Cs245 F16 Part 1

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 310

Logic and Computation:

Propositional Logic
Jonathan Buss
November 1, 2016
Based in part on materials prepared by B. Bonakdarpour
from Huth & Ryans text.
Additional thanks to D. Maftuleac, R. Trefler, and P. Van Beek.

1/241

Broad Outline of Propositional Logic

Introduction to Propositional Logic


Syntax
Semantics
Proof Systems

2/241

Logic: What and Why


Logic is the systematic study of the principles of reasoning and
inference.
We use logic throughout computer science,
To model the computer hardware, software and embedded

systems we create or encounter, in order to reason about those


objects in a mathematically precise and rigorous manner.
To understand how to develop systems that can themselves

apply reason and make inferences (artificial intelligence).


Historically, logic and CS are closely linked.
To define and build a computer required deep ideas from logic.
Computer science gave the first real definition of rigorous

argument: an argument that may be checked by a machine.

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

3/241

An Example Argument
Consider this example.
If the train arrives late and there are no taxis at the station,
then John is late for his meeting.
John is not late for his meeting.
The train did arrive late.
Therefore, there were taxis at the station.
Question. Is this argument valid? Why, or why not?

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

4/241

An Example Argument
Consider this example.
If the train arrives late and there are no taxis at the station,
then John is late for his meeting.
John is not late for his meeting.
The train did arrive late.
Therefore, there were taxis at the station.
Question. Is this argument valid? Why, or why not?
Question. What is the structure of the argument?

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

4/241

An Example Argument
Consider this example.
If the train arrives late and there are no taxis at the station,
then John is late for his meeting.
John is not late for his meeting.
The train did arrive late.
Therefore, there were taxis at the station.
Question. Is this argument valid? Why, or why not?
Question. What is the structure of the argument?
We can represent the structure symbolically as
If p and not q, then r. Not r. p. Therefore q.

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

4/241

An Example Argument (2)


The argument in the previous example has the form
If p and not q, then r. Not r. p. Therefore q.
where
p stands for the train arrives late.
q stands for there are taxis at the station.
r stands for John is late for his meeting.

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

5/241

An Example Argument (2)


The argument in the previous example has the form
If p and not q, then r. Not r. p. Therefore q.
where
p stands for the train arrives late.
q stands for there are taxis at the station.
r stands for John is late for his meeting.
What happens if we change our notion of p, q and r? Perhaps
p stands for It rains.
q stands for Jane takes her umbrella.
r stands for Jane gets very wet.
Then the argument changes. . .
Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

5/241

An Example Argument (3)


The essential argument: If p and not q, then r. Not r. p. Therefore q.
New choices for p, q and r:
p stands for It rains.
q stands for Jane takes her umbrella.
r stands for Jane gets very wet.
The new argument is
If it rains, and Jane does not take her umbrella, then Jane
gets very wet. Jane does not get very wet. It rains.
Therefore, Jane takes her umbrella.
An equally valid argument!

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

6/241

What Is Logic?Reprise
In the example argument,
The factual content of the statements doesnt matter.
The relationships among the statements govern the argument.

Logic concerns careful reasoning about the process of reasoning.


As part of this care, we need to know
What, exactly, constitutes a statement?
What, precisely, do the logical relationships mean?

We shall start with a basic form of logic, called propositional logic.

Introduction to Logic

What is logic?

7/241

Propositions

A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or false.


In other words, we make the following defining assumption:
For any particular proposition, in any particular situation (or
world), either the proposition is true, or the proposition is
false, and it is never the case that the proposition is both
true and false.

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

8/241

Examples of Propositions
Each of the following is a proposition.
The sum of 3 and 5 is 8.
The sum of 3 and 5 is 35.
5.
Program p terminates.
If the input to program p is a non-negative integer , then

p outputs the value 2 .

If Kathleen Wynne is a Tory, then Justin Trudeau is a Liberal.


Every even number greater than 2 is the sum of two prime

numbers.
Jane reacted violently to Jacks accusations.

In some of the cases, we may not know whether the statement is


true or false, but its one or the otherand not both.

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

9/241

Translating from English to propositional logic


English phrases for connectives
p

not p; p does not hold; p is false;


it is not the case that p

pq

p and q; p but q; not only p but q; p while q;


p despite q, p yet q, p although q

pq

p or q, p or q or both, p and/or q, p unless q

pq

if p then q; p implies q; q if p, p only if q, q when p,


p is sufficient for q, q is necessary for p,

p q

p if and only if q (p iff q);


p is equivalent to q; p exactly if q;
p is necessary and sufficient for q,

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

10/241

Translating from English to propositional logic

Examples
1. She is clever and hard working.
2. He is clever but not hard working.
3. He didnt write the letter or the letter was lost.
4. If he does not study hard then he will fail.
5. He must study hard; otherwise he will fail.
6. He will fail unless he studies hard.
7. He will not fail only if he studies hard.

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

11/241

Translating from English to propositional logic

Examples
1. If it rains, he will be at home; otherwise he will go to the market
or to school.
2. The sum of two numbers is even if and only if both numbers are
even or both numbers are odd.
3. If y is an integer then z is not real, provided that is rational.

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

12/241

Propositions

Some sentences are not propositions. For example, a sentence


might be
Interrogative: Where shall we go to eat?
Imperative:
Please pass the salt.
Ambiguous:
Time flies like an arrow.
Nonsense:
The mome raths outgrabe.
Otherwise problematic:
This sentence is false.
In the field of artificial intelligence, one must deal with such
sentences. For this course, however, we shall ignore them.

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

13/241

The Aspects of Logic

Propositional logic is a form of symbolic logic. That is, it uses strings


of symbols to represent propositions and to build arguments.
A symbolic logic is formalized by the following.
Syntax: What statements do we consider?
Semantics: What does a statement mean?
Proof procedures: Given a statement, can we prove it true?
We shall treat each part in detail.

Introduction to Logic

Propositional logic

14/241

Syntax of
Propositional Logic

Syntax

15/241

Atomic and compound propositions


In propositional logic, simple atomic propositions are the basic
building blocks.
They cannot be broken up into smaller propositions.
We connect atomic propositions into compound propositions, and
then analyze sets of interrelated propositions.
Typical questions to consider:
Does a given sequence of propositions form a valid argument?
Can all propositions in a given set be true simultaneously?

First, however, we must answer the question,


What is the structure of a proposition?

Syntax

16/241

Symbols and expressions


Propositions are represented by formulas.
A formula consists of a sequence of symbols. There are three kinds
of symbols.
Propositional variables: Usually lowercase Latin letters;
e.g., p, q, r, etc., perhaps with subscripts (p1 , p2 , q27 , etc.),
Connectives: We shall use , , , and .
(Others are possible.)
Punctuation: ( and ).

Every formula is a sequence of symbols, but not every sequence of


symbols is a formula.
An arbitrary finite sequence of symbols is an expression (or string).

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

17/241

More on Expressions
An expression is a finite sequence (or string) of symbols.
The length of an expression is its number of symbols.
For example, ()()pq is an expression.
Questions:
What is its length of this expression?
Is it a formula?

We often use a letter that is not formally a symbol in order to name


an expression. For example, we might denote the expression above
by .
This is an example of a meta-symbol. It is NOT a symbol!

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

18/241

Talking about expressions


Some terminology for expressions.
Two expressions and are equal, written as = , iff they are

of the same length, say n, and if n > 0 then for all [1..n] the
th symbol of is the same as the th symbol of .

We write to mean the concatenation of two expressions

and . For example, if


and
then

= ()()
= pq
= ()()pq .

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

19/241

Concatenation, formally

Definition:
If is an expression of length and is an expression of
length j, then is an expression of length + j. We have

the k th symbol of
if k
th
The k symbol of is
th
the (k ) symbol of if k >

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

20/241

Definition of well-formed formula


Let P be a set of propositional variables. We define the set of
well-formed formulas (or WFFs) over P inductively as follows.
1. An expression consisting of a single symbol of P is a well-formed
formula.
2. If is a well-formed formula, then () is a well-formed formula.
3. If is a well-formed formula and is a well-formed formula,
then each of
( ) ,

( ) ,

and

( ) ,

and

( )

is a well-formed formula.
4. Nothing else is a well-formed formula.

(Note the use of the meta-symbols and to refer to formulas.)

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

21/241

Examples: well-formed formulas

Example: The following are well-formed formulas.


1. p, q, r, s

(rule 1)

2. (p)

(rule 2, from #1)

3. (r q)

(rule 3, from #1)

4. ((p) s)

(rule 3, from #2 and #1)

5. ((r q) ((p) s))

(rule 3, from #3 and #4)

6. ((r q))

(rule 2, from #3)

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

22/241

The Kinds of Formulas


The definition implies that each formula has one of the following
kinds.
A propositional variable is called an atom.
A formula () is called a negation.
A formula ( ) is called a conjunction.
A formula ( ) is called a disjunction.
A formula ( ) is called an implication.
A formula ( ) is called an equivalence.

Question: Can a formula have two (or more) kinds? E.g., can it be
both a conjunction and an implication? Or both a negation and a
disjunction?

Syntax

Symbols, expressions and formulas

23/241

Semantics of
Propositional Logic

Semantics

24/241

Semantics
The semantics of a logic describes how to interpret the well-formed
formulas of the logic.
The semantics of propositional logic is compositional; in other
words, the meaning of a whole formula derives from the meaning of
its parts.
In propositional logic, we need to give meaning to atoms,
connectives, and formulas.
For example, the interpretation of formula (p q) depends on three
things: the meaning of p, the meaning of q, and the meaning of .

Semantics

25/241

Valuations: the status of atoms

Definition:
A truth valuation is a function with the set of all proposition
symbols as domain and {F, T} as range.
In other words, a truth valuation assigns a value to every
propositional variable.
If t(p) = T, then we say/write, t makes p true.
If t(p) = F, then we say/write, t makes p false.

A propositional variable has no intrinsic meaning; it gets a meaning


only via a valuation.

Semantics

26/241

Compound formulas

Let and be two formulas that express propositions A and B.


Intuitively, we give the following meanings to combinations.

Not A
A and B
A or B
If A then B
A iff B

The English, however, can be ambiguous. We want precise


meanings for formulas.

Semantics

27/241

Semantics of Connectives
Formally, a connective represents a function from truth values to
truth values.
There are two types of connectives: unary and binary.
The connective is unary; it maps one value to one value. We can
show its function in a picture, known as a truth table:

T
F

()
F
T

The other connectives are binary; they map two values to one value.
Thus their truth tables require four lines to cover the possibilities.

Semantics

Connectives

28/241

Truth tables for connectives


The binary connectives:

T
T
F
F

T
F
T
F

( )
T
F
F
F

( )
T
T
T
F

( )
T
F
T
T

( )
T
F
F
T

is as expected: ( ) is true if and only if both and are true.


The column for shows that it means one or the other or both.
This version is called inclusive or (as opposed to exclusive or).
The column for may not match your intuition.
Semantics

Connectives

29/241

If-then??
Some people find the meaning of rather unintuitive. You may
want to think of as meaning truth is preserved.
The meaning of T T is T because truth is preserved.
The meaning of T F is F because truth is not preserved.
The meaning of F T and F F are both T, because there is no

truth to preserve.
For example, the following sentence comes out true:
If everyone is a child, then the moon is made of green
cheese.
Some people prefer to call that sentence non-sensical, rather than
true. But propositional logic gives every formula a meaning.

Semantics

Connectives

30/241

Summary: value of a formula


Fix a truth valuation t. Every formula has a value under t,
denoted t , determined as follows.
1. pt = t(p).


2. ()t =

3. ( )t =
4. ( )t =

T
F


6. (

)t

The value of a formula


comes from the values of
its variables, combined as
given by its connectives.

T
F

if t = t = T
otherwise

T
F

if t = T or t = T
otherwise

T
F

if
= F or
otherwise

T
F

5. ( )t =

if t = F
if t = T

The valuation t is
necessary.
Without a valuation, a
formula has no value.

=T

if t = t
otherwise

Semantics

Formulas

31/241

Unique Readability of Formulas


We have defined the semantics (meaning) of a formula from its
syntax (the succession of symbols).
Is this well-defined? Or can a formula get two different meanings?

Theorem. Every well-formed formula has a unique derivation as a


well-formed formula. That is, each well-formed formula has exactly
one of the following forms:
(1) an atom, (2) (), (3) ( ), (4) ( ), (5) ( ) ,
or (6) ( )
In each case, it is of that form in exactly one way.
Another way of thinking about it is to ask the question: which
connective do the outer parentheses correspond to?

Semantics

Properties of formulas

32/241

(Why) Is the Theorem True?


As an example, consider (p q) r . It can be formed from the
two formulas (p q) and r using the connective .

If we tried to form it using , the two parts would need to be (p and


q) r. But neither of those is a formula!
How can we be sure the theorem holds for every formula?

Semantics

Properties of formulas

33/241

Mathematical Induction

To prove the theorem, we will use mathematical induction.


Before doing the proof, we will review mathematical induction.
This starts with the natural numbers.

Semantics

Properties of formulas

34/241

Natural Numbers
The natural numbers are the numbers we use to count things.
Before we start, we count zero; as we find things we count one, two,
etc.
The natural numbers form an unbounded sequence
0, 1, 2, 3, 4, . . .
Suppose P names a property. We write P(2) to mean 2 has
property P, or P holds for 2.
A statement every natural number has property P corresponds to
a sequence of statements
P(0), P(1), P(2), P(3), P(4), . . .

Semantics

Mathematical induction

35/241

Mathematical Induction
Principle of mathematical induction:
Suppose we establish two things: that
0 has property P, and that
whenever any number has property P, then the next
number also has property P.
Then we may conclude that every natural number has
property P.

Example: Show that

n
P
=0

n(n+1)
2

for every natural number n.

Let P be the property; that is, let P(n) be

n
P

=0

Semantics

Mathematical induction

n(n+1)
.
2

36/241

Proof for the example


Step 1 (basis step): The property P(0) is

0
P

=0

0(0+1)
2

The left side of the equation is just 0. Also the right side evaluates
to 0.
Thus 0 has property P.
Step 2 (inductive step): hypothesize that some number has
property P; in other words, that
some P
number
=0

some number (some number+1)


2

Semantics

Mathematical induction

37/241

Proof for the example


Step 1 (basis step): The property P(0) is

0
P

=0

0(0+1)
2

The left side of the equation is just 0. Also the right side evaluates
to 0.
Thus 0 has property P.
Step 2 (inductive step): hypothesize that some number has
property P; in other words, that
some P
number

=0

some number (some number+1)


2

For simplicity, we give a name to the some number. I choose k.


