regularly cause true beliefsassertion may even as a
matter of fact cause mostly true beliefsnevertheless inducing true belief is not what
assertion is for. In this section I reply to four counter-arguments. Responding to these
should help persuade the unpersuaded. The last counter-argument will also take us from
the function of assertion to the function of comprehension-with-filtering.
162
The first counter-argument focuses on what the speaker has in mind when making her
assertion. Call this the argument from occasion specific intentions. The argument goes as
follows. First, a function is a goal or purpose. Second, the function of a particular
assertion on a particular occasion is the goal, purpose, or intention of the speaker on that
occasion. Third, speakers have all sorts of purposes on various occasions. Sometimes
they intend that their interlocutors form true beliefs, sometimes they only intend shared
belief, sometimes they don't intend belief at all, sometimes they intend false belief, and
sometimes the truth status is just irrelevant. True hearer belief is thus not the intended
effect on each and every occasion. Hence true hearer belief cannot be what assertion, as a
type, is for. Assertion is for whatever speakers use it for.
Though I think this argument may be in the mind of many readers, it is rather easy to
rebut. From the fact that a particular speaker does not fail at fulfilling his aim when
making a false assertion, it does not follow that the etiological function of the linguistic
device he used performed its function.
Consider the heart. Though its function is to pump blood, a malicious surgeon may use
one as a paperweight. Or consider a bird's wing. Its e-function is to enable flight, though
you can cut it off and use it as a fan. Cut off from the bird, it clearly does not perform its
function, even if it keeps you cool. A speaker can use a language device, just as he can
use a tool or one of his body parts, to perform a function or to serve a purpose that is not,
however, the language device's own function (Millikan 1984: 52). E-functions and i-
functions are simply different things. So from the fact that a speaker does not intend to
convey truth on a particular occasion when asserting, nothing follows about the e-
functions of assertion.
There is, however, a connection between speaker purposes and the function of assertion.
Speaker purposes must be satisfied often enough, or they will stop making assertions. So,
in a clear sense, the fulfilment of speaker intentions in general is an etiological function
of assertion. But the CoadyMillikan argument places a constraint on speaker purposes.
Speakers must purpose true belief in hearers often enough for true belief to be a function
of assertion. Here again is Millikan:
But although the stabilizing function of a language device is independent of the purpose
of the particular speaker who utters it, it is not independent of speaker purposes in
general. The survival of a public language element without change of function must
depend upon their being a critical mass of occasions upon which speakers and hearers use
the element such that it performs its stabilizing function. (Millikan 1984: 53)
And so long as speakers purpose true belief often enough, hearers will respond to
assertions with belief often enough for speakers to keep making assertions. So speakers
satisfy their purposes in general when making assertions because they purpose true hearer
belief often enough. Speaker benefits are thus intertwined with hearer benefits, the
benefit of true belief in particular.
163
The next counter-argument exploits the standard Gricean view of communication. Call it
the argument from successful communication. On the Gricean view, communication
succeeds or occurs when the hearer recognizes the speaker's communicative intention. A
communicative intention is the speaker's intention that the hearer recognize that the
speaker intends that the hearer form a belief, answer a question, follow a command, and
so on. When the hearer recognizes the communicative intention communication occurs,
even if the hearer does not form the belief, answer the question, or follow the command.
Here is Stephen Levinson from his classic textbook:
[C]ommunication involves the notions of intention and agency, and only those inferences
that are openly intended to be conveyed can properly said to be communicated. . . .
Communication consists of the sender intending to cause the receiver to think or do
something, just by getting the receiver to recognize that the sender is trying to cause
that thought or action. So communication is a complex kind of intention that is achieved
or satisfied just by being recognized. [ . . . ] Attaining this state of mutual knowledge is to
have successfully communicated. (Levinson 1983: 1516)
Kent Bach puts the point more succinctly:
Communicative success is achieved if the speaker chooses his words in such a way that
the hearer will, under the circumstances of utterance, recognize his communicative
intention. ( . . .) An act of communication is successful if whoever it is directed to
recognizes the intention with which it is performed. In short, its fulfilment consists in its
recognition.
(Bach 2006: 153)
In a simple case, in assertively uttering U, the speaker intends that the hearer recognize
the speaker's intention that the hearer believes the propositional content(s) of U, and
perhaps various implicatures. Communication succeeds' if the hearer recognizes the
intention. A speaker can thus communicate when asserting P whether or not P is true, and
whether or not his interlocutor comes to believe P. That is simply how communication
works.16
With this view of communicative success' in hand, we can state two related arguments
for the conclusion that the function of assertion isn't inducing true hearer belief. The first
focuses on the transpersonal communicative process. The second focuses on the speaker's
side of the equation. I'll state and discuss the first before turning to the second.
So first think of communication as a transpersonal process: if the hearer correctly
recognizes the speaker's communicative intention, then communication has occurred. If
uptake did not occur, neither did communication.
164
Here is the counter-argument. First, function fulfilment is a success; failure to fulfil a
function is just that, failure. So we can derive the function of communication from what
counts as communicative success and failure. Third, communicative success involves
recognition of the speaker's communicative intention, and does not require forming belief
in the content of the assertion, let alone forming true belief. So if communication can
succeed (occur) without conveying true belief, true belief cannot be what it is for;
inducing true hearer belief cannot be a function of assertion.
This argument is a non-starter. For it conflates the ontological question of what
communication is (what it consists in, what must happen for it to occur) with the
teleological question of what it is for. The relevant sense of success' and failure in the
third premise is ontological or constitutive. But the relevant sense of success' and
failure in the first premise is teleological or purposive, where functions may go
unfulfilled. To say what assertive communication is for requires pointing to some effect
of successful communication. This argument is silent on that issue. Nothing in the
argument shows that inducing true beliefs is not what communication is for.
This problem, however, may be avoided if we formulate the argument in the second way
mentioned, in terms of the speaker's communicative act itself and its function. Here we
ask what the function of the speaker's communicative act happens to be, an act that may
fail in fulfilling its aim. The counter-argument would then go as follows. First, function
fulfilment is a success; failure to fulfil a function is just that, failure. So we can derive the
function of an assertive communicative act from what counts as success and what counts
as failure. Third, the speaker's assertive communicative acthis assertionsucceeds
when the hearer recognizes the speaker's communicative intention. The etiological
function of assertion would then be to induce hearer recognition of the speaker's
communicative intention. And recognizing this intention does not require that the hearer
believe what the speaker asserted, let alone require that the hearer believe something true.
So inducing true hearer belief cannot be what assertion is for. Paraphrasing Paul
Faulkner, when a hearer fails to form a true belief from communication, there is no sense
in which the speaker has failed to communicate (2000: 587).
Though this version of the argument from communicative success focuses on assertion
and its effects, and thereby avoids the rejoinder just made to the first version of the
argument, it fares no better. Simply put, it doesn't focus on effects that explain why
assertion as a type persists. An etiological function is an effect of a type that occurs often
enough that explains why the type persists. This argument does not address this issue. All
it points out is that a speaker, when making an assertion, intends that the hearer recognize
his communicative intention, and when the hearer does, the speaker has communicated.
But what is all of this for? What effect explains why speakers make assertions? What
effect explains why speakers publicize communicative intentions? What effect explains
165
why hearers even bother to recognize communicative intentions? The argument, though
arguably correct about the mechanics of assertive communication, does not address the
etiological question of what assertion is for.
Levinson himself is clearly aware of the fact that an account of how communication
works is one thing, and what linguistic devices are for is another. Well after arguing for a
Gricean account of communication, he notes that
[since] nearly all of the world's languages have the three basic sentence types: imperative,
interrogative and declarative . . . one might argue . . . on the grounds that these seem to be
used paradigmatically for ordering, questioning, and asserting . . . that they recur in the
languages of the world because humans are, perhaps, specifically concerned with three
functions of language in particularthe organization of other persons' actions, the
eliciting of information, and the conveying of information. (1983: 40)
The mechanism of communication is one thing; its purpose is another. Griceans may be
right about how communication works, while Darwinians (so to speak) are right about
what communication is for.17
Another counter-argument comes from a paper by Gloria Origgi and Dan Sperber entitled
Evolution, Communication, and the Proper Function of Language (2000). They target
Millikan's view that the indicative mood is for inducing true hearer belief. They argue
that its function is to provide evidence to assist the hearer in recognizing the speaker's
communicative intention. The function of linguistic utterances', and so the function of
assertions in particular, is not to affect hearer beliefs in the content of what is asserted,
but rather to provide highly precise and informative evidence of the communicator's
intention (Origgi and Sperber 2000: 163).
The following passage contains Origgi and Sperber's reasoning. I have added emphasis to
draw attention to a key premise:
Our disagreement with Millikan has to do with the level of processing at which linguistic
devices elicit the reliable response to be identified as their direct proper function. For
Millikan, this reliable response is to be found at the level of belief or desire formation, or
even at the behavioral level in the case of compliance . . . What is the alternative?
Linguistic
166
devices produce highly reliable responses, not at the level of the cognitive outputs of
comprehension such as belief or desire formation, and even less at the level of behavioral
outputs such as compliance, but at an intermediate level in the process of comprehension.
Linguistic comprehension involves, at an intermediate and largely unconscious level, the
decoding of linguistic stimuli that are then used as evidence by the hearer, together with
the context, to arrive inferentially at the speaker's meaning . . . Linguistic devices have
proliferated and stabilized because they cause these highly reliable cognitive responses at
this intermediate level. Linguistic devices provide speakers and hearers with
informationally rich, highly structured, and reliably decoded evidence of speaker's
meaning.
(Origgi and Sperber 2000: 163)
Call this the argument from highly reliable effects. The argument goes like this. First,
etiological functions are highly reliable effects. Second, the highly reliable effect of
assertions (and other linguistic devices and speech acts) is not true hearer belief but the
providing to hearers of evidence for the speaker's communicative intentions. Hence
providing evidence of the speaker's communicative intention, or perhaps the hearer's
decoding and recognizing that evidence (Origgi and Sperber speculate on where to locate
the function in the causal chain) is the etiological function of linguistic devices.
The argument makes two mistakes. First, as we have seen, etiological functions are not
necessarily highly reliable effects. True, pumping blood is a highly reliable effect of the
heart, and the function of the heart is to pump blood. But this is not true of all items with
etiological functions. Recall sperm. Millikan would be the last person to identify
functions with highly reliable effects. Though some items do have reliability as an aspect
of their function (like the heart), some clearly do not. You thus cannot infer function from
highly reliable effect. Indeed, some highly reliable effects are not even functions. The
heart makes noise just as frequently as it pumps blood, and making noise is not one of its
functions.
Second, even if providing evidence of the speaker's communicative intention is an
etiological function of a linguistic device, it does not follow that it is the only etiological
function. Recall that items with etiological functions often have a number of functions,
both horizontally and vertically. Just as the heart assists in removing wastes and
circulating nutrients by pumping blood, and it pumps blood by beating at a certain rate in
a certain way, so too assertion may induce true hearer belief by providing evidence of
speaker's intentions. Assertion, like any other functional item, can have more than one
function. Linguistic devices may have proliferated and stabilized (in part) because they
provide evidence of speaker's intentions, but they have also proliferated and stabilized by
having effects on hearers that explain why hearers care to recover speaker's intentions
from the evidence provided in the first place. Origgi and Sperber have provided no reason
for thinking that inducing true hearer belief cannot be an etiological function of assertion.
At best they are correct that inducing true hearer belief is not its only function. And so
this argument too fails to undermine the thesis that inducing true hearer belief is an
etiological function of assertion.
167
Though I have already expanded at some length defending this thesis, I would be amiss to
not address one last counter-argument. The argument derives from discussions of the
evolutionary origin of the human language faculty. It is widely held in those discussions
that language arose in order to facilitate social bonding and social interaction, so that our
primate evolutionary ancestors might operate effectively in larger groups, where larger
groups promote higher levels of fitness. Robin Dunbar argued for this view at length in
his book Grooming, Gossip, and the Evolution of Language (1996). Here is Robbins
Burling stating the older view of the origins of language in his book The Talking Ape:
There was a time, not so many decades ago, when anyone who thought at all about the
evolution of language took the reasons for its selection to be more or less self-evident.
We use language today for every sort of practical purpose, to exchange information, to
coordinate our daily lives, and to instruct the young, so it only seemed reasonable to
suppose that, from its earliest days, hunters and gathers used language for much the same
purposes. (Burling 2005: 181)
He goes on to embrace the social interaction view:
I share a growing consensus that our intelligence evolved primarily as a means for
dealing with other individuals. Ours is primarily a social intelligence, and language is one
product, and one part of, that intelligence. In preurban societies, and even our own,
language in its most delicately nuanced form is used, not so much for basic subsistence
tasks, as for establishing, maintaining, and refining social relationships. It is when dealing
with people, not with material objects, that we call on our richest linguistic resources.
(Burling 2005: 184)
And so we once thought that language arose for exchanging information but we now
think language arose for dealing with other individuals'. Communication, and assertion
in particular, is thus not for inducing true hearer belief, but rather for interacting with
others and maintaining social bonds. So instead of focusing on more proximal effects of
assertion (such as providing evidence of speaker intentions or the actual recognition of
such intentions), this argument focuses on the more distal effects of inducing belief
through communication. Assertion is thus for social bonding, not for conveying true
information. Call this the argument from social interaction.
The error in this argument should be easy to spot. There is no opposition between social
bonding and conveying information as etiological functions for assertion. A closer
reading of Dunbar and Burling (see also Pinker and Bloom 1990; Dessalles 2007;
Hurford 2007) reveals no such opposition at all. In fact, Dunbar holds that language
conduced bonding and so the forming of larger groups by conveying information about
social matters. Social bonding is simply higher up in the vertical hierarchy of language
functions. Conveying true information is one etiological function of communication:
language evolved to facilitate the bonding of social groups, and . . . it mainly achieves
this aim by . . . the exchange of socially relevant information. (Dunbar 1996: 120)
168
language evolved to exchange information about other individuals in the
group . . . language evolved to exchange social information. (Dunbar 1996: 142)
Language . . . is very much a social tool . . . it allows us to exchange information relevant
to our ability to survive in a complex, constantly changing social world . . .
(Dunbar 1996: 170)
And so the old view is that language evolved primarily to convey information about
where and how to find food and avoid danger. The new view is that it evolved in
addition, if not primarily, to convey information about social matters to build groups
where building groups, in turn, has obvious implications for survival. Burling concludes:
Thanks to the eagerness of people to display their knowledge, we are able to learn
important things from conversation and it is people that we learn most about. Since it is
maneuvering through the social system that gives us the most difficult challenges of our
lives, the information we gain by learning how others have behaved is extremely
valuable. It is fortunate for the hearer, then, that we are at least as eager to pass on
information as to receive it. (Burling 2005: 196)
Either way, language originated, in part, to convey true information.
Summing up, assertive utterances provide evidence of speaker's intentions. Hearers
recognize speaker's intentions and thereby comprehend speaker's assertions.
Comprehension in turn induces true belief, often enough, and thereby provides an
obvious benefit to hearers. Conveying true belief builds social bonds, where building
bonds conveys benefits to both speakers and hearers. Conveying true information is one
effect of assertion that clearly explains why assertion, as a type, persists. The immediate
effect of language when used in standard conditions, in other words, its proximal
function, is . . . to convey . . . the information and knowledge possessed . . . by the
speaker (Dessalles 2007: 315).18 (In need of a break? This would be another good place
to pause.)
6. COMPREHENSION, RELIABILITY, AND FILTERING
Absent counter-considerations, we take comprehension at face value. My topic is the
epistemology of this process. What kinds of warrant do beliefs
169
based on comprehension-with-filtering enjoy? I argued a priori in section 3 that beliefs
based on a normally functioning process that has forming true beliefs reliably as an
etiological function enjoy prima facie pro tanto entitlement. Beliefs based on
comprehension-with-filtering will thus enjoy entitlement provided comprehension-with-
filtering has forming true beliefs reliably as an etiological function. Does comprehension-
with-filtering have that function?
I have just argued that the usual causal precursor to comprehensionassertionhas
inducing true hearer belief as an etiological function. If assertion is for producing true
belief, and it does so by triggering comprehension states, so comprehension states are
also for inducing true hearer belief. If not enough of the beliefs formed on the basis of
comprehension were true, then hearers would not be moved to comprehend assertions or
transition from comprehension to belief in the first place. The argument of section 4 and
its defence in section 5 carries over automatically to comprehension. And since the
transition from comprehension to belief is not intentional in the way assertions are, the
first three counter-arguments just discussed do not touch the extension of the argument
from assertion to comprehension. Comprehension has inducing true beliefs as a function.
But what about inducing true beliefs reliably? Does comprehension have producing true
beliefs reliably as a function?
I am happy to grant the possibility that comprehension taken alone, comprehension
without filtering, may fail to have inducing true beliefs reliably as a function. I am happy
to grant the possibility for my thesis does not require it. My thesis is that comprehension-
with-filtering has forming true beliefs reliably as a function, not comprehension neat,
comprehension taken alone. It's the filtering, or so I argue, that is for producing a
sufficiently high truth ratio. On the other hand, if it turns out that comprehension neat
reliably induces true beliefs, and that is why we do it, then comprehension as such would
confer entitlement when functioning normally. My argument here would then establish a
higher degree of entitlement for beliefs based on comprehension-with-filtering.
But before I argue that comprehension-with-filtering is for reliably inducing true belief,
let me make one point very clear. I am not arguing a priori that comprehension-with-
filtering is necessarily reliable. My argument is broadly empirical. What's a priori is my
account of entitlement. Its application to comprehension-with-filtering is empirical (cf.
Goldman 1986).
So why should we think comprehension-with-filtering induces true beliefs reliably, and
why should we think it has inducing true beliefs reliably as an etiological function? The
answer turns on understanding why we filter, what filtering is for.
170
Recall the logic of the argument derived from Coady and Millikan. Speakers assert for
some benefit. Hearers in turn form beliefs for some benefit. Unless hearers formed true
beliefs often enough, they would stop forming beliefs as a response to speaker assertions.
Speakers would no longer benefit by making assertions. Assertions would then no longer
get made. Inducing true hearer belief is thus a stabilizing function of assertion. So far I
have emphasized how hearers benefit: they form true beliefs. I have not discussed how
speakers benefit, benefits that explain why we are so disposed to make assertions in the
first place.
There are many ways speakers might benefit by making assertions. By providing useful
and relevant information, speakers gain status and build coalitions (Dessalles 2007), build
social bonds (Dunbar 1996; Burling 2005), enhance cooperative activities (Tomasello
2008), and even attract reproductive partners (Burling 2005). And the argument so far
reveals that speakers acquire these benefits by providing true information, at least often
enough. Some of these benefits explain the origins of informative speech and
communication. Some explain its current shape. Providing true information leads to
speaker benefits that historically and currently explain why assertions get made, and so
explains why assertion as a type persists.
So we benefit both as speakers and hearers in a variety of ways from communication,
where the passing along of true information plays a vital role in accounting for all of this.
But despite the utility of true information, how often do we actually present the truth?
How honest are we? Don't we often deceive? What about the actual frequency of cheats
and liars? Don't speakers often appear to cooperatively provide useful information that
turns out to be bogus? And can't speakers sometimes reap the benefits associated with
making assertions but without paying the price of providing true information? Perhaps
speaker benefits on occasions may be best achieved not by providing true information,
but by distorting the truth, or even saying what is clearly false (Sperber 2001). And won't
the cost to speakers of acquiring true and useful information, and the cost of sharing such
information, sometimes serve as a motive for trying to reap the benefits of being a good
information provider by providing apparently genuine information that is not the real
thing (Dessalles 2007)? Won't conflicting motives and the cost of acquiring information
lead speakers, on occasions, to say what is not the case? Isn't some degree of
misinformation guaranteed by the logic of the argument? Dan Sperber concludes that
a significant proportion of socially acquired beliefs are likely to be false beliefs, and this
not just a result of the malfunctioning, but also of the proper [normal] functioning of
social communication. . . . [T]he cognitive manipulation of others is one of the effects
that makes the practices of testimony and argumentation adaptive. This contributes to
explaining why these practices have evolved and stabilized among humans.
(Sperber 2001: 402)
171
Some degree of misinformation is thus bound to result from the very logic of the
argument that shows that assertion has providing true information as (one of) its
etiological function(s).
On the other hand, hearers do not sit idly by as speakers mislead or otherwise misinform.
Hearers develop countermeasures. Hearers develop capacities for filtering out reliance on
fake information providers. Indeed, for communication to stabilize, hearers must develop
such filters. Here again is Sperber:
if communication has stabilized among humans, it must be that there are ways to
calibrate one's confidence in communicated information so as that the expected benefits
are greater than the expected costs. (Sperber 2001: 406)
One important filter consists in detecting cognitive conflicts: coherence checking.
Sperber suggests that
coherence checkingwhich involves metarepresentational attention to logical and
evidential relationships between representationsevolved as a means of reaping the
benefits of communication while limiting its costs. (Sperber 2001: 410)
Jean-Louis Dessalles agrees with the challenge and its solution:
Let us assume that whatever benefit speakers derive will increase with the salience of the
situations they speak of. This makes for a strong temptation to exaggerate or even to tell
lies. The risk run by a hearer is that of affording an undue benefit to the speaker. Against
this risk, hearers have two strategies, trivialization through comparison with already
known situations and detection of inconsistencies. Both of these rely on faculties with
which natural selection has endowed us as human beings, among which are a sense of
probabilities and the ability to detect cognitive conflicts. Each of these conversational
mechanisms has thus much the same function as the other, that is avoidance of cheating
in communication. (Dessalles 2007: 331)
hearers . . . run the risk of being cheated in verbal interactions . . . The original role of the
detection of cognitive conflicts can be made sense of as the attempts of hearers to guard
against lying. (Dessalles 2007: 330)
Though there are incentives for speakers to cheat or mislead, we develop filters for
screening out their influence. Coherence checking is one. We encountered other filters in
the first section. We deploy all of these and more.19
172
Filtering thus plays a very important role; it ensures the reliability of beliefs formed on
the basis of comprehension, for misleading or untrustworthy assertions often get filtered
out. We're not so easy to mislead:
hearers have effective ways of assessing the quality of information supplied to them
and . . . this makes it difficult to mislead them. (Dessalles 2007: 332)
the only signals that natural selection can favour are the reliable ones. With
language . . . the reliability of the message is . . . guaranteed by . . . its resistance to
hearer's assessments. . . . It is not . . . easy to tell lies, even with words, as hearers test the
logical consistency of what they are told. (Dessalles 2007: 331)
Furthermore, filtering not only dampens the possibility of accepting a false report, it also
provides an incentive for speakers not to cheat in the first place. For cheaters often get
caught. Indeed, a good deal of the social gossip hypothesis is driven by the idea that one
very useful kind of information we receive from communication is information about
which speakers tend to cheat (Dunbar 1996). Given the cost of getting caught, nature has
even implanted in speakers a disposition to stick to the facts:
[We have] an emotional warning whenever we are tempted to lie. Our own nervousness
cautions us to be careful, and the nervousness may be visible enough to make others
suspicious. We are not as good at lying as evolutionary theory and sheer self-interest
might lead us to expect, but since lying can be risky, caution may be beneficial. Once
people catch you in serious contradictions, and once they start to share this interesting
and relevant information with your friends, you will lose badly in the competition for
prestige. You would have fared even worse in a society of a few hundred people where
everyone know and depended on everyone else. Most of us simply don't have the skill to
stray very far from the truth without getting caught. We can avoid danger by sticking
reasonably close to reality. (Burling 2005: 196)
Filtering not only filters out false or misleading assertions, it also provides an incentive
for speakers to not mislead in the first place.
Comprehension-with-filtering may not, as a matter of fact, be as reliable as perception.
But for all that, it is still an awfully good way of acquiring information; it is a very
reliable guide to the way things are. And the reliability enhancing aspect of filtering
explains, at least in part, why we bother to filter what we take others to assert.
Comprehension-with-filtering has inducing true beliefs reliably as a function. Getting
informed is one thing, among others, that comprehension-with-filtering is for.
There are different kinds of warrant. Many comprehension-based beliefs are supported by
justifications. But comprehension-based beliefs also enjoy entitlements. For beliefs based
on normally functioning processes that have
173
forming true beliefs reliably as an etiological function enjoy entitlement, and
comprehension-with-filtering has that function.20
174
9 Knowing from Being Told
Alan Millar
1. INTRODUCTION
In this chapter I sketch an epistemology of what I shall call straightforward cases of
testimony. Here is an instance. Wondering if I have left a certain book in my study I
phone home from the university. My son answers, I tell him about the book, he looks in
my study and sees that it's on my desk. He tells me this. From his telling me I come to
know that the book is on my desk. Straightforward cases are like this. They have the
following features.
(1) It is entirely natural to suppose that recipients gain knowledge of what they are told
from being told it. As a result they can rationally be assured of the matter and cease
any enquiry into it that they have been pursuing. Should the need arise they could
responsibly vouch for the truth of what they have been told.
(2) Recipients do not deliberate about the likelihood or otherwise that what they have
been told is true. They unhesitatingly accept what they have been told.
(3) Notwithstanding (2), recipients are not undiscriminating. Features of the utterance
and its context are relevant to their unhesitant acceptance of what they have been told
and to their knowing what they have been told. In the example I have given it is
relevant, for instance, that it is my son who is telling me, that the content of his
communication is a routine matter, and that he speaks to me in a straightforward
matter-of-fact way. I might not have so readily accepted something he had told me if
the subject matter or context had been different. For instance, if he had told me that
there is a smudge on my nose, in the context of light-heartedness, I might well have
been more circumspect, knowing that he takes pleasure in showing me to be gullible.
175
The challenge posed by straightforward cases arises from three considerations. The first
is that the knowledge gained by recipients is evidence-based if only in the sense that
something occursan act of tellingthat is empirically detected and that supplies the
reason or at least part of the reason for accepting the thing told. The second is that telling
is a speech act by means of which informants give it to be understood that they are
informing those with whom they are communicating. The third is that recipients need not
at any conscious level register the features of the act of telling that account for their
unhesitating acceptance of what they are told. Stepping back from the situation in which
my son confirmed the location of my book, I can think of factors that help to explain my
unhesitating acceptance of what he told me. There are factors relating to the content of
the utterance. It was clearly within my son's capabilities to ascertain that the book was in
my study. He could have little reason for misleading me on this trivial matter. He speaks
as he would if straightforwardly communicating information. The context is one in which
I have expressly enquired about the book and would be unlikely to appreciate his fooling
around. However, there is no reason to suppose that these factors need have been
registered at the level of judgement. Indeed, the factors themselves and their full range
are elusive. I cannot describe them specifically but can at best gesture towards them. I
could not pin down what it was about his manner of speaking, the context and so forth
that made the communication effective. Even to provide a gesturing description requires
a degree of reflection that recipients in the straightforward cases are not bound to have.
To some it might sound odd to say that my son's telling me that the book is at home is
evidence that the book is at home and that the knowledge I gain is, accordingly, evidence-
based. Calling it evidence might suggest that it is to be viewed as something to be
weighed alongside other considerations for and against taking what I am told to be true.
But a feature of the straightforward cases is that no weighing up is done even though
knowledge is acquired. Another motivation for pausing over whether knowledge in the
straightforward cases should be treated as evidence-based is supplied by the second of the
features of those cases noted above. Whereas treating acts of telling as evidence for the
thing told might suggest that the epistemology of testimony is reducible to the
epistemology of empirical evidence in general, the fact that telling is a speech act
suggests that a central role in the epistemology of testimony should be assigned to speech
act considerations. If we accede to the latter suggestion then it might seem that we should
not treat acts of telling as evidence at all but as calling for special treatment drawing upon
the character of the practices surrounding the speech act. Such a reaction would be
unjustified. If telling is a distinctive speech act then it might well be that an adequate
epistemology of testimony must incorporate elements that have no echo in the
epistemology of knowledge based on non-testimonial evidence. But that does not
establish that when those
176
elements are in play we should not think of acts of telling as constituting evidence in the
broad sense countenanced above.1
A further reason for hesitating over whether knowledge received in the straightforward
cases constitutes evidence for the thing told arises from the thought that it would be hard
on such a view to account for the recipient's entitlement to treat the act of telling as
evidence. The problem that seems to arise here is closely linked to the third of the
features of the straightforward cases that I noted above. This has to do with the
elusiveness of the factors that explain the ready acceptance by recipients of what they
have been told. There is a way of thinking of knowledge from indicatorsindicating
phenomena like readings on fuel gauges and tyre marks on roadson which this
elusiveness seems problematic. It can be that the occurrence of tracks of a certain sort on
a path indicates, and is in that way evidence, that deer have recently passed. People who
know about deer might be able to tell that deer have recently passed from the presence of
such tracks on a path. A standard way of thinking about how they can do this is to
suppose that they justifiably accept, and exploit, a generalization to the effect that when
there are tracks of the relevant sort on a path then deer will have recently passed by. In
particular cases they apply the generalization to the circumstances and conclude that deer
have recently passed. If we try to adapt this way of thinking to straightforward
testimonial cases then we would have it that if you were to accept that p on the basis of
being told that p by an informant A, you would have to apply a suitable covering
generalization to this act of telling.2 What might the generalization be? Given the
elusiveness of the relevant factors it is hard to say. Do we need a generalization about A
or about people like A? If the latter, then what similarities are relevant? Do we need a
generalization about utterances with the same sort of content? If so, what determines the
relevant sort? Analogous problems arise about the sorts of context and manner of
speaking that are relevant. And there is the further matter of how we know that all the
relevant factors have been covered. The reason why this matters is that on the model
under consideration we are supposed to base our acceptance of testimony on facts to the
effect that the speaker, context, and so forth have such-and-such features. To the extent
that it is unclear which features count for us, and accordingly which generalizations are
being exploited, it will be unclear what is the basis of our acceptance. Now, one might
take these problems to provide the motivation for further enquiry into the form of
relevant generalizations and the features they incorporate. I am sceptical that such a
project has much chance of success. This
177
is in part because I think that a different approach is more plausible and avoids the
problems. My aim in this chapter is to outline key features of this account. I shall focus
on two in particular. The first is that a central role is assigned to the speech act of telling.
I suggest, more specifically, that we must think of telling as a move in a practice, where a
practice is conceived as an essentially rule-governed activity or cluster of such activities.
Crucially, considerations about speech acts do not take us all of the way. This takes us to
the second featurean account of the kind of sensibility that enables us to recognize acts
of telling and to recognize some (trustworthy) acts of telling as indicative of the truth.3
2. SAYING, TELLING, AND THE PRACTICE OF INFORMING THROUGH
TELLING
Telling someone that p is a distinctive communicative act. My telling you that p is an act
of saying to you that p by which I give you to understand that I am thereby informing you
that p. I take informing you that p to entail speaking from knowledge that p, with the aim
that you should thereby come to know that p. Thus I do not inform you that p unless p,
though I may give you to understand that I am informing you that p when I know full
well that not-p.4
Not all cases of saying to someone that p are cases of telling that person that p. If by way
of advice I say to a colleague that he should consider pursuing some topic, I do not take
myself to be informing him of anything and do not expect him to regard what I say as
knowledge that I am conveying to him. My aim will be to encourage him to pursue the
topic. Good advice recommends a course of action and presents considerations in the
light of which the course of action can be seen to be a good idea. In advising my
colleague I don't wish him to consider pursuing the topic just on my say so but rather on
account of whatever it is that makes acting in the suggested way a good idea.
There are other cases in which sayings are plainly not acts of telling. I might sound off
about the qualities of well-known political figures. These may be unqualified and
accompanied by manifest strength of conviction. But I would view them as expressions
of opinion and perhaps anger too, not as aiming to convey knowledge. That is how others
are likely to take them.
I said telling is a move in a practice. The practice may be conceived as that of informing
through telling, but it should be understood that the practice embraces
178
both informing through telling, understanding acts of telling, and adopting a stance
towards what one is being told. In the sense intended here, a practice is an essentially
rule-governed activity or group of interrelated activities.5 Playing in a game of football,
for instance, is participating in a practice. The activity is subject to the rules of the game
and is indeed individuated by those rules.6 Informing through telling is also subject to
rules. I shall assume that the following are rules:
(A) when informing someone that p you should speak from knowledge that p;7
(B) when informing someone that p you should intend that this person should, by your
act of informing, come to know that p.
The (A)-rule makes sense of the fact that by telling you are supposed to inform. While an
act of telling might not inform, and indeed might be deliberately deceptive, a felicitous
act of tellingone in keeping with the rulesdoes inform. The (B)-rule accounts for a
way in which an act of telling can be infelicitous even when the informant speaks from
knowledge. Suppose that Bill, speaking from knowledge, tells Sally that her husband
John is not having an affair. But Bill's intention is to get Sally to suspect that John is
having an affair by trading on Sally's alarm at John's friendship with a female colleague
and her tendency to suspect that he (Bill) would lie to protect his friend.8 Arguably, Bill's
act of telling is infelicitous in that he has no intention to inform Sally. As we might say,
that is not what telling is supposed to be; hence the second rule.
How should we think of the relationship of participants in a practice to the rules
governing the practice? Consider a game of football again. Obviously, players are subject
to the rules in that the rules apply to them. The rules also set limits to what counts as
playing the game. Games can proceed despite some rules being broken, but there are
limits to how anarchic play can be if a game is to proceed. Whatever players actually do
they incur a commitment, just in virtue of being players, to following the rules of the
game. The commitments here are normative in that they relate, in a way to be explained,
to how a player ought to behave. Some might be attracted by the idea that the rules do not
generate any such commitments beyond those incurred by aiming to play. If we ask what
reason there is for players to follow the rules, the answer by this account would be,
because they intend to play the game and could not do so without
179
following the rules at least to some extent. On this way of thinking the only normativity
we need to acknowledge in connection with rule-governed activities is instrumental
following the rules by and large is what you have to do if you are to play. The rules have
no normative force; it's just that you won't count as playing unless by and large you
conform to them. If this is right there need be nothing wrong with a football player's
being in breach of a rule. That is because flouting a rule evidently need not be at odds
with being a player and so does not put one in breach of the commitment incurred by
intending to play the gamethe commitment to doing what is necessary to that end. All
we have is a clash between what the player has done and what some rule prescribes. I do
not think that this is satisfactory. There is something wrong about being in breach of a
rule and this is reflected in the fact that breaches of the rule are subject to legitimate
criticism. What is it that makes the criticism apt? Ethics need have nothing to do with it. I
suggest that we need the notion that it is in the nature of rules governing a practice that
those who participate in the practice incur a (normative) commitment to following the
rules. Behaviour that flouts a rule may (legitimately) be criticized because it is in breach
of this commitment. That you have incurred the commitment does not entail that you
ought to follow the rules. (So by speaking of a normative commitment I do not mean to
suggest that it imposes an obligation to do that to which you are committed.) There can
be games so appalling that no one ought to play them and therefore no one ought to
follow their rules. By my account it remains true that if you play such a game you incur a
commitment to following the rules. The commitment amounts to something like this: you
ought to avoid continuing as a player, and not follow the rules. There are two ways to
discharge this commitment: one is to carry it out, that is, follow the rules, the other is to
withdraw from the game, thereby removing the condition in virtue of which the
commitment was incurred. It could be that you ought to withdraw from the game. On this
view the mere existence of a practice gives no one, not even participants, an obligation to
follow its rules. The sense that practices do not generate obligations to follow their rules
may explain the resistance that some have to the very idea that there is an intrinsic
normative dimension to participation in practices. But we can acknowledge the point
about obligation while still acknowledging that practices have an intrinsic normative
dimension. What we need is a weaker normative notion than that of obligationthe
notion of a commitment.9
The notion of a practice is philosophically interesting for at least two reasons. One has to
do with the explanation of action. The fact that there is a practice that commits
participants to acting in a certain way figures in the explanation
180
of why participants act in that way. This happens in part because people simply become
habituated to complying with what the practice requires. The other reason is
epistemological. Observers and competent players of a game know how the game is
supposed to be played. This enables them to form reasonable expectations about the
course of play and to make sense of the play that unfolds. In a team game like soccer,
knowledge of what the game requires enables players to coordinate with others on their
team and to be prepared for moves on the part of the opposing team. Grasp of a
practiceknowing how to engage in itcan ground expectations have about how
participants are liable to act even in the absence of knowledge of the participants as
individuals. This is not to deny that in some games, for instance, tennis, a player's
individual quirks and preferences have an important bearing on what in detail he or she
will do. The point remains that even then we do not need to know the quirks or
preferences to make out the general shape of what a player will do.
The sorts of practices I have mentioned thus far are instituted by design and have more or
less well-defined rules by reference to which participants guide what they do. There can
be practices for which rules are never formulated but which develop because certain ways
of proceeding come to be seen as the done thing or the way to go about things. This is
manifested by the fact that there arise mutual expectations of conformity, and a
willingness to do the done thing and to view departures, whether by oneself or others, as
open to legitimate criticism. What is it for there to be rules of such a practice, given that
the rules are not instituted? Consider, for instance, the practice of giving and receiving
invitations. It's a rule of the practice that you don't issue invitations without planning, and
implementing plans for, the activity in question. There is a certain pattern of behaviour
that is in keeping with the rule: issuing invitations, planning, and implementing plans for,
the activity in question. There is behaviour that is not in keeping with the rule: issuing
invitations and not planning, or not implementing plans, for the activity in question. To
say that there is a rule along these lines is, roughly speaking, to say that behaviours of the
former kind are acknowledged by those giving or receiving invitations as right or correct
or appropriate, and behaviours of the latter kind are acknowledged to be wrong or
incorrect or inappropriate. Part of what these acknowledgements involve is an
understanding that one's behaviour is expected to conform to the first pattern and not to
conform to the second. These informal practices, as one might call them, have epistemic
utility as much as those that have been instituted by design. That there is a practice of
giving and receiving invitations enables those who issue invitations to have a reasonable
expectation that those invited will respond in a certain way, for instance, accept the
invitation and then turn up at the set time. It enables those invited to have a reasonable
expectation that the activity will indeed take place. All this can proceed smoothly with
little detailed knowledge of the characteristics of those with whom one is interacting
beyond the fact that
181
they may be expected to do the done thing with respect to the giving and receiving of
invitations.
A very great deal of what we expect of others, and much of our understanding of them,
turns on our having a grasp of practices in which we, and they, participate. In our familiar
communities, for the most part we are not like anthropologists striving to make sense of
what others are about. We have a sense of what makes sense when people are engaged in
activities with respect to which there is by custom a right way to go about things. We
have such a sense because we, like they, have been initiated into the appropriate ways to
go about things, and into thinking of them as the appropriate ways. That initiation brings
with it mutual expectations of conformity and preparedness to acknowledge the
legitimacy of criticism when there are breaches.
Linguistic practices ensure that there are shared abilities and sensibilities that make
communication and mutual understanding possible. The upshot of the shared abilities and
sensibilities is that we do not in general approach users of our language with an
interpretative problemwhat to make of the sounds they utter or the inscriptions they
write. We are already geared up to viewing them as fellow speakers of our language and
to recognizing what they are doing with the words they use: asking us this, telling us that,
and so on.10 A sense that there are right and wrong ways to communicate with our
language serves to reinforce our own continuing conformity to the demands of using our
linguistic practices. It is easy to overlook this because so much in our use of language,
and our understanding of uses of language, is unreflective. It seems plausible however
that our willingness to adjust our usage when we find that it is out of kilter with common
practice, and we are not in the business of being innovative, testifies to our having a sense
of correctness and incorrectness in linguistic matters.11 There is a standing temptation to
suppose that our conformity to prevailing practices can be explained simply in terms of
instrumental reasoning: if we do not conform we will not understand or be understood.
My point is that thanks to the existence of practices, and our initiation into them, we do
not routinely, and do not have to, get to the stage of reasoning in this way; we are
instilled from the start with a sense of there being correct and incorrect ways to speak and
write.
Against the background of these ideas I shall now pick up a claim made towards the end
of section 1. There I said that my account of the epistemology of testimony would make
use of the idea that our ability to gain knowledge in straightforward cases of testimony
depends on our having a certain sensibility. This is the theme that I shall now pursue.
182
3. RECOGNITION AND RELIANCE ON INDICATORS
Much of our knowledge is perceptual, being gained directly, without reasoning, through
the exercise of perceptual-recognitional abilities.12 We might have, for instance, the
ability to recognize that a sound is that of a fire alarm, or recognize by looking that the
flowers in a vase are daffodils, or recognize that a fabric is silk from the way it feels.
Possession of any such ability requires more than that the appropriate sensory system is
functioning adequately; it requires that we have appropriate concepts and have learnt to
apply them in response to what we perceive. We have to learn to recognize robins or
goldfinches from the way they look. We have to learn to recognize people we know from
the way they look or sound or perhaps from their gait. Thanks to perceptual-recognitional
abilities, perceptual knowledge can extend far beyond the superficial features of things
that go to make up their appearance. We can recognize Bill as Bill and not as just
someone or something having the look of Bill. Such abilities involve refined sensibilities
by which one is attuned to the significance of a host of physical cues that one would be
hard put to describe. This is rather obviously so in the case of face recognition. The
information we can capture by a description of a face is a tiny fraction of that to which
we respond when we recognize the person whose face it is.
It is thanks to our perceptual-recognitional abilities that we are able to take in rich facts,
and not merely facts concerning the superficial features of things. Such abilities enable us
to have perceptual knowledge that extends well beyond the features that make up the
superficial appearance of things to this or that sense modality. As conceived here the
exercise of such abilities is the acquisition of knowledge. The ability to recognize a
goldfinch from its visual appearancefrom the way it looksis an ability to tell of
goldfinches that they are goldfinches from the way they look. I exercise this ability only
if I tell, and thus come to know, of the thing looked at, that it is a goldfinch. For present
purposes it is especially important to appreciate that the knowledge acquired in virtue of
exercising this ability is not implicitly evidence-based but is genuinely recognitional.
Though I tell that the bird at which I am looking is a goldfinch from its appearance and
might pick out some salient markings, it is the entire Gestalt presented by the bird to
which I respond and which triggers recognition. Goldfinches have that distinctive flash of
red on the side of the beak, but it is (showing you the illustration in the bird book) that
distinctive flash of red in that feathery context. You need to see it (or some representation
of it) to know what I am talking about. As I look at a goldfinch I do not propositionally
represent its visible features in any very specific way, nor therefore do I work with a
generalization that connects
183
specific such features to being a goldfinch. No plausible model of perceptual knowledge
of the presence of goldfinches should require this of me.
Perceptual-recognitional abilities have not figured prominently in the epistemology of
testimony.13 That is not surprising. If we gain knowledge that p from testimony that p it is
on the basis of the testimony, which clearly contrasts with perceiving that p. Against the
background of the traditional problem of other minds, one might suppose that even
knowing that we are being told that p is inferentialthat we judge that we are being told
that p on the basis of evidence that can be specified independently of the meaning of the
words used, and of their being used to tell us something. On this way of thinking, it is
assumed that the evidence can comprise only what can be taken in perceptually, and that
what can be taken in perceptually is confined to the level of superficial features. It does
not include psychologically loaded facts to the effect that someone's words mean this or
that, or that he or she is telling us this or that.14 A problem for such a view is that there is
no reason to think that we routinely treat psychology-free facts as evidence for a
judgement as to what the speaker is telling us. And if that is so, then such facts can hardly
figure routinely in the explanation of how we can know things on their basis. But there is
a contrasting picture on which perceptual-recognitional abilities have a role even in
relation to knowledge of other minds'.15 For instance, of people we know we can
sometimes tell that they are pleased about something from their smile and sparkling eyes.
