Gadamer, H-G - Idea of The Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy (Yale, 1986) PDF
Gadamer, H-G - Idea of The Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy (Yale, 1986) PDF
Gadamer, H-G - Idea of The Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy (Yale, 1986) PDF
THE
IDEA OF THE G O O D
IN
PLATONIC-ARISTOTELIAN
PHILOSOPHY
HANS-GEORG
GADAMER
T R A N S L A T E D A N D WITH AN
INTRODUCTION AND ANNOTATION
BY P. C H R I S T O P H E R S M I T H
YALE UNIVERSITY P R E S S
NEW HAVEN A N D L O N D O N
9 8 7 6 5 4 3
CONTENTS
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
Though shorter than Truth and Method} and, as Gadamer readily acknowledges, not a completely unified study. The Idea of the
Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy^ must be counted
nonetheless among Gadamer's most important books. For one
thing, it gives us an extended example of the hermeneutical or interpretive techniques for which Gadamer has become so well
known; for another, it provides us with remarkable new insights
1. Hans Georg Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode (Tbingen, 1965), henceforth WM. This work has appeared in translation as Truth and Method (New
York, 1975). Translations of passages cited here are my own.
2. Gadamer, Die Idee des Guten zwischen Plato und Aristoteles (Heidelberg,
1978). The zwischen is difficult to render in ordinary English. "Between," naturally, will not do, and Gadamer intentionally avoids the more common "von . . .
zu" (from . . . to) and "in." He found the circumlocution I have used here appropriate for two reasons, which should become clearer in the course of this introduction. Briefly, he gives priority not to the individual authors as such, but to the
thought we find expressed in their works. Hence he tends to say "the Socratic
question" and "Platonic philosophy" rather than Socrates' question and Plato's
philosophy. Furthermore, he includes expositions of texts whose authorship may
be contested, for example, the Magna Moralia, but whose content is clearly Platonic or Aristotelian "heritage." He also wants to stress that one should not approach these thinkers "developmentally," which is to say, in a way that makes it
appear that Aristode broke with Plato. Instead, he contends, it is best to think of
a shared, continuous tradition to which both belong. In short, the choice of
zwischen is meant, above all, to set off Gadamer's approach from that of Werner
Jaeger. See Jaeger, Aristoteles, Grundlegung einer Geschichte seiner Entwicklung
(Berlin, 1923), translated as Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of his Development (London, 1948).
vu
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
something wrong here. For one thing, before the modern period
(Galileo) no one thought of putting the two thinkers in opposition to each other/ For another, the ancient tradition reports no
such modification of the views of either one of them. Hence it is
far more promising, Gadamer argues, to assume that they were
consistent, with themselves and with each other, in "getting at"
the same thing, albeit in quite different modes of discourse. The
task then becomes to find out what that same thing is and to display it as it shows up in Plato's and Aristotle's diverse presentations. Here two influences on Gadamer's thought become evident at once: above all Husserl, of course, but also, I suggest,
Rudolf Bultmann. Gadamer will use the ^'workman-like" techniques of Husserl's phenomenological description to bring to
light the common subject matter of Platonic-Aristotelian
thought. And in Plato's case that means that he will have to be
"demythologized," to use Bultmann's termthat is, what he
says metaphorically will have to be translated into conceptualizations of the phenomena of bur existence, the kind of conceptualizations that Aristotle was attempting.
But it is not only inattentiveness to textual differences that is
responsible for the misunderstanding that pits Plato and Aristotle against each other. The misunderstanding is also the result
of failure to establish the occasion for what is said in each case.
With that we come to the second hermeneutical principle exemplified in this book. The principal problem with reducing any
form of discourse to a series of statements is that the context or
setting, which alone gives what is said its meaning, is thereby
omitted. Naturally, we face this problem with any written text:
in order to know what was said, we need to know what it was
4. The modern period is faced with a new problem: how to overcome teleoiogical science. Galileo is thus led to play off the Pythagorean-mathematical in
Plato against Aristotelian physics. See Gadamer, Dialogue and dialectic, p. 195.
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
said in response to, and, more often than not, written texts do
not tell us this expressly. They have come down to us as excerpts, as it were, even if, prima facie, they are complete in themselves. Hence, for someone who would understand them, the
task is to put them back in their setting. Said another way, one
must give priority to the question being addressed over the answer to it contained in the text; precisely what is unsaid and tacitly presupposed must be brought to the fore. Thus Gadamer replaces propositional logic's testing of statements with "the logic
of question and answer" (cf. WM 351 ff.).
Gadamer applies this principle of interpretation in several
ways. On .the other hand, he often takes into account those
things which are meant precisely by not being said, that is, "indirect" or "negative" meanings, as he calls them. The paradigm
here is satire, of which he finds a good deal in Plato's Republic;
the absurdly impractical proposals that Plato makes there can
only be understood as satirical inversions of the perversions of
political life in the Athens of that time. That is to say, they can
only be understood "e contrario."^ But, more generally, he finds
it imperative to treat anything that Plato or Aristotle says as an
answer to a particular question posed. If we are to understand
what they are saying, this question must be uncovered and
specified.
It turns out that Plato and Aristotle are answering questions
posed somewhat differently, and that is the primary reason for
5. The phrase "e contrario" epitomizes one important sense of the word "dialectical" in Gadamer: one must read satire "dialectically," which is to say, as
the contrary of what is meant. But not only satire. Gadamer's analysis of Hegel's
"Verkehrte Welt" (inverted-perverted world) provides a masterful exposition of
this principle of dialectical reading (see Gadamer, HegeVs Dialectic^ pp. 35-53).
And Socratic irony, of course, is another prime example of something which
must be understood e contrario.
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
to Anaxagoras because the latter, so it seemed, wanted to account for natural things in terms of what is best (beltiston) for
them (97c). Hence Anaxagoras's nous (mind) promised, albeit
deceptively, to overcome the deficiencies of merely physiological
causal accounts. Aristotle, on the other hand, begins with "what
is by nature," the physei onta, in responding primarily to theoretical questions. Yet ultimately Aristotle too may be said to
have extended Socrates' and Plato's question concerning arete
(virtue) and the good or best (ariston) in his investigations of the
universe: the "physicists" {physikoi), he says, with only two
kinds of explanation at their disposal from what, and by the
agency of whatcould not properly grasp the cosmos, in which
things occur for the sake of (heneka) what is good.
It remains now to specify briefly how Gadamer arrives at these
conclusions. I offer here an overview of Gadamer's argument
since it often seems highly compressed and, in any event, is
sometimes difficult to follow once one is immersed in the details
of it.
In regard to Plato, what is emphasized above all is the continuity of his thought. Gadamer adheres to the traditional chronology assigned to Plato's dialogues but not to the prevailing twentieth-century theory that this chronology can be arrived at by
establishing turning points at which Plato is supposed to have
distanced himself from positions he had taken previously. On
the contrary, he maintains, there is continuity in the line of
thought unfolded in Plato's work. What varies is only the way he
chooses to get at his subject matter.
To begin with there are the refutational, or elenchtic, dialogues, in which Socrates confronts the great sophists of his
timeProtagoras, Gorgias, Callicles, Thrasymachusand displays the emptiness of their claims to be able to teach virtue. In
truth theirs is a technical mentality, and what they teach is only a
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
the concern with arete. (The problem here is one of long standing, for Aristotle himself argued that Plato's introduction of the
question of arete in his lecture "On the Good" led to an incoherence, which would make it appear that the idea of the good is a
purely ontological doctrine that has no connection with the
practical question of arete.)
In regard to the Republic^ Gadamer points out that the extension of the discussion beyond book 4 does seem to have something arbitrary about it, in that book 4's discussion of the unity of
the virtues in knowledge is not continued, nor is what follows
tied in to, or derived from, this discussion. The concern is now
the theoretical education of the guardians, an education which in
book 6 will lead them out of the impure world of practical matters, the shadowy "cave," into the pure world of the forms.
Whether intended or not, the discussion here would seem to result in an absolute antithesis of theory and practice. Moreover,
there seems no doubt that, as a way of life, the former is far superior to the latter in Plato's eyes.
Gadamer maintains, however, that if one asks what question
is actually being addressed in the allegory of the cave, one sees
that the concern is not just, or even primarily, a theoretical, scientific one, but in fact an existential-practical question of holding steadfastly to the truth in the face of tests or refutations
(elenchoi)^ much as a soldier holds his ground in battle or a wrestler stands firm against attempts to throw himthis is the language Plato uses here. And what are these tests of mettle? The
guardians will find themselves in a conflict between honest execution of the duties of their office for the public weal and the
"pursuit of power after power," as we in the English-speaking
world might put it, using the words of Thomas Hobbes. The
guardians, in other words, will be tested by the flattery of both
their own desires for gratification and sophistic sycophants, flat-
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
Aristotle's mean between the extremes, which is to say, an ontological principle with very clear practical relevance.
In anticipating Aristotle's criticisms, it should be noted that, as
measuredness, the good in Plato must be distinguished, or "separated" intellectually, from the mixture itself. But if one abstracts
from this metaphor, one finds that, as measuredness, the good is
what Hegel calls ein Moment^ namely, an aspect of something
which does not exist separately from it. In short, it is in the thing
of which it is the structure. Thus, when we say that it is christon
(separate), we are not denying that it is in the thing. We are saying only that it must be distinguished from the thing in our
thinkingsomething that Aristotle would be the last to deny.
For he too raises the question ti estin ("what is it?"), a question
aimed at distinguishing the invariable Moment^ the "what" {ti)
in any "this-whatever" (tode ti).
These striking convergences of Plato's thought with Aristotle's
leave us puzzled about Aristotle's critique of Plato. Why would
he criticize Plato if in fact he and Plato are saying the same thing?
The question raised here is twofold: on the one hand, we must
ask what the ontological intent of his critique of Plato's idea of
the good is; on the other, we need to know the moral-theoretical
intent of that critique.
In resolving this twofold question Gadamer finds it best to
hold to the hermeneutical technique of displaying the phenomena with which Aristotle's three ethical treatises are concerned the ''mens auctoris" is of so Httle importance that the
issue of whether all three are by Aristotle himself need not even
be raised. The task is to repeat in ourselves {nachvollziehen) the
steps in the arguments, and thereby to bring to light the thing
they are about, what they are aiming at, or, as Husserl and Gadamer following Husserl put it, their ''Intention/' And it can be
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
established right away that whoever their author might be, they
are indeed "about" the same thing.
At the core of the argument in all three is the contention that
Plato improperly fuses the ontological and the practical in his
applications of the idea of the good. Consequently, it is argued
that from the start a clear separation must be made between the
practical good and the idea of the good in whatever explanatory
function it might have in the universe, and that ethics must be restricted to a consideration of the former. Aristotle justifies this
restriction by pointing out that the idea of the good is of no use
in the various technai, but this argument, far from weighing
against Plato, only affirms Plato's contention that the idea of the
good is not accessible to technical knowing, and that knowing
the good and knowledge in the technai are radically distinct, a
conclusion which, to be sure, was not at all the one "intended"
by the Aristotelian line of thought here.
