Our Aesthetic Categories Sianne Ngai PDF
Our Aesthetic Categories Sianne Ngai PDF
Our Aesthetic Categories Sianne Ngai PDF
948
125.4
Sianne Ngai
[ PM L A
the sense of the ironic detachment attributed
to das Interessante, a style of eclectic novelty
first explicitly theorized by Friedrich Schlegel
and the German Romantic ironists as part of
a larger agenda calling for art to become more
reflective or philosophical (see Wheeler), and
in the technocratic, informatic sense Alan Liu
conveys in his book on postmodern knowledge work. And the zany, for its part, is hot:
hot under the collar, hot and bothered, hot
to trot. Pointing to the intensely embodied
affects and desires of an agent compelled to
move, hustle, and perform in the presence of
others, these idioms underscore that the zany
is the only aesthetic category in our repertoire
with a special relation to affective or physical
effort and is thus an aesthetic whose dynamics
are most sharply brought out in performance:
dance, theater, happenings, television, film. It
is because the zany, interesting, and cute are
respectively about performance, information
or media, and domestic lifeand more specifically about the ambiguous status of performance between labor and play, the ceaseless
relaying of artworks through the medium of
discourse, and the paradoxical complexity of
our desire for a simpler relation to our household commoditiesthat the deepest content of
these aesthetic categories concerns the socially
binding processes of production, circulation,
and consumption. And it is because the zany,
interesting, and cute are about production,
circulation, and consumption that they are so
important, as a triad, to the genealogy of the
postmodern and to our aesthetic theory.
Yet the interesting, cute, and zany are also
undeniably trivial. Indeed, in contrast to the
powerful moral and political resonances of the
beautiful and sublime, each of the aesthetic
categories in this triad revolves around a specific type of inconsequentiality: the low affect
that accompanies the perception of minor
differences against a backdrop of the generic,
in the case of the interesting; physical smallness and vulnerability, in the case of the cute;
and the flailing helplessness of impotent rage,
125.4
in the case of the zany. Because of a contradictory mixture of affects underscoring their
politically ambivalent naturefor the zany,
fun and unfun; for the interesting, interest
and boredom; and for the cute, tenderness and
aggressionwe might say that the cute, interesting, and zany have a certain mereness at
their cores. Yet this triviality is not itself trivial; it explains why these aesthetic categories
are suited for helping us think more deeply
about the shifting meanings of the aesthetic,
art, and even culture in our time, a period in
which, with the integration of aesthetic production . . . into commodity production generally, as Fredric Jameson notes, the frantic
economic urgency of producing fresh waves of
ever more novel-seeming goods (from clothing
to airplanes), at ever greater rates of turnover,
now assigns an increasingly structural function and position to aesthetic innovation and
experimentation (4). In addition to posing
unprecedented challenges for our understanding of the new and avant-garde, this increasing
interpenetration of economy and culture has
wrought two significant changes for the concept of art as such, Jameson notes: the weakening of arts capacity to serve as an image of
nonalienated labor (which it has arguably done
since the eighteenth century) and the loss of
arts more specifically modernist, twentiethcentury mission of producing perceptual
shock (14647, 12122). With the waning of
these older vocations for art and aesthetic experience, minor aesthetic categories crop up
everywhere, testifying in their ubiquity to how
aesthetic experience, radically generalized in
an age of design and advertising, becomes less
rarefied but also less intense. The romance of
cuteness, the comedy of zaniness, and the realist and information-oriented aesthetic of the
interesting are thus important to autonomous
arts attempts to reflect on the smoothness of
its integration in mass culture. What better
way to get traction on arts diminishing role
as the privileged locus for modern aesthetic
experience than an aesthetic category of and
Sianne Ngai
PM L A
125.4
Sianne Ngai
[ PM L A
than to styles such as art deco or cubism, as if,
when it comes to postmodernism, only the less
institutionally codified, less chronologically
restricted set of styles can still be historical.
To consider aesthetic categories not as
styles but as discursive judgmentsculturally formalized ways of publicly sharing our
pleasures and displeasuresis to go to the
heart of Kantian aesthetic theory in a way
that might make us wonder why so little attention has been given to this aspect of them.
Yet in a sense the asymmetry is not hard to
understand, since the discursive life of aesthetic categories, subtly woven into the fabric
of ordinary conversation, is both less visible
and also arguably more complex. For one
thing, as Stanley Cavell has shown, aesthetic
judgments belong to the troublesome class
of performative utterances that J. L. Austin
classified as perlocutionary: verbal actions
such as praising, criticizing, complimenting,
soothing, or insulting, which, in contrast to
illocutionary acts like betting and marrying,
are more successfully performed in an inexplicit rather than explicit form. Saying Nice
haircut! is a more effective way of complimenting than announcing I compliment
you. The most important feature of perlocutionary utterances for Cavell, however, and
particularly of the affective subset of perlocutions he calls passionate utterances, is the
way in which the power to assess their accomplishment shifts from the speaker to the
interlocutor. It is the person in the position
of receiving a compliment or apology rather
than the one who offers it, in other words,
who ultimately determines whether the act
of complimenting or apologizing has successfully taken place (if my friend takes Nice
haircut! as a sardonic insult, for example, my
act of complimenting failed).