We should resist the temptation to treat these cases on the model of inference from
evidence. The cues are too subtle for that. They trigger recognition of a how the person
feels rather than furnish evidence for what the person feels. It is more a matter of
deploying a sensibility whereby we are responsive to the cues that enable us to recognize
what the person is feeling. Focusing on recognitional abilities, here as elsewhere, opens
up the prospect of explaining how a host of factors can be relevant to acquiring
knowledge that something is so even though the knowledge does not result from
reasoning from evidence pertaining to those factors. This is of crucial importance for the
epistemology of testimony. If I were to tell you that you left your umbrella in my room,
then unless the circumstances were rather unusual, you would thereby come to know that
I am so telling you. Your coming to know would be a response to features of my
utterance, and of the context, that you would be hard put to articulate. The role of these
features, though, is not
184
that of furnishing you with evidence. Their presence prompts recognition: you would
simply hear me to be telling you that the umbrella is in my room. You would not need to
base your judgement on evidence any more than you would when recognizing a friend
from her appearance or telling that she is pleased from her appearance.
Our concern, of course, is not simply with how we tell when we are being told this or
that, but with how, in the straightforward cases, we tell that something is so from being
told it. On the picture I am working with someone's telling you that p in a case like this
can indicate, and in that way be evidence, that p. But it being such evidence is obviously
only part of the story. The question is what entitles us to treat it as such.
What might be called the standard model of knowledge from indicators (indicating
phenomena) envisages that experience furnishes us with facts about particulars, which
provide the basis for generalizations, which can then be applied to new cases. On this
model, to know that a's being F indicates that it is G one needs empirical support for a
covering generalization that connects a's being F with its being G. This might be that
everything F is G. Obviously, there can be support for such generalizations, and one can
be justified in thinking them true or at least in placing some fair degree of confidence in
their being true. I have already pointed to difficulties in applying such a model to
testimony but it is open to doubt that it applies to much of our knowledge from non-
testimonial indicators. Who among us has tested whether our car's fuel gauge is accurate
or whether only cows moo in just the way we think of cows as mooing? Yet we
sometimes tell from the reading on the fuel gauge roughly how much fuel is in the tank
and we sometimes tell that cows are nearby from the sound of their mooing. Our
experience is undoubtedly relevant to our abilities to do such things. I want to suggest
that we should think of the role of experience as that of inculcating and shaping the
abilities. By experience here I include our perceiving that this or that is so but also the
experience by which we are bombarded with observations, corrections, explanations, and
so on by those who surround us. Through such experience we get the hang of telling that
it has been raining from the wetness of the streets and pavements, or telling that someone
wishes to enter from the knocking sound at the door, or telling that it has been very cold
from the frost on the grass, and so on. When I say that we get the hang of these things I
mean simply that we learn to do them. The upshot of the learning process is a kind
recognitional ability. This time though it is an ability to recognize a situation as having a
certain significance. We should think of the role of experience accordingly. Its role is in
some respects akin to the role of experience in shaping an ability to saw wood straight, or
cultivate orchids, or cook fish perfectly. In these latter cases we take steps towards a
certain end, and gain feedback from our faltering attempts, perhaps assisted by guidance
from those who know about these things. The upshot of the learning process is mastery of
a technique. The role of experience is that of honing that technique
185
by trial and error, so that in time it becomes an ability to do something well. The test for
whether we have achieved this is whether we saw wood well, cultivate orchids well, cook
fish well, as the case may be. Likewise, the test for whether we have mastered the ability
to tell that deer have recently passed by along a path from the presence of tracks on that
path, is, roughly speaking, whether we pull off this feat on all or nearly all of the
occasions on which we aim to do so. Often the abilities are inculcated by others rather
than deriving from our own independent enquiry. Sometimes, though, they are acquired
through such enquiry. Without guidance from others, a person shipwrecked on an island
might learn that the presence of certain droppings indicates that rabbits are around. This
will involve observing rabbits produce such droppings and learning to discriminate the
rabbit droppings from others that might be around. Initial steps towards this may be
faltering. Perhaps there are droppings very like rabbit droppings, produced by another
small mammal. But in time the learner catches on to recognizing just the right sort. The
upshot again is a certain technique, in this case judging that rabbits are around on the
basis of the droppings. Getting the technique right is acquiring a recognitional ability
the ability to recognize droppings as having a certain significance: that rabbits are around.
The test for whether the ability has been acquired is whether over a wide range of cases
in which an attempt is made the learner judges correctly with a very high degree of
reliability and judges wrongly only when there is no interferencedistraction,
inadequate attention, or the like. The focus of the learning process is on identifying the
right sort of dropping. The same applies to knocks at the door. Not any sound at the door
is the right kind of sound to count as a knock. One has to learn to discriminate the knocks
from the bumps and scrapings. Learning to connect the sound with the knocks is just
learning to recognize the right kind of sounds as knocks.16
It is, of course, true that generality is built into the abilities under consideration. The
abilities involve being prone to respond to phenomena of a certain type in a certain way.
It would be entirely natural for the deer-tracker to say that you can tell from the presence
of tracks like these that deer have recently passed or to say that the presence of tracks like
these is a sign (tells you) that deer have recently passed. In the light of this it might be
thought that what I called the standard model of knowledge from indicators is fine at least
so far as it goes. But, first, as already remarked, it is doubtful that in all cases in which it
would be correct to ascribe the ability it would be correct to credit the subject with
evidence adequate to establishing the truth of an appropriate generalization. Second, the
generalizations that come to the mind of subjects and theorists alike are somewhat
indeterminate because of the elusiveness of the relevant phenomena. Even in a simple
case like that of telling that it has rained from the wetness of the streets and pavements
we are hard put to characterize just what sort of wetness counts.
186
We know it when we see it, yet if we ask precisely what generalization we need to have
support for in order to treat the wetness on some occasion as an indicator of recent rain,
no very clear answer can be forthcoming. That, I think, is a sign that a sensibility is in
play rather than a command, exercised at the level of judgement, of which features
wetness must have to make it wetness of the rain-indicating sort. This is not to say that
covering generalizations can play no role in our thinking. On the contrary, they form part
of the understanding that informs our recognitional abilities and that we exploit when
explaining and justifying the judgements we form. The crucial point though is that we
account for the acquisition of knowledge in these cases in terms of the exercise of an
ability to recognize a phenomenon as having a certain significance. It is the ability that is
in the driving seat and its possession does not turn on independent support for any
generalization that informs it.
Considerations analogous to those just set out apply to the epistemology of testimony.
They bear on our ability to recognize speech acts as acts of telling. This ability is
inculcated through our initiation into the practice of informing. But we should also take
seriously the idea that our knowledge that p from someone's telling us that p is
recognitional as well. It obviously involves recognition because we have to recognize the
relevant utterance as an act of telling us that p. On the account I am proposing we should
also think of our ability to tell that p from being told that p as being recognitional. The
upshot of the exercise of such an ability is recognition that our interlocutor is telling us
the truth. I exercise such an ability in telling from what my son says that my book is at
home on my desk. Having such an ability I shall be prone to respond to utterances like
this one in respect of content, manner of speaking, and so on, in circumstances like this,
in the way I do on this occasion. While, stepping back, I can gesture towards features of
the utterance that are truth-indicative, I need not register these at the level of judgement
and it is accordingly implausible that my acceptance of a covering generalization
capturing their significance figures as a premise in reasoning to the conclusion that the
thing told is true.
What drives the account of knowing the truth in terms of recognizing the truth-indicative
significance of the telling is not simply the phenomenological immediacy with which the
truth is taken in. It is that while there are features of the act of telling that are undoubtedly
relevant to our reception of the testimony, we do not register these at the level of
judgement. The lesson to draw, I suggest, is that these responses have a greater kinship
with perceptual-recognitional judgements than might at first seem. That is why we have
to bring into play the notion of a sensibility not only to account for the identification of
acts of telling but also to account for our taking in the truth-indicative significance of
what we are told.17
187
4. SENSIBILITY AND TRUSTWORTHINESS
What I have to say about the sensibility by which we recognize an act of telling to be
truth-indicative merely gives a clue to the direction in which I think we should go in these
matters. The issue merits further exploration. However, I doubt that philosophical
reflection will yield anything like a theory as opposed to making it progressively more
plausible that testimonial knowledge in the straightforward cases is best conceived in
terms of the exercise of a sensibility and not in accordance with the standard way of
thinking about knowledge from indicators.
We should note first that although the practice of informing by telling goes a considerable
way towards explaining how it is that we so often acquire true beliefs from testimony it
does not take us all of the way. The practice is in place only because often enough people
follow its rules. Beyond mere participation in the practice there are additional incentives
to avoid breaches of its rules: deception and incompetence are liable to be exposed, to the
detriment of the informant. These factors explain why in a suitable setting even the
gullible will often acquire true beliefs by accepting what they are told and the more
discriminating can do so with a fairly high degree of reliability simply by accepting what
they are told when they do not detect any reason to do otherwise.18 They impose limits on
believing falsely from testimony but they do not illuminate what makes for knowledge or
well-grounded belief in particular cases. For instance, they do not explain why someone's
telling us something can settle the matter so that we acquire knowledge from what we are
told. While it is clearly relevant to the explanation of our ability to gain knowledge in the
straightforward cases that there is a practice of informing by telling, which conditions our
responses to testimony, an account of how we gain knowledge must say something about
why we readily trust particular individuals and why we can be right to do so. A natural
thought at this point is that to acquire knowledge from a person in a straightforward case
of telling, (a) the person has to be trustworthy, and (b) we
188
must have knowledge of the person that enables us to recognize him or her as trustworthy
on the matter in hand on the occasion in question. Trustworthiness has two components,
sincerity and competence.19
Competence with respect to whether p is knowing whether p, which entails knowing that
p if p, and knowing that not-p if not-p. A crucial dimension of competence is being in
command of the requisite ways of telling. My son meets this condition in my example
because he knows the title of the book about which I am enquiring and can determine by
looking whether a book of that title is in my study. Obviously, merely being in command
of the requisite ways of telling is not enough. The ways of telling must have been
exercised. My son meets this condition because he has seen that the book is on my study
desk.
Sincerity, as I shall understand it, has three strands: you are sincere in telling me that p if
and only if (i) you believe that p, (ii) you believe that you speak from knowledge, and
(iii) you intend that I should come to know that p through your telling me. Condition (i)
needs no explanation. The rationale of condition (ii) is provided by the nature of telling as
an act by which you give it to be understood that you know. If you believe what you say
but think that your standing on the matter is less than knowledge then you are misleading
those you tell because your act of telling gives it to be understood that you know. The
rationale for condition (iii) is similar. As I observed in section 2, when commenting on
the (B)-rule for telling, there are cases when informants speak from knowledge but whose
telling is infelicitous because they do not intend that the recipient should be informed by
their telling. All that I am adding here is that this is a form of insincerity.
The practice of informing by telling imposes limits on the extent to which we are likely to
believe falsely by accepting what we are told. Within the context provided by the
practice, trustworthiness plays a role in relation to knowledge from being told that is
analogous to the role played by favourable environments in relation to perceptual
knowledge and knowledge from indicators. To tell of a structure that it is a barn from its
visual appearance, the environment in which the barn is situated must be favourable to
the exercise of the relevant recognitional ability: in that environment barns must have a
distinctive appearance or set of such appearances. An appearance is distinctive of barns
if and only if not easily could something have this appearance and not be a barn. In a
fake-barn scenario (as in Goldman 1976) barns do not have a distinctive appearance
because too many of the structures that look like barns are not. No one could have the
ability to tell, and thus come to know, of things in such an environment that they are
barns from their visual appearance to the points of view that would normally suffice for
this purpose. The conclusion to draw from this is that the ability in question is tied to
constitutively dependent for its exercise
189
onfavourable environments.20 There are analogues of fake-barn scenarios for cases of
telling from the occurrence of an indicator phenomenon. Think of a shepherd in an
environment is which a certain bleating sound is distinctive of sheep: not easily could
there be that sound in these parts and it not be produced by sheep.21 With respect to such
an environment it is possible to learn, as the shepherd has, to tell that there are sheep
nearby from the sound of bleating. But suppose the shepherd to be transported to an
environment superficially looking like his familiar environment but in which there are
sheep that produce the familiar bleating sound and goats that produce an
indistinguishable sound. In this environment the bleating sound is not distinctive of
sheep. Because all too easily could something produce that sound and not be a sheep it
would not be possible in that environment to tell that sheep are nearby just from the
sound of bleating. Now, a trustworthy person with respect to a certain subject matter is
one who is such that not easily could that person tell you something concerning that
subject matter and speak falsely. Just as in suitable environments a suitably equipped
person may legitimately take at face value the appearance of barns, or a bleating sound,
so those who are suitably equipped may legitimately take at face value the acts of telling
of a person who is trustworthy with respect to a certain subject matter.
If Bill is my friend and an expert gardener, I can know him well enough to be able to take
what he tells me about gardening at face value. We shall not be able to do justice to the
role of experience gained through acquaintance with a person if we stick with the model
of accumulating evidence that we sift and weigh, and exploit in reasoning. Apart from
anything else we do not keep a record of all of the evidence we glean, but nor can we pin
down all the factors that are germane to our responses to what the person tells us. Yet it is
not a mystery that our experience of a person can equip us with an ability to recognize the
truth-indicative significance of an act of telling. We are not baffled by the idea that I
come to know that the book about which I am enquiring is on my study desk at home
from my son's telling me that it is. I come to know because I know him well enough to
have acquired an ability to tell from certain of his acts of telling that what he is telling me
in those acts of telling is true. In the scenario envisaged his competence on the matter of
the book's location is not an issue. But nor is his sincerity. My past experience of him
puts me in a position to respond to his report in an atmosphere of trust. But the role of
past experience is that of attuning me to the significance of his acts of telling with respect
to the truth of what he tells. This kind of role for experience is not a peculiarity of
testimonial cases. Experience also subtly shapes the abilities exercised in perceptual
knowledge and in non-testimonial indicator cases.
190
5. OBJECTIONS BRIEFLY CONSIDERED
The suggested account is likely to provoke an objection on the grounds that often there
can be knowledge from testimony when the recipient does not know the informant well
enough to have the kind of recognitional ability illustrated in the case of my son's
testimony. Yet cases in which this is so might be just like what I have been calling
straightforward cases.
Consider, for instance, informants like ticket clerks, shop assistants, and representatives
of organizations who inform us about their products. We usually do not know these
people personally though we sometimes acquire knowledge from them in the way we do
in the straightforward cases. It might be thought that there is nothing about them from
which we can tell that they are trustworthy. Such a view overlooks the function of roles
and practices. In addition to the practice of informing there are practices associated with
information-disseminating roles. People who occupy such roles have little incentive to
mislead and the risks to their doing so are significant. They will have acquired training so
that they will generally be competent on the sort of matters on which we are likely to
trust them. Providing that we are sufficiently discriminating about, for instance, the roles
they occupy, and about the contents of what they tell us, we can be in a position to know
some of the things they tell us. Here too experience hones our discriminative powers.
What about the stranger in the street whom one asks for directions to the castle?22 Can we
not obtain knowledge from such a person while not knowing him or her personally and
knowing nothing of any information-disseminating role the person occupies? Perhaps. It
depends on how the scenario is spelled out and it is wise not to prejudge cases that are
under-described. But it would be no objection to my account if we do not acquire
knowledge in such cases. What we gain from testimony will often be less than knowledge
but useful nevertheless. Provided one exercises a modicum of discrimination it is entirely
reasonable to act on the information we receive from a stranger when little is at stake or
when one has no alternative. Reasonably acting on information supplied does not even
require belief, far less knowledge. All it requires is that there should be a reasonable
chance that what one is being told is true. That will be guaranteed by the fact that there is
a practice of informing by telling, along with the fact that there is nothing suspicious
about one's informant. This does not force us into the standard defaultist position, since it
concerns the reasonableness of action rather than justified belief or knowledge.
A rather different line of objection focuses on early learning. When we are young we take
on board a great deal of information from parents, teachers,
191
and others. We are in no position to have acquired the kind of recognitional abilities that
are central to my account. If early learning is to be conceived as the acquisition of
knowledge through being told, as in the straightforward cases, then the knowledge will
not meet the conditions I have laid down. But there is no reason to view early learning in
this way. We acquire a picture of the world through early learning, but nothing compels
us to treat the picture in its early stages as embodying knowledge-through-being-told as I
have conceived it in relation to straightforward cases. Knowledge of the latter kind is
knowledge that we gain on someone's say so. Its status as knowledge, all else equal,
depends on the subject's continuing to have a reason to believe the thing tolda reason
that is constituted by the fact that he or she has been told it. When we were young acts of
telling undoubtedly contributed to inculcating facts in us but it does not follow that what
we gained in this way is to be understood on the model of straightforward testimonial
interchanges. Much of what we imbibe when young never becomes knowledge. Some of
it, for instance, basic geographical and historical facts, becomes knowledge through
repeated encounters with sources of the facts in question. But we often lose touch with
the relevant sources in the sense that we could not say from which sources we acquired
this or that item of knowledge. In these cases our knowing the fact in question is not like
knowing that an ex-colleague was at some conference because a present colleague reports
having met him there. In the latter case one knows not just because of, but in view of,
having been told, and one has a reason to believe the thing told, which is supplied by the
fact that one has been told it. However, it could be that I know, say, that Hobart is the
state capital of Tasmania, without being able to pin down any particular source or sources
from which I gleaned this information. I have a good idea of relevant kinds of source
teachers, atlases, encyclopedias, newspaper reports, and so forth. I also know how to
confirm this item of information if called on to do so. Yet while I have been caused to
believe that Hobart is the state capital of Tasmania by encounters with suitable sources,
this is not a clear case of knowledge based on evidence, by which I mean knowledge the
current standing of which as knowledge is explained by my currently being in possession
of evidence that gives me a reason to believe that Hobart is the state capital of Tasmania.
Rather, this knowledge consists in an ability to recall a publicly available, known fact,
which has been gained from repeated encounters with reliable sources of information.23
The role of past experience has been to expose me to reliable sources of information and
to inculcate the ability to recall the facts that those sources made available. It
192
is not that of having supplied me with evidence in view of which I now take the fact in
question to be a fact.24 The upshot, I suggest, is that early learning should not be a test
case for the adequacy of an account of straightforward cases of acquiring knowledge
from testimony. I have no more than hinted at a line of approach to early learning that is
compatible with the account I have proposed of the straightforward cases.25
193
10 Can A Priori Entitlement be Preserved by Testimony?
Ram Neta
Before we address the question that forms the title of this chaptera question that Tyler
Burge articulated and famously and controversially answered in the affirmativelet us
begin by clarifying it.1 Doing this will take considerable work, since we have to clarify
what is meant by entitlement, what is meant by speaking of an entitlement's being a
priori, what is meant by speaking of this a priori entitlement being preserved, and
finally, what is meant by speaking of its being so preserved by testimony. In the course
of clarifying these terms, we will locate the resources necessary for Burge to defend his
view from a prominent recent criticism, a criticism that focuses on the fact that Burge
regards the entitlements preserved by testimony as typically a priori. But we will also
find that Burge's argument for his view can seem plausible to us only to the extent that
we confuse entitlement with justification, and this is a confusion against which Burge
himself warns.
I'll begin by saying what Burge means by entitlement, then proceed to clarify what is
meant by speaking of an entitlement's being a priori. Next, I'll discuss the notion of this
a priori entitlement being preserved, and finally, I'll say what it is for it to be preserved
by testimony. Once all that is on the table, we'll then turn to the task of defending
Burge's thesis from the criticism of it that we find in Malmgren (2006). This defence will
help us to understand Burge's view more clearly, and also help us to see that what's
implausible about Burge's view has nothing in particular to do with his widely contested
claims about the a prioricity of our testimonially preserved warrants.2 (Indeed, Burge may
very well be right in claiming that testimonially preserved warrants are sometimes a
priori.) What is implausible about Burge's view has to do rather with his generally
uncontested claim that testimonially preserved warrants are sometimes entitlements.
194
1. ENTITLEMENT
So, first, what property does Burge mean to denote by the term entitlement? We can
answer this question by sketching the ambitious theoretical picture within which the
notion of entitlement is supposed to fit.
For Burge, animals, and their functional subsystems, have ends, goals, commitments, or
functions. The satisfaction of one of these ends, the attainment of one of these goals, the
fulfilment of one of these commitments, or the successful performance of one of these
functions is a good for the creature, or the functional subsystem, of which it is an end,
goal, commitment, or function. This is as true of the creature's psychological subsystems
as it is of the creature's respiratory, circulatory, or reproductive subsystems: each such
system has a function, and the successful performance of that function is a good for the
functional subsystem. So, for example, a creature's circulatory system functions to
circulate nutrients to all of the creature's cells, and the successful performance of that
function is a good for the circulatory system. (It is typically a good for the creature as
well, but it need not befor instance, the creature's overall health or survival may, in
some cases, depend on the starvation of a particular part of the creature's body, and in
that case what is a good for the circulatory system is not a good for the creature.) Another
example: a creature's representational system functions to provide correct representations.
And more specifically, a creature's belief system functions to provide true beliefs. While
it may sometimes be good for a creature to have false beliefs, it is a good for the
creature's belief system to have true beliefs.3
Now, given a creature's habitat and its perspectival and other representational limitations,
there will be some ways of forming beliefs that are, necessarily and a priori, likely
(though not certain) to lead to true beliefs. Beliefs that are so formed under normal
circumstances in the creature's habitat will themselves be, necessarily and a priori, likely
(though not certain) to be true. On Burge's view, what it is for a creature to be warranted
in forming beliefs in a particular way, or for a particular belief to be warranted, is just for
that way of forming beliefs, or for that particular belief, to fall into the respective
categories just describedthe categories that necessarily and a priori involve likelihood
of truth. For a way of forming beliefs, or a particular belief, to enjoy the epistemic good
warrant, is for it to be such that, in forming beliefs in that way, or in forming that
particular belief, the creature is doing just what creatures so constituted should do, when
under normal circumstances in their habitat, in order to attain true belief. The epistemic
good of warrant is in this way related to the belief system's good of true belief.
195
This is how Burge understands warrant. But there are two kinds of warrant: entitlement
and justification. Burge explains the difference between these two kinds of warrant in the
following passage:
The distinction between justification and entitlement is this: Although both have positive
force in rationally supporting a propositional attitude or cognitive practice, and in
constituting an epistemic right to it, entitlements are epistemic rights or warrants that
need not be understood by or even accessible to the subject. We are entitled to rely, other
things equal, on perception, memory, deductive and inductive reasoning, and onI will
claimthe word of others. The unsophisticated are entitled to rely on their perceptual
beliefs. Philosophers may articulate these entitlements. But being entitled does not
require being able to justify reliance on these resources, or even to conceive such a
justification. Justifications . . . involve reasons that people have and have access to. These
may include self-sufficient premises or more discursive justifications. But they must be
available in the cognitive repertoire of the subject. (Burge 1993: 4589)
This passage strongly suggests that Burge intends the distinction between entitlement and
justification to be understood as follows:
If C is a creature and E is a warranted epistemic act or state of C's, then C is justified in E
if C can, upon reflection, offer an articulate reason for E. If C cannot do this, then C's
warrant for E is an entitlement.
This interpretation of Burge's distinction is corroborated by other passages, such as this:
Entitlement is epistemically externalist inasmuch as it is warrant that need not be fully
conceptually accessible, even on reflection, to the warranted individual. The individual
need not have the concepts necessary to think the propositional content that formulates
the warrant. . . . The other primary sub-species of epistemic warrant is justification.
Justification is warrant by reason that is conceptually accessible on reflection to the
warranted individual. (Burge 2003: 504)
Unfortunately for his reader, at other points, Burge's writing suggestsor at least may
seem to suggesta different distinction between entitlement and justification. For
instance:
An individual's epistemic warrant may consist in a justification that the individual has for
a belief or other epistemic act or state. But it may also be an entitlement that consists in a
status of operating in an appropriate way in accord with norms of reason, even when
these norms cannot be articulated by the individual who has that status. We have an
entitlement to certain perceptual beliefs or to certain logical inferences even though we
may lack reasons or justifications for them. The entitlement could in principle
presumablythough often only with extreme philosophical difficultybe articulated by
someone. But this articulation need not be part of the repertoire of the individual that has
the entitlement. (Burge 1996: 934)
In this passage, when contrasting entitlements with justifications, Burge says that
entitlements consist in a status of operating in an appropriate way in accord with
196
norms of reason, even when these norms cannot be articulated by the individual who has
that status'. This passage may seem to some readers to suggest that Burge's distinction
between entitlements and justification should be understood as follows:
If C is a creature and E is a warranted epistemic act or state of C's, then C is justified in E
if C can articulate the norms according to which E is warranted. If C cannot do this, then
C's warrant for E is an entitlement.
One problem with this second interpretation of Burge's distinction between entitlement
and justification is that, if this is how Burge intends to draw the distinction, then it makes
it very hard to understand why Burge says what he does in the passages just quoted from
Burge (1993) and Burge (2003). A second and perhaps more serious problem is that, if
this is how to understand Burge's distinction between entitlement and justification, then
justifications are possessed only by creatures that are capable of articulating the epistemic
norms to which they are answerable. But, given his other commitments, Burge cannot
reasonably restrict so narrowly the range of creatures that can enjoy justifications. For
instance, Burge tells us that only creatures that have propositional attitudes can enjoy
entitlements, but only creatures that are capable of justifying their propositional attitudes
are capable of having such attitudes.4 Thus, if Burge were to claim that justifications
could be enjoyed only by creatures that are capable of articulating the norms according to
which their attitudes are warranted, he would be committed to claiming that entitlements
could be enjoyed only by such creatures. Now, Burge clearly and repeatedly states that
young children and some non-human animals can enjoy entitlements.5 Therefore, if he
were to claim that justifications could be enjoyed only by creatures that are capable of
articulating the norms according to which their attitudes are warranted, he would be
committed to the obviously false claim that young children and some non-human animals
are capable of articulating the norms according to which their attitudes are warranted. We
should therefore avoid attributing to Burge the view that justifications could be enjoyed
only by creatures that are capable of articulating the norms according to which their
attitudes are warranted.
Why, then, does Burge (1996) contrast entitlements with justifications by saying that
entitlements consist in a status of operating in an appropriate way in accord with norms
of reason, even when these norms cannot be articulated by
197
the individual who has that status'? I think this sentence should be understood not as
suggesting that justification for believing that p requires the ability to articulate the norms
of reason that make it appropriate for one to believe that p, but rather as suggesting that
entitlement to believe that p requires the lack of such an ability. When a believer is able
to articulate the norms by virtue of which she is warranted, then her possession of that
ability is sufficient, but not necessary, to her warrant's being a justification: in such a
case, the believer can offer an articulate reason for her warranted act or state, and she can
do this by citing the norm by virtue of which it is warranted. Therefore, it is necessary,
but not sufficient, for a warrant's being an entitlement that the believer cannot articulate
the norms by virtue of which she enjoys that warrant. This means that it is sufficient, but
not necessary, for a warrant's being a justification that the believer can articulate the
norms by virtue of which she enjoys the warrant. On Burge's view, as I understand it, a
warrant is a justification whenever the believer can articulate the warrant. In particular, if
a believer is warranted in believing that p on the basis of an inference to her conclusion
that p, then, for Burge, this is sufficient for the believer's warrant for p to be a
justification.
We've now said all that we're going to say about what sort of property Burge means to
denote by means of the term entitlement. What makes an entitlement a priori?
2. A PRIORICITY
Whenever a creature C is warranted in an epistemic act or state E, there is something that
makes C warranted in E. In other words, there is something that constitutes C's warrant
for E. Whatever this thing is that constitutes C's warrant for E, either that thing includes
C's specific perceptual and sensory experiences, or it does not. If it does, then C's warrant
for E is a posteriori (or, in other words, empirical). Otherwise, C's warrant for E is a
priori. I should note that this conception of the a priori is not entirely standard today (not
that there is any conception of the a priori that is entirely standard today!). It will be
important to keep Burge's conception of a prioricity in mind throughout this paper,
especially since failure to keep it in mind has occasioned some misunderstanding among
his critics.
Where I've spoken of what constitutes someone's warrant, Burge speaks of what
constitutes the justificational force of a warrant (i.e. a justification or an entitlement)
in doing so, of course, Burge is using the term justificational force more broadly than he
uses the term justification (which he intends to contrast with entitlement). Here's how
Burge explains a prioricity: A justification or entitlement is a priori if its justificational
force is in no way constituted or enhanced by reference to or reliance on the specifics of
some range of sense
198
experiences or perceptual beliefs' (Burge 1993: 458). And he elaborates on this
formulation:
An individual need not make reference to sense experiences for his justification or
entitlement to be empirical. My term reliance on, in the explication of apriority, is
meant to acknowledge that most perceptual beliefs about physical objects or properties do
not refer to sense experiences or their perceptual content. Such beliefs make reference
only to physical objects or properties. But the individual is empirically entitled to these
perceptual beliefs. The justificational force of the entitlement backing such beliefs partly
consists in the individual's having certain sense experiences, or at any rate in the
individual's perceptual beliefs being perceptual. (Burge 1993: 460)
Notice that Burge's distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori is a distinction
that applies to warrants in general, and it cuts across the distinction between entitlements
and justification. So long as what makes C entitled to E does not include any of C's
specific perceptual or sensory experiences, C's entitlement to E is a priorialthough C
might, of course, fail to know this, since she might not know, and not even have the
ability to conceive of, what entitles her to E. (Recall that entitlements need not be
understandable by those who enjoy them.) Therefore, C might have an a priori
entitlement to E, even though C has no idea that she is so entitled, and is completely
unable to offer any a priori justification for E. So, even if we are entirely unaware of the a
priori entitlements that we enjoy by virtue of testimony, this fact does nothing to tell
against our enjoyment of such a priori entitlements. Again, this point will become
important later on, when we consider how Burge can defend his view against a recent
criticism.
3. PRESERVING ENTITLEMENT
We've said what entitlements are, and what it is for an entitlement to be a priori. Now,
what is it for an entitlement, or any other kind of warrant, to be preserved? Burge does
not explicitly answer this question, but his remarks in Burge (1993)6 suggest a partial
answer. In criticizing Chisholm's conception of the role of memory in providing us with
justification for believing the conclusions of long deductive arguments, Burge writes:
If memory supplied, as part of the demonstration, contingent propositions about what we
happen to remember, the demonstration could not be purely logical or mathematical. But
the normal role of memory in demonstrative reasoning is, I think, different. Memory does
not supply for the demonstration propositions about memory, the reasoner, or past events.
It supplies the propositions that serve as links in the demonstration itself. Or
199
rather, it preserves them, together with their judgmental force, and makes them available
for us at later times. Normally, the content of the knowledge of a longer demonstration is
no more about memory, the reasoner, or contingent events than that of a shorter
demonstration. One does not justify the demonstration by appeals to memory. One
justifies it by appeals to the steps and the inferential transitions of the demonstration.
(Burge 1993: 462)
In this passage, Burge is contrasting two different ways in which memory can be
involved in furnishing us with inferential justification: it can be involved by giving us
justification for believing various contingent propositions about our memory, or it can be
involved simply by preserving the propositions that serve as links in the demonstration
itself along with their judgmental force, and it makes them available for use at later
times'. But what is it to preserve a proposition, or its judgemental force? Presumably,
Burge means that our memory of the proposition can be preserved, along with our
memory of the proposition's being (as we judge) true: just as I can now judge that 68 + 57
= 125, I can later on remember that 68 + 57 = 125. It's not simply that I will remember
the proposition that 68 + 57 = 125rather, I will remember that 68 + 57 = 125. What I
rememberthat 68 + 57 = 125has the same propositional content and the same
judgemental force as my original judgement (i.e. the judgement that 68 + 57 = 125).
Besides preserving propositional content and judgemental force, memory also, according
to Burge, makes propositions available for use at later times'. What does Burge mean
when he speaks of such availability? The context of Burge's discussion suggests an
answer: memory makes a proposition available for use at later times if it preserves one's
warrant for the proposition, so that one continues to be in a position to draw warranted
conclusions from the proposition. Right now, as I judge that 68 + 57 = 125, I am justified
in drawing the conclusion that 12568 = 57. But later on, as I remember that 68 + 57 =
125, I will still be justified in drawing the conclusion that 12568 = 57: whatever warrant
attached to my earlier judgement also attaches to the later judgement. The warrant is
preserved, along with content and force, by memory.
This is one example Burge gives of warrant preservation. But, as we'll see in our
discussion of Burge's views on the epistemology of testimony, it is not the only kind of
warrant preservation that Burge countenances. Warrants (whether entitlements or
justifications) can be preserved in at least two different ways: a warrant for a particular
epistemic act or state can be preserved in memory from one moment to a later moment,
and a person's warrant for a particular epistemic act or state can be preserved in testimony
from one person to another. Inspection of Burge's various cases of warrant preservation
reveals that warrant preservation involves three elements:
First, there are two distinct epistemic acts or states.
200
Second, one of these two epistemic acts or states occurs because the other one does.
Third, the former epistemic act or state is warranted because the latter is.
In sum, whenever warrant is preserved, one epistemic act or state occurs and is warranted
because another epistemic act or state occurs and is warranted. I should make clear, by
the way, that Burge does not tell us enough about warrant preservation to make clear
whether the relation denoted by because in the third of the three conditions above must
be a causal relation: while warrant preservation involves a causal process, it's not clear
that the relation between the warrants themselves is a causal relation.
I take the three conditions above to be necessary conditions of the phenomenon that
Burge calls warrant preservation, but I do not know if they are jointly sufficient
conditions. Burge does not say enough to allow us confidently to specify fully, and in a
non-circular way, what is involved in warrant preservation. But for present purposes, this
doesn't matter: we can make the points we need to make about Burge's view without
attempting to enumerate conditions that are both necessary and sufficient for warrant
preservation.
Just as entitlement is one form of warrant, so entitlement preservation is one form of
warrant preservation. Entitlement preservation involves three elements:
First, there are two distinct epistemic acts or states.
Second, one of these two epistemic acts or states occurs because the other one does.
Third, the epistemic agent who is the locus of the former epistemic act or state is entitled
to that act or state because the epistemic agent who is the locus of the latter epistemic act
or state is warranted in that act or state. (Notice that it is not specified whether the former
epistemic agent is identical to, or distinct from, the latter.)
And again, while these three elements are necessary for entitlement preservation, they
may not be sufficient for it.
Notice that, in specifying the third condition of entitlement preservation, I describe the
epistemic act or state that is at the receiving end of the preservative process as being one
to which its agent enjoys entitlement, whereas I describe the epistemic act or state that is
at the initiating end of the preservative process as being one to which its agent enjoys
warrant. The kind of testimonial process that we will be interested in discussing here is a
process that begins with an epistemic act or state that is warranted somehow or other
(perhaps the warrant takes the form of justification, perhaps it takes the form of
entitlement), and ends with an epistemic act or state that is warranted in a way that its
epistemic agent need not be aware of: in short, the sort of process that we will be
interested in discussing here is a process that ends with an epistemic act or state to which
its agent enjoys entitlement, and not (or not only) justification. Once again, this point will
become important later on, when we consider how Burge can defend his view against a
recent criticism.
201
4. PRESERVING ENTITLEMENT BY TESTIMONY
I have said that entitlement preservation involves a causal process that begins with an
epistemic act or state that is (somehow or other) warranted, and ends with an epistemic
act or state to which its agent is warranted in a way that she need not be aware of, i.e. to
which its agent enjoys entitlement. On Burge's view, there are at least two different kinds
of causal process that sometimes have this profile. One of those processes is preservative
memory, and the otherthe one that will concern us hereis testimony. When Burge
speaks of testimony, he means to denote an activity that may be, but is not necessarily,
verbalit is simply the activity of presenting something as true. If, while performing in a
musical, I utter the declarative sentence the rain in Spain falls mainly on the plain, I
have not thereby offered any testimony. If, while telling a joke, I begin by saying A man
walks into a bar, once again I have not thereby offered any testimony. But if you ask me
how many endowed chairs are in my department, and I say nothing but hold up five
fingers, then, although I have uttered no words, I have (at least if my intentions and
circumstances are otherwise normal) offered testimony: I have presented it as true that
there are five endowed chairs in my department. If you ask me whether Jones has finally
decided to pay his debts, then, even though you have asserted nothing in asking this
question, you have nonetheless offered testimony: you have presented it as true that Jones
has debts. While assertion is perhaps the most typical way to offer one's testimony, it is
not the only way.7
Whenever a sincere act of testimony is understood and accepted by someone (call this
latter agent the auditor, putting aside the misleading suggestion that testimony must be
heard in order to be understood)8 , there is a causal process of a certain kind running from
the testifier to the auditor. This causal process starts with the epistemic act or state that
the testifier was presenting as true in giving her testimony; and it ends with the epistemic
act or state by virtue of which the auditor accepts the testimony. According to Burge, this
causal process can, and often does, involve entitlement preservation. The epistemic act or
state the content of which the testifier presents as true is warranted, and because it occurs
and is warranted, the auditor is entitled to an epistemic act or state with the very same
content and judgemental force.
202
Recall, however, that one may be warranted in believing what is completely false, and so
one may be warranted in believing something on the basis of hallucinated testimony.
Perhaps no rational source has ever presented it as true that, say, Ghana is in Africa. But
it seems to me that a rational source has presented this to me as true, and I have no reason
to doubt that a rational source has done so: in that case, I am warranted in believing that a
rational source has presented it to me as true that Ghana is in Africa, and indeed, I am
warranted even in believing that Ghana is in Africa, but no testimony to this effect has
actually occurred. (In such a case, my belief, while true and warranted, would not
constitute knowledge. This is a Gettier case.) My beliefs are warranted by my
hallucination of testimony, but the warrant that I can enjoy by dint of this hallucination
may be the same as the warrant that I can enjoy by dint of actual testimony, so long as
there are no defeating reasons in either case. That, at any rate, is Burge's view.
Now that we've explained Burge's view, let's lay out his argument for this view.
5. BURGE'S ARGUMENT FOR THE VIEW THAT TESTIMONY PRESERVES A
PRIORI ENTITLEMENT
Here is Burge's very compressed summary of his own argument:
We are a priori prima facie entitled to accept something that is prima facie intelligible
and presented as true. For prima facie intelligible propositional contents prima facie
presented as true bear an a priori prima facie conceptual relation to a rational source of
true presentations-as-true: Intelligible propositional expressions presuppose rational
abilities and entitlements; so intelligible presentations-as-true come prima facie backed
by a rational source or resource for reason; and both the content of intelligible
propositional presentations-as-true and the prima facie rationality of their source indicate
a prima facie source of truth. (Burge 1993: 472)
This argument aims to establish the following conclusion a priori: if it seems to you that a
particular proposition (p) is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
prima facie9 entitled to believe that p. (The passage that I've just quoted from Burge
[1993] does not clearly make the qualification that I've just made concerning the
entitlement that you receive by virtue of its seeming to you that p is presented as true by a
rational source. I add the qualification that the entitlement is received by its so seeming to
you in order to accommodate the point made on Burge's behalf at the end of the
preceding section, i.e. that the warrant that one has on the basis of testimony is warrant
that one would equally
203
well have even if one merely hallucinated that testimony. Thus, Burge writes, In the
order of epistemic warrant, seeming understanding is the rational starting point [1997:
31].)
What a priori argument does Burge take to establish this conclusion? The passage quoted
just above is very compressed, but, given the context in which it is set, it is reasonable to
suppose that the steps of Burge's argument can be laid out as follows. In stating this
argument, I use the schematic variable p in step 5 and the conclusion to range over all
propositions our understanding of which does not require perceptual identification of
some deictic element. These are the propositions our understanding of which is, in
Burge's words, purely intellectual,10 and it is only these propositions, according to
Burge, a priori entitlement to which can be preserved through testimony. (That is because
it is only these propositions, Burge thinks, which one can ever be a priori warranted in
believing.) I hereby introduce the term purely conceptual propositions' to denote this
class of propositions.
I should make clear, before stating this argument, that there is not a single step of this
argument that is uncontroversial (or, indeed, anything less than highly controversial!). I
will not attempt to defend the steps of this argument here, but only to set them out.
(1) Necessarily, rational sources are, other things being equal, likely not to believe what
is not true. (It is supposed to follow a priori from the nature of rationality and from
the nature of belief that a rational believer tends, though perhaps with many
exceptions, to believe only what is true. The kind of likelihood that Burge has in
mind here, and in the steps of the argument below, is objective, not subjective.)
(2) Necessarily, rational sources are, other things being equal, likely not to present as
true something that they do not believe to be true. (It is supposed to follow a priori
from the nature of rationality and from the nature of testimonyof the activity of
presenting something as truethat a rational testifier tends, though perhaps with
many exceptions, to present as true only what she believes to be true.)
(3) Necessarily, the content of a presentation-as-true is constitutively determined by
relations between content-bearing items and their referents in such a way that
presentations as true are, other things being equal, likely to be true. (It is supposed to
follow a priori from the nature of content that contents presented as true are, though
perhaps with many exceptions, true.)
204
(4) Necessarily, what is presented as true by a rational source is, other things being
equal, likely to be true. (This is supposed to be supported a priori by 1, 2, and 3.
Notice that, if the inference from 1, 2, and 3 to 4 is sound, then the inference from 1
and 2 to 4 should be sound as well: 3 looks to be redundant. But Burge thinks that 3
is also true, and provides a ground for 4 that is distinct from, and reinforces, the basis
for 4 provided by 1 and 2.)
(5) Necessarily, if it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then
you are warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a rational source. (It is
supposed to follow a priori from the nature of understanding that what we seem to
understand to be presented as true by a rational source tends, though perhaps with
(4) Necessarily, what is presented as true by a rational source is, other things being
equal, likely to be true. (This is supposed to be supported a priori by 1, 2, and 3.
Notice that, if the inference from 1, 2, and 3 to 4 is sound, then the inference from 1
and 2 to 4 should be sound as well: 3 looks to be redundant. But Burge thinks that 3
is also true, and provides a ground for 4 that is distinct from, and reinforces, the basis
for 4 provided by 1 and 2.)
many exceptions, to have actually been presented as true by a rational source; or in
other words, apparent understanding tends, though perhaps with many exceptions, to
be genuine understanding. And if there is a necessarily reliable connection between
apparent understanding of p as having been presented as true and p's having actually
been presented as true, then, given Burge's account of the nature of warrant, it
follows that, if it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then
you are warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a rational source.)
(6) Necessarily, if it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then
you are warranted in believing that p. (5 tells us that necessarily, if it seems to you
that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are warranted in believing
that p is so presented. But if you are warranted in believing that p is presented as true,
and if 4 is also true, then it follows that, necessarily, any process that leads a believer
to whom it seems that p has been presented as true to believe that p will be a reliable
process. And so, from the nature of warrant, it follows that, necessarily, if it seems to
you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are warranted in
believing that p.)
Burge takes each step of the argument above to be a priori warranted, and a priori
knowable. But Burge's claims concerning what is a priori warranted, and a priori
knowable, extend even farther than the claims in the argument above. For step 5 to be a
priori is for it to be a priori that: If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational
source, then you are warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a rational
source. But Burge wants to claim something over and above this. Burge wants to claim
that, when it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a
priori warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a rational source. On what
grounds can he make this stronger claim? Burge does not explicitly address this issue, but
it seems to me that the most plausible account of his thinking on this issue takes it to go
as follows:
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that it seems this way to you.
205
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing the conditional: if it seems to you that p is presented as true by a
rational source, then you are warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a
rational source. (This second premise follows from the a prioricity of step 5, by
disjunction introduction.)
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that you are warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a
rational source.
If you are a priori warranted in believing that you are warranted in believing that p is
presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori warranted in believing that p
is presented as true by a rational source.
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that p is presented as true by a rational source. And if this warrant
is not epistemically accessible to someone who enjoys it, then it is an entitlement.
Although this argument is obviously not formally valid, it still seems to have some
plausibility, and it seems to me to provide the most plausible account of why Burge
thinks that an auditor (or apparent auditor) has an a priori entitlement to believe that a
rational source presented something as true. In any case, if this is not how Burge is
thinking of the matter, then it is not at all clear on what grounds he could believe that an
auditor (or apparent auditor) can have a priori entitlement to believe that a rational source
presented something as true.