Thus the hypothesis becomes

k
P

=0
Semantics

k(k+1)
2

Mathematical induction

37/241

Step 2 (inductive step), continued:


We hypothesize that k has property P; that is,

k
X

k(k + 1)

=0

We need to demonstrate that k + 1 has property P; that is,


k+1
X
=0

(k + 1) ((k + 1) + 1)
2

(k + 1) (k + 2)
2

We calculate:
k+1
X

=0

=
=
=

k
X

+ (k + 1)
=0
k(k+1)
+ (k + 1)
2

k
+ 1 (k + 1)
2
(k+1)(k+2)
2

Semantics

definition of

hypothesis
"algebra"
DONE!
Mathematical induction

38/241

Step 2 (inductive step), continued:


We hypothesize that k has property P; that is,

k
X

k(k + 1)

=0

We need to demonstrate that k + 1 has property P; that is,


k+1
X
=0

(k + 1) ((k + 1) + 1)
2

(k + 1) (k + 2)
2

We calculate:
k+1
X

=0

=
=
=

k
X

+ (k + 1)
=0
k(k+1)
+ (k + 1)
2

k
+ 1 (k + 1)
2
(k+1)(k+2)
2

Semantics

definition of

hypothesis
"algebra"
DONE!
Mathematical induction

38/241

Observations/Techniques
To talk about something, give it a name.
E.g., property P, number k, etc.
A formula is a textual object. In this text, we can substitute one
symbol or expression for another. For example, we put k + 1 in
place of k.
The induction principle gives a template for a proof:
The proof has two parts: the basis and the inductive step.
In the inductive step, hypothesize P(k) and prove P(k + 1) from

it.
But the induction principle does not say how to actually do either
step. We must invent the method ourselves.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

39/241

Simple Induction vs. Strong Induction


Simple Induction

Strong Induction
or Course of Values
Basis
Show P(0)
Show P(0)
Ind. Hypothesis P(k) holds
P(m) holds, for every m k
Ind. Step
Show P(k + 1) holds
Show P(k + 1) holds
Conclusion
P(k) holds for every k P(k) holds for every k
Simple induction is sometimes called weak induction.

What is the difference?

Semantics

Mathematical induction

40/241

Simple Induction vs. Strong Induction


Simple Induction

Strong Induction
or Course of Values
Basis
Show P(0)
Show P(0)
Ind. Hypothesis P(k) holds
P(m) holds, for every m k
Ind. Step
Show P(k + 1) holds
Show P(k + 1) holds
Conclusion
P(k) holds for every k P(k) holds for every k
Simple induction is sometimes called weak induction.

What is the difference?


Define Q(k) as the property P(m) holds, for every m k.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

40/241

Simple Induction vs. Strong Induction


Simple Induction

Strong Induction
or Course of Values
Basis
Show P(0)
Show P(0)
Ind. Hypothesis P(k) holds
P(m) holds, for every m k
Ind. Step
Show P(k + 1) holds
Show P(k + 1) holds
Conclusion
P(k) holds for every k P(k) holds for every k
Simple induction is sometimes called weak induction.

What is the difference?


Define Q(k) as the property P(m) holds, for every m k.
Q(0) is equivalent to P(0).

Semantics

Mathematical induction

40/241

Simple Induction vs. Strong Induction


Simple Induction

Strong Induction
or Course of Values
Basis
Show Q(0)
Show P(0)
Ind. Hypothesis P(k) holds
P(m) holds, for every m k
Ind. Step
Show P(k + 1) holds
Show P(k + 1) holds
Conclusion
P(k) holds for every k P(k) holds for every k
Simple induction is sometimes called weak induction.

What is the difference?


Define Q(k) as the property P(m) holds, for every m k.
Q(0) is equivalent to P(0).
Q(k + 1) is equivalent to Q(k) and P(k + 1).
To prove Q(k + 1) from Q(k), need only to prove P(k + 1).

Semantics

Mathematical induction

40/241

Simple Induction vs. Strong Induction


Simple Induction

Strong Induction
or Course of Values
Basis
Show Q(0)
Show P(0)
Ind. Hypothesis Q(k) holds
P(m) holds, for every m k
Ind. Step
Show Q(k + 1) holds
Show P(k + 1) holds
Conclusion
P(k) holds for every k P(k) holds for every k
Simple induction is sometimes called weak induction.

What is the difference?


Define Q(k) as the property P(m) holds, for every m k.
Q(0) is equivalent to P(0).
Q(k + 1) is equivalent to Q(k) and P(k + 1).
To prove Q(k + 1) from Q(k), need only to prove P(k + 1).
Q(k) for every k is equivalent to P(k) for every k.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

40/241

Simple Induction vs. Strong Induction


Simple Induction

Strong Induction
or Course of Values
Basis
Show Q(0)
Show P(0)
Ind. Hypothesis Q(k) holds
P(m) holds, for every m k
Ind. Step
Show Q(k + 1) holds
Show P(k + 1) holds
Conclusion
Q(k) holds for every k P(k) holds for every k
Simple induction is sometimes called weak induction.

What is the difference? No difference!


Define Q(k) as the property P(m) holds, for every m k.
Q(0) is equivalent to P(0).
Q(k + 1) is equivalent to Q(k) and P(k + 1).
To prove Q(k + 1) from Q(k), need only to prove P(k + 1).
Q(k) for every k is equivalent to P(k) for every k.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

40/241

Structural Induction
Goal: prove that every formula has property P.
How to prove such a statement? Can we use induction?
A formula is not a natural number. . . .

Semantics

Mathematical induction

41/241

Structural Induction
Goal: prove that every formula has property P.
How to prove such a statement? Can we use induction?
A formula is not a natural number, but it suffices to prove any one of
the following.
For every natural number n, every formula with n or fewer
symbols has property P.
or
For every natural number n, every formula with n or fewer
connectives has property P.
or

Semantics

Mathematical induction

41/241

Structural Induction (2)


Goal: prove that every formula has property P.
or
For every natural number n, every formula whose parse tree
has height n or less has property P.
or
For every natural number n, every formula producible with n
or fewer uses of the formation rules has property P.
In each of these formulations, the induction step requires showing
that


If P() and P(), then P () and P ( ? ) .
Formulas and have smaller n values than () and ( ? ) do,
where ? represents an arbitrary binary connective.
Semantics

Mathematical induction

42/241

The principle of Structural Induction

Theorem. Let R be a property. Suppose that


1. for each atomic formula p, we have R(p); and

2. for each formula , if R() then R () ; and
3. for each pair of formulas and , and each binary connective ?,
if R() and R() then R ( ? ) .
Then R() for every formula .
Use of this principle is called structural induction.
Structural induction is a special case of mathematical induction.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

43/241

Example: Parentheses in Formulas


For example, to illustrate structural induction, we shall prove the
following.
Lemma. Every well-formed formula has an equal number of
left and right parentheses.
Proof. We use structural induction. The property to prove is
R(): has an equal number of left and right parentheses
for every formula .

Base case: is an atom.


has no parenthesesonly a propositional variable. Thus R()
holds.
This completes the proof of the base case.
Semantics

Mathematical induction

44/241

Example, contd the Inductive Step


Inductive step:
Hypothesis: formulas and both have property R.
To prove: each of the formulas (), ( ), ( ), ( ) ,
and ( ) has property R.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

45/241

Example, contd the Inductive Step


Inductive step:
Hypothesis: formulas and both have property R.
To prove: each of the formulas (), ( ), ( ), ( ) ,
and ( ) has property R.
W.l.o.g., we consider ( ).
Notation: For any formula , let op() denote the number
of ( in , and let c() denote the number of ) in .

We calculate op ( ) :

op ( ) = 1 + op() + op()

Semantics

inspection

Mathematical induction

45/241

Example, contd the Inductive Step


Inductive step:
Hypothesis: formulas and both have property R.
To prove: each of the formulas (), ( ), ( ), ( ) ,
and ( ) has property R.
W.l.o.g., we consider ( ).
Notation: For any formula , let op() denote the number
of ( in , and let c() denote the number of ) in .

We calculate op ( ) :

op ( ) = 1 + op() + op()

= 1 + c() + c()

Semantics

inspection
R() and R()

Mathematical induction

45/241

Example, contd the Inductive Step


Inductive step:
Hypothesis: formulas and both have property R.
To prove: each of the formulas (), ( ), ( ), ( ) ,
and ( ) has property R.
W.l.o.g., we consider ( ).
Notation: For any formula , let op() denote the number
of ( in , and let c() denote the number of ) in .

We calculate op ( ) :

op ( ) = 1 + op() + op()

= 1 + c() + c()

= c ( )

Semantics

inspection
R() and R()
inspection .

Mathematical induction

45/241

Back to the Unique Readability Theorem


Theorem. Every formula is exactly one of an atom, (),
( ), ( ), ( ) or ( ); and in each case it is of
that form in exactly one way.
We want to prove this using structural induction. How will it go?

Semantics

Mathematical induction

46/241

Back to the Unique Readability Theorem


Theorem. Every formula is exactly one of an atom, (),
( ), ( ), ( ) or ( ); and in each case it is of
that form in exactly one way.
We want to prove this using structural induction. How will it go?
The proof will consider formulas of the form ( ). One such is our
previous example ((p q) r), which has (p q) for and r for .

Semantics

Mathematical induction

46/241

Back to the Unique Readability Theorem


Theorem. Every formula is exactly one of an atom, (),
( ), ( ), ( ) or ( ); and in each case it is of
that form in exactly one way.
We want to prove this using structural induction. How will it go?
The proof will consider formulas of the form ( ). One such is our
previous example ((p q) r), which has (p q) for and r for .
Is this the only way to write the formula ((p q) r)?

Semantics

Mathematical induction

46/241

Back to the Unique Readability Theorem


Theorem. Every formula is exactly one of an atom, (),
( ), ( ), ( ) or ( ); and in each case it is of
that form in exactly one way.
We want to prove this using structural induction. How will it go?
The proof will consider formulas of the form ( ). One such is our
previous example ((p q) r), which has (p q) for and r for .
Is this the only way to write the formula ((p q) r)? What about
((p q) r) = ( 0 0 ) ,
where 0 is the expression ((p and 0 is the expression q)r)?

Semantics

Mathematical induction

46/241

Back to the Unique Readability Theorem


Theorem. Every formula is exactly one of an atom, (),
( ), ( ), ( ) or ( ); and in each case it is of
that form in exactly one way.
We want to prove this using structural induction. How will it go?
The proof will consider formulas of the form ( ). One such is our
previous example ((p q) r), which has (p q) for and r for .
Is this the only way to write the formula ((p q) r)? What about
((p q) r) = ( 0 0 ) ,
where 0 is the expression ((p and 0 is the expression q)r)?
Fortunately, neither 0 nor 0 is a formula. (Why?)

Semantics

Mathematical induction

46/241

Does It Always Work?


The theorem worked out for one example.
How can we make sure the inductive step works for every formula?
That is, if ( 0 0 ) is the same expression as ( ), how can we
argue that neither 0 nor 0 can be a formula?
Can 0 (or 0 ) have an equal number of left and right parentheses?
If not, why not?

Semantics

Mathematical induction

47/241

Does It Always Work?


The theorem worked out for one example.
How can we make sure the inductive step works for every formula?
That is, if ( 0 0 ) is the same expression as ( ), how can we
argue that neither 0 nor 0 can be a formula?
Can 0 (or 0 ) have an equal number of left and right parentheses?
If not, why not?

To do the proof, we actually need to know more about formulas.


This illustrates a common feature of inductive proofs: they often
prove more than just the statement given in the theorem.

Semantics

Mathematical induction

47/241

Proving Unique Readability


Property P(n):
Every formula containing at most n connectives satisfies
all three of the following.
A: The first symbol of is either ( or a variable.
B: has an equal number of ( and ), and
each proper prefix of has more ( than ).
C: has a unique construction as a formula.
(A proper prefix of is a non-empty expression such that is y
for some non-empty expression y.
E.g. if = ((p q) r)) then could be any of the following (, ((,
((p, ((p , ((p q, ((p q), ((p q) ,((p q) r,
((p q) r).
We prove property P for all n by induction.
Semantics

Mathematical induction

48/241

A Key Case of the Inductive Step


Inductive hypothesis: P(k) holds for some natural number k.
To show P(k + 1), let formula have k + 1 connectives.
A key case: is ( ? ). For property C, we must show that if is
(0 ?0 0 ) for formulas 0 and 0 , then = 0 , ? = ?0 and = 0 .
If 0 has the same length as , then they must be the same string
(both start at the second symbol of ).
Otherwise, either 0 is a proper prefix of or is a proper prefix
of 0 . But since and 0 are formulas with at most k
connectives, the inductive hypothesis applies to them.
In particular, each has property B, and thus neither can be a
proper prefix of the other.
Thus has a unique derivation, as required by property C.
Semantics

Mathematical induction

49/241

Commentary
The goal of the proof is property Cunique formation.
However, properties A and B are required in order to prove C.
There are actually two equally good options for a proof:
1. Prove A, B and C simultaneously, as a single compound
property.
(As done here.)
2. Prove them separately: first A, then B, and finally C.
(The text uses this method.)
Two fundamental techniques:
1. If a proof doesnt work, go back and fix it
as often as necessary.
2. Start from the end and work backwards.
Semantics

Mathematical induction

50/241

Two consequences of unique formation


We will define the semantics (meaning) of a formula from its syntax.
Thus unique formation ensures unambiguous formulas.
..............................................................................
Given a formula, determine its sub-formulas by counting
parentheses.
...

( rest of subformula )
{z
}
|
To determine m: count
excess of ( over )

m+1

m+ 2 ... n 1

subformula 2

When the count returns to zero, the subformula has ended.


(For efficient parsing of more-complicated formulas/programs, see CS 241.)
Semantics

Consequences of unique formation

51/241

Working with Formulas

Working with Formulas

52/241

Evaluating formulas
Recall that propositional logic is compositional. The value of two
subformulas, determines the value of their composition using a
propositional connective. Given a valuation t:
pt = t(p)

T
()t =
F

T
( )t =
F

if t = F
if t = T
if t = t = T
otherwise

( ) =
( )t =
( )t =

T
F

if t = T or t = T
otherwise

T
F

if t = F or t = T
otherwise

T
F

if t = t
otherwise

Using these rules, we can build a truth table considering all


combinations.
For a formula with n variables, the full truth table has 2n lines.
Working with Formulas

Evaluation of Formulas

53/241

Example: evaluating a formula


Example. Consider ((p q) (q r)).
It has the following truth table.
p
F
F
F
F
T
T
T
T

q
F
F
T
T
F
F
T
T

r
F
T
F
T
F
T
F
T

(p q)
F
F
T
T
T
T
T
T

(q r)
F
F
F
T
F
F
F
T

(p q) (q r)
T
T
F
T
F
F
F
T

Columns: List all the propositional variables on left and all the
subformulas (in increasing order of the number of connectives) on
the right.
Rows: Create a row for every possible combination of truth
valuations for the propositional variables.
Working with Formulas

Evaluation of Formulas

54/241

Exercises

Build the truth table for



i. q (p)

ii. (q) (p)



iii. p (q)) q (p)

Working with Formulas

Evaluation of Formulas

55/241

Tautology, Satisfaction, Contradiction


Classifying Formulas
A formula is a tautology if and only if for every truth
valuation t, t = T.
(p (p)) is a tautology.

A formula is a contradiction if and only if for every truth


valuation t, t = F.
(p (p)) is a contradiction.

A formula is satisfiable if and only if there is some truth


valuation t such that t = T.
(p q) is satisfiable. Set both variables to T.

Note: a formula is satisfiable if and only if it is not a contradiction.


Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

56/241

A Tautology Example
Example. Is ((((p q) r) (p q)) (p r)) a tautology?
One method: Fill out a truth table.
For larger formulas, with more variables, this approach can take a
long time.
Can we do better? Is there some other method?

Basic Idea For a formula like (p q) ((p) r) , if we set t(p) = T

then the formula simplifies to (T q) (F r) which in turn
simplifies to q.

Clearly this formula is not a tautology. When you set t(p) = T and
t(q) = F it has the value F.
Clearly this formula is not a contradicton. When you set t(p) = T and
t(q) = T it has the value T.

Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

57/241

Short-Cutting a Truth Table


Rather than fill out an entire truth table, we can observe what
happens if we set a variable to T (or F) in order to simplify the
formula.
Let A be a truth value; that is, A {F, T}. We can combine it with
other truth values as follows.
T
F

F
T

AT
AF
TA
FA
AA

A
F
A
F
A

AT
AF
TA
FA
AA

T
A
T
A
A

AT
AF
TA
FA
AA

T
A
A
T
T

We can use these rules to evaluate a formula, by using a valuation


tree. A valuation tree may sometimes be much smaller than the
corresponding truth table. Especially if one or two variables occur
frequently in a formula.
Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

58/241

Example: Valuation trees



Example. Show that (p q) r) (p q) (p r) is a
tautology.

Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

59/241

Example: Valuation trees



Example. Show that (p q) r) (p q) (p r) is a
tautology.

Case 1: In valuations with t(p) = T, we put T in for p:




(T q) r (T q) (T r) .

From the previous table, this becomes (q r) q r.

Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

59/241

Example: Valuation trees



Example. Show that (p q) r) (p q) (p r) is a
tautology.

Case 1: In valuations with t(p) = T, we put T in for p:




(T q) r (T q) (T r) .

From the previous table, this becomes (q r) q r.

If t(q) = T, this yields (r r) and then T. (Check!).


If t(q) = F, it yields (F r) and then T. (Check!).

Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

59/241

Example: Valuation trees



Example. Show that (p q) r) (p q) (p r) is a
tautology.

Case 1: In valuations with t(p) = T, we put T in for p:




(T q) r (T q) (T r) .

From the previous table, this becomes (q r) q r.

If t(q) = T, this yields (r r) and then T. (Check!).


If t(q) = F, it yields (F r) and then T. (Check!).
Case 2: In valuations with t(p) = F, we get

((F q) r) (F q) (F r) ,

Simplification yields (F r) T T and eventually T.

Thus every valuation makes the formula true, as required.


Working with Formulas

Semantic properties of formulas

59/241

Equivalence of Formulas
Suppose that a formula ( ) is a tautology.
Then and must have the same final column in their truth
tablesthey have the same value under any valuation.
E.g. if = (q (p)) and = (p q) we can see that their
corresponding columns are identical.
p
F
F
T
T

q
F
T
F
T

(q (p))
T
T
F
T

p
F
F
T
T

(p q)
T
T
F
T

q
F
T
F
T

In symbols: t = t , for every valuation t.


Such formulas are called equivalent formulas. We use the notation

to mean that and are equivalent.


Working with Formulas

Equivalence

60/241

Equivalent is Equivalent
Equivalent formulas are equivalent in any context.
Lemma. Suppose that . Then for any formula , and any
connective ?, the formulas ( ? ) and ( ? ) are equivalent:
( ? ) ( ? ) .
Proof idea: a value ( ? )t depends only on the values t and t ,
and the identity of ?.

Example: (p) p p. Check this with a truth table.

p
F
T

(p)
T
F

(p) p
F
T


Hence we get that (p p) q (p q).
Working with Formulas

Equivalence

61/241

Algebra of Formulas
Many equivalences of formulas look much like rules of ordinary
arithmetic.

Commutativity
( ) ( )
( ) ( )

Idempotence
( )
( )

Associativity

Double Negation
(())



( ) ( ) 
( ) ( )

Distributivity


( ) ( ) ( )
( ) ( ) ( )

Working with Formulas

Equivalence

De Morgans Laws
( ) ( )
( ) ( )

62/241

Algebra of Formulas, contd


Simplification I (Absorbtion)
( T)
( T) T
( F) F
( F)

Implication
( ) (() )

Simplification II

( )
( )

Equivalence

Contrapositive
( ) () ()

( ) ( ) ( )
Excluded Middle
( ()) T
Contradiction
( ) F

(T and F arent really formulas, but well pretend.)

Working with Formulas

Equivalence

63/241

Examples of Using Identities


Prove or disprove each of the following.

1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.


(p q) (q r)

(p r) (q s)

p (p q)

(p (r s))

((p q) p)
p
p

p ((q p) p)


q (p r)

(p q) (p s) (r q) (r s)
p (without using Simplification II)

(p r) (p s)
F

p (q p)

p (((q) (p)) p)
q

Note: Apply only one rule per line of your proof (but you may apply
the rule multiple times).
Working with Formulas

Equivalence

64/241

Application: Cards
We are given a deck of cards with a letter of the alphabet on one
side and a natural number on the other side.
Claim: For the four cards shown below, each card that has a vowel
on one side, has an even number on the other side.

Is the claim true?


How many cards must you turn over, in order to determine whether
or not the claim is true? Which ones?
Express the claim in propositon logic as a statement about four
cards and use the formulas on the previous slides to reduce it to a
statement about fewer cards.
Working with Formulas

Equivalence

65/241

Satisfiability of Sets of Formulas


Previously we talked about the notion that a single formula can be
satisfiable but satisfiability extends to sets of formulas.
Let denote a set of formulas and t a valuation. Define

T
if for each , t = T
t
=
F
otherwise
When t = T, we say that t satisfies .
A set is satisfiable iff there is some valuation t such that t = T.
Example: The set of formula = {, , } is satisfiable iff
( ) is satisfiable.
Example: The set {((p q) r), (p q s)} is satisfiable with the
valuation t(q) = T.

Working with Formulas

Entailment

66/241

Logical Consequence, a.k.a. Entailment


Let be a set of formulas, and let be a formula. We say that
is a logical consequence of , or
(semantically) entails , or
in symbols, |= ,

if and only if for any truth valuation t,


if t = T then also t = T.
We write 6|= for not |= . That is,
there exists a truth valuation t such that t = T and t = F.
Note that ( ) is a formula but |= is a statement about
formulas, specifically how a set of formulas is related to another
formula.

Working with Formulas

Entailment

67/241

Examples: Entailment
Example
{(p q), (q r)} |= (p r)

Working with Formulas

Entailment

68/241

Examples: Entailment
Example
{(p q), (q r)} |= (p r)

Example


((p (q)) r), (q (r)), (p r) 6|= (p (q r))

Working with Formulas

Entailment

68/241

Examples: Entailment
Example
{(p q), (q r)} |= (p r)

Example


((p (q)) r), (q (r)), (p r) 6|= (p (q r))

Example
|= means that is a tautology. Why?

Working with Formulas

Entailment

68/241

Examples: Entailment
Example
{(p q), (q r)} |= (p r)

Example


((p (q)) r), (q (r)), (p r) 6|= (p (q r))

Example
|= means that is a tautology. Why?

Example
{, ()} |= is always true, whatever and are. Why?

Working with Formulas

Entailment

68/241

Equivalence and Entailment

Equivalence can be expressed using the notion of entailment.


Lemma. if and only if both {} |= and {} |= .

Working with Formulas

Entailment

69/241

A Code Example
if ( (input > 0) OR NOT output ) {
if ( NOT (output AND (queuelength < 100) ) ) {
P1
} else if ( output AND NOT (queuelength < 100) ) {
P2
} else { P3 }
} else { P4 }

When does each piece of code get executed?

Let :
:
q:

input > 0,
output,
queuelength < 100.

Working with Formulas

Conditional Code

70/241

A Code Example, contd


if ( ) {
if (( q)) {
P1
}
else if ( q) {
P2
}
else {
P3
}
} else {
P4
}

P4

P4

Working with Formulas

Conditional Code

( q)

Action

71/241

A Code Example, contd


if ( ) {
if (( q)) {
P1
}
else if ( q) {
P2
}
else {
P3
}
} else {
P4
}

( q)

Action

P3

P1

P1

P1

P4

P4

P1

P1

Working with Formulas

Conditional Code

71/241

A Code Example, contd


if ( ) {
if (( q)) {
P1
}
else if ( q) {
P2
}
else {
P3
}
} else {
P4
}

( q)

Action

P3

P1

P1

P1

P4

P4

P1

P1

P2 is never executed.

Working with Formulas

Conditional Code

71/241

Finding Dead Code

Prove that P2 is dead code.


The conditions leading to P2 can never be true.
To execute P2 , the condition for the first if stmt is T, for the second
if stmt it is F, and for the else if stmt it is T.
( ) ( q) ( q)
( ) ( q) ( q)
( ) ( q) (q )
( ) (q q)
( ) F
F

Working with Formulas

Negation
Commutativity
Associativity
Contradiction
Simplification I

Conditional Code

72/241

Finding Live Code


Prove that P3 is live code.
The conditions leading to P3 can be true.
To execute P3 , the condition for the first if stmt is T, for the second
if stmt it is F, and for the else if stmt it is F.
P3 is executed when the formula
( ) ( q) ( q)
is true.
Find a satisfying truth valuation for this formula.
For example: t() = T, t() = T, t(q) = T.

Working with Formulas

Conditional Code

73/241

Simplifying Code
Consider these two fragments of code. Are they equivalent?
Fragment 2:

Fragment 1:

if ( q ) {
P3
}
else if ( ) {
P4
}
else {
P1
}

if ( ) {
if ( ( q) ) {
P1
}
else if ( q ) {
P2
}
else {
P3
}
}
else {
P4
}

Working with Formulas

Conditional Code

74/241

Simplifying Code

To prove that the two fragments are equivalent, show that each
block of code P1 , P2 , P3 , and P4 is executed under equivalent
conditions.

Block
P1
P2
P3
P4

Fragment 1
( ) ( q)
( ) ( q) ( q)
( ) ( q) ( q)
( )

Working with Formulas

Fragment 2
( q) ( )
F
( q)
( q) ( )

Conditional Code

75/241

Definability of Connectives
Formulas and are equivalent.
Thus is said to be definable in terms of and .
There are actually sixteen possible binary connectives. (Why?)
Two of these are essentially nullary (they ignore the input).
1. one is always T no matter what the input
2. the other is always F no matter what the input
Four others are essentially unary (they ignore one value but not the
other).
E.g. a connective (p ? q) = p ignores the first value and always

returns the second value.


This leaves ten additional binary connectives.

Working with Formulas

Alternative Sets of Connectives

76/241

Adequate Sets
A set of connectives is said to be adequate iff any n-ary (n 1)
connective can be defined in terms of the ones in the set.
Lemma. {, , } is an adequate set of connectives.
Proof: see the equivalence rules Implication and Equivalence.
Lemma. Each of the sets {, }, {, }, and {, } is adequate.
Proof: For the first two, use De Morgans laws. For the third, . . . ?
Theorem. The set {, } is not an adequate set of connectives.
Proof: For both and : the output is always F if both inputs are F;
the output is always T if both the inputs are T. So you cannot
implement .

Working with Formulas

Alternative Sets of Connectives

77/241

Some Questions about Adequate Sets


Question: Is there a binary connective such that the singleton
set {} is adequate?

Question: Are there binary connectives c1 , c2 and c3 such that


{c1 , c2 , c3 } is adequate, but none of {c1 , c2 }, {c1 , c3 }, or {c2 , c3 } is
adequate?
(Such a set is called a minimal adequate set.)

Question: Find all minimal adequate sets containing only binary,


unary and nullary connectives.

Working with Formulas

Alternative Sets of Connectives

78/241

Proofs in Propositional Logic:


Resolution

Proofs in Propositional Logic

79/241

What Is a Proof?
A proof is a formal demonstration that a statement is true.
It must be mechanically checkable. A reader need not apply any

intuition or insight to verify that it is correct.


In fact, a computer could verify its correctness.

A proof is generally syntactic, (i.e. format) rather than semantic (i.e.


meaning.
Syntactic rules permit mechanical checking.
The rules are chosen for semantic reasons, but their use

remains purely syntactic.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Notions of Proof

80/241

What Makes a Proof?


Generically, a proof consists of a list of formulas.
The premises, if any, are listed first.
Each subsequent formula must be a valid inference from

preceding formulas.
That is, there is an inference rule (defined by the proof system)
that justifies the formula, based on the previous ones.
The final formula is the conclusion.

The key here is the set of inference rules. A set of inference rules
defines a proof system.
We notate there is a proof with premises and conclusion by
`
which can be read as proves .
Proofs in Propositional Logic

Notions of Proof

81/241

Inference Rules
In general, an inference rule is written as
1

...

This notation means,


suppose that each of the formulas 1 , 2 , . . . , already
appears in the proof (either assumed or previously inferred).
Then one may infer the formula i.e. write it as the next
formula in the proof.

Examples of possible rules:


A kind of definition of .

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Notions of Proof

Rules need not be


equivalences.
82/241

Approaches to Proofs
Direct proofs:
To establish ` , give a proof with 1 , 2 , . . . , n as
assumptions, and obtain as the conclusion.
Refutations (a.k.a. indirect proofs, or proofs by contradiction):
To establish ` , take as an assumption, in addition to
1 , 2 , . . . , n . Obtain a definitive contradiction (denoted )
as a conclusion.
In other words, give a direct proof of {} ` .
Why does the refutation approach work?
If {} is a contradiction, then any valuation t that makes
true must make false and thus make true. Therefore, |= .

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Notions of Proof

83/241

Proofs and Entailment


Recall that
The following is a statement about truth valuations: |= iff for

any truth valuation t, if t = T then also t = T,

The following is a statement about proofs: ` iff there is a

proof with assumptions and conclusion .


We have outlined the following plan.
Goal: Show that |= .
Method: Show that ` (i.e., give a proof).
To justify this, we need to eventually show that
` implies |= .
More on this topic later (specifically slide 93). First let us consider a
proof system.
Proofs in Propositional Logic

Notions of Proof

84/241

The Resolution System and Rule


Resolution is a refutation system, with the following inference rule:
p p

for any variable p and formulas and .


We consider the following as special cases:
Contradiction:
(refutation is complete)

Unit resolution:
(eliminate p)

p p

A proof is complete when one derives a contradiction .


In this case, the original assumptions are refuted.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

85/241

Example of Using Resolution


Example: prove {p, q} `Res p q.
Our aim: derive a contradiction from {p, q, (p q)}.
As a preliminary step, re-write the third formula as (p q).
We start the actual proof with the three formulas.
1.

premise

2.

premise

3.

p q

negated goal

Now, we recall the inference rule: p p .

Consider lines 1 and 3. . . .

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

86/241

Example of Using Resolution, contd


The proof so far:
1.

premises

2.

premises

3.

p q

from negated goal

We have the formulas (1) p and (3) p q.


Apply unit resolution, yielding the formula q.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

87/241

Example of Using Resolution, contd

1.

premises

2.

premises

3.

p q

from negated goal

4.

1, 3

We have the formulas (1) p and (3) p q.


Apply unit resolution, yielding the formula q.
We have the formulas (2) q and (4) q.
Apply the contradiction rule, yielding .

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

87/241

Example of Using Resolution, contd

1.

premises

2.

premises

3.

p q

from negated goal

4.

1, 3

5.

2, 4

We have the formulas (1) p and (3) p q.


Apply unit resolution, yielding the formula q.
We have the formulas (2) q and (4) q.
Apply the contradiction rule, yielding .
Done!

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

87/241

Conjunctive Normal Form


The Resolution rule can only be used successfully on formulas of a
restricted form.
Conjunctive normal form (CNF):
A literal is a (propositional) variable or the negation of a variable.
A clause is a disjunction of literals.
A formula is in conjunctive normal form if it is a conjunction of

clauses.
In other words, a formula is in CNF if and only if
its only connectives are , and/or ,
applies only to variables, and
applies only to subformulas with no occurrence of .

