Mikhail Lifshits - An Enigmatic Marxist - 2016
Mikhail Lifshits - An Enigmatic Marxist - 2016
Mikhail Lifshits - An Enigmatic Marxist - 2016
DOI 10.1007/s11212-016-9261-x
Mikhail Lifshits (Lifschitz, , 19051983), the Soviet friend and comradein-arms of Georg Lukacs has for a long time been a neglected figure, remembered in
the West mainly for his work The Philosophy of Art of Karl Marx. The English
translation of the book was published in 1938. Although it was republished in the
70s with a short but approving foreword by the distinguished English Marxist Terry
Eagleton, Lifshits has remained something of a private tip for the few initiated.1 As
late as 1997, Stanley Mitchell, who publishedat the request of Lifshits widow,
Lidia Reingardtin the Oxford Art Journal a long essay on Lifshits views on
aesthetics and philosophy, repeatedly pondered the question why is he not known
here(Mitchell 1997, 38). The situation quite obviously puzzled Mitchell, since,
given Lifshits original interpretation of Marxism, he should have been much more
well-known and esteemed not only in Russia, but elsewhere in the world. But no:
while Lukacs was able to enjoy worldly fame, Lifshits remained in oblivion.
In recent times, however, some changes in this situation are discernible, albeit
mostly in Russia only. It is probably too ambitious to speak of a Lifshits renaissance,
but nonetheless his disciples and followers have in the last few years, despite financial
difficulties and lack of interest on the part of the cultural establishment of present-day
Russia, managed to publish new editions of his writings (writings is here an
1
The first sketch of the book was published already in 1927; the English translation is based on the final
version Esteticheskie vzglyady Marksa, published in 1932. A reprint of the English edition by Pluto Press
came out in 1973, with a foreword by Terry Eagleton.
Helsinki, Finland
123
242
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
appropriate label, because Lifshits was more an essayist than an academic writer and
was not interested in producing large monographs). These publications include even
hitherto unknown texts from Lifshits vast archives, among other things his
correspondence with Georg Lukacs. Two volumes, consisting of Lifshits correspondence, have been described in a detailed review by Evgeni Pavlov in the latest issue of
Historical Materialism (Pavlov 2012, 187198).2 Another interesting publication is
the collection Nadoelo, published in 2012. It contains an extensive interview with
Lifshits accorded to the Hungarian Marxist Laszlo Sziklai in the 1970s, which
provides many valuable clues as to Lifshits views and intentions. Much, however,
remains still unpublished. According to his pupil Viktor Arslanov, in the Archives of
Russian Academy of Sciences there are some 700 files of notes, sketches, and other
materials waiting for publication (Arslanov 2010, 5). At the moment, there is no good
survey of the contents of the archives.
Lifshits book on Marxs aesthetics was indeed a pioneering work. It was written
in a constant struggle on two fronts: against vulgar sociologism, on the one side,
and the ultra-leftist Formalist tendencies, on the other. The so-called Plekhanov
orthodoxy had reduced the Marxist theory of art to a kind of sociology, and Soviet
Marxism in the 1920s mainly restricted itself to interpreting literature and art as
phenomena of the superstructure reflecting the economic basis. Against these
tendencies, Lifshits set as his task to reconstruct the genuine Marxist aesthetics from
disparate statements by Marx and Engels. However, as Terry Eagleton rightly
remarks, his aim was not to distill a separate philosophy of art from the corpus of
the classics of Marxism. Instead, he sets out to trace some crucial aesthetic themes
in Marxs work in terms of their integral relations to the developing totality of his
thought. In doing so, Lifshits showed, that far from being only some kind of
superstructure arising on the economic basis of society, the aesthetic moment is
present at all levels of Marxist theory; in fact, Marx had a close and continuous
engagement in imaginative production (Eagleton 1973, 8).
In the early 1930s the young Lifshits met Georg Lukacs in Moscow, and this
inaugurated a period of fruitful collaboration which lasted for several years. Both
Lifshits and Lukacs contributed on a regular basis to the journal Literaturnyi kritik. Its
first editor was the philosopher Pavel Yudin, who had earned his stripes in the
ideological campaign against the Menshevizing Idealism of the Deborinites a couple
of years earlier. Together with Mark Mitin, Yudin has gone into history as Stalins
The reviewed books of Lifshits are Mikhail Lifshits and G. Lukach, Perepiska 19311970, .:
Grundrisse 2011, and Pisma V. Dostalu, M. Mikhailovu, V. Arslanovu, .: Grundrisse, 2011. Other recent
publications of Lifshits by this small publishing house are Varia, M.: Grundrisse 2010, and Monten.
Vypiski i kommentarii, .: Grundrisse 2012, the latter containing materials of an unrealised book project
on Montaigne. Further publications: Problema Dostoevskogo (Razgovor s chrtom), M.: Akademicheskii
Proekt 2013, and Pochemu ja ne modernist? Filosoja. Estetika. Khudozhestvennaja kritika, M: Iskusstvo
XX vek 2009. Several years earlier by the financial support of the Aleksanteri Institute in Helsinki
was published Dialog s Evaldom Ilyenkovym, M: ProgressTraditsija 2003, which is a critical essay on
the philosophical ideas of Ilyenkov, especially the concept of the ideal, and Chto takoe klassika? M:
Iskusstvo XXI vek 2004, a collection of fragments from the extensive Lifshits Nachlass by Viktor
Arslanov. Finally, one should mention the volume on Lifshits, edited by Viktor Arslanov, which has been
published in the series Russian Philosophy of the Second Half of the twentieth Century (V. G. Arslanov
(ed.). Mikhail Aleksandrovich Lifshits, M: ROSSPEN 2010), containing i.a. a useful bibliography.
123
243
henchman in philosophy. The journal did not, however, directly continue this campaign
but represented a position Lifshits later calledwith an ironical pointthe Techenie
(Current). Although Deborin had been denounced as a Hegelian, Lukacs and Lifshits
developed a Marxist theory of art leaning even more on Hegel than Deborin had.
In the works of the Berlin master thinker Lifshits sought a historical dialectics,
the existence of which other Soviet philosophers had not noted (and in the West,
too, it was just beginning to come into fashion thanks to the lectures of Alexandre
Koje`ve in Paris). Much as Lenin consulted Hegel before taking important political
decisions in the years of the First World War and War Communism, so, too, does
Lifshits hope that it is possible to understand the logic of the post-revolutionary
development of Soviet culture with Hegels help. He writes:
The Hegel in the works of Deborin and his school was a scholastic philosopher
of minor interest, an abstract thinker [] Our interest in Hegel was of quite
dissimilar character. For us, what was important in the doctrine of the German
thinker was its real content and a deeply tragic relationship to the events of the
French Revolution and the post-revolutionary epoch. All this had many
smiliarities with the problems encountered those who have tried to make sense
of the immense historical changes which have taken place in our days (Lifshits
2012, 84).
The mission of the artist was, according to Lifshits, to depict in a veridical manner
these dramatic and contradictory changes. Of the novelists of the time, whose
production best corresponded to the aesthetic and political programme of the
Techenie, Andrei Platonov was the most important. And in fact Platonov
published several articles in the Literaturnyi kritik. However, the journal was closed
already in 1940 by a Party decree. This came across as the turning point in Lifshits
career, since thereafter he found himself in growing isolation. As Mitchell puts it,
his post-war intellectual role was very different from what it had been in the
thirties, particularly when the ideological restrictions were eased after the death of
Stalin. Heterodox then, Lifshits now appeared orthodox [] [H]e was hopelessly
isolated from the young, who regarded him as a reactionary (Mitchell 1997, 34).
Lukacs had already aroused opposition among other Marxist theoreticians by
stubbornly clinging to the novel of the classical bourgeois epoch as the role model
for all subsequent, thus even proletarian, literature and condemning modern art, for
example, in the well-known debate on expressionism with Bertolt Brecht. But
Lifshits was even more hostile towards new forms of modern art. His essay Why I
am not a modernist?, published in the early 1960s,3 in which he denounced
modernist art as essentially nihilist, sealed his reputation as a retrograde thinker and
alienated him from the new generation of the shestidesiatniki, the liberals of the
Khrushchev era. Solzhenitsyn called him a fossil Marxist. Lifshits wittily replied:
There are useful fossils, too. The articles written by his critics Lifshits put into a
folder labelled Chorus of the unhatched chickens.
A German translation of this article was included in the collection of essays: Michail Lifschitz, Krise
des Hsslichen, Dresden: Verlag der Kunst 1971.
123
244
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
In the last years of his life Lifshits finally obtained the freedom to write what he
thought openly. He was elected corresponding member of the Academy of Arts of
the Soviet Union in 1967, his works began to be published, and translations of them
appeared in other socialist countries. Lifshits dreamed, alluding to the example of
Spinoza, of presenting a systematic philosophy in a book with the title Aesthetics
(Lifshits 2010, 89). He said:
In a long life so astonishingly little is done, and all that is but spin-offs,
occasional works, marginal remarks. Astonishingly little is seen of the
invisible part of the iceberg. Indeed, I am myself guilty that this happened
(Lifshits 2011, 93).
Following Lifshits death, a three-volume collection of his works was published
(Lifshits 19841988) and soon after, in 1987, a German translation of his works,
containing texts from the 1930s, was published in Dresden.4 The posthumous
publication of Lifshits manuscript Ob idealnom i realnom, which is his critique
of Evald Ilyenkovs theory of the ideal, triggered a lively debate that continues to
this day.
In his extensive autobiographical interview, published in Hungarian in 1980 and
a year later in German with the title Gelebtes Denken, Lukacs seems to have taken
distance from his erstwhile Russian friend. When the interviewer Istvan Eorsi asked
for his views about Lifshits, Lukacs answered first with praise:
[W]e were the first to speak about a specifically Marxist aesthetics, not of this
or that aesthetics that would complete the systemof Marxs system. The idea
that aesthetics forms an organic part of Marxs system is to be found in my
article that I wrote about the Sickingen debate between Marx and Lassalle, and
in Lifshits this idea is in his early book that he wrote about the young Marx
[] My opinion of Lifshits is that he belonged to the greatest talents living in
those times [in the 1930sA.M. & V.O.], especially at the purely literary
level. He saw the problem of realism very clearly (Lukacs 1981, 141).
But then Lukacs switched to a more critical tone, claiming that Lifshits did not
extend this to other fields of culture, and remained stuck in his old positions of the
1930s, whilst he, Lukacs, on the contrary, had already then managed to go further.
Lukacs claimed that, unlike Lifshits, he was able in his book Der junge Hegel and
especially in the Zerstrung der Vernunft, to give an interpretation of Marxist
philosophy that abandoned the official line represented by Zhdanov, which reduced
modern philosophy entirely to the opposition between materialism and idealism.
Poor Lifshits stayed in Russia. I do not blame him for this. What could he possibly
do in Russia? He supported the line that modern literature is not good. His views
became outrightly conservative. I will not say that our friendship would have ceased
because of that. But of course I have left those things far behind that Lifshits has not
managed to settle to this day (Lukacs 1981, 1412).
4
Michail Lifschitz, Die dreissiger Jahre. Ausgewhlte Schriften, Dresden: VEB Kunst (Fundus-Bucherei
113115), 1987. It seems that the intention was to publish more volumes, but if so, the fall of the Berlin
Wall in 1989 nullified these plans.
123
245
The belittling tone of Lukacss memoirs reveals a hidden jealousy between the
two Marxist savants. It seems that Lifshits never had the opportunity to read
Lukacs interview with Eorsi, but despite this he managed to pay back Lukacs.
Recently, notes have been published, from the folder No. 232 of Lifshits archive,
labelled simply as Lukacs, in which he comments, polemically and in a
uncompromising manner which was characteristic of him, his friends writings (see
Lifshits 2004, 99166). Lifshits compared himself to the teacher of swordplay who
taught Cyrano de Bergerac some tricks of how to use the saber, but remained in the
shadow of his more famous pupil:
But in not one of my main ideas do I see any influence of Lukacs. On the
contrary, he followed me in at least two major points of his aesthetics []: a)
the contradiction between capitalism and the destiny of art; b) the idea of
realism in the broad sense of the word, or of truth in art (Lifshits 2004, 160).
Acerbically, Lifshits recalled that Lukacs had celebrated, in his well-known book
Zerstrung der Vernunft, the charlatan of science Lysenko, comparing his position to
that of Tertullians credo quia absurdum (Lifshits 2004, 102).5 Although the notes
in the folder are very fragmentary, even cryptic, one main line of Lifshits critique
seems to be that Lukacs has a tendency to emphasize the role of the subjective
factor, whilst Lifshits tends towards a more Platonic worldview. Lifshits traces
this subjectivism in Lukacs to a Neo-Kantian influence: Lukacs is insufciently
Hegelian. That he would be a Hegelian is but a fancy. The southwest German
current of Neo-Kantianism has had much influence on him much (ibid., 113).
Lifshits followed Lukacss later career and was especially critical of his
ontological turn in the 1960s. According to him, with the ontology project
Lukacs returned to the themes of his youth (ibid. 111). Especially the core idea of
the project, the teleology of human activity, was to Lifshits mind one-sided. Human
labour, argued Lifshits, consists not only in the realisation of goals, but is a
reaction that is transformed into the reproduction of life, which generates even the
goal itself (Ibid., 139). In other words, Lukacss concept of human labour is for
Lifshits too subjectivistic, since it reduces labour to teleological positing.
Lifshits returned several times to the theme of non nito, the tragic incompleteness of human works, the unfinished solutions of historical theorems. He referred
in this respect, inter alia, to Marx, who, as well, never completed his main work
(Lifshits 1985, 190200). However, he expressed the hope that maybe someone in
posterity will be able to reconstruct the antediluvian animal from one vertebra of
his skeleton. If this indeed is the case, maybe our present thematic issue will prove
helpful to the future Cuvier.
To sum up, there seemed to be something enigmatic in Lifshits position: clearly
he was not a Stalinist, nor an anti-Hegelian, although he opposed the Deborin
school. But neither did he belong to the adherents of new and critical trends in
Marxism. He did not want to make compromises in his critique of modernism,
although nor did he identify with the official doctrine of Socialist Realism. Lifshits
characterized himself as chelovek tridtsatykh godov, a man of the Thirties,
5
Lifshits adds: But do you think that Tertullian was a fool because he believed in the absurd?
123
246
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
pointing to the fact that the early years of the 1930s had been of formative
significance for him: all the central motives of his later writings can be traced back
to the discussions of this period.
This issue of SEET contains 8 articles that approach the Lifshits phenomen
from different angles. We begin with an interview by Dmitri Gutov, an
internationally known Russian artist, who has devoted much time to researching
the Lifshits heritage and is one of the most important connoisseurs of his work in
present-day Russia. The papers by Klimova, Jubara, Maidansky, Oittinen, Dmitriev,
Mareev, and Mareeva each deal with certain aspects of Lifshits oeuvre.
References
Arslanov, V. G. (2010). Ot redaktora. In V. G. Arslanov, (Ed.), Mikhail Aleksandrovich Lifshits. M:
ROSSPEN.
Eagleton, T. (1973). Preface. In M. Lifshitz (Ed.), The philosophy of art of Karl Marx. London: Pluto
Press.
Lifshits, M. (19841988). Izbrannoe, 13, M: Izobrazitelnoe iskusstvo, 19841988.
Lifshits, M. (1985). V mire estetiki. M: Izobrazitelnoe iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. (2004). Chto takoe klassika? M: Iskusstvo XXI vek.
Lifshits, M. (2010). Varia. M.: Grundrisse.
Lifshits, M. (2011). Pisma V. Dostalu, M. Mikhailovu, V. Arslanovu. M.: Grundrisse.
Lifshits, M. (2012). Nadoelo. V zashchitu obyknovennogo marksizma. M: IskusstvoXX vek 2012.
Lukacs, G. (1981). Gelebtes Denken. Eine Autobiographie im Dialog, ed. by Istvan Eorsi, Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp 1981 (edition suhrkamp NF 88), p. 141.
Mitchell, S. (1997). Mikhail Alexandrovich Lifshits (19051983). Oxford Art Journal, 20(2).
Pavlov, E. V. (2012), [Review of: Perepiska [Letters], Mikhail Lifschitz and Gyorgy Lukacs, Moscow:
Grundrisse, 2011; Pisma V. Dostalu, V. Arslanovu, M. Mikhailovu [Letters to V. Dostal, V.
Arslanov, M. Mikhailov], Mikhail Lifschitz, Moscow: Grundrisse, 2011] in: Historical Materialism
No. 4 (2012), pp. 187198.
123
Dimitrii Gutov is a Russian artist and art theoretician. Born in Moscow, 1960, he is one
of the most widely known and charismatic artists of the post-Soviet era. His works are
stored and exhibited in leading museums of the world: the Tretyakov Gallery, the
Russian Museum, Russian Icon Museum (all in Moscow), the Louvre, the Guggenheim
(New York), Kiasma (Helsinki). Gutov participated in the Venetian Biennials of 1995,
2007 and 2011, at Manifesta (1996), Documenta (2007), Volta (New York, 2009), the
Biennials in Istanbul (1992), Sao Paulo (2002) and Shanghai (2012).
The theoretical interests of Gutov focus on the philosophy of Marx and the
heritage of the Soviet aesthetician Mikhail Lifshits. In 1994 he founded a creative
group named The Lifshits Institute in Moscow.
Despite the fact that Gutov has become famous thanks to his avantgarde
paintings and installations, he has always applied himself to exploring the forgotten
and non-modern phenomena of the art. Hence his interest in the painting of the
Peredvizhniki group, Rembrandts sketches, orthodox icons, and the design of
Soviet journals of the thaw epoch. Lately he has worked especially with metallic
materials and organised expositions on Chinese and Japanese calligraphy, on
erotic motifs in antique Greek vases and Picassos graphics. One of his first metal
works was a 3D manuscript page of Marxs and Engelss The German Ideology.
AM and VO: Dear Dmitri Gutov, there have not been many translations of
Lifshitss works in other languages, maybe with the exception of some anthologies.
Which text of Lifshits would you, above all, recommend for translation?
123
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
DG: There are some publications of Lifshits in the good old German Democratic
republic, but in English there exist practically no translations. Even the anthologies
containing texts of Marx and Engels on art have not been published according to his
plan, with the exception of the GDR edition of Marx and Engels Uber Kunst und
Literatur (Berlin 1948, with several later printings). In English there exists only the
text Lifshits wrote when he was 27 years old, The Philosophy of Art of Karl Marx,
published in New York in 1938 (Lifshitz 1938). The translation is not very good and
contains many cuts. In addition there exist some articles lost in American journals of
the 1930s. At present, the Lifshits Institute is working intensively on translating
Lifshits works into English.
Of the shorter and forceful texts which contain the quintessence of Lifshits
aesthetics, I could mention the letter to Fridlender on Pushkin, written April 8,
1938.1 To this letter one can apply what Lifshits once said of himself in a note:
There remains the hope that some day a future Cuvier will reconstruct on the basis
of one bone fragment from my skeleton the entire antediluvian animal. This letter
contains in concentrated form the reflections of a man at the very centre of a
universal cataclysm at such a tragic and intense moment of history which humanity
has seldom experienced. Compared to those times everything which later
generations had to cope with looks like duck soup. It is exactly this fact which
hinders us from understanding what was said in the 1930s. Every word in this text
requires a comprehensive commentary, which, to boot, cannot be only historical. It
is kind of a Tao-te Ching. I do not doubt that such commentaries will be written.
Have you worked in the Lifshits Archive? Have you seen Lifshits drawings, and
if so, what do you think of them?
Yes, I have been working on the manuscripts of Mikhail Aleksandrovich and
have studied for hours both his drawings and the few remaining paintings. They
contain a very forceful paradox, a real drama. At the age of 19, Lifshits made a
decision to abandon his aspirations to become an artist. Despite this, he was drawn
to artistic activities throughout his entire life whole his life, as we learn from his
letters. One has to understand what kind of choice this was. It permeates all his
writings and in many respects determines their energy and problematics. Not
incidentally, Lifshits was so interested in that moment of the life of the young Marx
when he abandoned poetry. The theme of the end of art, its death and future
resurrection belongs to the core of Lifshits views. In the above-mentioned letter to
Fridland there is the phrase: Art is dead!Long live art!. One must know well
the first half of this sentence in order to avoid turning the second part into empty
babble.2 The first half of the sentence distinguishes Lifshits from all official Soviet
aesthetics (which, according to his definition, was but pure babble), the second half
from Western aesthetics. Thanks to this, his position is quite unique in the twentieth
century. This sentence contains the essence of Lifshits ideas and that which
determined the movement of his wrist when he painted landscapes and portraits. His
drawings are like an electric arc between these Dead and Long live!.
1
The letter was published in Pushkinist, vol. 1, Moskva: Sovremennik 1989, pp. 40314.
ibid., p. 404.
123
Furthermore, Lifshits acquired a phenomenal formal education in the VKhUTEMAS. The covers of self-made binders, in which he preserved his archive of
manuscripts, are visible evidence of this.
In a recent program Tem vremenem of the TV channel Kultura you
mentioned a room dedicated to Lifshits at an art exhibition in Madrid. Could you
say more about this project?
In 2012, I was invited by Boris Groys to participate at the Shanghai Biennale.
There I had at my disposal a big hall where I exhibited 28 stands with collected
materials on Lifshits: photographs, document copies, manuscripts, marginal notes to
books, book covers, and so on. It was a cross-section of what had accumulated
during the last 25 years, a kind of a tacit research, a little reminiscent of Aby
Warburgs Mnemosyne Atlas. Alongside the exhibition there was a 45 min film
devoted to Lifshits and the small group of artists interested in him. The film had
been produced ten years earlier by appointment of the Zentrum fur Kunst und
Mediatechnologie (ZKM) in Karlsruhe. During those ten years it was shown in
several places throughout the world. The Shanghai exhibition aroused interest
among the professionals, and we decided to stage it in some places in Europe, in
particular at the Vienna Secession of 2013 and, in Autumn 2014, in the main
Spanish museum of modern art, the Reina Sofia in Madrid.
Which should to your mind be the main direction for future studies of Lifshits
philosophical heritage?
The study of Lifshits should go through two phases. The first is, simply, to read
and attempt to understand what is said in his texts. This is an elementary level, but
even it has not yet been carried out in a satisfactory manner. More serious work on
Lifshits begins where one encounters most profound ideas, which the author himself
did not strive to make public; or, to state the point in a more complicated manner,
one encounters situations in which the ideas were expressed in an inverted manner,
v obratnoj forme as Lifshits himself said. A valuable cargo can be exported only
under this flag at those times, he sometimes said.
Here is what he writes about the problem of the rationality of the world in Hegel:
In Hegels formula Everything real is rational is contained the assertion of the
irrationality of realityin the only form which was possible for him and, generally,
for the epoch (Lifshits 2004). Or about Dostoevsky: He directs curses to that
which is for him the most valuable, the highest good (Besedy 1988).3 Or about
Diderot: The anger of Diderot against Boucher: he quarrels with his own bread and
butter. This is an element of protest against libertinage and demonic materialism.
But the fools think (Lifshits)
Every thought can be read literally, but it can be read even in another, deeper
manner, which Lifshits called the inverted gesture and the error of great men.