Furthermore, despite his aversion to introducing physics and
metaphysics in the ethical treatises, Aristotle constantly finds his
arguments drawing him in the direction of ontological considerations which by rights he ought to pursue, but he is prevented
from pursuing them by the way in which he was put his question. In the first place, he resorts to the category argument, with
the idea of showing that, just as there is no one "being" in itself
but only a number of ways in which "is" can be said of something, so too there is no idea of the good, separate {christon)
and for itself, but only a number of ways in which the same word
"good" is used. As Gadamer points out, putting things this way
raises "uncomfortably more" issues than it should. For when he
is expressly pursuing questions of ontology, as he is in the CategorieSy Aristotle maintains that the relationship of the other categories, or ways of using "is," to the central category of "sub-
TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION
xxiii
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
good or best of and for all things, might bethe universal/ ontological structure of measuredness in Platoremains present in
Aristode, despite his stated purpose of limiting himself in his ethics to consideration of the ariston tn praktn, that is, what is
good or best in practical matters.
Aristode, of course, is a consummate phenomenologist who
wishes above all to avoid running distinct things together. But is
it just his "descriptive caution" that leads him to try to keep ontological and practical theory separate? Gadamer suggests that
there is something else fundamental in Aristotle's way of inquiring that leads him to put things as he does, namely, his orientation toward life science. Mathematically oriented thinking such
as Plato's would indeed lead to inquiry about the idea of the
good as an abstract structure of good things, much as one might
inquire about the abstract arithmetical structure of what is numbered or the abstract principles of harmony in what is harmonious. But that is not the orientation of Aristotle's questioning,
which gives primacy precisely to the concrete living thing. Consequently, the ariston tn pantn for him must not be a conceptual structure but instead a "mover" of other things, a first reality that is not epeikena tes ousias^ beyond existence as Plato's
idea of the good is, but an existent god. With the postulation of
this god, Aristotle does indeed carry out Socrates' demand that
we understand the universe starting from our moral experience,
that is, that we understand it in terms of what is good, and to
7. Gadamer uses the German allgemein in both its English senses, "general"
and "universal." I have had to rely on intuition, however fallible, in deciding
which to use in the translation, and on occasion I have switched back and forth
in the same passage where it seemed that Gadamer had both the more ordinary
"general" and the more terminological "universal" in mind. One interesting
point: the German allgemeinliterally "common to all"tends to sustain Aristotelian analogical thinking: the form, or eidos, is taken to be to koinon, or what
all particulars have in common.
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
this extent he too fuses the practical and the theoretical. But for
him this fusion does not mean that a discussion of arete should
lead to a discussion of the cosmos, even though the same sort of
structures might be constitutive in both. His concern is not with
abstract structures but with the "this here."
In the final chapter, "The Idea of Practical Philosophy,"
Gadamer addresses the broader issues raised by Aristotle's attempt to exclude any considerations of physics or metaphysics
from practical philosophy. This exclusion raises questions about
the relationship of the special field of theory that we call practical philosophy, that is, ethics and politics, to theory in general,
that is, physics, metaphysics, ontology, and cosmology. How
does the application of moral theory, as Aristotle understands it,
to moral practice differ from the application of scientific theory,
say, in technology or medicine? For the latter may certainly be
called practices also, and Aristotle even seems to take techne as a
model for practice in general. And just what application does
moral theory have in the first place? How does it bear on life as it
is actually lived? Finally, what is the relationship between the
two lives of reason of which Aristotle speaks, the life of practice
and the life of theory? What does Aristotle mean when he calls
the life of practical reason a second {deuteron) best? Does deuteron mean "another," or does it mean "inferior"? Or is its
meaning somewhere in between?
The first of these questions is introduced directly by Aristotle's
critique of Plato's idea of the good, for a good such as Plato
speaks of has, in Aristotle's view, precisely no application to life
as it is lived. In medicine all things aim at the specific good of
health, at a good, but an idea of the good in general is of no use
here whatsoever. And so it is with all practices. The good,
whichever specific good it might be, must be limited to the specific conditions of particular human practices. Here Aristotle
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
sees a fundamental confusion in Plato, in that he fails to distinguish between the use of "good" in ontology and its use in human practice. (As Gadamer pointed out to me during our discussion of this chapter, according to Aristotle we would have to
clearly differentiate between "good" snow insofar as it approaches the ontological good of pure whitenessperfect snow
as snow, as what it means to be snowand "good" snow in
practice, snow that is "good" for skiing, for instance. The ontological sense is wholly irrelevant when there is a question of
what ought to be done, for example, of whether one ought to go
skiing given the snow conditions.)
So the question comes down to this: What role could there be
for practical philosophy, if, as it would seem, each of the specialists would be best equipped to say what is good in their respective technical fields? Put another way, how does doing moral
philosophy contribute to arete, excellence in practice?
With that Gadamer has arrived at a crucial issue in his own
thinking, which, perhaps more than anything else, is aimed at
pointing out the mistake in making modern scientific technical
reasoning the paradigm for all reasoning. The relationship of
moral theory to practice is not at all the modern relationship of
theory to practice in which an objective, neutral theory can be
applied generally to particular problems. In distinction to producing something {techne, poiesis), doing the right thing is not
simply an application of general rules, and thus there is some8. Here Gadamer's thinking is diametrically opposed to the current conception of "moral reasoning" in American philosophy, and, of course, to any attempt to found that conception on Platonic-Aristotelian thought. W. Frankena,
for instance, writes in his Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, 1973, p. 2): "In this [Socrates*] pattern of moral reasoning [in the Crito] one determines what one should
do in a particular situation by reference to certain general principles or rules,
which one takes as premises from which to deduce a particular conclusion by a
TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION
xxiii
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii
TRANSLATOR'S
INTRODUCTION
xxviii T R A N S L A T O R ' S
INTRODUCTION
10. As Gadamer pointed out to me, C. Perleman's The New Rhetoric (South
Bend, 1981) argues convincingly that the Cartesian methodological model,
which provides the foundation for much contemporary logic and analytical philosophy in the English-speaking world, in fact falsifies language and discursive
reasoning as we actually experience it. S. Toulmin's An Introduction to Reasoning (2nd ed., Englewood Cliffs, 1984) represents a major advance in emancipation from Cartesianism insofar as it acknowledges the contextuality of reasoning,
that is, the differences in the occasions for it, and recognizes its dialogical, openended character. Even so, he has not quite succeeded in establishing "the hermeneutical priority of the question*' (WM 344) over the answer-proposition, or
"claim" as he calls it. All in all, it appears that, paradoxically, modern physics
has long since transcended the Cartesian method, whereas the human sciences
and logic, for which it was least appropriate to begin with, remain mired in it. F.
A. Heyek makes this point well in regard to economics in his Studies in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics (Chicago, 1967).
PREFACE
Hegel, it cannot be denied, did indeed grasp the speculative tendency in both Plato's doctrine of the ideas and Aristotle's substance ontology, since his thinking was so congenial to theirs.
And to that extent he is the first in modern times to break
through the schema of interpretation of Plato's doctrine of the
ideas shaped by Aristotle and further developed in Neoplatonism and the Christian tradition. Nor can one say that Hegel has
remained without any lasting influence on scholarship in the history of philosophy. Such good Aristotelians as Trendelenburg
and Eduard Zeller owe him a great deal. Above all, Hegel was
the first to make the philosophical significance of Plato's "esoteric," "dialectical" dialogues accessible. However, the unitary
effect^ connecting Plato's and Aristotle's logos philosophy
1. Wirkungseinheit. The word is related to Gadamer's concept Wirkungsgeschichte, the history of effects. The point is that far from being opposed to each
other, Plato and Aristotle belong to a continuous line of thought. They have in
mind the same subject matter, or Sache. Hence, rather than stressing the individual contributions of each, Gadamer finds it best to ask just what that subject
matter is which concerns both thinkers, and to explicate it phenomenologically.
One further point regarding Wirkung, or effect: since it is the subject matter and
not the indidivudal thinker that is primary, one must be careful to read "effect"
not as the effect that a thinker has on subsequent thinkers, but as the effect that
the subject matter, as it is passed on by tradition, has on an individual. It is not
the thinking subject that comes first, but the tradition that makes his or her
thou^t possible. Accordingly, Gadamer's wirkungsgeschichtliches Bewusstsein
might best be translated not as "historically effect/W," but as "historically effected/consciousness." TRANSLATOR.
PREFACE
PREFACE
the schema for which Hegel provided the inspiration which construed Greek thought as not yet able to conceive of the absolute
as spirit, life, and self-consciousness, did not promote a proper
evaluation of the fundamental significance of Greek thought for
modern philosophy.
Nicolai Hartmann's dissociation of himself from neo-Kantian
idealism stimulated me to try to penetrate Aristotle's thought,
and the French and English researchof Robin, Taylor, Ross,
Hardie, and, above all, the incomparable Hicksproved most
helpful in my endeavors. At that time, however, I fell far short of
seeing the unity in the logos philosophy, which started with
Socrates' questioning and then quickly deteriorated in the postAristotelian period, but which, nevertheless, permanently determined the entire conceptual apparatus of Western thought. Encountering Heidegger turned out to be decisive for me at that
stage. Heidegger had worked his way through both the CatholicPlato's idealism precisely because it appeared to them that Plato had set out to
uncover these same forms of consciousness. Plato's "ideas" were thus understood epistemologically rather than ontically, that is, as transcendental forms of
thought rather than the forms of things in themselves. Aristode's insistence that
the forms inhere in the thingshis doctrine of the enhylon eidosand on the
primacy of the tode ti thus seemed to them a regression to a naive realism. When
Gadamer refers to Neo-Kantianism as a mere "idealism of consciousness," he is
implicitly contrasting it with Fichte's and Hegel's idealism, which goes beyond
any epistemic-ontic dichotomy, and which, like Aristotle, whom Hegel favors (cf.
Logik II, "The Logic of the Concept"), views the forms of thought at one and the
same time as the forms of what is, that is, being. Heidegger's break with transcendental philosophy, be it either neo-Kantian or Husserlian, exposed the onesidedness of any idealism that founds itself exclusively on our consciousness of
reality. The question to be asked is not how consciousness construes reality, but
how reality, being, presents itself in our awareness of it. The key here is language,
in which that which is assumes its form for us. Language is the medium (Gadamer: Mitte) in which consciousness and world are joined. Hence it, not consciousness, is the "condition of the possibility" (Kant) of anything's being what it
is. TRANSLATOR.
PREFACE
PREFACE
PREFACE
turn out to be a truly unified work, just as the essay which I offer
here did not, but is instead a series of reflections and observations on the question posed.
It will be noticed that I have referred to recent scholarship
only sparingly. For one thing, I do not feel qualified to take a
comprehensive stand on it. For another, the presuppositions of
my own interpretation are all too different from those of other
research. I ask that the reader take what follows as an attempt to
read the classic Greek thinkers the other way round as it were
that is, not from the perspective of the assumed superiority of
modernity, which believes itself beyond the ancient philosophers
because it possesses an infinitely refined logic, but instead with
the conviction that philosophy is a human experience that remains the same and that characterizes the human being as such,
and that there is no progress in it, but only participation. That
these things still hold, even for a civilization like ours that is
molded by science, sounds hard to believe, but to me it seems
true nonetheless.