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

88/241

Converting to CNF
1. Eliminate implication and equivalence.
Replace ( ) by ( )
Replace ( ) by ( ) ( ).
Now only , and appear as connectives.
2. Apply De Morgans and double-negation laws as often as
possible.
Replace ( ) by .
Replace ( ) by .
Replace by .
Now negation only occurs in literals.
3. Transform into a conjunction
of clauses usingdistributivity.

Replace ( ) by ( ) ( ) .
4. Simplify using idempotence, contradiction, excluded middle and
Simplification I & II.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

89/241

The Resolution Proof Procedure

To prove from , via a Resolution refutation:


1. Convert each formula in to CNF.
2. Convert to CNF.
3. Split the CNF formulas at the s, yielding a set of clauses.
4. From the resulting set of clauses, keep applying the resolution
inference rule until either:
The empty clause results.
In this case, ` is a theorem.
The rule can no longer be applied to give a new formula.

In this case, ` is not a theorem.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

90/241

Example: Resolution

To show: {(p q), (q r)} `Res (p r).


Convert each premises formula to CNF.
We get (p q) and (q r).
Convert the negation of the goal formula to CNF:
Replacing the yields (p r); then
De Morgans law yields (p r).
Split the which yields four clauses: (p q), (q r), p and r.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

91/241

Example, contd

Now we can make inferences, starting from our premises.


1.

p q

premise

2.

q r

premise

3.

from negated conclusion

4.

from negated conclusion

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

92/241

Example, contd

Now we can make inferences, starting from our premises.


1.

p q

premise

2.

q r

premise

3.

from negated conclusion

4.

from negated conclusion

5.

1, 3 (variable p)

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

92/241

Example, contd

Now we can make inferences, starting from our premises.


1.

p q

premise

2.

q r

premise

3.

from negated conclusion

4.

from negated conclusion

5.

1, 3 (variable p)

6.

2, 5 (variable q)

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

92/241

Example, contd

Now we can make inferences, starting from our premises.


1.

p q

premise

2.

q r

premise

3.

from negated conclusion

4.

from negated conclusion

5.

1, 3 (variable p)

6.

2, 5 (variable q)

7.

4, 6 (variable r)

Refutation complete!

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Resolution

92/241

Proofs and Entailment


Recall (from slide 84) that a proof is different from semantic
entailment.
The following is a statement about truth valuations: |= iff for

any truth valuation t, if t = T then also t = T,

The following is a statement about proofs: ` iff there is a

proof with assumptions and conclusion .


Resolution is a proof system but it is not entirely clear that `Res
has anything to do with |= .
We want to show
1. Soundness: `Res implies that |= , that is, if we prove
something using Resolution then it is true.
2. Completeness: |= implies that ` , that is, every
entailment has a proof.
Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

93/241

Resolution Is Sound
For resolution to be meaningful, we need the following.
Theorem. Suppose that {1 , . . . , n } `Res ; that is, there is a
resolution refutation with premises 1 , . . . , n and conclusion .
Then the set {1 , . . . , n } is unsatisfiable (contradictory).
That is, if {} `Res , then {} is a contradiction.
Therefore, |= .
In other words, the Resolution proof system is sound.
I.e. if we prove something, (with a method like resolution) then it is
true using a truth valuation.
We prove the theorem by induction on the length of the refutation.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

94/241

Soundness: The central argument


Note: we are skipping the base case.
Claim: Suppose that a set = {1 , . . . , k } is satisfiable. Let k+1 be
a formula obtained from by one use of the resolution inference
rule. Then the set {k+1 } is satisfiable.
Proof: Let truth valuation t satisfy ; that is, t = T for each .
Let k+1 be 1 2 , obtained by resolving = p 1 and
j = p 2 i.e. we took two previous formulas and applied
Resolutions inference rule.
But p is either T or F, i.e. more formally
Case I: t(p) = F. Since t = T, we must have t1 = T. Thus tk+1 = T.
Case II: t(p) = T. Since tj = T, we must have t2 = T. Thus tk+1 = T.
In either of the two possible cases, we have tk+1 = T, as claimed.
Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

95/241

The Claim Implies the Theorem


Using induction on n, the previous claim implies
Claim II: Suppose that the set = {1 , . . . , k } is satisfiable.
Let be a formula obtained from by n uses of the
resolution inference rule. Then the set {} is satisfiable.
(The previous claim is the inductive step of this one.)

Therefore, if a set of premises leads to after any number n of


resolution steps, the set must be unsatisfiablesince any set
containing is unsatisfiable.

Thus Resolution is a sound refutation system, as required.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

96/241

Can Resolution Fail?


In some cases, there may be no way to obtain , using any number
of resolution steps. What then?
Definition. A proof system S is complete if every entailment has a
proof; that is, if
|= implies `S .
Here the subscript S refers to a particular proof system. So far we
have seen Resolution, but there are other proof systems such as
Natural Deduction (ND).
Theorem. Resolution is a complete refutation system for CNF
formulas. That is, if there is no proof of from a set of premises
in CNF, then is satisfiable.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

97/241

Resolution Is Complete (Outline)


Claim. Suppose that a resolution proof reaches a dead endthat
is, no new clause can be obtained, and yet has not been derived.
Then the entire set of formulas (including the premises!) is
satisfiable.
Proof (outline): We use induction again. However, it is not an
induction on the length of the proof, nor on the number of formulas.
Instead, we use induction on the number of variables present in the
formulas.

Basis: only one variable occurs, say p.


After conversion to CNF and simplification, the only possible clauses
are p and p. If both occured, would be derivable. Thus at most
one does; we can satisfy it.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

98/241

Completeness Proof, part II


Inductive hypothesis: The claim holds for sets having at most k
variables.
Consider a set of clauses using k + 1 variables, from which no
additional clause can be derived via the resolution rule. Suppose
that it does not contain . Select any one variable, say p, and
separate the clauses into three sets:
Sp : the clauses that contain the literal p.
Sp : the clauses that contain the literal p.
R: the remaining clauses, which do not contain p at all.

The remainder set R has at most k variables.


Thus the hypothesis applies: it has a satisfying valuation .

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

99/241

Completeness Proof, part III


We have a truth valuation t, on the variables other than p, that
satisfies set R, the clauses that do not contain p. We now must
satisfy the sets Sp and Sp .
Case I: Every clause in Sp , of the form p , has t = T.
In this case, the set Sp is already satisfied. Define t(p) = F,
which additionally makes every clause in Sp true.
Case II: Sp has some clause p with t = F.
In this case, set t(p) = T; this satisfies every formula in Sp .
What about a clause p in Sp ?
Consider the formula , obtained by resolution from
p and p . It must lie in R; thus t = T. Thus also
(p )t = T, as required.
Thus the full set of clauses Sp Sp R is satisfiable.
By induction, every set that cannot produce is satisfiable.
Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

100/241

Resolution Provides an Algorithm

The resolution method yields an algorithm to determine whether a


given formula, or set of formulas, is satisfiable or contradictory.
Convert to CNF. A well-specified series of steps.
Form resolvents (the result of applying resolutions inference

rule) until either is derived, or no more derivations are


possible.
If is derived, the original formula/set is contradictory. Otherwise,
the preceding proof describes how to find a satisfying valuation.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

101/241

The Algorithm Can Be Very Slow


The algorithm can be souped up in many ways.
Choosing a good order of doing resolution steps. (It matters!)
Sophisticated data structures, to handle large numbers of

clauses.
Additional techniques: setting variables, learning, etc.

However, it still has limitations.


Theorem (Haken, 1985): There is a number c > 1 such that
For every n, there is an unsatisfiable formula on n variables
(and about n1.5 total literals) whose smallest resolution
refutation contains more than cn steps.
Resolution is an exponential-time algorithm!
(And you thought quadratic was bad. . . .)

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

102/241

Resolution in Practice: Satisfiability (SAT)


solvers

Determining the satisfiability of a set of propositional formulas is a


fundamental problem in computer science.
Examples:
software and hardware verification
automatic test pattern generation
planning
scheduling

. . . many problems of practical importance can be formulated as


determining the satisfiability of a set of formulas.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

103/241

Resolution in practice: SAT Solvers


Modern SAT solvers can often solve hard real-world instances with
over a million propositional variables and several million clauses.

Annual SAT competitions:


http://www.satcompetition.org/
Many are open source systems.

Best SAT solvers are based on backtracking search.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

104/241

Satisfiability in Theory
If a formula is satisfiable, then there is a short demonstration of that:
simply give the valuation. Anyone can easily check that it is correct.
The class of problems with this property is known as NP.
The class of problems for which one can find a solution efficiently is
known as P.
(For a precise definition, we need to define efficiently. We wont,
here.)

A Fundamental Question: Is P = NP?

A partial answer: If SAT is in P (by any algorithm), then P = NP.

Proofs in Propositional Logic

Soundness and Completeness of Resolution

105/241

Proofs in Propositional Logic:


Natural Deduction

Natural Deduction

106/241

Why Another Proof System?


The Resolution system is both sound and complete. Why do we
need another proof system?
Resolutions Limitations
Resolution proofs are fine for computers, but people normally

reason quite differently. To model what people do, we must take


another approach.
Resolution is closely tied to propositional logic. Extending it to
other forms of logic requires significant additional techniques.
Thus we will consider a system called Natural Deduction (ND).
It closely follows how people (mathematicians, at least)

normally make formal arguments.


It extends easily to more-powerful forms of logic.

Natural Deduction

Introduction

107/241

Overview of Natural Deduction


As in Resolution, a proof in Natural Deduction consists of a collection
of formulas, in some order, each with a justification.
It has some contrasts, however.
It does a direct proof, rather than a refutation.
Assumptions (formulas without a justification) play a crucial role.
Using an assumption creates a sub-proof.

Formulas inside a sub-proof may not be used outside it.


An inference rule may refer to a completed sub-proof.
We use the same notation as before for existence of a proof. If there
is a proof of a formula from a set of assumptions, we write
`ND

or simply

Natural Deduction

Introduction

` .

108/241

The Basic Rules of Natural Deduction


The simplest rule is, if you have a formula in the proof already, you
may write it down again. This is called reflexivity.
We will write NDs rules in the following format:
Name
Reflexivity,
or Premise

`-notation

inference notation

{} `

The notation on the right is as we had before (on slide 82): if we


have the formula above the line available, we may write the formula
below the line in the proof.
The version in the center reminds us of the role of assumptions in
Natural Deduction. Other rules will make more use of it.

Natural Deduction

Basic Rules

109/241

A First Example
Recall the format of a proof from slides 80-82. For Natural Deduction
each line is identified with a line number,
followed by the formula,
followed by the justification.

Here is a proof of p, q ` p.
1. p

Premise

2. q

Premise

3. p

Reflexivity: 1

Alternatively, we could simply write


1. p

Premise

and be done.
Note: extra formulas never hurt anything.
Natural Deduction

Basic Rules

110/241

Rules for Conjunction: i


Each connective symbol has an introduction rule to conclude
formulas that contain it, and an elimination rule to conclude a
formula that removes it from an earlier formula.
We start with the -introduction rule.
Name
-introduction
(i)

`-notation
If ` and ` ,
then `

inference notation

Rule i means
If each of the formulas and already appear in the proof,
then we may write the formula as the next formula of
the proof.

Natural Deduction

Conjunction Rules

111/241

Rules for Conjunction: e

The -elimination rule basically undoes the -introduction rule.


Name
-elimination
(e)

`-notation
If ` ,
then ` and `

inference notation

Rule e means
If the formula already appears in the proof, then we
may write either or as the next formula of the proof.

Natural Deduction

Conjunction Rules

112/241

Example: Conjunction Rules


Example.
Show that p q ` q p.
1. p q

Premise

2. q

e: 1

3. p

e: 1

4. q p

i: 2, 3

Explanation
The second line of the proof is saying that the formula q was

obtained by applying the e rule to the formula that appears on


line 1 of the proof.
The same line/formula (e.g. line 1) can be referenced multiple

times (e.g. in lines 2 and 3).


Natural Deduction

Conjunction Rules

113/241

Example: Conjunction Rules (2)

Example. Show that p q, r ` q r.


1. p q

Premise

2. r

Premise

3. q

e: 1

4. q r

i: 3, 2

Explanation
The premise (or premises) are listed first.
The final formula is the conclusion.

Natural Deduction

Conjunction Rules

114/241

Rules for Implication: e


The -elimination rule requires two formulas earlier in the proof.
Name
-elimination
(e)

`-notation
If ` and ` ,
then `

inference notation

In words:
If each of the formulas and already appear in the
proof, then you may conclude .

This rule is sometimes referred to its Latin name, modus ponens.


(Rumours that modus ponens is the Latin equivalent of Duh! are untrue, however well justified.)

Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

115/241

Rules for Implication: i


The -introduction rule is our first to employ a sub-proof.
Name

`-notation

-introduction
(i)

If {} ` ,
then `

inference notation

..
..

The rule uses the formula as a hypothesis or assumption. The


assumption functions as a premise in the sub-proof, but it is not a
premise of the main proof.
The box around the sub-proof of {} ` reminds us that
nothing inside the sub-proof may come out (analogous to local
variables in a functions scope).
Outside of the sub-proof, we may use only the whole sub-proof, in a
rule (like -introduction) that specifies a sub-proof.
Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

116/241

Sub-Proof Rules
To use rule i, we must have a completed sub-proof.
Assumption Rule
A sub-proof may be opened at any point.
Its first line, labelled assumption, may be any formula.

Sub-proof Closure Rules


The most-recently opened sub-proof may be closed at any time.
No formula inside a closed sub-proof may be referenced outside

the closed sub-proof.


Once it is closed, only the entire sub-proof may be used.
Every sub-proof must be closed before the last line of the proof.

Because of the very specific format of the sub-proof (e.g. the


assumption at the beginning and the conclusion at the end for
the -introduction rule) you may have to use the reflexivity rule.
Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

117/241

Example: Rule i and sub-proofs


Example. Give a proof of

p q, q r ` p r.

To start, we write down the premises at the beginning, and the


conclusion at the end.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

qr

Premise

pr

What next?

???

Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

118/241

Example: Rule i and sub-proofs


Example. Give a proof of

p q, q r ` p r.

To start, we write down the premises at the beginning, and the


conclusion at the end.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

qr

Premise

3.

Assumption

What next?
The goal p r contains .
Lets try rule i. . .

4.
5.
6.

pr

i: ??

Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

118/241

Example: Rule i and sub-proofs


Example. Give a proof of

p q, q r ` p r.

To start, we write down the premises at the beginning, and the


conclusion at the end.
What next?

1.

pq

Premise

2.

qr

Premise

3.

Assumption

The goal p r contains .


Lets try rule i. . .

4.

5.

e: 2, 4

Inside the sub-proof, we can


use rule e.

6.

pr

i: ??

Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

118/241

Example: Rule i and sub-proofs


Example. Give a proof of

p q, q r ` p r.

To start, we write down the premises at the beginning, and the


conclusion at the end.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

qr

Premise

3.

Assumption

4.

e: 1, 3

5.

e: 2, 4

6.

pr

What next?
The goal p r contains .
Lets try rule i. . .
Inside the sub-proof, we can
use rule e.

i: 35
Done!

Note the use of the range 3-5 on line 6 to specify the beginning and
the end of the sub-proof.
In order to conclude p r on line 5 the box must begin with p (line
3) and end with r (line5).
Natural Deduction

Implication Rules

118/241

Rules of Disjunction: i and e


The -introducton rule is much like the -introduction rule;
however, the -elimination rule is more complicated.
Name
-introduction
(i)
-elimination
(e)

`-notation
If ` ,
then `
and `
If , 1 `
and , 2 ` ,
then
, 1 2 `

inference notation

1
..
..