Cavell thus brings out the surprising relevance of Austins theory of performative language for aesthetic theoryand particularly
for our understanding of the feature of the
aesthetic claim, as suggested by Kants descrip-
125.4
tion, as a kind of compulsion to share a pleasure, hence as tinged with an anxiety that the
claim stands to be rebuked (9). Though forming judgments of beauty silently in our heads
seems possible, making aesthetic pleasure
a feeling that does not need to be publicized
and confirmed by others, this is not the way
in which Kant describes it.4 In his account,
it does not seem possible to judge something
beautiful without speaking or at least imagining oneself speaking and without making the
error of putting ones judgment in the form
of a descriptive, third-person statement (X is
cute) rather than a first-person statement that
looks more openly like the subjective evaluation it is (I judge X cute). There is thus something rhetorically stealthy in a curiously open
way, about the work of aesthetic categories, as
Grard Genette underscores in his account of
aesthetic predicates as persuasive or valorizing descriptions that bridge the abyss between
fact and value without becoming too conspicuous. Because interesting and cute (and
perhaps we could add glossy and messy) are
semidescriptive or semijudgmental, they are
essentially means [by] which one judges under cover of describing (92; emphases added).
The rhetorically clandestine work of aesthetic categories thus throws further light on
a problem for criticism that, I have elsewhere
suggested, the interesting embodies (Merely
Interesting): why it is so strangely easy to
mistake criticism that identifies with and
strives to participate in the making of aesthetic judgments with criticism in which the
main goal is analyzing aesthetic judgments.
The fact that they are so frequently conflated
is itself of theoretical interest. For mistaking
aesthetic evaluation with analysis mirrors
not only the constitutive error of Kantian
taste, which necessarily confuses subjective
judgments with statements of objective fact,
but also the way in which it is paradoxically
internal to the interesting to toggle between
aesthetic and nonaesthetic judgments. I want
to turn our attention to this issue, since it
Sianne Ngai
an amused and desultory way that seems intended to highlight their irrelevance:
As far as taste is concerned (and as readers of
the preceding chapters will have become aware),
culturally I write as a relatively enthusiastic
consumer of postmodernism, at least some
parts of it: I like the architecture and a lot of
the newer visual work. . . . The music is not bad
to listen to, or the poetry to read; the novel is
the weakest of the newer cultural areas and is
considerably excelled by its narrative counterparts in film and video (at least the high literary novel is; subgeneric narratives, however, are
very good, indeed . . . ). My sense is that this is
essentially a visual culture, wired for sound
but one where the linguistic element . . . is slack
and flabby, and not to be made interesting without ingenuity, daring, and keen motivation.
(29899; emphasis added)
PM L A
125.4
NOTES
I am grateful to Mark McGurl for his comments on this
essay. I would also like to thank Jonathan Culler and
Cathy Caruth.
Sianne Ngai
1. It is worth noting how quickly displeasure seems
to drop out of the picture not just in contemporary aesthetic theory but also in The Critique of Judgment, where
Kant first mentions dissatisfaction without any interest
side by side with satisfaction without any interest but
never gives us an account of what the former is (leading
to much debate about whether or not Kantian aesthetics can genuinely account for the ugly; 96). Would the
widely held idea that aesthetic judgments have no place
in critique be less prevalent if it were recognized that the
aesthetic includes displeasure as well as complicated mixtures of displeasure and pleasure? This is in fact the case
for all the aesthetic categories featured in my study.
2. On the disappearance or impossibility of the
avant-garde, see Jameson 167. On the parergon as index
of the relation between art and theory, see Derrida.
3. Thanks to Mark Goble for helping me see this.
4. See par. 6 and esp. par. 7, in which the difference between the pleasant and the beautiful is described first and
foremost as a difference in how we converse about them.
WORKS CITED
Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 1958. Print.
Benjamin, Walter. Charles Baudelaire: A Lyric Poet in the
Era of High Capitalism. Trans. Harry Zohn. London:
New Left, 1973. Print.
Bourdieu, Pierre. The Rules of Art: Genesis and Structure
of the Literary Field. Trans. Susan Emanuel. Stanford:
Stanford UP, 1992. Print.
Brown, Judith. Glamour in Six Dimensions. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 2009. Print.
Cavell, Stanley. Philosophy the Day after Tomorrow. Cambridge: BelknapHarvard UP, 2005. Print.
Derrida, Jacques. The Truth in Painting. Trans. Geoffrey
Bennington and Ian McLeod. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1987. Print.
Genette, Grard. The Aesthetic Relation. Trans. G. M.
Goshgarian. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1999. Print.
Harris, Daniel. Cute, Quaint, Hungry, and Romantic: The
Aesthetics of Consumerism. New York: Da Capo, 2001.
Print.
Harvey, David. The Condition of Postmodernity: An Inquiry into the Origins of Cultural Change. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1989. Print.
Henke, Robert. Performance and Literature in the Commedia dellArte. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2003. Print.
James, Henry. The Art of Fiction. The Critical Muse:
Selected Literary Criticism. New York: Penguin, 1987.
186206. Print.
Jameson, Fredric. Postmodernism; or, The Cultural Logic
of Late Capitalism. Durham: Duke UP, 1991. Print.
[ PM L A
Schlegel, Friedrich. On the Study of Greek Poetry. Ed. and
trans. Stuart Barnett. Albany: State U of New York P,
2001. Print.
Stewart, Susan. Poetry and the Fate of the Senses. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2002. Print.
Wheeler, Kathleen M., ed. German Aesthetic and Literary
Criticism: The Romantic Ironists and Goethe. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1984. Print.
Williams, Raymond. Culture and Society, 17801950.
New York: Columbia UP, 1983. Print.