The error of great men: they think that they are understood not only by
denotation, but even by connotation, to use medieval terminology. However, they
are constrained to speak not at all about what they have in mind, but in such and
3
Iz avtobiografii idej.
123
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
such manner, and the readers and listenersespecially posteritywho are not
aware of the intellectual folklore of the epoch nor of the real situation of the times,
take their words literally. Such was the fate of Hegel with his Prussian police ideal,
such was the fate of Chernyshevsky with his paradoxical simplifications. Such is the
fate of all great conservatives of mankind who must necessarily express their
curious and progressive thought in a lopsided and even contrary form. But if great
men had to commit this mistake, if they are guilty without guilt, so for us, the
ordinary men who read their works, there is no need to follow them and repeat their
mistakes.4
Lifshits never wearied in repeating the following in several of his texts: I have
to give an account of some details of our intellectual life in the Thirties above all
because I myself was aboard, and my works of that epoch, which are now presented
to the reader, need specifications, especially in places where they may understand
this epoch too literally and externally, and do not understand its inverted gesture
and the real, valuable content of the epoch.5
Well, what about Lifshits critique of modernism? Should it, too, be understood
as an inverted gesture? If the answer is positive, then what is the real, valuable
content of modernism?
In making an anathema of modernism, Lifshits was merciless to the extreme. In
his texts there is not a word about the valuable and real content of modernism. For
him, modernism reflected a monstrous historical situation and was in itself a
contribution to its consolidation. He never compromised on this view.
Stanley Mitchell, the best connoisseur of Lifshits in the English-speaking world,
who valued him unusually highly and wrote a couple of important publications
devoted to him, once said to me: Conceal everything that Lifshits has written about
contemporary art and try to make it that no one ever sees it, if you want to make sure
that he does not lose his reputation for all time. Actually, on a literal reading, what
Lifshits says is but the usual Soviet rubbish. Dreadfully reactionary, only executed
in a considerably more rigorous manner and developed ad absurdum. What should
one, indeed, think about one of his declarations in the programmatic manifest from
1963, Why I am not a modernist?: Faced with such a program, I opt for the most
mediocre, the most epigonic academism, because it is the lesser evil (Lifshits
1978). The Dadaists in Zurich of 1916 could not have invented a better phrase with
which to startle the philistine, who from the end of the 1950s had already begun to
worship the newest forms of art.
In his pamphlet Why I am not a modernist? Lifshits attempted to express his main
ideas in a hyper-concentrated form. Compared with the letter to Fridlender, this text
is even more complicated from the point of view of its reception, since it is
constructed as an open challenge, as a poetics of shock.
Lifshits views modernism as the new religion of educated philistines of the
twentieth (and now the twenty-first) century. Whereas in earlier times, a cathedral
stood in a city centre, now there must be a museum of modern art. Essentially,
4
Ibid., p. 107.
Ibid., p. 105.
123
123
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
That is, the Moscow-based Institut filosofii, literatury i istorii imeni N.G. Chernyshevskogo (MIFLI,
often abbreviated as IFLI), which existed from 1931 to 1941; later incorporated into the Moscow State
University.
123
with how others might receive his message. In this light, Lifshitss stubborn nonconformism seems very un-Hegelian. He does not follow the current of his time nor
mind what others think of him
It seems to me that Lifshits is simply literally following the ideas which are put
forth in this famous Foreword. He does not grow weary in repeating that he himself
is the voice of a definite historical situation, literally a function of the
circumstances that had emerged at the time. On this he builds his entire theory
of reflection. There cannot be, in the head of a man, anything which does not exist in
reality itself. What was is Reason, wrote Hegel in the Foreword. But he does not
say here or anywhere else that every thinker must reckon with his circumstances
and with how others might receive his message. Why should one reckon with this?
Everybody is, anyway, the child of his age. The already cited most important thesis
of Lifshits is that everything can be read in two principally different ways. You have
to seek the contrariesthat is how you might formulate the essence of his approach.
If Lifshits moved against the current of his time, that means that there was another
current, deeper and more powerful, and not superficial. That is why in the thirties
Lifshits popularity was actually off-scale.
Lifshits edited in the 1930s works of Johann Joachim Winckelmann and wrote
an extensive introduction to them. Do you see any affinities between the aesthetic
programs of Lifshits and Winckelmann? As is well known, Winckelmann insisted
that imitation of the Ancients is the best way to greatness and to the flourishing of
culture. Of course, he meant by imitation (Nachahmung) something other than
mere copying. Lifshits, for his part, dreamed of a resurrection of the art of classical
antiquity.
Winckelmann built up his aesthetics in a very peculiar manner: if you want to be
modern, so follow the Ancients; if you want to be inimitable, then imitate antiquity.
But what does this mean? You have to imitate the Ancients in the first instance
because they themselves imitated no one. Open your eyes in order to investigate
Nature in its immediacy. All this has nothing to do with attempts to force-feed
people with classicistic academic schemes (although such a meaning may of course
be deduced from the idea of imitation). We can once more remind ourselves of the
Foreword to Hegels Philosophy of Right. Philosophy does not tell the world what it
should be likeand it would as senseless to tell this to art. Behind the achievements
of antique sculpture there was a phenomenal level of personal freedom. In the
present conditions of wage labour it is impossible even to dream of it. Talk about the
resurrection of ancient art boils down to the idea that, in more benevolent
circumstances, Man can move the weight of the body on one foot as freely as
Polykleitoss Doryphoros did. And the artist gets visual material to create a classical
figure. When Lifshits speaks of Russian icon painting of the fifteenth century and
connects its achievements with the epoch when the peasants had not yet became
serfs, he, too, is relating to Winckelmann. A harmony which is achieved by
abandoning all that is organic or plastically natural constitutes the other focus, the
focus of our days. The Mondrian Grids. Lifshits calls this the crazy tyrannical
utopia of straight lines.
123
A. Maidansky, V. Oittinen
References
Besedy M. A. (1988). Lifshitsa. In Kontekst 1987. Literaturno-teoreticheskie issledovanija (p. 300)
Moskva: Nauka.
Lifshits, M. A. (1978). Pochemu ja ne modernist? In Iskusstvo i sovremennyj mir (pp. 2829) Moskva:
Izobrazitelnoe iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A. (1979). Karl Marks Iskusstvo i obshchestvennyj ideal, (2nd ed.). Moskva: Khudozhestvennaja literatura.
Lifshits, M. A. (2004). Chto takoe klassika? Ontognoseologija. Smysl mira. Istinnaja seredina. (p. 429).
Moskva: Iskusstvo XXI vek.
Lifshits, M. A., & Reinhardt, L. J. (1968). Krizis bezobrazija (p. 77). Moskva: Iskusstvo.
Lifshitz, M. (1938) The Philosophy of Art of Karl Marx, New York: Critics Group 1938 (2nd ed.)
London: Pluto Press 1973.
123
Department of Philosophy, Belgorod State University, ul. Preobraghenskaya 78b, kv. 79,
Belgorod, Russia 308000
123
A. Maidansky
added the third, aesthetic dimension: the true is beautiful, and vice versa. To him,
portrayal of real life is the matter of art and the artists supreme vocation.
The quest of truth is not a purely intellectual exercise, it is a continuous drama
of life, as Lifshits expressed the idea. It was the Russian October Revolution that
became the historical culmination of this drama. Lifshits called himself a son of
the Revolution, who had the opportunity to learn its lessons at firsthand (Lifshits
1988a, 266). Every revolution begins with the abstract negation of the old, and
young Lifshits, as he confessed years after, was captured by the fantastic
enthusiasm of breaking and denial, joining the radical left wing painters at
VKhUTEMAS (Higher Artistic and Technical Workshop), a stronghold of Leftist
revolutionary art, much like Weimars Bauhaus. However, this enthusiasm did not
last for long, a year or two, after which Lifshits developed a strong immunity to
neopathy, as he called the pursuit of the new, that disease of a modern philistine.
Like any seeker of truth, Lifshits was in a state of permanent conflict with the
mainstream in arts, in philosophy, and in life itself. Criticism of avant-garde art
earned him a reputation as an aesthetic counter-revolutionary and made it
impossible to continue his studies. Lifshits switched to the teaching of philosophy
and moved to the Marx and Engels Institute.
At that time he studied German, collected all of Marxs and Engels judgments
about art in the writings, and prepared to publish an anthology designed to prove
that the founders of Marxism had their own, genuine aesthetic theory, though no one
had ever noticed it before.1 Needless to say, this theory vindicated the classical
ideals of Antiquity and the Renaissance. In this way Lifshits acquired allies against
which nobody could argue in those years.
Meanwhile, avant-garde art was crushed in the Soviet UnionStalin began to
establish his own socialist pseudo-realism. Lifshits once again found himself in
opposition. He had to defend his views in discussions with the creators of the new
mythology, whose arguments resembled the sound of a falling mortar shellhello
from hell. One cannot but marvel at Lifshitss courage: in the years when churches
and monasteries were being destroyed, he writes articles and delivers lectures on the
realism of ancient Russian icon-painting. It might seem strange that he preferred
orthodox icons to canvases of the revolutionary avant-garde. And after that, he
would still consider himself a foster child of the October Revolution?
Lifshits expands the scope of this paradox, showing that both fathers of the
proletarian revolution, Marx and Lenin, were also notable for their conservative
predilections in art. It is a well-known fact that Marx placed Aeschylus and
Shakespeare above all contemporary writers. Lenin acknowledged that he did not
like nor even understand avant-garde art. How do a revolutionary spirit in politics
and a deep-rooted conservatism in art correspond to each other?
In his Introduction to the Grundrisse Marx had meditated upon the same
problem: why is it that Greek art is still appreciated as a norm and unattainable
example, if in a material respect modern civilisation has made such great strides?
1
I remember that I submitted a report to the Director of the Institute, suggesting setting up a room for
aesthetics, in order to study Marxs and Engels aesthetic views. My initiative came to nothing. It was
received with a certain irony, though kindly enough. Ryazanov did not believe that Marx and Engels had
their own system of aesthetic views. However, nobody realised this at that time (Lifshits 1988a, 278).
123
Ein Mann kann nicht wieder zum Kinde werden oder er wird kindisch. Aber freut ihn die Naivetat des
Kindes nicht, und mu er nicht selbst wieder auf einer hohren Stufe streben, seine Wahrheit zu
reproduzieren? Lebt in der Kindernatur nicht in jeder Epoche ihr eigner Charakter in seiner Naturwahrheit
auf? (Marx 1983, 45).
The term realism may be used in a wide sense, as the truth of displaying the actual world in its
inherent sensible form; and there is realism as a historical phenomenon, relating to definite literary-artistic
currents (Lifshits 1984c, 380).
123
A. Maidansky
Naturalism is an abstract realism, a dead and empty artistic form, having lost its
real substance.
In contrast, a fairy tale or icon, for all the irreality of their plots, may have a
deeply real sense, if they grasp the vital values of human beingif they exactly
render the difference between good and evil, the true and the false, the beautiful and
the ugly. Realism is not just exactness in depicting the outer world. It is the true
estimation of reality, expressed in the sensual forms which are derived from reality
itself.
A confusion of the beautiful and ugly, and, even more, removal of the border
between them, are the typical features of bad, false art, however much this art
operates with the most real images.
The artist as well as the scientist are called upon to search for the absolute.
Despite all the catchwords of our century, absolute beauty exists, just as absolute
truth exists,the young Lifshits postulated (Lifshits 1984a, 233). He conceives
these absolutes as the sums of all relative truths and beautiful images. Lifshits
sharply condemned any relativisation of the concepts of truth and beauty.
Relativism is a dialectics for fools.
Every work of art, even the most abstract, reflects something in reality. The
concept of reflection in Lifshits, and generally in Marxism, is a materialistic version
of Hegels category Reflexion. According to Hegel, Mind reflects itself in the
external, material world, whereas for Marxism it is Nature that reflects itself by
means of the human mind.4 Art is one of the forms of this reflection of nature in
itself, viz. its reflection in artistic images. An artist, like an actor, must be a voice
or herald of the very nature of things, Lifshits asserts.
I would note that one can say the same about a scientist. Hegel wrote that science
demands from that mind that it immerse (versenken) its freedom in the subject
matter and abstain from interrupting the immanent rhythm of concepts.5 The
striving of the mind to impose its own selfness on the subject is regarded by Hegel
as vanity, conceit (Eitelkeit). Lifshits rails against Modernism for the same sin.
A loving, honest portrayal of the real world was important for the old art. The
personality of the artist receded more or less into the background in the face of
his creation, surpassing, in this way, his personal level. In the newest art
matters are quite the opposite what the artist does, is ever more reduced to a
pure symbol, to a sign of his personality (Lifshits 1978, 30).
Along the lines of Hegels distinction of bad and true singularity,6 Lifshits
draws out a difference between genuine individuality creating a new universal
and stupid uniqueness with its dubious claim to be absolutely new. In modernistic
art, he sees a manifestation of the latterthe cult of pure subjectivity, deliberately
breaking all ties with objective reality, with true being.
4
The term nature is used here in an ultimate sense, including people, human society. Man is an
avant-garde of nature (Lifshits 2004, 121).
Sich des eigenen Einfallens in den immanenten Rhythmus der Begriffe entschlagen (Hegel 1970,
56).
6
Schlechte Einzelheit vs. wahrhafte Einzelheit, Individualitat, wahrhafte Subjektivitat. See: Hegel
(1971, 170).
123
Science and art perform one and the same task, they seek truth. Though, unlike
Hegel, Lifshits never considered cognition in artistic images as a lower stage in
comparison with logical thought. Both forms of cognition possess equal rights as
moments of truthtruth being understood as the conformity of a things
existence with its essence, i.e. as perfection, or something ideal. Lifshits calls such a
truth substantial, to distinguish it from formal truth as the correspondence
between thought and the facts of experience. The word pravda refers only to the
substantial truth. That is the truth of things themselves, reflected in the human mind.
Aesthetics is called upon to reveal the truth or falseness of a work of art. What is
the reality that has found its expression in this or that workis it genuine and
profound, or shallow and spectral (prizrachnyj), as the classic of Russian literary
criticism Belinsky expressed it? Quite often, as Lifshits writes, the subject matter
manifests itself to an artist from the side of its petty singularity, lacking a deep
connection with reality, and therefore bordering on complete disintegration, on nonbeing. Meanwhile, its formal side is in order, the artists idea is good, the execution
is faultless, only one thing is missingthat supreme power which makes the work
of art genuine.7 In Hegels lectures on aesthetics this supreme power was called die
Macht.
Sometimes an artist loses this very power, although all his technical skills remain
and are at his free disposal. Thus, Lifshits valued Solzhenitsyns first works
extremely highly, and recommended One Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovich for
publication with the following remark: It is something more than literature It
would be a crime to leave this narrative unpublished. Solzhenitsyn was an
outstanding writer, as long as his hand was guided by life itself; but as soon as he
began to speak with his own tongue, he became free and miserable, as Lifshits
affirmed (Lifshits 1995, 236).8
There is something independent of an artists arbitrary will in his creative
work. And as long as he speaks, whether deliberately or instinctively, in the
name of this objective element, he feels within himself the blessing of this
miraculous objective power, and Heaven forbid that he lose it, like Samson
lost his hair (Lifshits 1995, 108).
These words of Lifshits are, to all appearance, a paraphrase of Belinskys views in
his work A Look at Russian Literature of 1847. From Belinsky he seems to adopt
also the concept of realism as a sense of truth. A philosopher speaks in syllogisms,
and a poet speaks in images and pictures, but they are saying the same thing,
Belinsky wrote. The poet, unlike the scientist, gives a true expression to life without
reasoning and arguing, he simply shows. Often he does not realise how he shows,
instinctively perceiving the truth of his time. And once he starts to argue logically,
to philosophise,then
he stumbles, and how he does so!.. And the mighty hero suddenly loses his
strength, like Samson after losing his hair, and he, who had been running
7
A few pages in this collection of archival notes contain the most brutal ethical and sociological
assessments of Solzhenitsyns worldview.
123
A. Maidansky
ahead of all, is now is dragging himself along among the stragglers, in the
crowd of his former enemies (Belinsky 1941, 401).
At all times there have been weak writers who showed not so much reality as
themselves, their personal vision of the world. The ideology of Modernism turns
this imperfection into a virtue,that is why Lifshits regards modernistic art as false.
But that very illness of art reflects the ailing state of the modern world. In the
creative work of the best representatives of the avant-garde, this illness of being is
expressed and refracted through their personal traumas as well as in the distinctive
deformations of artistic form. As Lifshits puts it,
[t]he founders of Modernism in the past century were poets and painters of
great talent, and they created artworks capable of acting strongly on the mind
and senses of their contemporaries, despite the presence in their creative
activity of many symptoms of disease, and partly even due to this weakness. It
is enough to mention Baudelaire in poetry or Van Gogh in painting. There
exists a huge difference between their particular art, which seemed to be
hanging over an abyss, and the consequences, with which the possibilities they
discovered, were fraught (Lifshits 1988c, 432).
The late modernists transform this illness of art, and of social life itself, into a norm,
an example of style, or a standard. Feelings of suffering and weakness are replaced
now by the abstract insensibility of cubes and squares and even by a feeling of
satisfaction with free imageless creativity.
History
Lifshitss book Krizis bezobrazija (A Crisis of Shapelessness, 1968), as Dmitry
Gutov aptly remarks, called into question the whole aesthetic project of
Modernity. The avant-garde criticism of bourgeois normality is nothing other
than this very bourgeois principle, just turned inside out and made into an absolute.
That is the conclusion reached by Lifshits.
His train of thought is very similar to the criticism of crude communism in the
young Marxs manuscripts of 1844. Such a communism, with its abstract negation
of private property, is actually nothing else but universal private property (das
allgemeine Privateigentum), where, according to Marx, the entire world of wealth,
i.e. of mans objective essence, passes from exclusive marriage with a private owner
to universal prostitution with all society.9
In modernist art we see the very same abstract negation of the capital of
artistic forms, accumulated by classical art, and the equalisation of the rights of all
forms of the creative self-expression of personality (the universal prostitution of
artistic style). Modernism is a crude communism in the world of aesthetics.
9
So tritt die ganze Welt des Reichtums, d.h. des gegenstandlichen Wesens des Menschen, aus dem
Verhaltnis der exklusiven Ehe mit dem Privateigentumer in das Verhaltnis der universellen Prostitution
mit der Gemeinschaft (Marx 1974, 45).
123
123
A. Maidansky
Ich mit Herzen nirgendwo und niemals zusammen figurieren will (Marx 1963, 434).
123
123
A. Maidansky
he says. Such is the irrational logic of historyforgive it in our hearts. But when
it comes to art, he does not tolerate lies. He demands from artists that they express
the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth. He permits no assumption that
modernism is also a necessary, and therefore a justifiable, transitional stage in the
development of artthat such is the cruel cost of releasing the creative powers of
human masses. With this, degradation of the high classics appears to be inevitable,
just as the communist movement begins by levelling and humiliating the human
personality (as was demonstrated by the history of proletarian revolutions, starting
with the October revolution).
Marx considered crude, levelling communism as a necessary moment of human
emancipation and redemption, and as a necessary form and energetic principle of
the immediate future, but he also made the reservation that as such [crude]
communism is not an aim of human development, a form of human society.15 I
think, the same should be said about Modernism. It is an equally false or, in Marxs
terms, alienated and inverted form of the emancipation of artistic activity, but it is a
historically indispensable moment along the way of turning art into a personal
property of every individual.
The mission of modernist art can be expressed by paraphrasing Marxs famous
thesis: the artists have only portrayed the world in various ways, the point however
is to change it. Art will penetrate into everyday life, involving each and every
person in artistic creation, diffusing high and popular culture.
Art has renounced itself and wishes to be life itself, Lifshits comments,
sarcastically adding that in practice all these strange constructions made of iron,
glass, and wood were directly related not to the real needs of living people, but to
the afterlife history of painting (Lifshits 1979, 2627).
And what about the earthly history of revolution? Modernism and Stalinism are
set in motion by the same dark energy of negation. But if Stalin, in Lifshitss
opinion, has brought about the rise of the country, although by terrible and
barbaric means, then modernism was a sheer regress and degradation of mind. A
certain reactionary philosophy has taken place of the slain art, and nothing more.
It is the philosophy expressing the domination of force and fact over clear
thought and poetic contemplation of the world. The brutal breaking of real
forms means the eruption of blind, malicious will. It is the revenge of the
slave, his imaginary liberation from the yoke of necessity, a simple outlet
(Lifshits 1978, 52).
This description perfectly characterises the initial impulse of all proletarian
revolutions, too. The beautiful dream of pravda never comes true, but the revenge
of the slave and the breaking of real forms actually occur. Somewhat later the
broken social forms are restored in a surrealistically warped or hypertrophied form
(e.g. the socialist market or the Gulag). And in art, Modernism very soon gives way
to pseudo-realism, the false restoration of the real forms (Lifshits).
15
Der Kommunismus ist die notwendige Gestalt und das energische Prinzip der nachsten Zukunft, aber
der Kommunismus ist nicht als solcher das Ziel der menschlichen Entwicklungdie Gestalt der
menschlichen Gesellschaft. (Marx 1974, 546).
123
123
A. Maidansky
Reflection
In the last years of his life, Lifshits designed an original metaphysical conception
that he named materialist ontognoseology. It is a kind of aesthetic interpretation
of the old materialist theory of reflection. Proponents of the latter linked the term
reflection to the psyche, seeking out proto-psychical and quasi-mental phenomena in nature. Lifshits imparts to this term an entirely different cosmic sense.
Reflection is a way of turning the abstract into the concrete, or converting an
indefinite universality, diffused in nature, into actual universality.16 The latter
16
Reflection in general, in the objective sense of the word, as a reproduction. Reproduction has a
cosmic sense, for in such a way the diffused universality is turning into the actual one (Lifshits 2010,
25).
123
123
A. Maidansky
consciousness, and the small being is perceived as the only available object of
consciousness. Vulgar Marxism, discovering the selfish class interests in
symphonies and poems, is smitten by the same blindness to the eternal, big being.
But where has man to seek for that coveted big being? We do not need to
transcend into another world, Lifshits answers. The small being reflects the big
being in a particular way, the infinite expresses itself in the finite. Hence, the task of
consciousness is to seek, within the field of our small being, events and situations
that are charged by universality. Granting his voice to these concrete,
individualised universalities, listening and giving utterance to the confession of
the world, man turns his consciousness into the mirror of objective reality:
To think means to make the object of thought think in us. To act freely is to be
the subject of a greater reality beyond us, almost to stand apart from ones own
self, not feeling oneself bound up with ones own small being, with ones
flickering existential Only relying on this broader reality, can one cross the
threshold of blindness, which is imposed on us by our empirical being
(Lifshits, n.d.).
These lines bear a distinctly Spinozist note: freedom is the immersion of thought
and action into the infinite reality, into the very nature of things. Reason has no
selfish logic, it is as universal as nature itself. The full description of reason
would be equivalent to building a model of the universe, which is the object of
thought. In this sense, thought is the attribute of nature, and not simply one of its
modes.
But in resolving the mindbody problem, Lifshitss ontognoseology openly broke
with Spinozism, aligning rather with La Mettrie and other materialist writers of the
eighteenth century who developed the theme of a causal link between body and
mind (Lifshits 2003, 123). In Spinoza, brain and conscious mind are two different
modes of being of one and the same thinga man. According to Lifshits,
consciousness is a product of the brain, the form in which brain is experiencing
for itself its own process of reflection of the external world.18
This statement is a cornerstone of the contemplative materialism (der
anschauende Materialismus), which Marx criticised in the Theses on Feuerbach.