So that, I take it, is why Burge thinks that, if it seems to you that p is presented as true by
a rational source, then you are a priori warranted in believing (and typically, entitled to
believe) that p is presented as true by a rational source. But now, why does Burge think
that, if it seems to you that p (a purely conceptual proposition) is presented as true by a
rational source, then you are a priori warranted in believing that p? For step 6 of the
argument above to be a priori is for it to be a priori that: If it seems to you that p is
presented as true by a rational source, then you are warranted in believing that p. But
Burge wants to claim something over and above this. He wants to claim that, when it
seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that p. On what grounds can he claim this? Burge does not
explicitly address this issue, but, again, it seems to me that the most plausible account of
his thinking on this issue takes it to go as follows:
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that it seems this way to you.
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing the conditional: if it seems to you that p is presented as true by a
rational source, then you are warranted in believing that p. (This second premise
206
follows from the a prioricity of the conclusion of the six-step argument set out above, by
disjunction introduction.)
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that you are warranted in believing that p.
If you are a priori warranted in believing that you are warranted in believing that p, then
you are a priori warranted in believing that p.
If it seems to you that p is presented as true by a rational source, then you are a priori
warranted in believing that p. If this warrant is not epistemically accessible to someone
who enjoys it, then it is an entitlement.
Again, although this inference is not formally valid, it still seems to have some
plausibility, and this inference seems to me to provide the most plausible account of why
Burge thinks that an auditor (or apparent auditor) has an a priori entitlement to believe
the proposition that a rational source seems to have presented as true. In any case, if this
is not how Burge is thinking of the matter, then it is not at all clear on what grounds he
could believe that an auditor (or apparent auditor) can have this a priori entitlement.
Notice that, in attempting to give a plausible account of Burge's argument, I have
interpreted Burge as accepting two instances of the following form of argument:
If p, then S is a priori warranted in believing that p
If p, then S is a priori warranted in believing that: if p then S is warranted in believing
that q.
211
If p, then S is a priori warranted in believing that q.
It is not easy to see what argument Burge could be giving to support his controversial
claims concerning the a priori entitlements preserved by testimony unless he relies on the
two arguments of this form that I set out in section 5. I take it then, that the success of
Burge's arguments requires that this form of argumentor at least the two instances that
Burge employsbe truth-preserving. Are they?
They may seem to be truth-preserving. To deny this would require either denying that a
priori warrant is closed under modus ponens consequence, or else denying that having a
priori warrant for believing that you have warrant for believing that p does not imply
having a priori warrant for believing that pand it may seem implausible to deny either
of these things. Indeed, it's the plausibility of all this that makes it reasonable to interpret
Burge as tacitly accepting arguments of this form for his controversial views concerning
the a priori entitlements that are preserved by testimony.
But notice that Burge is claiming not simply that a priori warrants are preserved by
testimony, but more specifically that a priori entitlements are preserved by testimony. So,
what Burge needs is not just that some arguments of the form set out above be truth-
preserving, but that those truth-preserving arguments justify a conclusion that is
specifically about entitlement. Now, since the kind of a priori warrant that is preserved by
testimony is typically, Burge thinks, one to which the auditor does not have epistemic
access, can't we use arguments of the form set out above to show that the auditor has
certain a priori warrants, and then conjoin these conclusions with the premise that the
auditor has no epistemic access to these warrants to reach the conclusion that the auditor
has a priori entitlements?
No. For the conditions under which arguments of the form set out above are truth-
preserving might also be conditions under which the warrants mentioned in those
arguments are warrants to which the auditor has epistemic access. In other words, we
have not considered the possibility that arguments of the form set out above are truth-
preserving only when the warrants mentioned in those arguments are justifications, and
not entitlements.
Let's see whether this might be the case. It is plausible that what you're justified in
believing is closed under modus ponens consequence, and it is also plausible that having
an a priori justification to believe that you're justified in believing p suffices for having an
a priori justification to believe that p. So, pending a defence of the controversial steps of
his 16 argument given in section 5, Burge can, I think, plausibly argue that a priori
justification is preserved by testimony. But what he claims is that a priori entitlement is
preserved by testimony. To argue for this along the lines that I've offered him here, he'd
have to give us some reason to believe two things:
212
(a) what you're entitled to believe is closed under modus ponens consequence, and
(b) having an a priori entitlement to believe that you're entitled to believe that p suffices
for having an a priori entitlement to believe that p.
But, in fact, when we recall what Burge has to tell us about the nature of entitlement, it
becomes clear that we have no reason to accept either (a) or (b).
Recall from our discussion of warrant in section 1 above that Burge thinks of warrants
generally as attaching to beliefs by virtue of the process that leads to those beliefs
specifically, by virtue of the necessary reliability of that process under normal
circumstances in the creature's habitat, given the creature's normal perspectival
limitations. To say that a believer is warranted in believing that p is to say that there is, in
the believer's present circumstances, some suitably reliable process that does or could
lead the creature to believe that p. To say that a believer is justified in believing that p is
to say that there is such a process, and that the creature has epistemic access to it as what
warrants him in believing that p. And finally, to say that a believer is entitled to believe
that p is to say that there is such a process, and that the creature does not have epistemic
access to it as what warrants him in believing that p.
Now, justification is plausibly closed under modus ponens consequence for a simple
reason. When there is a suitably reliable process that does or could lead a creature to
believe that p, and a suitably reliable process that does or could lead a creature to believe
that if p, then q, then there is bound to be a suitably reliable process that does or could
lead a creature to believe that q: namely, deduction. But when a creature deduces q from
the conjunction of p and (if p, then q), then the creature's warrant for believing that q
consists in this inference, and such inferential warrants, recall, are all justifications, for
Burge. Thus, when a creature has a warrant for believing that p, and also has a warrant
for believing that (if p, then q), then that creature is bound to have a justification for
believing that q (whether or not she avails herself of that justification and proceeds to
believe that q).
But why think that, under such conditions, the creature would also have an entitlement to
believe that q? For the creature to have such an entitlement, there would have to be
another process, distinct from deduction, and one to which the creature does not have
epistemic access, that does or could, under normal circumstances, lead the creature to
believe that q whenever she believes both p and (if p, then q). Why should we suppose
that there is any such process? Burge certainly offers us no such reason, and I am aware
of no such reason. So, even if justification is preserved under modus ponens
consequence, we have no reason to suppose that the same is true of entitlement. In other
words, we have no reason to accept (a) above.
213
Now consider (b). If a creature is justified in believing that she is justified in believing
that p, then there is a suitably reliable process that does or could lead the creature to
believe that p: namely, a suitably reliable inference from the premise that she's justified in
believing that p to the conclusion that p. (If the creature is warranted in believing that p,
then she is in a position to make a reliable, though of course not deductive, inference to
p.) But notice, again, that if a creature infers p from the fact that she is warranted in
believing that p, then the creature's warrant for believing that p consists in this inference,
and such inferential warrants are, once again, justifications. And so it follows that the
creature has a justification for believing that p. So, if a creature is justified in believing
that she's justified in believing that p, then it follows that she's justified in believing that
p. But is the same sort of principle true of entitlement? Once again, only if there is some
other process, distinct from inference, and one to which the creature does not have
epistemic access, that does or could, under normal circumstances, lead the creature to
believe that p whenever she believes that she's warranted in believing that p. Why should
we suppose that there is any such process? Burge certainly offers us no such reason, and I
am aware of no such reason. So, even if it's plausible that being justified in believing that
you're justified in believing that p implies that you're justified in believing that p, there is
still no reason to think that being entitled to believe that you're entitled to believe that p
implies that you're entitled to believe that p. In short, we have no reason to accept (b)
above.
I conclude thatwhatever the merits of Burge's metaphysical views connecting
rationality, intelligibility, truth, and presentation-as-trueBurge still gives us no reason
to accept either (a) or (b) above, and so gives us no reason to accept crucial steps in his
argument for the claim that a priori entitlements are preserved by testimony. Even if we
grant Burge all of the controversial metaphysical claims in his argument 16 above, the
farthest that this will get him is the claim that, if a rational source presents it as true that
p, then you are entitled to believe that a rational source has presented it as true that p,
and also, if a rational source presents it as true that p, then you are entitled to believe that,
if a rational source has presented it as true that p, then you are warranted in believing
that p. But we have not yet seen how these claims can jointly entail anything about what
you're entitled to believe about the truth value of p, when a rational source presents it as
true that p. It may seem that they do jointly entail that, if a rational source has presented it
as true that p, then you are entitled to believe that pbut if it seems this way to us, then
that is probably because we are confusing entitlement with justification.
214
The problem with Burge's argument is not that it fails to show that a priori entitlements
are preserved by testimony, but rather that it fails to show that entitlements of any kind
(as Burge conceives of entitlements) are preserved by testimony.12
215
11 The Assurance View of Testimony
Frederick F. Schmitt
enough for justification); versions of the assurance view will differ on whether that
requires the addressee's acceptance of the assurance. For the addressee's belief to be
testimonially justified in the doxastic sense, the addressee must base that belief on the
epistemic reason; this presumably requires that the belief arises from the addressee's
acceptance of the assurance.6
Presumably merely giving an epistemic reason is not yet enough for giving a good
epistemic reason or one adequate for the addressee's belief to be justified, or even for
giving a reason having any positive quality.7 Accordingly, Richard Moran adopts a two-
tiered assurance view in his rich defense of the assurance view, Getting Told and Being
Believed.8 In the first tier, assurance or its acceptance is enough for giving the recipient
an epistemic reason to believe p, though not enough for giving the recipient a good
epistemic reason to believe p.9 In the second tier, the presence or absence of background
conditions determines whether the reason given is good or bad:10
Whether this [the assurance or its acceptance] counts as a good or sufficient reason is not
a matter of the speaker's illocutionary authority, but will depend both on his sincerity
218
and on his having discharged his epistemic responsibilities with respect to the belief in
question. (295)
Assurance, although not sufficient for giving a good or bad reason, is necessary for the
given reason even to count as epistemic and thereby licence the background conditions as
determinants of whether the reason is good or bad:
These background conditions can themselves be construed as evidential, or at any rate not
at the behest of the speaker to determine, but they are not themselves sufficient for giving
any epistemic significance to the speaker's words, for the relevance of these conditions
only comes into play once it is understood that a particular speech act is being performed
with those words . . . The speaker has to constitute his utterance as having this or that
illocutionary force before the empirical background conditions can contribute anything to
its epistemic significance . . . Determining his utterance as an assertion is what gets the
speaker's words into the realm of epistemic assessment in the first place. (289)
Moran here clarifies the assurance view by contrasting it explicitly with evidentialism
and implicitly with alternative non-evidentialist views like the reliability, social
responsibility, and transindividual reasons views.11 On these alternative views, conditions
like the testifier's sincerity, responsibility, knowledge, trustworthiness, and reliability in
asserting p are sufficient for the utterance to give a good epistemic reason, and their
absence is sufficient for the utterance to give a bad epistemic reason, so long as the right
vehicle of testimony is in place. And the right vehicle may be something other than
assurancemere assertion, for example. On these views, what vehicle is right for
testimony to give any epistemic reason (good or bad) is determined by what vehicle is
appropriate for giving a good or bad epistemic reason as conceived by the view. Moran
opposes these views by insisting that assurance is necessary for giving a good or bad
epistemic reason in non-evidential cases, and this fact is independent of any good- or
bad-making characteristics of the reason given by assurance. I take the two-tiered
assurance view to be this:
(i) Assurance that p or its acceptance is enough to give the recipient some epistemic
reason to believe p.12
(ii) This reason is determined to be either good or bad by the presence or absence of
background conditions'.13
219
(iii) If the reasons are determined to be good, then the subject is testimonially justified
in believing p.
The background conditions include some or all of the following: the testifier's sincerity in
asserting p, his having discharged his epistemic responsibilities with respect to the belief
in question (Moran 2006: 295), the testifier's knowledge that p, trustworthiness, or
reliability as to whether p, or at least the addressee's assumption that some or all of these
conditions obtain (Moran 2006: 289).14 I allow that all this is only one option for
interpreting Moran, but I know of no better option.15
The assurance view divides into what I will call an agreement version and a
communicative norm version. On the agreement version, assurance or its acceptance
gives the addressee an epistemic reason to believe p in something like the way a promise
and its acceptance give the promisee a practical reason to rely on the promised action.
When assurance is accepted, this establishes an agreement of sorts between the testifier
and the addressee. The testifier initiates the agreement by presenting an epistemic reason
to believe, inviting trust, or offering to assume responsibility for the truth of the
proposition (conditional on the addressee's acceptance of that offer). The addressee may
complete the agreement by accepting these. A completed agreement of this sort forms a
personal relation between the testifier and the addressee. Reference to such a personal
relation in turn explains the sense in which in testimonial uptake the addressee may be
said to believe the testifier that p, and not merely believe the testifier's utterance.
The communicative norm version of the assurance view differs from the agreement
version in treating assurance as giving the addressee an epistemic reason to believe in
virtue of the fact that assurance is governed by norms of communication. These norms
make demands on the activity of assuring and confer prima facie permission for any
addressee to trust what is assured whether
220
or not an agreement is proferred or accepted.16 This version of the assurance view does
not entail that testimony gives an epistemic reason to believe in virtue of any actual
personal relation between the testifier and the addressee or any reason to form such a
relation. I believe that the communicative norm version faces fewer difficulties than the
agreement version, but as no one has endorsed it, and Moran's view is clearly an
agreement assurance view, I will focus on the agreement version and set aside the
communicative norm version (only pausing later to note that the latter faces at least one
difficulty that afflicts the agreement version). For convenience, I will refer to the
agreement version simply as the assurance view.
Turning now to two main variants of the agreement version, on one, a testimonial
epistemic reason is given only by an actual agreement. Such an agreement generates
commitments of both the testifier and the addressee, and these commitments give the
recipient an epistemic reason to believe. Call this the actual agreement variant. On the
other variant, the assurance by itself gives the addressee an epistemic reason to believe
without any acceptance, hence without an agreement. It does so because in virtue of its
content it offers the recipient a benefit great enough to give a practical reason to accept
the assurance and fulfil its terms. Call this the offer-of-benefit variant. The difference
between these two variants is analogous to the difference between the reason one has to
fulfil the terms of a contract simply because one has made the contract and thereby
agreed to fulfil its terms, and the reason one has to sign a contract and fulfil its terms
because of the benefit contingent on signing. Moran's insistence that reason-giving
depends on a personal relation might suggest attributing to him the actual agreement
variant. But his core account of reason-giving is in fact an offer-of-benefit variant, and I
believe this is the better choice for defending the assurance view.17
221
I grant at the outset that there is an important and pervasive phenomenon of assurance,
understood to involve some or all of the following: presenting oneself as having adequate
epistemic reason to believe p, presenting oneself as being epistemically responsible in
asserting p, inviting the addressee to trust that p, or offering to assume responsibility for
p's being true. And when assurance involves the latter speech acts, the addressee often
enough accepts it. I grant too that assurance or its acceptance can give the addressee some
practical reason to trust the testifier beyond what a hearer has in a case of mere assertion.
My question is rather whether assurance or its acceptance gives the addressee an
epistemic reason to believe, in the sense of a reason that contributes to the addressee's
epistemic justification for believing p.
I will begin by criticizing the putative analogy between assuring and promising. I will
then object to the assurance view, on three grounds. First, though assurance may give the
recipient a practical reason to trust the testifier as to whether p, neither assurance nor its
acceptance is sufficient to give the addressee an epistemic reason to believe p. Second,
assurance isn't necessary for testimony to give the addressee a non-evidential epistemic
reason to believe the proposition. Third, the assurance view cannot account for the
conferring of epistemic reasons by testimony in the most important class of cases for a
non-reductive view, the primitive ones for which the hearer lacks a substantial base of
non-testimonial reasons. My first and second objections are consonant with those made
by Jennifer Lackey (2008: ch. 8), to which I am much indebted here, though my
arguments generally differ from hers. At the end of the paper, I will suggest an alternative
non-reductive, non-individualist view of testimonial justification based on speech acts.
PRELIMINARY: ASSURANCE AND ASSERTION
The assurance view, as Moran presents it, assumes that assurance involves something
beyond mere assertion in virtue of which the testifier gives the addressee a reason to
believesuch as presenting oneself as having adequate epistemic reason to believe p or
inviting the addressee to trust that p.18 As Moran observes, assertions without any
assurance occur in persuasion, argument, demonstration, therapy, examination, and
interrogation (2006: 27980; cf. Hinchman on conversational indirection, 2005: 568
72).19 I would add that
222
the sentences we utter to teach young children language are usually assertions without
assurance. It is compatible with these observations that assertion is an affirmation of a
sort that normally expresses belief.20 Various writers have insisted that assertion involves
more than thisthat it involves representing oneself as believing or as knowing.21
Moran's examples of persuasion, argument, therapy, examination, and interrogation show
that the knowing variant is too strong, and examination seems to show that the
believing variant is also too strong. These claims very likely arise from confusing
assertion with assurance. Nevertheless, they are compatible with both the assurance view
and the assertion view I will eventually contrast it with, so we need not contest them here.
That assurance is more demanding than assertion is confirmed by the fact that the two are
relationally different. Assuring entails asserting something to an actual addressee. If I say
something intending to assure Audrey, but she does not hear me, I do not assure her of
anythingI do not make any assurance at all. But I do assert something. Asserting, then,
does not require asserting to anyone. Indeed, it seems that it does not even require an
intended audience. I can utter I'm alone in the privacy of my house, and thereby assert
that I'm alone. Even if the only possible point of such an utterance is to fix my belief that
I am alone, it does not follow that I am addressing my assertion to myself. It seems
unlikely that self-address is necessary or helpful for belief-fixation; verbal repetition does
the job.22
IS ASSURING ANALOGOUS TO PROMISING?
Having formulated the assurance view and remarked on the difference between assurance
and assertion, we may now consider arguments for it.
Moran analogizes assuring in testimony to promising.23 I take it that the analogy is
supposed to lend significant support to the assurance view. The
223
proposed analogy is this. Suppose I promise you that I will weed the garden. Then my
promise not only gives me a practical reason to perform the action of weeding the garden,
but gives you a practical reason to rely on my performing this action when you plan your
own actions. In promising, I make a commitment to perform the action, and you receive
an entitlement to rely on my performing the action.24 Analogously, my assuring you that
it rained in Portland gives you an epistemic reason to believe this proposition. In
assuring, I make a commitment that the proposition is true, and you receive an
entitlement to believe it, at least if you accept my assurance. This is just what the
assurance view claims.
I don't deny that we can describe promising and typical cases of assuring in a parallel
way, but the differences between these stand in the way of analogical support for the
assurance view.25
First, a promise is made only if the promisee accepts the promise, hence only if there is
an agreement to perform the promised action.26 The promisee's reason to rely on the
promised action is no more given by the promise than by the acceptanceit is given by
the agreement. The reason does not arise merely because in virtue of its content the
promise offers a benefit that gives the recipient a reason to accept the promise and fulfil
its terms. If I say I promise to weed the garden to Elmer and Alma, and Elmer accepts
my promise but Alma shrugs, Elmer will, and Alma will not, be entitled to rely on my
performance of the action. If Alma rebuked me for not weeding the garden, I could
respond, But you just shrugged when I offered. So I never gave you any reason to rely
on my weeding the garden. By contrast, in the case of assuring in testifying, I can assure
you whether or not you accept my assurance. All that is required on your part is that you
hear and understand what I say and recognize that I am assuring you. More importantly,
if my assurance or its acceptance is to give you an epistemic reason to believe what I say,
then my assurance all by itself must do so, regardless of whether you accept it. For when
I assure you that it rained in Portland, I do so before you accept my assurance. In
assuring, I guarantee that the proposition is true. I have already stuck my neck out, and
once I have done this, it is too late for me to pull it back in and deprive you of a reason to
believe, if you should
224
decide not to accept my assurance. The guarantee all by itself gives you a reason to
believe, if anything does. I will return to this point below.
This disanalogy between assuring and promising fits the offer-of-benefit agreement view,
that testimonial reason-giving does not require an actual agreement but only a reason to
accept the assurance because in virtue of its content it offers the addressee enough
benefit. But of course that there is such a disanalogy reduces or undermines support for
the offer-of-benefit agreement view from the comparison of assuring and promising. And
obviously the disanalogy contradicts the actual agreement view.
There is a second disanalogy between assuring and promising, one that reduces or
undermines support for Moran's two-tiered assurance view from the comparison of
assuring and promising. My testimonial assurance, and your acceptance or reason to
accept, are supposed to give you an epistemic reason to believe without giving you a
good epistemic reason to believe. More is required for a good epistemic reason than
assurance or its acceptance, as Moran allows. I must be sincere, responsible,
knowledgeable, trustworthy, or reliable in assertion if a good epistemic reason is to be
given at all.27 Suppose I assure you about a subject, yet later it turns out that I was not
responsible, or knowledgeable, etc. in asserting p. Then my assurance hasn't given you a
good epistemic reason to believe p. Or so Moran allows in order to respond to the worry
that assurance or its acceptance is not enough for a good reason. But my promise and
your acceptance of it give you not only a (prima facie) practical reason to rely on the
promised action, but a good practical reason to do so, whether or not I am responsible,
and so forth, in promising. If later it turns out that I was not responsible, you still have
good reason to rely on my promise; I am still bound by it, and you may hold me to it. The
objection to the analogy, then, is that my promise and your acceptance by themselves
give you more than my testimonial assurance and your acceptance do according to the
two-tiered assurance view. If assuring were fully analogous to promising, the analogy
would support a single-tiered view. Luckily for Moran's two-tiered view, the full analogy
does not hold. Assurance or its acceptance depends on background conditions to give a
good epistemic reason, and promising does not depend on such conditions to give a good
practical reason. This disanalogy reduces or undermines support for Moran's two-tiered
view from the comparison of assuring and promising.
This second disanalogy is related to a third. While testifying and promising both exhibit a
variation from one instance to the next in the degree of assurance offered, the two differ
in the way that the degree of assurance offered affects the quality of the reasons given. In
the case of testifying, the greater the degree of assurance the better the epistemic reason
given, other things equal. But greater assurance in making a promise doesn't increase the
quality of the
225
practical reason donated by the promise. The most tepid promise commits the promisor as
firmly as the most emphatic promise. No doubt greater emphasis increases the quality of
the promisee's evidentially based epistemic reason to expect the promised action to occur,
and that may in turn increase the quality of the promisee's practical reason to rely on the
promised action. But this increase in the quality of the practical reason to expect the
action derives not from the promise and its acceptance but from whatever implicit
testimony or evidence that the promised action will occur that the promisor incidentally
gives while promising. The quality of the practical reason to rely on the promised action
depends entirely on whether there is an agreement, not on the degree of assurance.28
These three disanalogies reduce or undermine altogether any support for Moran's version
of the assurance view from the comparison of assuring and promising.
DOES AN ACTUAL AGREEMENT GIVE AN EPISTEMIC REASON?
Let us set aside the question of an analogy with promising and ask directly whether
anything in assurance or its acceptance might generate an epistemic reason to believe the
testimonial proposition. We will need to treat separately the two variants of the
agreement assurance view, since they identify different sources of an epistemic reason. I
will focus in this section on the actual agreement variant:
An actual agreement gives the addressee an epistemic reason to believe p because the
assurance and acceptance together generate commitments for both the testifier and the
addressee, and these commitments give the addressee an epistemic reason to believe.29
226
We are to consider, then, whether an actual agreement gives the addressee an epistemic
reason to believe the testimonial proposition.30 We may initially focus on just one
proposal for what is involved in assurancemy inviting you to trust me that pand then
generalize what we find about this proposal. Does my inviting you to trust me together
with your acceptance of my invitation give you an epistemic reason to believe p? We
may grant that if you accept my invitation, then you have a (prima facie) reason to do
what I invite you to do (in this case, trust me that p), just as one always has a reason to do
what one is invited to do when one accepts an invitation. You have such a reason even if
you lacked any reason to accept my invitation. By accepting my invitation to trust me,
you commit yourself to trusting me and you have a reason to do so in virtue of this
commitment. On the assumption that if something gives you a reason to trust me that p of
the sort just mentioned, then it also gives you an epistemic reason to believe me that p,
your acceptance of my invitation gives you an epistemic reason to believe me that p.
The trouble with this argument is that we cannot infer from the fact that your accepting
my invitation to trust me gives you a reason to trust me, that it also gives you an
epistemic reason to believe me that p. The reason your accepting my invitation gives you
is not itself an epistemic reason to believe p; and there is no basis for thinking that giving
you a reason that is not itself epistemic could give you an epistemic reason. To show that
the reason your accepting my invitation gives you is not itself an epistemic reason to
believe p, one might observe that it does not bear on whether p is true, as required for an
epistemic reason to believe p. Although I find this observation sufficient to make the
point, an assurance theorist might reply by denying that an epistemic reason must bear on
the truth, conceding only that an evidential epistemic reason must do so. Not knowing
how to riposte a blank denial of the basic principle that an epistemic reason must bear on
the truth, I support the point in a different way.
If the reason your accepting my invitation gives you is simply the sort you generally
acquire from accepting an invitation, then it is defeasible by countervailing non-epistemic
reasons. For example, it may be overridden by its being prudentially costly or risky for
you to trust mejust as the reason you have to join me for dinner, given by accepting my
invitation to dinner, may be overridden by its being costly or risky for you to join me.
Suppose that after accepting my invitation to trust me, someone threatens to do you
physical harm if you trust me. If the threat is credible and severe, the reason you have to
trust me is defeated by prudential reasons you have not to trust me. But no epistemic
227
reason to believe me is defeated by such countervailing prudential reasons. So the reason
your accepting my invitation gives you to trust me is not an epistemic reason to believe
me. And there is no reason to think that your being given a reason to trust me gives you
an epistemic reason to believe me. This is enough to cast doubt on the argument for the
actual agreement view (or the version of it that traces the epistemic reason to an accepted
invitation to trust).31 In the absence of a persuasive argument for the view, we have no
cause to take the view seriously.
I do not deny that the practical reason to trust given by an accepted invitation is a reason
to do somethingto trust me that pthat facilitates having an epistemic reason to
believe p. For testimony gives an epistemic reason to believe p only if one takes up
testimony in the right way, and trusting is one of the right ways to take up testimony. But
this is only an instrumental relation between accepted invitations to trust and being given
an epistemic reason.
I have considered the version of the actual agreement view that traces the epistemic
reason to an accepted invitation to trust. But what we have said against the argument for
that version generalizes to parallel arguments for other versions, including those that
trace the epistemic reason to a presentation of an epistemic reason and to an offer to
assume epistemic responsibility for asserting p. The reason given by an agreement in
testimony is always defeasible by countervailing practical reasons. This is a consequence
of the general fact that the reason given to fufil any agreement whatever is always
defeasible by countervailing practical reasons. No such reason is an epistemic reason to
believe. And giving such a reason never gives an epistemic reason to believe.32
228
DOES AN OFFER OF BENEFIT GIVE AN EPISTEMIC REASON?
I have rebutted the argument for the actual agreement view by contesting whether an
actual agreement accounts for giving an epistemic reason. I turn now from the actual
agreement to the offer-of-benefit agreement variant of the agreement view:
Assurance gives the addressee an epistemic reason to believe p because in virtue of its
content it offers the addressee a benefit great enough to give the addressee a reason to
accept the assurance and fulfill its terms.
On this view, the character of the benefit must make the reason to believe epistemic.
I see more hope for this variant than for the actual agreement variant. The hope is that,
even though no agreement gives a reason not defeasible by countervailing practical
reasons, an offer of a benefit may nevertheless do so, and an offer of the right kind of
benefit may make this an epistemic reason to believe. The offer of the benefit must by
itself provide a reason to believe not defeasible by practical considerations and aptly
called epistemic. Now, there is no plausibility to the suggestion that my invitation to trust
is such an offer. Any reason given by an invitation to do something would seem to be
defeasible by countervailing practical considerations. But there is another candidate for
what I offer in assurance that stands a better chance of providing the desired sort of
reason. I have in mind my offer of my taking or assuming epistemic responsibility for
asserting p. This is an offer to satisfy norms of epistemically responsible behaviour in
asserting p. This offer would seem to be closer to a guarantee that p than the other
components of assurance mentioned by Moran.33 My offer specifies a benefit to you, of
my taking epistemic responsibility for asserting p. The prospect of receiving the benefit
of my assuming epistemic responsibility for asserting p conditional on your accepting my
offer is supposed to entice you to accept my offer. And the benefit offered gives you a
reason to believe p, since doing so is part of accepting the offer.34 Since the benefit
offered is epistemic (namely, my assuming epistemic responsibility), the offer might
plausibly be taken to give you an epistemic reason to believe p. It is not obvious that your
reason to accept the
229
offer can be defeated by countervailing practical reasons, as the reason given by my
invitation to trust (and your acceptance of that invitation) is. In any event, I set aside the
objection from defeasibility that afflicts the invitation proposal and press a different
objection to the present proposal.
I read Moran as making this proposal in the only passage in his article that suggests why
he takes assurance to give an epistemic reason:
If it seems difficult to see how anything, even someone's words, could acquire some
epistemic value through something like conferral, perhaps because this suggests
something too arbitrary or ceremonial to constitute a genuine reason for belief, it should
be remembered that for both parties this conferral is by its nature an overt assumption of
specific responsibility on the part of the speaker. This is no more (or less) mysterious
than how an explicit agreement or contract alters one's responsibilities, actions which are
also within the capacities of ordinary speakers. (Moran 2006: 2889)
On the most charitable reading of this passage, Moran proposes that my offer of taking
epistemic responsibility for asserting p gives you an epistemic reason to believe p
because it gives you a reason to accept the offer.35 The reason it gives you to accept the
offer is that doing so will bring the benefit of my taking such responsibility. And having
such a reason gives you an epistemic reason to believe because the benefit offered is
epistemic.36
Is this proposal correct? The final sentence of the passage most recently quoted from
Moran suggests that all the assurance view need do to support an affirmative answer is to
explain how your acceptance of my offer would alter my epistemic responsibilities. But
to support the claim that the offer gives an epistemic reason, it is not enough to explain
how my epistemic responsibilities would differ; it must be shown that the offer of such a
difference gives you an epistemic reason to believe p. It must be shown that the offer of
the benefit to you of my taking epistemic responsibility for asserting p gives a reason
that, when good, contributes to your epistemic justification for believing p.37
230
The objection to the proposal I want to press is that the offer it attributes to me makes no
sense.38 Clearly it is logically impossible for me to offer you that the assertion I now
makeone completed at the moment I complete this very offeris epistemically
responsible. For by the time I complete the assertion and the offer, it is too late for the
epistemic responsibility of the assertion to depend on whether you accept the offer, as it
must if my offer is to make sense. Rather, my offer must be that I will take epistemic
responsibility in the future for my present assertion that p, where this means taking the
consequences should it later be discovered that my assertion was not epistemically
responsible at the time I made it. (Presumably, taking the consequences amounts to
admitting that my assertion was not epistemically responsible and making reparations for
any damage from your trusting that p under those conditions.) Now, it is logically
possible for me to make this offer. However, you can have no reason to accept it if your
aim is merely to acquire an epistemic reason to believe p. This offer gives you no more
epistemic reason to believe p than would my offer to flip a coin and in exchange for your
trusting that p if it lands Heads and not-p if it lands Tails, take the consequences should it
later be discovered that the proposition in which you trust is false.
Granted, if you had epistemic reason to believe that I would not offer to take the
consequences should it later be discovered that my assertion was not epistemically
responsible unless my assertion were epistemically responsible, this would give you an
evidential reason to believe that my assertion was epistemically responsible, and this in
turn might very well give you an evidential reason to believe p. But Moran proposes that
my offer gives you a non-evidential epistemic reason to believe p. And my merely
offering to take the consequences does not by itself give you any such reason. Nor is it
plausible that such an offer provides an epistemic reason to believe p, though if it were
later discovered that my assertion was not epistemically responsible, it would be a bad
epistemic reason. For whether the reason given at the time of testimony is good or bad
should not depend on whether it is later discovered that my assertion was not
epistemically responsible. The key point, however, is that my offer is missing something
crucial for giving a reason. One might say that what is missing is a guarantee that my
assertion was epistemically responsible at the time. But that simply names the problem
Moran is trying to solve by specifying that the relevant offer is to take the future
consequences of my
231
present assertionan unsuccessful proposal, as I have argued. The offer Moran cites is
not one that could give you an epistemic reason to believe p.39
In short, on no version of what is involved in assurance and its acceptance do either of
these give you an epistemic reason to believe p, at most a practical reason to accept an
invitation to trust or to accept an offer to take epistemic responsibility in asserting p.
Neither the actual acceptance nor the offer-of-benefit assurance view is correct.
Assurance and its acceptance provide no epistemic reason to believe that is not present in
other cases of assertion.
It is fair for the assurance theorist to respond at this point by asking what benefit a
practice of assurance can be thought to confer on our communicative-cognitive economy,
if not the benefit of donating epistemic reasons? I would suggest that it confers benefits
of two sorts.
First, as I have explained, an invitation to trust can bind the addressee who accepts it in
the usual way that acceptances of invitations bind the invitee. The social desirability of
accepting an invitation to trust may motivate the recipient to accept the invitation, and the
binding then motivates the addressee to follow through and trust. This is beneficial to the
extent that testifiers give assurances only of true beliefs. The fact that addressees tend to
believe assurances motivates testifiers to be cautious in their assurances. To the extent
that people desire to be able to give assurances, this desire motivates them to acquire true
beliefs, and toward that end justified beliefs, in propositions for which they then provide
assurances. Similarly, an offer to take future responsibility for what is assured can
motivate addressees to accept the offer as insurance and thus to trust, and this in turn
motivates testifiers to be cautious in their assurances and acquire true and justified
beliefs.
Second, assurance itself (weakly) indicates the truth of the assured proposition. That
someone is willing to offer an assumption of responsibility in exchange for trust indicates
his or her confidence in the truth of the proposition, and confidence in the truth of a
proposition indicates that it is true. In virtue of this, our recognition of assurance gives us
an epistemic reason to believe (whether an evidential reason or some other kind). These
benefits of assurance do not depend on the truth of the assurance view.
IS ASSURANCE NECESSARY FOR GIVING A TESTIMONIAL REASON?
It is natural to include in the assurance view the position that assurance is necessary and
not just sufficient (as we have taken the view) for giving a
232
non-evidential epistemic reason. And it is equally natural to object to this position on the
ground that testimony gives an overhearer of the testimony the same epistemic reason to
believe p as it gives the addressee. Suppose a testifier assures an addressee and as a
consequence, whether foreseen or not, leads an overhearing bystander to believe p. The
objection is that the testimony gives the overhearer the same epistemic reason to believe
p as it gives the addressee. Yet the testifier does not assure the overhearer that p, present
any reason to believe p to the overhearer, invite the overhearer to trust him, nor offer to
take epistemic responsibility for the assertion, and the overhearer therefore cannot, and
has no reason to, accept any invitation or offer. So testimony can give a hearer an
epistemic reason to believe p even though the testifier does not assure the hearer, does not
lend the hearer an opportunity to accept any assurance, and the hearer does not accept any
assurance. I will press this objection to the assurance view.
Lackey sets out an overhearer case:40
Ben and Kate, thinking that they are alone in their office building, are having a discussion
about the private lives of their co-workers. During the course of their conversation, Ben
tells Kate that their boss is having an affair with the latest intern who has been hired by
the company, Irene. Unbeknownst to them, however, Earl has been eavesdropping on
their conversation and so he, like Kate, comes to believe solely on the basis of Ben's
testimonywhich is in fact both true and epistemically impeccablethat his boss is
having an affair with Irene. Moreover, Kate and Earl not only have the same relevant
background information about both Ben's reliability as a testifier and the proffered
testimony, they also are properly functioning recipients of testimony who possess no
relevant undefeated defeaters. (Lackey 2008: 241)
On the assurance view of testimony, Ben's assurance or Kate's acceptance of it gives Kate
an epistemic reason to believe that the boss and Irene are having an affair, but it does not
give Earl an epistemic reason to believe this. For Earl is given and accepts no assurance.
Earl may have an evidential reason to believe the proposition, based on his belief that
Ben assures Kate and that Ben is a trustworthy and reliable source of information of this
sort when he makes assurances in circumstances of this kind. But Earl has no reason from
assurance. Thus, Kate is given and has an epistemic reason to believe that Earl is not
given and does not have. But this implication of the assurance view is counter-intuitive.
Intuitively, Earl is given and has the same epistemic reason to believe that Kate does,
even though Kate is assured and Earl is not.41
233
There are several ways the proponent of the assurance view of testimony might reply to
this objection. One is to stonewall and insist that Kate has an epistemic reason that Earl
lacks. According to Ross, for Kate not to believe Ben would be for her to challenge
Ben's authority, but this would not be so for Earl.42 Moreover, Kate would be entitled to
resent Ben if it turned out he was not trustworthy on the matter, but Earl would not be so
entitled. According to Hinchman, Ben would be entitled to feel slighted if Kate did not
believe him, but not if Earl did not believe him. Ross and Hinchman take these points as
evidence of a difference in the non-evidential reasons Kate and Earl are given. If Earl
were given the same reasons by Ben's testimony as Kate is, then his not believing Ben
would challenge Ben's authority, he would be entitled to resent Ben if it turned out that
Ben was not trustworthy, and Ben would be entitled to feel slighted if Earl did not believe
him. The power of challenge and the entitlements to resentment and feeling slighted are
powers and entitlements that typically arise from agreements. So it is natural to propose
that Kate's agreement with Ben gives rise to these powers and entitlements and that Kate
has a reason in virtue of that agreement that Earl does not have.
Lackey questions whether the cases of Kate and Earl really differ in these ways. If Earl
were not to believe Ben, then, according to Lackey, he too would challenge Ben's
authority in the sense that his action would reveal his belief that Ben is untrustworthy.
And Earl would also be entitled to resent Ben if it turned out Ben was not trustworthy.
And if Earl were not to believe Ben, then Ben would be entitled to feel slighted.
Ross and Hinchman may respond persuasively to this criticism by allowing that all this is
true, but maintaining that there is still a crucial difference between Kate and Earl: Kate
could specially challenge Ben's authority and would have a special reason to resent Ben,
but Earl could not, and Ben would be specially entitled to feel slighted by Kate, but not
by Earl. Earl's challenge and reason to resent Ben, and Ben's entitlement to resent Earl,
fall under norms of assertion rather than norms generated by assurance and acceptance. If
Earl were not to believe Ben, Earl would challenge Ben's authority in the sense that not
believing Ben manifests that Earl does not take the relevant norm of assertion (One
should believe what people assert when one takes them to be authoritative) to apply to
this instance of assertion. Earl's not believing Ben would manifest that Earl does not
believe Ben to be authoritative. And Earl would have reason to resent Ben if it turned out
that Ben is untrustworthy because then Ben would violate a different norm of assertion
(One should not assert something about which one is not trustworthy). Earl would have
the sort of reason one has to resent the behaviour of those who violate norms that do not
arise from agreements. Finally, if Ben were to discover that Earl does believe him, then
Ben would be entitled to
234
feel slighted because by not believing him Earl manifests that he does not believe Ben to
be authoritative.
But, Ross and Hinchman may legitimately insist, these reasons and entitlements deriving
from norms of assertion are quite different from the reasons and entitlements that arise
from Ben's assurance and Kate's acceptance. In assuring Kate, Ben makes an offer for
Kate to rely on his word by trust alone and an offer to fulfil the obligation imposed by
making this offer only if he is trustworthy. If Kate were not to believe Ben because she
does not accept Ben's assurance, then she would challenge Ben's authority, not only in the
sense in which Earl would challenge it were he not to believe, but in an additional sense:
not to believe Ben would indicate not accepting Ben's assurance, and this would manifest
that Kate does not believe Ben to be authoritative, since it manifests that she does not
take the relevant norm of assurance (One should believe what people assure when one
takes them to be authoritative) to apply to this instance of assertion. And if Kate were
not to believe Ben after accepting his assurance, then she would challenge Ben's authority
in the different sense that she manifests that she regards the agreement they have made to
be illegitimate, presumably because she does not take Ben to be trustworthy. And if it
turned out that Ben is not trustworthy, Kate would be entitled to resent Ben, not merely
for violating the norm of assertion to which we referred above, but for reneging on his
accepted offer. And finally, if Kate were not to believe Ben, then Ben would be entitled
to feel slighted because Kate reveals her belief that Ben is not trustworthy, either by not
believing him once she has accepted his offer, or by refusing to accept his offer. These
appear to be genuine differences between Kate and Earl. Moreover, these differences
arise from the fact that Kate accepts Ben's assurance, while Ben does not give his
assurance to Earl, and Earl accepts no assurance.
But this response to Lackey shows only that there are differences of these sorts between
Kate and Earl, and that the differences stem from differences in assurance and
acceptance. There remains an objection to the assurance view, also made by Lackey, that
these differences are not epistemically relevant; they do not show that Ben's testimony
gives a non-evidential epistemic reason to Kate but not to Earl. I have already supported
the same conclusion in the preceding sections. Kate has a practical reason to trust that
Earl lacks. But this difference between them does not entail that Kate has an epistemic
reason to believe that Earl lacks.
Moran defends the assurance view from the objection from overhearers in a different
way:
while the overhearer may get a reason to believe without having the right to complaint
that is conferred on the addressee, the fact that the overhearer of the assertion acquires
any reason to believe from listening to these words is dependent on them being addressed
to someone, with the force of assuming responsibility and thereby conferring a right of
complaint . . . Without that [dependence], the question of what speech act, if any, is
235
being performed with these words would not be settled, and hence the overhearer could
not get started on assessing their epistemic significance. (Imagine overhearing someone
say The rain in Spain falls mainly on the plain. Until you know what speech act, if any
is being performed here, you don't know if considerations of reliability or trustworthiness
are even relevant to the status of the words as source of knowledge about the weather in
Spain.) So, while in both cases (promising and telling), the overhearer can gain a reason
to believe something without entering into the normative relation of promisor-promisee
or teller-believer, in the overhearing of testimony he only gains a reason to believe
something because such a relationship has been established by the original speaker and
addressee.
(Moran 2006: 296)
Here Moran maintains that the overhearer gains a non-evidential epistemic reason to
believe p in virtue of knowing that the testifier assures and the addressee accepts this
assurancein virtue of the normative, or personal, relation between the testifier and the
addresseedespite not receiving or accepting that assurance. Moran's analogy to the
utterance about Spain suggests that his argument for his position is that the overhearer
wouldn't gain an epistemic reason to believe if he or she didn't know that the testifier
assures and the addressee accepts this assurance.
A preliminary point about Moran's argument is that (in a typical case) to gain an
epistemic reason, the overhearer need know at most that the testifier assures, not that the
addressee accepts the assurance. This is indeed what Moran should say, given that (as I
argued earlier) he should hold the offer-of-benefit agreement view, not the actual
agreement view. On the offer-of-benefit view, all that is needed for the addressee to be
given an epistemic reason to believe is the testifier's assurance. So all that is needed for
the overhearer to have an epistemic reason to believe is knowing that the testifier assures.
The overhearer need not know of a personal relationship between the testifier and the
addressee. Indeed, there need be no such relationship. So far, there is no objection to the
argument. The objection comes when we see that the premise of dependency does not at
all entail the conclusion of a non-evidential epistemic reason. The overhearer's having an
evidential epistemic reason would also depend on knowing that the testifier assures. So
Moran cannot infer from a dependency to a non-evidential epistemic reason.
Moran would have to reply that the overhearer must have a non-evidential epistemic
reason because the epistemic reason the overhearer has depends on knowing that there is
assurance and not merely assertion. But, Moran must insist, if the overhearer merely has
an evidential epistemic reason, having this reason could just as well depend on knowing
that there is assertion as on knowing that there is assurance. The fact that it does depend
on knowing that there is assurance can be explained only by supposing that the epistemic
reason gained is non-evidential.