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT
ISSUE
If one surveys the last fifty years of research on ancient philosophyand it has been more than fifty years since Werner Jaeger's book on Aristotle gave new and significant impulses to
scholarship in this fieldone finds oneself more and more embarrassed by the results of that scholarship. In Werner Jaeger a
simple schema still prevailed which gave us the outlines of Aristotle's development from Platonist to critic of Plato's doctrine of
the ideas and, finally, to empiricist. Even at that time, to be sure,
one could have doubted that this construction was universally
valid. But, starting from a literary-historical interpretation of
Aristotle's Metaphysics^ Jaeger extrapolated a line of development backwards and forwards in Aristotle's divergence from the
doctrine of the ideas, and it could be said in his favor that his
construction was at least unequivocal, not to mention the fact
that his analyses exposed the artificiahty in the editing of the Aristotelian corpus up to that time. Even then, of course, it was
noted that Jaeger's construction yielded a "proto-physics" with
far less tangible contours than his "proto-metaphysics," and that
the proto-physics was, if seen from the perspective of literary history, not supported convincingly, given the state in which the
Physics books have come down to us. But most of all [his claim
to have found] a "development" in Aristotle's ethicswhich
Jaeger, with a certain drastic superficiality, managed to fit into
his construction by availing himself of only parts of the Eudem-
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
at
Reconstruction
9 T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
and seems not to have noticed at all that Plato himself had ever
placed his dogmatic theory of the ideas in question. In truth it is
almost absurdly obtrusive to the modern reader that the late
Plato of the Parmenides seems every bit the equal of Aristotle in
criticizing the doctrine of the ideas. Even the famous "third
man" argument is, as is well known, not only found in the critique of the ideas in Aristorie's Metaphysics^ but in the Parmenides as well. Certainly the worst of all hypotheses is to assume
that Aristotle ignored Plato's self-criticism and cold-bloodedly
repeated Plato's critical arguments in his own critique of Plato.
The picture looks even worse with regard to the "development" in Aristotle's ethics. Aristotle's presumed evolution from
a "politics of the ideas" (in the Protrepticus) through a still hesitant distancing of himself from Plato in the Eudemian Ethics to
the "mature" and self-confident position of the Nicomachean
Ethics is an arbitrary and contradictory construction of Jaeger's.
It is particularly unconvincing if one also brings Plato's late dialogues to bear on the issue, for the Philebus and the dialogue on
the statesman would be so far in advance of the supposedly
Platonizing beginnings of Aristotle's ethics that one can properly
ask onself just who is criticizing whom here. The development
schemathe postulation of the ideas apart by themselves, then
participation of the appearances in the ideas, then dialectic of
idea and appearance, and then, at the end, the equating of idea
and numberslowly begins to come apart.
Did Plato at first really underestimate the problem in the participation of the appearances in the ideas? Did he teach that the
ideas were apart for themselves until one day he recognized that
the problem of participation entailed in the postulation of such
ideas for themselves was altogether insoluble? Or do both postulations belong together: the ideas being for themselves, the socalled chorismos (separation), and the difficulty, to which one is
thereby exposed, concerning participation, or methexis^ as it is
10
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
11 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
With this new word, it seems to me, Plato wants to bring out
the logical connection of the many to the one, the thing "in common," a connection that was not implied in mimesis and in the
Pythagorean relationship of number and being conceived of as
the "approximation [of number] to being" (J. Klein)/ And beyond that: if we pay attention to Plato's set of synonyms as such,
we will have to take methexis as well as mimesis more "objectively," *that is, not as "acts" of subjectivity, our ways of conceiving of things, but as real relationships*. Mimesis refers to the
existence of what is imitated or represented, while methexis refers to coexistence with something. Of course, like the Latin
participatio and the German Teilhabe^ the word methexis evokes
the image of parts. That it does is shown by the early usage of
metechein.^ That the part belongs to the whole is precisely what
the new word underscores. Even in what is perhaps the earliest
allusion to the ideas, in the Euthyphro, the question is formulated in such a way that to hosion (what is pious), for instance,
could be a morion (part) of to dikaion (what is just).^ In the first
place that means that where one of them is, the other is too: the
part is present "in the whole." However Plato is obviously fully
aware of the paradox in a participation or taking part {Teilhabe)
that does not take a part, but participates in the wholeas the
day participates in the light of the sun. That he is, is shown by
the use of that very image in the Parmenides and is indirectly
confirmed by the set of synonyms I listed above. Indeed, as I
J. Klein, "Die griechische Logistik," in Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Mathematik, vol. 3, no. 1 (1934), and vol. 3, no. 2 (1936).
5. The predominant meaning is plainly to take part in something. But taking
part in something along with other things, links all the participants to each other.
6. Metoche obviously became terminological later in the academy and precisely in such usage as this where one speaks of the participation of a species in a
genus.
12
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
13 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
14
THE Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
15 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
"physikoi"hyle (matter) and both en he kinesis (whence motion comes)and he grants Plato and the Pythagoreans their
concept of the ti estin (what something is). (For the Pythagoreans, see 987a20, and for Plato, 988alO and, above all, 988a35.)
Unlike Aristotle, neither the atomists nor Anaxagoras nor the
Stoic school, and perhaps not even a * mathematically oriented'^
man like Strato in the Peripatetic school, can be understood
starting with the legomena (things we say). In other words, unlike Aristotle, they cannot be interpreted as successors of Plato's
"flight into the logoi (ways of saying things).'' In opposition to
the privileged ontological status that Plato accords the idea,
Aristotle emphatically asserts that the primary reality is the particular individual, the tode ti (this-something), but even so he remains within the framework of Plato's orientation toward the
logoi. His "primary" substance in no way excludes the eidos.^^
On the contrary, there is an obvious and indissoluble connection
between that "secondary" substancethe eidos that answers
the question ti estinand the primary substance of any given
"this."^^
12. In Amicus Plato^ Magis Arnica Veritas," Gadamer argues similarly that
what separates Plato from Aristotle is not at all Plato's emphasis on the eidos and
the idea, for Aristode emphasizes these no less than Plato. The difference (aside
from their divergent means of presentation) is that Plato approaches the eidos
through mathematics, Aristotle, in contrast, through life science. For Plato the
eidos, as an answer to ti estin ("what is it?"), is to be understood in distinction
from its appearancesas mathematical circularity, for example, is to be understood in distinction from circular things. Aristotle, on the other hand, sees the
eidos as that which a living thing (tode ti) actualizes as it grows from lack {steresis) to fulfillment. Thus, for Aristotle, the eidos is one predicatealbeit the
principal oneamong many others that may be said of some thing. And as such,
it, unlike circularity, cannot be thought of in separation from the subject of
which it is predicated, TRANSLATOR.
13. It seems risky to me to build an interpretation as extensively upon the
shifting meanings of "primary being" in the Categories and the late books of the
16
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
17 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
18
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
what they were doing was in any case not some sort of physics.
This distinction between mathematics and physics is a fundamental truth. Moreover, it is no coincidence that modern mathematical natural science can make a lot more sense of Plato's
treatment of the world of mathematics as an intelligible reality
for itself and as a prefiguration of nature than it can of Aristotle's derivation of the world of mathematical objects by abstraction {aphairesis) from physical appearances. Aristotle's 'solution' (Physicsy Beta 2) suppresses the actual problem of the
being of what is mathematical, which is to say, that very beingfor-itself which has such seminal relationships to the being of appearances as those discovered by modern mathematical physics
and anticipated by Plato in the Timaeus.^^
Things are similar in regard to moral phenomena. The distinction between justice itself and what is considered [dokei) to be
just is anything but an empty conceptual abstraction. On the
contrary, it is the truth of our practical consciousness itself, the
truth as Plato saw it graphically before his own eyes in the person of Socrates: true and just human behavior cannot be based
on the conventional concepts and standards to which public
opinion clings. Rather, such behavior must take as its standard
only those norms that transcend any question of public acceptance, and even the question of whether they can be, or are ever
found to be, fully realized, and that thereby display themselves
to our moral consciousness as incontestably and unalterably true
and right. This severance of the noetic from the sensory, of true
insight from mere points of viewthis chrismos, in other
wordsis the truth of moral consciousness as such. Again, it is
no coincidence that this insight of Plato's was dignified anew
14. Compare my "Dialetic and Sophism in Plato's Seventh Letter"^ and "Idea
and Reality in Plato's Timaeus.''
19 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
when the concern was to give morality a transcendental foundation. Kant's rigor is exceeded only by the rigor with which Plato,
in the dialogue on the true state, compels his Socrates to separate
the true essence of morality from what is held to be socially acceptable {Republic^ book 2) and to display this separation with
the example of a man who is held by all to be unjust and therefore put to death by use of every conceivable torture (361c ff.).
And finally, what if one now ventures out upon the entire vast
sea of the things we say and looks for a fixed orientation within
the ups and downs of speaking and reflection, amidst the very
unsteadiness, in other words, which had been cultivated at just
that time into the new art of speaking and arguing that Plato derogatorily labels sophism?^^ Once again, only the divorce of the
illusory way an argument sounds from its real meaning and of
the apparent cogency of what is said from the consequential
logic inherent in the subject matter can provide that orientation.
The so-called epistemological excursus of the Seventh Letter
(which I have already treated elsewhere^^) makes completely
clear, I think, what this divorce actually means. It is intended to
expose the weakness of sense experience, a weakness that threatens to prevent our reaching any mutual understanding.^^
The chrismos is not a doctrine that must first be overcome.
15. That the label was discriminatory, at least in the eyes of high society, is
demonstrated by the Protagoras 317b.
16. See "Dialectic and Sophism in Plato's Seventh Letter."
17. In his "Dialectic and Sophism in Plato's Seventh letter^"* Gadamer shows
how the "means" of languagename, image, concept, ideacan all assert
themselves instead of the thing that they were intended to bring to light. Thus
language, as that which "lets things be" (Heidegger), conceals as well as discloses: Sophism is quick to seize upon this potential of language to obfuscate and
confuse, for its concern is not with the truth but with manipulation. The "new
paideia," to which Gadamer often refers, was essentially instruction in the techniques of manipulation by means of language, TRANSLATOR.
20
THE Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
21 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
totle's critique of Plato, has been neglected in modern scholarship until now because of the dominant "historical" interpretive
schema deriving from Hegel '^that construes its subject matter in
terms ofantithetical relationships. Scholarship, it seems to me,
finds itself at a loss in regard to Aristotle's critique of Plato as a
consequence of this neglect. I see the beginnings of a better understanding of this critique in Anglo-American research, for example, in Cherniss's The Riddle of the Platonic Academy
which in my views gets somewhat bogged down, nonetheless, in
arguing against the traditionally accepted authority of Aristotle's
accountsand in Lee's Phronesis}^ Each rightly relies on, and
emphasizes, the dialectical, propaedeutical character of the critical introductory books in Aristorie's three ethical treatises. But
to do that is not enough. The task is to get back to the common
ground upon which both Plato and Aristotle base their talk of
the eidos.
The question about the good and, in particular, about the
good in the sense of arete, the "best-ness" of the citizen of the
polis (city-state), dominates Plato's writings from the very start.
And even if we leave aside the consensus that has been reached
today regarding the chronology of Plato's dialogues by and
large, there can be no doubt that in these writings the doctrine of
the ideas does not occur in the same way from beginning to end.
Naturally that does not mean that Plato came to this theory only
later on. It is time that we finally abandoned such a naive chron18. Cf. H. F. Cherniss, The Riddle of the Platonic Academy (Berkeley, 1945),
and E. N. Lee, "Exegesis and Argument," in Phronesis, vol. 1 (1973). Only after
I had completed this manuscript did two books appear that show that I am not
alone in my contention: A. Blum, Theorizing (London, 1974), and above all, J.
Findlay's thorough and speculative work, Plato. The Written and Vnivritten Doctrines (London, 1974), my review of which has appeared in the meantime in the
Philosophische Rundshau, vol. 24 (1977).
22
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
23 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
In contrast, the inclusiveness of the question posed in the Republic seems intended to counter the conventionality of the conceptions of arete found in the earUer discussions. Here the inquiry is about the sympasa arete (all-encompassing virtue) and
dikaiosyne (justice), and consequently about all aretai (virtues).