Lifshits seems not in the least embarrassed by that. He is trying to spread the
brain explanation of consciousness across the world of human culture and, thus,
to give battle to the cultural-historical theory on its own territory. According to that
theory, defended by philosopher Evald Ilenkov and his associatesthe psychologists of Lev Vygotskys schoolconsciousness is a form of active communication
between man and man by means of tools and objects of labour. Consciousness is a
function of culture, not of nature. The genuine substance and subject of
consciousness is not an organic human body with all its neurons, but the artificial
body of culture.
To Lifshits, on the contrary, material culture is as if an extension of brain by
means of inorganic appendages (Lifshits 2003, 273). This cultural mediastinum,
rising up between consciousness and nature, on the one hand, enlightens
18
123
consciousness, extending its independence from the natural ground, but on the other
hand it obscures consciousness by myths and other cultural stereotypes.
It is a terrible thing the bureaucracy of culture, from Egyptian hieroglyphic
writing and the clerical wisdom of Sumerian scribes to the ink culture, which
Herder complained of, and necrotic stamps of media in later times (Lifshits
2003, 274275).
Modernism also refers to the category of terrible things of culture. Abstract art
replaces reality with myths and tightly closes our consciousness within the small
being. For this reason, Lifshits refuses to consider Modernism as an ideal.
Criticizing the fetishism of culture, Lifshits keeps in mind Marxs communist
ideal. Communism is defined by Lifshits as an ideal society, corresponding to its
concept, as opposed to perverse relationships of the world of commodities (Lifshits
2003, 278). As soon as such a crystal clear form of social relations among people
will emerge, the bureaucracy of culture will disappear forever. Every mythology
will vanish like smoke, abstract art will go into oblivion, and realism will finally
prevail.
In general, Lifshitss ontognoseology can be described as the attempt to resurrect
naturalist ideas, traced to French enlighteners and Russian revolutionary democrats,
on Marxist soil. The project was left unfinished, but its main lines are visible clearly
enough. The search for higher truth, Naturwahrheit, was the soul, the driving force
of Lifshits work. In this respect, he was one of the staunchest and more talented
defenders of classical art and philosophy through the most difficult times of their
history.
References
Arslanov, V.G. (2010). Problema termidora 30-kh godov i rozhdenie teorii tozhdestv. In: Mikhail
Aleksandrovich Lifshits (pp 338366) Moscow: ROSSPEN.
Belinsky, V. G. (1941). Vzgljad na russkuju literaturu 1847 goda. In V. G. Belinsky (Ed.), Izbrannye
filosofskie sochinenija (pp. 376452). Moskva: Gosudarstvennoe izdatelstvo politicheskoj
literatury.
Burke, E. (2005). Reflections on the revolution in France. Clark, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange.
Groys, B. (2013). Gesamtkunstwerk Stalin. Moskva: Ad Marginem Press.
Gutov, D. (2007). Marksistsko-leninskaja estetika v postkommunisticheskuju epokhu. Mikhail Lifshits.
In: Svobodnaja mysl, 2, pp. 125141. [German translation: Gutov, D. Die marxisitisch-leninstische
sthetik in der postkommunistischen Epoche. Michael Lifsic. In: B. Groys, A. von der Heiden, & P.
A
Weibel (Eds.), Zuruck aus der Zukunft. Osteuropaische Kulturen im Zeitalter des Postkommunismus. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2005, pp. 709737].
Hegel, G. W. F. (1970). Phanomenologie des Geistes. In: G. W. F. Hegel (Ed.), Werke: 20 Bde. Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp. Bd. 3.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1971). Vorlesungen uber die Geschichte der Philosophie. In: G. W. F. Hegel (Ed.),
Werke: 20 Bde. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Bd. 20.
Herzen, A. I. (1986). K staromu tovarishchu. In A. I. Herzen (Ed.), Sochinenija: 2 vols (Vol. 2,
pp. 531547). Moskva: Mysl.
Lenin, V. I. (1968). Materializm i empiriokriticizm. In: Polnoe sobranie sochinenij, 5th ed.: 55 vols.
Moskva: Politizdat. Vol. 18.
Lifshits, M. A. (1954). Dnevnik Marietty Shaginjan. In: Novyj mir, 2, pp. 206231
123
A. Maidansky
Lifshits, M. A. (1978). Pochemu ja ne modernist? In: Iskusstvo i sovremennyj mir (pp. 1931). Moskva:
Izobrazitelnoe iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A. (1979). Karl Marx. Iskusstvo i obshchestvennyj ideal (2nd ed.). Moskva: Khudozhestvennaja literatura.
Lifshits, M. A. (198488). Sobranie sochinenij: 3 vols. Moskva: Izobrazitelnoe iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A. (1984a). Dialektika v istorii iskusstva. In Sobranie sochinenij. Vol. 1, pp. 223240.
Lifshits, M. A. (1984b). Marksizm i esteticheskoe vospitanie. In Sobranie sochinenij. Vol. 1,
pp. 388430.
Lifshits, M. A. (1984c). Marx i Engels ob iskusstve. In: M. A. Lifshits (Ed.), Sobranie sochinenij. Vol. 1,
pp. 316384.
Lifshits, M. A. (1984d). Veter istorii. In: Sobranie sochinenij. Vol. 1, pp. 273315.
Lifshits, M. A. (1985). V mire estetiki. Moskva: Izobrazitelnoe iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A. (1988a). Iz avtobiografii idej. Besedy M.A. Lifshitsa. In: Kontekst 1987. Literaturnoteoreticheskie issledovanija. (pp. 264319) Moskva: Nauka.
Lifshits, M. A. (1988b). Modernism kak javlenie burzhuaznoj ideologii. In: Sobranie sochinenij. Vol. 3,
pp. 438453.
Lifshits, M. A. (1988c). Modernism v iskusstve. In: Sobranie sochinenij. Vol. 3, pp. 430437.
Lifshits, M. A. (1995). Podgotovitelnye materialy k vospominanijam o Tvardovskom. In: Ocherki
russkoj kultury. (pp. 232244) Moskva: Nasledie.
Lifshits, M. A. (2001). Estetika Hegelja i sovremennost. In: Voprosy filosofii, 11, pp. 98122.
Lifshits, M. A. (2003). Dialog s Evaldom Ilyenkovym (Problema idealnogo). Moskva: ProgressTradicija.
Lifshits, M. A. (2004). Chto takoe klassika? Ontognoseologija. Smysl mira. Istinnaja seredina. Moskva:
Iskusstvo XXI vek.
Lifshits, M. A. (2010). Varia. Moskva: Grundrisse.
Lifshits, M. A. (2012). Nadoelo. V zashchitu obyknovennogo marksizma. Moskva: Iskusstvo XXI vek.
Lifshits, M.A. (n.d.). Bytie i soznanie (arkhivnaja zametka). In: http://www.gutov.ru/lifshitz/texts/
bitie&soznanie.htm. Accessed 05.07.2016.
Lifshits, M. A., & Reinhardt, L. J. (1968). Krizis bezobrazija. Moskva: Iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A., & Reinhardt, L. J. (1974). Nezamenimaja tradicija. Kritika Modernisma v klassicheskoj
marksistskoj literature. Iskusstvo: Moskva.
Maidansky, A. D. (2015). Konservativnaja revoljucija: Lifshits na urokakh Hegelja. Svobodnaja mysl, 3,
pp. 209220.
Marx, K. (1963). Letter to Engels from 13 February 1855. In: Karl Marx/Friedrich Engels, Werke. Bd. 28
konomisch-philosophische Manuskripte aus dem Jahre 1844. In: Karl Marx/Friedrich
Marx, K. (1974). O
Engels, Werke, Erganzungsband, Erster Teil.
konomie]. In: Karl Marx/
Marx, K. (1983). Einleitung [zu den Grundrissen der Kritik der politischen O
Friedrich Engels. Werke: 43 Bde. Berlin/DDR: Dietz Verlag. Bd. 42, pp. 1545.
Pavlov, P. V. (2010). Obosnovanie tretego puti rossijskoj istorii i kultury. In: Mikhail Aleksandrovich
Lifshits (pp. 367404). Moscow: ROSSPEN.
123
Moscow, Russia
123
A. Dmitriev
123
fantastic vision), and generally many signs of genius (letter dated April 28, 1862).
These aspects provided safe conduct for the Italian philosopher under the new
conditions. Besides this, Vico was favoured with several substantive positive
remarks in Plekhanovs book, The Development of the Monist View of History.
In 1923, the translation of Lukacs important work Materialization and
Proletarian Consciousness was published in the Vestnik Kommunisticheskoj
Akademii. This article became central to his following famous book, Geschichte
und Klassenbewutsein (1923), where Vicos postulate regarding cognition
grounded in doing is connected with the entire course of development of European
thought from Descartes to Kants Copernican turn in philosophy.
The publication in the Arkhiv Marksa i Engelsa of Vladimir Maksimovskijs
(18871941) detailed article Vico and his theory of social cycles became the
major event in the reception of Vico in the 1920s. This academic text mentioned the
reworked character of the old French translation of The New Science and was filled
with quotations about Vico from the main Western works of Benedetto Croce,
Robert Flint, and others. The author, a graduate of Moscow University, an old
Bolshevik and a member of different opposition groups after the Revolution,
underlines in Vicos main book the ideas of social conflict, class struggle during
the transition from one phase to the next. Thereby he makes a tally of the Italian
philosophers views in light of the future views of Marxism (Maksimovskij 1928a,
8, 57, 6061). A detailed knowledge of Italian history and a familiarity with the
classical and most recent literature on the history of ideas allowed Maksimovskij to
present Vico in the light of the historical materialistic world view, absorbing him
into the context of that epoch and into the actual political and ideological life of
Italy in the first half of the eighteenth century. Maksimovskij insists that Vicos and
Machiavellis works have a secular basis and real political character in their vision
of history, and that Vico saw the struggle between plebeians and patricians as the
essence of Roman freedom (Maksimovskij 1928b, 1929, 13, 1930, 459).
Maksimovskijs article, The aesthetic views of Giambattista Vico appeared in
the mid-1930s in the above-mentioned authoritative journal, Literaturnyj Kritik,
where the works of Lukacs and his circle were regularly published. Here
Maksimovskij considers Vicos ideas about the origin of language and poetry and
shows that Vico has to be included among the founders of modern aesthetics. A note
is added to the article mentioning that it will be published as an appendix to the
Russian translation of Andrey Gubers Scienza Nuova, to be printed by the famous
Academia publishing house (Maksimovskij 1935, 27). Indeed, this publication
appeared only five years later, printed by Goslitizdat (the State Literary Publishing
House) in Leningrad in an edition of five thousand copies.
Finally, the young but already authoritative philosopher Mikhail Aleksandrovich
Lifshits wrote the editors preface to the Vico volume. Why Lifshits? He was not an
Italianist, but his text in particular brought popularity and significance to Vicos
text, which was considered to be more than an antiquated monument of thought.
Certainly, it should be remembered that the preface had very important functions in
the 1930s. A preface had not only to include the academic outline of a research
question but also to indicate the topicality of the subject for Soviet readers. Not
long before the publication of the preface, Lifshits published the book Voprosy
123
A. Dmitriev
iskusstva i filosofii (1935) in which a comprehensive article about Marx and the
fundamentals of Marxist aesthetics occupied the central place. A volume of Johann
Joachim Winckelmanns works was also published with an introduction by Lifshits
(1933).
The zenith of Lifshits intellectual career paradoxically coincided with the time
of Stalins Terror. Lifshits article about Vico, which was published in Literaturnyj
Kritik a year before the publication of The New Science, infuriated the orthodox
(Lifshits 1939). The head of the Union of Soviet Writers, Aleksandr Fadeev, and his
associates saw in this article empathy for the theories of historical cycles and the
reactionary ideas of Spengler and, potentially, support for the thesis about the
approach of Thermidor as a stage which inevitably comes after any revolutionary
breakthrough. A special decision of the Central Committee of the Communist Party
of the Soviet Union on literary criticism was prepared in 1941. Literaturnyj Kritik
was shut down, but no direct repression was directed against Lukacs, Lifshits, and
their group (Artizov 1999, 456).
In the text, Lifshits emphasises the popular origins of Vicos thought and his
vision of history magnificence from the point of view of the masses. He sees
Vicos main merit in that it can be turned against the positions of the newest
sociology of knowledge. Here Lifshits stays close to Maksimovskij, who also fought
the imposition of vulgar sociological schematics for the sake of a genuine Marxist
historicism. In particular, hostility towards sociology in historical research
increased from the mid-1930s under the sign of the struggle with the heritage of
Mikhail Pokrovsky. The ideas of Lifshits and his allies undoubtedly responded to
the tendency to restore history to its rights.
Along with Lifshits main work about Vico, another of Lifshitshis works
devoted to the Italian philosopher was published posthumously in the second
volume of his Collected Works Lifshits(both dated 1936). This article was devoted
generally to Vicos aesthetics. It should be remembered that the aesthetic aspect of
the Italian thinkers theories was the very subject of Maksimovskijs article on Vico
in Literaturnyj Kritik at the end of 1935. It is obvious that Lifshits work exceeds
Maksimovskijs in the depth of its analysis. In Maksimovskijs article, literally one
line is devoted to Hegel; however, for Lifshits, Vico, as a philosopher concerned
with art, can be understood only from a Hegelian perspective.
As distinct from Maksimovskij, who compares Vico with his contemporaries and
predecessors such as Bodin and Montesquieu, Lifshits sees in Vico a founder of the
historical theory of knowledge and an isolated thinker within his own epoch. In a
quite positive review of Vicos publication, in the pages of the journal Pod
znamenem marksizma, this strange formulation was marked as obviously lame, as
a new term which can only add confusion to the readers minds (German 1940,
203, 201). However, for Lifshits, Vico was important as a counterpoint to the
sociological outlook of Scheler and Mannheim (and the vulgar sociology of
Valerian Pereverzev)!
What is the historical theory of knowledge? It is that new science forecast in
the early eighteenth century by Giambattista Vico. Without it, it is impossible
to make the step from the realm of necessity to the realm of freedom (namely,
123
the rational control of human society over the development of its own creative
forces), the step from hazy semi-consciousness to lucid comprehension of the
historical prerequisites of culture, to its self- consciousness. The new science
is the science of the future dialectics. (Lifshits 1948, 393)
The category of progress is at the centre of Lifshits attention. However, he sees
it not as a problem-free and unidirectional process, but as a crooked path with forks,
inescapable returns, repetitions and cycles. For Lifshits, Vicos approach to the
Enlightenment in particular has another value (not only affirmative)it is a view
from below which also considers the rights and presumptions of the reactionary
mass:
The Enlightener judges from the point of view of the developed individual
consciousness, Vico from the point of view of the great mass of people, which
is not always sufficiently aware, but is always concerned with matters of the
most genuine necessity, and is therefore rational in the historical sense of the
word. (Lifshits 1948, 403)
Vicos New Science [] is a fantastic anticipation of that task of
reconstruction of the history of human thought, science, and technique which
Lenin described as a continuation of the work of Hegel and Marx. Vicos
book embraces the history of the various sciences, the history of language, art,
and poetry, and of the childs mental development, the history of the state,
law, and material culture. All this is expressed in extremely naive forms,
profound thoughts are interspersed with all sorts of pedantic trifles, the
exposition is very confused; yet it is beyond doubt that the basic idea is a work
of genius. (Lifshits 1948, 394).
Both of Lifshits articles demonstrate a good knowledge of the literature of the
time, mainly Western, about Vico. In particular he mentions an important book by
B. Croce (Croce 1911). But if in Maksimovskijs works an academic approach to
Vico, combined with sociological conclusions and sometimes with artificial direct
convergences between Scienza Nuova and Marxism, prevails, then, Lifshits
detailed knowledge of the subject and erudition is buried in footnotes and comes out
in certain reservations. Among other examples, there is the casual mention of a
thesis, which, by the way, is contained in the unpublished article about Vico, On
the Genealogy of Morals of Nietzsche, a poor dilettantish toy in comparison to the
historical analysis of Vico (Lifshits 1986, 35).
Generally, as distinct from Maksimovskijs detailed historiographical endnotes,
Lifshits does not consider at all the former Russian tradition of the reception of the
Italian philosophers works in his article about Vico and in unpublished additions to
it. For Lifshits, this tradition was not important. He considered himself as standing
outside the Russian modes of interpretation. Also he could not cite the works of the
emigre Vipper or arrested Maksimovskij. The main means of understanding the
heritage of Vico, for Lifshits, is retrospective. Lifshits considers Vico as a
predecessor to Marx through Hegel, particularly emphasising the masterslave
dialectic in Vicos analysis of the collapse of heroic society (a reference to the
theory of gestalts of consciousness in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit).
123
A. Dmitriev
Lifshits and his associates measured their surrounding Soviet and European
reality of the 1930s with their broad historiosophical measure of the great thinkers
of the past. For that reason precisely they were able to avoid a conjunctural and
simplified interpretation of history from the position of the ideological collisions of
the time. In 1934, in the pages of the Literaturnaja Gazeta, Lifshits argued against
Aleksej Dzhivelegovs view, which was stated in the afterword to the translation of
the works of Francesco Guicciardini (Lifshits 1934). There, the venerable historian
and researcher on Vico tried to show a proximity between Guicciardinis
aristocratism or pessimism and fascism. This dubious actualisation and black-andwhite division between progressive and reactionary were particularly criticised
by Lifshits (this review was even included in his Collected Works together with his
two articles about Vico).
During Stalins epoch, Lifshits and Lukacs especially underlined the importance
of Hegels category of reconciliation with reality, the fundamentals of which are
found in Vicos works. This concept enabled these philosophers to connect the idea
of the continuation of the revolutionary outbreak of 1917 with true Leninism,
particularly with Stalin (but not with Leo Trotsky or with any other oppositionists):
Vicos philosophy is based on a reconciliation with reality,1 within which he
discovers its rational course and ineluctable laws. This is the beginning of his
radical divergence from eighteenth century illumination and his approach to
Hegel. The most general trait of the Age of Enlightenment may be said to be
rationalism, the tendency to judge everything from the point of view of the
abstract demands of the understanding. In the name of civilization everything
which emerged from the sombre depths of the Middle Ages was contemptuously rejected. To the men of the eighteenth century bourgeois relations
seemed to be a law of rational nature. The class strife, the period of the French
Revolution, and the emergence of the bourgeois way of life dissolved the
illusions of the Enlighteners and evoked a great wave of political disillusionment. Hegel plays the same sort of role with respect to this epoch as did Vico
with respect to the Italian Renaissance. Both of them live within their
memories of the past revolutionary period and both reject the illusions of the
finite understanding and try to discover the rational kernel in the contradictions of real history. (Lifshits 1948, 396397)
Vicos anti-rationalism and his hostility to Cartesianism were re-examined by
Lifshits in favour of the Italian philosopher. His providentialism appears as a
reliable counterbalance to relativism and allows regularity to be found in the
unfolding historical process:
Vico takes an ironical attitude toward the occult wisdom of philosophers, has
more respect for the administrative wisdom of statesmen, but assigns the
highest place to the popular wisdom of the mass of people which makes
history with its hands, makes it unconsciously, along with many a prejudice
and superstition, many a wild and barbaric rite, makes it in the bloody and
1
Acquiescence in actuality (as translated in the English translation of Lifshits article) does not
correspond to the well-known Hegelian concept Versohnung in the original Russian text.
123
bloodless struggle around material property and power. Vico not only tries to
lay bare the natural laws in history, which are independent of the desires of
individuals; he also understands that the contradictory and complex course of
all human and civil things contains some implicit justification, some List
der Vernunft, as Hegel would say. Vico conceives of this justification as a
fantastic divine providence, and the philosophy of history as a rational civil
theology. (Lifshits 1948, 397)
It is very important to note that in Lifshits (1936) two texts, the well-known
principle of verum factum is not mentioned at all. But it was because of this
principle that Vico would be juxtaposed with Marx more than once in the second
half of the twentieth century (Morrison 1978; for more contextual interpretation see
Perez-Ramos 1988). It is understandable why: for Lifshits, as opposed to early
Lukacs in History and Class Consciousness, emphasising this formula would be
equivalent to moving towards romantic Fichteanism or social constructivism, which
Lifshits always opposed. In Soviet philosophy, this principle of cognition stressing
the primacy of activity became important for representatives of the following
generation, e.g. Evald Ilyenkov. Lifshits attitude to Ilyenkov was favourable from
the start, though Lifshits did not at all share Ilyenkovs views on the primacy of
activity.
In the late important collection of Lifshits works, Mifologija drevnjaja i
sovremennaja (1980), Vicos name appears more than once as a symbol of true
historicism in which, nevertheless, a very important anti-relativist point is included:
The painting of Rembrandt can be considered, because it is encoded within a
certain system of signs, as an expression of the interests of the seventeenth
century Dutch bourgeois. It can be said that this work of art expresses
northern German artistic will []
In fact, in front of us there is the disclosure of certain sides of eternal history,
Vicos storia eterna. Here, in front of us, there is verity in the form of
contemplation, seen once and understood with inimitable depth in the given
possible historical perspective; its name is Rembrandt. (Lifshits 1980, 523)
From Lukacs and Lifshits point of view on the idea of high realism, the bourgeois
writer Thomas Mann sees further and deeper, owing to his objective artistic method,
than the proletarian author of essays about factory life or even the pro-Soviet avantgardist Bertolt Brecht. This idea of the objective measure, which is more important
than momentary conjuncture, was very significant for Lifshits.
What, from our perspective, is the main deficiency of this most authoritative
Russian interpretation of Vico in the twentieth century?2 Vicos worldview is
reduced by Lifshits to a system where the informative and, on the whole, most
essential core (a comprehensive historicism and seeing history from below) and
the purely historical shell (providentialism, baroque rhetoric) coexisted as a
concession to place and time. Lifshits did not want to repudiate the historical
specificity of his hero (Vico was creative exactly when his pedantry was becoming
2
About another form of Vicos reception within Soviet humanities (Marr, Bakhtin, Freidenberg), see
Monas (1995), Perlina (2002, 82).
123
A. Dmitriev
poetry). However, in the last instance he came to present the author of Scienza
Nuova as the predecessor of Hegel, the landmark in the history of thought on the
way to Marxism. In this retrospective vision, Lifshits actually constates the
limitation of not only in Soviet but of almost any other orthodox Marxist
interpretation of Vico (as well as in the interpretation of any philosopher before
Marx). The same was true of Maksimovskij, in whose works Vico becomes a herald
of determinism: religion stayed aside from his scientific constructions, and in
general, attempts to connect Vicos theory with catholic belief have no basis
(Maksimovskij 1928a, 13).
Certainly, Lifshits interpretation of Vico can be read in an international context
as a kind of Marxist symmetrical response to Croces early twentieth century
interpretation. Such a forced secularisation of Vicos ideas was typical not only of
Maksimovskij, but also of Valentin Asmus, who was one of the leading specialists
on the history of modern philosophy.