236
The claim is that a dependency on knowing that there is assurance can be explained by
supposing the reason is non-evidential, while a dependency on knowing that there is
assertion cannot be so explained. But can a dependency on knowing that there is
assurance be explained by supposing the reason is non-evidential? Suppose that (contrary
to my earlier argument) the assurance theorist is right in claiming that we can explain
how assurance gives the addressee a non-evidential epistemic reason. The explanation is
that assurance involves an offer to take epistemic responsibility that entitles the addressee
to rely on its being the case that p. But this explanation does not transfer to the
overhearer. The offer is not made to the overhearer, so confers no title in the overhearer
to rely on the testifier's taking epistemic responsibility for asserting p. So we have no
explanation of how assurance provides the overhearer with an epistemic reason, no
explanation that entails that the reason is non-evidential. Hence, we have no ground to
claim that a dependency on knowing that there is assurance can be explained by
supposing that the reason is non-evidential. Similarly, we have no ground to claim that a
dependency on knowing that there is assertion cannot be so explained. For as far as we
can now tell, when we finally obtain an explanation of how assurance provides the
overhearer with an epistemic reason, we may convert it to a parallel explanation of how
assertion provides the overhearer with an epistemic reason, and that explanation does not
suppose that the reason is non-evidential.
Perhaps the more important objection to the envisioned reply is that the overhearer's
having an epistemic reason does not depend on knowing that there is assurance as
opposed to mere assertion. It seems that an overhearer of persuasion, examination,
interrogation, and the like can acquire a reason to believe that does not differ significantly
from one acquired from assurance. Suppose you overhear someone answer another's
question, and you assume, plausibly enough, that the answerer assures the questioner.
You may well have an epistemic reason to believe the answer. Suppose you later find out
that the person was not assuring that p but rather answering an exam question. This news
would not by itself lead you to concede, Well, then, I must not have come to have an
epistemic reason from what they said. Indeed, it does not seem crucial for receiving an
epistemic reason to believe that you even have considered whether the case was one of
assurance or mere assertion in an examination. Of course, if you discovered that the
examinee was a beginning student of the subject and the question overheard was the most
difficult question on the test, you would reduce your confidence in their answer and judge
that your reason isn't as strong as you thought, though I don't think you would necessarily
have to retract your judgement that you acquired an epistemic reason. A proponent of the
assurance view might protest that what you receive in such cases is merely an evidential
reason to believe. But where is the argument that this is any more true in these cases than
in that of the overhearer of assurance?
237
CAN THE ASSURANCE VIEW ACCOUNT FOR ALL NON-EVIDENTIAL, NON-
REDUCTIVE TESTIMONIAL REASONS?
A final reservation about the assurance view is that it is incomplete given one of its
motivations: it cannot account for all non-reductive epistemic testimonial reasons if the
regress objection to reductive views of testimonial justification is successful. According
to the regress objection, reductive views are mistaken because we do not have enough
experience, or enough non-testimonially justified beliefs, on which to base all of our
testimonially justified beliefs. Some testimonially justified beliefs are therefore not based
on these non-testimonial sources of justification. The assurance view cannot explain the
justification of all of these non-reductively testimonially justified beliefs. For the
acceptance of assurance requires the recognition of assuranceor of what is involved in
it, the testifier's presentation of a reason, invitation to trust, or offer to assume epistemic
responsibility. So on the actual acceptance view, giving an epistemic reason to believe
requires actual recognition of assurance or the involved actions. And on the offer-of-
benefit view, it requires that the addressee is assumed by the testifier to be able to
recognize assurance. But according to the regress objection, we do not have enough non-
testimonially justified beliefs about intentions to afford a basis for our recognition of
testimonial intentions in all instances of testimonially justified belief. Thus, if the regress
objection establishes that there is some non-reductive testimonial justification, it also
establishes that we do not recognize assurance in all instances in which we have
testimonially justified beliefs. So it establishes that the assurance view gives an account
of only some instances of testimonially justified belief. The assurance view does not
apply to all primitive instances of testimonially justified beliefs (where primitive
instances are those in which the hearer does not already have enough non-testimonially
justified beliefs to recognize assurance). Thus, an assurance view motivated in part by the
regress argument must be supplemented with another view of testimonial justification to
cover all primitive instances.
The proponent of the assurance view might respond that there must be something wrong
with this objection to the assurance view. For on any tenable view of testimonial
justification, such justification must involve the testifier's assertion that p and the hearer's
recognition that the testifier asserts p. Yet there is just as much reason to doubt that there
is a non-testimonial basis for our recognition of assertion as for our recognition of
assurance: each requires recognition of speaker intentions and applicable norms; you
recognize that the testifier asserts p only if you recognize that the testifier has certain
communicative intentions and is governed by norms of assertion. But then the premises
of the
238
consideration against the assurance view lead to scepticism about testimonial
justification.
In reply, I find it plausible that on any tenable view testimonial justification must involve
the testifier's assertion that p, but I doubt that it must also involve the hearer's recognition
that the testifier asserts p. It is enough for the recipient to believe p because the testifier
asserts p, in a manner analogous to that in which remembering p requires only believing p
because one has believed p. Just as one can remember p without recognizing that one
once believed p, so one can believe on testimony without recognizing that the testifier
asserted p. This is borne out by the fact that much of what we believe we absorb from
the air, without noticing that anyone has asserted the relevant propositions. We can only
surmise that we hold these beliefs because others asserted these propositions. But we are
testimonially justified in these beliefs, regardless of whether we recognize that anyone
asserted them.
I don't think the assurance theorist can respond to this by proposing that on the assurance
view the hearer need only believe p because the testifier assures p, in a manner analogous
to remembering p, or knowing p now because one knew p. The story the assurance view
tells about how the testifier's presentation (or the like) gives the hearer a reason is
implausible unless it is assumed that the recipient recognizes that there is a presentation.
No reason to believe on the model of the assurance view is given if I utter p, I assure
you, but you are not in a position to accept my assurance because, for want of non-
testimonial justification, you are not in a position to recognize that I am making a
presentation. I conclude that in this regard the assurance view labours under theoretical
limitations that do not encumber other tenable non-reductive views of testimonial
justification. These views can aim at full generality where the assurance view cannot.
IF NOT ASSURANCE, THEN WHAT?
Our discussion suggests the following condition on testimonial reason-giving: testimony
that p gives the hearer an epistemic reason to believe p only if the hearer believes p
because the testifier asserts p. Call this the assertion view of testimony.43
239
On this view, testimony gives such a reason only in cases of assertion. These include not
only cases of assurance, but of persuasion, examination, linguistic training, and so on.44 A
reason is given only when the testimony is taken up in a certain way. A major burden for
the assertion view is just what sort of uptake is required for giving a reason. It would
seem not to be enough for the recipient merely to hear the testimony. But it is too strong
to require that the hearer recognizes that the testifier asserts p, as in the air cases and
primitive instances of testimonial justification show. There are several possible sources of
inspiration in looking for the right requirement. One is an analogy with what is required
for memorial reason-giving. Memory gives me an epistemic reason to believe only if I
believe because I believed, but the former belief must arise from the latter in a proper
way. Another possible source of inspiration is that a substantive condition on justification
like reliability may limit the sorts of uptake that can give rise to testimonially justified
belief and in this way render unnecessary any further constraint to rule out exceptionable
cases. But I will not pursue here the difficult question of what sort of uptake is required.45
The assertion theorist can allow that, where there is assurance, the degree of assurance is
a factor in the quality of the reason giventhat, other things equal, believing p from
assurance gives the recipient a better epistemic reason to believe p the greater the
testifier's assurance. The quality of the epistemic reason would be a function of all of the
good-making properties. Obviously, it is a major project to define this function. But the
assurance theorist who, like Moran, wishes to concede that properties other than
assurance or acceptance are good-making is burdened with the same project.
240
It is natural to think that a reason must have representational content of some kind and
that the content of a testimonially given reason must be one the hearer is in a position to
recognize (i.e. recognize as being the content of the given reason). The assurance view
has a ready answer to what the content isnamely, the testifier assures that p. It also
requires that the addressee is in a position to recognize that the testifier assures that p.
This requirement takes us close, though not all the way, to the requirement that the
addressee is in a position to recognize the content as being the content of the reason
given. One might take this approximation to the latter requirement to be an advantage of
the assurance view over the assertion view. But in fact any view that endeavours, as the
assertion view does, to cover primitive instances of testimony will have to swallow the
idea that there are instances of testimonial reason-giving in which the hearer is not in a
position to recognize what content the given reason has or that it has the content of the
given reason. One candidate for the content of a testimonial reason is the testifier asserts
p. Another, less plausible candidate is the content of some reason the testifier possesses
that favours p. But hearers are not in a position to recognize these in all instances of
testimonial reason-giving. The assertion view may well have to deny either that a reason
must have representational content or that the content of the reason must be one the
hearer is in a position to recognize. This is a cost of any account of testimonial reason-
giving that covers the primitive instances.46
There is a lingering question: if assurance isn't required to give the hearer an epistemic
reason to believe, why should even assertion be required? Lackey (2008) argues
persuasively that insincere assertion (in which the testifier does not believe p) is enough
to give testimonial knowledge. But if insincere assertion is enough to give a reason, why
shouldn't any saying that p, whether an assertion or not, also be enough? A natural
answer is that what counts as a vehicle for giving an epistemic reason is the sort of thing
that generally gives a good reason, and what generally gives a good reason is assertion.
Requiring the vehicle to be a sincere assertion is too strong because it happens often that
testifiers possess good reasons to believe what they (for social or practical reasons) assert,
even though for epistemically irrelevant reasons they do not believe those assertions.
Allowing the vehicle to be less than an assertion is too weak because it happens very
often that testifiers lack good reasons to believe what they merely say. Whether a saying
is an assertion is a fairly accessible indicator of the presence of good reasons.
None of this is to deny that assurance and its acceptance play a role in the testimonial
creation of reasons beyond what assertion plays. They generate practical reasons to trust
given the aim of trusting what is truly and responsibly
241
asserted. The generation and transmission of these reasons motivate both the testifier and
the hearer to a higher level of responsibility in assertion, testimonial uptake, and follow-
up than they would otherwise exhibit. In these ways, assurance and its acceptance
contribute to the acquisition of beliefs for which testifiers have a good epistemic reason.47
242
12 The Epistemology of Silence
Sanford C. Goldberg
1.
Consider the following two sorts of case.
CASE 1. In the course of a conversation, the issue comes up whether Jones regularly wore
a bright red suit. You think about it come to the belief that, no, he did not. You reason
that if he had regularly worn such a suit you would have seen him in it, and you can recall
nothing of the sort.
CASE 2. In the course of a conversation, the issue comes up whether weapons of mass
destruction were ever found in Iraq after the second Gulf War. You think about it and
come to the belief that no such weapons have been found to date. You reason that if they
had been found you would have heard about it by now, and you have heard nothing of the
sort.
In this chapter I aim to compare and contrast these two sorts of belief based on the
silence of a trusted source.
Let us begin with the most salient features of the comparison. In both cases two salient
points emerge immediately. First, the subject does not have any relevant confirming
memory (of having seen Jones wearing such a suit; of having been informed that WMDs
were found in Iraq). And second, the subject assumes that if the relevant proposition (that
Jones regularly wore the suit; that WMDs were found in Iraq) were true, she would have
obtained the relevant information (through perception or testimony) and would have
retained that information in memory.
There are other, perhaps less salient similarities between the cases. For one, in both cases
the proposition believed is a negation: Jones didn't regularly wear such a suit, WMDs
have not been found to date. For another, in both cases the corresponding affirmative
proposition is one regarding whose truth you might well have assigned (or have been
disposed to assign) some low probability prior to reflecting on whether you had seen or
heard about such a thing. For example, if Jones is not known for sartorial flamboyance,
the hypothesis that he regularly wore a bright red suit would get a low prior probability
(even before you reflected
243
on whether you had ever seen him in one, etc.). Or if you are deeply suspicious about
Bush's motives in starting the second Iraq war, you might well have doubted the
existence of WMDs in Iraq, even before reflecting on whether you had ever come across
a report of such. In this light, the fact of silence in the sources that are relied upon
should be seen as bearing on a proposition regarding whose truth you already have other
(indirect) evidence.
So far we have been attending to the similarities between the cases, but there are
differences too. The most obvious one concerns the identity of the information source
being relied upon. In CASE 1 you are relying upon yourself, whereas in CASE 2 you are
relying in addition on someone (or ones) other than yourself. In the latter case your
ability to identify the relevant source or sources may be quite limitedyou may only
know that some source or other would have found out about the discovery, and would
have reported itor it may be relatively informedyou may know the identity of the
CNN reporter on whom you rely for news from the Middle East, and in fact may know
quite a bit about the CNN research team as a whole. But this difference between CASE 1
and CASE 2 may not be that significant. Granted that it is only in situations like CASE 2
that the question can meaningfully arise regarding the identity of the source on whom you
are relying, even so, in many cases of this type there may be no question in your mind
regarding whom you are relying upon (you know you are relying upon the reporters of
the New York Times for your news). What is more, while it is true that in CASE 2 there
can be variability in how much the subject might know about (the reliability1 of) the
relied-upon source (you might fail to know much about the Times' methods of gathering
and disseminating that information), this might well be a similarity with CASE 1, as you
may fail to know very much about how you gathered and stored the relevant information
about Jones' clothes. To be sure, you will probably know enough in CASE 1 to say that
your methods involve perception and memory; but at this level of generality the cases
might well remain similar, since you might say in CASE 2 that the New York Times
gathers its information by placing journalists in the field, and then disseminates the
information through the publication of the daily paper (in hard copy or on the web). This
leaves open precisely how much you know about (the reliability of) these processes you
are designating as perception and memory, journalistic practices', and publication of
the daily paper.
How should an epistemic assessment of these beliefs accommodate the similarities and
differences between the individualistic case (CASE 1) and the social case (CASE 2)? In
what follows I will argue that in both cases the beliefs themselves involve the same
potential sources of unreliability,
244
and depend for their reliability on the goodness of the coverage that is provided.
2.
My ultimate aim in this chapter is to characterize the epistemic significance of the
silence of a relied-upon source, whether that source is oneself (CASE 1) or
another/others (CASE 2). To appreciate the epistemic significance of silence, however, it
will help to begin with the notion of epistemic reliance on an information source, as this
bears on cases in which an information source, far from being silent, offers a report.
Once again we can distinguish the case of self-reliancefor example, the case of having
a memory impression as of it being the case that pand cases in which the epistemic
reliance is on another subject as information sourcethe familiar case of testimony.
After examining these cases, we will then return to the cases where the source in question
is silent.
2.1.
Take the self-reliance (memory) case first. What sense does it make to say that in cases of
memory one relies on oneself qua information source? Confronted with an apparent
recollection whose content is p, one is relying on oneself in two ways. One is relying on
oneself, first, as the source of the information that p: here one relies on the reliability of
the processes through which one originally acquired the belief that p. In addition, one is
also relying on oneself as responsible for the reliable transmission of a previously
acquired belief-content: here one relies on one's memory to have succeeded in
transmittingretrieving and making available for one's present usethe very content
one previously acquired, such that one wouldn't currently have the memory impression as
of p unless one acquired that very information, p, at some earlier time. Hence we can
distinguish reliance on oneself qua source of information,2 from reliance on oneself qua
transmitter (or preserver) of information.
245
Parallel distinctions can be made in the interpersonal case, where one's reliance is on an
information source other than oneself. Here too we can distinguish two dimensions of
reliance: on the source, and on the process of content preservation (or content
transmission).3 With respect to the latter sort of reliance, the parallel rests on the idea that
we can regard proferred testimony, just as we regard apparent recollection, as serving the
role of transmitting or preserving previously acquired information. Just as it is clear that
memory (qua would-be preservative process) can fail to preserve the content of a
previously acquired belief, in a way that does not impugn the reliability of the belief on
acquisition, so too it is clear that the process by which a journalist's report is publicized
(qua would-be preservative process) can distort the report, in a way that need not reflect
poorly on the reliability of the original report.
So far I have been arguing that there are two dimensions along which we can develop the
parallel between the sort of epistemic reliance in play in memorial belief and that which
is in play in testimonial belief. In particular, both involve (i) an original source of
information (ii) whose contents are presently transmitted (made available) to the subject.
This distinction between (i) and (ii) will bear a good deal of weight in what follows.
In the case of testimony the distinction is clear enough: one's source for the information
in question is another person, and that person might or might not choose to provide her
audience with the information in question, and might or might not be reliable in the
transmission. In the memory case the distinction between (i) and (ii) may not be so clear,
but it is present. Perhaps everyone will agree that self-reliance in memory cases includes
reliance on oneself for information preservation (or what Burge (1993) calls content
preservation). In recollecting that p, the information that p is retrieved and (through the
memory impression) made available for the subject's present purposes. But self-reliance
in cases of memorially sustained belief goes beyond this, to include reliance on oneself
qua source as well. That is, one is not merely depending on oneself to have retrieved
information that one in fact had acquired earlier (one doesn't want one's memory just
making things up); one is also depending on oneself, or on one's past self, to have reliably
acquired that information right at the outset (beliefs acquired through wishful thinking,
even when successfully preserved in memory, are none the more reliable for having been
so preserved).4
I have been arguing that in both memorial belief and in testimonial belief, we can factor
the epistemic reliance involved into reliance on (i) the source of information and (ii) the
transmission process whereby information acquired at some earlier time is presently
made available to the subject. In connection with
246
(ii), however, there would appear to be several differences between the memory case and
the testimony case.
One such difference concerns the link between the message and its recipient. Clearly, the
link between the two can be severed in testimony cases: the source(s) on whom one relies
might well make a report without one's coming across that report.5 In memory cases,
however, the link would not appear to be severable: it makes little sense to say that one's
memory system has issued an apparent recollection which one oneself has failed to come
across. (One might try to make sense of this in terms of different parts of the mind/brain
failing to communicate; but as this is a matter for empirical theories of memory, not for
epistemology, I will not pursue this idea here.) However, this difference, though real,
need not impugn the parallel I have been developing between memory and testimony.
Even if it is true that there are no memory transmissions' that fail to be apprehended by
the subject herself, whereas there are testimonial transmissions' that can fail to be
apprehended by her (as when she is not near the testifying source at the time of the
testimony), still the distinction between source and transmitter remains in the memory
case. This is seen in a case in which one oneself has information stored in memory, yet
fails to be able to access it at some later time. Such cases are naturally thought to be the
analogue of the case in which a subject reliably believes that p but does not express this
belief to her audience.
A second, related difference between the nature of information transmission in memory
and testimony cases concerns intermediaries in the process of transmission. Whereas few
of us get our news straight from the horse's mouth, and so stand in need of
intermediaries in the chain of communication that links our source's testimony to us,
there are no such intermediaries in the case of memory: nothing comes between you and
your apparent recollections. Again, however, this difference does not impugn the
relevance of the distinction between (i) and (ii) for memory cases and testimony cases
alike. Rather, it merely suggests that the process of transmission in testimony cases can
be significantly more involved than it is in memory cases.
Finally, a third apparent difference along the dimension of information transmission
concerns the need for message comprehension. Whereas testimony, if it is to be useful to
a subject, must be comprehended by her, it is by no means obvious that there is any intra-
personal analogue of comprehension in cases of apparent recollection. The issue is
somewhat complicated. Suppose (for example) that at least some memories are stored via
sentential (or sentence-like)
247
vehicles. And suppose that for a public-language speaking subject the sentential vehicle
is not a sentence of mentalese but rather a sentence from one's public languagethe
sentence of the language one would use to express the content of the recalled belief. In
that case we might think that these stored sentences' require comprehension just as much
as do pieces of testimony. Indeed, Burge 1999 appears to suggest a variation on this
theme:
Comprehending standing, conceptual aspects of one's own thought and idiolect is itself,
as a matter of psychological and sociological fact, normally dependent on having
comprehended thoughts (one's own) that were shaped and expressed by the words of
others. (Burge 1999: 243)
(What is interesting here is Burge's use of comprehension and its cognates, in
connection with one's own thoughts.) The matter is vexed, however, and I would not
want to put too much weight on this aspect of the alleged analogy between memory and
testimony. But once again it is worth pointing out that even if memory is disanalogous
from testimony on this score, in that memory does not involve any comprehension of a
message, this need not undermine the claim that the epistemic reliance involved in both
memory and testimony can be factored into reliance on (i) and on (ii). All that it would
suggest is that the process of transmission differs between the two cases.
In sum, even if all of these alleged differences between memory and testimony are
conceded to be actual differences, such a concession would only establish that the process
of content transmission is more complicated (and allows for more distinctive kinds of
error possibility) in the case of testimony. These differences in question are not
sufficiently great to call into question the parallel between memory and testimony, nor
are they sufficiently great to undermine the claim that in both types of case epistemic
reliance can be factored into (i) and (ii). What is more, we might even think that whatever
differences there are between testimony and memory in the above respects are to be
expected, given the differences between intra-personal and interpersonal processes of
information transmission. For it would seem that all three of the recently-noted
differences flow from the difference between a system's retrieval of information that is
already stored within the system itself, and a system's reception of information proffered
by some source other than the system itself. The latter sort of case involves the
possibilities of missing the message altogether, of the utility of communication chains
involving intermediaries, and of the need to decipher and re-encode the message once
it is received. These differences would thus appear to point to two distinct species (intra-
personal and interpersonal) of a single underlying genus (information transmission).
2.2.
So far we have been considering epistemic reliance in cases in which a subject receives a
transmission from an information source. But what should be said
248
of epistemic reliance in cases in which a relied-upon source is silent? These would appear
to be importantly unlike the standard cases in the epistemology of memorial or
testimonial belief: arguably, the lack of a memory impression, or of a report, should not
itself be thought of as something that the source in question presents'.
This initial difference would appear to make an epistemic difference. For while the fact
that you have an apparent recollection to the effect that p, or that you have observed a
report to the effect that p, might (together with whatever justifies you in accepting the
presentation-as-true) ground a justification for your sustaining or acquiring the belief
that p, it is not clear how the fact that you have no apparent recollection to the effect that
p, or that you have not observed a report to the effect that p, might (together with other
things) ground a justification for your acquiring a belief in p. After all, a popular
(though not universally endorsed) claim among people working on testimony is that,
when successful, testimony affects a transmission of epistemic status, from the testimony,
to the hearer (or the hearer's belief). Since no such transmission is affected in cases in
which there is no testimony (or other sort of report) in the first place, it is not
immediately clear how to account for the epistemology of silence.6
The issue before us, then, is this: how (if at all) does the epistemic status of a hearer's
belief depend on the epistemic perspective of those on whom she is epistemically relying,
in those cases in which her sources are silent? This issue can be helpfully framed by
comparing two subjunctive conditionals, one that (I will suggest) lies at the heart of the
epistemology of testimony (and memory), and the other that lies at the heart of the
epistemology of silence (whether the relied-upon information source is oneself or
another).7
Take first the testimony and memory cases. In these cases the relevant source does
(purport to) transmit information. In order to have a single expression covering the sort of
transmission involved in both, it will be helpful to follow Burge (1993) and use
presentation-as-true and its cognates as the general term covering the positive
deliverances of a source. (The idea, then, is that both memory-impressions and
attestations/reports are species of the single genus presentation-as-true.) Here the
conditional relevant to assessing the epistemic status of a subject's belief, formed through
accepting the presentation-as-true in question, is what we might call the presentation-to-
truth conditional:
(1) If source were to present-as-true that p, then it would be the case that p.
(As stated, (1) is a bit awkward. More intuitively, the claim is this: would present-as-
true that p only if it were the case that p.) If the case is one of memory, then is oneself,
and the presentation-as-true takes the form of a
249
seeming recollection (or memory impression); whereas if the case is one of testimony,
then is the (news) source on whom (or on which) one relies for information of this kind,
and the presentation-as-true takes the form of a piece of testimony.
The role of (1) in the epistemology of memorial or testimonial belief is best seen as a
claim exploited by the epistemologist in determining the reliability of a given
presentation-as-true. In saying that (1) is a claim exploited by the epistemologist, I mean
that it is not something that needs to be entertained by the subject herself in the course of
memorial or testimonial belief-fixation. It is arguable that the truth of (1), together with a
hearer's counterfactual sensitivity to indications that (1) is false, suffice to render a
(memorial or) testimonial belief justified. The subject who acquires such a belief need not
draw any inferences from premises like (1), nor even so much as have (1) in mind in the
process of memorial or testimonial belief-fixation.8
Let us move on to the silence cases.9 These differ both in the subjunctive conditional
involved, and in the role that the relevant subjunctive conditional plays in the
epistemology of silence. Begin with the conditional involved. Whereas the relevant
conditional in cases involving a presentation-as-true is the presentation-to-truth
conditional, (1), in cases of silence, the relevant conditional is one that we might call the
truth-to-presentation conditional:
(2) If it were the case that p, then some source would present-as-true that p.
(2) captures the idea that there is relevant coverage in the domain in question: all
relevant truths will be presented as such.10 This is what lies behind the reasoning one
exhibits when, on the basis of not recalling having seen Jones wear a bright red suit, one
concludes that he did not regularly wear any such suit; or when, on the basis of not
recalling having come across any report of the discovery of WMDs in Iraq, one
concludes that there has been no such discovery to date. Of course, it is not (2), so much
as one of (2)s implications, that is used in our reasoning in such cases. The relevant
implication is this:
(2*) If no source has presented-as-true that p, then p.
250
In what follows my claim will be that what I am calling the epistemology of silence is
best explored by examining the epistemic status of (2*), and in particular, by exploring
the epistemic grounds one may have for endorsing a conditional of this sort.
Not only do silence cases differ from the presentation cases in the conditional that is
involved in epistemic assessment; the role that the conditional plays in the epistemology
of the resulting belief differs as well. In particular, whereas (1) is a claim used by the
epistemologist during assessment (and need not be exploited by the subject who comes to
acquire the belief in question), the relevant instance of (2*) itself would appear to figure
in the very process by which a silence-supported belief is formed by the subjectat least
if that process is to be a reliable one. To see this, consider the difference between having
evidence for p , and lacking evidence for p .11 Without introducing further
qualifications, it would be false to say that a lack of evidence for p is evidence for p
. So insofar as one's belief in p is acquired through one's recognition of a lack of
relevant evidence for p , the epistemic goodness of one's belief in p would appear to
depend on how reliable an indication of p it is, when one lacks evidence for p .
What is more, it would seem that without background beliefs to justify the hypothesis
that the lack of evidence for p is a reliable indication that p, a subject who formed her
belief in p merely on the grounds of recognizing the evidential lack for p will have
formed an unjustified belief. This is so whether one's theory of justification is reliabilist
or more internalist and reasons-based. If one is a reliabilist, then the belief in question is
unjustified because unreliably formed; whereas if one is more internalist, then the belief
is unjustified since grounded in an inference from ignorance (which is a fallacious
inference-type).
Under what conditions, then, might a silence-supported belief enjoy a doxastic
justification? To some extent, our answer depends on our favoured theory of justification.
If one is a reliabilist, reliability in the formation of such a belief would appear to require
having inferred the belief in p in a conditionally reliable way from a reliably-formed
belief in the relevant instance of (2*). If one regards justification as a matter of good
reasons, one will regard silence-supported beliefs as justified only if the subject has good
reasons for regarding the relevant state of ignorance as indicative of the truth of what she
believes. But whatever one's favoured theory of justification, we can now see that the
acquisition of a silence-supported belief that p is best seen as a kind of inference from
ignorance; and so the role of (2*) in this process is that of the key premise in the
inference from which the subject herself draws the conclusion that p. Insofar as the
subject formed her belief that p in this way, this belief is justified only if she is justified
in believing the relevant instance of (2*). We have reduced
251
the epistemology of silence to the question, What does it take to be justified in believing
the relevant instance of (2*)? I propose to return to address this matter below.
3.
Let us first ask after the truth-likeliness of a belief formed on the basis of the silence of a
relied-upon source of information: how likely is it that a belief of this sort will be true?
And let us deal first with the case where the relied-upon source is oneself, and the
silence is that of one's lacking any relevant memory (CASE 1). As anticipated above (in
our discussion of the sources of possible error in these beliefs), two main factors are
relevant to the truth-likeliness of these beliefs: (a) the coverage-reliability of oneself qua
information source, and (b) the preservation-reliability of one's memory.
Coverage-reliability supervenes on considerations bearing on the subjunctive conditional
corresponding to (2) above, as follows12 :
(S-M) If it were the case that p, subject S would have found out that p.
The idea is that one can rely on oneself for coverage of the relevant facts in the domain in
question. Let us say that a p -world w enjoys coverage by subject S with respect to p
at time t when in w S finds out that p at some point at or before t. And call a set of p -
worlds clean at t relative to S when all of the worlds in the set are such that each enjoys
coverage by S at t regarding p , i.e. none of them are such that by t S does not find out
that p. Then we can characterize a source's coverage-reliability in a rough but intuitive
way in terms of nearby p -worlds. The broader the circle of worlds (with the actual
world at centre) that are clean at t relative to the source, the more coverage-reliable that
source is regarding p . Of course the temporal dimension is also relevant here: if one's
source finds out that p long after the time by which the subject needed to know whether
p, then such knowledge, even when it is presented to the subject by the source, will be of
little or no help. So we might want to restrict t to the latest time at which possession of
the knowledge in question by the subject would satisfy the relevant practical and
theoretical aims bound up with her interest in p . A source who is coverage-reliable in
this sense will be such that for most or all of the propositions in some domain of interest
to the subject, were true the source would know this, and she would present this
knowledge on time to help the subject in whatever aims were bound up with the
subject's interests in
252
the matter. Clearly, to the extent that a source is not coverage-reliable, to that extent the
source's failure to discover that p is a less reliable indication that p. To just this extent,
the beliefs one forms on the basis of the silence of that source will not enjoy a high
truth-likeliness quotientwith the result that it will be increasingly a matter of luck if
one's current silence-based belief turns out to be true.
Of course, the truth-likeliness of one's silence-based belief also depends on how well
one's memory preserves (the contents of) one's beliefs. The point can be put in terms of
another conditional:
(P-M) If (i) at some earlier point S acquired the belief that p, (ii) in the interim S acquires
no relevant information bearing on whether p, then if presently S were to be queried
regarding whether p, S would have the memory impression that p.
A subject's memory may fail to be good in this regard in at least two distinct ways. There
is straight forgetfulness, in which (although at some earlier point S had acquired the
belief that p) memory fails to retain that belief. And there are failures of content
preservation, where (although at some earlier point S had acquired the belief that p) what
is preserved in connection with that belief is a content distinct from p .13 Either way, as
one's memory fails to preserve one's original beliefs (rendering (P-M) false), one
increases the risk of error in a silence-based belief. This is easiest to see in cases of
straight forgetfulness. Here it should be clear that the more straightforwardly forgetful a
subject is, the less her having no recollection of p (when queried) correlates with the
falsity of p (= the truth of p ). Arguably, a similar point holds in cases involving the
failure of content preservation. Here it can happen that the subject (when queried) has no
recollection of it being the case that p, under conditions in which she originally acquired
the belief that p: her memory shifted the content of her original belief from p to
(logically distinct) q , and her current memory-sustained belief that q failed to trigger
the recollection that p.14 Once
253
again, a subject whose memory exhibits this sort of failure is a subject facing an
increased risk of falsity in her silence-supported beliefs.
It is clear that these same points hold in the interpersonal case, when the subject relies on
the coverage-reliability of some source other than herself (CASE 2). Here coverage-
reliability depends on the interpersonal analogue of the subjunctive conditional (S-M), as
in the following:
(S-T) If it were the case that p, one of the sources on whom S relies would have found out
that p.15
Suppose our subject forms the silence-supported belief that p, under conditions in
which (S-T) is false. Then her silence-supported belief is exposed to an increased risk of
falsity: even assuming that her failure to recall having been told that p accurately reflects
that her sources did not in fact report or publicize that p, her silence-supported belief that
p is not properly sensitive, since the failure of her sources to report/publicize that p
reflects a failure on their part to have discovered that p (as when the fact that p has been
successfully covered up by the relevant authorities).16 Alternatively, the truth-likeliness
of one's silence-supported belief is decreased under conditions involving unreliability in
the transmission of the message from source to subject. In these cases the following
subjunctive conditional (corresponding to (P-M) in the memory case) would be false:
(P-T) If the source(s) on whom S relies had acquired the information that p, they would
have reported or publicized that p, in such a way that S would have come across the
transmission (or something that stood in a reliable communication-relation to that
transmission, and which preserved its content).
Even on the assumption that one's source(s) is/are coverage-reliable in the sense of (S-T),
S's silence-supported beliefs (formed through relying on said source(s)) will have an
increase in the likelihood of falsity if said source(s) doesn't/don't reliably transmit the
information in question. For in that case, even assuming one's failure to recall having
been told that p accurately reflects that one's sources did not in fact report or publicize
that p, even so, one's silence-supported belief that p is not properly sensitive, since the
failure of one's sources to report/publicize that p reflects a failure on their part to have
reported what they had, in fact, discovered.
In the light of the foregoing considerations about the reliability of silence-supported
belief, we can now explicitly address the question regarding the conditions on the
doxastic justification of such beliefs. Insofar as the subject
254
formed her belief that p by inference from the relevant instance of (2*), her belief is
justified only if she is justified in believing that the relevant instance of (2*) holds. This
does not require the truth of that instance of (2*), so much as it requires whatever is
necessary and sufficient for justified belief in (what is expressed by) the relevant instance
of (2*). Assuming a reliabilist theory of justification, this will require that the process or
method through which a hearer arrived at her belief in the relevant instance of (2*) is
globally reliable.
Under what conditions would one count as globally reliable in the formation of the belief
that
(2*) If no source has presented-as-true that p, then p?
Although it might be too much to ask for necessary and sufficient conditions on the
reliable formation of such a belief, perhaps we can be satisfied here with sufficient
conditions. A subject S reliably forms a belief in (2*) so long as S's own relevant
expectations for the news are well calibrated to the sorts of news reports that are
prevalent in her community.17 Other accounts of justification, of course, may demand
other things of her in order for her belief in (2*) to be justified. But whatever one's
favoured theory of justification, the point remains: whereas our subject cannot acquire
silence-supported knowledge unless (2*) is true, doxastic justification in these cases does
not require the truth of (2*) so much as it requires that the subject's belief in (2*) be
justified.18 Insofar as testimonial belief does not require that the subject have any belief in
the presentation-to-truth conditional (1) (let alone that such a belief be justified),19
testimonial belief and silence-supported belief receive different epistemological
treatments in this respect.
4.
Parallels between testimony and memory have been profitably explored elsewhere.20 It is
popular to assimilate the two by treating one on the model of the other, for example, by
thinking of memory as a matter of one's past self testifying to one's present self.
Though I have touched on this, the plausibility of such an assimilation has not been
defended here. My claim, rather, has been that there is another dimension to this
assimilationone not often described by those who liken memory and testimonyand
that this dimension is one that brings
255
out in a particularly vivid way another form taken by our epistemic reliance on our social
peers. In this connection I have been stressing the similarities between beliefs in p
formed through noting that one does not remember having observed otherwise, and
beliefs in p formed through noting that one does not remember having heard
otherwise. With this comparison in mind, we might wonder whether the epistemology of
silence-supported belief, in those cases involving our reliance on sources other than
ourselves, is fruitfully thought of as the epistemology of socially extended memory.
I begin with the least controversial of the claims that can be made on this score (which is
not to say that the claim is uncontroversial!). Epistemology of silence cases involving
reliance on sources other than oneself illustrate the following hypothesis in social
epistemology: there are occasions on which the epistemic assessment of (the cognitive
states of) a given individual will be incomplete without taking into account the
dispositions and cognitive states of the individuals' social peers. The illustrating cases are
those in which the members of the individual's community play a role akin to that of a
perceptual and memory system: they acquire information from the world through
perception, they store this information, and they transmit this information in such a way
as to enable its subsequent retrieval by the subject. It is clear that cases in which the
subject's peers play these roles are importantly different, and in many ways, from cases in
which only her own perceptual and memory systems are in play. Even so, for at least
some of a subject's beliefs, if we are to give an accurate assessment of the epistemic
status of these beliefs, then the (perception- and memory-like) roles played by the
subject's peers must be taken into account, in a way that is analogous to the way that we
take into account the performance of her own perceptual and memory systems, in cases
where she relies on these. I call this the Thesis.
If we endorse a broadly reliabilist approach to epistemology, then the Thesis is true.21
Suppose that you are not particularly attentive to the way people dress, and that you do
not find anything noteworthy in what others would regard as outrageous attire. So, had it
been true that Jones regularly wore a bright red suit, even so you would not have attended
to (or registered) this fact. Were you then to form the belief that Jones did not regularly
wear a bright red suit, on the basis of the fact that you can recall having seen no such
thing, your belief would not be reliable. On the contrary, the lack of coverage-reliability
of your perceptual system in the relevant domain translates into a lack of reliability in the
belief you form through reliance on that coverage-reliability.
Consider now the case involving epistemic reliance on the coverage provided by one's
community. The less coverage-reliable are the individuals on whom one is relying
(relative to the domain of facts in question), the less reliable will be
256
any silence-supported belief formed through reliance on the coverage-reliability of these
peers. Suppose that neither the New York Times nor CNN nor any of the other media
sources on whom you rely for the news is particularly attentive to what is going on in
Iraq.22 We can suppose, contrary to the facts, that without publicizing this fact the media
have left Iraq after deciding not to put any resources into reporting from there any more,
and after deciding not to get any reports from others (such as the Associated Press) who
remain there. So, had it been true that WMDs were found in Iraq last week, even so they
would not have attended to (or registered) this fact. Were you then to form the belief that
WMDs have not been found to date in Iraq, on the basis of the fact that you cannot recall
having come across any report of such a finding, your belief would not be reliable. On the
contrary, the lack of coverage-reliability of your sources in the relevant domain translates
into a lack of reliability in the belief you form through reliance on those sources for
coverage.
The point common to both cases would appear patent: the epistemic significance of
silencethe epistemic significance of the fact that you recall no source having
presented p as trueis in direct proportion to the quality of coverage by, and
transmission through, the source on whom you are relying. This is as true when that
source is someone other than yourselfas in the case of coverage by members of news
organizations, where p (were it presented at all) would be presented via testimony
as when it is you yourselfthat is, in memory cases, where p (were it presented at
all) would be presented through a memory impression. As we saw above, in both sorts of
case the main threat of unreliability in the silence-supported belief can be decomposed
into the threats of (a) unreliability in the coverage (= failure to satisfy the truth-to-
presentation conditional, (2)), and (b) unreliability in the transmission of the source's
information (= failure to satisfy one or both of the transmission conditionals (P-M) and
(P-T)). Admittedly, in cases involving reliance on the coverage provided by someone
other than one oneself, cases are complicated by the fact that, in addition to one's source
having to satisfy the transmission conditional (P-T), one must currently be reliable in
one's judgement that one did not encounter any such report in the past. But this only
suggests that the case of relying on another, in addition to having the same features as
cases involving reliance on oneself, has other features besides. This should come as no
surprise: self-trust appears to be a basic form of trust.23
Might we then make the stronger claim, that silence-supported beliefs formed through
reliance on the coverage-reliability of others is akin to a case of extended
257
memory? In defence of this idea, we might try comparing the role of others as
repositories of information with the role of what might be called personal mental
prosthetics (diaries and notebooks).24 The core contention of Clark and Chalmers (1998)
is that a diary could count as a case of extended memory so long as (a) it stores
information that one has acquired and information about plans for the future that one has
put into it, and (b) this information stored there is readily accessible to the subject.25
Those philosophers convinced by the case from Clark and Chalmers (1998) might try
seeing the role other people play in a subject's acquisition of a silence-supported belief as
that of a repository of information for the subject, a sort of social version of the
extended memory hypothesis.
Unfortunately, the extended memory proposal runs into difficulties with respect to both
(a) and (b). It runs into difficulties with respect to (a), in that other people are not
repositories for information that one oneself has put in those repositories.26 Of course it
might be replied that the assumption, that memory storage is storage of information that
one oneself has put into the relevant repository, is question-begging against the proposal
of a socially extended form of memory. Perhaps a better way of thinking of a subject's
memorial storage is as a repository of information that she can exploit in the course of her
belief-fixation and belief-revision. So long as information is stored in a repository in such
a way that the information is sufficiently accessible to her, and in particular is accessible
as needed for belief-formation and belief-revision, one's peers might constitute such a
repository (at least by the standards of Clark and Chalmers 1998). Or so it might be
argued.
But this brings us to the problems that the extended memory proposal faces regarding
(b): it would seem that the information in the minds of those on whom one is relying for
coverage is not sufficiently accessible to one. In this respect it is worth bearing in mind
that there is one important feature of the silence case involving reliance on others for
coverage: the subject does not have access to the information stored in others' minds, but
instead merely notes that she (the subject) cannot recall having received a relevant report
from any of them. The result is that if we regard them as storing information for the
subject, this is information that will forever be inaccessible to her (unless she can read
their minds or they testify to her). It thus seems that we do not properly regard
information stored in others' minds as relevantly accessible to the subject herself.
258
The considerations just advanced suggest that the case has not been made for regarding
our reliance on others for coverage on the model of a socially extended memory. Still,
we must find some way to acknowledge the role that others play in the epistemology of
silence-supported beliefs. If it is not by way of assimilating their role into that of an
extended sort of memory, how should we characterize this role?
Here is a proposal that I favour. (I offer this in the spirit of a suggestion that is worth
developing further.) We begin by noting that, in cases where a subject is assuming the
coverage of others, reliable silence-supported belief is not the cognitive achievement of
any single individual. We then go on to hold that the relevant social facts that underwrite
the reliability of a given silence-supported beliefthe social facts that ensure that the
subject has reliable coverage in the case at handare all-important background
conditions on the formation of silence-supported belief. In particular, it is against these
conditions that we assess the epistemic features of silence-supported beliefs. There is in
this way a kind of division of epistemic labour. The subject herself must be justified in
believingmust have reliably acquired a beliefin the relevant instance of (2*). This is
a matter of her news expectations being properly calibrated to the relevant news-
dissemination practices in her community. But whether or not she is properly calibrated
in this way, whatever the prevalent news-dissemination practices in her community
happen to be, it is against the background of such practices that we assess the reliability
of her belief in (2*), as well as the reliability of her silence-supported belief (inferred
from her belief in (2*)). This sort of view thus regards the cognitive achievement of
silence-supported knowledge and justified belief (in cases where the relevant coverage is
assumed to be provided by others) to be an achievement that is made possible by the
existence of certain social arrangements, even as it denies that we should regard those
arrangements as constituting anything like a socially distributed memory system.
It is worth noting that the proposal to regard social factors in this way is thoroughly in
keeping with the spirit of reliabilist epistemology. After all, reliabilists have long
assessed the reliability of a belief-forming process against what Hilary Kornblith calls
the natural environment in which [the process itself] operate[s]. Here is Kornblith's
extended comment, made in connection with social factors:
Just as we wish to know whether our natural inferential tendencies are likely to give us an
accurate or a distorted picture of the world, we also need to know whether our social
institutions and practices are helping to inform us or to misinform us. And just as we
need to examine our perceptual and inferential equipment against the background of the
natural environment in which they operate, we also need to investigate these mechanisms
against the background of the social environment in which they operate. Such
investigations are straightforward extensions of the naturalistic project in epistemology.
(Kornblith 1994b: 97, italics added)
259
Since Kornblith makes this point in a paper which is otherwise advocating a
conservative extension of naturalistic epistemology (1994b: 94, italics added), it seems
that the present proposal should be relatively uncontroversial to anyone who is already on
board with reliabilist epistemology.