And at the end the idea of the good "beyond" all these is introduced. The knowledge sought is not there, and perhaps is not
even attainable, as long as one does not consciously look beyond
what is generally accepted to be knowledge. *In assessing just
how far we have gone beyond the Socratic dialogues here*, it is
of particular significance that Plato's brothers are the ones who
make the transition with Socrates in the discussion in book 2 of
the Republic.
The key notion in what is generally accepted to be knowledge
is techne (art). For Plato too, that goes without saying. Thus, in
the Apology^ Socrates finds among the handworkers, at least,
real knowledge of the special things they deal with. To be sure,
like other "wise" men, handworkers, too, fail us when the concern is the most important thing of all {ta megista) {Apology
22d), for which all human will to know ultimately strives.
Knowledge of the good is exactly what is not asked about in the
technai (arts) and by the technites (artisan-handworker). That it
is not is the standard argument used later by Aristotle in his critique of Plato {Nicomachean Ethics 1097a5 ff., henceforth EN;
Eudemian Ethics 1218b2, henceforth EE; Magna Moralia
1182b25 ff., henceforth MM). But this fact, far from weighing
against Plato, is precisely what gets Plato's Socrates started on
his way. His awareness of it is the basis of his superior "ignorance." Knowledge of the good would seem to be different in
kind from all familiar human knowledge. Hence, if measured
against such a concept of specialized expertise, it could indeed be
called ignorance. The anthrpine sophia (human wisdom) that is
aware of such ignorance must inquire beyond, and see beyond,
24
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
all the widespread presumed knowledge that Plato later will call
''doxa'' (belief, opinion). That the good can be caught sight of
only in this apoblepein prosthis looking at it in seeing past all
elseis not merely suggested by the negative result of the Socratic discussions. It is stated explicitly in the first dialogue in
which the acceptance of the ideas is actually proposed, the
Phaedo. The Phaedo thus stands as the noteworthy link between
the elenchtic or refutational dialogues, which must be attributed
to the early Plato, and his work on the ideal state.
The Phaedo has been singled out as the dialogue in which
Plato first introduces us to the doctrine of the ideas. The Marburg school in particular availed itself of Plato's introduction of
eidos as the best "hypothesis," for a somewhat forced assimilation of Plato to Kant. To be sure, Natorp's interpretation was
not lacking in insight into the exceptional role of the good. For
him the good was the principle of self-preservation. He saw
hypothesizing the eidos as a procedure for knowing this principle, and in this way he came to identify "idea" with "natural
law." What he had in mind, accordingly, was natural science. In
its ascending hypotheses the latter does indeed move ever closer
to the true order of the universe, and it is carried out in ongoing
determination of its object. For Natorp the "thing in itself" is
nothing more than the infinite, "unending task."
Today that interpretation sounds like false modernism. If, instead, one looks at the Phaedo as an interim stage on the way to
the idea of the good, another structural parallel emerges. After
all, the Phaedo too is a dialogue full of refutations, and in their
own way the interlocutors in the Phaedo represent a position
that is to be taken seriously, even if they defend it only halfheartedly, namely, "scientifically" founded materialism. They are Pythagoreans, of course, but Pythagoreans of a later generation
that is entirely at home in mathematics and science and that ab-
25 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
26
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
27 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
In this regard the idea of the good assumes a special significance within Plato's new noetic orientation. The Republic focuses on it, and it provides the basis for determining the order of
the polis and the psyche. Socrates' partners in the discussion
would be content if he were to speak about the good in the same
way as he had spoken earlier about dikaiosyne (justice) and sophrosyne (temperance) {Republic 506d). But whenever the conversation turns to this highest and ultimate subject, the speaker
in Plato begs off, saying that it would be unnecessary at that moment to go into it and perhaps even beyond his abilitiesjust as
in the Timaeus at 48a, for instance. And as a matter of fact, the
famous epekeina tes ousias (beyond all being) lends the idea of
the good a transcendence that distinguishes it from all other noetic objects, which is to say all other ideas.
That Plato uses only the word idea^ and never eidos^ for the
agathon^ smdy has something to do with that transcendence.
There is no denying, of course, that these words, idea and eidos^
were interchangeable in the Greek of that time and in the language usage of the philosophers too. Still, that Plato never
speaks of the eidos tou agathou (form of the good) indicates that
the idea of the good has a character all its own. Eidos always refers only to the object, as accords with its being neuter. In following the natural tendency of our thinking to objectify, the
Though Gadamer does not pursue the thought here, one might add that the
contemporary pseudo-scientific forms of "moral reasoning," utilitarianism in
particular, also confirm reason's need for unity insofar as they aim to carry the
scientific method over into the realm of practice, and thereby reestablish the
unity of reason. But here the result is the evisceration of moral thought, A.
Maclntyre, in After Virtue (Notre Dame, 1980), shows convincingly why such
attempts inevitably miscarry and end in "emotivism." In so doing, he corroborates Gadamer's argument that the methodology of modern natural science is
misplaced in many fields of the human quest for truthin aesthetic interpretation, politics, history, and, not least of all, moral philosophy, TRANSLATOR.
28
T H E Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
29 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
Now there seems to be a simple way to account for this privileged status and incomprehensibility of the idea of the good,
which distinguishes it from the remaining ideas. The idea of the
good, it is said, is precisely what comes "first" {to proton), and is
thus removed from any derivation. Thus it is what one was later
to call a principle. And, after all, this solution has generally been
the one resorted to ever since Aristotle, who was the first to introduce the concept of the arche (first principle). Furthermore,
wherever Aristotle introduces Plato's philosophy as an extension
of Pythagorean teachings, he does in fact treat it as analogous to
the Pythagorean doctrine of the peras (limit), and the apeiron
(unlimited, indefinite). He presents it in the doctrine of the hen
(one) and the ahoristos dyas (indeterminate two)the two principles of either the ideas or ideal numbers, as the case may be. It
seems consistent to grant the idea of the good in Plato the same
special place that Aristotle assigned to those two principles in his
account, for it would explain why any speaking of the idea of the
good, which is to say, all dialectical treatment of it, could never
take "the good itself" as its object directly, and why, consecapable concomitance (Heidegger: Gleichurspriinglichkeit) of unity and indeterminate duality is lost from view. It is far more accurate, he contends, to see
Plato's number doctrine as an extension of both the Pythagorean concepts: the
peras and the apeiron too. For Plato, whatever is unified or delimited as "one"
finds itself within the indeterminate duality {ahoristos dyas) of unlimited extremes, for .example, large and small, hot and cold, pleasure and pain, and so
forth. Hence what is determined as one, as a thing, is inseparable from the indeterminacy in which it is embedded.
This point has important consequences for Plato's ethical thought as Gadamer
understands it: human beings are never purely good, which is to say never purely
harmonized, integral, unified, but always struggling for (diamachesthai) unity
against those passions and drives that threaten them with dissolution and loss of
integrity. It is in this sense that Plato's ethics may be said to be "dialectical": reasonableness (nous, phronesis) is always in dialectical tension with the immediate
desire for what is "sweet" (hedone). TRANSLATOR.
30
THE Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
31 T H E Q U E S T I O N A T I S S U E
32
THE Q U E S T I O N AT ISSUE
111
s o C R A T I C K N O W1 N G
A N D N O T - K N O W1 N G
34
NOT-KNOWING
35 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
the Socratic question about the virtues and the resultant question
about the good. But, imperceptibly, Plato's Socrates proceeds
here to a theoretical knowledge of the good and of being. What
he calls dialectic is a sort of meta-science that opens up behind
the mathematical disciplines described here as pure theoretical
sciences.
Nevertheless, this science is not called "dialectic" unthinkingly. The heritage of Socrates and his art of dialogue lives on in
it. Accordingly, Plato often applies the word phronesiswhich
for Aristotle characterizes the virtue of practical reasonablenessin a wide sense. And he can also use it as synonymous
with both techne and episteme. This usage is never meant to imply that knowledge of the good is really the kind of knowledge
that techne is. [Rather, it shows that] the knowledge of the handworker plays such a paradigmatic role in any kind of knowing at
all that language usage conforms to it. Besides, there is indeed
something that practical reason and technical know-how have in
common: in a certain sense it is true of anyone who has a science
or art that his knowledge is based on grounds, reasons. That
holds for the doctor (an example of which Aristotle is particularly fond), for the mathematician, and for anyone at all who
claims to have knowledge as opposed to mere opinion.
Still, an essential difference between technical-theoretical reasonableness and practical reasonableness becomes discernible
here at once. When he who knows is required to give reasons in
any other case but practical matters, he can draw upon a general
knowledge that he has learned. It is exactly this recourse to general knowledge that characterizes techne or episteme. Hence, in
regard to these Plato speaks of a mathema (an insight to be
learned). But things look very different in respect to the exercise
of practical reason. Here one cannot rely upon previously acquired general knowledge, and yet one still claims to reach a
36
NOT-KNOWING
judgment by one's own weighing of the pros and cons and to decide reasonably in each case. Whoever deliberates with himself
and with others about what would be the right thing to do in a
particular practical situation is plainly prepared to support his
decision with nothing other than good reasons,^ and he who always behaves this reasonably possesses the virtue of reasonableness, of "well-advised-ness." {Euboulia was a political slogan of
the new paideia of that time.) Now it strikes me as significant
2. Gadamer is raising the issue here of moral argumentation, that is, how I
can justijpy to myself and others the choices that I make at the end of my moral
deliberations. Giving justificationlogon didonaimeans giving grounds, or
reasons, in support of my decision. In a society such as that in which Socrates
finds himself, a society, namely, in which "no one does what is just voluntarily,"
the mere patterning of one's behavior on paragons of virtue no longer suffices.
(See "Plato and the Poets" and "Plato's Educational State.") And appeals to traditional morality become empty rationalizations of self-interest. Consequently,
one must take a stand and be able to hold to itto justify it. The issue then becomes what sort of justification this will be, for it is clear that giving reasons, or
grounds, in scientific accounts of things is quite different. What the difference is
emerges clearly in regard to teaching and learning. Scientific knowledge and technical know-how can be taught. What is right, just, or good, on the other hand,
cannot.
With that we come to a critical question for Gadamer. On the one hand, he argues that we are dependent on tradition for justifying our moral choices and
places great emphasis on Sitten, or moral customs (see WM 11). The authority of
these alone, and not autonomous intellection, founds our morality. On the other
hand, he emphasizes here that Socrates, as an individual, knows a good that transcends the merely "conventional" morality to which hoi polloi, or the "many"
(Heidegger: das Man), uncritically subscribe. This apparent contradiction could
be resolved, I suggest, if one were to distinguish between traditional, as opposed
to conventional, morality. The latter, though its sophist advocates often appeal
to traditional authorities (Homer and the like) for justification, consists in fact of
nothing more than prudential accommodations coerced and acceded to, respectively, by unequal individuals whose sense of solidarity and community with
each other has vanished. What is convened on here is not what is sittlich, but
what is convenient for the most powerful. Here, might indeed makes right, and
no real justification is possible (cf. Republic, books 1 and 2). TRANSLATOR.
37 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
38
NOT-KNOWING
39 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
40
NOT-KNOWING
41 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
each one of us must have the right to his own opinion. I am referring to the question of the good in personal, as well as social, life.