The idea of the cycle, criticism of trivial progressivism, the danger of new
scientific barbarism, a sense of the profound plebeian Truth, and finally, already in
the post-Stalin years, images of the great conservatives of humanity3 (for whom
he felt a special respect: Plato, Vico, Hegel), all of which are found in Lifshits notes
from the archive, testify that Vico, for Lifshits, was not an ordinary author. Lifshits
article in the volume of the Russian edition of Scienza Nuova also testifies that this
work was far from being a mere publishing stint for Lifshits. In the middle of the
1960s, Lukacs proposed that an essay on Vico in be included in a volume of
Lifshits works to be published in German [Lifshits and Lukacs 2011, 109 (letter
dated 17 September 1966)]. A certain self-projection of Vicos fate can be found in
Lifshits late autobiographical notes, which were written on the fate of the
movement in the frightening tones of nostalgia of the people of the 1930s for late
Soviet liberals:
An absence of necessary connections, an inability to come to an understanding
with the chiefs, a pride of the great personality who had to grovel before
scholarly nonentities, prevented him from obtaining a position at the
Department of Law which was the most important at the University for those
times. In the last years of his life Vico exercized considerable influence and
enjoyed a significant circle of students to whom he privately taught the
fundamentals of his The New Science.
It is noteworthy that following the closure of Literaturnyj Kritik, interest in
Vicos philosophy of history was marked with a stamp of a certain unreliability.
Immediately after Stalins death, the literary marshal Aleksandr Fadeev notes:
For instance, certain literary discussions of 19391940 in the journal
Literaturnyj Kritik should be recalled, discussions during which the statements
by Lifshits about eternal categories of reality, about the theory of the cycle
were unmasked. As a confirmation of the idea of the cycle Lifshits cited Vico,
Heraclitus, and Ecclesiastes. But he passed over in silence the fact that one of
3
For an interpretation of Vico beyond the mood of his progressivism, see Lilla (1993).
123
123
A. Dmitriev
in the study of Vico in the West. This was not because of a conspiracy of silence
on the part of the opponents of Marxism. Already at the end of the 1920s, the
Austrian social-democratic theoretician Max Adler was writing about Vico in the
spirit of Maksimovskij, emphasizing Vicos proximity to the Marxist understanding of history and to the social scientific interpretation of the evolution of
humanity (Adler 1929). The leader of the Frankfurt School, Max Horkheimer,
appealed to Vicos ideas in his criticism of the Enlightenment and technological
rationality. He devoted a large chapter to Vico in his book Anfange der
burgerlichen Geschichtsphilosophie (1930). Like Lifshits, Horkheimer contrasts
Vicos serious appeal to the ancient myths with the one-dimensional rationalism
of Cartesians and with Hobbes criticism of prejudices (Horkheimer 1930).
However, Horkheimer is certainly more restrained than Lifshits in underlining the
magisterial line of the modern philosophy of history from Vico straight to Hegel
and Marx. Antonio Gramsci, in his The Prison Notebooks chooses a strategy
similar to Lifshitsthe renewal of the classicseven though, for him,
Machiavelli is much more important (than Vico) in the Italian intellectual
tradition. Gramscis main opponent in this reassessment was Croce (Rubini
2014).
From the 1960s to 1980s, in the renewed interest inf Vico in the West (of which
the protagonists were, among others, Hayden White and Edward Said) the Marxist
component is likewise important (Jay 1988). However, these writers, thinking in the
vein of the Frankfurt School and social criticism, are more interested in Vico and his
conception of praxis and social self-activity (Tagliacozzo 1983) rather than in a
materialist rethinking of his providential historiosophy, as in the case of Lifshits (his
late attention to the ideas of mesotes, the median way, etc.). Soviet scholars of the
1960s and 1970s (for instance, Leonid Batkin in 1976) did not attend international
conferences on Vico for ideological and censorship reasons (Tagliacozzo 1994,
176). In any case, at that time little attention was paid to Vico in the USSR other
than haphazard and chaotic but retrospectively important discussions by certain
Soviet philosophers (Mamardashvili, Iljenkov) and Althusser as well as Western
Marxists with regard to what Marxism owes to Today it can be said that Soviet
strategies of interpretation of the Scienza Nuova (in the works of Maksimovskij or
Kissel) seem not only ideologically, but content-wise outdated in comparison with
the work of Erich Auerbach on the aesthetic historicism of Vico in the 19201940s
(Auerbach 2013) or Isaiah Berlins interpretation (Vico as the Opponent of the
Enlightenment). For sure, the contextualising rather than modernising approach to
understanding Vico has gained the upper hand (including the Marxist interpretations
by Horkheimer and Gramscians) (Mali 2012). Lifshits vision is important not only
in order to understand the Italian philosopher on his own terms, but also in order to
interpret his legacy in the twentieth century as well as for the development of Soviet
thought in general.
Acknowledgements This research, carried out in 2015, was supported by The National Research
University Higher School of Economics Academic Fund Programme Grant No. 1505005. I thank
Anna Abakunova and Huseyin Oylupinar for important consultations during preparation of this text.
123
References
Adler, M. (1929). Die Bedeutung Vicos fur die Entwicklung des soziologischen Denkens. Archiv fur
Geschichte des Sozialismus und der Arbeiterbewegung, 14, 280304.
Artizov, A. N. (Ed.) (1999). Vlast i khudozhestvennaja intelligentsija. Dokumenty TsK RKP(b)
VKP(b), VChKOGPUNKVD o kulturnoj politike 19171953.
Auerbach, E. (2013). Philologie als kritische Kunst. Neue Einleitung zur Scienza Nuova (1947)/Edition,
Kommentar und Nachwort bei M. Vialon. In P. Konig (Ed.), Vico in Europa zwischen 1800 und
1950 (pp. 223319). Heidelberg: Universitatsverlag Winter.
Clark, K. (2011). Moscow, the Fourth Rome: Stalinism, Cosmopolitanism, and the Evolution of Soviet
Culture 19311941. London: Harvard University Press.
Fadeev, A. (1953). Nekotorye voprosy raboty Sojuza pisateley. Literaturnaja gazeta, 38, 2.
German, L. Rev. (1940). Dzhambattista Viko, Osnovanija novoj nauki ob obshchej prirode natsij, per.
A. Gubera, vstup. st. M. A. Lifshitsa, M., Pod znamenem marksizma, (12), 194204.
Horkheimer, M. (1930). Vico und die Mythologie. In M. Horkheimer (Ed.), Anfange der burgerlichen
Geschichtsphilosophie (pp. 95114). Stuttgart.
Jay, M. (1988). Vico and Western Marxism. In M. Jay (Ed.), Fin-de-sie`cle Socialism and Other Essays
(pp. 6781). London: Routledge.
Karev, N. (1924). Professor istorii v krugovorote zhizni. [Review of: Vipper, Robert (1923) Krugovorot
istorii, Berlin: Vozrozhdenue, 1923]. Pod znamenem marksizma, 1, 262264.
Kissel, M. A. (1980). Dzhambattista Viko, M.: Mysl.
Lifshits, M. (1933). Johann Joakhim Vinkelman i tri epokhi burzhuaznogo mirovozzreniya. In I.
Winckelmann (Ed.), Istoriya iskusstva drevnosti (pp. vii-lxii). M.: L: Academia.
Lifshits, M. (1934). Rez.: Guicciardini F. Sochineniya. M.: Academia, 1934. Literaturnaya gazeta, 10
ijunja, 2.
Lifshits, M. A. (1939). Dzhambattista Viko. Literaturnyj kritik, 1939(2), 1941.
Lifshits, M. A. (1948). Giambattista Vico (transl. Henry F. Mins), Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 8, 391414.
Lifshits, M. A. (1980). Mifologija drevnjaja i sovremennaja. M.: Iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A. (1986 [1936]). Dopolneniya k statye: Dzhambattista Vico//Lifshits M.A. Sobranie
sochinenij v trekh tomakh (Vol. II, pp. 2956). M.: Iskusstvo.
Lifshits, M. A. (1988). Iz avtobiografii idej, Kontekst 1987. Literaturno-teoreticheskie issledovanija (pp.
264318). M.: Nauka.
Lifshits, M. A., & Lukach, G. (2011). Perepiska. 19311970. M.: Grundrisse.
Lilla, M. (1993). G. B. Vico: The making of an anti-modern. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Maksimovskij, V. N. (1928a). Viko i ego teorija obshchestvennykh krugovorotov. Arkhiv K. Marksa i F.
Engelsa, 4, 762.
Maksimovskij, V. N. (1928b). Karl Marks: vypiski iz sochinenij Makiavelli. Arkhiv K. Marksa i F.
Engelsa, 4, 432451.
Maksimovskij, V. N. (1929). Ideja diktatury u Makiavelli. Istorik-marksist, 13, 5594.
Maksimovskij, V. N. (1930). Novye knigi o Makjavelli. Arkhiv K. Marksa i F. Engelsa, 5, 457465.
Maksimovskij, V. N. (1935). Esteticheskie vzglyady Dzhambattista Viko. Literaturnyy kritik, 11, 1027.
Mali, J. (2012). The legacy of Vico in modern cultural history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Monas, S. (1995). Vico and Bakhtin. New Vico Studies, 13, 144154.
Morrison, J. C. (1978). Vicos principle of verum is factum and the problem of historicism. Journal of the
History of Ideas, 34, 579595.
Perez-Ramos, A. (1988). Francis Bacons idea of science and the makers knowledge tradition. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Perlina, N. (2002). Olga Freidenbergs works and days. Bloomington: Slavica Publishers.
Radek, K. (1934). Razgovor Nikkolo Makjavelli s Zh.-Zh. Russo o demokratii i diktature. Izvestija, 261,
7 nojabrja, 7.
Rubini, R. (2014). The other renaissance: Italian Humanism between Hegel and Heidegger. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press.
Sziklai, L. (1992). After the Proletarian Revolution: Georg Lukacss Marxist Development, 19301945.
Budapest: Akademiai Kiado.
Tagliacozzo, G. (Ed.). (1983). Vico and Marx: Affinities and contrasts. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities
Press.
123
A. Dmitriev
Tagliacozzo, G. (1994). The study of Vico worldwide and the future of Vico studies. In M. Danesi (Ed.),
Giambattista Vico and Anglo-America science: Philosophy and writing (pp. 171188). Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
van der Zweerde, E. (1997). Soviet historiography of philosophy: Istoriko-Filosofkaja Nauka. Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Vico, G. (1940). Osnovaniya novoy nauki ob obshchey prirode natsiy, per. A. Gubera, vstup. st. M. A.
Lifshitsa. M: Goslitizdat.
123
123
S. Klimova
It seems that even Soviet Marxism had a slight romantic touch: myths were not
only products of creative work of the people performing aesthetic or compensatory functions in culture. The encyclopaedia Mify narodov mira (Myths of the
Peoples of the World), published in two volumes in 1980 and edited by S.
A. Tokarev, was a unique attempt to represent the most important myths of the
peoples of the world, but likewise certain scientific theories, trends, and schools of
mythology studies. There were a number of Soviet scholars eminent in linguistics,
philology, and literature, who investigated myths and mythology. Prominent
examples are the representatives of the TartuMoscow School, such as Yu. Lotman,
M. Gasparov, V. Toporov, and Zara Mints. They maintained lively contacts with
representatives of French structuralist semiotics, especially the Tel-Quel group, and
of course the French scholars, obviously following in Levi-Strauss footsteps and
inspired by de Saussure, wrote some well-known works on the topic. Of the latter,
Roland Barthes Mythologies (1957) is perhaps one of the best known (see Gasparov
1996). The collections of this school included the works Ye. M. Meletinsky and V.
Ya. Propp who were successfully developing a structural-semiotic method. A
special place in research on mythology belonged to A. F. Losev, who defined myth
as a special type of symbol and mythology as a science capable of grasping both the
essence of an individual thing and the whole world in a special discourse.
At the same time, Mikhail Lifshits was developing his teaching in Soviet
philosophy. His conception was fully independent, Marxist, and simultaneously
corresponded entirely to structuralist tendencies. In addition, Lifshits was one of the
Soviet romantics, believing in the high significance of ancient mythology and also
in its positive educational role, in relation to his own time as well. Ye. Meletinsky
pointed out that for Lifshits myth was the reaction of poetry against prose: the
point of view of M. Lifshits is sufficiently original and interesting and is in essence
typically romantic (Meletinskij 1995, p. 149). This same thought was poetically
expressed by one of the few contemporary researchers of Lifshits mythology, L.
K. Naumenko, who pointed out that for Lifshits myth was a hot point of
contemporaneity (gorjachaja tochka sovremennosti), and he himself wasnt a
cold sage (Naumenko 2010, p. 91). It must be emphasized that Lifshits was not as
lucky as the representatives of the Tartu School or Losev due to the fact that this
aspect of his creative work has not attracted as much attention. This remains the
case today. In this article I will try to fill in this gap, even if only partially.
First published in the anthology Ideji esteticheskogo vospitanija, vol. 1 (Moskva: Iskusstvo 1973,
pp. 7113). Here quoted according to re-publication in Lifshits 1984.
123
Logomythy
Lifshits claims to possess the right theory of myth, its true logic which he
called logomythy (logomifija), i.e. the reason of myth, its underlying content
(Lifshits 1984, p. 366). The term cannot but evoke an association with Losevs
logos of myths: By mythology, inasmuch as we consider it to be a science, we
mean [] the logos of myths (Losev 1990a, b, pp. 162164).
123
S. Klimova
123
123
S. Klimova
Das Ganze, wie es im Kopfe als Gedankenganzes erscheint, ist ein Produkt des denkenden Kopfes, der
sich die Welt in der ihm einzig moglichen Weise aneignet, einer Weise, die verschieden ist von der
kunstlerisch-, religios-, praktisch-geistigen Aneignung dieser Welt.
123
ambivalent images of any myth. The fact that literary fiction and even philosophy
hark back to mythological imagery is also important.
One cannot deny that Geek mythology occupies the most comfortable perch
on the historical ladder. It is closer to its loftier heirs literature and
philosophy without forfeiting its originality that stems from its being based
on tales of hoary antiquity. In short, to borrow Aristotles idiom, it is the
mesotes of the system, the true middle which simultaneously represents the
akrotes, or the supreme (Lifshits 1984, p. 364).
In that sense his ideas are very close to the theory of O. M. Freidenberg:
It may look odd to us, but these struggling heroes, kidnapping one other,
represent an archaic form of our future abstractions, our philosophies and
epistemologies, the systems of our perception of the world (Freidenberg 1978,
p. 50).
A staunch opponent of any formalism, including the structural study of myths,
Lifshits unexpectedly finds himself on the same page with Levi-Strauss, having
discovered in his structural typology proof of the Hegelian idea of the universal
ascent of thought from the lower to the higher, from the abstract to the concrete.
After almost a century of derision of the savage philosopher Levi-Strauss proved
the capacity of the savage for abstract thinking (Lifshits 1984, p. 367),
classification, and generalisations. However, in Lifshitss opinion, the Frenchman
exaggerated the importance of his own mathematical discoveriesformalization
of primitive logicto throw out the baby with the bathwater.
Levi-Strauss uses the term primitive logic forgetting that this logic, in its
relentless consistency, represents a woeful shortage of logic. The childish
passion for formal structures is in inverse relationship to logomythia, that is,
the development of the more general meaning that makes the myth of
Prometheus and Heracles a phenomenon of concrete thinking, of logos, as it
was understood by the Greeks. The less formal the order, the more concrete
the content. This was how modern European thought developed after
Scholasticism (Lifshits 1984, p. 370).
The foregoing analysis has shown that when Lifshits attacks and criticizes, he does
not appear to be a hypocritical orthodox dinosaur who seeks to thwart new thinking.
His critique is at its most powerful when he inveighs against vulgar Marxists
whom he detested as much as he detested modernists of every stripe, waging his
battle on two fronts, albeit in accordance with the laws of dialectics. He often
dresses in Marxist garb the ideas of Russian and Western Enlighteners of the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries who opposed the dualism of spirit and matter,
idealized nature and its significance as a subject, and offered poetic panegyrics to
objective truth and beauty.
He denied a direct correlation between the level of economic and cultural
development and creative thought; logomythia reveals an inverse relationship: the
huge edifice of custom arises on a small economic basis. He sees the foundation of
the truth above all in nature as the generating element (echoes of Spinoza here). His
123
S. Klimova
dialectic of nature is highly original since for him it is not only a kind force, as
with the French Enlighteners, it is also a dark force capable of revenge:
A substance that does not have the form of a subject cannot take revenge, but
man by his careless actions renders it active, or, to use Hegels words, turns
substance into a subject. Rather, nature itself at the level of human being
acquires subjective qualities, but it happens not in the human head taken
separately from the external object, but in the process of practical interaction
between man and nature (Lifshits 1984, p. 382).
In this interpretation there is no dialectical materialist interaction between man and
nature; on the contrary, through technology (a synonym of tampering with nature)
people develop a predatory consciousness seeking dominance. Nor does he agree
with the Marxist classics who maintained that all mythology overcomes and
dominates and shapes the forces of nature in the imagination and by the
imagination; it therefore vanishes with the advent of real mastery over them
(Marx 1973, p. 110).
On the contrary, Lifshits is convinced that such dominance is likely to provoke
a backlash, the revenge of nature on people who have come to think of themselves
as gods on stilts (Nietzsche). Another object of mythologisation is the moral
relations among people and the world of human experiences. The danger posed by
another and the revenge of nature are abiding subjects of discussion, aestheticisation, and assessment for Lifshits (he frequently uses examples from ancient
mythology). To him, the notion of harmony/disharmony between the micro- and
macro-cosmoses is key. Stripped of mysticism and deification, harmony arises not
only from genetic myths, but from logomythia itself which carries the notion of a
spurious world that lives according to the law of liberty inherent in the life processes
as their inner part, as the absolute truth and reasonable basis (Lifshits 1984,
p. 420).
It proves the ability of primitive humans to think in a perfectly concrete manner
(logo-mythically), to grasp the overall meaning not only of their own life, but of life
in nature and history even if it appears to be nonsense in terms of formal logic.
Behind the false form of mythical images lurks the true and eternal content and
profound existential meaning that are often more truthful than the formulas of cold
reason of modern scholastic thinkers.
Thus, logomythy demonstrates the overcoming or the irrationalnonsensical
element in the life of ancient societies by linking it to the rational or meaningful
content of artistic images. But on the other hand, logomythy contains more than a
hint of the contradictions, the crisis of rationalism and pragmatism in the twentieth
century, which in their real dominance ruthlessly destroyed harmony and the
spiritual kinship of nature, Cosmos, and man. The logomythia of the ancients is a
key to the description of the crisis of the Soviet mythology which first brought up
believers in the communist ideal by exposing them to lofty artistic myths about
justice and equality, and then turned everything into a historical madness of wars,
prison camps, and the massive silence of rock-hard Marxists.
123
V. G. Arslanov uses Lifshitss mention of the concept of the gap to stress the proximity of his ideas
to post modernism and the concept of difference introduced by Jacques Derrida (see: Arslanov 2009,
pp. 93107). I am more inclined to think that by gap (schel) Lifshits meant the elusive point of balance
between opposing forces of life and consciousness, nature and society in a period of transition to a new
type of social organization that highlights the logical threads of any mythology rather than the battle
against logocentrism with J. Derrida and various discriminations used in Deconstructivism. Lifshits did
not mince his words in expressing his attitude to such fiddling with French words by the Derridas of
his time: The American ethnologist Paul Reidin writes that it is hard to explain why such notions as
representations collectives, participation mystique, mentalite prelogique, mythisches Denken have met
with such universal enthusiasm. To be sure, the reason is the times we have been living in for two
generations already. The latter is absolutely true of course (Lifshits 1984, 351).
123
S. Klimova
individual people. A Greek was not only a creature of a polis capable of community
and solidarity with a collective, but an individual capable of suffering, compassion,
love, hatred, revenge, and self-sacrifice, like any person in any other era. It is
another question whether in a Greek myth life manifests itself as individual life at its
intersection with the life of a genus in the shape of sensual (plastic) images in art,
literature, philosophical poetry, and journalism.
Whenever a child encounters a wall (to borrow Dostoyevskys word) it
turns to a myth as the realm of freedom, the story of the free basis of all things
that in its position is entangled in a web of necessity. Myth is the kingdom of
freedom people find only in their fantasy and do not find in the dreary day-today reality (Lifshits 1984, p. 413).
The wall is a common metaphor of modern existentialism which describes a
situation when lifes issues cannot be resolved through the laws of formal logic
outside the self-generated myth about happiness and meaning. The realm of
freedom is the self-same nature which suddenly acquires a social and human
meaning (Lifshits 1984, p. 395), and the lofty myth that gives aesthetic shape to
the best ethical (collective) aspirations of people is a crucial element that pacifies
and harmonises a persons life. Such myths include the ideas of the kingdom of
freedom, communism, justice, eternal love and faith in the ultimate triumph of good
over evil.
Conclusion
The upshot is that myth can maintain the fickle balance in transitional periods only
if its content embodies profound ethical and aesthetic meaning that unites society
into a collective Self, i.e. when it grows out of the vital needs of people. In a
disintegrating autonomous world of consumption and total alienation it can crumble
overnight and become a historical nightmare. This is what happened in Russia a
couple of decades ago.
Leaning towards conservatism is fraught with the sway of historical madness,
demagogy, nationalistic excesses, and the dance of the possessed on the
historical bones of the ancestors; going to extremes in the latesttranshuman
myth-making threatens with the technological liquidation of living human being.
Lifshits bequeathed to us the idea of harmony of the micro- and macro-cosmos
which sees logomythy as the measure of man keeping peace with the Universe,
and as the harmonious unity of rational and emotional-sensual elements, ethics and
aesthetics, logic and myth. Any deviations are fraught with social, spiritual, and
man-made tragedies, and endless cycles of historical madness.
References
Arslanov, V. G. (2009). A.F. Losev i Mikh. Lifshits o Homere i drevnej mifologii (dve koncepcii
Absoljuta). In Voprosy filosofii, vol. 3.
123
123
123
296
E. Mareeva
123
297
objective and the subjective is not excessive.1 By contrast, Pavlov was interested
precisely in the subjective element of the human reflection of the world, which made
him the target of criticism in his time by Bulgarian and Soviet comrades. The
preface to the second edition of Pavlovs Theory of Reflection reads, in part:
The authors concentration on the subjective aspect of mans cognition of
reality is so great that it sometimes produces language that may lead to
subjectivism (Georgiev 1949, xxvi).
While giving due to mans active attitude to the worldfrom practice to scientific
knowledge and artLifshits distinguishes in the cognitional process the understanding of a phenomenon and its essence. The subjective image of an individual
thing, delivered by our sensual perception, is one thing, while the knowledge of the
laws of the objective world, obtained by reason and science, is another thing.
Commenting on Lockes distinction between primary and secondary
properties of things, both Lifshits and Pavlov insist on the adequacy of the
perception of colour, taste, etc. But they diverge seriously over the issue of the
causes of the subjectivity of perceived images. Lifshits attributes subjectivity
above all to our bodily organization, invoking neurophysiology and other natural
sciences to bolster his argument.
If you do not find among neurons, etc. any image of a red body, there is none
inside that body, instead there is only movement and reflection (in the physical
sense) of waves of a certain length. (Lifshits 2003, 339).