No doubt, there is great variation in social practices and institutions worldwide, and even
between local communities there can be relevant differences. But this fact of social
variation is no objection to the proposal to regard the relevant social conditions as
background conditions on silence-supported belief. For one thing, social variation itself is
a normal feature of our larger world-environment. For another, it is a normal part of
socialization within a community that one becomes sensitive to prevailing social
arrangements. Included in this socialization process is the process of learning what counts
around here as newsworthy, what sorts of news one can expect (and where and when one
can expect this news), and so forth.27 Acknowledging all of this merely forces us to
acknowledge that the background conditions that obtain in any given case depend on the
community in play.
In short: it may be too much to regard silence-supported belief, where one is relying on
others for coverage, as involving a kind of socially extended memory. At the same time,
we can recognize the all-important role that a subject's peers play in ensuring the
reliability of her silence-supported belief in another way: we can think of the relevant
social practices as part of the background conditions on the process(es) used in the
formation of silence-supported belief.
5.
The epistemic significance of the silence of a relied-upon source of information is in
many respects the same, whether that source is oneself (as in memory cases) or members
of one's social community (as in cases of coverage-reliance on a news organization). To
say this is to encourage the parallel between memory and testimony, in ways that go
beyond the standard parallels. It is also to encourage novel thinking about testimony
itself. In addition to relying on what others tell us, we also rely on what they do not: their
silence can back our claims to know, and in any case brings to the fore our reliance on
them for coverage. I submit that the phenomena of coverage and silence-supported belief
go alongside
260
that involving actual testimony, as manifesting distinct varieties of our epistemic reliance
on our social peers.28
261
13 Epistemic Circularity and Epistemic Incommensurability
Michael P. Lynch
1. INTRODUCTION
If I were to believe you are trustworthy just on your say-so, my reasoning would be
infected with what is called epistemic circularity. I would be supposing a source is
trustworthy by relying on that very source. Generally speaking, we tend to think this is a
very bad idea. It is why we don't bother asking politicians or salesmen whether they are
honest.
A well-known line of reasoning stemming from the Ancientswhat we might call the
criterion argumentclaims that epistemic circularity leads to radical scepticism. Baron
Reed has recently put the point this way:
Let F1, F2, F3, etc., be a subject S's cognitive faculties, of which S has a finite number. In
order to know that F1 is a reliable source of knowledge, S will have to use either F1, or
another faculty. But if S uses F1 his belief that F1 is reliable will be epistemically circular.
So, S must instead use (say) F2. But S should not use F2 unless she knows that it is a
reliable source of knowledge itself. In order to come to know this, S will have to use F1,
F2, or some other faculty. But S cannot use F2, on pain of epistemic circularity. And S
cannot use F1, without first knowing that it is a reliable source of knowledge, which is
still in question. So, S must use some other source-say, F3. But it should be clear that the
same issues will arise with respect to F3, and that S will eventually run out of faculties to
which she has not already appealed. Epistemic circularity is inescapable.
(Reed 2006: 1867)
The invited conclusion: we don't know whether our faculties or sources of belief are
reliable. And if we don't know that, then, according to the sceptic, those same sources
cannot be sources of knowledgethat is, they cannot produce justified beliefs.
Consequently, says the sceptic, I don'tand perhaps can'tknow anything.
262
The criterion argument is disarming in its simplicity. But it is open to an equally simple
response grounded in epistemic externalism.1 The externalist rejects the key assumption
of the argumentnamely, that one must first know that a source of belief is reliable
before it can be said to produce knowledge. From the externalist's viewpoint, all that
matters is whether the source is reliable, not whether we know or even believe that it is.
As long as the source is in fact reliable, it can produce knowledge, including knowledge
about whether it, or some other source, is reliable. Epistemic circularity may be
pervasive, says the externalist, but it doesn't prevent us from having knowledge or
justified belief.
The externalist response to the problem of the criterion continues to be the subject of a
wide-ranging controversy.2 One thought is that far from providing an easy victory of
scepticism, the externalists' response only reveals the inadequacy of their view, by
demonstrating that knowledge is too easy to come by if externalism is correct.3 To some,
the if my sources of belief are reliable, then I can know they are response simply shows
that the externalist is missing the point, or talking past the sceptic, or somehow not
addressing the original issue.
Despite these doubts, I'm going to assume for present purposes that some version of the
externalist response succeeds in answering the criterion argument. My reasoning, such as
it is, is that it is difficult to see how that argument could be answered without relying on
such a response. Nonetheless, I also think that there is something right about our
misgivings about the externalist answer to the criterion argument. What is right about
those misgivings is that the externalist response has no traction against a different
problem, distinct from scepticism. Like the sceptical argument above, this other problem
is rooted in part in the issue of epistemic circularity. But unlike its cousin, it is not a
problem about whether we in fact have knowledge or are justified in our opinions. It is
about rationally resolving explicit disagreement over the reliability of our most basic
methods for forming beliefs. Although I will not try to show it here, this latter problem,
what I will call the problem of epistemic incommensurability, is arguably the root worry
behind the criterion argument, and, in my view, the reason why Chisholm was right to
say that the latter was one of the most important and difficult of all problems of
philosophy (1982: 61).
The bulk of this chapter will be concerned with clarifying the problem and its nature. In
the final section, I briefly sketch a solution.
263
2. EPISTEMIC INCOMMENSURABILITY
Cain and Abel, let's imagine, are having coffee and arguing about the age of the Earth.
Abel asserts with great confidence that the earth is a mere 7,000 years old. Cain, amazed,
points out that Abel's claim is not justified by the evidence of the fossil record, the best
explanation of which is that the Earth is far older. Inference to the best explanation from
the fossil and historical record can work sometimes' Abel concedes, but the best method
for knowing about the distant past is to consult the Holy Book; it overrides any other
competing evidence. Cain scoffs and rejects the book as an unreliable source for
knowing about the distant past; the only reliable method, he insists, is to employ a
combination of abduction and induction from the fossil and historical record.
As this toy example indicates, disagreements usually start with a disagreement over the
facts. But disagreement over facts often turn into disagreement over whose view of those
facts is best supported or justified. And sometimes we move still further up what we
might call the epistemic ladder: we begin to disagree over how we ought to support our
views of the facts, about the sort of evidence that should be admitted, and whose methods
more accurately track the truth. When we do that, we are engaged in a truly epistemic
disagreement: a disagreement over epistemic principles.
By an epistemic principle, I mean a normative principle to the effect that some source or
way of forming beliefs has some valuable epistemic status. The valuable epistemic status
I'll be discussing here is reliability. So we might say that an epistemic principle is one
that says that some doxastic practice or method is reliable. The reason reliability is
valuable is that reliable doxastic methods are those that are likely to produce true beliefs.
And having true beliefs, I'll assume for present purposes, is a good; it is what we might
call a, or even the, epistemic goal.4
Doxastic methods are more or less basic. A less basic method would be a blood test, since
the reliability of that test would presumably be justified by employing other methods.
Plausible candidates for basic methods, on the other hand, include inferential methods
like deduction or induction and non-inferential methods, like sense perception. It is hard
to see how these sorts of methods could be justified solely by appeal to any other method.
Consider just one case: induction. If Hume was right, there isn't much hope in justifying
the reliability of inductive inference without relying at some point on induction to do so.
But I will not quibble here about examples. It seems likely that there are basic epistemic
methods, and I will assume that there are. Let's say an epistemic principle is fundamental
when it is about such a method and derivative when it is not.
264
Belief-forming methods, whether basic or not, are more or less restricted in applicability.
Deduction is clearly of wide scopesince deductive inference from true premises, if it is
reliable, is reliable for forming beliefs of any sort. Not so with sense perceptionsense
perception is not a reliable means for forming beliefs about mathematics. It is, broadly
speaking, applicable to ascertaining the contingent facts about the external world. Still
more restricted are Cain and Able's principles: both assert the reliability of methods with
regard to a single domain of factsfacts about the distant past.
Let us say that A disagrees with B over some epistemic principle just when A does not
believe EP and B does. Thus one disagrees with someone over an EP in this sense when
one either disbelieves the EP or withholds belief in it (e.g. when one doubts that it is
true). A overtly disagrees with B over some EP just when A explicitly withholds assent
from an EP B asserts. The paradigm case of overt epistemic disagreement is where assent
is withheld because the relevant EP is simply denied. An overt epistemic disagreement is
mutual just when both sides to the dispute deny an epistemic principle the other asserts.
Overt mutual epistemic disagreement can be deep or shallow. I'll say a disagreement is
deep when it meets the following conditions:
1. Commonality: The parties to the disagreement share common epistemic goal(s).
2. Competition: If the parties affirm distinct principles with regard to a given domain,
1. Commonality: The parties to the disagreement share common epistemic goal(s).
those principles (a) pronounce different methods to be the most reliable in a given
domain; and (b) these methods are capable of producing incompatible beliefs about
that domain.
3. Non-arbitration: There is no further epistemic principle, accepted by both parties,
which would settle the disagreement.
4. Mutual Circularity: The epistemic principle(s) in question can be justified only by
means of an epistemically circular argument.
By these criteria, most epistemic disagreements will not be deep. In most cases where my
methods of belief formation are questioned, Non-arbitration, and hence Mutual
Circularity failas might happen when one doctor questions another about the reliability
of a given test, and the dispute is settled by appeal to other more basic methods. In other
cases, subsequent investigation may reveal that the methods in question do not really
competeperhaps because one is more restricted in application than another. Finally, in
some cases, the disputants are simply talking past one anotherone is aiming at truth, for
example, the other at practical success or some such.
Nonetheless, it seems pretty clear that deep epistemic disagreements can and do occur.
Cain and Abel's dispute seems a likely example. The two principles involved, again, are:
265
C: Inference to the best explanation of the historical and fossil record is the most reliable
method for knowing about the distant past.
A: Reading the Holy Book is the most reliable method for knowing about the distant
past.
We can easily imagine that Cain and Abel share the same goalto ascertain the truth
about the distant past of the planet. Moreover, their principles compete. Both practices
cannot be the best for determining what is true of the distant past. And assuming that
neither thinks that time travel is an option, there appears to be no shared principle that
will settle the matter either.
The case plausibly satisfies Mutual Circularity as well. In Cain's case, it is hard to see
how he could avoid appealing to a track record argument to justify the reliability of his
method. And it is equally hard to see how he could avoid assuming the reliability of that
method in accepting the premises of such an argument. For there seems to be no other
means (that Cain would accept) which can serve as a check on whether our abductions
about the past are accurate. In Abel's case, we can imagine that the circularity might
manifest itself in a very different way. He might, for example, give the following
argument for his trust in the Holy Book's pronouncements about the past:
God wrote the Holy Book in the distant past.
Everything God wrote in the Holy Book is true.
Therefore the Holy Book is the most reliable guide to the distant past.
Suppose that we ask Abel why he is committed to the first premise, and he responds that
the book says that God wrote it. Since this is a belief about the past, it assumes the
reliability of the book as a guide to the truth about the past. Abel's argument is not
premise-circular: the conclusion is not literally one of the premises of the argument, but it
is epistemically circularit assumes the reliability of a method in an attempt to show that
the method is reliable.
Some will wonder if there is an asymmetry to the cases Cain and Abel can make for their
epistemic principles. One might think that Cain, but not Abel, will be able to
independently confirm the reliability of his method. In fact, however, both Cain and Abel
can offer independently confirming arguments. But any such argument will either be
itself epistemically circular or push the disagreement back to the applicability of a
different fundamental epistemic principle.
Take Cain first. First, recall that the issue in question is whether abduction from the fossil
record is the best method for learning about the distant past. Unless time travel is an
option, direct confirmation of the reliability of this method by observation is not an
option. That is, we can't check to see whether the method has produced accurate results
by direct observation. This fact is part of what will make any track-record argument for
the reliability of the method epistemically circular. Moreover, even if Cain were to appeal
to certain non-inferential methods (such as sense perception) to indirectly bolster the case
for
266
the reliability of abduction from the fossil record, these methods can themselves be
challenged. And as we've already noted, a defence of the reliability of sense perception,
the most likely candidate in Cain's case, will most probably itself be subject to epistemic
circularity.5 As Alston and many others have argued, it is hard to see how we could show
that sense perception is reliable without relying on its reliability. And presumably it will
not help Cain to protest that his favoured method is merely a local application of a more
general reliable method: abduction. For in the imagined case, Abel does not deny the
reliability of that method. What he denies is that abduction from the fossil record is the
most reliable method for forming beliefs about the distant past.
In addition, note that Abel too might well try to give some independent argument, in
addition to the one I've given above, in defence of his principle, one that does not rely on
what the book says. He might appeal to the teaching of various prophets, or other sacred
texts. Cain will question the reliability of these sources. So Abel might appeal to still
more basic, non-inferential methods of belief formation, such as divine revelation or
mystical perception of God's actions and will. But here again the question can (and
presumably will) be raised about the reliability of such methods. As in Cain's case, it is
difficult to see how Abel will be able to demonstrate their reliability without an
epistemically circular argument, for it is difficult to see how one could defend one's
claims to reliably speak for, or perceive, God without appealing either to the book, or to
mystic perception again.
These points hark back to Reed's argument given at the outset. The general lesson is that
where deep epistemic disagreement occursand again, it frequently does notthen the
disagreement is ultimately disagreement over fundamental epistemic principles.
I emphasize that the Cain and Abel case is an example. You may not agree that it is a
deep epistemic disagreement. If you don't, then choose an example you prefer. If you
doubt there are any such examples, then reflect on the possibility of an overt debate over
the reliability of induction, or sense perception, or any other basic doxastic method.
This is worth stressing. In order for an epistemic disagreement to qualify as deep, there
need not be a clash of principles. It only needs to be the case that one side does not affirm
a principle that the other side does affirm, and that Mutual Circularity, Competition, Non-
arbitration, and Commonality are all satisfied. So overt scepticism about induction, for
example, where the sceptic overtly
267
doubts its reliability, qualifies as a deep epistemic disagreement. Commonality is easily
satisfied. Competition is satisfied vacuously since the antecedent will be false. Non-
arbitration will be satisfiedpresumably because, if Hume is right, there is no more
fundamental epistemic principle that can justify the reliability of induction. And Mutual
Circularity is satisfied because the principle in play is defensible only by epistemically
circular arguments. Consequently, overt scepticism about a fundamental epistemic
principle like induction is a default case of deep epistemic disagreement. This is a helpful
point to keep in mind if you are doubtful about the prevalence of mutual disagreements
like that between Cain and Abel. But it is also helpful because it illustrates that overt
sceptical challenges are merely a limit case of a broader phenomenonepistemic
disagreement.
Finally, even if deep epistemic disagreements never occur, it is clear that they could. And
that is enough to raise the questions with which we will be concerned. The basic issue is
simple enough. Where the debate is over basic methods for finding the truth, common
ground is peculiarly elusive. It is not as if the parties to the dispute are sharing evidence
and drawing distinct conclusions from it. Rather, they are disagreeing over what should
be counted as evidence.6 As a result, there is a symmetry of argumentation in epistemic
disagreements. This is because while we don't share the same evidence in cases of deep
epistemic disagreement, our epistemic principles are themselves subject to evidence that
has the same structural character. Neither side can fully justify their principles without
circularity; their principles are epistemically incommensurable.
3. THE THEORETICAL PROBLEM OF EPISTEMIC INCOMMENSURABILITY
For all I've said so far, one could be excused for thinking that epistemic
incommensurability is anything but a regrettable fact about the human condition. After
all, I've already conceded that epistemic circularity doesn't bar us from knowing which
epistemic principles are true. Given externalism, I can give an argument for my epistemic
principles. If so, then so long as induction is reliable, I can give an inductive argument for
its reliability. And that means, that so long as my epistemic principles are true, I can
know they are. So epistemic incommensurability
268
may be unfortunate, but if we've already agreed that scepticism doesn't follow, then what
about this poses a distinctly philosophical problem?
In fact, it poses two problems. The first looks formidable but, is, I believe, actually not
so. The second may seem less deep but is in fact more so. I'll take the easy one first. It is
meta-epistemic. I'll lay it out in the simplest way I can and then discuss the premises.
1. Deep epistemic disagreements are rationally irresolvable (epistemic
incommensurability).
2. The best explanation for why deep epistemic disagreements are rationally irresolvable
is that there are no objectively true fundamental epistemic principles.
3. If there are no objectively true fundamental epistemic principles, there are no
objectively true derivative epistemic principles.
4. All epistemic principles are either fundamental or derivative.
5. Therefore, there are (probably) no objectively true epistemic principles.
The argument parallels a familiar argument for moral anti-realism. That argument moves
from the premise that deep moral disagreements are rationally irresolvable to the
conclusion that there are no objectively true moral principles. Such arguments are widely
used to undermine moral realism.7
As I see it, the first premise of the argument is reasonable, but only when qualified in a
certain respect. But once qualified in that respect, the second premise is false.
Let's start with the first premise. What is meant by rationally irresolvable and why
believe that epistemic disagreements are so? One relevant sense of rational here is
presumably epistemic rationality. Epistemic rationality trades in epistemic reasons. An
epistemic reason is a reason for thinking that some belief or principle is true. Let us say
that a debate is epistemically resolvable just when it is possible that an epistemic reason
could be given, as I'll call it, for resolving it. A debate is epistemically irresolvable when
this is not the case.
What do I mean by giving a reason? Suppose we are wondering which of two plans for
building a bridge is the safest, and we consult an engineer to find this out. In so doing, we
not only expect the engineer to be able to discriminate whether the one plan is safer than
the other, but to be able to articulate, or otherwise make clear, the rational basis of her
discrimination. In short, we expect her to give us a reason for favouring one plan over the
otherto articulate the rational basis of her discrimination so that we can recognize it as
such. For only if we can, from our evidential standpoint as it were, recognize her reason
for favouring one plan as a reason can it serve to rationally underwrite our subsequent
plan of action. Barring a recognized reason that one or the other plan is safest,
269
we will either not build the bridge at all, or we will judge them equally safe, and choose
between the plans in some other way.
This suggests a general constraint: where A gives a reason (in the sense intended) of
some type to B for some p, it must be possible for B to recognize, from his standpoint,
that it is a reason. This constraint is consistent with some familiar distinctions. One might
be justified in believing p without having a reason for the belief. The belief may simply
be produced by a reliable method. Likewise one's belief might be justified by a reason
without you recognizing that it is a reason. But that is not what is at issue in the case of
the engineer, or in the case of an overt epistemic disagreement. In both cases, there is a
standing demand to justify one's beliefs or commitments. And to actively justify
(epistemically) a belief essentially requires giving an epistemic reason for the belief, and
one gives a reason only if it can be recognized as such by oneself and others.8
So a debate is epistemically irresolvable just when no epistemic reason can be given for
resolving it. Overt deep epistemic disagreements are marked by epistemic circularity.
Together, these facts support the first premise, at least when it is understood in the
epistemic way we've been developing. This is because epistemically circular arguments
cannot be used to give a reason for why some epistemic principle is true.
This is not to deny that an epistemically circular argument might be an epistemic reason
for believing a principle (the belief might be justified by such an argument). But it cannot
be used to effectively give an epistemic reason for a belief in the face of a standing
demand to actively justify the belief. For it will fail to be recognized as a reason by
anyone who doesn't already share the principle. As the bridge-plan case illustrates, in a
case where live demands for justification are on the table, we demand reasons we can
recognize as such. Epistemically circular arguments are hopeless for doing this. If I am
wondering whether I can trust you, the fact that you say I can doesn't give me a reason for
why I shouldeven if, in fact, I can.
For this reason, epistemic externalism, even if it true, is of little use here. We may well
know (via an epistemically circular argument perhaps) which basic methods are reliable.
But that fact has absolutely no traction when one is trying to justify employment of a
method in the face of disagreement. When posing a challenge, it doesn't help to be told
that if you adopt the right method, you'll be able to know that you did. That answer
offers stone instead of bread.9
270
Nor, I think, is it any more help to claim that one is entitledin the sense intended by
Crispin Wright (2004)to one's fundamental epistemic principles. To be entitled in
Wright's sense is, roughly, to have epistemic warrant for a proposition without having
any epistemic reasons to believe it. One is entitled to a proposition in this sense when (a)
that proposition is presupposed by one's cognitive projects; (b) one has no reason to think
it is not true; and (c) any attempt to justify it would rest on propositions whose epistemic
standing is no better off. Perhaps we are entitled in this sense to our fundamental
principles. And perhaps, as Wright suggests, entitlement is epistemic and not pragmatic
in character. The problem is that even if these points are true, citing that one is entitled to
believe some proposition is not going to help rationally resolve a deep epistemic
disagreement.
Suppose, for example, that Abel claims to Cain that he is entitled to his fundamental
epistemic principles. This may well be so. We can imagine that treating the Holy Book as
the most reliable guide to the past is presupposed by one of his basic cognitive projects
like understanding the will of God. And he sees no reason to think it is unreliable. Cain of
course will hardly be moved, nor should he be. He doesn't accept Abel's cognitive project
(he may even think it is incoherent). And from his standpoint he has offered a reason to
believe that Abel's methods are unreliable, and therefore that his fundamental epistemic
principles are false. But of course, whether this is so is the very issue they are disagreeing
about. If their epistemic disagreement is truly deep, Cain and Abel aren't going to
recognize each other's epistemic reasons in the domain of belief in question precisely
because those reasons themselves are produced by methods that are the very methods in
question. In short, I'm entitled to p cannot be used to give a reason for p in a case of
deep epistemic disagreement, even if the person who is entitled is warranted in holding p.
So understood, the argument's incommensurability premise seems reasonable. Deep
epistemic disagreements are rationally irresolvable in the epistemic sense: the principles
involved require defence by an epistemically circular argument, but epistemically circular
arguments can't be used to give reasons. But of course, it also leaves room for the claim
that epistemic disagreements might be rationally resolved in another sense of rationality.
I'll return to just that suggestion shortly. For now, I'll bracket premise one and turn to the
second premise.
4. A BETTER EXPLANATION
When qualified as I've done above, the first premise of the above argument is reasonable.
Deep epistemic disagreements are rationally irresolvable in the epistemic sense. But once
qualified in this way, the second premise appears to be false.
271
The second premise is a straightforward appeal to best explanation. In order for it to be
plausible, the advocate of the theoretical argument has to rule out the other alternatives
or at least the most reasonable ones. This I don't think can be done. Indeed, I think there
is a much simpler explanation available. But first let's briefly consider a few other
alternatives.
A sceptic will claim that the best explanation for why deep epistemic disagreements are
epistemically irresolvable is not that there are no objectively true epistemic principles,
but that we can't know which epistemic principles are true. But if externalism about
knowledge is correct, as I've been assuming, we can know which epistemic principles are
true. So given externalism, scepticism is not the best explanation of the rational
irressolvability of epistemic disagreements.
This consideration also underlines an important fact already noted but worth noting
again: namely that the argument is consistent with externalism being true. For an
externalist will claim that if our epistemic principles are true, then we can know they are
true (by way of those same epistemic principles). But this conditional can be true even if
the antecedent is false. So externalism is not ruled out by the argument.
Of course, if externalism is false, then it may well be that the best explanation for why
deep epistemic disagreements are epistemically irresolvable is that we can't know which
epistemic principles are true. But that is cold comfort surely.
Another possibility is that premise two is false because the epistemic irresolvability of
deep epistemic disagreements is due to defective concepts. That is, we might think that
our basic epistemic concepts are simply too vague or imprecise, or otherwise mangled,
and that is why disagreements which essentially employ such concepts can not be
epistemically resolved. This too would be cold comfort. For if our basic epistemic
concepts are radically defective, it may be that many of our epistemic principles which
employ such concepts will lack a determinate truth value. We end up reaching the same
conclusion by other means.
And of course, there are the familiar possibilities of non-factualism and relativism about
epistemic principles.10 But far from being rival explanations, non-factualism and
relativism presuppose the general negative claim (that there are no objectively true
epistemic principles) allegedly supported by the above argument. Consequently, it
remains our first task to see whether there is a simpler explanation of the epistemic
irresolvability of epistemic disagreements.
There is a simpler explanation. The simpler explanation for the epistemic irresolvability
of deep overt epistemic disagreements is that it is a direct consequence of the nature of
epistemic rationality itself together with the relevant facts about the kind of disagreement
in question. More precisely: once one understands what it means to give an epistemic
reason, the epistemic irresolvability of deep epistemic disagreements is just what one
should expect. It is a consequence of the
272
human cognitive condition; what Pritchard has memorably called our epistemic angst.11
Where there is deep epistemic disagreement over some fundamental principle, the
disagreement has hit bedrock, the spade has turned. It has hit bedrock precisely because
the disagreement obeys Mutual Circularity, Non-arbitration, and the other constraints
constitutive of deep epistemic disagreement. And when bedrock is reached in this way,
the process of giving epistemic reasonsof engaging in the activity of justifying in the
epistemic senseloses its point. But the best explanation for this is not some deep
metaphysical fact about the objectivity of our epistemic principle. The best explanation is
that epistemically circular arguments for the reliability of some method won't be
recognized as a reason to accept that method by those challenging its reliability in the
first place. In other words, the very nature of the debates themselves, together with facts
about what is to give a reason, already explain the epistemic irresolvability of deep
epistemic disagreements.
So it is plausible that epistemic disagreements are not epistemically resolvable. But that
fact should not incline us to think that there are no objectively true epistemic principles.
Nor does it entail that we can't know which epistemic principles are true. It merely
demonstrates that, like all things, the process of giving epistemic reasons has its limits,
limits imposed by epistemic circularity and the nature of epistemic disagreement.
5. THE PRACTICAL PROBLEM OF EPISTEMIC INCOMMENSURABILITY
So deep epistemic disagreements are epistemically irresolvable; but that does not warrant
an irrealist conclusion. It may seem tempting to some to leave it at that. But that would be
a mistake, for to do so would be to avoid the obviousand realremaining problem. For
we've just conceded that deep epistemic disagreements are not rationally resolvable in the
epistemic sense. That leaves it open that they might be rationally resolvable in some other
sense. But what other sense, and how, in that sense, are such disagreements to be
rationally resolved?
This seems, to me anyway, a live and pressing question. It is quite different from the
question of whether we can answer the Cartesian sceptic. There are very few, if any,
radical sceptics. And there are unlikely to be any. But disagreements over basic epistemic
methods are, in my view, quite possible. Moreover, the issue at hand is not whether one
side or other of an epistemic disagreement can persuade the other that their principles are
the true ones. Persuasion is a
273
psychological phenomenon, and can be accomplished in a variety of ways. (A big club is
a good method; so is an expensive advertising campaign.) What we presumably want
here is not a psychological but normative explanation. We want to make sense of what
ought to be done in the face of deep epistemic disagreement.
The fact (if it is a fact) that deep epistemic disagreements can't be epistemically resolved
means we have to look elsewhere than epistemic reason. An obvious alternative is
practical reason. Indeed, one might think that this would have been a reasonable starting
place anyway since there is a clear sense in which the problem at issue is practical.
Considerations given above, after all, already suggest that the underlying issue isn't a
matter of what we know or don't know, but of what we should or shouldn't do. It is not
even best conceived as a problem about which principles we ought to believe (because
one might say we ought to believe what we know to be true). After all, the root issue at
the heart of an epistemic disagreementthat which makes the dispute an epistemic
oneis the question of which methods we ought to employ. What we want is a reason for
employing one method over another. That's a practical matter. No wonder epistemic
disagreements seem irresolvable when conceived of as epistemic matters. Epistemic
reasons are simply not the right tool for solving them. It is not a matter of trying to justify
our belief in our epistemic principles, it is a matter of trying to justify our actionsour
employment of a method.
So I suggest that we reframe the problem of epistemic incommensurability as a practical
problem. In saying this, I don't mean that it is a moral problem. Not all questions about
what to do are moral questions. The question we are faced with in the face of an overt
deep epistemic disagreement concerns our ability to justify our doxastic methods. Since
these methods are aimed at producing (true) beliefs, the issue at hand is hardly divorced
from epistemic matters. It is practical, but not morally practical. Call it a matter of
epistemic practicality.
6. EPISTEMIC PRACTICALITY
The main goal of this essay has been to get clear on the problem caused by the
phenomenon of epistemic incommensurability. That problem, I've argued, is an
epistemically practical problem. It concerns how we can justify our employment of our
basic epistemic methods in the face of overt disagreement. I've argued that this problem
is distinct from the issue of whether we can know that our methods are reliable, and
moreover, distinct from the question of whether it is true that they are. Moreover, it is a
not a problem that will be resolved by appeal to epistemic reasons. It will be solved, if at
all, by appeal to practical reasons.
I'll conclude with a suggestion for how to arrive at such reasons. I say the suggestion is
about how to arrive at such reasons because one cannot foresee in advance what
specific practical reasons might be relevant to cite in favour of
274
a method for any disagreement over that method. What is needed is a general
frameworka way of identifying the types of practical reasons relevant for settling on
one method or another.
In setting up the framework, we must recall the general constraints about rational
resolution of disagreements uncovered above. Rational resolutions require the giving of
reasons. And reasons are given only when they are recognizable as reasons. Together,
these constraints suggest that no practical reason for resolving an epistemic disagreement
will be successful if it doesn't employ a type of reasonor if, you like, a valueshared
by both sides of any such debate. Briefly put, we need common ground.
Of course it is an open question whether such ground can be reached. But rational self-
interest provides an obvious initial suggestion. How might we employ such a
consideration to argue for one method over another? One possibility is to play what I'll
call the epistemic method game.12
Let us say that an epistemic principle is privileged when it is worthy of teaching in the
schools, used in evaluating research, and seen as trumping other, possibly conflicting
methods. In the epistemic method game, players are charged with cooperatively coming
up with reasons for privileging some epistemic methods for forming beliefs over others in
some world wa world distinct from their own. Candidate methods include methods like
deduction, induction, sense perception, reading palms, and consulting sacred texts.
Players operate, in good Rawlsian style, under the following rules or constraints. First,
they cannot, in their deliberations, presuppose that any method is more reliable for
producing true beliefs than others in w. That is, they must operate under the assumption
that consulting the sacred texts may well be as reliable a method of belief formation for
the inhabitants of w as sense perception. In effect, their deliberations must take place
under the assumption that scepticism is trueall methods for forming beliefs are as
reliable as others because none are reliable. Second, just as they cannot, in their
deliberations, assume that one method of belief formation is more reliable than any other,
so they cannot assume that one metaphysical picture of the world is any more accurate
than others. By a metaphysical picture I meanadmittedly somewhat looselya view
about the ultimate structure and nature of reality. Thus, players cannot, in their
deliberations assume that, for example, naturalism is true, nor that, for example, Christian
theism is true. Third, players know that they will each eventually inhabit w themselves.
But finally, fourth, they don't know all the methods they willbecause of upbringing,
education, religion, and so forthwish to employ themselves in w.
Were we to play the method game, it would seem in our self-interest to favour privileging
those methods that, to the greatest degree possible, were repeatable, adaptable, public,
and widespread. Repeatable methods are those that in like cases
275
produce like results. It would be in our interest to favour repeatable methods because
such methods could be used over and over again by people with different social
standings. Adaptable methods are those that can be employed on distinct kinds of
problems and which produce results given a variety of kinds of inputs. It would be in our
interest to favour such methods because we don't know what sort of problems we'll face
in w. Public methods are those whose effectiveness could, in principle, be judged
publiclythat is, it is not the case that only one person is its sole judge of effectiveness.
It would be in our self-interest to favour public methods because we don't know if we'll
be lucky enough to be that one person in w. And finally, widespread methods are those
that many people can in fact employ. It seems rational that we would privilege methods
with these features simply because by doing so, we would maximize each of our chances
to both use and assess the use of the privileged methods. In this sense, such methods
could be called democratic.
But aren't players of the epistemic method game using various methods (such as a priori
and causal reasoning) to arrive at their conclusion about w? Obviously they are, and they
may be using other, more idiosyncratic methods as well. The rules do not in any case
prohibit this. The situation described is not one where the participants are without
epistemic methods, nor is it one where the players must share epistemic methods. It is
one where they are asked to decideusing whatever methods they have available, and
acting under the relevant constraintswhich methods should be politically privileged in w.
And the methods that are so privileged are those that will form the content of their
subsequent epistemic standards and principles.
One might object that Abel was asking Cain for some reason to believe that certain
standards of reason are true. Our suggested form of argument gives something else. It
gives practical, self-interested, reasons for adopting some standards over others. Why
isn't this stone instead of bread?
Two answers suggest themselves. The first is that stone soup is sometimes the best item
on the menu. Given the dialectical situation forced upon us by the nature of deep
epistemic disagreements, giving practical reasons is the best we can do. Moreover,
practical reasonsand this has been my pointare still reasons. They are better than big
sticks.
There is something to be said for the first answer. But there is a better answer available.
Namely, not only is giving practical reasons the best we can do, it is what we should do.
For if Cain and Abel are to engage in real discussion, they should respect each other as
fellow judgersas being capable of arriving at the truth. And where we respect each
other as fellow judgers, we should, where possible, defend our claims with reasons that
we each recognize as reasons. And that means, if we are to satisfy the demand to respect
each other as fellow judgers, we should appeal to the common currency of our self-
interest to justify why we should privilege certain methods. For only by doing so can we
give reasons that can be recognized as reasons. Put most provocatively: if we wish to
respect each
276
other as fellow judgers of the truth in cases of deep epistemic disagreement, we should
not appeal to reasons for judging something to be true.
I have not tried to argue which specific methods would emerge from the epistemic
original position, although I very much doubt that reading the sacred text would be one.
My point is that even in the face of disagreement, we can give reasons for our methods.
The reasons are practical, not theoretical, but they are reasons all the same. Moreover, we
should try to give such reasons. If we are to treat each other as autonomous judgers
worthy of equal respect, we must engage in the process of giving and asking for reasons,
even when the question at hand concerns the reliability of our most basic methods for
reaching the truth.13
277
14 The Epistemology of Disagreement
Ernest Sosa
This chapter will take up one main question: when and how can a belief be sustained
reasonably in the face of known disagreement? On the answer to this question will
depend our prospects for sustaining cherished opinions in fields where controversy
abounds, such as religion, politics, history, morality, art, philosophy, and even medicine
and the law.
1.
We begin with a subsidiary question: is reasonable disagreement ever possible? Opposing
answers to one and the same question can both be reasonable, of course, if at least one of
them is based on evidence that is persuasive but misleading. This much is
uncontroversial.
In a more interesting case, Pro and Con share all their evidence. Can they still assess the
shared evidence differently? Can one affirm what the other denies, though each proceeds
reasonably enough? For each to be reasonable, each needs positive justification. Unlike
ethics, epistemology repels arbitrariness. Facing a choice between bringing it about that p
and bringing it about that not-p, you may have no sufficient reason to prefer either over
the other, in which case you might well be free to take your pick. That's how it is for
practical choices or actions. By contrast, with no more reason for believing either a
proposition or its negation in preference to the other, you are definitely not free to
proceed either way. Here you must withhold, if you are to proceed reasonably at all,
epistemically. If two opponents are both to be reasonable, then, each needs a balance of
reason favouring his side.1 But is this compatible with their sharing all of their evidence?
278
Not if any reason they may have, for or against believing, would have to be found in the
evidence that they share. We are supposing they share all their evidence. Since the
evidence cannot point in two opposite directions at once, Pro and Con cannot each have
substantial positive reason for affirming what the other denies.
Based on such reasoning, you may well conclude that reasonable disagreement with full
disclosure is just impossible. But others will no doubt disagree. Even after you pool your
evidence, suppose they still remain unimpressed.
On one view, with substantial support in the literature, if you encounter opposition from
an apparent peer, then, absent independent reason to downgrade him, you must lower
your confidence, perhaps below the threshold of belief. Without independent reason to
downgrade an overt opponent, we are told, the only reasonable option is to withhold.
Upon encountering opposition this view is self-defeating. Any subscriber to it who is
unable to demote independently an opponent who disagrees is then required to withhold.
His opponent, by contrast, labours under no such handicap, and is able coherently to
sustain his side.
Enemies of reasonable disagreement advocate an even stronger thesis, moreover, the
Uniqueness Thesis:
No body of evidence E justifies more than one doxastic attitude (believing, disbelieving,
withholding) on any given question.2
When Pro and Con fully share their p -relevant evidence E, we are told, each must
withhold unless he can find some independent reason for demoting the other.3
279
Consider the following assumptions:
1. A pondered question, whether p, admits just three doxastic attitudes: belief,
withholding, and disbelief. Which of these one should adopt is determined by the total
p -relevant evidence in one's possession, along with the fact that it is one's total
evidence.
2. Full disclosure between Pro and Con, on the question whether p, results in their
sharing some E as their p -relevant evidence, in such a way that E is for each the
total evidence bearing on that question.
3. One and the same total evidence E cannot favour both p and not-p at once. The
degree to which it favours p is the same as the degree to which it disfavours not-p
and vice versa.
4. Whether S is reasonable to believe that p depends on the degree to which his total
evidence E favours p . E must favour p , and must do so sufficiently.
It follows from these assumptions that Pro and Con cannot both be reasonable, with full
disclosure on a certain question, when one believes what the other disbelieves. It is not
possible to disagree reasonably under full disclosure.
Reasonable disagreement can be rife even so, especially in domains like politics, religion,
and philosophy. For one thing, such disagreements rarely take place under full disclosure.
For another, it is not obvious that what matters here is always (ever?) just a matter of
evidence, properly so called, much less of disclosable evidence.
Perhaps the main reason why disagreements on controversial issues are often reasonable
on all sides is that they are to some extent verbal. Verbal but not uninterestingly
superficial, as when someone believes there's a bank nearby while someone else
contradicts' him. Disagreement can be reasonable and interesting when its nature as
verbal can emerge only through patient, extended analysis and discussion.
Such disagreement can be more or less verbal. Here's one way to think of that. Suppose
analysis reveals that sentence X, as understood by S, is true if and only
280
if p, while as understood by S' it is true if and only if p. Then we can wonder about the
extent to which p and p overlap in content. And this might of course vary
enormously.
At one extreme the overlap is minimal, as when for S the meaning is that a river bank is
near, whereas for S' it is that a financial institution is near. But the overlap can be huge,
as where for S the sentence X is tantamount to an n+1-termed conjunction
p1 . . . &pn&q , whereas for S' the sentence is tantamount rather to p1 . . . &pn&q . If
S affirms X while S' denies it, but each would agree on the conjunction p1 . . . &pn
then their verbal disagreement may be as largely verbal as is the disagreement of those
who disagree on the sentence There's a bank nearby.
Still, though largely verbal, such disagreement need not be superficial, as is the one about
banks. How substantive (and not merely verbal) a disagreement is in this sort of example
will depend on how many of the n p-conjuncts the parties disagree about, with some
weighting presumably for the substantive importance of the various conjuncts. How
deep (non-superficial) their disagreement is will depend on how much work of
conceptual analysis would be required in order to uncover its real locus, and thereby
whether it is really as verbal as is the one about banks.
Though convinced that much disagreement on controversial issues, especially in
philosophy, has that deeply verbal nature, I here put that aside, because (a) it deserves a
discussion of its own (preferably with philosophical case studies, such as that of
disagreement among epistemologists on issues concerning epistemic justification), and
because (b) I discuss it elsewhere, in defending armchair philosophy from attacks on the
evidential worth of intuitions when people ostensibly disagree in their ostensible
intuitions.4 Here we shall pursue other ways in which ostensible disagreement might be
compatible with beliefs that remain reasonable even when they ostensibly clash. How
might one reasonably defend one's own side in such a reasonable disagreement?
281
2.
Several philosophers have converged on the view that the proper response to
disagreement among ostensible epistemic peers is for each to give equal weight to the
opponent's view.5 We are told that it would be unreasonable to downgrade the opponent
based simply on the substance of the disagreement. Here are some examples offered in
support of that claim.
1. Pro looks out on the quad and thinks There goes the dean walking on the lawn again.
The day is bright, the quad treeless, the lawn visible throughout, from edge to edge.
Yet Con, standing next to Pro, intones It's nice to see the quad with no one there at
all. What is Pro to do, once it is clear that Con is dead serious? One thing he cannot
properly do, according to our converging philosophers, is to downgrade Con's
epistemic credentials based just on their disagreement.
2. At the end of a restaurant meal, Pro and Con mentally compute and Pro arrives at $42
as what they each owe, whereas Con comes up with $45 as the right amount. One
thing that Pro cannot properly do, in sustaining his side, is to downgrade Con's
epistemic credentials on the question before them, based just on their disagreement.
To demote your opponent based just on your disagreement is likened to declaring
someone else's watch inaccurate because it disagrees with your own, in the absence of
any independent basis to prefer either watch over the other.6
If I can find no independent reason to downgrade an opponent below my epistemic level,
I must consider him no less than a peer. What does it take to be someone's peer on a
given question? Some require parity on general competences that bear on how to answer
that question, plus familiarity with the pertinent evidence and arguments. Alternatively,
one might define A and B as peers on a given question if and only if, conditional on their
disagreement, they are equally likely to be right on that very question.7
282
Our two definitions are intimately related if how likely you are to be right on a given
question is determined just by your relevant competences and your familiarity with the
pertinent evidence and arguments. However, the likelihood of your being right on the
question may be determined by more than just having such competences and familiarity.
It may also depend, for one thing, on how likely you are to employ them. In order to
decide whether these factors are required in addition, we need a fuller conception of
competences and of how they relate to the relevant arguments and evidence. When facing
a certain question, for example, would you necessarily be lacking (somewhat) in
competence if you failed to employ your competences on the relevant evidence and
arguments familiar to you?
Pending such refinements, the account before us seems reasonable enough as a working
hypothesis. In any case, the interesting question here concerns what it would be
reasonable to adopt as one's epistemic stance when one disagrees with someone respected
as a peer.8
Suppose you share with your friend all the available evidence concerning a shared
question. Suppose at first you count your friend a peer, and then it turns out you disagree.
According to the Equal Weight View, when you learn of your friend's disagreement, you
are called upon to consider him equally likely to be right.9
We shall discuss that view in due course. But first we consider its implications for
avoiding a dispiriting spinelessness' whenever we disagree with apparent peers. The
importance of this issue is shown by how broadly it would bear on questions that matter
to us in politics, religion, philosophy, and other such
283
domains. It would be bad to have to suspend judgement on just about any controversial
question.10
Some have urged that we must be adults and face the facts. This we may be forced to do,
but a more hopeful option first demands attention: why not protect our controversial
views by denying that we are likely to consider someone a peer on an important and
controversial issue if we disagree with him on that issue.11
Let the issue be abortion, for example, on which Ann and Beth deeply and persistently
disagree. Ann surely does not consider Beth a peer on that issue. This is because she
takes Beth to be profoundly mistaken on many linked issues. Once Ann sets aside Beth's
opinions on a host of issues linked with that of abortion, Ann may simply not consider
Beth a peer.12
On an issue that divides them, Pro might take Con to be either his peer, or inferior, or
superior. On the other hand, Pro might consciously suspend judgement on any or all of
these, and in particular might consciously suspend on whether he, Pro, is superior to Con
on the question at hand.
With these distinctions in mind, we return to Ann and Beth on abortion. Here is the
proposal before us:
It fails to be the case that Ann will consider Beth a peer on whether abortion is
permissible, once so many of Ann's considerations have been set aside.
Nor does Ann consider herself superior to Beth, presumably, for the same reasons. So,
here's Ann's state of mind: She is sure that abortion is permissible in a given set of
circumstances. But she does not consider herself more likely to be right than Beth, who
openly denies that abortion is there permissible. Ann fails to consider herself superior to
Beth on that question. But she now seems incoherent. Ours is hence after all no way for
Ann to sustain her positive opinions in the face of controversy. She needs not only to
avoid taking her opponents to be peers; she needs somehow, more positively, to consider
herself superior.
Not only must one fail to consider an opponent at least equally likely to be right. That is
perhaps Ann's position with respect to Beth. As has been suggested, Ann may be unable
to pass judgement on Beth's credentials concerning the question of abortion, given the
gulf that divides them, since their respective linked opinions differ so radically. Let us
grant this for the sake of argument.