Here everybody talks to everybody else, and each seeks to convince the other of the veracity of his opinion, especially when it
comes to political decisions. A debate about the good is always
going on, and as we saw, everyone would maintain that he was
doing nothing other than advancing reasons or grounds. The
claim made by the new paideia is founded on this circumstance,
in particular the claim it makes for its rhetoric, which is really
the new art. We see this foundation most clearly in the way that
Protagoras defends this claim for his rhetoric in Plato's dialogue
of the same name. He maintains that he educates people to be
good and, indeed, that he does this apparently by nothing other
than his rhetorical and dialectical art; he leaves aside any and
every specialized knowledge {Protagoras 318d). In opposition to
Protagoras's claim, Plato advances the true dialectical art of giving justification, which submits assertions about the good to
question and answer. Plato has a way of making both clear and
convincing that in order to keep oneself from being confounded
in such matters, something else is required besides a technique of
speaking and disputation and besides mere acuity. To be sure,
the ability to differentiate things according to their genera and
thereby expose confusions must be called an art. But more is required than mere acuity to do this.
And true dialectic entails still more. It provides practice in
holding undisconcertedly to what lies before one's eyes as right,
and in not allowing anything to convince one that it is not. Plato
can also call this true dialectic "phronesis," and with good reason. Here, in the question of the good, there is no body of
knowledge at one's disposal. Nor can one person defer to the authority of another. One has to ask oneself, and in so doing, one
necessarily finds oneself in discussion either with oneself or with
42
NOT-KNOWING
I attempted to make a convincing case for this point at the time that I
Platos dialektische Ethik.
Here again Gadamer has in mind that unity of logos (word, reason) and
(deed) that figures so prominendy in all his interpretations of Plato: any
43 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
his partners that this is what they lack. Plato gives self-understanding a more general meaning: wherever the concern is
knowledge that cannot be acquired by any learning, but instead
only through examination of oneself and of the knowledge one
believes one has, we are dealing with dialectic. Only in dialoguewith oneself or with otherscan one get beyond the
mere prejudices of prevailing conventions. And only the person
who is really guided by such pre-knowledge of the good will be
able to hold to it unerringly, Plato has various metaphorical
ways of expressing this fact. For example, he says [that such a
person can hold to the good] because the good "resides" in him,
or because it is "related [syggenes) to him." Thus, unlike the unfortunate victims of Socrates' refutational arts who do not understand themselves, the true dialectician does not allow himself
to be artfully misled past the truth. But the converse holds too:
whenever someone who knows how to give justification nevertheless goes astray, as Socrates himself occasionally does in
Plato's dialogues, he finds his way back and then knows how to
articulate what he intended to say better than before. That occurs, for instance, after Protagoras's famous repudiation of a
conversio falsa which Socrates commits (350c ff.).
question about arete and the good is not merely a question for intellectual inquiry but also an existential question of how I am to understand and lead my
lifea question of what I am to do.
One must be careful, however, not to conflate this element of "existential"
concern in Gadamer's reading of Plato with the subjectivism of modern existentialism. Neither Plato nor Gadamer begin with the individual subject, but rather
with the language we speak and the traditions and customs that constitute our
world and from which we as individuals derive. Hence gnthi s'auton, Socrates'
"know thyself," really means, know the logoi, our ways of saying things, which
lend our world its significances and values. We come to know the logoi and what
we are to do not in solitudinous "existing towards death" but in dialogue with
others and with ourselves. Wir sind ein Gesprch: we are a discussion (cf.
Phaedrus 23Od on Socrates* passion for discussion), TRANSLATOR.
44
NOT-KNOWING
45 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
46
NOT-KNOWING
47 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
48
NOT-KNOWING
was and always will bein a new way. Knowledge about arete
is always sustained and transmitted by all. But the sophist does
what everybody does with "art," and that is what he means
when he praises his new "art" as the perfection of education. We
see this claim equally in Plato's characterizations of both Protagoras and Gorgias. And a lot of what we know of both these men
from other sourcesfor example, that they were held in high esteem by societyaccords with Plato's portrayal of them.
But now the Socratic question overturns the whole sophist
claim. Plato shows in the dialogues named for these two sophiststo which group the Republic^ book 1, the so-called "Thrasymachus," also belongswhat ill fate this paideia's new claim
to be knowledge actually bodes. Theirs is a technical mentality,
which passes itself off as arete without really being arete at all.
This pretense is exposed by displaying its radical consequences
in radical immoralists of the cut of a Thrasymachus or a Callicles. In the Protagoras the unmasking is not as explicit, but certainly the way is cleared for it. For there is no doubt that there
Protagoras ought to be forced into a radical hedonism as the true
consequence of his concept of knowledge. Precisely by decking
himself out in another garb and thereby evading this radical consequence, he makes clear negatively that it is a conclusion he
would have to draw. In truth, his pragmatic knowledge and his
art are incapable of establishing any other norms or defending
them. Then, in book 6 of the Republic (493 ff.), this point is
stated explicitly: the so-called sophists are actually the hirelings
of public opinion. Every one of them teaches nothing other than
the opinions that people form when they get together. And that
is what they call wisdom. The new paideia appears to accommodate itself to the traditional system of norms. But this appearance, we see, is false and only obscures the fact that the
traditional concepts of arete cannot be given sufficient justi-
49 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
fication and conceals that this world of norms has itself become
equivocal.
Thus the purpose of Socrates' pointing to the paradox in the
knowledge of virtue is precisely to show that the traditional
world of norms has come to need justification, but that it is incapable of being justified: what this new paideia is really claiming
is that it is a techne of success. When it purports to impart a
knowledge founded in [what for it is] the self-evident continuing
validity of the world of norms, its apparent knowledge proves
false, and its sureness of being able to justify itself illusory. As we
saw, its pretense is exposed in the Protagoras in the caricature of
an art of living that would amount to technical knowledge
{metretike techne) of how to get the greatest amount of pleasure
possible. But most of all, its pretense is exposed in the paradox
that all arete, despite its claim to be knowledge, is unteachable.
One now sees how skillfully Plato's Protagoras is composed,
and what a powerful statement its dramatic setting makes just by
itself. Plato's idea of confronting the famous sophists of the time
(Protagoras, Gorgias, Hippias, Thrasymachus) with his Socrates
appears to be an invention all his own, and it serves the purpose
of defending Socrates against the fateful equation of him with
the sophists, an equation that was the reason for his tragic condemnation. Xenophon reports only one other comparable pairing with a sophistwith Hippias (Memorabilia^ Delta 4)but
it is set up quite differently. The sophist knows Socrates well. He
complains that Socrates is forever saying the same things, and
that one can never get a positive answer out of him (the theme of
the Clitopho), Therefore Hippias insists that Scorates himself finally say something positive about to dikaion (what is just). But
what Xenophon has Socrates say in response could hardly be
based on authentic remembrances. Xenophon's apologetic motif
is all too trivial and transparent. Socrates may have argued be-
50
NOT-KNOWING
51 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
52
NOT-KNOWING
need only ask oneself Plato's question: Who was this Socrates
and what was his knowledge? After all, he had declared that precisely knowing that one does not know is the real human wisdom. His teaching could never be different from what it always
is, namely, demonstrating that his partner does not know, and
by doing that, making it urgent that one know and give justification. For someone who has come to seek and question on his
own, the pretentious assumptions that Meno, for example, has
learned from the likes of Gorgias and advances himself are
empty. And emptier still is a sophistry that would argue someone
out of seeking and questioning altogethersuch a sophistry,
that is, as Meno produces with blind acuity. The significance of
the Meno is'that here Plato expressly thematizes the aporia (perplexity) in which the other Socratic dialogues tend to end.
Like these other dialogues, the Meno begins with a series of
failed attempts to define arete that disclose sometimes more,
sometimes less, clearly that the sole reality behind moral conventions is the pursuit of power. The last answer that Meno ventures virtually says as much. He appropriates the poet's Hne:
charein te kaloisi kai dynasthai (to delight in the beautiful and
have power) in such a way that arete would mean nothing else
but having the power to acquire the beautiful thing that one desires (77b). But Plato takes a new step here. He shows that reaching the aporia in which Meno's attempts to determine the nature
of arete end is the precondition for raising the question of arete
in the first place. But here, raising the question means questioning oneself. The knowledge in question can only be called forth.
All cognition is re-cognition. And in this sense it is remembrance
of something familiar and known.
The conversation with Meno makes this fact clear e contrario.
Meno appears on the scene as one who wants to acquire the new
wisdom as cheaply as possibly, and he bolts when he is about to
53 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
54
NOT-KNOWING
things, and that the soul is consequently immortal. On the contrary, any such claim that it has been proved is explicitly retracted (86b). The only thing accepted is the practical certainty
that we are better off holding firmly to the belief that one can indeed seek the truth, and that one should not allow oneself to be
misled in this search by sophistic objections. And it is accepted
logi kai ergbi (in word and deed) (86c). Hence the mythical horizons within which Plato places this certaintyand not without ironic ceremoniousnessserve essentially only to display
and explicate the capacity of the human mind to place things in
question.
The Phaedo demonstrates fully and convincingly that we are
not dealing' with a religious truth here. There the anamnesis
theme is taken up anew, and once again it is explicated quite
unmythologically. The way in which the doctrine of preexistence
is "proved" hereby the "prior knowledge" that underlies all
knowledgeeven has a comical side to it. To be sure, it is made
clear here that as religious heritage what this preexistence proof
demonstrates with its pseudo-stringency, is worthy of solemn respect. But this comical aspect of the argument makes clear that
what is 'proved' hardly lends itself to a rational legitimation in a
style such as this. In particular, the sharpening of the argument
after Simmias's objection that knowledge could, after all, be
given to one at birth makes the discrepancy between the mythical claim and the logical concepts with which the argument proceeds especially palpable. Obviously it is with this discrepancy in
mind that Plato has Socrates now venture the following argument (Phaedo 76d): since knowledge cannot be attained after
birth, it must derive from a "previous" Ufeunless, that is, it is
acquired at the moment of birth. But after all, as the initial ignorance of the newborn shows, it is not present at birth. So at one
and the same time, it would be acquired and losta pretty piece
55 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
56
NOT-KNOWING
tempts to solve the problem by doubling are wrong and to recognize the true solution when it is presented to him. As we know,
he does not find it on his own. Socrates has to show it to him
(85e). That fact is of no concern, however. The point is that he
himself recognizes it as the solution he seeks.
It should be noted that we are dealing with a mathematical insight here, that is, not with a result of empirical generalization.
The slave already knows enough of mathematics to accept without question that the problem put to him is eidetic-universal and
to grasp it as such without giving it a second thought. The entire
path along which the slave is guided to his eidetic insight proceeds through eidetic terrain. Even his first mistaken attempts at
solving the problem are meant to be eidetic. They are wrong only
mathematically. For him, unlike his master, the insight that his
proposals are false is not anything that might cripple him. Instead, it actually makes the right insight possiblean insight
that would require only sufficient repetition of the exercise to be
stabilized in him as genuine mathematical knowledge (85c ff.).