Pavlov, to the contrary, first, emphasizes the subjective aspect of every
perception, and more broadly, of mans cognition of the world, and second, shifts
the accent from natural to social conditioning of human perception. Citing Marx to
the effect that the eye has become a human eye just like its object has become a
social, human object created by man for man,2 Pavlov stresses:
It is in the process of mastering (humanization) of nature that man
humanizes his own senses and brain, and accordingly his own sensual
perceptions and thought which for the first time become conscious in the full,
precise and true sense of the word [] That is why modern man can, for
example, see colours and shapes to such a degree and with such nuances that
not only animals, but even humans in eras when production and social life
were poorly developed could not attain (Pavlov 1949, 111).
Lifshits builds his dialectical ontognoseology into the tradition that runs through
the whole history of philosophy to the works of Lenin, seeing in the theory of
1
This is expressed in the following way in Materialism and Empiriocriticism: That the conception of
matter must also include thoughts [] is a muddle, for if such an inclusion is made, the
epistemological contrast between mind and matter, idealism and materialism, a contrast upon which
Dietzgen himself insists, loses all meaning. That this contrast must not be made excessive,
exaggerated, metaphysical (Lenin 1972, quoted from the Internet version in: https://www.marxists.org/
archive/lenin/works/1908/mec/four8.htm).
2
See Marx/Engels (1974, 540): Das Auge ist zum menschlichen Auge geworden, wie sein Gegenstand
zu einem gesellschaftlichen, menschlichen, vom Menschen fur den Menschen herruhrenden.
123
298
E. Mareeva
reflection a Copernican revolution. Clearly, the revolution has to do not with the
problem of subjectivity of human perception, but with a more fundamental problem
of the nature of the subject of cognition. In ontognoseology the true subject is
material being whereas man is an instrument of its self-reflection. As Lifshits writes,
the identity is not between subject and object, but between the logical law of
being, its rational character, and our reason. More precisely, our reason is a
repetition, concentration, and a special way of expressing the rational
character of the world (Lifshits 2010, 18).
A key word here is concentration which prevents us from interpreting repetition
as banal copying. Lifshits frequently refers to the relations of modality in the
endless recreation of the world. The mechanism of this modality consists in the
fact that the diffuse and reified universality of the world is actualized in
increasingly clear and adequate forms. Man occupies a special place on this
dialectical ladder because in his social practice nature achieves maximum
concentration of its universal reasonable content. What is higher than the
individual? What is more fundamental than elementary matter? Lifshits asks
rhetorically. Thus the world of culture becomes part of gnoseology not by
transcending natural being, but by drawing closer (returning) to its essence. By
recreating nature in his social practice, man consciously isolates its laws and
creates its most accurate spiritual mirrors in science and art.
In recreating the objective world, consciousness derives from it the dormant
universality and makes it real by practically shaping it [] Mimesis with
regard to the external world acquires a kind of autonomy, consciousness
reproduces its own law which is the law of repeated reality (Lifshits 2010, 26).
On that point, Lifshitss ontognoseology directly challenges the theory of reflection,
as interpreted by Pavlov, and is indeed its antipode. Carried away by the common
enthusiasm for the creation of a new world, Pavlov sees reflection as primarily
the basis for the re-ordering of the world by man. Referring to the Communist
future, he writes:
And then human thought (scientific, artistic, etc.) will attain its final and
perfect dialectical character. And then human thought the product and
function of human and natural being and mans cause will itself finally and
completely emerge as the decisive factor, will completely and finally free
itself of blind social necessity and creatively change the world, man and itself
(Pavlov 1949, 111).
Understandably, Pavlov seeks to balance the pathos of freedom and creativity that is
akin to Fichtean activism by making objective necessity the foundation of mans
subjective activities. The creative force and effectiveness of consciousness, he
stressed, must be achieved not by negating matter and its objective necessity, but
through objective cognition (reflection) and their real mastery (see Pavlov 1949,
112).
123
299
It will be seen that, in Pavlov, man is not an instrument of self-reflection and selfknowledge of nature, but an independent subject that transforms it. Methodologically, the difference between the interpretations of the Leninist theory of reflection
by Lifshits and by Pavlov is that the former considers creativity as part of the selfreflection of nature while the latter, on the contrary, considers the reflection of
natural being to be part of mans creative activity.
It is worth noting that the problem of linking the theory of reflection and the
subjects activity in cognition and practice gained a new relevance in the post-war
years in connection with the debate around so-called creative Marxism, promoted
by the Yugoslavian journal Praxis (19641974). The Praxis school that sprang up
during that period survived until the collapse of Yugoslavia.
The section of the book Lenin kak filosof (1969) which is devoted to the Leninist
theory of reflection, highlights the danger of opposing the activity of the subject to
the reflection of objective reality.
This is the true meaning of the attacks on the theory of reflection not only by
bourgeois philosophers, but also by those Marxists who seek to correct the
Marxist-Leninist theory of reflection. Thus, for example, in maintaining that
no version of the reflection theory (not even an improved one) can be
harmonized with the Marxist theory of man as an active practical being, the
Yugoslavian philosopher Gajo Petrovic separates human activity and the value
of that activity which only brings practical results when it is based on an
accurate reflection of reality, thus committing an unpardonable sin against
Marxism (Lenin kak filosof, 180).
For Petrovic, one of the leaders of the Praxis School, the concept of practice in the
early works of Marx did not dovetail with any version of the theory of reflection.
But this is precisely what Todor Pavlov, who was thoroughly conversant with
Marxs early manuscripts of 1844 as early as the 1940s, sought to do. Already in the
1940s he was criticized for being inclined to subjectivism on account of his attempt
to incorporate early Marx into the theory of reflection.
For his part, Lifshits opposed the pathos of the idea of the radical transformation
of the world, and he did so not only by criticizing modernist art (see Gutov
2005, 2007). He stresses that, according to Lenin, the criterion of practice is flexible
and relative. In effect, Lifshits offers his own interpretation of the Marxian first
Thesis on Feuerbach according to which the object, reality, and sensuality should be
regarded not as an object of contemplation, but as human sensual activity, practice
in a subjective way. Lifshits writes:
How can one put a thing in the position of a mirror of other things? This is the
problem of an active and adequate consciousness. This means considering an
object not only in the form of an object, but in the form of a subject, in a
practical way. Practice must turn an object into a subject, reveal in us its
subjective properties, in other words, make it a mirror (Lifshits 2010, 42).
Conspicuously absent here is Marxs emphasis on human sensual activity. Without
it, practice is anything but transformation of an object by a subject. On the contrary,
through a paradoxical swapping of roles the object is put in the position of the
123
300
E. Mareeva
subject, which in this capacity forms its reflection in us. What is left of practice,
whose mechanism is expressed in the dialectic of objectifying and de-objectifying
(VergegenstandlichungEntgegenstandlichung), is only de-objectification, as seen
from notes in Lifshitss archive.
It is true that objectification poses a threat to the theory of reflection. Lukacs,
too, failed to show how these concepts agree. That calls for the concept of an
objective mirror of which objectification is a continuation (Lifshits 2002,
112).
Lifshits is ready to admit that objectification is an inalienable part of human activity,
but only if objectification merely continues but does not change nature. In other
words, mans practical activity put through the crucible of ontognoseology, loses its
creative character. While Pavlovs version of the reflection theory makes human
creativity productive, in Lifshits it is reproductive only. Nature itself creates while
practice based on mimesis is incapable of generating new forms of being. Where
that happens we get something stillborn, a product of arbitrary deviation from the
truth.
123
301
123
302
E. Mareeva
other hand this modality turns even moral responsibility into a miraculous quality
of our personality.
But does it follow, asks Lifshits, that individual consciousness has its little
corner of subjective freedom independently of being?(Lifshits 204, 313) Again,
this is a rhetorical question prompted by the concept of freedom as a deviation from
the need for natural and social order. What Lifshits refers to in this context as
relative freedom and relative autonomy cannot be an instrument for changing
being itself. Relative freedom offers only a corridor which man uses to advance
towards the Truth.
Lifshits writes: It takes luck chance to join true being, to become its organ
(Lifshits 2004, 313). Therefore, in describing the mechanism of becoming part of
true being Lifshits defines not the parameters of freedom, but the behaviour of
being that offers a relative opportunity to make a choice. Being meets free
consciousness half-way. It must have a corresponding relief (coaction, Grace in
Christianity) (ibid.).
For Lifshits, mystical parallels on the issue of freedom are not accidental, which
is why his ontognoseology looks more contradictory.
The content of consciousness is broader than consciousness proper, and what
it cannot accommodate, the infinite, appears as irrational, as eccentricities and
quirks (the irrational according to Freud).
And he goes on:
In our soul there are limits, censorship by which we forcibly limit the content
of the infinite and thus make it more accessible (Lifshits 2004, 292).
The latter sentence implies the eternal challenge to reason which irrationalists have
always passed off as reason. If the absolute truth defies reason, there is something
not quite rational in it. Similarly, for Lifshits, in the light of the infinity of being the
foundations of the world are not quite rational, and reason cannot be the sole tuning
fork of the diffuse universality of the world. This is particularly true of the
paradoxes of history and culture which reach out to infinity.
123
303
the horses allegory is not an image of the trauma of history abstracted from its
own course. Platos world of ideas deals with eternal and perfect models whereas
oblomovshchina and tolstovshchina, with all their contradictions, cannot be
perpetuated, and of course they have no prototypes in nature.
The principle of non-resistance to evil is more than a sigh of an oppressed
creature. Tolstovshchina is the real-life choice of the followers of Count Tolstoy.
The truth of such abstractions does not consist only in their being mirrors. The
reality of these living types consists in the fact that they do not merely reflect
history, but take part in it. In this capacity the mirrors of culture do not fit into the
general schemes of the reflection theory, which is particularly apparent in the case
of objective and subjective products of fantasy.
According to Lifshits, fantastic images, in terms of their artistic value, can be
more powerful than the reproduction of the external aspects of life. Even historically
limited forms of art may isolate and highlight rather than obscure things. Another
version of such fantastic images is Greek idealism, beginning with Socrates and
Plato, in which, as Lifshits writes, a false expression of the truth of being did not
prevent these delusions from delivering huge benefits to humanity.
The fantastic image, a distorting mirror of being, such as the vulgar
sociology of the 1930s, is a different case. Philosophical systems, expressing the
arrogance of the collective subject concerning its capacity to create and recreate
reality, are distorting mirrors. The fate of Kants doctrine is a highly revealing
example. The virtue of the Kantian philosophy, Lifshits believes, is that in addition
to the empirical subject he introduced the transcendental subject thus imputing
qualities of the subject to external reality.
Does it not negate the rights of the human subject? The conventional wisdom
has it that it does. In reality genuine subjectivity is not reduced to empirical
singularity, but predating the corporeal form is played out with respect to the
infinite external world and, one may even say, is born within it (Lifshits 2014).
This is a debatable interpretation of Kants transcendentalism. Nevertheless,
according to Lifshits, personality here is already perceived as one facet of the
Universe. Neo-Kantians moved in the opposite direction recognizing the
objectivity of the world of culture as the antipode of natural being. On this count,
Neo-Kantianism can be considered to be one of humanitys collective dreams.
Society, communication, culture are not a subjective human convention. It is
in itself a reflection, reproduction of the universality of the world, which alone
makes it possible (Lifshits 2004, 240).
Lifshits invokes the concept of a blase collective subject to describe not only the
theory, but the practice of the embodiment of the dark images of collective
fantasy where arbitrariness brings forth cultural forms that are not viable.
It is interesting that in opposing the distorting mirrors of subjectivism Lifshits
enlists the support of natural sciences. At various periods of his work he tries to use
natural sciences as a foundation of ontognoseology. The mechanism of change and
natural selection, he believes, can be the true mirror of the birth of the new in
history. Agreeing that new types of being arise as deviations from the norm, through
123
304
E. Mareeva
anomaly, through the particular and the partial, Lifshits extends this principle to any
type of relations, the history of the economy, art, and so on.
Indeed, history by deviating from its previous type, by uncertain change and
natural selection forms itself into a system to become Vicos eternal history
(Lifshits 2003, 1845).
Thus elements of Darwinism creep into ontognoseology. Occasionally, even
Lifshitss exquisite taste seems to fail him.
Community in nature, is a phenomenon that predates and does not post-date
the individual Therefore social phenomena reminiscent of society in nature,
reminiscent of colonies of polyps constitute a reception of an earlier stage. An
angle from which to analyze sociality with ants and bees. The inclusion of
unity of individuals whereas in reality there is no genuine individuality, in
higher animals sociality is either undeveloped or is developed much less
(Lifshits 2010, 23).
This tendentious approach leads to paradoxical results. Where, according to Popper,
it is but one step from an amoeba to Einstein, so, according to Lifshits, the distance
between the sociality of polyps and the Bolshevik Party is not all that great.
We see that Lifshits has sympathy for the prospect of deriving the social from the
biological, history from the outcomes of natural selection. While the transition from
the animal kingdom to humanity is a leap, for Lifshits there is no element of
negation in such a leap. But human forms of life arose to compensate for mans
animal inadequacy which is why the social and the biological are antagonists. Todor
Pavlov also, in his own way, notes the negative aspect in understanding the essence
of man. The fact that the opus magnum Leninskaja teorija otrazhenija i
sovremennost, edited by Pavlov, was published on the occasion of the centenary
of Lenins birth meant that his position was accepted as the official position. The
versions of the reflection theory presented in it by Pavlov and other contributors
placed accents in ways that were unacceptable for Lifshits. The section Reflection
and Creativity reads in part:
This means that acting according to the laws of nature people simultaneously
go beyond the framework of natural existence, enter a form of life activity that
is different from nature, namely, society which assumes various forms in
history, history being the true act of the birth of man.
And further along:
The essence of practice is that in the process each time it has to transform the
given conditions into conditions of their self-negation, supplanting them and
giving birth from them to a new reality (Leninskaja teorija, 584).
It would be no exaggeration to say that Todor Pavlov and Mikhail Lifshits
demonstrate opposite trendsone subjectivist and the other objectivistin their
interpretation of Lenins theory of reflection as a distinct phenomenon in Soviet
philosophy. They isolate and juxtapose, even though not in a banal form, two
dialectical aspects of the Marxist concept of practice, namely, reflection and
123
305
References
Georgiev, F. I. (1949). Vstupitelnaja statja. In T. Pavlov (Ed.), Teorija otrazhenija Osnovnye voprosy
teorii poznanija dialekticheskogo materializma. Moskva: Izdatelstvo inostrannoj literatury.
Gutov, D. (2005). Die marxistisch-leninstische Asthetik in der postkommunistischen Epoche. Michael
Lifshits. In B. Groys, A. von der Heiden, & P. Weibel (Eds.), Zuruck aus der Zukunft.
Osteuropaische Kulturen im Zeitalter des Postkommunismus (pp. 709737). Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp.
Gutov, D. (2007) Marksistsko-leninskaja estetika v postkommunisticheskuju epokhu. Mikhail Lifshits. In
Svobodnaja mysl, Vol. 2, pp. 125141.
Lenin, V. I. (1972). Materialism and Empiriocriticism. In Collected works, Vol. 14, Moscow: Progress
1972. Here quoted according to the Internet version, in: https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/
works/1908/mec/four8.htm. Accessed 25. 6. 2016.
Lifshits, M. A. (2002). Lukacs. In Voprosy filosofii, 12.
Lifshits, M. A. (2003). Dialog s Evaldom Ilyenkovym (Problema idealnogo). Moskva: ProgressTradicija.
Lifshits, M. A. (2004). Chto takoe klassika? Ontognoseologija. Smysl mira. Istinnaja seredina, Moskva:
Iskusstvo XXI vek.
Lifshits, M. A. (2010). Varia. Moskva: Grundrisse.
Lifshits, M. A. (2014). Bytie i soznanie. In http://mesotes.narod.ru/lifshiz/bitieisoznanie.htm. Accessed
11.11.2014.
Marx K., & Engels, F. (1974). Werke, 43 Bde., Erganzungsband, Erster Teil, Dietz Verlag, Berlin/DDR.
Pavlov, T. (1949). Teorija otrazhenija. Osnovnye voprosy teorii poznanija dialekticheskogo materializma.
Moskva: Izdatelstvo inostrannoj literatury.
Pavlov, T. (Ed.). (1969). Leninskaja teorija otrazhenija i sovremennost. Moskva, Sofija: Nauka i
iskusstvo.
Rozental, M. M. (Ed.). (1969). Lenin kak filosof. Moskva: Politizdat.
123
Abstract In his essay Das literarische Erbe Hegels (The fate of Hegels literary legacy, 1931) Lifshits addressed the fate of Hegelianism in the first third of
the 20th century. He observed a struggle surrounding Hegels heritage between
Marxism on the one hand, and Neo-Hegelianism or ,,the Hegel renaissance on the
other hand and came to the conclusion that the only legitimate Hegel heir is
Marxism. According to Lifshits, Neo-Hegelianism exploits the Hegelian state to
justify the modern power state by illegitimately shifting the meaning of the
Hegelian concept of the state. Thanks to Koje`ves philosophy, a diffuse yet profound Neo-Hegelian influence continues to have an impact on modern thinking,
which gives cause in this essay to examine Lifshits verdict on the illegitimacy of
the Neo-Hegelian Hegel heritage by confronting his argumentation with Koje`ves
Neo-Hegelian concept. So, this essay will update Lifshits perspective on the fate of
Hegelianism and broaden it beyond the horizon that was available to Lifshits.
Keywords Marxism Hegel renaissance Neo-Hegelianism Koje`ve Bourgeois
Citizen (citoyen) Hegelian concept of the state Modern power state
Lifshits addressed Hegel time and again throughout his life; and his was an interest
of many facets. It ranged from addressing Hegels theoretical philosophyin
particular questions concerning truth and the ideato working on Hegels
philosophy of art. I am concerned with another aspect of this engagement with
Hegel, viz., Lifshits view of the fate of Hegelianism in the first third of the 20th
century, considered from todays vantage point.
Lifshits was an observer and participant in a struggle surrounding Hegel; a
struggle which became the subject of Lifshits essay Das literarische Erbe Hegels
& Annett Jubara
[email protected]
1
Germersheim, Germany
123
A. Jubara
(The fate of Hegels literary legacy), written in 1931 (Lifschitz 1988). In this
struggle, Lifshits takes sides and comes to a conclusion which at first appears trivial
since it is what would be expected from a Soviet Marxist author, namely that
Hegels only legitimate heir is the proletariatthat is to say, Marxism or the
revolutionary wing of the labor movement. Less trivial, however, is how Lifshits
justifies the legitimacy of a Hegel heritage by referring to very specific aspects of
Hegelian philosophy that are still of interest today. To come right to the point, these
aspects are related to the Hegelian concept of the state.
The struggle surrounding Hegel which Lifshits addresses took place during a
German Hegel renaissance that firmly opposed the Marxist reception of Hegel. This
Hegel renaissance picked up on the impulses of a renewed focus on Hegel known as
Neo-Hegelianism, which began in Germany around 1900 and then spread to other
European countries, and it had a profound impact on thinking: for example, the
influence it had on German sociology1of the time is considerable; an influence that
has its origins in the break of German Neo-Hegelianism with the Absolute Spirit.
With this break, the focus moved to the Objective Spirit and estrangement
became firmly established. Hegels understanding of estrangement is the separation
of the subject as self-consciousness and the object as the outer world. It is only by
means of religious reconciliation with reality which comprehends this philosophy
in the Absolute Spiritthat sublation of this separation is possible. If reconciliation
and comprehension do not occur, separation persists and estrangement can be
declared as the human normal state in the modern age.2 Yet from a genuine
philosophical standpoint, what remained of this Neo-Hegelianism following its time
of origin and blossoming during the first third of the 20th century? While German
Neo-Hegelianism practiced philosophical abstinence due to a critical (Neo-Kantian)
view of metaphysics, the Russian-French philosopher Alexandre Koje`ve was a NeoHegelian who not only presented an original and refreshing interpretation of the
Hegelian Philosophy of Spirit (during the famous lectures he held in Paris from
1933 to 1939), but also was able to provide productive stimuli for significant
philosophical discourses beyond the limits of a direct interest in Hegel.
Koje`ve thus inspired various changes in recent intellectual history, including the
run-up to French Postmodernism (Bataille3) and the anti-positivist turning point in
psychoanalysis (Lacan4). He conveyed through an exchange of ideas5 with the
father of American Neo-Conservatism Leo Strauss the last great legitimating
ideology; one that is still in effect today, despite frequent critique by opponents
within his own camp, namely that of American Imperialism (Fukuyama 1992).6 All
As with Hans Freyer (See: Freyer 1930). Freyer as well as his pupils Arnold Gehlen and Helmut
Schelsky, who were associated with the right-wing intellectual milieu, influenced the development of
sociology in post-war West Germany.
Agamben describes the theoretical relationship between Koje`ve and Bataille in: Agamben 2004.
Which is reflected in Koje`ves critique (Koje`ve 1950) of the book by Leo Strauss (Strauss 1948).
Francis Fukuyama was a student of Allan Bloom who studied under Strauss.
123
of these changes, as varied as they might have been, share the formal commonality
that in their respective fields, they set the course for further developments.
Neo-Hegelian thought plays a role in contemporary discourses that, though not
always explicitly, have recourse to Hegel. This diffuse yet profound Neo-Hegelian
influence continues to have an effect today and gives cause in this essay to examine
Lifshits verdict on the illegitimacy of the Neo-Hegelian Hegel heritage by
confronting his argumentation with Koje`ves Neo-Hegelian concept. I intend, in this
essay to update Lifshits perspective on the fate of Hegelianism during the first third
of the 20th century (as far as it is related to the aspect mentioned above) and
broaden it beyond the horizon then available to Lifshits. The question is therefore
whether or not the Neo-Hegelianmore specifically: the Koje`vianHegel heritage
is legitimate.
In what follows I will first present and then criticize Lifshits discussion about the
illegitimacy of the Neo-Hegelian Hegel heritage which he contrasts with what he
considers to be the legitimate Soviet Marxist Hegel heritage. (I) This presentation
will then be applied to Koje`ves Neo-Hegelianism in order to answer the question
whether or not Koje`ve is a legitimate Hegel heir. (II)
I
Lifshits about the illegitimacy of the Neo-Hegelian Hegel heritage
In his essay mentioned above, Lifshits first outlines the background of the Hegel
renaissance of his time. Hegel, states Lifshits, presented the contradictions of civil
(bourgeois) society and tried to solve them in an idealistic state cult. This did not
please the German Liberals (Karl v. Rotteck, Karl Theodor Welcker)they
protested in the name of individualism, freedom and humanism against the
cruelty of Hegelian progress. During the emerging era in the wake of the defeat
of the 1848 Revolution, Rudolf Haym declared that Hegel, whom he accused of
state glorification and even deification, was finished. In the subsequent 50 years,
it was only Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels who maintained Hegels best traditions.
They had even come into conflict with Wilhelm Liebknecht who, in true liberal
style, stigmatized Hegel as the discoverer and glorifier of the Prussian idea of the
state, as a Prussian; a judgment which was met with fierce resistance from Marx
and Engels. Yet despite their objections, the liberal assessment of Hegel took hold in
Social Democratic literature. The Reformistsspecifically Eduard Bernstein
preferred Kants teachings of endless progress to an unattainable goal.