1 2

2
..
..

For the -elimination rule, if you have 1 2 and you can show
both that 1 implies and that 2 implies , then you can conclude
.
Rule e is also known as proof by cases.
Natural Deduction

Disjunction Rules

119/241

Example: -Introduction and -Elimination


Example: Show that p q ` (p q) (q p).
1.

pq

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

Assumption

4.

Reflexivity: 2

5.

qp

i: 34

6.

(p q) (q p)

i: 5

7.

Assumption

8.

Assumption

9.

Reflexivity: 7

10.

pq

i: 89

11.

(p q) (q p)

i: 10

12.

(p q) (q p)

e: 1, 26, 711

Natural Deduction

Disjunction Rules

120/241

Example: -Introduction and -Elimination


The overall format of the proof on the previous slides is an
-elimination.
The premise, p q, is stated on line 1.
The sub-proof for p implies (p q) (q p) runs from line 2 to 6.
The sub-proof for q implies (p q) (q p) runs from line 7 to 11.
Line 4 uses an assumption outside and prior to the box around lines
3 to 4.
Since line 3 is the beginning of a sub-proof, any formula can be the
assumption.
Since the first line in the box (line 3) is p and the last line in the box
(line 4) is q, the conclusion for this sub-proof is p q.
A very similar sub-proof happens in lines 7 to 11, except here the
assumption is q.
All the rules on slide 117 are followed.
Natural Deduction

Disjunction Rules

121/241

Negation
We shall treat negation by considering contradictions, such as
( ()).
The notation , sometimes called bottom or contradiction will be
used to represent any contradiction.
It may appear in proofs as if it were a formula.
The -elimination rule (a.k.a the -introduction rule).
Name
-introduction, or
-elimination (e)

`-notation
, , `

inference notation

The -elimination rule means


The formulas and cannot both be trueto have each
as a line in a proof means there is a contradiction.
Natural Deduction

Negation

122/241

Negation Introduction (i)

The -introduction rule also uses a sub-proof.


Name

`-notation

-introduction
(i)

If , ` ,
then `

inference notation

..
..

In words:
If the assumption of a sub-proof, , leads to a contradiction,
then derive .

Natural Deduction

Negation

123/241

Example: Negation
Example. Show that ` .

Natural Deduction

Negation

124/241

Example: Negation
Example. Show that ` .

1.

Natural Deduction

Premise

??

Negation

124/241

Example: Negation
Example. Show that ` .

1.

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.
4.

5.

Natural Deduction

??
i: 2?

Negation

124/241

Example: Negation
Example. Show that ` .

1.

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

e: 1, 2

4.

5.

Natural Deduction

??
i: 2?

Negation

124/241

Example: Negation
Example. Show that ` .

1.

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

e: 1, 2

4.

e: 2, 3

5.

i: 24

An assumption is made on the first line of the sub-proof (line 2).


A contradiction is reached at the end of the sub-proof (line 4).
So the negation of the assumption is derived on line 5.

Natural Deduction

Negation

124/241

Double-Negtion Elimination

The -elimination rule deals with a pair of negation symbols.


Name
-elimination
(e)

`notation
If ` ,
then `

inference notation

In words:
Two adjacent negation connectives can cancel each other
out.

Natural Deduction

Negation

125/241

Contradiction Elimination
The -elimination rule specifies what can be derived if there is a
contradiction.
Contradiction Elimination:
Name

`-notation

-elimination
(e)

If ` ,
then `

inference notation

In words:
Any formula, can be derived from a contradiction.

Natural Deduction

Negation

126/241

A Redundant Rule
Although the -elimination is quite useful is not actually needed.
Since it can be derived from other rules it is called a derived rule.
Suppose a proof has

We can replace line 28 by

27.

some rule

28.

e: 27.

27.

some rule

28.

Assumption

29.

Reflexivity: 27

30.

i: 2829

31.

e: 30.

Line 28 in the first proof can be replaced by lines 28 to 31 in the


second proof.
Thus any proof that uses e can be modified into a proof that does
not use it.
Natural Deduction

Negation

127/241

Example: Modus tollens


The principle of modus tollens: p q, q ` p.

Natural Deduction

Negation

128/241

Example: Modus tollens


The principle of modus tollens: p q, q ` p.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

Premise

??


MT

Natural Deduction

Negation

128/241

Example: Modus tollens


The principle of modus tollens: p q, q ` p.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

Premise

3.

Assumption

5.

??

6.

i: ??

4.


MT

Natural Deduction

Negation

128/241

Example: Modus tollens


The principle of modus tollens: p q, q ` p.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

Premise

3.

Assumption

4.

e: 3, 1

5.

??

6.

i: ??


MT

Natural Deduction

Negation

128/241

Example: Modus tollens


The principle of modus tollens: p q, q ` p.
1.

pq

Premise

2.

Premise

3.

Assumption

4.

e: 3, 1

5.

e: 2, 4

6.

i: 35

Modus tollens is sometimes taken as a derived rule:



MT

Natural Deduction

Negation

128/241

Derived Rules
Whenever we have a proof of the form ` , we can consider it as a
derived rule:

If we use this in a proof, it can be replaced by the original proof of


` .
The result is a proof using only the basic rules.
On the previous slide, with the set of rules = {e, e, i} we
derived the modus tollens rule.
Using derived rules does not expand the formulas that can be
proved. But they can make it easier to find and present a proof.

Natural Deduction

Negation

129/241

Some Useful Heuristics


Ideas to construct a proof:
1. Start with the premises at the top and the conclusion at the
bottom.
2. If you can apply an elimination rule to premises, do so.
(In the case of -elimination, open two sub-proofs.)
3. Next, work backwards from the end. If your target formula has a
connective, try its introduction rule.
This will yield a new target. Repeat steps 2 and 3 with the new
target, until you reach premises and/or available assumptions.
4. Treat a subproof as if it were a full proof (with a new premise).
Sometimes these ideas will lead you to a proof; sometimes they will
not.
If not, try something else instead of an introduction rule (idea 3).
Sometime nothing works. Take a break, and perhaps try again later.
Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

130/241

Further Examples of Natural Deduction


Example. Show that p q ` (r p) (r q).
Write down premises and conclusion (step 1).
No elimination applies (step 2). Thus try i (step 3).
1.

pq

Premise

(r p) (r q)

??

Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

131/241

Further Examples of Natural Deduction


Example. Show that p q ` (r p) (r q).
In the sub-proof, try -elimination on the assumption
(step 2).
1.

pq

Premise

2.

rp

Assumption

rq

??

(r p) (r q)

??

9.

Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

131/241

Further Examples of Natural Deduction


Example. Show that p q ` (r p) (r q).
No elimination applies from the assumptions (step 2).
What about -introduction for the conclusion (step 3)?
1.

pq

Premise

2.

rp

Assumption

3.

Assumption

4.

rq

??

5.

Assumption

7.

rq

??

8.

rq

e: ??

9.

(r p) (r q)

i: 28

6.

Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

131/241

Further Examples of Natural Deduction


Example. Show that p q ` (r p) (r q).
It works!

1.

pq

Premise

2.

rp

Assumption

3.

Assumption

4.

rq

i: 3

5.

Assumption

6.

e: 5, 1

7.

rq

i: 6

8.

rq

e: 2, 34, 57

9.

(r p) (r q)

i: 28

Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

131/241

Lifes Not Always So Easy. . .

Example. Show that


` (p q) p p.

1.


(p q) p p

Natural Deduction

Try i. . .

Additional Examples and Techniques

132/241

Lifes Not Always So Easy. . .

Example. Show that


` (p q) p p.

1.

(p q) p

5.

6.


(p q) p p

Natural Deduction

Assumption

Try i. . .

Additional Examples and Techniques

132/241

Lifes Not Always So Easy. . .

Example. Show that


1.


` (p q) p p.

(p q) p

Assumption
No elimination applies.

2.
3.
4.

?????

5.

6.

No connective.

(p q) p p


Natural Deduction

Try i. . .

Additional Examples and Techniques

132/241

Lifes Not Always So Easy. . .

Example. Show that


1.


` (p q) p p.

(p q) p

Assumption
No elimination applies.

2.
3.
4.

?????

5.

6.

No connective.

(p q) p p


Try i. . .

Time to try something ingenious. . . .

Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

132/241

Some Common Derived Rules


Proof by contradiction (reductio ad absurdum):
if , `, then ` .
The Law of Excluded Middle (tertiam non datur):
`
Double-Negation Introduction:
if ` then `

You can try to prove these yourself, as exercises.


Hint: in the first two, the last step uses rule e: ` .
Or see pages 2426 of Huth and Ryan.
Natural Deduction

Additional Examples and Techniques

133/241

Soundness and
Completeness
of Natural Deduction

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

134/241

Soundness and Completeness of Natural


Deduction
As with Resolution, we want Natural Deduction to be both sound and
complete.
Soundness of Natural Deduction means that the conclusion
of a proof is always a logical consequence of the premises.
That is,
if `ND , then |= .
Completeness of Natural Deduction means that all logical
consequences in propositional logic are provable in Natural
Deduction. That is,
if |= , then `ND .

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

135/241

Proof of Soundness
To prove soundness, we use induction on the length of the proof:
For all deductions ` which have a proof of length n or
less, it is the case that |= .
That property, however, is not quite good enough to carry out the
induction, because of the issue of open sub-proofs.
We actually use the following property of a natural number n.
Suppose that a formula appears at line n of a partial
deduction, which may have one or more open sub-proofs.
Let be the set of premises used and be the set of
assumptions of open sub-proofs. Then |= .

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

136/241

Basis of the Induction


Base case. The shortest deductions have length 1, and thus are
either

1.

Premise.

or
1.

Assumption.

We have either (in the first case), or (in the second case).
Thus |= , as required.

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

137/241

Proof of Soundness: Inductive Step


Inductive step. Hypothesis: the property holds for each n < k; that
is,
If some formula appears at line k or earlier of some partial
deduction, with premises and un-closed assumptions ,
then |= .
To prove: if 0 appears at line k + 1, then 0 |= 0
(where 0 = 0 when 0 is an assumption, and 0 = otherwise).

Formula 0 must have a justification by some rule. We shall consider


each possible rule.

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

138/241

Inductive Step, Case I


Case I: 0 was justified by i.
We must have 0 = 1 2 , where each of 1 and 2
appear earlier in the proof, at steps m1 and m2 ,
respectively. Also, any sub-proof open at step m1 or m2 is
still open at step k + 1.
Thus the induction hypothesis applies to both; that is,
|= 1 and |= 2 .
By the definition of |=, this yields |= 0 , as required.
I.e. a valuation that makes true is also making 1
evaluate to T and 2 evaluate to T, so it is making the
formula 1 2 evaluate to T.

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

139/241

Inductive Step, Case II

Case II: 0 was justified by i.


We must have 0 = 1 2 and there is a closed sub-proof
with assumption 1 and conclusion 2 , ending by step k.
Also, any sub-proof open before the assumption of 1 is still
open at step k + 1.
The induction hypothesis thus implies ( 1 ) |= 2 .
Hence |= 1 2 , as required.

Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

140/241

Inductive Step, Cases III ff.


Case III: 0 was justified by e.
This is not the case when a contradiction occurs inside a
sub-proof and so we negate the assumption.
We must have 0 be the pseudo-formula , and that the
proof contain formulas and for some , each using at
most k steps.
By the induction hypothesis, both |= and |= .
Thus is contradictory, and |= 0 for any 0 .
Cases IVXIII:
The other cases follow by similar reasoning.
This completes the inductive step, and the proof of soundness.
Natural Deduction

Soundness and Completeness

141/241

Completeness of Natural Deduction


We now turn to completeness.
Formally, completeness means the following.
Let be a set of formulas and be a formula.
If |= , then ` .
That is, every consequence has a proof.

How can we prove this?

Natural Deduction

Proof of Completeness

142/241

Proof of Completeness: Getting started

Suppose that |= , where = {1 , 2 , . . . , m }.


Thus the formula (1 2 . . . m ) is a tautology.
Lemma. Every tautology is provable in Natural Deduction.
Once we prove the Lemma, the result follows. Given a proof of
(1 2 . . . m ) , one can use i and e to complete a
proof of ` .

Natural Deduction

Proof of Completeness

143/241

Tautologies Have Proofs


For a tautology, every line of its truth table ends with T.
We can mimic the construction of a truth table using inferences in
Natural Deduction.
Claim. Let have k variables p1 , . . . , pk . Let be a
valuation, and define 1 , 2 , . . . , k as

p
if (p ) = T
=
p if (p ) = F.
If = T, then {1 , . . . k } ` , and
if = F, then {1 , . . . k } ` .
To prove the claim, use structural induction on formulas
(which is induction on the column number of the truth table).
Once the claim is proven, we can prove a tautology as follows. . . .
Natural Deduction

Proof of Completeness

144/241

Outline of the Proof of a Tautology


1.

p1 p1

L.E.M.

2.

p2 p2

L.E.M.

..
.
k.
k + 1.

m + 1. p1

pk pk

L.E.M.

p1

assumption

p2

assumption

..
.

n.

..
.

assumption

e: 1, (k + 1)m,
(m + 1)n

p2

assumption

..
.

m.

e: 2, . . .

Natural Deduction

Once each variable is


assumed true or false, the
previous claim provides a
proof.

Proof of Completeness

145/241

Proving the Claim


Hypothesis: the following hold for formulas and :
If {1 , . . . , k } |= , then {1 , . . . , k } ` ;
If {1 , . . . , k } 6|= , then {1 , . . . , k } ` ;
If {1 , . . . , k } |= , then {1 , . . . , k } ` ; and
If {1 , . . . , k } 6|= , then {1 , . . . , k } ` .
If {1 , . . . , k } |= , put the two proofs of and together, and
then infer , by i.
If {1 , . . . , k } 6|= (and thus {1 , . . . , k } |= and
{1 , . . . , k } 6|= ),
Prove and .
Assume ; from it, conclude (e) and then (e).
From the sub-proof, conclude ( ), by i.

The other cases are similar.


Natural Deduction

Proof of Completeness

146/241

First-Order Predicate Logic

First-Order Logic

147/241

What Propositional Logic Cannot Express


Recall: Propositional logic deals with logical forms of compound
propositions. It works well with relationships like not, and, or,
if/then.
A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or

false.
A compound proposition was made up of
propositional variables, e.g. p, q, r
connectives, e.g. , , ,
punctuation, e.g. (, )

We would like to have a way to talk about


individuals (also called objects) and
some object and all objects, without enumerating all objects in a

set.
This requires extensions to Propositional Logic.
First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

148/241

Some Example Statements


Some example statements:
Not all birds can fly.
Every student is younger than some instructor.
These statements refer to things: birds, students, instructors. They
also refer to properties of things, either as individuals (ability to fly)
or in combination (relative age).
We would like to make such statements in our logic and to combine
them with the connectives of propositional logic.

Statements like those above require a context or world to be


meaningful.

First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

149/241

Informal Introduction to Predicate Logic


We shall briefly discuss some contexts for predicate logic.
Arithmetic (the inspiration for formal predicate logic).
The blocks world (a classical AI example).
Graphs (a ubiquitous concept in CS).
Databases (the applied CS version of predicate logic).

In each, we shall see the following ingredients.


Domains: the set of objects; also called the universe.
Constants: objects with specific names.
Relations: properties of objects, alone or in combination.
Functions: association of objects to others.