Here, however, this mathematical example stands for everything that Plato would call real knowledge or insight. One always has aletheis doxai (true beliefs) in oneself concerning what
ones does not know {Meno 85c). Indeed, just this fact emerged in
the mathematical lesson: the refutation of false assumptions is
needed in order for these to be recognized as false, but that entails that one always already^' has some idea of what the true as19. Immer schon. This common tum of speech has special importance in
Heidegger's work and also in Gadamer's. It underscores the fact that I actually
never was, and never will be, in the state of unprejudiced objectivity which the
Enlightenment considers prerequisite for valid knowing. Put another way, I am
never in an "original position" (Rawls); rather, I can understand what I encounter within my world only because of the pre-knowledge that I "always already"
have. Implied here is Heidegger's and Gadamer's theory of the circularity of understanding. Gadamer extends Heidegger's line of thought in arguing for the in-
57 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
58
NOT-KNOWING
59 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
hold for every sort of real knowing. The dialectical art of making
distinctions allows us to distinguish the good from the bad or, as
we might say with moral reserve, to distinguish the right thing to
do from everything which would not be right. But in its full extent this art has to be applicable to knowing anything worth
knowing. In the end, the structure of anamnesis proves to be coextensive with all possible questioning. Questioning is seeking,
and as such it is governed by what is sought. One can only seek
when one knows what one is looking for. Only then, only with
what is known in view, can one exclude the irrelevant, narrow
the inquiry down, and recognize anything. That is what the
Meno teaches us.
Another illustration, albeit negative, of what Plato has in mind
is the failure of Socrates' sophist interlocutors when they want to
do the questioning themselves. The questioner seems to them to
play a superior role, to which, accordingly, one should aspire.
But questioning is not a technique of role playing. The questioner is always one who simultaneously questions himself. The
question is posed for him just as it is for the other person. What
we have here is the dialectic of dialogue, and its logical structure
is simultaneous synopsis (seeing things as together one) and
dihairesis (division, or differentiation). Both recognition of what
one knows oneself to bethat is, recognition of how one understands oneselfand recognition of everything one knows are always at one and the same time synoran eis hen eidos (seeing together as one form) and kata gene dihairesthai (separating
according to species), which is to say, differentiation. We always
find ourselves in dialectical tension with the prejudices which
take us in and parade themselves as knowledge but which really
mistake the particularity and partiality of a given view for the
whole truth. That holds for both the person asked and the person asking. Plato's most abstract way of expressing this phenom-
60
NOT-KNOWING
61 S O C R A T I C K N O W I N G A N D
NOT-KNOWING
62
NOT-KNOWING
bind Plato and Aristorie together and, for once, to read the
moral-philosophic paradoxes of Plato's writings with an eye to
what he and Aristotle have in conimon. The next step in this direction will be an exploration of the relationships between the
Protagoras and book 4 of the Republic.
111
THE
POLIS
AND
K N O W L E D G E OF
THE G O O D
The unity and multiplicity of the so-called cardinal virtues became a problem in the Protagoras^ and Socrates demonstrated
therealbeit often with sophistic meansthat these cardinal
virtues are reducible to being knowledgeable. As we emphasized
above, the sophistry of these means presupposes in principle that
Plato is secure in what he is aiming at: the sophistry is there to
serve his purposes. Being able to give justification, being responsible for what one does, is essential to the ethical disposition, and
that implies that the whole of one's ethical consciousness and
ethical being are at stake here. Consequently, giving justification
cannot be limited to any single moral phenomenon, tendency to
behave, or special skill. Obviously Socrates has this fact in mind
when he plays his game of refutational dialectic and juxtaposes
particular virtues with the good. In essence, however, his doing
so amounts to the same thing as Aristotle's rejection in the
Nicomachean Ethics of the separation of the aretai from each
other and his assignment of the very same unifying function to
the logos (rational principle) of phronesis (EN 1144b). The
problem figuring in many of Socrates' numerous elenchoi (refutations) becomes especially easy to get hold of in the Protagoras,
insofar as the question concerning the unity of the many virtues
63
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 64
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
65
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 66
ented toward external appearances. Hence both of the alternatives are misleading. Arete is not to be thought of at all as a unity
or multiplicity of ways of behaving primarily presented to an observer. Rather, it is self-knowledge, phronesis. In the end our behavior attains its unity when our actions are undertaken in regard to the good.^
To be sure, Plato's Republic confronts us with a difficulty: it
introduces the question of knowledge of the good only in a second stage of the argument, as if it were an afterthought. Once
the aretai have all been shown to have the character of knowledge, the analogy between the harmony of the classes in the polis
and the harmony of the soulits "health"would seem to suffice as an answer to the question about the definition of justice.
With the conclusion drawn in book 4 the goal has been reached.
As is common knowledge, it is only after this apparent conclusion that the question about the megiston mathema (the greatest
insight), the idea of the good, arises, leading us further along
winding paths. It is striking that this question about the good
does not follow, as one might have expected, from an attempt to
1. The thought here can be traced to Kierkegaard too (cf. WM 91). In rising
above the aesthetic "stage on life's way" to the ethical stage, I move beyond a life
that consists in discontinuous "great moments" of aesthetic exhilaration to a life
that maintains continuity in temporal transienceto a life, in other words, in
which unity and integrity are established within what would otherwise disintegrate in the flow of time. A question worth pursuing would be the extent to
which Heidegger's reception of Kierkegaard in SZ opened up new possibilities
for understanding Plato, say in Gadamer's PDE, It is striking that in ethical matters at least, Kierkegaard and Plato emerge in Gadamer's writings as astonishingly close. That by no means says that Plato is an "existentialist" (see ch. 2, n.
9). Of interest to Gadamer is the transition from the aesthetic, to the ethical stage
on life's way, not the transition from the ethical to the religious stage, in which
the existential decision made in anxiety supersedes dutiful and consistent adherence to what ought to be done (Plato: to deon; Gadamer: das Tunliche).
TRANSLATOR.
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
67
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 68
flict with the task of poHtical leadership for which the guardians
are chosen {Republic 519d ff.). Left to themselves, those who
have been freed from the cave of murky sense experience and
practical routine, those who have been set free for theria, it
could be objected, cannot possibly feel any impetus to return to
the cave of politics, in which all knowledge is inexact and where
things always go wrong.
Of course Socrates sees no difficulty in defending his position
against this objection {Republic 519c): in his ideal state there is
no private sphere for the individual at all, and hence no question
of the happiness of the individual either. Accordingly, he rejects
the question of whether those dedicated to theria would not be
done an injustice if they were forced away from the higher fulfillment they find in theria and, for a time at least, were constrained to pursue the ugly business of politics. Not their own
happiness is at issue but the happiness of the whole. Indeed, one
even trusts that these ideal guardians of the ideal state will not
feel externally coerced but will submit understandingly to the
political task assigned to them (520d).
Nonetheless, one must ask oneself if this is really supposed to
be an answer to the question of how an existence devoted to
theria sees itself in this world of appearances, the world of social power structures? In Plato's state in the clouds, of course, all
problems that would otherwise confuse and distort political and
social life are solved ideally. Everyone does what he is supposed
to do, and consequently everything is ordered in such a fashion
that the whole prospers and flourishes. Just like all the other
classes, those who have knowledge and who have been brought
up to be leaders of the polis and have been educated in science
have careers in the ideal state defined for them in advance, which
they must follow. Knowing himself to be almighty, the poet who
invents this ideal state is not bothered by the fact that the guard-
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
69
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 70
T H E P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
71
opposite of what is now].) Surely one must take all the institutions and structures in this model city as dialectical metaphors.
Of course, reading dialectically does not simply mean taking the
opposite of what is said, to be the true belief. Here, reading
dialectically means relating these Utopian demands in each instance to their opposite, in order to find, somewhere in between,
what is really meantthat is, in order to recognize what the circumstances are, and how they could be made better. Per se, the
institutions of this model city are not meant to embody ideas for
reform. Rather, they should make truly bad conditions and the
dangers for the continued existence of a city visible e contrario.
For example, the total elimination of the family is intended to
display the ruinous role of family politics, nepotism, and the idea
of dynastic power in the so-called democracy of Athens at that
time (and not only there).
Indubitably, one must read the argument for the rule of philosophers just as dialectically as everything else that is said about
this splendid state in the clouds. This argument is not meant to
specify a way to actualize the ideal city. But it is not intended either solely as a negative demonstration of its impossibility.
Rather it uncovers somethingand not only the obvious fact
that no polis would let itself be governed by such philosophers.
Is the paradox of the philosopher-king not also meant to give us
the positive insight that both aiming at the good and knowing reality pertain to the political actions of the true statesman as well
as to the true theoretical life? In support of this thesis one could
appeal to biographical factsI mean Plato's repeated attempts
with Dionysius II in Syracuse. Plato certainly had no intention of
proposing communal women and children to this tyrant, nor
later to his friend Dion, to whom he made very reasonable
recommendationsfor instance, that of a general amnesty. But
the same point could be deduced directly from what Plato says
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 72
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E O F T H E G O O D
73
culation of the marriage number (546d). The mystifying, yet ingenious, thing about this invention of Plato's, it seems to me, Ues
in the fact that this comical shortcoming of a comical institution
symbolically displays why no system of human social order,
however wisely planned or thought out, can endure. What can
only be brought about by an artfully contrived institution will in
the end be done in by its own artificiality. This is the insight
Plato gives us here. The successful calculation of mating, which
insures the continuance of the ideally ordered polis, fails not because of malevolence or external forces, but because of its own
complexity. That is a true statement concerning something we
all know to be the reality of any humanly planned economy: be
the rationality of the planning ever so highly developed, in the
execution of it there is always the power of coincidence, and
above all, there is always human shortcoming. Because we are
human beings, not because we planned mistakenly, even an ideal
self-sustaining organization in full accord with the plan for it
will nevertheless go under in the rolling seas of historical life. To
say this is not at all to deny the task of reason to shape action
reasonably. Book 8 of the Republic undertakes to show that wisdom and reason are not only at home in the game of utopianism,
but that in our dealings with "real" historical life too, foresight
and insight are attainable within certain limits. The doctrine of
the cycle of state constitutions presented in book 9this brilliant example of intellectual penetration of the course of historyconfirms that human reason is not restricted to the realm
of Utopia and strict ideal order. On the contrary, it is fully capable of expanding into the historical world of vague regularities.
The disorder of human things is never complete chaos. Ultimately this disorder represents the periphery of a sensibly ordered universe that under any circumstances would have its periphery. That * there is order, albeit finite in human events'^ is
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E O F T H E G O O D 74
brought out above all by the fact that in Plato's dialogical fiction
the Timaeus follows the Republic. To display the republic that is
really supposed to come into being, the entire grand project of
the demiurge's ordering of the world, which the Timaeus portrays, is necessary.^
The question that guides our inquiry here is how Plato unites
his concern with the Socratic question about arete and the good
with his scientific program. If we are to find an answer to it, the
requirement that we read dialectically must also be taken to
heart in regard to the assertions in the Republic concerning scientific knowing/ In respect to interpreting the allegory of the
cave, reading dialectically entails that we abandon all attempts
at an exact interpretation of this wonderful and many-layered
metaphor regarding its bearing on the theory of scientific knowing. Instead, we must focus on only one point, namely, what
function the allegory has within the course of the discussion.
Here there is no ambiguity: it is intended to dispel the illusion
that dedication to philosophy and the theoretical life is wholly irreconcilable with the demands of political practice in society and
the state. The theme is the blinding by the brightness that befalls
5. The demiurge, it will be noted, is always confronted with intractable
anange (necessity). Hence he can create order, but never complete order. "Demythologized," what we have here is the principle of unity or order within indeterminancy, the one and the indeterminate two (see ch. 1, n. 22). TRANSLATOR.
6. The German appears here in adjectival form: wissenschaftstheoretisch.
Wissenschaftstheorie (translated here as "theory of scientific knowing") is the
theory of science in a broad sense of science that would include not only the natural, but the social and human, sciences, which is to say, any body of knowledge.