Now (1931), states Lifshits, the tide has turned. Liberalism is no longer the
dominant ideology. Post-war society has lost its faith in endless progress and in
formal democracy; Neo-Kantianism is suffering a defeat. The search for a new
metaphysics has become fashionable and Hegel has been commemorated by both
the bourgeoisie and in Social Democratic circles: On the occasion of his 100th
birthday, the Social Democratic Prussian Cultural Minister Adolf Grimme declares
Hegel to be a living presence. A philosophical neoclassicism goes hand in hand with
a Hegel renaissance and a resurgence of Neo-Hegelianism.
123
A. Jubara
What, asks Lifshits, is the meaning of this pendulum swing in the history of NeoHegelianism? The new era of Imperialism, he states, is distinguished by a quest for
dominance instead of freedom and this marks the end of old Liberalism. The sought
for dominance is that of an oligarchy that exploits the masses disenchantment
with bourgeois democracy in its own interest; disenchantment which manifests itself
in anti-democratic and anti-liberal resentment. According to Lifshits, elements of an
anti-democratic and anti-liberal contemporary ideology transit seamlessly into
fascism. These elements are also accompanied by both a bourgeois and Social
Democratic critique of Manchester Liberalism from the standpoint of state
capitalism adorned with socialist rhetoric. Active state intervention in economic
life now seems desirable, while protecting private life from state intervention seems
to no longer be necessary. Hegel becomes relevant once again as the dogmatist of
the power of the universal over the individual and of the power of the state over
private life.
This state capitalism adorned with socialist rhetoric merits a more detailed
examination. Wording in which rhetoric plays a prominent role often represents a
makeshift solution on Lifshits part. This term obscures what Lifshits is not able to
articulate clearly or explain at that particular point. A circumstance which seems in
this case difficult for Lifshits to explain is a similarity established during the Age of
Imperialism: the similarity between bourgeois and Reformist Socialist (Social
Democratic) ideologies on the one hand and in turn their similarity, which he leaves
unmentioned, to the Revolutionary Socialist (communist or Soviet) ideology on the
other hand. The latter manifests itself in what Lifshits calls rhetorical justification
of state capitalism (which, as Lifshits leaves out, was called socialism in the
Soviet Union), that of a powerful state (Machtstaat) and the power of the
universal. Lifshits attempts to identify, beneath this superficial similarity, essential
differences between revolutionary Socialism-Marxism on the one hand and
reformist Socialism and bourgeois ideology on the other. For him, the ideological
watershed lies, in this essay at least, among the different references to Hegel by
means of which he distinguishes the legitimate from the illegitimate heirs of Hegel.
Illegitimate heirs are for Lifshits the contemporary bourgeois and Social
Democratic ideologies that, he claims look back to Hegels critique of Liberalism
(one influenced by the resonating impression that terror had left behind) resulting in
his idealization of a state superior to all individual interests. According to Lifshits,
both pick up this element and distort it: Hegels state cult (Staatskult) had nothing to
do with contemporary social demagogy. The contemporary idea of a modern power
state, writes Lifshits, is instead the fruit of a regressive metamorphosis of the state
as it had been presented in the Hegelian Philosophy of Right. Neo-Hegelianism
exploits the Hegelian state to legitimize the modern power state. In the protocols
from the first Hegel Congress (Wigersma 1931) to which Lifshits referred in his
essay, he finds a critique of individualism based on Hegel as well as arguments
made for the primacy of the state over private interests. At first, these arguments
bring Hegel, Robespierre and Bonaparte to mind. Yet according to Lifshits, they
have a completely different meaning for the Neo-Hegelians. It is exactly this shift in
meaning that is illegitimate according to Lifshits.
123
Rousseaus opposition of the concepts bourgeois and citoyen in Le contrat social is decisive
here. To highlight this opposition, I will use the English term bourgeois for the concept of bourgeois
and the term citizen for the concept of citoyen (and not the term citizen for both concepts as is
sometimes the case in English).
123
A. Jubara
phenomenon of state capitalism. This is because the established system at this point
in the Soviet Union, the state of the proletariat, was nothing other than state
capitalism.
There is, however, one difference between Western and Soviet state Capitalism.
The first is distinguished by the close relationship private enterprises (capital)
maintain with the state and by more or less direct state intervention in
entrepreneurial activities. (One example was the centrally administered economy
with private property in Germany during the Nazi era.) In Soviet-style state
capitalism by contrast, the state is the monopolistic capital owner. Is it therefore
possible to argue that it is the representative of the true universal?
Capital organized by the state, regardless of the concrete form of organization (as
state control of individual capital or where the state is the sole or main capital
owner) does not embody universal interests but instead economic interests.
Economic interest is simply another term for egoistic private interest. Capital
interests are always economic, i.e. egoistic interests, regardless of whether it is a
matter of private capital or state monopoly capital. This is because the interests of
(state) monopolistic capital do not represent a universalization of individual
interests. Such universalization can only be achieved by rational political means.
Submission to capital interest in contrast is submission to a blind, unconscious force
and it excludes political mediation of interests. This was clearly demonstrated by the
repressions beginning in 1937 which ushered in a brutal industrialization of the
Soviet Union; one which disregarded and devastated individual human lives. As this
demonstrated, Soviet state capitalism was also not the power of the universal.
History has rebutted Lifshits postulate: The proletariat has also proven to be an
illegitimate heir of Hegel.
Today, after a further, presently more neoliberal metamorphosis of capitalism, it
has become evident that the primacy of economic, egoistic interests progressively
undermines and destroys the political community that made it possible to develop
and articulate universal interests in the first place. In Germany, this was made very
clear some time ago by a discussion about market compliant democracy
(Altenbockum 2012) and is reflected currently in the discussion about the
Transatlantic Trade and Investment Partnership (TTIP) between the EU, the USA
and additional states with its negotiations behind closed doors to be concluded
without consideration of the will of the general public. The capitalist state was and
isalso in its now historical socialist forma state of egoistic private interests,
i.e. economic interests, which is virtually the opposite of the Hegelian citizen state
in which power embodies the universal. The Hegelian state was and remains a
utopia; a desideratum.
II
Is Koje`ves Neo-Hegelianism a legitimate heir of Hegel?
What role then does the notion of the state play in Koje`ves Neo-Hegelianism? How
do matters stand with the legitimacy of his being an heir to Hegel? Does Lifshits
123
123
A. Jubara
123
For more on the discussion among contemporary Marxists concerning faith in the state in early
works by Marx and Engels see: http://www.marx-forum.de/marx-lexikon/lexikon_s/staatseigentum.html
(21.03.14).
Since 1859, when he published A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (first in German
Zur Kritik der politischen Okonomie).
123
A. Jubara
which labor does not play a socially mediating role that would allow for the
constitution of another form of social mediation(Postone 1993, 361). Social
life could be mediated in an overtly social and political fashion. In such a society,
a political public sphere could play a more central role than in capitalism (Postone
1993, 361362), since it would be free from the constraints of utilization and the
enhancement of value as an end in itself. Such a political sphere would be a true
polis, a state as the sphere of the spirit in the Hegelian sense.
In the draft of this critical social theory (A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy) lies Marxs actual anti-idealist turning point. Whereas Hegel felt
that the spirit had now (during his lifetime) attained absolute self-knowledge and
that this self-knowledge only needed to be realized, Marx sees enormous
obstacles standing in the way of such a realization. These obstacles are the
contradictions within civil (bourgeois) societyin the sphere of egoistic private
interests; i.e. economic interests. They condense into a blind spot in selfconsciousness, into a sphere in which human conditions are mystified, fetishized
and obscure. The economy is anything but rational; here ones own actions appear
foreign. The solution to these economic problems for Marx requires that the
socialized man, the associated producers, rationally regulate their interchange with
Nature, bringing it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by the
blind forces of Nature. () But it (the sphere of material production, A.J.)
nonetheless still remains a realm of necessity. Beyond it begins that development of
human energy which is an end in itself, the true realm of freedom (Marx 1999,
571). It is only this kind of association of producers that would allow something like
a Hegelian citizen state to even become a possibility beyond production. This
association is not be equated with the transfer of means of production to state
propertyeuphemistically called public property (Volkseigentum) as experience
has shown with state socialism. If association and nationalization were (had
been) one and the same, then there should never be wage labor, money or capital in
state socialism.10
Koje`ve between political emancipation and nationalization
Yet Koje`ve is not interested in the later Marxs economic research, nor does he
pursue the early Marxs idea of human emancipation, i.e. council communism.
He instead alternates between two other solutions to the problem: One is the
political emancipation that Marx deemed to be insufficiently qualified, i.e. the
constitutional state which also complies with Hegels line of thought in his Early
Writings. The other (which was not discussed in this essay; see for this: de Berg) is
nationalization, or state capitalism called socialism (which is in principle
identical to Marxs proposed solution of nationalization in Communist Manifesto).
The role that he attributes to terror indicates a notion of the constitutional state
evolving into a state capitalist social state. Based on the reasons listed above and
10
As is known, institutionalized Marxism-Leninism argued its way out on this point by stating that there
should be two phases of social development, the first was called socialism (=state capitalism) and
the second should someday be communism (=association). It seems to me, that the status of this
statement was however an excuse and/or a deference to the Greek calends.
123
11
123
A. Jubara
References
Agamben, G. (2004). The open: Man and animal. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Altenbockum, J. V. (2012). Marktkonforme Demokratie? Oder demokratiekonformer Markt? Frankfurter
Allgemeine Zeitung, 15.04.2012. http://www.faz.net/aktuell/politik/harte-bretter/marktkonformedemokratie-oder-demokratiekonformer-markt-11712359.html March 27, 2014.
de Berg, H. (2007). Das Ende der Geschichte und der burgerliche Rechtsstaat. HegelKoje`ve
Fukuyama. Tubingen, Basel: A. Francke.
Freyer, H. (1930). Soziologie als Wirklichkeitswissenschaft. Logische Grundlegung des Systems der
Soziologie. Leipzig: B. G. Teubner.
Freyer, H. (1955). Theorie des gegenwartigen Zeitalters. Stuttgart: DVA.
Fukuyama, F. (1992). The end of history and the last man. New York: Free Press.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1966). Theologische Jugendschriften. Based on the manuscripts of the Royal Library of
Berlin. In H. Nohl (Ed.), (Unaltered reprint) published by J. C. B. Mohr in 1907 in Tubingen,
Frankfurt/Main: Minerva. In English: Hegel, F. (1961). On Christianity. Early Theological Writings,
New York: Harper Torchbook.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991). Elements of the philosophy of right. Ed. by Allen W. Wood, (H. B. Nisbet,
Trans.). Cambridge: University Press.
Koje`ve, A. (1950). Laction politique des philosophes. In Critique, 41, 4655 and Critique, 42, 138154.
Koje`ve, A. (1980). Introduction to the reading of Hegel: Lectures on the phenomenology of spirit. New
York: Cornell University Press.
Lifschitz (t.i. Lifshits), M.A. (1988). Das literarische Erbe Hegels. In Id., Die dreiiger Jahre.
Ausgewahlte Schriften. (pp. 2354). Dresden: Verlag der Kunst. Originally in Russian:
. In: , Moskva 1932, t. 2, pp. 187208.
Marx, K. (1999). Capital. A critique of political economy, Volume III. The process of capitalist
production as a whole. In F. Engels (Ed.), International Publishers, NY, [n.d.]. First Published:
1894, On-Line Version: http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/download/pdf/CapitalVolume-III.pdf. May 1, 2014.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1906). Manifesto of the Communist party. Chicago: Charles H. Kerr & Company.
Marx, K. A Contribution to the critique of political economy. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/
works/1859/critique-pol-economy/index.htm. October 22, 2016.
Marx, K. On the Jewish question. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1844/jewish-question/
October 22, 2016.
Postone, M. (1993). Time, labor and social domination: A reinterpretation of Marxs critical theory. New
York, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ritter, J. (1965). Hegel und die Franzosische Revolution. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp. In English: Hegel
and the French Revolution. Cambridge, Mass. and London: MIT Press 1982.
Roudinesco, E. (1993). Jacques Lacan. Esquisse dune vie, histoire dun syste`me de pensee. Paris:
Fayard.
Strauss, L. (1948). On Tyranny: An interpretation of Xenophons Hiero. New York: Foreword by Alvin
Johnson. (Political Science Classics).
Wigersma, B. (Ed.) (1931). Verhandlungen des ersten Hegelkongresses vom 22.-25. April 1930 im Haag.
Im Auftrag des Internationalen Hegel-Bundes. Tubingen-Haarlem.
123
Abstract This article compares the concepts of the ideal proposed by two prominent Soviet Marxists: the contemplative concept (Lifshits) and that based on the
activity approach (Ilyenkov). The former derives the ideal, along with man himself,
from nature and the latter derives the ideal from the dialectics of labour which
generates man, his feelings and thoughts and the higher forms of cultural being.
Keywords Marxism Dialectics Lifshits Ilyenkov The ideal Labour
Activity Contemplation Practice Culture History
A masterpiece usually denotes a work of art. A masterpiece is the supreme model
with which the concept of the ideal and the category of the ideal are associated.
Plato compares the eternal ideas with models that guide the master, the Demiurge
(Timaeus 28 a). But is nature itself capable of creating masterpieces or is the ideal a
product of human labour only? This is the key point in the argument between
M.A. Lifshits and E.V. Ilyenkov on the problem of the ideal. Lifshitss article Ob
idealnom i realnom exposed these differences soon after Ilyenkovs death. The
publication of the entire manuscript by Lifshits under the title Dialog s Evaldom
Ilenkovym (see Lifshits 2003) moved this problem to the focus of the discussions
among their successors today.
Lifshits was at one with Ilyenkov in criticising the subjectivist treatment of the
ideal. But he believed that Ilyenkov had stopped short of recognising the objective
existence of the ideal in nature.
This is not sufficient for a more complete definition of the ideal, but the first
step is of paramount importance, i.e. the idea that seems to challenge the
& Sergey Mareev
[email protected]
1
123
320
S. Mareev
common notion that the ideal world belongs to the world of objective things
and relations and not to formal-logical or socio-psychological phenomena of
consciousness. Ever since the times of William of Occam and the innovators
of the late Middle Ages, the ideal has been referred to the world of the human
intellect and, more broadly, to the subjective life of people (Lifshits 1984,
121).
It is known that Occams razor cut off Platonism with its objectively existing ideal
entities. But whence come the ideas in our heads? This was the question with which
all European philosophy, up to Hegel and Marx, had been struggling.
Lifshitss article Ob idealnom i realnom and Ilyenkovs well-known work The
Dialectics of the Ideal (Ilyenkov 2014) oppose the view that reduces the ideal to the
images of our consciousness, to subjective-psychological phenomena. Both Lifshits
and Ilyenkov see the ideal as an objective reality. Both reject the vulgar
juxtaposition of the ideal, as some subjective view, with the material as objective
stuff. But how is the ideal represented in the real world? And why does Lifshits
reproach Ilyenkov for subjectivism, albeit in a very mild form?
Let us note right off that the essence of the differences between them lies in the
understanding of objectivity. According to the most common definition, objectivity
or objective reality is what does not depend on our consciousness. And yet not only
the laws of nature, but the laws of the state are independent of our consciousness. As
Hegel noted, in Plato the ideal is presented above all as the organisation of society,
the State.1 The state opposes individual citizens and their consciousness as
objective reality, because we cannot say that the state exists only in our heads. This
reality is of much greater concern for us than nature. The interpretation of Platos
objective idealism that places his ideas in nature only, in the place above
heaven (hyperouranios topos), is very vulgar. Like the God-Demiurge, they exist
there in order to provide grounds and sanctify the existence of the ideal in society, in
the State.
This is the interpretation of the objectivity of the ideal that we find in Ilyenkovs
work, with the exception, of course, of the Demiurge and other Platonic bits.
Ilyenkov links the objectivity of the ideal with the objectivity of culture. A man
does not live in nature, but in culture. Nature, as Marx would say, is given to man
through natural science and industry.
Lifshits associates the problem of the ideal with what has realised its objective
measure:
Whether our thought wants it or not, it cannot do without such models of
realising the general. We call somebody a true friend or a true patriot to
indicate that they are the implementations of a certain perfectio or an ideal, as
distinct from false friends or sham patriots or at least those who have not
manifested themselves characteristically, but only in a latent, vague and
confused form that has not reached the threshold of universality (Lifshits
1984, 125).
1
Hegel (1971, 106): Platon erschien die Realitat des Geistesdes Geistes, insofern er der Natur
entgegengesetzt istin ihrer hochsten Wahrheit, namlich als die Organisation eines Staats.
123
321
In the opinion of Lifshits, nature itself creates masterpieces which embody the
ideal. In short, the ideal exists in everything, it exists in the material world and in
consciousness, it exists in society and in nature or else it does not exist anywhere
(Lifshits 1984, 123). In society and in nature this needs to be stressed. In the case
of nature we are talking about the ideal forms and relations among material things
which in themselves are not substance, but certain limits of what our sensual
perceptions give us through experience (ibid.) In science, such limits are usually
identified with the laws of nature expressed through scientific abstractions. Lifshits
cites some examples:
Such ideals are the ideal gas, and the ideal crystal, real abstractions that can be
approximated in the same way as a polyhedron with an infinitely increasing
number of sides approximates a circle. (ibid.).
The laws of nature turn out to be not scientific but real abstractions at the basis of
things whose ideal character is proved by the fact that they are not substantive.
Lifshits stresses that infinity as the ideal limit has not been seen or heard or smelled
by anyone. Interestingly, the Last Mohican of the Russian Silver Age, Aleksey
Losev, adduces a similar argument to prove the ideal character of the laws of nature:
All bodies fall. But the law that causes bodies to fall is not itself falling
anywhere and in general is not a body that one can smell or touch. On this
point, Platonism is irrefutable (Losev and Takho-Godi 1993, 9293).
Platonism, according to Losev, is irrefutable because everything that is not material
is ideal. Thus physicalism, which identifies matter and substance, connects with its
opposite, mentalism, but while in Plato things and ideas belong to two worlds, in
Losev the ideal laws order things from within nature.
Lifshits also recaps on what todays Marxists could usefully borrow from
Plato. But in the article Ob idealnom i realnom he invokes, first of all, Hegel
arguing that reality must correspond to its concept. The latter sets an ideal limit
towards which reality tends in the process of maturing. True cognition is cognition
of the true in reality, he writes, and accordingly the scientists intellect reflects real
abstractions produced by nature.
But while for the development of science the most important thing is that reality
should ascend to the level of being reflected in scientific abstractions, what about the
maturity of society that enables it to grasp the essence of things? Why was it that the
law of gravitation was discovered not before and not after but during the age of
industrial revolution? The laws of mechanics have always existed, but mechanics
was developed only in modern times.
On the face of it, these are elementary Marxist truths about the interconnection
between the development of science and mans productive activities. Industrial
history, according to Marx, is an open book of human psychology. If somebody tells
us that this was what early Marx wrote, we may point out that the same was
repeated by the later Engels:
Both natural sciences and philosophy have so far totally neglected the study of
the influence of mans activities on his thought. They know, on the one hand,
123
322
S. Mareev
only nature, and on the other hand, only thought. But the most essential and
immediate foundation of human thought is precisely the change of nature by
man and not nature as such, and human reason has developed even as man was
learning to change nature (Engels 1974, 498).
Citing examples from the history of science, Lifshits sidesteps this aspect. But while
with Lifshits scientific abstractions directly express the truth of being, in Ilyenkov
the prerequisite of all scientific abstractions is the process of abstraction, i.e. the
identification and generalisation of the laws of nature in the process of mans labour
activities. In this context the original abstraction of humanity is the instrument of
labour.
According to Ilyenkov, not nature as such, but only practice, transforming nature,
can extract the universal natural forms and turn them into necessary forms of human
activity. Labour is Marxisms bedrock concept. According to Ilyenkov, the process
of idealisation of reality begins in mans labour activities that transform the material
world. In labour the material and the ideal, the objective and the subjective are not
only neighbouring opposites, but conjugates. In labour they transform into each
other, and this is the basis of Ilyenkovs understanding of the ideal.
The ideal form is the form of a thing created by social-human labour,
reproducing forms of the objective material world, which exist independently
of man. Or, conversely, the form of labour realised in the substance of nature,
embodied in it, alienated in it, realised in it and, therefore, presenting
itself to man, the creator, as the form of a thing or as a special relationship
among things, a relationship in which one thing realises, reflects another, in
which man has placed these things, his labour, and which would never arise on
its own. This is why man contemplates the ideal as being outside himself,
outside his own eyes, outside his own headas existing objective reality. It is
only because of this that he frequently and easily confuses the ideal with the
material, assuming those forms and relations between things that he created
himself (Ilyenkov 2014, 76).
If the ideal is generated in the practical activity of man, then it does not and cannot
exist before the emergence of the world of culture. The counter-argument that the
forms of culture, and therefore the ideal, are already present in nature potentially
means that culture and nature are essentially identical, and differ in form only. So,
the essence of man is already present latently among animals, and vice versa, human
cultural life actualises the essence of the amoeba. Such a reductive logic was alien
to Ilyenkov. He sees the essence of man exactly in labour, where natural laws
become the principle of transforming human activity, eo ipso acquiring the ideal
form. James Watts double action steam engine is based on the laws of nature and
yet it cannot exist in nature. This difference is only the tip of the iceberg which,
however, hides a whole range of disagreements between Lifshits and Ilyenkov.
In Lifshits opinion, human labour does not so much transform as reproduce, not
so much create as simply confers a cultural form on natural processes. Thus, man
merely transfers the ideal from nature into culture. From where could human
123
323
labour derive something ideal, he writes, if it did not constitute a stylisation of the
processes of nature that is useful for the social man?(Lifshits 1984, 123).
For Ilyenkov, on the contrary, it is important to understand the creative essence
of labour, i.e. how man, transforming nature, at the same time idealises it. In labour,
the aim is to produce a utilitarian material object, but the ideal is also present, first,
at the stage of setting the goal, because labour is purposeful human activity, and
second, as the sign of the practicability of activity that endures in the shape of a
finished product. The ideal is born through labour in the form of the goal as an
image (model) of the future product. Paraphrasing Marx, one can say that mans
work differs from that of a bee in that human activity bifurcates into the opposites of
the material and the ideal in this initial cell. And the ideal is a necessary moment of
material activity.
On the other hand, man as the subject of labour approaches pristine nature in
terms of the models already generated by practice. We refer to the ideal in nature as
that which approximates manufactured objects, and thereby the models in our head.
When shipbuilders choose the wood for making a mast they look above all for a
straight tree. They usually choose the pine-tree which grows straight. The ship
carpenter can say that the pine-tree is an ideal mast. He looks at the tree through the
prism of his goal and the future result. This brings about a situationparadoxical
for common sensewhen it is not the ideal in man that reflects the material, but
vice versa: the ideal in nature turns out to be a reflection of what is in our head
and in our labour activity. The turnaround of the ideal and material in the dialectics
of labour, in the practical relationship of man and the world, goes a long way to
explain the source of mystifications of philosophical idealism. The dialectics of the
ideal and the material is what is conspicuously absent in Lifshitss work: with him,
these opposites do not morph into each other.
In his article Ob idealnom i realnom Lifshits quotes Ilyenkov:
Man exists as man, as the subject of activity directed at the surrounding world
and at himself for as long as he actively produces his real life in forms created
by himself, by his own work (Ilenkov 1974, 194).