First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

150/241

Arithmetic, Etc.
In arithmetic, we have several possible domains, e.g.
N: The natural numbers
Z: The integers
Q: The rationals
Integers modulo n

Over these, we have predicates (or relations):


<: Less than
Has a square root
...

Recall, from English grammar, that a declarative sentence has a


subject and a predicate (which states something about the subject).
We also have functions such as: +, , , .

A sample formula: y(y < ) .
First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

151/241

A Classic AI Example: Blocks Worlds


A blocks world consists of a set of blocks, and a table.
Each block may be on the table, or on one of the other blocks.
Each block may have a colour.

In the picture, there are three blocks.


B1

Two of them are blue (vertical stripes) and


one is red (diagonal stripes).

1111111111
0000000000
000000000
111111111
0000000000
1111111111
000000000
111111111
0000000000
1111111111
B3
000000000
111111111
0000000000
1111111111
000000000
111111111
0000000000
1111111111
000000000
111111111
0000000000
1111111111

11111
00000
00000
11111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111
00000
11111
0000
1111

B2

11111111
00000000
00000000
11111111
00000000
11111111
00000000
11111111

The domain (i.e. the set of objects) is {B1, B2, B3}.


We can describe this world with relations:
On, OnTable, Red, Blue, . . . .

First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

152/241

Describing a Blocks World

The domain {B1, B2, B3} is a finite set.


Therefore, we can list all of the properties, in various ways:
OnTable(B1), OnTable(B2), OnTable(B3).
On:

B1 B2 B3
B1
F
F
F
B2
F
F
F
B3
T
F
F


The set b | Be(b) of blue boxes is {B2, B3}.

First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

153/241

Properties in the Blocks World


Some properties are fundamental to the world.
No block is on itself"


(On(, )) .

A block on the table is not on any block:




 
OnTable() ( y On(, y) )
.
Some properties depend on the situation.
Every
red block has a block
on it:


Red() y On(y, ) .
Some block is on a block that is on the table:


y On(, y) OnTable(y)
.
First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

154/241

Graphs
A graph is a binary relation.
A finite graph:

An infinite graph:
y
4
3
2

1 2 3 4 5



(The set , y | y = 1 + / 2 ).

A graph is undirected if the relation is symmetric; i.e., the formula



y E(, y) E(y, )
holds, i.e. for every vertex and y if there is an edge from to y
then there is an edge from y to .
First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

155/241

Relational Databases
A relational database is a listing of one or more relations.
Example:
Person: The people (or their names).
NumberOf : An association between people and their phone

numbers, NumberOf (, y) means the phone number of person


is y.

Here the domain contains both people and phone numbers the
objects about which we have relations.
A sample statement: There exists a person who does not have a
phone number.


Person() ( y(NumberOf (, y) ) .

First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

156/241

A Conundrum
Consider the statement, Only people have phone numbers.
How shall we represent it as a logical formula?
Whenever and y satisfy NumberOf (, y), then is a person.


y NumberOf (, y) Person()
.
Whenever has some phone number y, then is a person.


y NumberOf (, y) Person() .
Using equivalences for and for ( z ), they are equivalent
respectively to


y (NumberOf (, y)) Person()
and to



( y NumberOf (, y) ) Person() .
First-Order Logic

Introduction and Motivation

157/241

Domains

We now turn to general definitions.

A domain is a non-empty set. In principle, any non-empty set can be


a domain: e.g. the natural numbers, people now alive, {T, F}, etc.
A constant symbol refers to an object in the domain; e.g., 1, Justin
Trudeau, block B1, etc.

First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

158/241

Predicates/Relations
A predicate, or relation, represents a property that an individual, or
collection of individuals, may (or may not) have. In English, we
might express a predicate as

is a student.

In symbolic logic, we write S() to mean has property S.


Examples
If S is the property of being a student then Alex is a student

becomes S(Alex).
If is the property of being an instructor then Sam is an

instructor becomes (Sam).


Similarly we could use Y(Alex,Sam) to mean Alex is younger

than Sam.
First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

159/241

Representing Relations
Mathematically, we represent a relation by the set of all things that
have the property.
E.g. if S is the set of all students, then S means is a student.
The only restriction on a relation is that it must be a subset of the
domain.
A k-ary relation is a set of k-tuples of domain elements. For
example, the binary relation less-than, over a domain D, is
represented by the set


, y D 2 | < y .
E.g., the On relation in the sample blocks world has just one pair:
{B3, B1}.
In a relational database, the listing of such a set is called a table.

First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

160/241

Variables
Variables make statements more expressive.
You may think of a variable as a place holder or blank, that can be
replaced by a concrete object.
Alternatively, a variable is a name without a fixed referent (the
object the name refers to). The referent can vary from time to time.
A variable lets us refer to an object, without specifyingperhaps
without even knowingwhich particular object it is. Thus we can
express a relation in the abstract.
S():
is a student
():
is an instructor
Y(, y): is younger than y

First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

161/241

Uses of Variables
In general, we use variables that range over the domain to make
general statements, such as
2 0 ,
and in expressing conditions which individuals may or may not
satisfy, such as
+ = .
This latter condition is satisfied by only two numbers: 0 and 2.
The meaning of such an expression will depend on the domain.
For example, the formula 2 < is always false over the domain of
integers, but not over the domain of rational numbers.

First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

162/241

Quantifiers
What about Every student is younger than some professor y?
In math-speak, we say for all to express every and there exists to
express some.
A familiar(?) example from calculus:
For all > 0, there exists > 0 such that for all y,
if | y| < then | () (y)| < .
For all is denoted by , the universal quantifier symbol, and
there exists is denoted by , the existential quantifier symbol.
In First Order Logic (FOL), the above comes out as the formula


> 0 > 0 y(| y| < | () (y)| < ) .

First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

163/241

Quantifiers: Examples
Quantifiers require a variable: (for all ) or z (there exists z).
For example, the statement Not all birds can fly can be written as
( (B() F())) .

Every student is younger than some instructor can become


(S() (y((y) Y(, y)))) .
Or should that be y ((y) (S() Y(, y))) ?
These two formulas are NOT equivalent!

First-Order Logic

Concepts of First-Order Logic

164/241

Syntax of Predicate Logic

Syntax of First-Order Logic

165/241

The Language of First-Order Logic


There are seven kinds of symbols:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.

Constant symbols
Variables
Function symbols
Predicate symbols
Connectives
Quantifiers
Punctuation

Usually c, d, c1 , c2 , . . . , d1 , d2 . . .
Usually , y, z, . . . 1 , 2 , . . . , y1 , y2 . . .
Usually , g, h, . . . 1 , 2 , . . . , g1 , g2 , . . .
P, Q, . . . P1 , P2 , . . . , Q1 , Q2 , . . .
, , ,
and
(, ), , and ,

Function symbols and predicate symbols have an assigned aritythe


number of arguments required. E.g. P() is unary, Q(, y) in binary
and R(t1 , . . . , tn ) is an n-ary predicate.
The first four kindsconstants, variables, functions, and
predicatesare not restricted. They may be assigned any meaning,
consistent with their kind and arity (e.g. unary, binary, etc).
The last three kinds of symbolsconnectives, quantifiers, and
punctuationwill have their meaning fixed by the syntax and
semantics of First-Order Logic.
Syntax of First-Order Logic

166/241

Terms
In FOL, we need to consider two kinds of expressions:
those that can have a truth value, called formulas, and
those that refer to an object of the domain, called terms.

We start with terms.


Definition. The set of terms is defined inductively as follows.
1. Each constant symbol is a term, and each variable is a term.
Such terms are called atomic terms.
2. If t1 , . . . , tn are terms and is an n-ary function symbol,
then (t1 , . . . , tn ) is a term. If n = 2 (a binary function symbol),
we may write (t1 t2 ) instead of (t1 , t2 ).
E.g. we can write +(t1 , t2 ) as (t1 + t2 )
3. Nothing else is a term.

Syntax of First-Order Logic

167/241

Examples of Terms
Example 1. If 0 is a constant symbol, and y are variables, and s(1)
and + (2) are function
 symbols, then 0, , and y are terms, as are
s(0) and + , s(y) .
The expressions s(, y) is not a term since s is a unary function
symbol.
The expression s + is not a term since s is a unary function symbol.
Example 2. Suppose is a unary function symbol, g is a binary
function symbol, and is a constant symbol.


Then g( (), ) and g , () are terms.

The expressions g() and (), are not terms.

Syntax of First-Order Logic

168/241

Atomic Formulas
As in propositional logic, a formula represents a proposition (a
true/false statement).
Relation symbols produce propositions.
Definition: An atomic formula (or atom) is an expression of the
form
P(t1 , . . . , tn )
where P is an n-ary relation symbol and each t is a term (1 n).
If P has arity 2, the atom P(t1 , t2 ) may alternatively be written
(t1 P t2 ).
E.g. < (t1 , t2 ) can be written as (t1 < t2 ).

Syntax of First-Order Logic

169/241

General Formulas
We define the set of well-formed formulas of first-order logic
inductively as follows.
1. An atomic formula is a formula.
2. If is a formula, then () is a formula.
3. If and are formulas, and ? is a binary connective symbol,
then ( ? ) is a formula.
4. If is a formula and is a variable,
then each of ( ) and ( ) is a formula.
5. Nothing else is a formula.
In case 4, the formula is called the scope of the quantifier.
The quantifier keeps the same scope if it is included in a larger
formula.

Syntax of First-Order Logic

170/241

Parse Trees

Parse trees for FOL formulas are similar to parse trees for
propositional formulas.
Quantifiers and y form nodes is the same way as negation

(i.e., only one sub-tree).


A predicate P(t1 , t2 , . . . , tn ) has a node labelled P with a sub-tree

for each of the terms t1 , t2 , . . . , tn .

Syntax of First-Order Logic

171/241

Examples: Parse trees

Example: (((P() Q()) S(, y))).

Syntax of First-Order Logic

172/241

Examples: Parse trees

Example: (((P() Q()) S(, y))).


Example: ((F(b) (y(z(G(y, z) H(, , y))))))

Syntax of First-Order Logic

172/241

Examples: Parse trees

Example: (((P() Q()) S(, y))).


Example: ((F(b) (y(z(G(y, z) H(, , y))))))
Ordinarily, one would omit many of the parentheses in the second
formula, and write simply


F(b) y z G(y, z) H(, , y)
.

Syntax of First-Order Logic

172/241

Semantics: Interpretations
We shall cover more about syntax later, but we first start the
discussion of semantics.
Definition: Fix a set L of constant symbols, function symbols, and
relation symbols.
An interpretation I (for the set L) consists of
A non-empty set dom(I), called the domain (or universe) of I.
For each constant symbol c, a member cI of dom(I).
For each function symbol () , an -ary function I .
For each relation symbol R() , an -ary relation RI .

Huth and Ryan use the term model instead of interpretation, which
is not a standard usage.
E.g. if L = {, (2) , R(1) } then the domain could be the natural
numbers, could be the constant 0, could be addition, and R could
be the set of prime numbers.
Variable-free semantics

173/241

Values of Variable-Free Terms


For terms and formulas that contain no variables or quantifiers, an
interpretation suffices to specify their meaning. The meaning arises
in the obvious(?) fashion from the syntax of the term or formula.
Definition: Fix an interpretation I. For each term t containing no
variables, the value of t under interpretation I, denoted t I , is as
follows.
If t is a constant c, the value t I is cI .
If t is (t1 , . . . , tn ), the value t I is I (t I , . . . , t I ).
1
n

The value of a term is always a member of the domain of I.


E.g. for the interpretation on the previous slide, if t is the constant
then the value t I is I which is 0. If t is (t1 , t2 ), the value t I is
I (t1I , t2I ) which is +(t1 , t2 ) which can also be written is (t1 + t2 ).

Variable-free semantics

174/241

Formulas with Variable-Free Terms


Formulas get values in much the same fashion as terms,
except that values of formulas lie in {F, T}.
Definition: Fix an interpretation I. For each formula containing no
variables, the value of under interpretation I, denoted I , is as
follows.
If is R(t1 , . . . , tn ), then
(

I =

T if t1I , . . . , tnI RI
F otherwise.

E.g. if is PrmeNmber(t1 ) then is true if t1 is a prime


number.
If is () or ( ? ), then I is determined by I and I in the

same way as for propositional logic.

Variable-free semantics

175/241

Examples
Let 0 be a constant symbol, (1) a function
symbol
and E(1) a



relation symbol. Thus E (0) and E (0) are both formulas.
Consider an interpretation I with
Domain:
0I :
I:
EI :

N, the natural numbers


zero


successor; , + 1 | N
is even; 2y | y N

I
Terms get numerical values: (0)I is 1 and (0) is 2.

I
Formula E (0) means 1 is even, and E (0) = F.


 I
Formula E (0) means 2 is even, and E (0)
= T.

What about some other interpretation?


Variable-free semantics

176/241

Example, Continued
Let J be the interpretation with
Domain:
0J :
J :
EJ :

Q, the rational numbers


two


halving; , / 2 | Q


is an integer; | Z


J
E (0) means 1 is an integer, and E (0)
is T.


 J
E (0) means 1/2 is an integer, and E (0)
is F.



Exercise: in both I and J , the formula E (0) E (0) receives
value F. Find another interpretation which gives it the value T.

Variable-free semantics

177/241

Gotchas
Two often-overlooked points about interpretations.
1. There is NO default meaning for relation, function or constant
symbols.
1 + 2 = 3 might mean that one plus two equals threebut only
if we specify that interpretation. Any interpretation of constants
1, 2, and 3, function symbol + (2) and relation symbol =(2) is
possible.
2. Functions must be defined at every point in the domain.
(I.e., they must be total.)
If we have language with a binary function symbol , we
cannot specify an interpretation with domain N and subtraction
for . Subtraction is not total on N.

Variable-free semantics

178/241

Variables

To discuss the evaluation of formulas that contain variables, we


need a few more concepts from syntax.
We shall discuss
bound and free variables,
substitution of terms for variables.

Syntax, Continued

Free and Bound Variables

179/241

Free and Bound Variables


Recall: the scope of a quantifier in a sub-formula or is the
formula .
An occurrence of a variable in a formula is bound if it lies in the
scope of some quantifier of the same variable; otherwise it is free.
In other words, a quantifier binds its variable within its scope.
Example. In formula y( + y = z), is bound (by ), y is bound
(by y), and z is free.
Example. In formula P() Q(), the first occurrence of is
free and the last occurrence of is bound.

(The variable symbol immediately after or is neither free nor bound.)

Syntax, Continued

Free and Bound Variables

180/241

Free and Bound Variables


Formally, a variable occurs free in a formula if and only if it is a
member of the set FV(), i.e. free variables in defined as follows.


1. If is P(t1 , . . . , tk ), then FV() = | appears in some t .
2. If is (), then FV() = FV().
3. If is ( ? ), then FV() = FV() FV().
4. If is Q (for Q {, }), then FV() = FV() {}.

In summary: a formula has the same free variables as its parts,


except that a quantified variable becomes bound.

A formula with no free variables is called a closed formula, or a


sentence.

Syntax, Continued

Free and Bound Variables

181/241

Substitution
The notation [t/ ], for a variable , a term t, and a formula ,
denotes the formula obtained from by replacing each free
occurrence of with t. Intuitively, it is the formula that answers the
question,
What happens to if has the value specified by term t?
Examples.


If is the formula E () , then [y + y/ ] is E (y + y) .


[ ()/ ] is E () .


E ( + y) [y/ ] is E (y + y) .