One of its major concerns is methodology. Of particular importance in this work
will be the method appropriate to the "science" of practical philosophy, and how
it differs from method in episteme and techne respectively. Gadamer maintains
that Plato and Aristode are alike in arguing that the method of practical philosophy must be rigorously distinguished from any sophistic "technical" method.
TRANSLATOR.
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
75
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 76
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
77
remain caught in moral, political conventions. This fact is displayed particularly well when, in first introducing the paradox
of the philosopher-king, Plato places him alongside the eroticist,
who loves everything beautiful, and the spectacle-seeker. All
three are alike in the universality of their passion. Glaucon is so
little mindful of the sciences when the philosopher is spoken of
that he even interchanges the spectacle-seeker's curiosity with
thirst for knowledge (475d). That conflation, of course, is seriously misleading. Whoever is drawn to spectacles, whoever is
swayed back and forth in indiscriminate curiosity about everything there is to see, has in truth no similarity whatever to the
philosopher. Indiscriminate passion for novelty constitutes the
extreme opposite of philosophy, for philosophy has to do with
the just and the unjust, the good and the bad, or, as Plato puts it,
with discriminating between the beautiful and the ugly.
To be sure, in what follows it is shown that such a sense for
the just, the good, and so forth, implies a fundamental distinction between what is known and what is believedthe distinction, namely, between the "one beautiful thing" itself and everything which only participates in it {ta metechonta). To this
extent, that sense of the just and the good is indeed philosophy,
which is to say, that it passes beyond the question of the conventional "just and good." This notwithstanding, the allegory of the
cave is, as we saw, applied to nothing other than the life of the
polis. It is stated expressly that those who have returned will
have to deal with the shadows and images of the dikaion, which
is to say, with what Plato calls ta tn anthrpn (human things)
(517c) or ta anthrpeia (that which is of human concern) (517d).
Accordingly, one ought not to take the description of the cave
and the superior insight of those who have been led upward to
the true sun to imply that those who have thus been liberated
are, by virtue of their comprehensive knowledge of all true
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 78
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E O F T H E G O O D
79
lern in the Phaedrus (268 ff.). Therewith an eye to the knowledge of rules in rhetoricmedicine and the arts of writing
drama and composing music are cited, in all of which there is
also "general" knowledge. That a natural ability remains indispensable is not disputed (269d), but besides having that ability,
education in the art is necessary. Moreover, as the Phaedrus
shows by means of Socrates' ironic dissimulation, in the case of
the art of oratory that means that the true art presupposes both
dialectical knowledge of the subject matter and dialectical
knowledge of "souls." Only he who has this double knowledge
is a true rhetorician. Here Plato specifically adds that the rhetorician must also be able to apply all this knowledge correctly in
practice: ''dei de tauta hikans noesanta meta tauta theomenon
auta en tais praxesin onta te kai prattonmena'' (it is necessary
that once he knows these things sufficiently, he see them actualized in practice and being done) (271e). Clearly this necessity
pertains to every techne. Moreover, it would seem to me that the
art of measuring what is "fitting," spoken of in the Statesman^
also accords with this argument. We shall return to this point
later.
In any case, this hermeneutical problem of concretizing [a general rule] has no bearing on the relationship between politics and
philosophy or on the tension between the political and the theoretical ideals of life. Certainly, application of a techne always
presupposes practice and experience. But the procedure remains
one and the same, whether it be the practice of the educated specialist who knows the reasons for the practical measures he takes
or only the action of an experienced man. On the other hand,
when Plato expatiates in his allegory on the relationship between
the political practitioner and the person who returns to the cave,
his concern is to draw a distinction of a very different sort.
Whether the political practitioner in this or that field is at the
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 80
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
81
That it is accords quite well with the fact that in book 6 Plato
sets the question of knowledge about the good in total opposition to a Hfe led in doxa, that is, in mere conventions, and that to
this end he even places knowledge of the good in analogy to
knowledge of one's own advantage (505d). There we read that
as far as the just and the beautiful are concerned, many might
content themselves with an appearance, with what is currently
accepted, ta dokounta. With regard to the good, on the other
handand that means even with regard to the benefit that one
hopes to have from somethingthe consensus of others is of no
importance to an individual. Only the real advantage counts [ta
onto). It is instructive that here the rationality in the relationship
of means to ends suffices to illustrate the knowledge involved in
knowing the goodsuffices, that is, to establish irrefragably
that it transcends all conventions. Nobody contents himself with
merely conventional concepts when the issue is the utility of the
means to be chosen.
Now one could also view the so-called technai (the knowledge
of the handworker and the so-called sciences) in the same way,
that is, as knowledge of the right means, and hence as knowledge
of a relative good. Evidently that was the reason why techne
knowledge was paradigmatic from early on for the Socratic art
of persuasion. But this knowledge is not the knowledge that is of
ultimate importance to human beings as human beings, for it
fails to provide an ultimate justification. In other words, it
knows nothing of "the good itself."
Plato has various names for the knowledge of the good,
knowledge which by giving justification sets itself apart from all
technai and epistemai (sciences). For example, he speaks of it as
a dynamis tou dialegesthai (ability to distinguish dialectically)
(532d), a methodos (method), and an episteme (333c). In so do-
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 82
T H E P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
83
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 84
gard to Plato's thought are never fulfilled. In the realm of dialectic, there is no differentiation that would correspond to differentiation in the mathematical sciences.
Thus this curriculum of education, insofar as it leads through
the sciences up to dialectical knowledge of the good, leaves us
with a peculiarly ambiguous result. The deduction and summary
with which the previous arguments conclude would appear to be
the crowning piece in the theoretical ascent to dialectic. Yet, in
fact, they are more than that. The issue is now the good itself,
which would correspond to the sun in the allegory, and now the
question of what this is, is finally supposed to be answered without a metaphor (oud' eikona) (533a). It turns out, however, that
this particular question literally dissipates in the universality of
[inquiry concerning] everything that truly is: the dialectician is
characterized as one who strives to find what any and every existent reality truly is {auto ge hekastou peri ho estin hekaston)
(533b), one who grasps the logos (concept, definition) of being of each thing {ton logon hekaston lambanonta tes ousias)
(534b). This characterization is given in order to distinguish dialectic from the mathematical sciences, which are to be termed
mere dianoia (understanding), and in this regard it is entirely
accurate.
But then the good too is said to be an objectsupposedly in
"just the same way" {hsauts) [as the other realities]: like the
ousia hekastou (being of each), one must separate the idea tou
agathou (idea of the good) from everything else, and, as if in battle, one must endure tests of mettle and make one's way undistractedly through every challenge aptti ti logi (with a logic
that cannot be overthrown). If not, one will recognize neither the
good itself nor anything else which is good.
We must pause here. This "in just the same way" is a source of
no small difficulty. Certainly one can comprehend that in the
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
85
case of the good too, it is the procedure of the dialecticiangiving justificationthat alone can prevent our being confused by
false similarities, being guided by mere conventions, or being seduced by flattery. In the imagery of the Republic, book 2, the dialectician is like a "philosophical dog" [in his faithfulness to his
task]. But it is astonishing even so that the idea of the good appears here merely ordered alongside the other ideas. This equation suggests that it is just one idea among others. At the very
most, one could say only that the dialectical differentiation of
this idea from all others is especially difficult to carry out because of the particularly strong interference of interests and preferences in this case. And perhaps one is also supposed to detect,
if one listens carefully, that cognition of the good, which is either
to be won or lost here, is more important than anything else for
one's whole life. That it is, is brought out negatively by the juxtaposition of "life here" with Hades (534c).^ But no retraction of
the likening of the good to the other ideas is implied thereby. To
say that one can only know everything else good if one knows
the idea of the good is to say practically nothing, for this way of
putting things holds just as much for all the other ideas also. At
the beginning, too, the question about the good was introduced
with the same schematic formulanamely, that it is the thing
by virtue of which everything else {kai dikaia kai talla [what is
8. "And it is the same in regard to the good: if someone is unable to define
the idea of the good by giving a reasonable account of it, abstracting it from all
else, and fails to get through to it, getting through all tests and seeking to defend
it against all these with a logic not to be overthrown (aptti ti logi), as if in
battleif all this be true of him, you would not say that he has recognized either
the good itself or any other good. Rather, you would say that if he has attained
to any image of it at all, he has done so through opinion and not through science,
and that in dreaming and slumbering this life away, he will land in Hades before
ever awakening here and sink into the deepest sleep" (Republic 534c). (Text provided by translator.)
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 86
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
87
with the sun at 508e in the following way: what gives aletheia
(truth) to what is known and gives the capacity to know it to the
one who knows it is supposed to be the idea of the goodjust as
visible things are visible and the eye can see, thanks to the sun
that sheds light. Thus, to begin with, the idea of the good is the
cause of knowledge and of truth (epistemes or gnses, and
aletheias). Obviously the point is the analogy with seeing and the
visible, and their dependence on light. Just as seeing and light are
sunlike, so too, knowing and truth are to be called "good-like,"
even if they do not yet count as the good itself, that is, as ton
agathou hexis: the character the good has about it, what it is.
And to this extent the analogy is indeed most expressive. One
can completely set aside the question of the cause of the light, the
question, that is, about the sun. True beingthe noumena (objects of intellection), the ontos onta (things that really are), the
eide (forms)appears in thinking in the same way that light
connects the visible with seeing: the good makes thinking what it
is. The capacity {dynamis) for something is, after all, always defined by what it is a capacity for, and by what it effects {eph'
hoite esti kai ho apergazetai) (477d). Thus, what lights up
(katalampei) as aletheia te kai to on (truth and being) (508d) allows thinking to be thinking, that is, allows it to noun echein
(have reason, be right, avoir raison) in that nice double sense of
both getting an insight and being capable of reasoning. With this
formulation it seems clear that the whole realm of the noeta
(things thought of) has been opened up.
The metaphor of light accomplishes all this, and it is significant that in the scene in the Parmenides in which the young
Socrates is supposed to clarify the participation of the many particulars in the idea, he takes refuge in the same marvelous metaphor. * Plato's own recourse to the metaphor of light is plainly
behind Socrates' answer in the Parmenides that the idea is like
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 88
the day. Socrates wants to say that just as things are only visible
in the one light of day that floods around them, so too the idea is
visible only to the extent that it emerges in thinking. This means,
however, that the idea is only visible to the extent that it allows
the beings which appear to be thought of as what they are. Thus
we have a threefold methexis (participation) here: (1) the methexis of the individual in the idea, (2) the methexis of the soul in
the idea, but ultimately, (3) the methexis of the ideas in each
otherfor any thinking of something is both a delimiting-from
and a combining-with (cf. the Sophist on dihairesis and synagdge). My thesis, then, is this: these three kinds of methexis are
nothing but aspects of one and the same relationship. To think
of "this here" as "what" it is, is always at the same time to differentiate the "what" from the "this." But to differentiate the
"what" is always to differentiate one "what" from another
"what": the impurity in the appearing "this" is in truth the existence of some other pure thing in it.' This circumstance provides
the background for the dialectic in the Parmenides*
There, of course, Socrates shows himself incapable of keeping
a firm hold on the sense of the metaphor of light and of elevating
it to the conceptual level. He is still young. In truth, Aristotle is
the first who could. He did so in availing himself of the distinction between poiein (doing or making something) and paschein
(suffering something), or poietikon (active) and pathetikon (passive), to conceptualize the structure of nous (intellect). In Aristotle too, nous enables, "makes" {poiei), thinking, hs hexis tis
(as a kind of condition), just as light * "makes potential colors
9. The impurity of fire, for instance, is coals or ashes, which to someone who
might use them for fertilizer are something else pure. It is not by accident, Gadamer points out, that one says reiner Schmutzpure filth. Thus there are indeed ideas for "mud" and "hair" though Socrates is reluctant to admit it. TRANSLATOR.