It is in labour, in real transformation of the surrounding world and of oneself as
its metamorphosis, Ilyenkov goes on, that the ideal is born and is functioning,
that reality, nature, and social relations are idealised, that the language of
symbols as an external body of the ideal image of the outside world is born.
Herein lies the mystery of the ideal and herein lies its solution (ibid.).
Ilyenkov obviously links here, yet again, the origin of the ideal to mans labour
activity through which both nature and social relations are idealised. It also
produces symbolic forms that mediate collective activities in which the ideal
becomes the content of the cultural product.
Lifshits seeks to reduce Ilyenkovs view of the ideal in the form of a symbol.
Quoting Ilyenkov, he states that one body, while remaining itself, constitutes the
being of another body and its ideal being as such, being that differs from its
immediate corporeal form. This, Lifshits stresses, is the source of the ideal
123
324
S. Mareev
123
325
[] mental labour is the domain of freedom par excellence, and when, owing
to historical circumstances, it is governed by the laws of material productive
labour, i.e. becomes a necessity in the direct economic sense of the word, it
does not in principle correspond to its true nature. In mental activity society
achieves a higher degree of ideal, although already Adam Smith noted with
surprise that the servants of the ideal, that is, scholars and writers were more
prone to quarrel and show ill will towards one another. But that paradox needs
to be considered more carefully. Immediate productive labour as the sphere of
material necessity inherently is less inclined to what may be called the ideal in
any sense of that word (Lifshits 2003, 262).
We see that the link between mental activity and material practice, according to
Lifshits, can only be forced by circumstances. By transforming nature, man
improves his material status whereas the ideal meaning of his life lies above
practice: in philosophy, science, and most notably in the arts which recreate the
ideal content of Being. Therefore it is clear that, according to Lifshits, the problem
of the ideal is resolved not through labour but through contemplation.
In Ilyenkov, man acts freely not when he imitates nature, even in its supreme
manifestations, but when he transcends nature. Beginning from the creative
synthesis of natures pure forms that are rooted in the foundations of cultural life
with its objective laws and ending with the aesthetic norms and the moral
imperative.
Man has undoubtedly crossed the boundaries of nature. But he has been able to
do so only by not living according to the laws of nature, but according to social
laws, including morality which does not exist without free choice. He has become
the master of nature, including the nature of his own organic body, by turning it into
a tool for achieving human goals. If the ideal is generated in physical activity as an
image of the goal, it is there that one should look for the sources of the ideal in the
relations among people who no longer live in herds or flocks, but in a collective
where the moral imperative is to treat the other as the goal,never as a means.
Morality is based on a similar dialectical turnaround when the animal instinct and
selfishness are replaced by conscious altruism as the necessity of sacrificing myself
for the sake of another. Such is the sense of Kants categorical imperative. But
Lifshits here is looking, once again, not for differences but for similarities, declaring
that the love of scorpions presages Romeo and Juliet (Lifshits 1984, 130).
However, this makes one think not of Marx but rather of Konrad Lorenz who
regards human aggression as a continuation of animal aggression. Where is the ideal
here?
On a large scale Lifshits fails to cope with the dialectics of the objective and
subjective, culture and nature. He suspects that behind the dialectical elements of
Ilyenkovs concept of the ideal there lurk concessions to subjectivism. What is
dialectics for Ilyenkov appears to be a serious mistake for Lifshits. This applies
above all to the essence of man as the subject of activity. At this point the circle of
reflection is broken. According to Lifshits, unless one recognises that humanity
stylises nature the inevitable conclusion is that man can project and impose on the
world arbitrary subjective schemes of action.
123
326
S. Mareev
Hegel (1987, 190): Ehre der List gegen die Macht, die blinde Macht an einer Seite anfassen, da sie
sich gegen sich selbst richtetsie begreifen, sie als Bestimmtheit fassen, gegen diese tatig seinoder sie
als Bewegung eben in sich selbst zuruckgehen machen, sich aufzuheben [].
123
327
it is drawn into culture in one way or another, that is, into production, seafaring,
trade, international communication, etc. The sun ensures the life of plants and
animals, including the cultural animals. In agricultural civilizations it is the main
deity. It is ideal precisely because it corresponds to human good. But in the absence
of rain, the sun brings evil and therefore ceases to be objectively ideal for us. Hence,
the sun is ideal not in itself, but only for us, and the whole of nature can be ideal
only for us, not in itself, as Lifshits supposes.
For him it is important that our head may contain all sorts of rubbish that does not
correspond to the truth and objective reality. In order to distinguish what is only in
the head from what is objectively ideal Lifshits introduces a terminological
distinction, utilising the difference between the German adjectives ideell and ideal.
He claimed that the distinction was first drawn by Marx who in his study of the
value form allegedly used only the term ideell. And he argued that in all the
excellent quotations about the ideal, cited by Ilyenkov, Marx used das Ideelle and
not das Ideal.
Having analysed Marxs original texts, Andrey Maidansky demonstrates that
such an assertion is incorrect: two quotations, cited by Ilyenkov, contain the term
ideal (as an adverb and an adjective). And in other works, beginning from the Paris
manuscripts of 1844, Marx used the term ideal to characterise money. Marx,
unlike Lifshits, did not limit the category of ideale to something that evokes
admiration and was in no hurry to dismiss all the ugly things as material
relations (see Maidanskij 2012, 1239). It is worth noting that Lifshits failed to
find even a single case where Marx uses the term das Ideal to refer to the highest
form of manifesting the real. And Marx never mentioned the existence of the ideal
in nature either.
Of course, one should distinguish the ideal in our head, i.e. the truth that
corresponds to objective reality, from what does not correspond to anything real.
The latter may be termed, for example, as mental. A thought can be false, and
then it is not ideal. The terminological differences between das Ideelle and das
Ideal, introduced by Lifshits, look like a purely scholastic issue. But within the
concept of the ideal, proposed by Lifshits, it is part of the critique of Ilyenkov who
allegedly imputes the true ideal to false ideas and non-genuine being. Indeed, the
example of value which is represented in the commodity only ideally (Marx),
given by Ilyenkov in his article Dialectics of the Ideal, is not exactly felicitous.
Until a commodity has been sold, its value exists merely as a price. Ilyenkovs
critics latched on to this asking where he found the ideal here.
Let us approach the problem from another direction and ask, what is an ideal
poison and an ideal medicine? Does a medicine, used as a poison, cease to be ideal?
We have already said that, even a natural thing or object becomes ideal only with
regard to our needs. The purpose can make an object truly ideal, but it is another
question whether this attitude to the object is based on the world of culture, in which
every creation bears the imprint of production activity, and that the form of activity,
posited as the form of a thing, always involves an element of idealisation of nature.
The concept of evil genius expresses this contradiction connected with the course
of history in its alienated form.
123
328
S. Mareev
The question of the truth value of our concept divorced from practice, Marx
wrote, is purely scholastic. Scholasticism in general begins where issues are isolated
from material practice. The question of the ideal, like the question of the truth, is
also a practical and concrete historical question. The same holds for the questions of
value, money and wealth.
The dialectics consists in that one and the same thing can be used for good or evil
purposes. The embodiment of value is money, gold, but here even the size of the
sum matters. In Platos ideal republic artisans need coins to exchange their
products for other products. Money as a means of exchange serves the Good and
therefore is ideal. By contrast, gold and silver as a means of exchange in
international and overseas trade where goods are bought to be sold is another matter.
As a means of enrichment, money, according to Plato, introduces hostility and
discord, and therefore it is evil. Excessive wealth of some people generates poverty
of other people at the opposite pole, and in that sense it is material. Plato defines the
ideal and material in accordance with whether a thing contributes to the idea of
Good. Money and wealth are like matches with which one can make a fire to warm
oneself or set a neighbours house on fire. Nevertheless in human culture matches
are a great good, otherwise people would still be extracting fire from pieces of flint
stones.
Thus the boundary between the ideal and the material is not a boundary between
the ideas in our head and objective reality. Lifshits rightly remarks: is an ideal friend
ideal only in my head? If you tell the woman you love You are my ideal which is
only in my head, your chances of winning over that woman are nil. But in
Ilyenkov, unlike Lifshits, an ideal friend, an ideal woman, an ideal ship objectively
exist not in nature but in culture. We can talk about the ideal in nature only when it
is involved in culture, even if only in our understanding. Then our concept becomes
ideal, albeit only in our head.
In a letter addressed to M.G.Mikhailov, Lifshits makes this comment concerning
Ilyenkov:
Although he has borrowed a great deal from me and Lukacs, on the other
hand, especially at the later stage, he became close with psychologists who are
ignorant of philosophy. They invented the concept of activity which to them
is the same as the pineal gland was to Descartes, i.e. a cross between mind
and matter. But such a thing does not exist, and activity is either material or
mental. I seek a solution to the problem of the ideal elsewhere and my advice
is to take a few more lessons in the materialist dialectics of Plato (Lifshits
2003, 3301).
Here the difference between Lifshits and Ilyenkov is carried to the point where it
diverges from the entire cultural-historical theory which in our days is represented
L.S. Vygotsky, A.N. Leontyev, and E.V. Ilyenkov. But psychologists have not
invented the concept of activity. Its origin should be traced not to vulgar
materialism, as Lifshits improperly does, but to the dialectical ideas of the German
classics. In Kant, thought and cognition is not a passive mirror that reflects the
external world but, on the contrary, a process of active construction. The pioneer of
the cultural-historical tradition, L.S. Vygotsky, following Marx, refers to the
123
329
material and transformative character of the activities that form the basis of our
mentality and thought.
Lifshits derives the ideal, and man himself, from nature, whereas Ilyenkov
derives it from the dialectics of labour, because man himself, his feelings and
thought, and the higher ideal forms of cultural being arise within the labour process.
Hence Lifshitss solution of the problem of the ideal is contemplative and
Ilyenkovs is activity-based.
References
Engels, F. (1974), Dialektik der Natur. In K. Marx & F. Engels (Eds.), Werke (43 Bde., Erganzungsband,
Erster Teil). Berlin: Dietz Verlag, DDR.
Hegel, G. W. F. (Ed.). (1971). Vorlesungen uber die Geschichte der philosophie II. In Werke (20 Bde.,
1971, Bd. 19). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1987). Jenaer Systementwurfe III. Naturphilosophie und Philosophie des Geistes. Felix
Meiner: Hamburg.
Ilenkov, E. V. (1974). Dialekticheskaja logika. Moskva: Politizdat.
Ilyenkov, E.V. (2014). Dialectics of the Ideal. In A. Levant & V. Oittinen (Eds.) Dialectics of the ideal
(A. Levant trans.). Leiden, Boston: Brill.
Lifshits, M. A. (1984). Ob idealnom i realnom. Voprosy filosofii, 10, 120145.
Lifshits, M. A. (2003). Dialog s Evaldom Ilyenkovym (Problema idealnogo). Moskva: ProgressTradicija.
Losev, A. F., & Takho-Godi, A. A. (1993). Platon. Aristotel. Moskva: Molodaja gvardija.
Maidanskij, A. D. (2012). Idealnoe u Marksa: Audit prekrasnykh citat. In E. V. Ilenkov (Ed.)
Idealnoe, myshlenie, soznanie (vols. 1, 2, pp. 1239). Moskva: SGA.
123
Abstract The article focuses on one highly idiosyncratic trait of Lifshits reading of
Hegel, namely his assertion that the epoch of Restoration during which Hegel
produced his main works was analogous to the period of the 1930s in the USSR. In
both cases, constructive tasks came to the fore as the fermentation of the revolutionary era waned. On this assumption, Lifshits built up his idea of a Restauratio
magna, which should serve as the guiding star of cultural politics. In fact, Lifshits
came very near to rehabilitating of Edmund Burkes views about the conservation of
cultural heritage, which is highly problematic in light of his initial Marxist
convictions.
Aleksanteri Institute, University of Helsinki, P.O. Box 42, 00014 Helsinki, Finland
123
V. Oittinen
inspiration came from Hegel, but not from Hegel the logician. Instead, it was Hegel
as the philosopher of historical reconciliation (Versohnung) who was important for
Lifshits. In its aspirations, this project went much further than Lukacss attempts to
make Hegel useful for Marxism, and the fact that its main contours were discernible
already in Lifshits early works published in the 1930s is an indication that his
collaboration with Lukacs did not necessarily mean that he shared the same
position.
Later, Lifshits dubbed his project as Restauratio Magna, with an obvious hint to
Bacons programme of the augmentation of sciences, Instauratio Magna. That
Lifshits saw himself as a reformer of Marxism comparable to Bacon as the
renovator of the sciences, shows the degree of his ambition. But whilst Bacon aimed
at a revolution of the sciences, Lifshits goals were rather the other way round: the
question was how to preserve, maintain, and nurture the cultural heritage threatened
by the Revolution.
Lifshits Restauratio Magna project is quite unknown even to those few who
have read and appreciated his work in Marxist aesthetics. Lukacs did not comment
on this. The first who noticed its existence seems to be the Hungarian philosopher
Sziklai (1990, 92 ff.) who, in a book on Lukacss Moscow period, published in
Hungarian in 1987 and in German a bit later, in 1990, noted the peculiar view
Lifshits had of Hegel in his articles from the early 1930s. For example, in the essay
Estetika Gegelya i dialekticheskii materializm, published in the journal Proletarskaya literatura in 1931 (republished in Lifshits 2012a, b), Lifshits first drew
attention to the utopian socialist Saint-Simon, who, writing in 1813, following the
turmoils of the French Revolution and the Napoleonic wars, asserted that the
humanity is now entering the period of a positive system. The order of the day is
to begin with scientific research which shall replace the revolutionary experiments.
Saint-Simon had thus, according to Lifshits, quite accurately formulated the task
which Hegels philosophy had to solve. In the foreword to the Science of Logic,
which Hegel wrote in 1812 at about the same time that Saint-Simon was working on
his system, he says:
However, once the substantial form of the spirit has inwardly reconstituted
itself, all attempts to preserve the forms of an earlier culture are utterly in vain;
like withered leaves they are pushed off by the new buds already growing at
their roots [] On the other hand, it seems that the period of fermentation
with which a new creative idea begins is past. In its first manifestation, such an
idea usually displays a fanatical hostility toward the entrenched systematization of the older principle; usually, too, it is fearful of losing itself in the
ramifications of the particular [Ausdehnung des Besonderen] and again it
shuns the labour required for a scientific elaboration of the new principle and
in its need for such, it grasps to begin with at an empty formalism. The
challenge to elaborate and systematize the material now becomes all the more
pressing. There is a period in the culture of an epoch as in the culture of the
individual, when the primary concern is the acquisition and assertion of the
principle in its undeveloped intensity (Hegel 1969, 2627; cf. Hegel 1999, 67
for the original).
123
I apologize for the long quotation, but it is justifiable, since Hegel here expresses the
main point which became the cornerstone of Lifshits own historico-philosophical
theory. Hegels philosophy of history is essentially a theory of a post-revolutionary
age, when the time of fermentation already belongs to the past:
The heroic period of the new order is thus finished. Now the task is to
constitute the bourgeois society and bourgeois state, to restore the order which
is necessary for the success of men of practical business [vosstanovit
porjadok, neobkhodimyi dlya preuspevaniya delovykh lyudei]. The constitutional administration, promised by Robespierre, obtains its prosaic realisation.
Coming in lieu of the revolutionary system, it has to take care mainly of civic,
but not of public freedom, and guarantee that the government does not
interfere in the business of private persons (Lifshits 2012a, b, 58).
As Sziklai (1990, 93) comments, Lifshits sees the actuality of Hegel in the fact that
he represents the German theory of the French Revolution and thus at the same time
is a theoretician of post-revolutionary times. The Marxist thinkers of today, too,
have no other task than to be philosophers of a post-revolutionary situation,
according to Lifshits. There is a direct analogy between the age of the Restoration
and the thirties in the Soviet Union. Both are periods of construction which began
following the negative and destructive period of the Revolution.
Lifshits does not, however, push this analogy too far. While for Hegel the
bourgeois revolution ends in reconciliation with reality (the famous Hegelian
Versohnung), for the Marxists historical dialectics develops instead through the
aggravation of contradictions until they find their solution in a revolutionary turn:
Hegel did not and could not carry to the end the idea of how contradictions
generate development. The social antagonisms he noted obtain their most
complete form in the contradiction between the bourgeoisie and proletariat.
They are solved in the real historical struggle between these contraries, in the
movement towards the dictatorship of the proletariat and the liquidation of
social classes. To understand this means already to accept the viewpoint of
Marx. Hegel was, in a sense, the antipode to Marx exactly because this way of
resolving the contradictions did not exist for him [] Thus, the philosophy of
Hegel became a theoretical justification of the idea that the revolutionary
process comes to a halt in its bourgeois phase (Lifshits 2012a, b, 6263).
Lifshits thesis, that the period inaugurated by the great leap of 19291930 in the
Soviet Union, when Stalin ended the New Economic Policy (NEP) and the period of
five-year plans started, is analogous to the Restoration period following the French
Revolution, seems to have been derived from his theory of art as well as from
discussions of the late 1920s. Lifshits developed his aesthetics as a critique of and
an alternative both to the attempts to reduce the theory of art to a mere sociology
and against formalist views on the tasks of art. The Proletkult movement, which
drew on ideas of Aleksandr Bogdanov, Lenins old adversary, preached a more or
less total break with all the old culture. In the Soviet Union, they declared, a quite
new culture must be built on purely proletarian foundations. These declarations
unquestionably exhibited analogies with similar tendencies during the most radical
123
V. Oittinen
phases of the French Revolution, when it was suggested that allfeudal culture
should be abandoned and churches and other monuments were vandalised.
Both Lenin and Lunacharskii, the Peoples Commissar for Culture, expressed
doubts with regard to the ultra-leftist tendencies. In October 1920, Lenin worked on
a draft of On Proletarian Culture, in which he stated that the task of Marxism is not
to break altogether with the past, but to absorb and preserve the heritage of previous
ages:
Marxism has won its historic significance as the ideology of the revolutionary
proletariat because, far from rejecting the most valuable achievements of the
bourgeois epoch, it has, on the contrary, assimilated and refashioned
everything of value in the more than two thousand years of the development
of human thought and culture. Only further work on this basis and in this
direction, inspired by the practical experience of the proletarian dictatorship as
the final stage in the struggle against every form of exploitation, can be
recognised as the development of a genuine proletarian culture (Lenin 1973,
316).
Lenins idea of Marxism as the quintessence of all previous cultures was intended as
an argument against the negative and nihilistic tendencies of the Proletkult and
similar ultra-leftist currents, that is, it was presented as an argument in a concrete
political situation. Lifshits, however, though adhering in the main to the views of
Lunacharskii and Lenin, takes the idea much farther. Actually, he turns it into a
historico-philosophical thesis in a way that goes far beyond what Lenin intended.
He is influenced not only by Hegel, but even by Giambattista Vico, about whom he
published an extensive essay in 19361937 and whose circular philosophy of history
seems to have much impressed him.1
In retrospect, in an interview with Laszlo Sziklai, conducted in November 1978,
Lifshits asserts that, in fact, it is not quite in order to see him as an aesthetician only.
I wanted to show that in Marxism as a world-view there exists an aesthetic, or if
you like, a moral-aesthetic tone, the absence of which is sometimes so pretentiously
lamented. This aesthetic moment in Marxism should not be understood as
something belonging only to some special craft:
Actually, I meant by aesthetics something else it is a kind of a philosophy of
culture, or putting the point more exactly, I had the ambition to put forth a
Marxist philosophy of history in a popular form [] [It was] a historical
world-view, a vision of the internal structure of human history as a totality, a
totality which develops in a contradictory way (Lifshits 2012b, 80).
I do not deal in my paper further with Lifshits study of Vico, since it is the subject of Aleksandr
Dmitrievs paper in this SEET issue. It should be noted, however, that a synthesis of Vicos cyclical
philosophy of history with Hegels theory can be construed rather effortlessly. For Hegel, too, the
previous stages of human history tended to repeat themselves laterbut on a higher level of development,
so that the movement of history took in Hegel the shape of an upward-going spiral. For Lifshits it must
not have been very difficult to use both Vicoan and Hegelian elements for his own idiosyncratic concept
of history.
123
Lifshits thus says outrightly that his intention has been to create a philosophical
synthesis of world history on the basis of the experience of the October revolution
a synthesis which, obviously, is not of the same character as offered by historical
materialism. In the same interview, Lifshits stresses that his and Lukacs interest in
Hegel was not of the same sort as that of Deborin and his disciples, who in the
canonical histories of Soviet philosophy are dubbed as Hegelians or dialecticians (in contrast to the Mechanists).
I disliked (as did Lukacs by the way) the Deborin school, as it was kind of
Katheder-Marxism2 [] Our interest in Hegel was of quite different character.
For us, what was important in the doctrine of the German thinker was its real
content and deeply tragic attitude towards the events of the French Revolution
and the post-revolutionary epoch. All this had much in common with the
problems which people encountered in trying to understand the huge historical
changes of our days (Lifshits 2012b, 8384).
The problem Lifshits here is referring to can be described briefly as the problem of
the relation between a pars destruens and pars construens in a revolutionary
process. In its initial phases, the revolution (both the French and the October
Revolution) acted in a destructive manner, dismantling the ancien regime. Of
course, they introduced new principles of social life, which were better than the old
ones, but at the same time these principles were still presented in an abstract
manner:
I repeat once more: this was expressly the problem of limiting the new which
was abstract and moving to newness of a kind which comprises the whole
fullness of life. Revolutionary declarations must be turned into flesh and blood
[] and they must cover the wholeness of the everyday existence of men, they
shall not remain abstract promises or, as the famous adversary of the French
Revolution, Edmund Burke said, a naked abstraction (Lifshits 2012b, 86).
It seems that the mention of Edmund Burke is here not fortuitous. The name of
Burke crops up here and there, although rather sparsely, in the oeuvre of Lifshits,
and mostly in a positive or at least neutral connotation. Burkes critique of the
excesses of the French Revolution, especially in its Jacobine phase, is a direct
parallel to Lifshitss own critique of the Proletkult and other forms of ultra-Leftism
in Russia of the 1920s.
In the same interview with Sziklai, Lifshits returns once more to his and Lukacss
attitude to Hegel:
Thus, my views on Hegel in the beginning of the 1930s were not scholarly
[] The way Lukacs and I related to Hegel in this period had a serious
content: we wanted to follow a Leninist tradition in analysing the questions of
socialist revolution [] The total negation of everything old should be
replaced by a more constructive period, which actually would deepen the
revolutionary process, although it outwardly might seem like a restoration of
2
An allusion to the German expression Kathedersozialisten, which meant academic bourgeois Marx
scholarship.
123
V. Oittinen
123
of the moment of continuity in history, its substance so to say. Only much later,
in the early 1980s, and quite independently of Lifshits ideas, there emerged in the
Soviet Union a discussion about the insufficiency of the so-called formational
approach (that is, the sequence of socio-economic formations of primitive
communism, ancient slavery, feudalism, capitalism, socialism) for the analysis of
historical processes. I cannot here go into the details of this interesting discussion;
suffice it to say that the proposal was to describe the discontinuous side of human
history by means of the received Marxist theory of socio-economic formations
(separated by revolutionary breaks), whilst the continuous side of history should
be conceptually captured by the categories of culture and civilisation (for example,
the Greek and Roman cultural tradition continues to our day despite the violent
breaks at the level of the socio-economic formation).3
Some results of this discussion were summed up in the book of Mchedlov (1980), which was translated
into German in the GDR (Mtschedlow 1983).