Substitution does NOT affect bound occurrences of the variable.



If is E( ()) S(, y) , then [g(, y)/ ] is ,
because has no free occurrence of .
Syntax, Continued

Substitution

182/241

Examples: Substitution


Example 1: Let be P(, y) R(, y) .

Formula could be interpreted as If is a parent of y, then is a


relative of y.
What is [z/ y]? It is P(, z) R(, z).
This could be interpreted as If is a parent of z then is a relative
of z.
Here the substitution does not change the meaning. It does not
matter if you use y or z.

Syntax, Continued

Substitution

183/241

Examples: Substitution
Example 2: Let be y (y > ).
Formula could be interpreted as There exists a y such that y is
greater than .
What about [y/ ]?
Is it y (y > y)?

There is a problem.

Formula could now be interpreted as There exists a y such that y


is greater than y.
The free variable in the term (y > ) got captured by the
quantifier y.
Here the substitution changes the meaning. It matters whether you
use or y. We want to avoid this capture.

Syntax, Continued

Substitution

184/241

Avoiding Capture

Example. Formula = S() y P() Q(y) ; term t = (y, y).

The leftmost can be substituted by t since it is not in the scope of


any quantifier, but substituting in P() puts the variable y into the
scope of y.
We can prevent capture of variables in two ways.
1. Declare that a substitution is undefined in cases where capture
would occur.
One can often evade problems by a different choice of variable.
(Above, we might be able to substitute (z, z) instead of (y, y).
Or alter to quantify some other variable.)
2. Write the definition of substitution carefully, to prevent capture.
Huth and Ryan opt for the first method. We shall use the second.

Syntax, Continued

Substitution

185/241

SubstitutionFormal Definition
Let be a variable and t a term.
For a term , the term [t/ ] is with each occurrence of the
variable replaced by the term t.
For a formula ,

1. If is P(t1 , . . . , tk ), then [t/ ] is P t1 [t/ ], . . . , tk [t/ ] ,
i.e. apply the substitution to each term in the predicate.

2. If is (), then [t/ ] is ([t/ ]),


i.e. apply the substitution to the subformula .
3. If is ( ? ), then [t/ ] is ([t/ ] ? [t/ ]),
i.e. apply the substitution to the two subformulas and .
4. . . .
(Continued next page. . . )

Syntax, Continued

Substitution

186/241

SubstitutionFormal Definition (2)


For variable , term t and formula :
..
.
4. If is (Q ), then [t/ ] is ,
i.e. if is a bound variable then do not substitute it.
5. If is (Qy ) for some other variable y, then
(a) If y does not occur in t, then [t/ ] is (Qy [t/ ]),
i.e. if no variable in t is captured, then apply the substitution to the
subformula .
(b) Otherwise, select a variable z that occurs in neither nor t;
then [t/ ] is (Qz ([z/ y])[t/ ]),
i.e. prevent capture by renaming the quantified variable, i.e. y, to
something harmless, e.g. z

Huth and Ryan specify that the substitution is undefined if capture


would occurcase 5(b) above. With this more complex definition,
one never has to add a condition regarding undefined substitutions.
Substitution always behaves the way it should.
Syntax, Continued

Substitution

187/241

Example, Revisited
Example. If is y + y = z, what is [(y 1)/ z]?
This falls under case 5(b): the term to be substituted, namely y 1,
contains a variable y quantified in formula .
Let be + y = z; thus is y .

Syntax, Continued

Substitution

188/241

Example, Revisited
Example. If is y + y = z, what is [(y 1)/ z]?
This falls under case 5(b): the term to be substituted, namely y 1,
contains a variable y quantified in formula .
Let be + y = z; thus is y .
1. Select a new variable, say .
2. Then substitute it for the variable y bound in i.e.
[/ y]

is

+ = z,

3. and then do the required substitution [(y 1)/ z],


[/ y][(y 1)/ z]

is

+ = y 1.

Thus the required formula [(y 1)/ z] is


+ = y 1 .
Syntax, Continued

Substitution

188/241

Semantics of Predicate Logic

Semantics

189/241

FOL Adds to Propositional Logic

In propositional logic, semantics was described in terms of


valuations to propositional atoms, e.g. if t(p) = T and t(q) = F then
the truth valuation of (p q), i.e. (p q)t , evaluates to T.
FOL includes more ingredients (i.e., predicates, functions, variables,
terms, constants, etc.) and, hence, the semantics for FOL must
account for all of the ingredients.
We already saw the concept of an interpretation, which specifies the
domain and the identities of the constants, relations and functions.
Formulas that include variables, and perhaps quantifiers, require
additional information, known as an environment (or assignment).

Semantics

190/241

Environments
A first-order environment is a function that assigns a value in the
domain to each variable.
Example. With the domain N, we might have environment E1 given
by E1 () = 9 and E1 (y) = 2.
If the interpretation specifies < is less-than, then the formula
( < y), which is interpreted as (9 < 2), gets the value false.
Example. With the domain of fictional animals, we might have
E2 () = Tweety and E2 (y) = Nemo.
If the interpretation specifies < is was created before, then
( < y), which is interpreted as (Tweety was created before Nemo),
gets the value true.

Semantics

Environments

191/241

Constants Vs. Variables

Example: Let 1 an 2 be two formulas in FOL: 1 is P(c) (where c is


a constant) and 2 is P() (where is a variable).
Let I be the interpretation with domain N, cI = 2 and PI = is even.
Then 1I = T, but 2I is undefined.
To give 2 a value, we must also specify an environment. For
(I ,E)
example, if E() = 2, then 2
= T.
If we wish, we can consider a formula such as 2 that contains a free
variable as expressing a function: the function that maps E(), an
(I ,E)
environment, to 2
, which is either T or F.

Semantics

Environments

192/241

Meaning of Terms
The combination of an interpretation and an environment supplies a
value for every term.
Definition: Fix an interpretation I and environment E. For each
term t, the value of t under I and E, denoted t (I ,E) , is as follows.
If t is a constant c, the value t (I ,E) is cI .
If t is a variable , the value t (I ,E) is E .
(I ,E)
If t is (t1 , . . . , tn ), the value t (I ,E) is I (t1
, . . . , tn(I ,E) ).

To extend this definition to formulas, we must consider quantifiers.


But first, a few examples.

Semantics

Environments

193/241

Meaning of TermsExample
Example. Suppose a language has constant symbol 0, a unary
function s, and a binary function +. We shall write + in infix position:
( + y) instead of +(, y).



The expressions s s(0) + s() and s + s + s(0) are both
terms.
The following are examples of interpretations and environments.
dom{I} = {0, 1, 2, . . .}, 0I = 0, sI is the successor function (the

successor of is + 1) and + I is the addition operation.

(I ,E)
Then, if E() = 3, the terms get values s s(0) + s()
=6

(I ,E)
and s + s + s(0)
= 9.

Semantics

Environments

194/241

Meaning of TermsExample 2

dom{J } is the collection of all words over the alphabet {, b},

0J = ,
sJ appends to the end of a string, and
+ J is concatenation.

Let E() = b. Then

and

s s(0) + s()

(J ,E)

= b


(J ,E)
s + s + s(0)
= bb .

Semantics

Environments

195/241

Quantified Formulas
To evaluate the truthfulness of a formula , check whether
holds for every value d in the domain.
To evaluate the truthfulness of a formula , check whether
holds for some value d in the domain.
How can we express this precisely?
Definition: For any environment E and domain element d, the
environment E with re-assigned to d, denoted E[ 7 d],
is given by
(
d
if y is
E[ 7 d](y) =
E(y) if y is not .

Semantics

Environments

196/241

Values of Quantified Formulas

Definition: The values of and are given by


(
T if (I ,E[7d]) = T for every d in dom(I)
( )(I ,E) =
F otherwise
(
T if (I ,E[7d]) = T for some d in dom(I)
( )(I ,E) =
F otherwise
Note: The values of ( )(I ,E) and ( )(I ,E) do not depend on the
value of E().
The value E() only matters for free occurrences of .

Semantics

Environments

197/241

Examples: Value of a Quantified Formula


Example. Let dom(I) = {, b} and RI = {, , , b, b, b }.

Let E() = and E(y) = b. We have


R(, )(I ,E) = T, since E(), E() = , RI .


R(y, )(I ,E) = F, since E(y), E() = b,
/ RI .

(I ,E)
y R(y, )
= T, since R(y, )(I ,E[y7]) = T.


(That is, E[y 7 ](y), E[y 7 ]() = , RI ).

What is y R(, y)

(I ,E)

Semantics

Environments

198/241

Examples: Continued
Example. Let dom(I) = {, b} and RI = {, , , b, b, b}.
Let E() = and E(y) = b.
What is y R(, y)

(I ,E)

Since b,
/ RI , we have
R(, y)(I ,E[7b][y7]) = F ,
and thus
y R(, y)

Semantics

(I ,E)

Environments

=F .

199/241

Examples: Continued
Example. Let dom(I) = {, b} and RI = {, , , b, b, b}.
Let E() = and E(y) = b.
What is y R(, y)

(I ,E)

Since b,
/ RI , we have
R(, y)(I ,E[7b][y7]) = F ,
and thus
y R(, y)
What about y R(, y)

(I ,E)

Semantics

(I ,E)

=F .

Environments

199/241

A Question of Syntax

In the previous example, we wrote


R(, y)(I ,E[7b][y7]) = F .
Why did we not write simply
R(b, ) = F
or perhaps

R(b, )(I ,E) = F ?

Semantics

Environments

200/241

A Question of Syntax

In the previous example, we wrote


R(, y)(I ,E[7b][y7]) = F .
Why did we not write simply
R(b, ) = F
or perhaps

R(b, )(I ,E) = F ?

Because R(b, ) is not a formula. The elements and b of dom(I)


are not symbols in the language; they cannot appear in a formula.

Semantics

Environments

200/241

Satisfaction of Formulas
When an interpretation I and environment E satisfy a formula (i.e.
(I ,E) = T), we denoted it as I |=E ,
If they do not satisfy (i.e. (I ,E) = F), we denoted it as I 6|=E .
Form of

Condition for I |=E

R(t1 , . . . , tk )

E
(I ,E)
, . . . , tk
RI
I 6|=E
both I |=E and I |=E
either I |=E or I |=E (or both)
either I 6|=E or I |=E (or both)
for every dom(I), I |=E[7]
there is some dom(I) such that I |=E[7]
D

(I ,E)

t1

If I |=E for every E, then I satisfies , denoted I |= .

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

201/241

Example: Satisfaction

Example. Consider the formula y R(, y y).


(For R a binary relation and a binary function.)
Suppose dom(I) = {1, 2, 3, . . .},
I is the addition operation, and
RI is the equality relation.
Then I |=E y R(, y y) iff E() is an even number.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

202/241

Validity and Satisfiability

Validity and satisfiability of FOL formulas have definitions analogous


to tautology and satisfiability for propositional logic.
Definition: A formula is
valid if every interpretation and environment satisfy ; that is, if

I |=E for every I and E,


satisfiable if some interpretation and environment satisfy ; that

is, if I |=E for some I and E, and


unsatisfiable if no interpretation and environment satisfy ; that

is, if I 6|=E for every I and E.


The term tautology is not used in predicate logic.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

203/241

Example: Satisfiability and Validity


Example: Let be the formula P g(), g(y) , g(z) . The formula is
satisfiable:
dom(I): N
I : summation
gI : squaring
PI : equality
E() = 3, E(y) = 4 and E(z) = 5.

is not valid. (Why?)

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

204/241

Quantifiers Over Finite Domains

The universal and existential quantifiers may be understood


respectively as generalizations of conjunction and disjunction. If the
domain D = {1 , . . . , k } is finite then:
R(1 ) . . . R(k )

R()

iff

R()

iff R(1 ) . . . R(k )

where R is a property.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

205/241

Relevance Lemma

Lemma:
Let be a first-order formula, I be an interpretation, and E1 and E2
be two environments such that
E1 () = E2 () for every that occurs free in .
Then
I |=E1 if and only if I |=E2 .
Proof by induction on the structure of .

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

206/241

Logical Consequence

Suppose is a set of formulas and is a formula. We say that is a


logical consequence of , written as |= , iff for any
interpretation I and environment E, we have I |=E implies I |=E .
|= means that is valid.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

207/241

Example


Example: Show that |= ( ) ( ) ( ) .

Proof by contradiction. Suppose there are I and E such that




I 6|=E ( ) ( ) ( ) .
For the implication to fail, we must have I |=E ( ) and
I 6|=E ( ) ( ).
For the second entailment to fail we must have I |=E and
I 6|=E .
Using the definition of |= for formulas with , we have for every
dom(I), I |=E[7] and I |=E[7] .
Thus also I |=E[7] for every dom(I).
Thus I |=E , a contradiction.
Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

208/241

Example
Example. Show that |= .

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

209/241

Example
Example. Show that |= .
Suppose that I |=E . By definition, this means
for every dom(I), I |=E[7] .
Again by definition (for a formula with ), this is equivalent to
for every dom(I), I 6|=E[7]
and also
there is no dom(I) such that I |=E[7] .
This last is the definition of I |=E , as required.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

209/241

Example
Example: Show that, in general,
( ) ( ) 6|= ( ) .
That is, find and such that consequence does not hold.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

210/241

Example
Example: Show that, in general,
( ) ( ) 6|= ( ) .
That is, find and such that consequence does not hold.
Key idea: yields true whenever is false. So have true in
some cases and so will be false.
Let be R(). Let I have domain {, b} and RI = {}, i.e. R is only
true for . Then I |= ( ) ( ) for any , because is false.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

210/241

Example
Example: Show that, in general,
( ) ( ) 6|= ( ) .
That is, find and such that consequence does not hold.
Key idea: yields true whenever is false. So have true in
some cases and so will be false.
Let be R(). Let I have domain {, b} and RI = {}, i.e. R is only
true for . Then I |= ( ) ( ) for any , because is false.
To obtain M 6|= ( ), we can use R() for so will be false
when is true.

Thus ( ) ( ) 6|= ( ), as required.

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

210/241

Example

Example: for any formula and term t,


|= ( ) [t/ ] .

That is, if is true for all then it must certainly be true when is
the term t.

Recall that functions must be total!

Semantics

Satisfaction of Formulas

211/241

Proofs in First-Order Logic


Using Natural Deduction

Natural Deduction

212/241

Natural Deduction for FOL

Natural Deduction for FOL extends Natural Deduction for


propositional logic by including rules for the introduction and
elimination of quantifiers.
Other proof techniques and tricks remain the same as natural
deduction for propositional logic.

Natural Deduction

213/241

e and i
Elimination of and introduction of are fairly straightforward.
Name

`-notation

inference notation

-elimination
(e)

If ` then
` [t/ ]


[t/ ]

-introduction
(i)

If ` [t/ ],
then `

[t/ ]

Given that a formula is true for every value of ,


conclude it is true for a particular value, such as that of t.
Given that a formula is true for a particular value (of t),
conclude it is true for some value.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

214/241

Example: e
Consider the proof of the following statements.
All fish can swim. Nemo is a fish. Therefore, Nemo can swim.


In FOL: show that (F() S()), F(Nemo) ` S(Nemo)..
Proof:
1.

(F() S())

Premise

2.

F(Nemo)

Premise

3.

F(Nemo) S(Nemo)

e: 1

4.