284
True enough, one will thereby avoid the incoherence of considering oneself reasonable in
taking abortion to be permissible despite granting that an epistemic peer believes it to be
impermissible. Nevertheless, an incoherence still looms. While facing the question of
how likely one's opponent is to be right, one is now forced to withhold on that question;
at least one is forced consciously and deliberately not to render a judgement. This puts
one in the following position: (a) one thinks that p, and that one is likely enough to be
right in so thinking, and (b) one also takes someone else to think that not-p, while (c) one
consciously fails to have a view on how likely this opponent is to be right. Doesn't simple
rational coherence require us to be more judgemental than that? If we think ourselves
likely to be right in believing that p, and we know our opponent to disbelieve what we
believe, are we not constrained to consider that opponent likely to be wrong, as likely to
be wrong as we are to be right? We fall short, surely, if we consciously remain neutral on
whether the opponent is right. Such neutrality fits ill with insisting on our own positive
view.
The fact that deep and broad disagreement will preclude one's respecting an opponent as
a peer fails therefore to protect us from the dispiriting implications of the Equal Weight
View. Avoiding those implications requires rather downgrading one's opponents as
somehow inferiors (on the questions in dispute).13 If we wish to avoid those implications,
therefore, we need to reconsider the Equal Weight View itself.
Here now is a capsule statement:
EWV Absent independent reason to downgrade an opponent epistemically on the
question whether p, one must give their opinion equal weight as one's own. (One cannot
properly insist on one's side of the disagreement while drawing from the very fact that
someone disagrees on that question a reason for considering their relevant judgement
inferior to one's own.)
This applies with special plausibility, so it is contended, in any case where disagreeing
parties have fully disclosed their evidence, and where neither has independent reason to
downgrade the other's ability to assess the now fully shared evidence.
With such disagreement out in the open, we turn reflective, and consider what our
evidence might be, and what it might render plausible or better on the
285
disputed thesis. Pro may then find himself convinced that his evidence supports the
affirmative on that thesis, whereas Con takes their shared evidence to support the
negative. When this happens, then, unless Pro has independent reason for preferring his
own judgement, he now has evidence, including Con's opposition, that requires him to
suspend judgement.
Why should that be so? We are told that confrontation with an opponent may reveal that
we have no reason for preferring the view that our evidence supports p above our
opponent's view that it supports not-p . Nor, often enough, has our opponent, for his
part, any reason that advantages his side of this disagreement. When that happens, as it
often does on controversial topics, then the right attitude is to suspend belief. Both sides
of the disagreement should come together in that middle position. Once we must
withhold on whether our evidence supports our belief that p, it is not possible coherently
and reasonably to sustain the belief that p.14
3.
Can we really sustain our side of a disagreement only by finding some independent
supporting reasons, while the opponent has no balancing reasons in favour of his side?
Much will depend on how we conceive of reasons. Suppose you have a headache. What
reason have you for thinking that you do? The important reason is, quite plausibly,
simply that you do! Is this a reason that enables you reasonably to sustain your side of a
disagreement when an employer believes you to be a malingering faker, with no
headache at all. If so, then you can after all demote an opponent by relying on the
substance of your disagreement. A huge part of your reason for rejecting the employer's
claim that you're faking it is the very fact that gives content to your belief, the fact of the
headache itself. Here then one has a conclusive reason that makes one's belief a certainty,
even if that reason will be useless in a public dispute. It will not much advance your
cause to just assert against your employer that you do have a headache, even if this is in
fact the reason that makes you certain that you do. (This gulf between private and public
domains will come to the fore again in due course.)
Nor are headaches special in this regard. The same point applies to any obstreperous
enough mental state. Anyone who denies to you that you are in that mental state is in a
position like that of the employer who accuses you of faking it.
286
Other examples of the same epistemic phenomenon will be found in any case of the
given, whether it is the phenomenal given, such as our headache, or the rational given,
such as the simplest truths of arithmetic, geometry, or logic. Here again if someone
denies what you affirm, you can uphold your side by appealing to the very fact affirmed.
Thus, if someone claims 2 and 2 not to equal 4, or a triangle not to have three sides, we
could reasonably insist on what we know. We could try to disabuse him, while
downgrading his conflicting judgement. Something must be misleading him, even if we
can't see what that is. And the basis for our stance might well be, as with the headache,
just the substance and fact of the disagreement.15
That seems to me conclusive on the general issue of whether you can demote an
opponent based essentially on the substance of your disagreement, even when you have
no independent reason for doing so. But it does not yet give us what we want. It does not
provide a way to avoid spinelessness on controversial issues that matter. For one thing,
there is no real controversy on any question whose answer is so obvious that it constitutes
its own reason, nor when no reason is even required for being justified in answering as
one does.
In such simple cases a belief's justification does not derive from its basis in ulterior
reasons. Either it derives from a reason provided by the very fact believed, or it may
perhaps derive from one's manifesting a competence in believing as one does, even
absent any reason whatsoever. Either way, in such simple cases you would be reasonable
to downgrade your opponent based essentially on your disagreement, even with no
independent reason for doing so.
This proves insufficient, however, because issues subject to troubling, persistent
disagreement are not properly decidable in the absence of ulterior reasons. Controversial
issues have no obvious resolutions. They are always complex, and resoluble only through
extensive reasoning or evidence. On such an issue it is not so easy to downgrade an
opponent based simply on the fact of your disagreement.
4.
Moore's disagreement with the sceptic is an intermediate case. The locus of that
disagreement is whether Moore knows about the hand before him. The sceptic
287
says no, Moore says yes. Moore insists by downgrading the sceptic's judgement. True,
Moore goes into some detail. But his bottom line is this: the sceptic must be going wrong
somehow, since it is more certain that he, Moore, does know about his hand than is
anything the sceptic can adduce against that fact.
The sceptic says that he, Moore, might be dreaming. Moore responds that he knows he is
not dreaming, if this knowledge is indeed required (as he concedes) for him to know
about the hand. His rejection of the sceptic's side on this disagreement is thus based on
insisting that he does know about the hand. He bases his rejection, in other words,
precisely on insisting that he is right in the earlier disagreement and the sceptic wrong.
Here he begs the question (whether properly or improperly).16
This case differs from any in which one side of a disagreement can be upheld because its
correctness is so obvious in itself that no ulterior reason or evidence is required. Moore
takes his case definitely not to be one where he has no need of ulterior reasons or
evidence. He is quite explicit that only based on conclusive reasons does he know himself
to be awake and not dreaming. Take again the question whether one can know oneself to
be awake. The sceptic answers this question in the negative as against Moore's own
affirmative response.
Moore does not claim it to be obvious that he is awake and not dreaming, so that he
needs no ulterior reasons for so believing. On the contrary, he claims rather that he
cannot expound his reasons fully, perhaps because they are too extensive and complex.
His reasons are said to constitute conclusive evidence for believing as he does, that he is
awake and not dreaming, despite his inability to expound them. Certainly he cannot cite
them to an opponent. And Moore might also claim, or so I suggest, that he could not
expound them even to himself. Those reasons seem conclusive, then, even if he cannot
lay them out, one by one, perhaps even to himself in private.17
Moore does not make explicit what he might include in such conclusive evidence. One
might however reasonably attribute to him considerations of the sort that seem persuasive
to Descartes and perhaps also to J. L. Austin.
288
For Descartes, wakeful experience has a sort of coherence that distinguishes it from
dreams; for Austin dreams have a dream-like quality that makes for a similar distinction.
Indeed, the distinctions are at bottom the same if what underlies the dream-like quality is
just the absence of the coherence that for Descartes distinguishes our wakeful
consciousness (often enough, at least when rich enough). Any case of wakeful experience
rich enough to have Descartes's coherence and to avoid Austin's dreaminess, would be
constituted specifically by some complex stream of consciousness composed of elements
that dovetail appropriately with others in the same time slice and also with relevant
preceding and succeeding elements. Each such fact of dovetailing presumably contributes
to the coherence of the stream of consciousness, and may constitute a reason which,
when combined with all the others, provides a conclusive justifying basis for the subject's
belief that he is then awake. Each is thus operative as a partial basis for that belief, but
Moore apparently believes that this does not require the subject's ability to detail each
separately, so as to enable a proof that he could cite to himself or to others.18
289
That all being so, Moore does then know, based on evidence in his possession, that he is
awake and not dreaming, despite the sceptic's disagreement.19
5.
Moore's reasoning suggests a way to handle disagreements commonly encountered in
fields where controversy abounds. In Moore's case we are unsure of having fully
expounded our evidence.20 Normal cases of deep, important controversy share relevant
features that make this comparison interesting. The evidence on which we base belief in
our side of a controversy need only be inscrutable, for whatever reason, or at least
sufficiently hard to uncover. For it cannot then be displayed for reflection on how well it
supports the content of our belief.
One reason why that body of evidence turns out to be inscrutable recalls Moore's
example, where although the evidence is right there in our present conscious experience
or remembered directly from our recent experience, it is too subtle or complex to be
noticed and detailed fully. That is not the main factor, however, in cases of public
controversy. Here there is a further source of opacity to our present reflective gaze. Our
basis for believing as we do on such questions generally fails to be fully formed and
operative in one fell swoop. Light dawns gradually over such questions. A belief forms in
us over time through the subtle influence of diverse sources. Some are testimonial, others
perceptual, others inferential, and so on. The belief might owe importantly to the
believer's upbringing, or to later influence by his community. We are social beings and
do well, socially and intellectually, to rely on such influence by our social and intellectual
communities. Such proper reliance over time on divergent communities might thus help
explain how disagreement can be reasonable.
When our full grounding for a belief is thus complex, and temporally extended with the
aid of memory, it lies beyond our present view. Why do we think that our math teacher in
high school algebra was named Mrs Hanson? Because we remember that fact. Right, but
we must have had reasons for first acquiring and sustaining that belief (which was then
held in place through retentive memory). What were those reasons? They are now
irretrievable, quite beyond our reach. Why do we take our friend to be touchy on a certain
subject. Because on many
290
occasions he has exhibited such a disposition. Yes, that's what we say now when asked
for a justification. But we needn't have earlier formed the belief that on many occasions
Tom has shown himself to be touchy on this subject. On the contrary, upon experiencing
variously and repeatedly how he has responded to relevant promptings, the belief may
have dawned on us and guided our future interactions.
Why do we think there are stars in the sky? Can we really cite the reasons that led us to
form and retain this belief? Sure, it may be thought, we know we've seen the stars
repeatedly; that's our reason. But is that our only reason? And, more importantly, what
about this proposition itself, that we have so seen the stars? What is our reason now for
believing it? That we ostensibly remember it? We cannot require here the experiential
memory of having seen the stars on a certain occasion, for this may well be missing.
What is said to be enough is rather the ostensible retentive remembering of the fact in
question. But such a paltry reason is unlikely to exhaust our epistemic justification (even
if it does sustain some minimal subjective justification) for believing that there are stars
in the sky or that we really have seen them. Even supposing that there is a distinctive
appearance of retentive memory, which is already dubitable, what is further dubitable is
that such an appearance could do much epistemically for our belief in the stars in the
absence of the relevant past experiences that prompted this belief, a belief then kept in
place through the proper operation of retentive memory. It is this latter, more substantial,
time- and memory-involving rational basis that need not now be present to our reflective
gaze in order to do its proper epistemic work.
And so it is, I submit, for nearly the whole of one's body of beliefs. The idea that we can
always or even often spot our operative evidence for examination is a myth.
If we can't even spot our operative evidenceso much of which lies in the past and is no
longer operative except indirectly through retained beliefsthen we cannot disclose it, so
as to share it. And this will apply to our opinions on complex and controversial topics no
less than to our belief about our teacher's name or the touchiness of our friend or the stars
in the sky. On all these matters we are in the position that Moore takes himself to be in on
the question whether he is awake. We have reasons (in our case through the mediation of
retentive memory) that, acting in concert, across time, have motivated our present beliefs,
but we are in no position to detail these reasons fully. This may be so, finally, as Moore
also thought, even in cases where the reasons are in combination quite conclusive.
6.
If we leave it at that, however, we risk obscurantism, the no less dispiriting position that
our reasons, far removed in our past, or deeply lodged in our
291
subconscious, cannot be uncovered for critical inspection. This can hardly be the way to
defend our prized ability to take reasonable stances on controversial topics of politics,
religion, philosophy, history, morality, and so forth. We would be trying to defend our
ability to take such stances only by removing the topics from the arena of proper debate
and critical reflection.
Or so it might seem. But a closer look is revealing. Even if a controversial view that one
upholds is justified by much that is then reflectively inaccessible, this by itself need not
free one from full responsibility for providing a supporting rationale. We may be justified
in insisting on our side of a disagreement despite being unable to spell out our
justification. But this does not empower us to proclaim the view unsupported. The
demands of public debate are different from those of private belief.
7.
The demands of public debate and public profession require a study of their own. Here
we focus rather on reasonable belief, which can properly remain unvoiced and
undefended. Our emphasis on the importance of hidden reasons can still show that, as in
Moore's case, our ability fully to disclose our reasons may be quite limited; which implies
in turn that even if reasonable disagreement with full disclosure is impossible, this has
little or zero bearing on the possibility of reasonable disagreement, since full disclosure
might be difficult and rare.
Nevertheless, let us focus on cases where we do seem able to disclose extensively or even
fully. Return first to our two examples used by enemies of reasonable disagreement, that
of the contents of the quad, and that of the restaurant bill. In fact such cases can differ
broadly. Some might require deference to our opponent, others that we insist on our
position, and others that we split the difference. And this may all be so even absent
sufficient reason, independently of the substance of our disagreement, to downgrade our
opponent's judgement. Cases might still differ dramatically, even if in none can we
downgrade independently.
Take the restaurant example. If my friend and I calculate in our heads and come up with
contrary results, and we reasonably take each other to be peers on the question at hand
(equally good track records, equally good competence as arithmetical calculators, equally
good present mental shape, equal attention to the matter, etc.), clearly then each should
give equal weight to the other's judgement, so that we ought to split the difference by
each moving to a middle position where we both withhold. However, suppose my friend
and I are now out of each other's sight, neither of us privy to what the other does in
double-checking our results. I take out pencil and paper, and perform the calculation that
way; then I remember the calculator in my pocket, and I perform the calculation that way
too. And all of these procedures repeatedly converge on one result: $42.
292
At the end of the period of rechecking I again compare notes with my friend, who insists
that his rechecking has confirmed his initial result: $45. Now things change dramatically.
Now I am in the Moore-like position of having to say that if his procedure has led to that
result, there must be something wrong with his procedure. I have no idea what it is, since
I am not privy to what he did. What has changed from the initial stage is how reliable I
can consider my procedure and the competence I manifest in employing it. Nevertheless,
I still lack independent reason to downgrade my opponent's relevant judgement and his
epistemic credentials on the question that divides us. Only based on our disagreement can
I now demote him.
The case of the quad may or may not be similar. If the quad is large and the dean barely
visible at the opposite end, then my opposing friend's remark can lead me to lower my
confidence sharply and with good reason. But if the quad is small and sunlit, and the dean
sports a bright blue jacket just fifty feet away below our window, and my friend says
there is no one there, and I see the dean there plain as day, then I find it about as plausible
to say, Moore-like, that here again something is wrong with my friend, I know not what.
And I do this based on the substance of our disagreement.
What makes the difference between the cases where we must yield some ground to our
opposing friend, and those where we demote him instead? What makes the difference in
such cases is plausibly a matter of how reasonably sure we are of our relevant
competence. Take our original restaurant disagreement, or one where the quad is huge
and the dean far away. In these cases, because we are sufficiently unsure of the
competence exercised, the outspoken disagreement of our friend creates a reasonable
doubt. When we double-check our addition, however, using paper and pencil and a
calculator, and when the conditions of perception are nearly ideal, we reach a very
different result. Here we are sure, reasonably so, that the competence we exercise is quite
reliable, which is in part why we can demote our friend, even if in doing so we must rely
on the substance of our disagreement.
That does seem initially plausible about such cases. But a further stance seems more
reasonable yet, and compatible with the plausible one just considered. On this further
stance the more important difference imported by repeated rechecking is not so much that
one is now sure of one's procedure and of its high reliability. The more important
difference is rather that one now fails to be sure independently that the opponent's
relevant reliability is a match for one's own. So, the important difference is that one no
longer has sufficient independent basis for judging the two opponents to be peers on the
question at hand.
There is moreover a further difference that seems more important yet. I have been
assuming that in the original restaurant case, you and I both (the disagreeing parties) have
some degree of confidence in our respective beliefs ($42 in my case, and $45 in yours).
But we are even more confident that we both are about equally reliable in such mental
arithmetic. In the revised restaurant case, there
293
is a crucial change here. After the period of rechecking, when I have checked through
paper and pencil and through a calculator, I end up considerably more confident that $42
is the right result than I am any longer that you are not my inferior on the matter at hand.
I have to lower my confidence that you are not inferior because I now know about my
greatly increased reliability and I have no such knowledge about you.
There is therefore the following difference between the original case and the revised case.
In the original case I am independently more sure that you are not inferior than I am that
$42 is the right answer. In the revised case I am more sure that $42 is the right answer
than I am independently that you are not inferior. Plausibly, then, our ability reasonably
to downgrade our opponent based on the substance of our disagreement varies depending
on the degree of confidence we have in our side of the disagreement, compared with the
independently based confidence that we have as to whether the opponent is our inferior
on the matter at hand.
That is just a matter of internal coherence, of whether we can coherently proceed by
downgrading based on the substance of a disagreement. Of course, the overall evaluation
of whether we proceed correctly in doing so will have to depend also on how reasonably
we hold the degrees of confidence that we hold concerning our side of the disagreement,
for one thing, and the inferiority of our opponent on the matter at hand, for another thing.
These apparently minor and subtle differences might make a crucial difference to our
ability reasonably to sustain our views on controversial issues. For, on such issues our
bases for our opinions are not open to view or easily and clearly displayable.
Controversial stances are hence liable to differ widely from our stance when we recheck
with pencil and paper and a calculator. When we recheck thus our mode of belief
acquisition is quite open to view and displayable for all to see. Not so for controversial
opinions, or indeed for the great bulk of our standing beliefs now retained through sheer
retentive memory. What in the restaurant case is the important difference between the
pre-checking and post-checking situations? What is the difference between our pre-
checking situation, which calls for suspension, and the post-checking situation, where we
may hold our ground and demote the opponent based on the substance of the
disagreement? Suppose we locate the important difference in the fact that after
rechecking, with pencil and paper and a calculator, we are sure that our method is highly
reliable, whereas pre-checking we had used only the unreliable calculation in one's head.
This move will put us in dire danger of falling short for any controversial stance that we
would like to uphold. After all, most often our position in such stances vis--vis our
opponents' is not like our position after rechecking in the restaurant case. On the contrary,
we are unlikely to have so much as a clear conception of just how we have formed the
opinion that we would like to uphold.
Compare with that the more moderate requirements for proper upholding and for proper
downgrading of one's opponent based on the substance of a
294
disagreement. On these more moderate requirements, what relevantly changes in the
restaurant case as we move from mere calculation in one's head to elaborate rechecking,
is not that one is later sure of the reliability of what one can now see clearly as a new and
improved basis for sustaining one's side of the disagreement. What relevantly changes is
rather that one is now no longer independently sure that the opponent is one's peer on the
question at hand. And, more relevantly yet, what changes is that after rechecking one is
now more sure that one is right on one's side of the disagreement than one is that one's
opponent is not inferior on the question under dispute. And this is precisely our position
vis--vis our opponents on controversial issues, or nearly always so.
8.
What then is the upshot for the possibility of reasonable disagreement on issues of
moment in controversial fields? Our reflections inspire cautious optimism. When Pro and
Con disagree openly on such an issue, and each insists on his side of the disagreement,
each needs to be confident that they proceed competently enough, based on adequate
grasp of the available evidence, or at least they need to avoid good independent basis for
thinking themselves to be peers on the matter at hand. It will be relatively rare for them to
be able to disclose fully their relevant reasons and evidence. To some extent, therefore,
they will be relying on a position similar to that of the second restaurant calculator (the
one who has rechecked his result). None of them is privy to the backing for their
opponents' contrary belief, not fully. Yet each might be quite reasonably confident of the
competence they themselves exercise, or at least each may have no sufficient independent
basis for thinking the other to be a relevant peer. And this is why they might properly
downgrade their opponents based essentially on the substance of their disagreement.
Such downgrading need imply no disrespect. Despite your highest respect for the
competence of an opponent, you may be forced to downgrade his judgement on a
particular issue that divides you. To downgrade him is just to think he must be going
wrong somehow on that particular issue. That this is sometimes appropriately based on
the substance of the disagreement, even absent any independent reason to downgrade
him, has been a main thesis of this chapter.
If that much is correct, we can then continue to believe as we do on issues of moment in
public debate, which does not require us to disrespect our opponents, nor does it exempt
us from arguing for our side as fully and convincingly as we can manage. Our inability to
defeat an opponent in public debate need not rationally require us to abandon our beliefs.
For various powerful reasons, our beliefs can be grounded adequately in reasons that give
us no dialectical advantage, either because they offer no dialectically persuasive leverage,
or because they are
295
undisclosably beyond our reach. While appealing to this fact, finally, we must avoid a
dispiriting obscurantism, but we need to recognize also that it is a fact, one with a clear
bearing on our main issue.
We can remain open-minded on how extensively the foregoing considerations may help to
protect our controversial views. They have some value, we can dare hope, but must be
supplemented. For one thing, we must also recognize how often we speak past each
other, to one or another extent, when we ostensibly disagree on controversial issues. We
need to bear in mind how often this tends to happen, especially in philosophical dialectic.
9.
We have taken note of three factors that may help enable reasonable dissent against open
opposition: (a) how verbal disagreement can be, (b) how deeply hidden and undisclosable
reasons can be, and (c) how epistemically effective a reason can be despite being
dialectically ineffective.
We have also examined a supposed obstacle to reasonably sustained dissent: namely, that
the substance of a disagreement can never provide a proper basis for downgrading one's
opponent. We have found this obstacle to be often enough surmountable.
Those four considerations, severally and collectively, open up possibilities for us to
sustain our views reasonably even in the teeth of outspoken opposition.21
296
APPENDIX: MOORE'S DISAGREEMENT WITH THE SCEPTIC
The sceptic and he cannot come together and disclose fully, according to Moore, since he
takes his evidence to be inexpressible, or not fully expressible, perhaps opaque even to
his own reflection. Nevertheless, Moore's discussion is still relevant in the following way.
There is a broader sense of disagreement where A does not simply affirm the very same
proposition that B denies. In this broader kind of disagreement,
A has total evidence E(A) pertinent to proposition P(A), and B has total evidence E(B)
pertinent to proposition P(B), where A would be justified in believing P(A) based on E(A)
if and only if B would be justified in believing P(B) based on E(B), and where A and B
know or believe that fact, or at least the fact that there is such evidence on each side.
Moreover: first, A believes that he is and would be justified in believing P(A) based on
his relevant total evidence, whereas, second, B for his part believes that he is not and
would not be justified in believing P(B) based on his corresponding total evidence.
Moore's is a special case of this.
Moore believes that his sensory experience while wide awake, and his memories of his
recent experiences while wide awake, provide him with evidence E(Moore) based on
which he is and would be justified in believing Awake(Moore).
Sceptic believes that his sensory experience while wide awake, and his memories of his
recent experiences while wide awake, provide him with total evidence E(Sceptic), based
on which he is not and would not be justified in believing Awake(Sceptic).
Finally, they both know or believe that Moore would be justified in believing
Awake(Moore) based on his relevant total evidence if and only if Sceptic would be
justified in believing Awake(Sceptic) based on his corresponding total evidence.
So far Sceptic and Moore do not disagree on a shared question, while sharing also all of
their relevant evidence. They do share similar enough evidence, however, evidence that
bears similarly enough on relevantly similar propositions in such a way that, as is
believed by them both, their respective beliefs in the similar propositions stand or fall
together. The sceptic thinks they fall. Moore thinks they stand.
We arrive thus after all at a strict disagreement on one and the same question. On this
disagreement Moore upholds his side and demotes the disagreeing sceptic by reasoning
that makes essential use of a proposition on which they disagree. The proposition that he
does know about the hand is part of Moore's basis for the conclusion that he must also
know himself to be awake and not dreaming, and for the further conclusion that things he
knows directly (such as his present and recent experiences) must provide him with
conclusive reasons and evidence for his corresponding belief (that he is awake and not
dreaming).22
297
15 A Justificationist View of Disagreement's Epistemic Significance
Jennifer Lackey
Disagreement with others is a familiar part of our lives. Most of us find ourselves faced
with friends who have radically opposing views on the war in Iraq, relatives who
explicitly reject our beliefs about religion, and colleagues who dispute our conception of
the nature of free will. These are just a few of the more common topics of disagreement,
but there are countless others, ranging from the mundaneThat is a cat by the tree, not a
small dog!to the extraordinaryThat I conquered my cancer was not purely a result
of my chemotherapy, but was also God answering my prayers.
In some instances, disagreement can be explained by one party to the dispute being privy
to more evidence than the other. You and I may have opposing beliefs about whether
Jones committed the murder because only you saw the relevant DNA results linking him
to the crime. Other cases of disagreement can be accounted for in terms of various kinds
of cognitive asymmetries. You and I may disagree about whether the bird in the backyard
tree is a starling because only I am using eyeglasses with an out-of-date prescription. Still
other instances of disagreement can be explained by one member of the dispute having
reason to believe that the other is epistemically inferior in some respect. You and I may
have differing attitudes about whether my daughter is the best ballet dancer in her class
because you believe that I am biased where my daughter's talents are concerned.1 But
adjusting our doxastic states in all of these sorts of cases does not reveal anything
significant about disagreement itself, since the fact that you and I disagree drops out of
the explanation of this adjustment; it is, for instance, the difference in our familiarity with
the relevant evidence or the asymmetry in our cognitive capacities that does the
explanatory work. In order to truly assess the significance of disagreement itself, there
cannot be any relevant epistemic asymmetries between the parties to the dispute to
shoulder the explanatory
298
burden;2 in other words, such parties should be epistemic peers.3 The question at issue,
then, is this: what is the significance of disagreement between those who are epistemic
peers? In particular, what is the rational response to disagreement in situations where
there are no relevant epistemic asymmetries between the members involved in the
dispute?
There are two answers to this question found in the recent literature. On the one hand,
there are those who hold that disagreement itself can be wholly without epistemic
significance; thus, one can continue to rationally believe that p despite the fact that one's
epistemic peer explicitly believes that not-p, even when one does not have a reason
independent of the disagreement in question to prefer one's own belief. I shall call those
who hold this view nonconformists. According to nonconformists, there can be
reasonable disagreement among epistemic peers. So, for instance, Gideon Rosen writes:
It should be obvious that reasonable people can disagree, even when confronted with a
single body of evidence. When a jury or a court is divided in a difficult case, the mere
fact of disagreement does not mean that someone is being unreasonable. (Rosen 2001:
71)
Similarly, Thomas Kelly claims that:
The mere fact that others whom I acknowledge to be my equal with respect to
intelligence, thoughtfulness, and acquaintance with the relevant data disagree with me
about some issue does not undermine the rationality of my maintaining my own view.
(Kelly 2005: 192)4
According to nonconformists, then, the mere fact that there is disagreement with one's
epistemic peer does not mandate any sort of doxastic revision from either party to the
dispute.
Now, there are two central explanations of the nonconformist response to peer
disagreement.5 First, there is what we may call the egocentric view. On this view, I am
justified in giving my belief extra weight6 in the face of peer disagreement because the
belief in question is mine. So, for instance, Ralph Wedgwood claims:
Perhaps, quite generally, it is rational for one to place greater trust in one's own
intuitions, simply because these intuitions are one's own, than in the intuitions of other
people. In other words, perhaps it is rational for each of us to have an egocentric
epistemic bias in favour of our own intuitions. (Wedgwood 2007: 261)7
299
325
Notes
1. INTRODUCTION
1
It is really preferable to view preservationist and expansionist conceptions as
representing degrees of distance or departure from traditional epistemology. There are no
sharp dividing lines here. But often it is useful to talk in terms of binary or discrete
categories, even when the underlying reality is messier than such categorization suggests.
2
An exception is Steve Fuller, who used social epistemology both as the title of his first
book (Fuller 1988) and as the title of a journal he founded. Another revisionist, Martin
Kusch (2002), uses a somewhat similar phrase for his position: communitarian
epistemology.
3
Whether it succeeds is another question. I have argued that the activities described by
Latour can be reinterpreted in respectably epistemic terms (Goldman 1999: 22730).
4
I am not prepared to endorse this denial in my own voice. For example, can't one be a
legitimate epistemologist and still endorse some type of epistemic relativism about
justification or rationality? And what about a philosopher who examines arguments for
and against relativism without taking a firm position of her own? Isn't she doing real
epistemologydespite the fact that one of the core assumptions of traditional
epistemology is the falsity of epistemic relativism? My purpose here, however, is only to
explain or reconstruct the probable reasoning of those epistemologists who, according to
Alston, would refuse to accept social epistemology as real epistemology. I am not
necessarily joining them in excommunicating (even) rejectionist social epistemology. Of
course, rejectionist social epistemology isn't the kind I personally favour. But it's a more
delicate question to decide whether it deserves to be considered epistemology at all.
5
Another formulation Boghossian offers of the key thesis of classical relativism is a
thesis he calls Equal Validity: There are many radically different [mutually
incompatible] yet equally valid ways of knowing the world, with science being just one
of them (Boghossian 2006: 2). Again, a claim of equal validity goes beyond any
semantical thesis of New Age relativism.
6
In addition, there are paradigmatic questions of epistemology to which social answers
have been offeredeven if the questions themselves do not invoke social properties or
relations. As long as these answers are defended in a characteristically epistemological
fashion, this should also be considered traditionalalbeit socialepistemology.
7
The term evidence is used here in two different but related senses. First, it can refer to
an object or state of affairs in the external world. This is the sense in which we speak of
rings in a tree trunk being evidence (for the age of the tree) and of fossils like Lucy and
Ida being evidence (about the evolution of Homo Sapiens). In addition to this external
sense, there is a second sense of evidence in which it refers to belief, justified belief, or
knowledge about evidence in the external sense. Thus, to possess, gather, or acquire
evidence is to have or acquire beliefs, justified beliefs, or knowledge about external
evidence. In this chapter, social evidence is sometimes used in the external sense,
referring, for example, to statements uttered or written by other people, or their opinions
(states of mind). Other occurrences of social evidence refer to subjective states of a
doxastic agent concerning external social evidence. I trust that the intended use will be
clear from the context.
8
Two volumes dedicated to these questions are Lackey and Sosa (2006) and Feldman
and Warfield (2010). Most of the articles in the present volume also address these
questions.
9
See Goldman and Shaked (1991). A proof of the relevant theorem appears in the
reprinted version of the paper. The proof presupposes a linear measure of truth
possession, which many would question because it isn't a proper scoring rule.
Nonetheless, other approaches to epistemic utility might offer related rationales for
preferring one test to others (Maher 1990; Fallis 2007). Any such rationale would suffice
for present (merely illustrative) purposes, so the argument does not depend essentially on
the assumptions used in the GoldmanShaked analysis.
10
See Unger (1975), Williamson (1996, 2000), DeRose (2002), and Hawthorne (2004).
11
Why doesn't Robert Brandom's (2000) discursive or communicational theory appear on
this list? Because Brandom's targets of analysis are semantical concepts, not epistemic
ones. He is not, fundamentally, trying to illuminate epistemic justifiedness.
12
The literature on dialectical, or dialogical, approaches to logic and argumentation is
substantial. It ranges from treatments oriented toward formal logic to treatments attuned
to informal logic, natural conversation, and norms of argumentation. Prominent
specimens of this work include Hamblin (1970), Barth and Krabbe (1982), Lorenzen
(2001), Toulmin (1958), and Woods et al. (2000).
13
Alston doesn't suggest that any epistemologists hold precisely this position. He says
that many would regard much of the material in Knowledge in a Social Worldnot all
of itas not real epistemology.
14
Someone might argue that what makes irrationality interesting for traditional
epistemology is the concern with doxastic decision-making processes of individual
agents. But collective agents don't really engage in doxastic decision-making, one might
claim. So why should a branch of epistemology take any interest in their irrationality? I
dispute the assumption that collective agents do not engage in doxastic decision-making
(DDM). Although collective agents are (presumably) not distinct centres of
consciousness, this does not mean that they don't engage in DDM. Doxastic decision-
making refers to whatever processes transpire to bring about, in a subject, a new or
revised doxastic state. Which process this is in the case of collective agents is up for
grabs. It might just consist in a set of distributed processes in their constituent members,
together with an aggregation process that works automatically, without any extra
individual activity. An assumption that needs to be avoided is that group DDM must
involve things like consciousness, attention, or purposefulness in the group entity.
15
In Knowledge in a Social World I restricted the relevant epistemic outcomes to
veritistic outcomes, i.e., true belief, false belief, and intermediate degrees of belief
associated with the truth. In general what I mean by epistemic outcomes' in this paper is
a wider family of epistemically valued and disvalued states, including justified and
unjustified belief, and so forth. In the legal context, however, I am again interested in
evaluations in terms of veritistic outcomes.
16
Section 4.2 may have suggested that doxastic decision-makers must always take the
initiative in gathering evidence. But as we see in the legal trial example, social systems
can play a crucial role in producing or assembling social evidence relevant to the doxastic
task at hand. In legal trials, the court issues subpoenas to relevant witnesses and requires
them to appear in court and testify, which involves answering questions posed by
attorneys. Witnesses' testimony, of course, is evidence for use by the jury. The jury itself,
which is the doxastic agent, does not have to collect such evidenceindeed, they are
barred from collecting evidence external to the trial situation. Many other social systems
serve a roughly similar evidence-assembling function. Traditional enterprises like entire
educational systems and public libraries are intended to do exactly this sort of thing. In
the modern era the Internet and its assorted applications serve this function. A salient
illustration is the online encyclopedia, Wikipedia. This may be viewed as a project in
mass collaboration that uses certain methods to produce a large collection of social
evidence (writings produced by multiple authors). How reliable and trustworthy is this
evidence? This is another suitable topic for expansionist social epistemology (see Fallis
and Sanger 2009).
17
For further elaboration of this point, see Goldman (1999: 298300).
18
For defence of the thesis that many epistemological assessments in mainstream
individual epistemology are fundamentally based on reliability considerations (or other
truth-linked considerations), see Goldman (1979, 1986).
19
Let me briefly elaborate this point. Can impartiality be understood as not giving one
party any advantage over the other in resolving the dispute? This is not quite right. If one
party to the dispute has a dozen witnesses on her side of the story of what occurred
whereas the opposing party has only two, the system confers an advantage on the
former by allowing all witnesses to testify. Does this mean that the system is unfair or
partial? Certainly not. Does impartiality consist in giving both parties to a dispute an
equal chance of winning? This would suggest that flipping a coin would be a good
decision procedure; but that would be absurd. A fair or impartial system, then, is better
understood as a system that confers no advantage to a party except in virtue of her merit-
determining properties, i.e. properties in virtue of which she deserves to win. If being on
the side of the truth (as concerns the material facts of the case) is a principal merit-
determining property, then producing decisions in accordance with the truth is what
makes a system fair and impartial. According with the truth is, of course, a primary
epistemic virtue (Goldman 1999: 2901).
20
This is how I have classified it in two earlier treatments of the topic, Goldman and Cox
(1996) and Goldman (1999: ch. 7). In both cases it was argued that the strong form of the
free-market-for-speech thesis, in which it is defended as a consequence of economic
theory, is false. However, the specific position I take on the subject is not at issue here.
The only issue here is whether this qualifies as a legitimate question of epistemology.
21
Franz Dietrich (2007) argues, however, that there is no notion of probability such that
the conditions of competence and independence are likely to be satisfied simultaneously.
22
Another example is Michael Fuerstein (2009), who emphasizes the role of scientific
method in democratically appropriate deliberation.
23
However, we shouldn't preclude a classification of theoretical for possible work of
this kind. The Condorcet Jury Theorem is plausibly classified as a theoretical
contribution to social epistemology. Another exampledirectly germane to the topic of
group deliberationis a formal result by Christian List (forthcoming), which doesn't,
however, bear on issues of reliability.
24
I refer to Larry Laudan's Truth, Error, and Criminal Law (2006), reviewed by Raphael
Goldman and Alvin Goldman (2009) in the journal Legal Theory.
25
Thanks to Blake Roeber, whose comments on the penultimate draft led to several
helpful clarifications. Earlier drafts of this material were presented at the Stirling
conference on social epistemology, a University of Calgary graduate student conference,
and the World Congress of Philosophy in Seoul, Korea (2008). I thank the audiences in
all these venues for stimulating discussion and criticism.
1
I discuss this example more fully in Code (1995).
2
Moran's view is largely consistent with Michael Welbourne's position in chs. 5 and 6 of
Knowledge, and in his The Community of Knowledge. See Welbourne (1986, 2001).
3
See Code (1987).
4
See Sosa (1991), Steup (2004), and Goldman (2008).
5
See in this regard Bergin (2002).
6
Wittgenstein observes, Knowledge is in the end based on acknowledgement (1968:
378).
7
See Welbourne (1979: 19, 2001: 10913).
8
I discuss Fricker (2007) in my (2008).
9
See Castoriadis (1991, 1994, 1998).
10
Code (2006).
11
The phrase is from Donna Haraway (1991).
12
Here I draw on Anderson (1995).
13
I elaborate this resistance in ch. 3 of my (2006).
14
Latour asks: When will we be able not to reduce matters of concern . . . to matters of
fact? (2004: 51).
15
See Harding (1993).
16
See Kroll (2002), Lytle (2007), and Smith (2001).
17
IDRC stands for the International Development Research Centre. I discuss this case
more fully in Code (2008).
18
From an unidentified letter-writer to the New Yorker, reprinted in its 1995 anniversary
issue (cited in Smith 2001: 741).
19
For Fricker, hermeneutical injustice exposes a lacuna in the collective hermeneutical
resources (2007: 150). Hence, a woman unable to claim a hearing for her suffering from
sexual harassment, before the concept became available, and a man unable to own his
nascent identity as a homosexual in 1950s America (1635), exemplify the harms
hermeneutical marginalization inflicts on a person's or a group's sense of self.
20
IDRC (International Development Research Centre) Online Publications: FIXING
HEALTH SYSTEMs, 2004; http://www.idrc.ca/en/ev-64404-201-1-DO_TOPIC.html
Refreshed: 14 August 2007.
21
Before TEHIP [Tanzania Essential Health Interventions Project] we did not identify
and prioritize our interventions, recalls Dr Harun Machibya, Morogoro District Medical
Officer. Rather, we implemented plans worked out centrally. Even in budgeting, the
tendency was to add some percentages to previous years' planned and budgeted
activities.
22
See Sackett et al. (2000) and Goodman (2003).
23
See especially ch. 5, Patterns of Autonomy, Acknowledgement, and Advocacy.
24
Recall Anne Seller: As an isolated individual, I often do not know what my
experiences are (1988: 180).
25
Bowden (2008: 52).
26
Cynthia Cockburn remarks, in another context, the researched take greater risks, and
lack the mobility, resources and choices available to the researcher (1998: 3).
27
See Lear (1977: 43352).
28
See e.g. Lytle (2007: Epilogue and Afterword)
29
See An Inconvenient Truth, a film directed by Davis Guggenheim; and Al Gore
(Guggenheim and Gore, 2006).
30
Subjugated knowledges is a term from Michel Foucault (1980: 82).
31
See Proctor and Schiebinger (2008), and Sullivan and Tuana (2006, 2007).
32
Williams (1997) exposes the harms of such neutrality. See also Mills (2008). Mills
observes: The point of trying to understand white ignorance is, of course, normative and
not merely sociological: the goal of trying to reduce or eliminate it (2008: 235).
33
Letter from Clarence Cottam to Carson, February 1962, quoted in Lear (1977: 401).
1
For an early case for the view that justification can be dispersed in the scientific
community, see John Hardwig (1985: 33549). Lynn Hankinson-Nelson (1990) has
argued for the view that the scientific community is the subject of scientific knowledge.
2
Hardwig (1985).
3
See Fricker (2007).
4
Williams's paper was originally delivered as part of a Symposium on Expanding
Epistemology, with Guy Axtell and Robert Brandom, APA Pacific Division Meeting,
Spring 2007. The present chapter grew out of my response as Commentator on that
occasion.
5
Note that Brandom himself is ready to go a step further in the externalist direction than
Williams is willing to. In Articulating Reasons he embraces reliabilism's Founding
Insight and allows that, for instance, an expert in distinguishing Toltec from Aztec
potsherds can know whether a shard is one or the other even if she cannot say how she
does it. Williams differs, and so maintains a stronger internalism in his responsibilist
position. See Brandom (2000: ch. 3, esp. 989).
6
This is the characterization of Cartesian scepticism that Williams has elsewhere argued
to be the only one to furnish radical scepticismthe view that we have no justified
beliefs. See, for instance, Williams (2001: 737).
7
This is how Brandom (2000b) puts the issue.
8
This distinction was first made by Bernard Williams, as Craig notes. See Williams
(1973: 146).
9
This is Michael Welbourne's term for it. See his (2001), especially ch. 6.
10
Here I paraphrase somewhat but intend to capture Craig's conditions. For his own
formulation, see Craig (1990: 85).
11
Properties such as these bestow what Bernard Williams (2002: 423) in his genealogy
of truthfulness (modelled closely on Craig's genealogy of knowledge) calls purely
positional advantage.
12
To be precise, there are three key pressures that push the good informant's proto-
knowledge towards the objectivized form it takes as, simply, knowledge. First,
sometimes enquirers may not need to recognize any informant here and now, but only at
some point in the future. Second, the enquirer may be aware that there can be good
informants whose indicator properties he is unable to detect. And third, it may not matter
to the informant that he himself acquires the information at all, as what may matter is
simply that someone around here has got it. All three push the idea of knowledge in the
direction of objectivization and away from any dependence on immediate subjective
availability to the enquirer.
13
See Craig (1990: 623).
14
In Unnatural Doubts (1991) Williams argues for contextualism independently from
considerations about Default and Challenge, since it pre-dates the publication of
Brandom's Making It Explicit (1994)I thank Alessandra Tanesini for first pointing this
out to me. In Williams's later book, Problems of Knowledge (2001), we see the two in
combination.
15
Most directly of all, our genealogical story undermines Cartesian scepticism
characterized in the traditional manner as a demand for absolute certainty, for that
demand is most immediately what the proto-contextualism generated in the State of
Nature exposes as fatally misguided, in as much as there is no practical context where a
good informant would have to be absolutely certain in the requisite sense of
indubitability. But the present focus is on the more potent interpretation of the Cartesian
challenge as threatening radical scepticism.
16
Bernard Williams (2002) exploits this facility by identifying in the State of Nature his
two fundamental virtues of truthAccuracy and Sincerityand then going on to explore
their contingent historical forms and significances.
17
Epistemological context already seems too generous a category, precisely because
there are already approaches (such as genealogical approaches) to epistemology that pre-
empt, or at least do not invite, sceptical challenge.
18
An earlier draft of this chapter was presented at a conference on Social Epistemology
held at the University of Stirling in 2007, and I am grateful to all those present for their
input, including Kathleen Lennon, who responded. I also thank Duncan Pritchard for
subsequent written comments. The present chapter is a slightly revised version of an
article that appears in Philosophical Papers. For details see the bibliographical entry for
Fricker (2008). I am grateful to the editor of Philosophical Papers for permission to
reprint.
4 On Saying that Someone Knows: Themes from Craig
1
Some well known exceptions and criticisms of this are found in Bishop and Trout
(2005a, 2005b), Goldman (1992a), Kornblith (2002), Stich (1990), and Weinberg,
Nichols, and Stich (2001).