4
To my mind, it is not the disregard of the Marxist concept of practice per se which makes Lifshits into
an idealist, but rather his strangely Platonist theory of ideas (for a would-be Marxist indeed strange),
which he developed more in detail in his latter-day polemics with Evald Ilyenkov. According to Lifshits,
ideas have an objective existence in nature outside us. It is, obviously, this theory that he sometimes
called ontognoseology, suggesting that ideas must have an ontological grounding in non-human nature,
123
V. Oittinen
Jubara is right in claiming that Lifshits did not sufficiently take account of the
epistemological break between Hegel and Marxa drawback Lifshits shares by
the way with Lukacs. Instead of a historical-materialist analysis of the French and
Russian Revolutions we thus get a more or less Hegelian metaphysics of history.
Lifshits himself was convinced that he represented the Marxian tradition in a
more authentic way than his colleagues in the Soviet ideological establishment. In a
note preserved in his archive he wrote:
There is a Restauratio Magna already in the Communist Manifesto. It is you
(that is, the bourgeoisie who thinks that it sustains traditions) who dissolve it.
You are criminals. The economic explanation and political development of
this [] Revolution as the preserving force. I was the only one in my day,
who understood this. Lukacs?, Yes, in part5
Lifshits is here referring to the initial pages of the Communist Manifesto, where
Marx and Engels note that the bourgeoisie has not only revolutionised the
instruments of production, but destroyed all the idyllic and patriarchal relations
between men and tore away the familys sentimental veil; in other words it has been
acting as a destructive force and dissolved all traditions. Dialectically, Lifshits now
sees the Revolution as an antithesis to the destruction evoked by the bourgeoisie.
In this paper, I can only briefly dwell on the problems of Lifshitss esoteric
philosophy of history. A thorough assessment is difficult due to the fact that not all
the materials from the Lifshits archive have been published. It seems that a large
part of the manuscripts in Lifshits Nachlass consist of fragments and notes only, the
interpretation of which is a difficult task. Obviously, one can get a rather good
picture of the quality of the archive materials from the volume Chto takoe klassika?
(2004) compiled by Viktor Arslanov. In the foreword Arslanov (2004, 7) warns
readers that it demands no less effort than reading Derrida or Deleuze. Actually,
it demands much more, since the book is a patchwork of small notes, often written
down in elliptic sentences and difficult to interpret as their context is not always
clear.
However, the hitherto published materials allow at least some comments. One
problem relates to the question of analogies. It seems that the basis of Lifshits
philosophy of history consists of analogy judgements. Such judgements are rather
commonplace in speculative theories of history, for example in Arnold Toynbee, or
in the different brands of geopolitics operating with analogies between the
behaviour of political states and biological organisms. While analogical judgements
are not to be rejected outright, since they can of course give useful popular
illustrations of facts, their use, however, introduces a non-scientific and arbitrary
element into theories. Lifshits (2012b, 85) seems to have been conscious of this
problem, since in one passage in the long interview with Sziklai he defends his use
Footnote 4 continued
a grounding which he seems to have interpreted as a kind of pre-existence of ideas ante rem. Here I
cannot go into details, but see: Lifshits (2003).
5
A fragment from the Lifshits archive, with the title Revolyutsiya kak sila khranitelnaya, published in
Nezavisimaya Gazeta 3. XI. 1995, cited here according to Mareeva et al. (2001, 234).
123
For Mezhuev, see e.g. my review of his recent books (Oittinen 2009), where I point to some further
problems in Mezhuevs theory, too.
123
V. Oittinen
I have come across only one study only in which this impossibly sounding task is attempted, namely
Ruth Bevans Marx and Burke (see Bevan 1973). In order to reconcile Burkes and Marxs views, the
author points out that both thinkers shared an empiricist approach towards history and both likewise
denounced the liberal Enlightenment idea of the free individual as a starting-point of historical
explanation (Bevan 1973, 7778). To find these and further similarities in Marx and Burke, Bevan
must, however, turn a blind eye to the fact that these thinkers came to their results from quite different
positions.
123
Because Lifshits did not put forth his Restauratio Magna project in a distinct
manner, but developed it mainly in notes written for himself only, its problematic
character has hitherto eluded the attention of thoserather fewwho have studied
his works more extensively. The student of Lifshits, Viktor Arslanov, for example,
draws the following consequence from the project:
In Lifshits conception of a Restauratio Magna one can see essential
similarities not only with Antiquity, but even with the medieval Christian
world-view. In fact, the philosophy recommended returning not only to
Aristotle, but to the Ptolemaic world picture, too, which was the official
cosmology of the Middle Ages (Mareeva et al. 2001, 305).
Such assertions equate Marxism with a kind of philosophia perennis, which indeed
is a sum of eternal truths with the unchanging validity from the beginning of time.
True, Lenin spoke, as well, of Marxism as the quintessence of all previous culture,
but it is hardly believable that he would have accepted an interpretation, according
to which we should return to the Ptolemaic geocentric picture of the world (to boot,
in its medieval form, supposing crystal spheres moved by the angels).
Lifshits never published a coherent presentation of his historico-philosophical
project, which he in later years began to call by the presumptuous name Restauratio
Magna. Actually, in contrast to Jubara, who here is more cautious, I would assert,
that Lifshits theory of history is in its very core un-Marxist. The concept of a
Restauratio Magna brings to the theory the idea of a philosophia perennis, an
eternal component.
Of course, it would have been difficult to publish, in the Soviet Union, a book
containing such a striking reformulation of basic ideas of Marxism. It thus remained
an esoteric theory, which Lifshits mostly kept to himself and put down in only
private comments in his notebooks. Neverthless, this theory of history exerted its
influence in the exoteric published writings of Lifshits. It must be seen as the
background of most of what Lifshits has written and managed to publish in
questions of literature, philosophy, and aesthetics. It explains, too, his tirades against
modernist art, which otherwise seems so inexplicable, because differing so much
from the received views of the Left. Once we understand that Lifshits interprets
culture and the cultural heritage as, so to say, a paradoxical symbiosis of the views
of Marx and Edmund Burke, we can see the hidden reason of his logic.
References
Arslanov, V. G. (2004). K chitatelyu etoi knigi. In M. Lifshits (Ed.), Chto takoe klassika?. Moskva:
Iskusstvo XX vek.
Arslanov, V. G. (2010). Ot redaktora. In V. G. Arslanov (Ed.), Mikhail Aleksandrovich Lifshits.
ROSSPEN: Moskva.
Bevan, R. (1973). Marx and Burke. A revisionist view. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court Publ. Company.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1848). Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte. In G. W. F. Hegel (Eds.),
Werke (Freundesausgabe), Bd. IX, 3. Berlin: Aufl.
123
V. Oittinen
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969). Hegels science of logic (A. V. Miller, Trans.). London New York: Allen &
Unwin/Humanities Press.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1999). Wissenschaft der Logik, I. In Hauptwerke in sechs Banden, Bd. 3, Hamburg:
Meiner Vlg.
Jubara, A. (2010). Universalism in cultural history and the meaning of the Russian Revolution: on some
aspects of cultural theory in the work of Mikhail Lifsic. Studies in East European Thought, 62.
Lenin, V. I. (1973). On proletarian culture. In Collected works, 4th ed. (Vol. 31). Moscow: Progress
Publishers.
Lifshits, M. (2003). Dialog s Evaldom Ilenkovym. Moskva: Progress Traditsiya.
Lifshits, M. (2012a). O Gegele. Moskva: Grundrisse.
Lifshits, M. (2012b). Nadoelo. Moskva: Iskusstvo XXI vek (quoted as Lifshits 2012 b).
Mareeva, E. V., Mareev, S. N., & Arslanov, V. G. (2001). Filosofiya XX veka (Vol. 1). Moskva:
Akademicheskiy proekt.
Marx, K. (1952). Capital (Vol. I). Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc.
Mchedlov, M. (1980). Sotsializm stanovlenie novogo tipa tsivilizatsii. Moskva: Politizdat (new
expanded edition with the same title, Moskva: Progress 1983).
Mtschedlow, M. (1983). Sozialismus - ein neuer Zivilisationstyp (Vol. 3). Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Oittinen, V. (2009). [Review of:] V. M.Mezhuev, Marks protiv marksizma. In Voprosy Filosofii (Vol. 3,
pp. 176179).
Sziklai, L. (1990). Georg Lukacs und seine Zeit. 19301945. Berlin/Weimar: Aufbau Vlg.
123
AM: We are presently preparing, here at the Institute for Human Sciences, the
translation of several essays by Bibikhin (2017). One of them is the essay For
Official Use Only from the book Another Beginning (2003). In this essay, Bibikhin
describes the mechanism of scholarly production in the context of the INION, the
Institute for Social Sciences, during the late Soviet period. The essay starts with a
somewhat mysterious phrase: The authorities began to look for an alternative
ideology to Marxism very early. Already in 1973, we knew that the military
political strategists were planning to abandon Marxism and replace it with
Orthodoxy as the ideological support of the Soviet army. Could you say the same
about yourself, namely, that you knew, at that time, that the Soviet nomenclature
was conducting this exploration of alternatives to Marxism?
SH: I am not part of this we. I knew nothing of such plans by the Soviet
authorities or top military leaders, and, moreover, I dont believe that there were
such plans. Immediately after the fall of the communist regime a big part of the
soviet nomenclature started to proclaim themselves to be champions of Orthodoxy
and the Church. But this took place following five years of perestroika and sharp
criticism of soviet ideology, when the demise of the latter was evident. However, in
This interview was held in March 2015 during the visit of Sergey Sergeevich Horujy to the Institute of
Human Sciences in Vienna. It was conducted by Kristina Stoeckl and Alexander Michailowski.
& Kristina Stoeckl
[email protected]
Alexander Michailowski
[email protected]
1
123
K. Stoeckl, A. Michailowski
the 70s this was hardly a real perspective, and I think that as a rule, members of the
nomenclature were still convinced of the strength and stability of soviet ideology,
even if many of them were not enthusiastic adepts. They could not see any serious
need to look for an alternative to this ideology; on the contrary, they had serious
reasons to hold on to it. For instance, the role and activity of the USSR on the world
scene was strongly dependent on the close ties with Marxist parties and movements
all over the world. Could they reject all this?
As for my views at that time, around 1973, I also didnt doubt that the
nomenclature and, in particular, military political strategists are in overwhelming
majority loyal adepts of soviet ideology and therefore very far from planning any
radical alternatives to it. And Im sure this view was largely shared in the milieu of
the Church people and Christian intellectuals, to which both Bibikhin and I
belonged.
AM: But what was the motivation for the statement by Bibikhin?
SH: I cannot speak for him. As a guess, this statement and its we could refer to
another milieu to which Vladimir Veniaminovich was connected, that of Moscows
liberal philosophers, in particular, from the INION, the Institute for Social Sciences,
whose activity he describes in the text you are quoting. This circle included also
party members, people with some inside knowledge. They knew much better what
party leaders were up to, and perhaps they could imagine such a shift and discussed
it during their table conversations (or rather kitchen-talk in the style of the soviet
intelligentsia). But still I think that the plans for such a shift were mostly the fruits
of their imagination and wishful thinking.
AM: In his book The Russian Party (Moscow, 2003), Nikolaj Mitrokhin claims
that in 1974, in the second issue of the underground journal Moskovskij Sbornik,
which appeared under the heading The problems of the nation and religion, the
real author of the article Lev Karsavin. A biographical sketch, published under
the pseudonym S. Glebov, is you. Is Mitrokhin right, and if yes, what can you tell us
about your collaboration with Leonid Borodin, the editor of this journal and leader
of the nationalist Russian Party?
SH: In the beginning of the 70s I was writing my first philosophical texts. They
were devoted to Russian religious philosophy, to Florensky, Karsavin, etc., and they
were of the kind that was not only unpublishable, but severely persecuted in the
USSR of that time. Thus it is only through the Samizdat, through underground
journals of the dissident movement, that they could find their way to readers. I
collaborated with this movement, but only to a restricted extent. Undoubtedly, I
shared its general anti-totalitarian and anti-communist positions, and I considered it
a kind of moral duty to support it. But, having first-hand knowledge of it and being
personally acquainted with many of its leaders, I saw clearly that the crude reality of
the movement, its representatives, its ethical atmosphere often did not correspond
fully to its high principles and goals. Moreover, I was very absorbed in my work in
quantum field theory and didnt think it was worth sacrificing this work for the sake
of dissident activity.
As a result, it was a distant relationship. One can say that I did not include myself
directly in the dissident movement but was part of its supportive milieu. For
instance, it was known that I was well acquainted with Russian emigre literature,
123
and so I used to draw up lists of books that should be ordered from the West and
brought to the Soviet Union. Long lists of philosophical and theological titles. And
you see, from time to time these lists of mine really went through and the books
arrived and could be read and used.
AM: But what about your article in the Moskovskij Sbornik and your
collaboration with Leonid Borodin?
SH: While I was not fascinated by the general atmosphere of the dissident
movement, at the same time I had a quite high opinion of some members of this
movement. Some were rather close acquaintances. In the first place I must name
here two persons who were among the leaders of two opposite trends or wings.
Sergey Grigoriants was one of the leaders of the European-oriented dissidents, while
Leonid Borodin belonged to the leaders of the opposite so-called nationalist or
Russian Party trend in the dissident movement. One could say probably that both
were my friends. For example, they both came to see me just few days before they
were arrested. Usually people like them knew quite well that they would be arrested.
And it makes a difference whom you choose to see in the last days of your freedom.
Such meetings create a link and leave a mark.
Now, as I said, my texts could only go to the Samizdat, and since Leonid was
publishing some underground journal (I cant remember whether I saw any issue of
it), I gave him some of them. And I dont know what happened afterwards. I
disliked the idea of a pseudonym, but on the other hand I understood very well that I
couldnt publish under my real name, so I just didnt put any name on these texts.
There were several such texts: one on Florensky, one on Karsavin. Then there was
one samizdat project (not connected with Borodin) about which I knew a bit more, it
was the collection of articles called Slovo (Word), dedicated to some anniversary of
the priesthood of father Alexander Men. I wrote a text about the concept of the
symbol especially for this project. I know that it was published, but I never saw the
book.
AM: So you are telling us that you dont know all your pseudonyms?
SH: Exactly. I dont know. But from your question I gather that this text about
Karsavin, under the pseudonym Glebov, must be by me. You see, if the publishers
had told me that I had to choose my pseudonym, I probably would have decided to
use my real name.
AM: How do you feel today about your collaboration with Borodin?
SH: As you see, my participation in Borodins projects was quite insignificant
and was based entirely on our warm personal relationship. My texts were
philosophical. I never read his journals and we never discussed their ideological
platforms (although I suspected that probably I would not subscribe to them). But in
no way did this mean that it was all the same for me with which texts mine were
grouped. No. It means that, having personal confidence in Leonid, I admitted a
priori that his selection would be good quality and would not propagate something
disgusting and unworthy.
I had the same kind of feeling about Grigoriants as well. And it is characteristic
that in the post-soviet period my relationship with both of them did not continue.
Something had finished. And the main element in this something is perfectly
123
K. Stoeckl, A. Michailowski
123
first stages. It started in 1988 or 1989 and then it proceeded in very quick tempo.
There is a famous anecdoteit seems that it is not invented, but realthat the last
decision made by the Politburo of the Communist Party, before it was dissolved,
was the decision to organise a big campaign to publish Russian religious
philosophers.
AM: This Return of the Forgotten Names worked through the journal Voprosy
filosofii.
SH: Yes, this journal was the centre of the campaign. It was the chief periodical
of soviet philosophy and it has preserved this standing in the post-Soviet epoch. By
the irony of fate, for a while its principal mission became the propagation of Russian
religious thought. To ensure success of the mission, a new secretary of the editorial
board was appointed who was the son of one of Gorbachevs closest collaborators.
And as early as 1989 the big publishing project was launched, in the first place the
book series devoted to works of Russian thinkers, religious philosophers. The series
continues to this day, although it ceased to be in the focus of public attention long
ago. Its volumes are not of rigorous academic standards, but still they gradually
achieved a decent level of the textological work and commentary, and the people
who prepare them are usually sufficiently expert.
Thus the project was a success, but on the whole the big boom around Russian
religious thought produced very mixed results. Throughout the period of Eltsins
Russia there were lots and lots of lies, falsities, ambiguity and, of course, crude
incompetence. As I said, the leading roles in the process had been seized, firmly and
everywhere, by former communist functionaries.
KS: So you are telling us that at the time when Russian religious thought finally
could emerge from the underground of Soviet society to public consciousness, it
was not you and your kindthe religious dissidents who had cherished this legacy
and kept it alive for decadeswho led the process, but it was the Communist Party?
SH: Not quite so. Of course, the Communist Party as such had lost its leading
role, but a very big part of its functionaries left its ranks in time and succeeded in
taking leading positions in all important fields. In particular, a great many
proclaimed themselves, as I said above, to be champions of Orthodoxy and the
Church. As for the ideological functionaries, they easily preserved their leading
posts within the machinery of philosophical (as well as cultural) life, changing
communist slogans to primitive Orthodox twaddle. They were, of course,
incompetent and unable to do any scholarly work in the field of religious thought,
but still they headed all big and important projects in this field, while real experts
were exploited for the concrete (and often hard) work for a song. They were also
active and energetic in hunting for huge grants, both Russian and foreign, presenting
projects with extremely noble and pious titles and goals. They started organizing
lots of programs, events, and institutions directed to such goals. For example, I was
once approached by a strange person who introduced himself as the head of the
World Congress of the Holy Trinity and Sobornost. Using Christian terms like
words from a poorly learned foreign language, he invited me to join his congress.
Later I found out that this person was a professor at a KGB academy.
123
K. Stoeckl, A. Michailowski
All this faked spiritual activity made the situation extremely mixed and muddled
and nasty smelling. It was a problem to find in this stuff real and valuable elements,
but such elements were also theremalgre tout!
KS: What does your story teach us about todays situation? You know that
President Putin recently quoted Berdyaev and Ilyin in his speeches.
SH: One more thing that must be said here: In spite of all the nasty things that I
described, the main task was to have the texts published, to make accessible to the
public what had been forbidden for many, many years. And this task was fulfilled
quite successfully. Now the entire body of texts of Russian religious philosophy is
easily accessible for anybody interested. In that sense, the return of forgotten
names was indeed successful.
KS: But what about the reception?
SH: Well, exactly, the reception is quite a different problem. The texts are
accessible, but what next? Next it might very well turn out that they are not needed.
Evidently, the problem of reception has two different aspects, namely, the reception
of individual thinkers and the reception of the tradition as a whole, the phenomenon
of Russian religious philosophy in its entirety. Taking the first aspect, I would say
that today for each of the big figures of the tradition the reception is quite different.
Philosophers are bright individuals and each of the towering figures of the Silver
Age has his own destiny in our times. Vyacheslav Ivanov, for example, has a very
happy destiny. There is a good academic community around him both in Russia and
abroad. This community is more or less united, there is not much difference whether
members of this community work in Russia or in Berkeley or elsewhere. They have
regular meetings, they communicate with each other. Florensky also has a rather
self-reproducing community of scholars who study him and publish his works. Ilyin
is again a slightly different case; he became the chief author of the nationalist
circles. Losev has an excellent centre in Moscow, which coordinates all the work on
his heritage. Karsavin has a small community as well. Berdyaev is still another story
(after decades of immense popularity he is not so lucky today), and so on. So there
is a set of individual receptions and, on the whole, there are some experts and some
continuing lines of research on each of the major figures of the tradition.
In contrast to this, with regard to the second aspect I would say that the rich
phenomenon of Russian religious philosophy as a whole still lacks a full and
consistent reception. One serious reason is that this philosophy is of a mixed nature,
combining properties of Western philosophy and Byzantine thought, which is
deeply different from the former in its constitution and discourse. (In particular, it
comprises a different relationship between philosophy and theology.) What
Byzantine thought is still not sufficiently understood and is actively investigated
at present; as a consequence, the nature of Russian religious philosophy is also not
yet sufficiently understood. Another reason is that at present the philosophical
situation both in Russia and on the global scale is not very creative. Missing in
contemporary Russian philosophy is the capacity to generalize for which reason it
seems unable to create a sound conception of the big phenomenon of Russian
religious thought in all its complexity and entirety.
The absence of a meaningful reception of its past stages is a big obstacle to the
further development of Russian philosophy. Because of this absence, when young
123
123
K. Stoeckl, A. Michailowski
intellectuals, and, vice versa, intellectuals can be nationalists. You see, the dividing
lines are not here, these two things are perfectly compatible.
KS: But what is incompatible then? Are there dividing lines that structure the
religious discourse into a liberal, reformist camp and a conservative, nationalist
camp?
SH: Of course, there is inevitably some structuring, but in the changing modern
reality its principles may change too. Sure, some universal principles are always there:
for instance, in the ROC, as in any religious society at any period, there are
fundamentalist (conservative, nationalist, anti-secular) and liberal (reformist, open to
dialogue) groups and trends. Today, as we already said, the fundamentalist trend is
growing and prevails. As for new principles, one very old dividing line is becoming
much more visible and important in the last years, under the present Patriarch: the
division between the rich and the poor, the rich hierarchy with its surroundings and the
majority of the poor clergy, paid miserably and dragging a heavy burden of evergrowing payments to higher ecclesiastic authorities. This greed for money is a new
feature closely connected with the new status of the Church.
After the fall of the monarchy and the Church Council in 19171918 the ROC
ceased to be the Synodal Church and restored the Moscow Patriarchate. Then after
the fall of the Soviet regime it ceased to be totally controlled by the secular state. As
a result, a certain new kind of relation of the Church and the state has emerged in
which the Church is much less subordinate to the state and included into its
mechanism. As before, it gives all its support to the state, but now it has the freedom
of choice (at least relative) and this support is not taken for granted. It means that
the Church has now some power of its own, and it wants very much to increase this
power. It wants to be a strong and independent ally of the state garnering all the
possible profits of its support of the latter. And a strong power is always greedy for
money and wealth.
Thus the striving for power and wealth is now very visibly high on the list of
priorities of the heads of the ROC. Quite close partnership with the secular
administration on all levels is very visible too. Moreover, as everywhere throughout
the country, the Church is affected by the enormous over-bureaucratization and
formalization of its life, bordering on absurdity. All these striking features are at the
forefront, but, in contrast to them, it is not so easy to see, which place is given to
properly Christian and spiritual values and goals.
Inevitably, this glaring predominance of quite worldly and dubious goals and
interests should sooner or later result in the loss of the spiritual authority of the
Church, disaffection with the Church by wider and wider strata, and the decline of
public support of the Church. The rise of these phenomena is already quite evident.
KS and AM: Sergey Sergeevich, thank you for this conversation.
Acknowledgements The authors acknowledge the European Research Council grant ERC STG 2015
676804 for the publication of this interview.
Reference
Bibikhin, V. (forthcoming 2017) Der andere Anfang. In A. Michailowski (Ed.). Matthes & Seitz, Berlin.
123