S(Nemo)

e: 2, 3

The e rule allows us to go from talking about all the elements in the
domain (line 1) to talking about a specific element, Nemo (line 4).
The proof doesnt care what F and S mean. Fishiness and swimming
ability really have nothing to do with the argument.
Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

215/241

Example: i

Example. Show P(y) ` P() Q(y) .

1.

P(y)

Premise

2.

P(y)

Assumption

3.

e: 2, 1

4.

Q(y)

e: 3

5.

P(y) Q(y)

6.

i: 24

P() Q(y)

i: 5

The i rule allows us to go from talking about a particular element in


the domain (lines 1-5) to talking about some element, (line 6).
If P(y) is true, then P(y) Q(y) is true because F T is true.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

216/241

Note to the example


The general form of rule i:

Use in the previous example:


P(y) Q(y)

[t/ ]

P() Q(y)

We took P() Q(y) for .


However, knowing what [t/ ] is, does not determine what is, i.e.
other substitutions are possible.
We could also take P() Q() for ; thus the derivation step would
be
P(y) Q(y)
 .
P() Q()

But the formula P() Q() is not what we wanted to prove.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

217/241

Soundness of -Elimination and -Introduction


Claim I: For any formula , variable and term t,
|= [t/ ]

and

[t/ ] |= .

E.g. (for the 2nd claim) if [t/ ] ` ND , then any interpretation


and environment that makes [t/ ] true makes .
Proof: Suppose I |=E Q ; i.e., for (every/some) d dom(I),
(I ,E[7d]) = T .
Since d = t (I ,E) is a domain value, it suffices to show
Claim II: For every formula , variable and term t,
[t/ ] (I ,E) = (I ,E[7t

(I,E) ])

I.e. you can substitute first and then evaluate with I, E or evaluate
with the modified environment where 7 t (I ,E) .
To prove this, use the defn of substitution, Cases 4, 5(a) and 5(b).
Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

218/241

Soundness of -Elimination, Contd


There are many cases (e.g. of the form (), ( ? ), ( )). One
of the cases (the others are an exercise): is a quantified formula,
say y .
We have (y )(I ,E[7t

(I,E) ])

= T iff for some d dom(I),

(I ,E[7t

(I,E) ][y7 d])

=T .

Likewise, we have (y [t/ ])(I ,E) = T iff for some d dom(I),


([t/ ])(I ,E[y7d]) = T .
In the first case, t is evaluated under environment E. In the second, t
is evaluated under environment E[y 7 d] (or a further modification).
If y is free in t, the difference matters!
Also, we have a problem if y is the same variable as .
Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

219/241

Defining Substitution
The definition of substitution included the following.
For a variable and a term t:
4. If is (Q ), then [t/ ] is .
5. If is (Qy ) for some other variable y, then
If y does not occur in t, then [t/ ] is (Qy [t/ ]).
Otherwise, let z be a variable that occurs in neither nor t;

then [t/ ] is (Qz ([z/ y])[t/ ]).

With this definition, we always get that, as required,


(Qy )(I ,E[7t

(I,E) ])

= (Qy )[t/ ]

(I ,E)

Proof left to you.


(Note: (Qy )[t/ ]

(I ,E)

may differ from Qy([t/ ])

Natural Deduction

-Elimination and -Introduction

(I ,E)

!)

220/241

Proving a Universal
The -introduction rule follows ordinary mathematical usage. To
prove a property holds for all integers, one often starts with
Let be an integer. . . .
This means the same as
Assume that the variable refers to an integer.
Then one proves that has the property.
Since we know nothing about the value , except that it is an
integer, this justifies that every integer has the property.
One could also start the proof with
Let be anything. If is an integer, then. . . .
The conclusion is essentially the same.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

221/241

Rule -Introduction
Definition: a variable is fresh in a subproof if it occurs nowhere
outside the subproof box (i.e. is not a free variable outside the
subproof).
Freshness captures the notion of know nothing about it.
Name
-introduction
(i)

`-notation

inference notation

If ` [y/ ] and
y not free in or ,

y fresh
..
.
[y/ ]

then `


In words: in order to prove (), prove (y) for an arbitrary y in
the domain.

Natural Deduction

-Introduction

222/241

Rule i Is Sound
To further clarify the rule i, we show that it is sound. That is,
Suppose that |= [y/ ] and y is not free in or .
Then |= .
Proof: Fix an arbitrary I and E with I |=E .
The supposition |= [y/ ] thus requires I |=E [y/ ].
We need to show that I |=E[7d] for every d dom(I).
Consider an arbitrary d dom(I).
Since y is not free in , the Relevance Lemma yields I |=E[y7d] ,
i.e. since y is not a free variable in any of and environments only
assign values to the free variables, this does not affect the truth of
any interpretation.
Since y is not free in , we have [y/ ] (I ,E[y7d]) = (I ,E[7d]) , i.e.
whether we set to d, or replace by y and set y to d, we get the
same result.
Therefore I |=E[7d] for every d, and thus I |=E as required.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

223/241

Example: Use of i
Example. Show that ` , for any .
1.

2.

fresh

n.

Premise

[/ ]

??

i: 26

Approach: By picking an arbitrary , substituting it in , resulting in


a contradiction, then for an arbitrary cannot exist.
Note: fresh means we choose any variable not in , or more
generally, that does not occur outside the subproof box.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

224/241

Example: Use of i
Example. Show that ` , for any .
1.

2.

fresh

3.

[/ ]

Assumption

4.

i: 3

5.

e: 1, 4

6.

[/ ]

i: 35

7.

i: 26

Premise

Approach: By picking an arbitrary , substituting it in , resulting in


a contradiction, then for an arbitrary cannot exist.
Note: fresh means we choose any variable not in , or more
generally, that does not occur outside the subproof box.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

224/241

Example: Another use of i


Show that ( ) ` ( ) ( ).
1.

( )

Premise

( ) ( )

i??

Approach: Since ( ) and , pick an arbitrary case,


[/ ], and show how that assumption leads to [/ ].
Note: do not apply rule e until you know which term to use.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

225/241

Example: Another use of i


Show that ( ) ` ( ) ( ).
1.

( )

Premise

2.

Assumption

8.

i???

( ) ( )

i??

Approach: Since ( ) and , pick an arbitrary case,


[/ ], and show how that assumption leads to [/ ].
Note: do not apply rule e until you know which term to use.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

225/241

Example: Another use of i


Show that ( ) ` ( ) ( ).
1.

( )

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

fresh

6.

[/ ]

7.

i???

8.

( ) ( )

i??

??

Approach: Since ( ) and , pick an arbitrary case,


[/ ], and show how that assumption leads to [/ ].
Note: do not apply rule e until you know which term to use.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

225/241

Example: Another use of i


Show that ( ) ` ( ) ( ).
1.

( )

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

fresh

4.

[/ ] [/ ]

e: 1

5.

[/ ]

e: 2

6.

[/ ]

e: 4, 5

7.

i: 36

8.

( ) ( )

i: 27

Approach: Since ( ) and , pick an arbitrary case,


[/ ], and show how that assumption leads to [/ ].
Note: do not apply rule e until you know which term to use.
Natural Deduction

-Introduction

225/241

Elimination of an Existential Quantifier


Name
-elimination
(e)

`-notation
If , [/ ] ` ,
with fresh,
then , `

inference notation

[/ ], fresh
..
.

This can be seen as a generalization of the -elimination rule: i.e. if


follows from any cases where [/ ] is true then the can be
eliminated.
In e, the variable should not occur free in , , or , or more
generally, anywhere outside the subproof box.
Of course, will normally be free in [/ ].

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

226/241

Rule e Is Sound

The rule e is sound. That is,


Suppose that , [/ ] |= and is not free in , , or .
Then , |= .

Proof: Exercise. Follow the proof of soundness of i, i.e. since is


not free in , or then, for example, it is not affected by different
environments.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

227/241

Example: Use of e

Example. Show that R() ` y R(y).


1.

R()

Premise

2.

R(), fresh

Assumption

3.

y R(y)

i: 2 (term )

4.

y R(y)

e: 1, 23

It is as if you are giving the name to the value of such that


R() is true in the R() formula.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

228/241

Extending the example?


Note: the previous proof did not depend on the particular relation R
that we used.
Idea: Can we do the same proof for arbitrary formulas?
Does ` y [y/ ] hold?
1.

Premise

2.

[/ ], fresh

Assumption

3.

[y/ ][/ y]

Is this step OK?

4.

y [y/ ]

i: 3 (term )

5.

y [y/ ]

e: 1, 24

Here [y/ ][/ y] (on line 3) means first substitute y for , then
substitute for y in forumula .
Is the formula on line 2 the same as the one on line 3?

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

229/241

Extending the example?


Note: the previous proof did not depend on the particular relation R
that we used.
Idea: Can we do the same proof for arbitrary formulas?
Does ` y [y/ ] hold?
1.

Premise

2.

[/ ], fresh

Assumption

3.

[y/ ][/ y]

Is this step OK?

4.

y [y/ ]

i: 3 (term )

5.

y [y/ ]

e: 1, 24

Here [y/ ][/ y] (on line 3) means first substitute y for , then
substitute for y in forumula .
Is the formula on line 2 the same as the one on line 3?
If y is free in , then no the derivation fails.
But otherwise, it works.
Natural Deduction

-Elimination

229/241

Example: and together


Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

e ??

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

230/241

Example: and together


Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

2.

[/ ], fresh

Assumption

i ??

e ??

7.

On line 2, it is as if you are giving the name to the value of


such that is true in the formula.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

230/241

Example: and together


Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

2.

[/ ], fresh

Assumption

3.

Assumption

4.

[/ ]

e: 3

5.

e: 4, 2

6.

i: 35

7.

e: 1, 26

On line 2, it is as if you are giving the name to the value of


such that is true in the formula.
On line 3, assume is true and then derive a contradiction.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

230/241

Example: e and i together, again


We can interchange the quantifiers in the previous deduction.
Example. Show ` .
1.

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

[/ ] ( fresh)

Assumption

4.

[/ ]

e: 1

5.

e: 3, 4

6.

e: 2, 35

7.

i: 26

On line 2, assume is true and then derive a contradiction.


On line 3, it is as if you are giving the name to the value of
such that is true in the formula and then getting a
contradiction from on line 1.
Natural Deduction

-Elimination

231/241

Quantifiers and Negation: The final case


So far, we have shown ` ,
` , and
` .
Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

[t/ ]

??

i: ??

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

232/241

Quantifiers and Negation: The final case


So far, we have shown ` ,
` , and
` .
Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

[t/ ]

??

i: ??

For what term t can we prove [t/ ]?

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

232/241

Quantifiers and Negation: The final case


So far, we have shown ` ,
` , and
` .
Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

[t/ ]

??

i: ??

For what term t can we prove [t/ ]?


We wont try to show [t/ ] directly. Well do a proof by
contradiction, i.e. assume (on line 2).
Then show that [/ ] leads to a contradiction and so does
[/ ].
Natural Deduction

-Elimination

232/241

The Final Case: A full proof


Example. Show that ` .
1.

Premise

2.

Assumption

3.

fresh

4.

[/ ]

5.

i: 4

6.

e: 5, 2

7.

[/ ]

i: 46

8.

[/ ]

e: 7

9.

Assumption

i: 38

10.

e: 9, 1

11.

i: 210

12.

e: 11

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

233/241

Repeated Quantifiers

The rules for elimination and introduction of quantifiers (slides 214,


222 and 226) can be generalized to multiple quantifiers.
Let 1 , . . . , n be n distinct variables.
-elim If ` 1 n , then ` [t1 / 1 ] [tn / n ].
-intro If ` [t1 / 1 ] [tn / n ], for terms t1 , . . . , tn ,

then ` 1 n .
-intro If ` [1 / 1 ] [n / n ], with variables 1 , . . . , n fresh,

then ` 1 n .
-elim If ` 1 n and {[1 / 1 ] [n / n ] ` , with

1 , . . . , n fresh, then ` .

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

234/241

Example: Repeated universal quantifiers

Example. Show that y A(, y) ` y A(, y).


1.

y A(, y)

2.

, fresh

3.

A(, )

e (2): 1

4.

y A(, y)

i (2): 3

Natural Deduction

Premise

-Elimination

235/241

Exercise on Quantifier Rules

Exercise. Show that






Q() R() , P() Q() ` P() R() .

Left to you.

Natural Deduction

-Elimination

236/241

FOL with Equality


Generally, relation symbols have no mandated interpretation.
Sometimes, however, one makes an exception for the symbol =.
Definition: First-Order Logic with Equality is First-Order Logic with
the restriction that the symbol = must be interpreted as equality
on the domain:


(=)I = d, d | d dom(I) .
There are two ways to account for this restriction in our proofs.
1. Add deduction rules for symbol =:
Equals-Introduction:
Equals-Elimination:

t=t

=i

t1 = t2 [t1 / ]
=e
[t2 / ]

2. Alternatively, use axioms rather than deduction rules. . . .


Logic With Equality

237/241

Axioms for Equality


Instead of deduction rules for =, one can define axioms for equality.
An axiom is a permanent premise; it may be used at any time.
EQ1: = is an axiom.
EQ2: For each formula and variable z,


y = y [/ z] [y/ z]
is an axiom.
These axioms imply

Symmetry of =: ` y = y y = .

Transitivity of =: ` y = y (y = = ) .

Logic With Equality

238/241

Symmetry of Equality: Proof



Lemma (EQsymm): ` y = y y = .

Using Axioms EQ1 and EQ2.


1.

, fresh

= =
y = y y =

???


Logic With Equality

i (2): 1?

239/241

Symmetry of Equality: Proof



Lemma (EQsymm): ` y = y y = .

Using Axioms EQ1 and EQ2.


1.

, fresh

2.

Assumption

??

= =
y = y y =

i: 2?


Logic With Equality

i (2): 1?

239/241

Symmetry of Equality: Proof



Lemma (EQsymm): ` y = y y = .

Using Axioms EQ1 and EQ2.


1.

, fresh

2.

3.

y = y ( = y = )

4.

= ( = = )

e (2) [, ]: 3

5.

==

e: 2, 4

??

Assumption

= =
y = y y =

EQ2 [z = ]

i: 2?


Logic With Equality

i (2): 1?

239/241

Symmetry of Equality: Proof



Lemma (EQsymm): ` y = y y = .

Using Axioms EQ1 and EQ2.


1.

, fresh

2.

3.

y = y ( = y = )

4.

= ( = = )

e (2) [, ]: 3

5.

==

e: 2, 4

6.

EQ1

7.

e []: 6

8.

e: 7,5

9.

= =

10.

Assumption

y = y y =

EQ2 [z = ]

i: 24


Logic With Equality

i (2): 110

239/241

Transitivity of Equality: Proof


Lemma (EQtrans): ` y = y (y = = )

Using EQsymm (from previous slide), Axioms EQ1 and EQ2.


1.

, , fresh

2.

y ( = y) ( = y = )

3.

= ( = = )

4.

Assumption

5.

EqSymm

6.

==

e: 5, 3

7.

= ( = = )

i: 46

8.

y

= y (y = = )

i (3): 18

Logic With Equality

EQ2 [z = ]
e (2) [, ]: 2

240/241

Derived Proof Rules for Equality


Equality satisfies the following derived rules.

EQtrans(k):

t1 = t2

t2 = t3
t1 = tk+1

tk = tk+1

for any t1 , . . . , tk+1 .

EQtrans(k) results from k 1 uses of transitivity.

EQsubs(r):
and t2 .

t1 = t2
r[t1 / z] = r[t2 / z]

for any variable z and terms r, t1

Prove as an exercise.

Logic With Equality

241/241

You might also like