2
See Fricker (1998, 2007), Neta (2006), Lane (1999), and Kusch (2009).
3
See Kaplan (2003).
4
Cf. the careful discussion of similar themes in Rysiew (2007).
5
This chapter has been long in the making. Thanks to Erik Olsson, Jesper Kallestrup, and
Mikkel Gerken for very helpful and stimulating discussions along the way. The material
was presented at The Place of Epistemic Agents' conference, Madrid, 23 October 2008.
I would like to thank the organizers for providing me with the opportunity to present the
material at that occasion, and the audience for helpful suggestions.
1
See e.g. Craig (1990).
2
See, especially, Timothy Williamson (2000), for discussion of the claim that knowledge
is the norm of assertion, and John Hawthorne (2004) for the claim that knowledge is
sufficient for use in practical reasoning.
3
See Lewis (1980: 26393). He later abandons the Principle Principal in Lewis (1994:
47390).
4
See Lewis (1996: 54967).
5
I am thinking of the particularist approach of Jonathan Dancy (2004).
6
The initial account of the fallacy can be found in Robert Shope (1978: 397413). Some
of the lessons of the fallacy for various counterfactual accounts in ethics are detailed in
Robert N. Johnson's excellent piece Virtue and Right (2003: 81034).
7
See e.g. Michael Smith (1995).
8
See ch. 5 of Kvanvig (2003). This conclusion involves a change from the conclusion
reached in Kvanvig (1998: 42651), where I claimed that the Swamping Problem
undermined every version of externalism as well as undermining nearly every version of
internalism (except for a radically subjective one).
9
Kvanvig (2003), see especially ch. 1.
10
It should be noted that Pritchard does not hold that an appeal to final value can solve
the value problem. The passage quoted reports an approach to the special and unique
value of knowledge that Pritchard investigates but in the end rejects.
11
Thanks to Christian Piller for helping me to see this point clearly.
12
The literature includes accounts that explicitly claim to be such, as well as the buck-
passing accounts that have become more popular since the publication of T. M. Scanlon's
(1998) What We Owe to Each Other. For the response-dependent approaches, see e.g.
Mark Johnston (1989), David Lewis (1989), Michael Smith (1995), John McDowell
(1985), David McNaughton (1988), and David Wiggins (1987).
13
Robert Shope (1978: 397413).
1
See for instance Unger (1984), Cohen (1988), DeRose (1992, 1995, 2009), Lewis
(1996), Rysiew (2001), Neta (2003), Hawthorne (2004), Stanley (2005).
2
See for instance the virtue epistemology of Sosa (1980, 2007) and Zagzebski (1996),
but also those who think knowledge is a norm of belief, action, and/or assertion, e.g.
Pollock and Cruz (1999: ch. 5), Williamson (2005), Hawthorne and Stanley (2008), and
those who follow Sellars (1956) in thinking that knowledge attributions place one in the
space of reasons', e.g. Williams (1992, 2001), Brandom (2000a: ch. 2), and Rosenberg
(2002).
3
In Bar-On and Chrisman (2009) and Chrisman (2009: 5), non-standard forms of
expressivism are explored, which attempt to be semantically neutral. However, in this
paper about the meaning of normative claims, such as epistemic claims, I set those views
aside as not addressed to the present issue.
4
See Grice (1957), Schiffer (1972), Davis (2003).
5
Compare Schroeder (2008) and Chrisman (forthcoming) for more discussion of the
semantic commitments of expressivism. Early expressivists like Ayer and Carnap can be
plausibly read as denying that ethical terms have semantic value at all. However, this has
come to seem increasingly implausible, which is why most recent expressivists should be
read, I believe, as relying on an ideationalism as their general semantic approach.
6
His is, at its core, a theory of judgements about rationality rather than a theory of
judgements about something being good. I'm simplifying for present purposes. What he
actually writes is this: An observer, we may assume, accepts at least an incomplete
system of general norms; call that system N. He then thinks an alternative rational if and
only if he thinks it N-permittedthat is to say, rational according to N . . . whether an
alternative is N-permitted is a matter of fact, and so a belief that the alternative is N-
permitted is a factual belief. Thinking X rational, then, is a combination of a normative
state and a state of factual belief (Gibbard 1990: 91).
7
See especially Davidson (1980: ch. 5), Smith (1987, 1994: ch. 4).
8
See Mackie (1977: ch. 1).
9
Some expressivists such as Ayer (1946), Stevenson (1937), and Gibbard (1990) have
assumed that this commits them to denying the truth-aptness of ethical claims. However,
more recent expressivists such as Blackburn (1998), Timmons (1999), Gibbard (2003),
and Ridge (2009) have sought to avoid this commitment in various ways.
10
One exception to this is ethical expressivists pursuing the quasi-realist programme of
reconstructing the language of realism within an anti-realist expressivism. Thus, both
Blackburn (1996: 87, 1998: 318) and Gibbard (2003: 235) argue briefly for extending
their ethical expressivism to cover epistemic claims. Outside of that, Field (1998) and
Heller (1999) have sketched views of particular epistemic claims that might be read as
expressivist views, although they have not been worked out in very much detail.
11
Compare citations in note 2 above.
12
See for instance Kvanvig (2003), Pritchard (2007b), and the papers collected in
Haddock, Millar, and Pritchard (2009).
13
Kvanvig (2003: ch. 7), Cuneo (2008: chs 56), and Lynch (2009a) have argued that
epistemic expressivism faces special problems not faced by ethical expressivism. These
arguments are discussed and rejected in Carter and Chrisman (unpublished).
14
For example, Copp (2001) defends a view he calls realist expressivism, where the
expressive function of ethical claims is seen as deriving from something other than their
semantic content. See also the papers cited in note 3 above.
15
In addition to the quote from Gibbard in note 6 above, compare Gibbard (1990: 93) and
Ridge (2006) for the most explicit examples of this strategy. Both, however, echo Hare's
(1952: 1820) distinction between the neustic and phrastic elements of meaning. One
possible exception to this is Blackburn (1988, 1993), who argues that logically complex
sentences serve a particular commissive function; that is, they tie one to a tree of
conditional commitments. For example, the claim If your stealing that money was
wrong, then you will eventually be punished commits its author to the content of its
consequent if she is committed to the content of its antecedent, and to the negation of its
antecedent if she is committed to the negation of its consequent. I think approaches of
this sort are quite promising; however, they seem to me to rest on a tacit abandonment of
the ideationalist alternative to truth-conditional semantics, from which expressivism
seemed to receive some shelter from objections to its implicit semantic assumptions. For
to hold that logically complex statements involving normative predicates mean what they
do in virtue of tying one to a tree of conditional commitments is to endorse something
much more like a conceptual or inferential role semantics. If that's right, then the
resulting view may be consistent with the advantages traditionally claimed for
expressivism (more on this below), but I think it can no longer be fairly thought of as a
species of the view that ethical claims mean what they do in virtue of the mental states
that they express.
16
One possible exception is the version of expressivism explored in Schroeder (2008),
which seeks to reconstruct the compositionality and semantic properties of normative
statements in a general expressivist framework. However, in order to capture the
semantic properties, he ends up forcing the expressivist to reconstruct notions of validity
and entailment for all statements (both normative and non-normative) in a global
expressivist account of languagethat is, all indicative sentences are thought to mean
what they do in virtue of the desire-like attitude of being-for that they express. Even if
this view escapes the criticism I go on to levy in the text above, it is not a very plausible
view. As Schroeder himself concludes, it is an extremely unpromising hypothesis about
the workings of natural language (2008: 179).
17
This is a simplification of a distinction deployed in Brandom (2009) drawing on Sellars
(1956).
18
For philosophical expositions of theories of concepts which are at least inspired by this
general tradition, see Dretske (1981) and Fodor (1990), though both Dretske and Fodor
pursue more complex models, anticipating many of the most natural objections to the
crude summation of the tradition presented in the text above.
19
For philosophical expositions of theories of concepts which are inspired by this general
tradition, see Sellars (1956), Dummett (1974), Rosenberg (1974), and Brandom (1994,
2000a, 2009).
20
In this way, the account bears some similarity to Wedgwood's (2007: chs 45)
conceptual-role semantics for normative claims. However, I differ from Wedgwood in
thinking that conceiving of meaning in terms of inferential-roles opens up room for anti-
realist views in normative ontology rather than forces one to adopt a very strong form of
normative realism.
21
I leave it open here whether, like truth-conditionalism, inferentialism should be seen as
a global view of meaning. If it is, normative inferentialism is an application, which draws
a contrast between the normative and the non-normative in terms of type of inferential
role.
22
You might also be able to answer in the order of causes by saying Because I approve
of giving to charity. This exhibits the ambiguity of the question Why did you do X?
Ethical inferentialism as I am conceiving of it is consistent with this response in the order
of causes, but it denies that such a response is adequate in the order of reasons.
23
At least, this could be viewed as a necessary condition for such commitment. Things
may be more complicated depending on one's view of ontological commitment.
24
What about views which see ethical claims as having both practical and theoretical
inferential connections? On the present account, as long as a claim like X is good
commits one to I shall promote X, it has a practical inferential role and so does not
commit one ontologically to the fact that X is good. However, it might imply that X is
approved of by many people, and this then could commit one to the fact that X is
approved of by many people.
25
Compare Kelly (2003) and my discussion of Kornblith (2001) in Chrisman (2008:
3548).
26
Of course, on some accounts of assertion, asserting that p commits one to I know that
p; however, even if that's right, it's still unclear that the implicit knowledge claim is
providing the link to motivation rather than the explicit claim that p.
27
Consider the debate over whether knowledge is a norm of action among, for instance,
Pollock and Cruz (1999: ch. 5), Williamson (2005), Stanley (2005), Hawthorne and
Stanley (2008), Neta (2008), and Brown (2008).
28
These ideas are related to Austin's suggestion that When I say I know, I give others
my word (1946, 1979: 99). However, I take it Rorty and Craig want their ideas to extend
to third-personal ascriptions of knowledge as well.
29
I would like to thank an audience at the University of St Andrews as well as J. Adam
Carter, Georgi Gardiner, Graham Hubbs, Alan Millar, and Michael Ridge for helpful
feedback on earlier versions of this material.
7 Norms of Trust
1
Elster (1989: 100).
2
A point observed by both Austin (1946) and Anscombe (1979).
3
Adler labels this norm the default rule: one ought simply to accept a speaker's
testimony unless one has special reason against doing so (2002: 143). And he observes
that the default rule actually functions as a presumption that our informants are being
cooperative (2002: 154).
4
This point is observed by Adler: Testimonial situations allow modelling as repeated
Prisoner's Dilemmas at least, presumably, in their origins (when testimony is more
functional and local, and so defection more readily detected) (2002: 155). And Pettit
claims that the norm of Telling the truth reliably rather than expediently, randomly, or
whatever is equivalent to cooperating in a many-party prisoner's dilemma (1990: 735).
5
See Faulkner (unpublished).
6
It is developed in detail in Axelrod (1984). See also Blais (1987).
7
I follow the terminology of Sripada and Stich (2006).
8
I discuss Williams's genealogy in more detail in Faulkner (2007b).
9
I tried to work out a definition of this thick sense of trust in Faulkner (2007a).
10
This explication is closer to the surface when more is at stake. Maybe it is a first date
and A and S are enamoured, or A is a potential informant and S is trying to gain his
confidence in a political climate where both have much to lose.
11
See Adler (2002: ch. 5).
12
This chapter was written whilst in receipt of AHRC funded research leave. My thanks
to Adrian Haddock and an anonymous referee.
1
Positive epistemic statuses make up the subject matter of epistemology. Some apply to
beliefs, some to believers. Knowledge and truth are both positive epistemic statuses that
apply to belief. Warrant is another. The connections between knowledge, true belief,
entitlement, and justification are complex. Justifications and entitlements both fall short
of enabling knowledge, even when they warrant a true belief. Such is the stuff of Gettier
cases. Justification (as understood here) is clearly not necessary for perceptual knowledge
(Kornblith 2008). I can only explicate testimonial entitlement here, and cannot pursue its
connections with testimonial justification and testimonial knowledge. I have discussed
testimonial knowledge elsewhere (Graham 2000a, 2000b, 2006b). See note 4 for my
construal of the adjective testimonial.
2
Prima facie entitlement means defeasible entitlement. Counter-considerations may
overturn the entitlement. Justification or further entitlements may be required to restore
the warranting force of an entitlement. Pro tanto entitlement means some entitlement,
where some may fall short of enough for on balance entitlement, given some threshold
(Graham 2006a). Justification or further entitlement may supplement the entitlement,
converting some warrant into enough. Do not confuse my thesis that comprehension-
based beliefs generally enjoy prima facie pro tanto entitlement with the obviously absurd
thesis that comprehension-based beliefs ipso facto enjoy indefeasible on balance warrant,
that believing everything you hear somehow confers maximal epistemic warrant.
3
I say a kind of entitlement because I believe one kind derives from normal functioning
(as I argue below) and another related kind may derive from function fulfilment. Still a
third related kind may derive from function fulfilment due to normal functioning. This
third kind is related to what Duncan Pritchard would call an achievement, a success
through the exercise of ability. On a looser understanding of achievement where
achievements are just successes or fulfilments, both the entitlement that turns on normal
functioning and the entitlement that turns on function fulfilment would be achievements.
I hope to pursue the connection between kinds of entitlement and notions of achievement
elsewhere.
Michael Bergmann (2006) (following Plantinga 1993), Tyler Burge (2003), and Ernest
Sosa (2007) each develop accounts of entitlement structurally similar to mine. My
account explicitly relies on the etiological notion of function and normal functioning.
Plantinga and Sosa explicitly reject reliance on etiological functions. Burge remains
neutral on etiological functions and on the importance of normal functioning. I intend to
discuss their views in detail elsewhere.
4
My subject matter is the epistemology of beliefs based on our capacity to comprehend
assertive speech acts. This category is much broader than the category of testimony-based
beliefs, insofar as (a) we take the latter category to involve a narrow account of testimony
(as a speech act), and (b) we require that a testimony-based belief that P be caused or
sustained by a speaker's testimony that P. Many comprehension-based beliefs do have, as
their distal causes, speakers having testified that such and such is the case. But many do
not. For testifying (taken narrowly) is just one of many ways a speaker can assertively
present a proposition (Alston 2000; Bach and Harnish 1979); testifying is a particular
way of assertively presenting a proposition, involving additional intentions on the part of
the speaker (Graham 1997). So there are plenty of comprehension-based beliefs that are
not based on a speaker's testimony. Furthermore, beliefs based on miscomprehending a
speech act are still comprehension-based. A speaker may question whether P, but the
hearer miscomprehends the force, and takes the question to be an assertion, and comes to
believe that P. Or a speaker may assert Q, but the hearer miscomprehends the content,
and comes to believe that P. Since both beliefs are exercises of the hearer's general
capacity to comprehend speech, they are both comprehension-based beliefs. The category
of comprehension-based beliefs is thus larger than the category of testimony-based
beliefs, and larger than the category of assertion-based beliefs. The epistemology of
testimony literature is, for the most part, interested in this broader category.
Testimonial entitlement is thus entitlement for beliefs based on comprehension.
5
Representing an utterance as the assertion that P sometimes leads a hearer to form the
belief that the speaker believes P, or to believe that the speaker asserted that P. But the
central case of a comprehension-based belief is a belief in the very propositional content
taken as asserted. For discussion of this point, see Hunter (1998).
I allow for leeway as to what counts as the propositional content taken as asserted. It may
include simple logical entailments or obvious evidential consequences from what was
strictly speaking said or meant. If someone says John was at the party, you may take the
speaker to have also asserted that someone was there (Goldberg 2001). It may include
obvious conversational implicatures. Someone says there is a gas station around the
corner, and you take the speaker to assert that you can fill your tank there. It may also
include what was communicated non-verbally, given an already existing linguistic
context. Pointing in response to a query is a perfectly good way of telling someone where
something is, or where to go. Assertions are also made both directly and indirectly. You
can assert by asking a question or making a command. In such a case, you make two
speech acts with one utterance.
6
For a survey of impressive psychological evidence in favour of the claim that credulity
is the default, see Gilbert (1991). For additional evidence and argumentation, see Gilbert
(1993). Gilbert examines three models of the transition from comprehension to belief:
Cartesian, Spinozan, and Cartozan. The Cartesian sees comprehension as neutral towards
belief. The Spinozan sees comprehension as consisting in belief; to comprehend an
assertion as an assertion that P just is to believe P as a result of one's linguistic ability to
comprehend. The Cartozan sees comprehension states as disposing belief, but still
ontologically distinct from belief. He favours the Spinozan view. The research he
surveys, and his own research conducted with colleagues, clearly undermines the
Cartesian view. But it is not obvious that it favours the Spinozan over the Cartozan
position. I favour the less controversial, Cartozan view. I discussed Gilbert's view in
Graham (1999).
7
Witness Origgi and Sperber: There are . . . reasons to expect the ability to attribute
false beliefs to others to develop after the ability to communicate verbally. The attribution
of false beliefs to others plays an obvious role in the ability to filter false information
communicated either by mistaken or deceitful speakers' (2000: 163)
8
There is the use of function to describe how something works or operateswhat it
doesas a part of a larger system (Cummins 1975). Functions, in this sense, are the
causal role capacities of parts that contribute to some capacity of the containing system.
If the part lacks the capacity, it lacks the function. A functional analysis' of the system
reveals functions'capacities or dispositionsof the parts; the analysis reveals how the
system operates or functions'. Call these causal-role functions, or just c-functions.
9
The etiological account was inspired by Larry Wright's (1973) article Functions' and
then developed independently along different lines by Millikan (1984, 2002), Karen
Neander (1991a, 1991b), Peter Godfrey-Smith (1994), and David Buller (1998, 2002),
among others. For a useful anthology, including challenging criticisms of the etiological
view, see Buller (1999).
10
There are (at least) four attractive features of the etiological account of functions. First,
as we have just seen, it gives an informative and non-circular account of normal
conditions and normal functions. Second, it underwrites teleological explanations;
something is there because of its function. Third, it accounts for the difference between
the function of an item and side effects that may be beneficial for the item or the user of
the item. The function of my nose involves affecting incoming air, but not to hold up my
glasses. The function of a large belt buckle in the Old West is to keep up trousers, and
maybe also to display social status, but not to stop bullets during a shoot-out at the corral.
Fourth, it explains malfunction. A diseased or deformed heart still has the function of
pumping blood even if it cannot, for the heart is there because its ancestors pumped
blood. A broken belt buckle is still supposed to hold up trousers, for it was reproduced on
the model of buckles that did.
1
Angus Ross (1986) and Richard Moran (2006) both resist the idea that acts of telling
should routinely be viewed as constituting evidence for the thing told for reasons
associated with the fact that acts of telling are acts freely undertaken by the speaker. My
conception of evidence is more minimal than theirs and I agree with them that the
epistemology of testimony should not be assimilated to the epistemology of empirical
evidence in general.
2
Such a view is treated sympathetically in Fumerton (2006). See especially p. 80.
3
The epistemological framework for the present discussion is developed at greater length
in my contribution to Pritchard, Millar, and Haddock (2010). There is some overlap
between this chapter and the last of the chapters in that contribution, though the treatment
of testimony here is somewhat fuller.
4
Acts of saying that p should be taken to include cases in which the informant simply
says, Yes', when asked whether p. Likewise, saying, No, in response to an enquiry
whether p, should be taken to be an act of saying that not-p.
5
In what follows I draw on an account of practices developed in Millar (2004).
7
When, as in Williamson (2000), it is said that there is a knowledge-rule for assertion
assert that p only if you know that pis assertion being understood broadly to encompass
declarative utterances that include advice and expressions of opinion or more narrowly so
that it is close to what I am calling telling? If the former then it seems to me that there is
no knowledge-rule for assertion. But what I am calling telling might be what some
theorists call assertion.
8
An example of this sort is considered in Welbourne (2001: 102).
9
Further refinements are required. Practices do not exist in isolation and so wider
considerations might dictate that one sticks with a practice while flouting the rules. (See
Millar (2004: ch. 3)). My thinking on commitments is much influenced by John Broome's
work. See, for instance, Broome (2002). However, his larger framework should not be
read into mine and I do not suggest that he would endorse the ideas presented here.
10
Compare McDowell (1984: esp. sections 1112). Mulhall (1990: especially ch. 4) is
instructive on the problems of explaining the understanding of utterances, on the model
of interpreting sounds conceived as devoid of meaning.
11
When corrected for misusing the term arthritis', Burge's (1979) patient does not
respond by saying that what he means by arthritis' is different. He adjusts his usage.
12
I put the notion of recognitional ability to work in Millar (2007a, 2007b, 2008), and in
my contribution to Pritchard, Millar, and Haddock (2010).
13
But see M. Fricker (2003).
14
Richard Fumerton thinks that the following is probably right: The meanings of
sounds or marks are to be found in the head, or better in the minds, of those who produce
those sounds and marks. To interpret reasonably those sounds or marks we now need to
solve the problem of other minds. . . . When the language we are interpreting is our
ownwithout begging the question, when the sounds or marks appear to be of the same
type as those we ourselves use to express thoughtsone might suppose that our best
hope is to rely on some version of an argument from analogy or an argument to the best
explanation (2006: 83).
15
On this see McDowell (1981, 1982). For related discussion of the scope of perceptual
knowledge, see Millar (2000).
16
The importance of discrimination for perceptual knowledge is emphasized in Goldman
(1976). Here I am emphasizing its importance for knowledge of what phenomena
indicate.
17
This is in keeping with Miranda Fricker's (2003) emphasis on the importance of a
testimonial sensibility.
18
This is the truth behind, what might be called, defaultist accounts of the epistemology
of testimony. J. L. Austin, for instance, writes, It is fundamental in talking (as in other
matters) that we are entitled to trust others, except insofar there is some concrete reason
to distrust them (1946, 1979: 82). H. H. Price discusses the maxim: Believe what you
are told by others unless or until you have reasons for doubting it (Price 1969: 124).
Tyler Burge advances the principle that we are entitled to accept as true something that
is presented as true and that is intelligible to [us], unless there are stronger reasons not to
do so (1993: 467). Michael Welbourne says that the [by implication appropriate] default
response to testimony is to accept what we are told (2001: 1045). For criticism of this
type of position, see E. Fricker (1994). For criticism of Fricker, see Goldberg and
Henderson (2006). For Fricker's defence, see Fricker (2006). My own position does not
invoke the idea that the appropriate default stance to testimony is acceptance. I doubt that
an adequate epistemology of testimony is delivered solely by highly general
considerations about speech acts or about presuppositions of rational communication.
19
Elizabeth Fricker (1994) thinks of trustworthiness as having these two components.
Much of what I say is in the spirit of her account though, unlike her, I am not working
within the framework of a conception of knowledge as built out of justified true belief.
20
This is more fully explored in Millar (2008).
21
I borrow the example from Travis (2005), which has helped to shape my own thinking.
22
This sort of case is discussed by Jennifer Lackey (2007) who takes it to yield
knowledge.
23
Jonathan Adler emphasizes that [o]nce testimony is accepted, there are many sources
which come into play which supply additional grounds relevant to the warrant for the
belief (1994: 266). That is surely right. My point is rather different since it concerns the
role of repeated encounters with sources of information, not in furnishing us with more
evidence supporting something acquired from testimony, but in inculcating factual
knowledge that amounts to little more than an ability to recall or acknowledge a publicly
available known fact.
24
The kind of knowledge under discussion is more fully explored in my contribution to
Pritchard, Millar, and Haddock (2010) under the heading detached standing knowledge.
25
I am grateful to the audiences at the Stirling Social Epistemology conference and at the
University of Manchester for helpful discussion of the issues addressed in this chapter. I
have benefited enormously from frequent discussions with Adrian Haddock, Duncan
Pritchard, and colleagues at Stirling. Thanks are due to the University of Stirling for
research leave during which this chapter was initially drafted and to Department of
Philosophy for further support.
1
See Burge (1993, 1997, 1999).
2
See e.g. Christensen and Kornblith (1997) and Malmgren (2006). The anti-Burgean
view that Christensen and Kornblith and Malmgren all defendthe view that all
testimonially preserved warrant is a posterioriis a widely received view in the
epistemology of testimony.
3
For Burge's articulation of this teleological picture, see Burge (2003: 5056). Burge
acknowledges the great similarity between his own teleological picture and those offered
by Sosa (1991) and Plantinga (1993).
4
I think that any being that has entitlements to beliefs must have justifications for some
other beliefsor at least must be capable of having justificatory support for some other
beliefs. For I think that having beliefs requires being able to carry out inferences, and the
relevant inferences must sometimes support beliefs. Inferentially supported beliefs are
justified, or are at least backed by beliefs that are capable of justifying them. Higher non-
linguistic animals have reasons or justifications for some of their beliefs in this sense
(Burge 2003: 5045 n.1).
5
See the last sentence of the passage from Burge (2003) quoted in note 4 above.
6
See especially his contrast between the preservative and substantive role of memory in
Burge (1993: 4625).
7
I use the term presentation as true to cover more than assertions and judgments.
Obvious presuppositions, or conventional implicatures, are examples. When someone
says to kill the shortest spy, he or she presents it as true that there is a shortest spy. In
such cases, as well as the indicative cases, the entitlement to accept what is presented as
true can be independent for its justificational force of perceptual connection to context
(Burge 1993: 4823).
8
Of course, deaf people may communicate by means of visual sign language. And
perhaps it is possible for creatures to communicate by means of some extra-sensory
perception. The only feature of testimony that matters, for Burge's view, is that there is a
passage of propositional content from one mind to another (Burge 1993: 481), however
that may happen.
9
Since warrants (both entitlements and justifications) are typically, for Burge, defeasible,
I will drop the phrase prima facie when speaking of warrants throughout this paper:
warrants are all to be understood as prima facie, unless otherwise specified.
10
It is understanding whose exercise in particular instances does not require in those
instances perceptual warrant for the application of what is understood. A first
approximation elaboration is that it is conceptual understanding that does not require, in
thinking and understanding an intentional content, perceptual warrant for the de re
application of some aspect of the content (Burge 1997: 212).
11
Burge (1997: 22).
12
I am grateful to Yuval Avnur and Alan Millar for helpful comments on an earlier draft
of this chapter.
11 The Assurance View of Testimony
1
Epistemic justification is whatever kind is required for knowledge in those instances of
knowledge for which it requires justification.
2
For our purposes in this chapter, it does not matter just what testimony or testimonial
justification is. I address the question whether assurance is necessary or sufficient for
giving a non-evidential justification in cases we commonly call testimonial. To this end,
we can use the broadest disjunctive sense of testimony. For a good presentation of a
broad, disjunctive view of testimony, see Lackey (2008: ch. 1).
3
A non-reductive view would take testimonial epistemic reason-giving or justification to
be in part sui generis. A non-individualist view would take testimonial reason-giving or
justification to depend in part on conditions other than the belief p's being based on the
epistemically justified beliefs of the hearer. Examples of non-individualist views are the
transindividual reliability view, that testimonial epistemic justification depends a reliable
process of testimonial propagation and hearer uptake (Schmitt 1999; Goldberg 2007a:
esp. 20033), the social responsibility view, that it depends on the testifier's being
epistemically responsible in believing p (Owens 2000, 2006), and the transindividual
reasons view, that it depends on the testifier's possession of an epistemically good reason
to believe p (Schmitt 2006).
4
The view traces back to Ross (1986). Versions have been developed by Hinchman
(2005, forthcoming) and Moran (2005, 2006, unpublished). I focus here on Moran's
(2006). All page references to Moran not otherwise marked are to that article.
5
I take it that accepting the testifier's assurance that p is not the same as trusting the
testifier that p. Accepting is an act and entails an acknowledgement of the assurance and
a recognition that one accepts. Trusting is a disposition or a practice and does not entail
any acknowledgement of the assurance or even a recognition that one trusts. An
assurance view that requires the addressee's uptake for reason-giving should maintain that
accepting, not trusting, is necessary for reason-giving. Trusting may not always be
voluntary, but accepting is on an agreement version of the assurance view. This raises a
concern about this viewthat in some instances in which assurance gives a reason, the
addressee cannot be said to accept because uptake is involuntary. However, I will not
press this concern.
6
I use propositional and doxastic in application to justification in the senses familiar
from the literature stemming from Firth (1978).
7
I take it that assurance or its acceptance counts as giving an epistemic reason to believe
p just in case it gives a reason that, were it possessed by the addressee and good, would
contribute to the prima facie epistemic justification of the addressee's belief p. As far as I
can make out, Moran's formulation of the assurance view presupposes that assurance or
its acceptance counts as giving an epistemic reason to believe p just in case it gives a
reason that is epistemically assessable by the addressee, where this epistemic assessment
involves judging that the reason has an epistemically relevant feature. (That Moran takes
assurance to give a reason only if the reason it gives is epistemically assessable by the
addressee, as opposed to a third party evaluator, is shown by his remark that the
speaker's knowledge and trustworthiness is epistemically inert for the audience until the
question of the particular speech act or illocution is settled (Moran 2006: 289). The word
settled here can only mean answered by the audience.) For now I will treat the account
of giving an epistemic reason expressed in the first sentence of this note and Moran's
presupposition as equivalent, but where they come apart, the former must be preferred if
we are to relate the assurance view to the issue of non-reductive testimonial epistemic
justification that has driven the testimony literature.
8
A remark of Moran's (2006: 2723) suggests that he prefers the assurance view to the
reliability view of testimonial justification on the ground that testimony is often
unreliable. But this makes no sense. His own assurance view yields the non-sceptical
outcome that we have justified testimonially based beliefs only when the background
conditions of trustworthiness and reliability are satisfied. He cannot consistently support
his view as a non-sceptical alternative to the reliability view by appeal to the frequent
unreliability of testimony.
9
Moran identifies assuring that p with telling that p. But the relation between the two is
more complicated than he notes, since assurance often (if not always) comes in degrees
and telling never does. Possibly, telling is assuring to a sufficient degree. Are we to take
it that any degree of assurance involves the conditions Moran proposes for telling: a
presentation of the utterance as giving a reason, an offer of responsibility, and the like?
Possibly any sufficient degree of assurance does.
10
Hinchman (2005) differs from Moran in claiming that telling requires the addressee's
recognition that the teller, in asserting that p, intends the addressee to gain access to a
prima facie entitlement to believe p through this recognition (2005: 567). Moran does
not expressly deny that telling requires an intention to give the addressee a reason to
believe, nor that giving the addressee a reason to believe depends on a recognition of this
intention. But he does argue persuasively (Moran 2006: 28492) that the recognition of
such an intention is not sufficient to give a reason. It seems to me that an assurance view
should also reject Hinchman's claim that an intention or its recognition is necessary for
conferring access to an entitlement to believe: it should be enough that by inviting the
addressee to trust or offering to take responsibility, the addressee gains access to an
entitlement. An interpersonal offer, rather than a personal intention, should be sufficient
for making a reason available. The intention is at most a condition of the reason's being
good. If an intention is necessary for telling, then telling is not necessary for the sort of
assurance that suffices for making a reason available.
11
See note 3 for formulations of these views.
12
That Moran endorses this clause is indicated, for example, by the paragraph where he
asks how the speaker's words . . . acquire the status of a reason to believe something
(288, emphasis deleted and added).
13
That Moran endorses this clause is indicated, for example, by the paragraph where he
says: the idea is not that the speaker's words all by themselves' should count as a reason
for belief . . . As with the explicit assumption of responsibility that goes with making a
promise, its success will depend on the various conditions that go into the speaker's being
in a position to take on any such responsibility (289). Though Moran speaks at first of a
reason for belief, the success' to which he refers in the second sentence is most naturally
taken as success in giving a good epistemic reason. In this case, he is saying that giving a
good epistemic reason depends on the speaker's being in a position to take on a
responsibility. This fits the analogy with promising: a promise gives a practical reason to
rely on the promised action, but the promisor must be in a position to carry through or
take the consequences of not doing so if the practical reason for reliance is to be a good
one.
14
Moran speaks of responsibilities with respect to the belief in question. I assume that
he really intends that the testifier is epistemically responsible in asserting p, rather than in
believing p. For the testifier need not believe p for the testimony to give the addressee a
reason to believe p.
15
One might suggest that for Moran the assurance or its acceptance does not give the
epistemic reason but merely determines that the reason given (in virtue of the obtaining
of the background conditions) is epistemic. Some of his remarks suggest this alternative
view. I am not sure how to understand the difference between this view and the one I
attribute to Moran in the main body of the text. It seems that the objections I raise to the
view I attribute would apply to this view as well, if it really does differ from the former
view.
16
Candidates for such norms include the Norm of Veracity, that one has a prima facie
obligation to assure that p only if one takes p to be true, and the Norm of Credulity, that it
is prima facie permissible to trust any proposition one is assured of.
17
That Moran holds the offer-of-benefit variant rather than the actual agreement variant
is supported by many passages in the text. For example, The epistemic value of his [the
testifier's] words is something publicly conferred on them by the speaker (2006: 288)
suggests that the testifier's assurance by itself gives the addressee an epistemic reason to
believe p. And again, When an act of telling completes itself, speaker and audience are
aligned in this way through their mutual recognition of the speaker's role in determining
the kind of reason for belief that is up for acceptance, so that when the speaker is believed
there is a non-accidental relation between the reason presented and the reason accepted
(2006: 299300). This suggests that an act of telling can be completed regardless of
whether the speaker is believed, and it determines the kind of reason for belief, hence
gives the addressee an epistemic reason in virtue of the conditional rule of
correspondence (that when the speaker is believed . . . accepted) regardless of whether
the addressee accepts the assurance. Despite this, Moran needs to establish the actual
agreement view to show that reason-giving by assurance involves a personal relation.
Hinchman (2005: 572) endorses something similar to an actual agreement view: telling
together with the recognition of the intention in telling merely makes an entitlement
available; the addressee acquires an entitlement only by trusting the teller (a notion not
far from an acceptance generating an agreement).
18
That assurance entails assertion is supported by the observation that there seems to be a
contradiction in saying that I assure you that p but I don't assert that p. It isn't merely that
my saying that I don't assert p defeats any assurance I give by saying that I assure you
that p.
19
I agree with Moran that in these contexts, one does not normally acquire a
testimonially justified belief from assertion. But I do not think that this is because the
assertions fall short of assurance. Rather, it is because in persuasion and similar contexts
it is assumed that one will not believe the speaker merely because the speaker makes an
assertion. Even in such a context one could acquire a testimonially justified belief from
an assertion without treating the belief as evidenceor at any rate, without treating it as
evidence any more than one must to acquire a testimonially justified belief in a case of
assurance.
20
Moran seems to recognize the latter feature of assertion when he contrasts telling and
simply giving expression to what's on your mind (280). Of course one can assert a
proposition one doesn't believe. And this prompts the disjunctivist account of assertion:
assertion is either an expression of belief or a representation of oneself as believing. For
variants of the disjunctivist view, see Williams (2002: 74) and Owens (2006).
21
For the knowing variant, see e.g. Unger (1975: 25065), DeRose (1991), and
Williamson (2000: 2525). Moran's catalogue also tells against Brandom's suggestion
that asserting commits one to being able to vindicate the original claim by showing that
one is entitled to make it (Brandom 1994: 171). (Compare Hinchman's similar criticism
of Brandom in Hinchman 2005: 569 n.19.) Brandom's suggestion is not even true of
assurance.
22
Owens (2006) gives the example of a secret diary. Such a diary may be full of
assertions without my addressing them even to my future self (I might know that I will
never read the diary).
23
Moran (2006: 292, 2978), and Hinchman (2005: 587). The analogy traces back to J.
L. Austin (1946: 100).
24
Moran seems to think that my promising gives you a non-evidential epistemic reason to
believe that I will perform the action. I have no decisive objection to this, but I see no
reason to think it's true. Suppose I promise to do A, but you know that I don't often keep
my promises. I still owe it to you to do A, but you would be a fool to expect me to do it.
Moran could respond to this by saying that my promise gives you a prima facie epistemic
reason to believe I will do A, although this is defeated by your evidence that I will not do
A. But I don't find this response convincing.
25
I postpone the point that the norm of promising is second-personal or bipolar, while the
epistemic norm of testimony is not (Darwall 2006; Owens 2006). Owens argues the point
by appeal to overhearer cases: the overhearer gains the same epistemic reason to believe
from assurance that the addressee does; so the reason given by testimony is not
asymmetrical between second and third person, as required for bipolarity. Here I am
discussing only the analogy between promising and assuring.
26
Thus the term accepted promise is redundant: there is not even a promise unless the
promisor's offer is accepted by the promisee.
27
Compare Lackey (2008: 235).
28
Might one explain the difference between testifying and promising in this regard by
saying that variation in the degree of assurance affects only the evidence assurance
supplies, not the non-evidential reason it supplies? Then the quality of the epistemic
reason does not vary with the degree of assurance, once evidential considerations are
subtracted. This would restore the analogy with promising. But I can see no ground for
this. Plausibly, the quality of the epistemic reason given varies with the degree of
assurance even in the primitive case, where this variation cannot be explained by the
evidential role of the degree of assurance.
29
A remark of Moran's may suggest that he takes it that my presenting my utterance as
having an epistemic status suffices to give an epistemic reason to believe: If, unlike a
piece of evidence, the speaker's words have no independent epistemic value as a
phenomenon, then how do they acquire the status of a reason to believe something? It
seems that this can only be by virtue of the speaker's there and then explicitly presenting
his utterance as a reason to believe, with this presentation being accomplished in the act
of assertion itself (288). Moran seems to say here that my presenting my utterance as an
epistemic reason to believe p gives you an epistemic reason to believe p. But my
presenting my utterance as such a reason is by itself epistemically inerta mere
presentation is not an invitation or offer, and it makes no sense to speak of your accepting
my presentation. I take it that Moran really means to say that my offer to take
responsibility gives you a reason.
30
I set aside here the objection to the actual agreement view implicit in our discussion of
the first disanalogy with promising, that an acceptance, hence an actual agreement, is not
necessary to give an epistemic reason. I also set aside the objection implicit in the second
disanalogy with promising, that an actual agreement should give a good epistemic reason
if it gives any reason at all, and this rules out a two-tiered view on which the agreement
gives only a reason, not yet a good reason.
31
The reason you have to trust me can be overridden by reasons other than prudential
ones. For example, it can be overridden by a practical reason not to trust me that you
acquire from accepting a different invitation to trust. Suppose you accept my invitation to
trust me that p. But then someone invites you to trust her that q, and you accept that
invitation. Now you have commitments and prima facie reasons to trust me that p and to
trust her that q. But suppose it turns out that it's psychologically impossible for you both
to trust me that p and to trust her that q. These activities place incompatible demands on
your cognitive resources. For example, it might be that merely understanding q uses
resources that crowd out trusting that p. Note that q need not be a contrary of pit may
be any proposition trust in which places incompatible demands on your cognition. Then
one or both of the prima facie practical reasons the two invitations give you to trust are
overridden. You have an overriding practical reason at most to trust one of us, not to trust
each of us. Nothing like this can happen to your epistemic reason to believe. The
psychological impossibility of your trusting me that p and trusting her that q does not
entail that you do not have an overriding epistemic reason to believe each of these.
32
Could a proponent of the actual agreement view reply to the objection from differential
defeasibility by proposing that the invitation at issue sets special terms for trust: the trust
you are invited to show me is conditional only on epistemic considerations? That is, by
the terms of the invitation, you are invited to trust me no matter what countervailing
practical reasons you may acquire. If you accept this invitation, your reason to trust is
vulnerable only to defeat by epistemic reasons, not by practical reasonsas desired to
avoid the objection. In reply, I observe that we never do make such invitations. No
sensible person would accept an invitation to trust on the condition of ignoring
countervailing practical considerations.
33
But perhaps not enough for a guarantee that p or for an epistemic reason to believe that
p. Neither my taking epistemic responsibility for asserting p, nor the epistemic
responsibility of my assertion is enough for me to have an epistemic reason to believe p.
For these may obtain simply because I cannot help but believe p. But plausibly, what is
not enough for me to have a reason to believe is also not enough for you to have a reason
to believe, and not enough to guarantee that p.
34
Should one say that it is the offer or rather the prospect of the benefit that gives you a
reason to believe? Suppose you had good reason to doubt that I will follow through on
my offer. If this would prevent my assurance from giving you a reason, then it is the
prospect and not the offer that gives the reason.
35
This assurance view differs from the social responsibility view mentioned in note 3. On
the latter view, the hearer is justified in virtue of successfully passing epistemic
responsibility for the belief that p to the testifier. This requires only that there be some
recognized way of passing responsibility, not that a reason is given or that an offer is
made. On the assurance view, a reason is given in virtue of an offer of epistemic
responsibility.
36
One might interpret the second sentence of the quoted passage as saying that my
testimony gives you an epistemic reason to believe only in virtue of an actual, completed
agreement between us; whereas, on the proposal that promises the best defense of the
assurance view, my testimony gives you an epistemic reason to believe in virtue of my
offer, because my offer gives you a reason to accept my offer. But the sentence could
mean merely that my testimony gives you an epistemic reason to believe in virtue of my
offer and your potential acceptance, and this is consistent with the more promising
proposal I would prefer to attribute.
37
Unlike Lackey (2008: 2325), I don't think that Moran needs to maintain that when I
become responsible for asserting p, this transfers all responsibility for your belief from
you to me. It may be that I become responsible for your believing p; but you are still
responsible for believing me as to whether p. This seems to be enough to meet Lackey's
objection that even though I assume responsibility for my daughter's behaviour while she
plays at your house, she may still herself be irresponsible for breaking your vase.
38
Lackey (2008: 235) objects to Moran's proposal on the ground that I can take
responsibility only if I have epistemic competence. I can't say, I will take responsibility
for the proper functioning of this aircraft, and succeed in doing what I offer to do, unless
I am competent to run the aircraft. It's not clear to me whether to take responsibility I
must actually be competent or merely that everyone must justifiedly believe me to be so.
But the latter is still enough to object to the proposal that taking responsibility is enough
to give a reason. However, Moran doesn't make this proposal. Rather, he proposes that in
assurance, I make an offer to be responsible for the truth of p in a sense that entails only
making reparations if p turns out to be false, and that this offer gives an epistemic reason.
This offer does not commit me to taking responsibility in a way that requires competence.
Of course there is a serious question how this could be enough for giving an epistemic
reason.
39
Of course I do not deny that an offer to take future responsibility for a present assertion
can be sensible under certain conditions. You may have reason to accept this offer if you
don't care whether there is reason to believe p, but do want compensation should it turn
out that there is no reason to believe it.
40
See also Owens (2006).
41
Hinchman (forthcoming: section II) draws the opposite lesson from the overhearer
case: that Moran's view does not deliver what is wanted from an assurance viewa
difference in the reason given to Kate and Earlbecause the relation of assurance and
acceptance merely depends on self-presentation and its recognition, and this recognition
is available to Earl. Hinchman proposes to remedy this deficiency by making the reason
given depend on the testifier's responsiveness to the addressee's epistemic needs. More
exactly, the assurance makes the reason available because it is governed by norms that
require the responsiveness. Hinchman allows that an unresponsive testifier still gives a
reason in virtue of the fact that the assurance is so governed. I cannot address here this
interesting version of the assurance view.
42
Ross (1986: 79).
43
The assertion view is quite close to Lackey's (2008: ch. 3) statement view of testimony,
although her target is testimonial knowledge, not reason-giving. Lackey motivates the
statement view with the case of the Creationist Teacher. I think that the teacher must be
taken to assert evolutionary theory (despite not believing it) if she is to give a testimonial
reason to believe p. If we identify statement with assertion, then Lackey's reliabilist
statement view entails the assertion view (on the plausible assumption that testimonial
knowledge-transfer entails testimonial reason-giving). The assertion view is also close to
Owens' (2006) belief expression model of testimony. On this view, sincere assertion
transmits a rational belief to the hearer: if I rationally believe p, my testimony that p gives
you a reason to believe p by expressing my belief that p, provided that you trust what I
say by accepting it. (Owens ties this to the social responsibility view by taking a
transmission of rational belief to depend on passing epistemic responsibility from the
hearer to the testifier. See my (2006) for criticisms of the social responsibility view.)
