Categorical Syllogisms The Structure of Syllogism
Categorical Syllogisms The Structure of Syllogism
Standard Form
In order to make obvious the similarities of structure shared by different syllogisms, we will
always present each of them in the same fashion. A categorical syllogism in standard
form always begins with the premises, major first and then minor, and then finishes with the
conclusion. Thus, the example above is already in standard form. Although arguments in
ordinary language may be offered in a different arrangement, it is never difficult to restate them
in standard form. Once we've identified the conclusion which is to be placed in the final position,
whichever premise contains its predicate term must be the major premise that should be stated
first.
Medieval logicians devised a simple way of labelling the various forms in which a categorical
syllogism may occur by stating its mood and figure. The mood of a syllogism is simply a
statement of which categorical propositions (A, E, I, or O) it comprises, listed in the order in
which they appear in standard form. Thus, a syllogism with a mood of OAO has
an O proposition as its major premise, an A proposition as its minor premise, and
another O proposition as its conclusion; and EIO syllogism has an E major premise, and I minor
premise, and an O conclusion; etc.
Since there are four distinct versions of each syllogistic mood, however, we need to supplement
this labelling system with a statement of the figure of each, which is solely determined by the
position in which its middle term appears in the two premises: in a first-figure syllogism, the
middle term is the subject term of the major premise and the predicate term of the minor
premise; in second figure, the middle term is the predicate term of both premises; in third, the
subject term of both premises; and in fourth figure, the middle term appears as the predicate
term of the major premise and the subject term of the minor premise. (The four figures may be
easier to remember as a simple chart showing the position of the terms in each of the premises:
M P P M M P P M
1 \ 2 | 3 | 4 /
S M S M M S M S
All told, there are exactly 256 distinct forms of categorical syllogism: four kinds of major premise
multiplied by four kinds of minor premise multiplied by four kinds of conclusion multiplied by four
relative positions of the middle term. Used together, mood and figure provide a unique way of
describing the logical structure of each of them. Thus, for example, the argument "Some
merchants are pirates, and All merchants are swimmers, so Some swimmers are pirates" is
an IAI-3 syllogism, and any AEE-4 syllogism must exhibit the form "All P are M, and No M are
S, so No S are P."
Form and Validity
This method of differentiating syllogisms is significant because the validity of a categorical
syllogism depends solely upon its logical form. Remember our earlier definition: an argument
is validwhen, if its premises were true, then its conclusion would also have to be true. The
application of this definition in no way depends upon the content of a specific categorical
syllogism; it makes no difference whether the categorical terms it employs are "mammals,"
"terriers," and "dogs" or "sheep," "commuters," and "sandwiches." If a syllogism is valid, it is
impossible for its premises to be true while its conclusion is false, and that can be the case only
if there is something faulty in its general form.
Thus, the specific syllogisms that share any one of the 256 distinct syllogistic forms must either
all be valid or all be invalid, no matter what their content happens to be. Every syllogism of the
form AAA-1 is valid, for example, while all syllogisms of the form OEE-3 are invalid.
This suggests a fairly straightforward method of demonstrating the invalidity of any syllogism by
"logical analogy." If we can think of another syllogism which has the same mood and figure but
whose terms obviously make both premises true and the conclusion false, then it is evident that
all syllogisms of this form, including the one with which we began, must be invalid.
Thus, for example, it may be difficult at first glance to assess the validity of the argument:
All philosophers are professors.
All philosophers are logicians.
Therefore, All logicians are professors.
But since this is a categorical syllogism whose mood and figure are AAA-3, and since all
syllogisms of the same form are equally valid or invalid, its reliability must be the same as that of
the AAA-3syllogism:
All terriers are dogs.
All terriers are mammals.
Therefore, All mammals are dogs.
Both premises of this syllogism are true, while its conclusion is false, so it is clearly invalid. But
then all syllogisms of the AAA-3 form, including the one about logicians and professors, must
also be invalid.
This method of demonstrating the invalidity of categorical syllogisms is useful in many contexts;
even those who have not had the benefit of specialized training in formal logic will often
acknowledge the force of a logical analogy. The only problem is that the success of the method
depends upon our ability to invent appropriate cases, syllogisms of the same form that obviously
have true premises and a false conclusion. If I have tried for an hour to discover such a case,
then either there can be no such case because the syllogism is valid or I simply haven't looked
hard enough yet.
Diagramming Syllogisms
The modern interpretation offers a more efficient method of evaluating the validity of categorical
syllogisms. By combining the drawings of individual propositions, we can use Venn diagrams to
assess the validity of categorical syllogisms by following a simple three-step procedure:
1. First draw three overlapping circles and label them to represent the major, minor, and
middle terms of the syllogism.
2. Next, on this framework, draw the diagrams of both of the syllogism's premises.
o Always begin with a universal proposition, no matter whether it is the major or the
minor premise.
o Remember that in each case you will be using only two of the circles in each
case; ignore the third circle by making sure that your drawing (shading or )
straddles it.
3. Finally, without drawing anything else, look for the drawing of the conclusion. If the
syllogism is valid, then that drawing will already be done.
Since it perfectly models the relationships between classes that are at work in categorical logic,
this procedure always provides a demonstration of the validity or invalidity of any categorical
syllogism.
onsider, for example, how it could be applied, step by step, to an evaluation of a syllogism
of the EIO-3 mood and figure,
No M are P.
Some M are S.
Therefore, Some S are not P.
Now we add the minor premise to our drawing. The diagram for
"Some M are S" puts an inside the area where the M and S circles
overlap. But part of that area (the portion also inside the P circle) has
already been shaded, so our must be placed in the remaining portion.
Third, we stop drawing and merely look at our result. Ignoring the M circle entirely, we need
only ask whether the drawing of the conclusion "Some S are not P" has
already been drawn.
Remember, that drawing would be like the one at left, in which there
is an in the area inside the S circle but outside the P circle. Does that
already appear in the diagram on the right above? Yes, if the premises
have been drawn, then the conclusion is already drawn.
But this models a significant logical feature of the syllogism itself: if its premises are true,
then its conclusion must also be true. Any categorical syllogism of this form is valid.
Here are the diagrams of several other syllogistic forms. In each case, both of the premises
have already been drawn in the appropriate way, so if the drawing of the conclusion is already
drawn, the syllogism must be valid, and if it is not, the syllogism must be invalid.
AAA-1 (valid)
All M are P.
All S are M.
Therefore, All S are P.
AAA-3 (invalid)
All M are P.
All M are S.
Therefore, All S are P.
OAO-3 (valid)
Some M are not P.
All M are S.
Therefore, Some S are not P.
EOO-2 (invalid)
No P are M.
Some S are not M.
Therefore, Some S are not P.
IOO-1 (invalid)
Some M are P.
Some S are not M.
Therefore, Some S are not P.
Establishing Validity