Owens denies that an insincere assertion transmits a rational belief. Lackey's Creationist
Teacher case shows that this is too strong. Testimony can give a reason to believe p
without expressing belief. Insincere assertion, if tied to good reasons to believe in the
possession of the testifier, is enough to give a good reason to believe. Owens is right to
analogize testimony to memory, as I do in (2006), but the analogy does not require belief-
transmission, only reason-transmission, for which assertion is enough.
44
I suppose we should concede to Moran that in these non-assurance cases, the hearer is
given no reason to believe the testifier, only to hold the belief. But this can mean only
that in these cases the testimony gives no practical reason to believe (aiming at believing
what is truly or responsibly asserted). And this difference, as I have argued, is not
epistemically significant.
45
Should we seek to rule out cases of double-bluffing as giving non-reductive epistemic
reasons? Suppose I intend to produce in you the belief that I am going to Minsk by
anticipating that you mistrust me enough to reason that I am trying to deceive you into
thinking that I am not going to Minsk, and this causes you to believe that I am going to
Minsk. This is a case of assertion and, in some sense, the hearer's believing because the
testifier asserts. It is not a case of assurance (Moran 2006: 290). But I am inclined to
think that in the double-bluffing case I do give you a non-evidential testimonial epistemic
reason. Of course what justifies your belief is not this non-evidential reason but the
evidential reason from which you elaborately reason to your belief. That is to say, the
non-evidential reason merely propositionally justifies you in believing the proposition,
while the evidential reason doxastically justifies your belief. I thank Adam Leite for
bringing the relevance of the double-bluffing case to my attention.
46
The assertion view does not hold, as Moran does, that in any non-evidential testimonial
reason-giving, the hearer believes the testifier in the sense singled out by Moran. Denying
this is a consequence of covering the primitive cases. So any view that covers those cases
will deny it.
47
I would like to thank Ted Hinchman, Adam Leite, and two anonymous referees for
helpful comments on this chapter.
1
Below I will note that the relevant reliability is not the reporting-reliability of the
source (as when most of the sources' reports would be true), so much as it is the
coverage-reliability of the source (as when most of the relevant truths would be
reported).
2
What should be said of memory's preserving what was originally a testimonial belief? I
think these should be treated as compound cases, where one's epistemic reliance is on
another subject as information source, but where the preservation of the information is a
joint effort including both the testifier and the subject. The preservative role of the
testifier is this: she must preserve a content she originally acquired, and perform a speech
act that enables her audience to quickly and easily recover the content of the information
itself. That the testifier has a role in content preservation here should not obscure that the
subject herself also has such a role: the subject is relying on her own reliable
apprehension of the testimony that confronted her. As argued in Goldberg (2007b), this
reliability can be analysed as involving (i) reliability in discerning the force and content
of the speech act (reliable comprehension), and (ii) reliability in discriminating reliable
from unreliable testimony (reliable filtering).
3
It is to Burge (1993) that I owe my use of content preservation, as covering both
memory (or at least what Burge calls preservative memory) and testimony.
4
Indeed, it is precisely this point that motivates Goldman's well-known (1986) distinction
between belief-dependent and belief-independent processes.
5
This point, asserting the possibility of failing to come across testimony proffered by a
source we (standardly) rely on, is insignificant from the perspective of the usual issues
that come up in the epistemology of testimony. For the reliability of a source's testimony
is independent of how likely it is that her intended audience will come across that
testimony. However, if her intended audience is relying on her for coverage, the
likelihood that this audience will fail to come across her testimony is all-important. See
Goldberg (forthcoming a) for further discussion.
6
Thanks to Jesper Kallestrup for this suggestion.
7
I introduced these in Goldberg (forthcoming a).
8
I am assuming something like a reliabilist picture here. See Goldberg (2007b) for an
extended defence of this picture.
9
Where is some source on which subject S relies throughout interval i for coverage in
domain D, we can say that is silent regarding p (some proposition in D) throughout i
when throughout i has not issued any report that bears directly on the question whether
p. (To be sure, in the standard cases it is not the actual silence of a source, so much as it is
the subject's belief in that silence, that will be relevant to an assessment of subject's
beliefs formed on the basis of the (alleged) silence of a given source.) We have here the
core of the issue before us: when you believe that Jones did not regularly wear any bright
red suit, or that to date WMDs have not been found in Iraq, what is the epistemic bearing
on these beliefs of the (alleged) silence of a source on whom (or which) you relied for
reliable coverage?
10
The restriction to relevant truths makes this realistic. After all, even as venerable a
daily paper as the New York Times only promises to publish All of the News That's Fit
to Print.
11
In saying this I do not mean that testimony should be treated as evidence; that would be
a mistake for reasons developed in Goldberg (2006).
12
My nomenclature for claims is as follows: claims will be designated as (X-Y), where
the term substituting for X will tell which sort of reliance is in question (S' for reliance
on a Source, P for reliance on the part of the system that Preserves contents acquired by
the source), and the letter substituting for Y will tell what type of case it is (M for
Memory case, T for Testimony case).
13
To a first approximation, these cases might be analysed as follows. A belief is acquired
at t; this acquisition causes a modification in one's memory system (the belief is put in
memory; perhaps there is a process involving transmission first to short-term memory,
then to long-term memory); and this modification in the memory system is causally
responsible for the subsequent sustainment of a belief with a content distinct from the
original belief. Presumably, the sustained content is related to the original content in such
a way as not to elicit any suspicion of a content-shift on the part of the subject herself. (It
is noteworthy that some content externalists have theories of the semantics of memory on
which content-shifts of this sort are to be expected under certain conditions. See Ludlow
(1995), Gibbons (1996), and Goldberg (2007c) for a discussion.)
14
While such a possibility is clear in the abstract, it would appear to be a substantial
empirical question whether, and if so to what extent, human memory is susceptible to
such failures. Suppose p is a proposition that is originally the content of a belief we
acquired at some earlier time, but where memory shifts the content of this belief, so that
on recollection we have the memory impression that q (where q and p are logically
independent of one another). Then, when at some later time one considers whether p, it
may be that, despite the fact that one presently has no recollection of p , one still has the
sense that it would be wrong to conclude that p on this basis. So even if we do suffer
here from a failure of content-preservation, our so suffering would not incline us to form
the corresponding silence-based belief.
15
Here I note that (S-T) does not identify any particular source; it speaks only of one of
the sources on whom I rely.
16
In this respect the motto of the New York Times is noteworthy for its coverage-related
ambition: All of the News That's Fit to Print.
17
See Goldberg (forthcoming b) for a full presentation of this idea.
18
Of course, a justified silence-supported belief would also require S to be sensitive to
the likelihood that S herself would come across any relevant report were one to be made.
See Goldberg (forthcoming a).
19
See Goldberg (2007a: ch. 5) for details.
20
See e.g. Burge (1993), Dummett (1994), Christensen and Kornblith (1997), Lipton
(1998), Edwards (2003), Lackey (2005), and Goldberg and Henderson (2006).
21
I develop this claim at length in Goldberg (forthcoming b).
22
To make the case do the job I want it to do, we have to imagine that any relevant facts
would only be reported by the news sources on which you rely. No doubt, this
assumption is unrealistic. But cases are easily imaginable where such an assumption
would be realistic: suppose the topic is one where there are only few people interested in
the topic, and only one news source that covers such a topic, etc. I will disregard the
unrealistic nature of my example in what follows.
23
This is a point made in Lehrer (1997) as well as in Foley (2006).
24
Here, and in the suggestions that follow, I am indebted to Alan Millar for very helpful
comments.
25
I should perhaps acknowledge that, while I find the hypothesis of extended cognition to
be an intriguing one, I am dubious about its truth. I offer the present argument to those
who do not share my scepticism on this score.
26
That is, other people are not such repositories unless the subject herself testified to
them, and they go on to store the subject's information. This is not the sort of case we are
envisaging here.
27
Indeed, so far as I can tell, the epistemological issues surrounding the notion of
newsworthiness have received no attention whatsoever from epistemologists (as opposed
to folks in journalism schools). I regard this as a lacuna in the epistemology literature. I
hope to address this at some future time.
28
I would like to thank Frank Dring for suggesting to me the interest (for social
epistemology) of cases like the ones considered herewhere you reason that if such-and-
such were true, you would have heard about it by now. I would also like to thank the
members in the audience at a conference on Social Epistemology at Stirling University,
where I presented a paper on a similar theme: Jessica Brown, Igor Douven, Miranda
Fricker, Alvin Goldman, Peter Graham, Klemens Kappell, Jon Kvanvig, Jennifer Lackey,
Peter Lipton, Nenad Miscevic, Alan Millar, Erik Olsson, Duncan Pritchard, Ernie Sosa,
and Finn Spicer, for particular comments on that paper. Special thanks to Jasper
Kallestrup, who served as my commentator at that conference, and whose suggestions
inform the present chapter in a variety of ways; and to Alan Millar, for extensive
comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.
13 Epistemic Circularity and Epistemic Incommensurability
1
See Alston (1989), Sosa (1997a, 1997b). For a novel defence of this strategy that links
externalism to Reidian common-sensism, see Bergmann (2004). Reed (2006) offers a
criticism of Bergmann's position.
2
See e.g. Fumerton (1995), Stroud (1994), and Pritchard (2005).
3
This is one of the lessons that can be drawn from S. Cohen's (2002) well-known
discussion in Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge. Cohen himself is
targeting the notion of basic knowledge in general.
4
I have defended the value of truth elsewhere, see Lynch (2004, 2009a, 2009b).
5
This illustrates a general lesson: where the methods in question each claim privileged
access to a special domain of facts, appeals to other principles will be apt to lead to non-
inferential principles that are themselves subject to epistemic circularity. Consider, to
take another example, where Hylas and Philo disagree about the only reliable method for
determining what is morally good. Hylas claims it is divine revelation; Philo rational
intuition. It is hard to see how mutual circularity can be avoided in such a case, since both
principles claim that a certain non-inferential method has privileged access to a restricted
domain of facts. Any other method will be rejected as not being capable of accessing
those facts.
6
For this reason, deep epistemic disagreements are not properly classed as what some
have come to call reasonable disagreements'. A reasonable disagreement in this sense is
one where each side recognizes that they are drawing equally reasonable but
incompatible conclusions from shared evidence. Deep epistemic disagreements don't fit
this model. For I can't say of someone who does not believe my FEP that we draw
distinct conclusions from shared evidence for the simple reason that I won't believe that
we share evidence if we don't share what counts as evidence. Think of a situation where
an advocate of divine revelation tells me that p. I doubt that p is the case because I doubt
that reliability of divine revelation. I may claim we have the same evidence, my opponent
will not.
7
Note the probably in the conclusion. The argument is deductive, but its conclusion
inherits its content from the abduction in the second premise.
8
Compare Thomas Nagel: To reason is to think systematically in ways anyone looking
over my shoulder ought to be able to recognize as correct (1997: 5). Here Nagel
oversteps: he suggests that reasoning itself (and therefore possessing a reason
presumably) requires that the reason so possessed be recognizable by anyone as a reason.
Not so: I can have a belief about my own mental states that may be a reason for some
other belief that could not possibly be recognized by you as a reason for the latter belief.
Nonetheless, the point holds where we are concerned with giving a reason, as opposed to
being or having a reason.
9
It would be like telling someone faced with a moral dilemma, where e.g. the demands of
utility clash with respect for persons, not to worry because, if you act on the correct
moral principles, you'll do the right thing. Thanks a lot.
10
For a non-factualist account, see H. Field (2001). Steven Hales (2006) discusses a
relativist solution to a similar problem.
11
See Pritchard (2005: 2459).
12
What I am calling the epistemic method game was first suggested to me by Eberhard
Herrmann; I am not sure he would approve of its use here, however.
13
This chapter has benefited from discussions at the University of St Andrews, the
University of Edinburgh, the Bled Epistemology Conference, and the University of
Connecticut. My thanks to Don Baxter, Tom Bontly, Matthew Chrisman, Patrick
Greenough, Terry Horgan, Scott Lehman, Alan Millar, Baron Reed, and, especially,
Duncan Pritchard for additional comments.
1
Or, perhaps more generally, what they need is not reason but justification, or, more
generally still, positive epistemic status; justification and reasons may perhaps provide
only some among the ways to gain such status. This footnote is intended to forestall
misinterpretation, allowing the main text latitude to proceed with the simplifying
assumption that reason is required, although we shall eventually find reason to reject
this as an oversimplification.
2
Feldman (2007) adopts the view under that label; see also Christensen (2007) and White
(2005) for additional support. Strictly speaking, it is not a body of evidence E that
justifies withholding. What matters is, rather, the fact that E is S's total evidence bearing
on p ; it is this fact that might justify S's withholding on p . Thus arises the question of
how to characterize the abstract relation of justifying so that it can apply equally in both
cases, both when it is believing that is justified, and when it is withholding. But we won't
tarry over this.
3
Suppose Pro does switch from believing to withholding, while Con holds his ground,
whereupon they disclose once again. What now is required of Pro? Plausibly, if neither of
them has acquired any independent reason to downgrade the other, each should take into
account the stance of the other, and the two should jointly settle on some intermediate
position. So, what is a position intermediate between Pro's withholding and Con's
disbelief? If Con now moves from disbelieving to withholding, this is just to join the
opposition, which seems wrong if they should really be splitting the difference. Is there
some position intermediate between withholding and disbelieving? Surprisingly enough,
it can be argued that there is: namely, deliberately abstaining both from positively
forbearing and also from disbelieving. Forbearing involves more, after all, than just not
believing. It is something more positive than that: namely, deliberately bringing it about
that one fails to believe. Is this now what they are both required to do: to abstain both
from disbelieving and from withholding? To occupy this position, then, one must
deliberately refrain from deliberately bringing about each (severally) of two outcomes:
that one believes not-p , and that one fails to believe not-p . Of course, one must either
believe or not believe. But one need not bring about either one of these. One might just
deliberately abstain from both options. Unfortunately, a closer look makes it doubtful that
there is any such coherent intermediate position. After all, if one deliberately abstains
from disbelieving and deliberately abstains from believing, that is tantamount to
positively forbearing. So one cannot abstain from both disbelieving and forbearing,
except by positively believing.
Here I will not press further along that path. Nor will I switch to a conception that
incorporates degrees of belief between 0 and 1, or even replaces the threefold structure of
attitudesbelief, withholding, and disbeliefwith a spectrum of degrees of confidence
between 0 and 1. Let us shelve such issues in favor of a focus on the stronger
disagreement where one of the parties affirms what the other denies. Can they both be
reasonable?
4
It might be argued that when a controversy is hoary, the key terms involved cannot have
different senses or meanings or proper interpretations, so that the participants could be
speaking past each other. And this is allegedly because the terms acquire their proper
senses, etc., from the aim of the disputants to participate in the traditional dispute. This I
do not find nearly as plausible as William James's view of a dispute by a campfire as to
whether a man goes around the squirrel who scurries around the tree always keeping the
tree between them as the man runs around full circle. The man goes first to the north,
then to the east, then to the south, and then to the west, and then back to the north of the
squirrel, so he goes around the squirrel in one sense. However, he fails to go around the
squirrel by failing to be first in front, then on one side, then in back, then on the other
side, and then back in front. Plausibly there are these two senses of going around, two
senses which no amount of firm intention to clash among disputants would seem to
remove. This approach fits also Hume's remark in his Enquiry, Section 8 that [f]rom this
circumstance alone, that a controversy has been long kept on foot, and remains still
undecided, we may presume, that there is some ambiguity in the expression, and that the
disputants affix different ideas to the terms employed in the controversy (Hume 2000:
62).
5
See Christensen (2007), Elga (2007), and Feldman (2006). For relevant disagreement,
see Kelly (2005), Rosen (2001), and van Inwagen (1996). I will side with the opposing
camp for the most part, though my reasons in what follows are multiply different from
those to be found in the earlier literature. Elga explicitly relates his rejection of
downgrading without independent reason to a certain well-known objection to
reliabilism, and he cites some of my own work in this connection. I agree that the
comparison is apt, and myself take the same position on both sides of it. In the earlier
work I defend the position as a solution to the Pyrrhonian problematic. In what follows I
defend the same position (or a close neighbour) on the epistemology of disagreement.
6
The restaurant and watch examples are Christensen's, the quad example Feldman's.
7
Here are some examples:
b. Epistemic peers with respect to a question are equals in regard to their familiarity with
the evidence and arguments which bear on that question, and . . . equals with respect to
general epistemic virtues such as intelligence, thoroughness, and freedom from bias
(Kelly 2005).
a. Epistemic peers are equals in regard to intelligence, perspicacity, honesty,
thoroughness, and other relevant epistemic virtues' (Gutting 1982: 83).
c. X and Y are epistemic peers with respect to a certain question if and only if conditional
on a disagreement arising between them on that question the two of them are equally
likely to be mistaken (Elga 2007). Elga insists that peerage on a specific question at a
specific time between two subjects, X and Y, requires his condition. For if one of them
is more likely to be right on that question at that time, then the two are not peers on
that question, regardless of how generally virtuous or specifically well informed that
subject may be. But how then are we to understand such likelihood? For example, if
it is likelihood relative to the information and virtues possessed by the thinker, then the
two definitions, Elga's and Kelly's, collapse into one. (Actually, we may need to add to
Kelly's definition that the two subjects not only possess those virtues, but employ them
equally as well. So let's take this to be implicit in that definition.)
8
We consider this question as posed through the present definition of peerage, even if we
might also find interest in parallel questions that use definitions less restricted to the
specific locus of the disagreement.
9
Elga's position is pleasingly clear and unambiguous: When you learn of your friend's
opposing judgment, you should think that the two of you are equally likely to be
correct . . . . If it were reasonable for you to give your own evaluation extra weightif it
were reasonable to be more than 50% confident that you are rightthen you would have
gotten some evidence that you are a better evaluator than your friend. But that is absurd
(Elga 2007).
10
Feldman argues persuasively that this sad outcome is to a large extent our fate.
11
Here in brief is part of the view, as stated by Elga: [With] respect to many
controversial issues, the associates who one counts as peers tend to have views that are
similar to one's own. That is why contrary to initial impressions the equal weight
view does not require one to suspend judgment on everything controversial (Elga 2007).
12
Rather than taking her views on the surrounding issues for granted, Ann should attend
to the larger disagreement between her and Beth: disagreement about a whole cluster of
issues linked to abortion (Elga 2007). Also: [Setting] . . . aside her reasoning about the
issues in the cluster, and setting aside Beth's opinions about those issues, Ann does not
think Beth would be just as likely as her to get things right. That is because there is no
fact of the matter about Ann's opinion of Beth, once so many of Ann's considerations
have been set aside. Hence the equal weight view does not require Ann to suspend
judgment about the cluster. That blocks the objection (Elga 2007).
13
Perhaps it will be contended that the relevant likelihood estimates are relativized. So it
might be held that what follows from our commitment to our likelihood of being right,
from our point of view, is the unlikelihood from our point of view, of someone else being
right if they contradict us. But that, it may be added, is trivial. The relevant issue for us,
it may then be concluded, the relevant more interesting issue, is that of whether our
opponent is likely to be right from their point of view. Perhaps. But if the relativization
here is to the evidence and competence of the subject, then if deep and broad
disagreement is compatible with different likelihood profiles for propositions under
dispute, so that one and the same proposition might be likely relative to S and unlikely
relative to S', then it must be that S and S' do not fully share their relevant evidence and
competence. So this would not be the sort of case that concerns us here at this stage.
14
According to Feldman (2006: 232) [p]erhaps the evidential relation can hold in the
absence of a believer's realization that it obtains. But once one thinks explicitly about the
topic, it becomes harder to see how it can remain reasonable to maintain belief once one
realizes that one has no good reason to think one's evidence supports that belief. In effect,
this realization serves as a defeater of whatever support the original evidence provided.
15
Here I have assumed that there are at least some possible cases of such disagreement,
where someone denies what to us is quite obvious. It might be thought that simple
arithmetic could never provide an example, but consider an adult learning arithmetic who
has nearly learned his arithmetical tables, but not quite. Can he not believe that, say,
6+7=14? Prior to delivering himself of that opinion, we might have held him a peer, if we
basically knew him as just a fellow adult. Indeed, independently of his unfortunate belief,
we might have no reason whatever to hold ourselves superior to him on matters of
arithmetic. Indeed, he might have been our dining companion in the original restaurant
example. So, if we now downgrade him it can only be based on the substance of the
disagreement, or so it would seem, in which case we have here a case of proper
downgrading based on the substance of a disagreement, even without any independent
reason to consider our opponent inferior.
16
I agree . . . that if I don't know now that I'm not dreaming, it follows that I don't know
that I am standing up, even if I both actually am and think that I am. But this first part of
the argument is a consideration which cuts both ways. For, if it is true, it follows that it is
also true that if I do know that I am standing up, then I do know that I am not dreaming. I
can therefore just as well argue: since I do know that I'm standing up, it follows that I do
know that I'm not dreaming; as my opponent can argue: since you don't know that you're
not dreaming, it follows that you don't know that you're standing up. The one argument is
just as good as the other, unless my opponent can give better reasons for asserting that I
don't know that I'm not dreaming, than I can give for asserting that I do know that I am
standing up (Moore 1959a: 247).
17
How am I to prove now that Here's one hand and here's another? I do not believe I
can do it. In order to do it, I should need to prove for one thing, as Descartes pointed out,
that I am not now dreaming. But how can I prove that I am not? I have, no doubt,
conclusive reasons for asserting that I am not now dreaming; I have conclusive evidence
that I am awake; but that is a very different thing from being able to prove it. I could not
tell you what all my evidence is; and I should require to do this at least, in order to give
you a proof (Moore 1959b: 149).
18
From J. L. Austin underline (1962: 489):
I may have the experience (dubbed delusive presumably) of dreaming that I am being
presented to the Pope. Could it be seriously suggested that having this dream is
qualitatively indistinguishable from actually being presented to the Pope? Quite
obviously not. After all, we have the phrase a dream-like quality; some waking
experiences are said to have this dream-like quality, and some artists and writers
occasionally try to impart it, usually with scant success, to their works. But of course, if
the fact here alleged were a fact, the phrase would be perfectly meaningless, because
applicable to everything. If dreams were not qualitatively different from waking
experiences, then every waking experience would be like a dream; the dream-like quality
would be, not difficult to capture, but impossible to avoid. It is true . . . that dreams are
narrated in the same terms as waking experiences: these terms, after all, are the best
terms we have; but it would be wildly wrong to conclude from this that what is narrated
in the two cases is exactly alike. When we are hit on the head we sometimes say that we
see stars'; but for all that, seeing stars when you are hit on the head is not qualitatively
indistinguishable from seeing stars when you look at the sky.
I know that in matters regarding the well-being of the body, all my senses report the truth
much more frequently than not. Also, I can almost always make use of more than one
sense to investigate the same thing; and in addition, I can use both my memory, which
connects present experiences with preceding ones, and my intellect, which has by now
examined all the causes of error. Accordingly, I should not have any further fears about
the falsity of what my senses tell me every day; on the contrary, the exaggerated doubts
of the last few days should be dismissed as laughable. This applies especially to the
principal reason for doubt, namely my inability to distinguish between being asleep and
being awake. For I now notice that there is a vast difference between the two, in that
dreams are never linked by memory with all the other actions of life as waking
experiences are. If, while I am awake, anyone were suddenly to appear to me and then
disappear immediately, as happens in sleep, so that I could not see where he had come
from or where he had gone to, it would not be unreasonable for me to judge that he was a
ghost, or a vision created in my brain [. . . ] like those that are formed in the brain when I
sleep; (added in the French version), rather than a real man. But when I distinctly see
where things come from and where and when they come to me, and when I can connect
my perceptions of them with the whole of the rest of my life without a break, then I am
quite certain that when I encounter these things I am not asleep but awake. And I ought
not to have even the slightest doubt of their reality if, after calling upon all the senses as
well as my memory and my intellect in order to check them, I receive no conflicting
reports from any of these sources. For from the fact that God is not a deceiver it follows
that in cases like these I am completely free from error. But since the pressure of things to
be done does not always allow us to stop and make such a meticulous check, it must be
admitted that in this human life we are often liable to make mistakes about particular
things, and we must acknowledge the weakness of our nature. (Descartes 1984: 612)
19
An appendix takes up more fully the nature of Moore's disagreement with the sceptic.
20
Indeed, he takes his case to be worse than that: he thinks we can be sure that we cannot
fully expound our evidence. But our weaker claim holds nonetheless: his case is one
where we are unsure that we have fully expounded our evidence.
21
Presented at the Stirling Social Epistemology conference of August 2007, at a Brown
workshop of February 2008, and a Princeton workshop of April 2008, with helpful
discussion following on each occasion.
22
The proposition on which they disagree is essential to Moore's argument that he knows
he is not dreaming, though he would not likely regard any such argument as essential to
his knowledge that he is not dreaming, or perhaps even to his knowledge that he knows
he is not dreaming. A fuller treatment of Moore's epistemology constitutes the first
chapter of my Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Vol. II (Sosa
(2009)).
15 A Justificationist View of Disagreement's Epistemic Significance
1
Of course, I am not really biased in my holding this belief!
2
Much will depend on which epistemic asymmetries are here relevant; I shall address
this issue in detail later in this chapter.
3
I borrow this term from Thomas Kelly (2005) who, in turn, borrows it from Gutting
(1982). I shall later give a more precise characterization of what is involved in being
epistemic peers.
4
See also van Inwagen (1996).
5
When I speak merely of peer disagreement I mean disagreement between epistemic
peers.
6
I borrow the phrase extra weight from Elga (2007).
7
See also Wedgwood (2007: 262).
8
There are passages in Fumerton (2010) that also echo egocentric nonconformism.
9
For a different version of nonconformism, one that combines a principle of epistemic
conservatism with an appeal to the underdetermination of theory by evidence, see Moffett
(2007).
10
In other words, the conformist claims that one cannot downgrade the epistemic status
of one's peer merely because of the disagreement in question itself; one must have an
independent reason for so downgrading. Thus, Adam Elga writes, Suppose that . . . you
and your friend are to judge the truth of a claim, based on the same batch of
evidence . . . . Without some antecedent reason to think that you are a better evaluator,
the disagreements between you and your friend are no evidence that she has made most
of the mistakes (Elga 2007: 487, emphasis added).
11
Full disclosure, according to Feldman, occurs when the parties to the disagreement
have thoroughly discussed the issues. They know each other's reasons and arguments,
and that the other person has come to a competing conclusion after examining the same
information (Feldman 2006: 220).
12
In particular, he argues that when faced with peer disagreement, (1) I should assess
explanations for the disagreement in a way that's independent of my reasoning on the
matter under dispute, and (2) to the extent that this sort of assessment provides reason for
me to think that the explanation in terms of my own error is as good as that in terms of
my friend's error, I should move my belief toward my friend's' (Christensen 2007: 199).
13
Even more precisely, Elga writes: Equal weight view: Upon finding out that an
advisor disagrees, your probability that you are right should equal your prior conditional
probability that you would be right. Prior to what? Prior to your thinking through the
disputed issue, and finding out what the advisor thinks of it. Conditional on what? On
whatever you have learned about the circumstances of the disagreement (Elga 2007:
490).
14
A possible exception is van Inwagen (1996, 2010), who focuses specifically on
disagreements that are matters of interminable debate (1996: 141), such as those found
in philosophy, politics, and religion. I should mention, however, that van Inwagen fails to
offer any general arguments or principles to justify treating various kinds of disagreement
differently.
15
I borrow this term from Christensen (2007).
16
Christensen calls this Cognitive Parity.
17
Adam Elga offers an alternative characterization, according to which you count
someone as an epistemic peer if you think that, conditional on a disagreement arising,
the two of you are equally likely to be mistaken (2007: 487). Elga defends his non-
standard usage of epistemic peer on the following grounds:
On more standard usages, an epistemic peer is defined to be an equal with respect to such
factors as intelligence, perspicacity, honesty, thoroughness, and other relevant epistemic
virtues' (Gutting 1982: 83), familiarity with the evidence and arguments which bear on
[the relevant] question, and general epistemic virtues such as intelligence,
thoughtfulness, and freedom from bias' (Kelly 2005). In defense of my use, suppose that
you think that conditional on the two of you disagreeing about a claim, your friend is
more likely than you are to be mistaken. Then however intelligent, perspicacious, honest,
thorough, well-informed, and unbiased you may think your friend is, it would seem odd
to count her as an epistemic peer with respect to that claim, at least on that occasion.
(Elga 2007: 499 n. 21)
Now, even if Elga's criticism of the standard use of epistemic peer is correct, it would
not apply to my characterization in the text since I specify that A and B are both
evidential and cognitive equals relative to the question whether p. Thus, according to my
use of epistemic peer, two people could not be evidential and cognitive equals with
respect to the question whether p and yet deviate in their likelihood to be mistaken
regarding this question.
There are, however, independent reasons to question Elga's non-standard use of this term.
For on his account, two people could radically differ in both their evidential backgrounds
and their cognitive abilities with respect to the question whether p, yet nonetheless turn
out to be epistemic peers regarding this question. For instance, I may be a complete
novice with respect to identifying birds of prey, and you may be an expert ornithologist.
When I am sober and you are highly intoxicated, however, we may be equally likely to be
mistaken about whether the bird flying overhead is an osprey. On Elga's account, then,
you and I would be epistemic peers with respect to this question, but this strikes me as
quite a counter-intuitive result.
18
It is unclear whether full disclosure for Feldman includes that A and B both know that
all of the evidence relevant to the question whether p has been shared, but I will assume
that this is the case at this point. Later in this chapter, I will consider the epistemic
significance of less idealized forms of disagreement.
19
More precisely, this condition (and the one to follow in my characterization of ordinary
disagreement) should be expressed as follows:
(2*) prior to recognizing that this is so, A and B would take themselves to be epistemic
peers with respect to this question, were they presented with the relevant concepts and
definitions involved in being such peers.
This version of the condition makes clear that the relevant parties need not literally
possess the concepts of evidential equality, cognitive equality, and full disclosure in order
to participate in a disagreement; it is sufficient that such parties would regard one another
as epistemic peers, were they in possession of these concepts. For ease of expression,
however, I shall stick with the less cumbersome formulation found in (2), leaving the
reader to interpret it along the lines found in (2*).
20
Otherwise put, A and B disagree in an ordinary sense if and only if, relative to the
question whether p, (1) A and B are aware that they hold differing doxastic attitudes, and
(2) prior to recognizing that this is so, A and B are not aware of any relevant epistemic
asymmetry between their situations.
21
What about cases where the parties to the debate should take one another to be
epistemic peers, but do not? Such cases may raise all sorts of interesting epistemological
questions about egoism, dogmatism, irrationality, and the like. But these issues seem
rather independent of the epistemic significance of disagreement itself, and thus lie
outside the scope of this chapter.
22
This may lead one to wonder whether there is a certain amount of talking past one
another taking place in this debate.
23
At the end of this section, I shall argue that this assumption is, in fact, incorrect.
24
For instance, recall that Rosen says, It should be obvious that reasonable people can
disagree, even when confronted with a single body of evidence . . . it would appear to be
a fact of epistemic life that a careful review of the evidence does not guarantee
consensus, even among thoughtful and otherwise rational investigators' (Rosen 2001: 71
2).
25
Recall, for instance, that Feldman writes, in situations of full disclosure, where there
are not evident asymmetries, the parties to the disagreement would be reasonable in
suspending judgement about the matter at hand. There are, in other words, no reasonable
disagreements after full disclosure (Feldman 2006: 235).
26
It is of interest to note that proponents of conformism often appeal to analogies with
non-agential instruments in an attempt to show the absurdity of nonconformist results.
For instance, Christensen provides the following example:
I look at my watch, a one-year-old Acme that has worked fine so far, and see that it says
4:10. Simultaneously, however, my friend consults her watchalso a one-year-old Acme
with a fine track recordand it reads 4:20. When she tells me this, it clearly gives me
new evidence that her watch is fast: I should not trust her watch as much as I would have
before finding out that it disagreed with mine. But just as clearly, I've just gotten new
evidence that my watch is slow, and this should diminish my trust in it. In this case, it's
obvious that the fact that one of the watches is on my wrist does not introduce an
epistemically relevant asymmetry. (2007: 196)
Feldman (2006: 234) makes a similar point appealing to different thermometers. The
intuition we are invited to share by conformists here is that, without a reason independent
of the disagreement in question for doing so, it is just as absurd to prefer my belief over
my peer's as it is to prefer the time my watch says over that of my friend's. But notice:
there are cases analogous to PERCEPTION involving non-agential instruments. Consider
the following:
WATCH: Sonya and I eat lunch together at a restaurant at noon, take a long walk around
the lake, shop at multiple stores, and read at the bookstore caf for several hours. I look
out the window, noticing that the sun is setting, and say, It is 7:45 PM, so we should get
going, after which Sonya responds, My watch says it is only 1:15 PM.
It seems clear to me in WATCH that, despite not having a reason independent of the
disagreement to prefer the time my watch says over that of Sonya's, I am rational in
regarding hers as the inaccurate one. For it is simply not at all plausible to think that we
could have eaten lunch, walked around the lake, gone shopping, and read for several
hours at the bookstore caf in an hour and fifteen minutes, nor is it likely that the sun
would be setting in Chicago at 1:15 in the afternoon. Thus, I take it that conformists fail
to garner the intuitive mileage that they hope to on behalf of their view from these sorts
of non-agential cases.
27
I should mention that Christensen (2007) and Elga (2007) consider a counterexample
to conformism that bears some similarities to those found here and attempt to show how
their respective views have the resources to rule out doxastic revision in such a case. In
Section 3 of this chapter, I shall consider their responses in some detail and argue that
they fail in various respects.
28
I borrow this phrase from Nathan Christiansen.
29
Perhaps this is why Kelly claims that to uncritically assume that things are perfectly
symmetrical with respect to all of the epistemically relevant considerations . . . is . . . to
subtly beg the question in favor of the skeptical view (2005: 1789).
30
Alvin Goldman makes a similar point in his (2010).
31
Henceforth, when I speak merely of disagreement, I mean ordinary disagreement.
32
See, for instance, Sosa (this volume, ch. 14).
33
I address this question in more detail in my (forthcoming).
34
It should be noted that there are two probabilities that need to be kept distinct: there is
(i) the subjective probability that p is true, and (ii) the subjective probability that I am
correct in my belief regarding p. Earlier in the chapter, the discussion focused on (i), but
now I am emphasizing (ii). It should be clear, however, that (i) and (ii) are intimately
related for the conformist. For instance, recall David Christensen's claim that, upon
discovering that I disagree with an epistemic peer, (1) I should assess explanations for
the disagreement in a way that's independent of my reasoning on the matter under
dispute, and (2) to the extent that this sort of assessment provides reason for me to think
that the explanation in terms of my own error is as good as that in terms of my friend's
error, I should move my belief toward my friend's' (Christensen 2007: 199). Here
Christensen is saying that in cases of peer disagreement, to the extent that I am willing to
assign a 50% probability both to my being correct in my belief regarding p and to my
epistemic peer's being correct, I should split the difference with my epistemic peer in the
degree to which I believe that p. Thus, the probabilities assigned with respect to (ii)
directly determine the probabilities that should be assigned with respect to (i).
35
I am grateful to Benjamin Almassi for this question.
36
What if the conformist were to respond that cases involving an asymmetry of access to
personal information are ones where I in fact have reason, independent of the ordinary
disagreement in question, to downgrade my opponent? (I am grateful to David
Christensen for this type of response.) Given this, the conformist could grant the intuition
that no doxastic revision is required in PERCEPTION, ELEMENTARY MATH, and
DIRECTIONS, but then deny that it is a problem for her view. By way of response to this
line of thought, notice that such a move has the consequence that there are virtually no
actual instances of the kind of disagreement to which the conformist view purportedly
applies. For in nearly all cases of ordinary disagreement, there is some sort of asymmetry
of personal information. How often, for instance, do I know to the same extent as I do in
my own case that my opponent is not distracted, sleep-deprived, melancholy, and so on?
Not very often (if ever). But then, given the response under consideration, it would turn
out that there are virtually no cases of actual disagreement where equal weight should be
given to both my view and my opponent's and, hence, it would turn out that there are
virtually no cases where disagreeing peers are rationally required to doxastically
conform. This, I take it, is an unwelcome result for conformism.
37
A further defence of conformism frequently found in the literature appeals to the
following:
The Uniqueness Thesis: A body of evidence, E, justifies at most one doxastic attitude
i.e. believing, disbelieving, suspending judgementtoward any particular proposition.
Indeed, Kelly (forthcoming) argues that a commitment to The Equal Weight View
carries with it a commitment to The Uniqueness Thesis' (forthcoming: ms, p. 11). For
proponents of this thesis, see White (2005), Feldman (2006, 2007), and Christensen
(2007). While it lies outside the scope of this chapter to discuss The Uniqueness Thesis,
let me say that none of the arguments I make here depends directly on its truth or falsity.
38
See Christensen (2007: 193). I have slightly modified inessential details of
Christensen's case, but all of the elements central to the conclusion about disagreement
are the same.
39
I am assuming that Ramona and I each asserting that we have carefully performed the
relevant calculations in our heads suffices for us to have reason to believe that full
disclosure has taken place. I should say, however, that the condition of full disclosure
itself can be fleshed out in more or less idealized ways. For instance, at one end of the
spectrum, it may be required that each of us provides all of the details of our respective
calculations to one another. In this case, we again face problems making sense of the
possibility of the disagreement. For if we have each gone step by step with one another
through our fairly elementary calculations, what room is left for us to continue to
disagree about the amount owed? At the other end of the spectrum, full disclosure may
require nothing more than each of us asserting that we have arrived at the conclusion in
question. But then this does not add anything significant to the initial disagreement. Thus,
I think it is best to understand full disclosure as falling somewhere in the middle, which is
what I have built into BILL CALCULATION.
40
By a belief enjoying a very high degree of justified confidence I mean a very
confident belief that is highly justified.
41
In my (forthcoming), I provide a far more detailed defence of my justificationist view
that adds crucial further conditions to the above two principles. In particular, I argue that
no doxastic revision is necessary if there is either a highly justified target or protecting
belief, and that substantial doxastic revision is required if there is neither a highly
justified target nor protecting belief. A's belief that p is protected by A's belief that q if
and only if both A's belief that p and A's belief that q are members of a subset of A's
beliefs, each of which is challenged by the same instance of ordinary disagreement with
B, and where A's belief that q is highly justified and confidently held.
42
I am grateful to Nikolaj Jang Pedersen for raising this sort of question to my account.
43
This reliability condition is certainly compatible with a subjective rationality constraint
being necessary for justification as well. For more on this, see my (2008).
44
Or, at least, roughly equal in terms of reliability or truth-conduciveness.
45
It should be noted that while Christensen (2007) and Elga (2007) both try to
accommodate the intuitions elicited by cases such as PERCEPTION and DIRECTIONS
within their conformist framework, Feldman (2006, 2007) instead tries to show that his
view delivers the correct result in such situations: both parties should indeed withhold
belief with respect to the question under dispute.
46
In a similar spirit, Christensen (2007) argues that in order for Mia to have reached such
an absurd answer, it is plausible for me to think that she must have failed to use a highly
reliable, commonsense method of checking her results. Since I am confident that I did use
such a reliable method, I do not have to engage in any doxastic revision in the face of our
disagreement.
47
The only possible exception to this claim is ELEMENTARY MATH, where it may be
argued that denying that 2 + 2 equals 4 is insane in and of itself. I am inclined to think
that this claim of insanity, too, makes sense only against the background of one's
extraordinarily justified belief that 2 + 2 does equal 4. But even if one does not share my
view here, the conformist is still left with the problem of explaining why doxastic
revision is not intuitively required in PERCEPTION, DIRECTIONS, and EXTREME
BILL CALCULATION in a way that does not appeal to the notion of justification.
48
For helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper, I am grateful to Larry BonJour,
David Christensen, Jeremy Fantl, Richard Feldman, Richard Fumerton, Peter Graham,
Jon Kvanvig, Matt McGrath, Nikolaj Jang Pedersen, Blake Roeber, Andrew Rotondo,
Ernie Sosa, Peter van Inwagen, audience members at the University of Washington, the
Social Epistemology Conference at the University of Stirling, the Disagreement
Conference at the University of Calgary, the 2007 meeting of the Eastern APA in
Baltimore, Brown University, the University of St Andrews, and, especially, to Baron
Reed.
Bibliography
social constructionism 3
social epistemology 1 , 2 , 30 , 36 , 51 , 91 , 113 , 116 , 1268 , 256
expansionist 1525
naturalized 44
preservationist 515
revisionist 35
social identity 523
social imaginery 335 , 449
socialization 260
social systems 1826 , 723 , 169
Sosa, E. 7 , 31n. , 113n. , 150n. , 195n. , 263n. , 312
Sperber, D. 152n. , 160n. , 161 , 162n. , 1667 , 1712
Sripada, C. S. 139n.
Stanley, J. 10 , 113n. , 126n.
State of Nature see epistemic State of Nature
Steup, M. 31n.
Stevenson, C. 115n.
Stich, S. 70n. , 139n.
Stroud, B. 263n.
subjugated knowledges 48
supervenience 93
Sullivan, S. 48n.
Swamping Problem 89111
Talisse, R. 24
Tanesini, A. 63n.
time 53 , 54 , 658 , 2901
telling, as a speech act 131 , 17592 , 218n. , 221n. , 223n.
testimony 6 , 1920 , 2933 , 3849 , 1407 , 17592 , 14953 , 171 , 194 , 199203 ,
208 , 212 , 24355 , 2601
assertion view of 23941
assurance view of 21642
agreement version 217n. , 2201
communicative norm version 2201
beliefs based on 149 , 151n.
belief expression model of 239n.
defaultist view of 188n. , 191
statement view of 239n.
straightforward cases of 1757 , 18893
Thompson, D. 24
Timmons, M. 116n.
Tomasello, M. 166n , 171
Toulmin, S. 13n.
Travis, C. 190n.
Trout, J. 70n.
trust 789 , 217n. , 22641 see also norm(s) (of trust)
trustworthiness 11 , 33 , 18890 , 218n. , 21920 see also norm(s) (of trustworthiness)
truth 768 , 264n.
truth-telling 1302 , 136 , 162n.
Tuana, N. 48n.
Tuomela, R. 15
Unger, P. 12n. , 113n. , 148 , 223n.
uniformity 3025 , 321
value 23 , 1405
extrinsic 1036
final 10311
instrumental 116 , 1412
intrinsic 1036 , 1415
Moorean conception of 1045
as response-dependent 10710 see also knowledge (value of)
Van Inwagen, P. 282n. , 299n. , 302n. , 304
Wagner, C. 7
Warfield, T. 7
warrant 14858 , 169 , 173 , 194203 , 20813 , 271
a priori 1989 , 20512
preservation of 199201 , 212
Wedgwood, R. 123n. , 299
Weinburg, J. 70n.
Welbourne, M. 313 , 37 , 48 , 60n. , 179n. , 188n.
White, R. 279n.
Wiggins, D. 109n.
Williams, B. 60n. , 66n. , 70 , 81 , 131 , 1407
Williams, M. 12 , 549 , 618 , 113n.
Williams, P. J. 29 , 324 , 378 , 46 , 49
Williamson, T. 12n. , 90n. , 113n. , 126n. , 179n. , 223n.
Wittgenstein, L. 12 , 32 , 47 , 70
Woods, J. 13n.
Woolgar, S. 3
Wright, C. 45 , 271
Wright, L. 154n.
Zagzebski, L. 113n.