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
89
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 90
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
91
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 92
aneu panton autn mathoi" ([we could] not learn any one [of
them] by itself apart from all of them) (18c). However, as accords with their specific nature, they constitute a deHmited
realm even so, and thus they serve as an example for any techne
(16c). Here, [knowledge of] the systematic structure (desmos
[bond]) is tantamount to mastery of writing or of making music
respectively. In regard to their structure, certainly, these two are
the same as dialectic: ascent to the primary and descent from the
primary belong together: ^'touton ton desmon au logizamenos
hs onta hena kai panta tauta hen ps poiounta^' (and we conceive of this, their bond, in turn as being one and somehow making all of them one and one into all of these) (18d). In each case
the reference is plainly to a relative unity to which each tone or
phoneme, respectively, belongs as such. Compare the parallel execution of dihairein (division), which departs from the one voice
(phone mia) (17c) and, conversely, at 18b, from indeterminate
voice [phone aperios), (The last approach seems easiest to Philebus, evidently because he follows the path of experience [18d].)
Structurally, dialectic here corresponds closely to dialectic as it is
portrayed at the conclusion of book 6 of the Republic (511bc).
Of course, in the Republic the only arche spoken of is a single
one, and there is no talk of relative first principles such as the
principle of either voice or tone in the Philebus. That there is not
would seem to signify that the examples in the Philebusinsofar as they involve something like tones or lettersmust belong
to what the Republic calls dianoia. Here, at 511c, the distinction
between dianoia and dialectic still sets dialectic sharply apart
from the "so-called technai," which do not justify their presuppositions. Only in the Philebus are technai such as music or the
science of letters described in such a way that they themselves
could be called dialectical. Does that not mean that Plato was indeed fully aware that the ideal of dialectical derivation of all
things from a single arche could never be carried out completely?
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
93
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 94
gar dei peri geneses kai phthoras ten aitian diapragmateusasthai'' (for it is appropriate to treat as a whole the cause of generation and destruction) (95e). Socrates advances his own example
of knowledge of the good only as an illustrative introduction to
the general question of what knowledge is. As early as the
Phaedo a teleological cosmology is postulated, which, to be sure,
is not worked out. Similarly, in the Seventh Letter^ we find the
extension of knowledge about arete to knowledge about the
whole of reality (344b). And, in the final analysis, the Timaeus is
the mythical exposition of the unelaborated postulate of the
Phaedoeven if, strictly speaking, the Socratic question is no
longer mentioned there at all. One sees that Aristotle is extending a Platonic line of thought in his teleological physics and
metaphysics. But how the widening of the agathon (good) to the
arche tn pantn (principle of all things) is supposed to follow
from the structure of dialectic is still obscure.
It seems to me that real clarification of this problem can be
achieved only if one analyzes the actual procedure of dialectic, a
procedure that is specified in the Republic only as a general program. We must find justification in this procedure of dialectic for
the disquieting "in just the same way" that places the good
alongside the other ideas. Let us remember that the underlying
principle of Plato's Utopian state (even in the first outlines of it)
was to educate the guardians, in whose hands the power of government lay, to be immune to the seduction of power: in the end
education in science was to be education by science. It is striking
that in our passage, with its confusing "in just the same way,"
grasping the good is portrayed as the breakthrough that brings
victory in battle. What battle? Against what enemy?^^
13. The image Plato useswhich, of course, was suggested in particular by
the warrior-guardian analogy of his Utopiain fact belongs to one self-con-
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
95
Obviously the concern is not only the abuse of power. Or, better said, even the abuse of power, which the constitution of a
state is intended to prevent, derives from another fault. And
Plato maintains that this other fault is a lack of dialectic, a lack
of the art of differentiating. That, of course, sounds absurd. As if
the passions which carry us away were forms of thinking, and all
thinking were not overpowered precisely by the force of them!
The Protagoras pushes this absurdity to the extreme: there, succumbing to the passions is said to be mere ignorance (352 ff.).
This assertion notwithstanding, Plato's intellectualization of
courage in book 4 of the Republic did disclose something important. He demonstrates convincingly that in regard to courage as
a qualification for the warrior-guardians, the concern is that
they hold fast to the right doxa (belief) about danger and not let
themselves be dissuaded from that beUef by anythingnot even
the seductive power contained in hedone (pleasure). That may
indeed be expressed too "intellectually," and Aristotle, who always takes Plato word for word, accordingly discounts the Socratic position all too much when he comes to its aid with the argument that to some, a man might actually appear courageous
only because they themselves overestimate the danger he faces
(EN 1116b3 ff.). What Socrates has in mind is substantiated insofar as the issue is real political courage and not just physical
courage (430b). For in political courage the concern is not so
much the physical anxiety as such that overpowers us, as the rationalizations into which fear seduces us. And in the case of
hedone the concern is even clearer: the seductive power of pertained semantic field: the expressions for logical operations are taken in large
part from the language of wrestling and similar forms of fighting; so too, aptti
(not to be overthrown) in the passage here (cf. n. 8 above), and frequently diamachesthai (to fight hard, or contend), for instance, in the Gorgias at 503a and
elsewhere.
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 96
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
97
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 98
Thus one should take note that the portrayal of the dialectician here contains not only the word elenchos (test, refutation),
which we know from the Socratic discussions, but a series of
other words that we find in the later dialogues in the context of
characterizing dialectic: dihorisasthai, aphelein^ diexienai^ to define thoroughly, to abstract, to run [get] through. "To define
thoroughly" means to mark off one thing from another, hence,
to differentiate. And that implies removing the thing meant from
everything which is not meant {abstrahere) and getting through
all differentiations until the end, that is, until an understanding is
reached with others as well as oneself. The prefixes are of particular importance. The dia (through, thoroughly) implies at the
same time'an "asunder," hence a differentiation. And the apo
(off, away) implies at the same time a "to," that is, a seeing together of what has been taken away. This vocabulary already anticipates the analyses of dialectic undertaken in the Sophist using
the highest generabeing, identity, difference, and so forth.
Here in the Republic the exposition still has a purely dialogical,
indeed even military, timbre [hsper en machei [as in a battle]).
That does not happen by chance for the danger lurks in logos
(discourse) itself.
Confusing something is the counterpart to distinguishing
something, and the wrong separation is the counterpart to the
right one. In confusing something and separating falsely, one
MP), Gadamer attempts to develop an ethical theory in which Kant and Aristotle, far from being in conflict, complement each other. The application of
practical reason in hitting the mean between the extremes in a particular situation can only succeed if reason is secured against the seductive influence of the
desire for gratification and the "flattery" of the senses. For when reason is not so
secured, it degenerates into rationalization. Gadamer reads Kant's Foundations
as devoted primarily to this preparatory task of purifying the rational sense of
duty from the subversive influence of the senses, TRANSLATOR.
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
99
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 100
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
101
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D 102
out. Above all, that means that the individual thing which participates in an eidos "counts" in an argument only in regard to the
eidos in which it participates, that is, only in regard to its essential, eidetic content. All logical confusion has its origin in not
keeping the eidos separate from what only participates in it. For
if one fails to keep these separate, one easily gets entangled in
contradictions, such as saying that the number two "comes into
being" both by addition and by division. A proper testing of the
hypothesis of the eidos repudiates as sophistic all adulteration
introduced here by the concept of "coming into being." (A good
illustration of this function of the hypothesis. Republic 525d,
has been treated above.)
The portrayal [of this procedure] in the Phaedo is obviously
intended to be of the highest formal generality: the illustration
given is the noetic example of the number. Even so, what is said
here is in complete accord with the demand made of the philosopher in the Republic^ that he differentiate the eidos from everything that participates in it. Of course, one must be clear that this
procedure of hypothesizing the eidos is only the preliminary precondition of all argumentation, only the first step which provides an initial foothold on the shaky ground of the logoi. No
knowledge is attained by this procedure yet. As early as the
Phaedoy no doubt is left about that. And to this extent there
never was such a thing as Plato's "Eleaticism": the schema of
"development" in Plato proposed by Stenzelfrom arete to
dihairesiswhich, per se, contains many correct observations
must be qualified accordingly. In the Phaedo only the application of the procedure of hypothesis to the immortality of the soul
and the comparison of the soul to snow, which disappears when
the fire of the sun warms it, is supposed to yield anything like
knowledge.
Nevertheless, this first step on the path of dialectic lays the
THE P O L / 5 A N D K N O W L E D G E OF T H E G O O D
103
foundation. It is the step into the noetic realm as such, a step that
is presupposed whenever one is serious about giving justification. When Plato describes dialectic in the Republic^ its differentiating is played out entirely in the noetic sphere (511c). We
will see later in our analysis of the Philebus that there, too, this
first step of reflection, the step into the noetic, is taken explicitly.
There, Protarchus names the contradictions that result from the
correlativity of the one and the many and, similarly, of the large
and the smallcontradictions that are introduced in the Republic (523a ff.) expressly as the "call" to awaken to thinking. In the
Philebus (14d) Protarchus has to be told by Socrates that these
contradictions are trite and overworked. Matters only become
serious once noetic unities are under consideration, and when
these are said to be one and many at the same time. And in what
follows, the dialectical nature of all science is founded on this
noetic basis. Even in the very words he uses here, Plato is
opposing true dialectic to the art of confounding someone: for
example, in the Phaedo, lOle, ''phyroio'' (would confuse), and
in the Philebus^ 15de, ""symphyron'' (confusing).
IV
GOOD
PHILEBUS
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
105
to concern the principles of dialectic. Instead, the universal question about the good is woven completely into the plot of the discussion, that is, the dispute about the respective importance to
human life of hedone and phronesis.
Thus here we find together again all those things that in the
Republic got dispersed over the wide-ranging considerations of
Socrates' long discussion of the true state: the Socratic question
about the good, the doctrine of the ideas and their dialectic^ and
the doctrine of the uppermost principle, that is, the good. And all
this occurs in a discussion between Socrates and quite young
people, whom he must introduce to these things ab ovo.
And indeed, here in the Philebus the question that we found
posed in the Republicwhether pleasure or thinking is the
highest good (505b)is made the theme of a dramatic confrontation. The advocates of pleasure are no longer dismissed from
the start as they were in the Republic. After all, in defending
their position they can summon in support a truly important
trait of life that pervades all living things. Behind these advocates
stands, we suspect, the figure of Plato's great friend, the mathematician and scholar Euduxus, to whom Aristotle later makes
respectful reference in the same context {N, Kappa 2). Those
who advocate "thinking" will have to justify their claim that it is
supreme against this universal principle of life that pervades even
the human being, who is distinct by virtue of memory, deliberation, and the like. At first it seems as if two irreconcilable basic
attitudes were being pitted against each other here. For just as it
steers the behavior of any living thing, the pleasure principle has
a kind of obvious predominance, unlimited and overpowering,
in the human being too. That one should argue for this principle
in [rational] statement and answer would seem to be self-contradictory, and hence it is entirely consistent that those who do advocate it do indeed resist^giving justification of their position in
T H E D I A L E C T I C O F T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 106
this way. The most visible indication of this reluctance is the fact
that Philebus, in whose honor the dialogue is named, withdraws
from the discussion entirely.
Thus there is good reason for why the old Socratic question of
the good in human life leads precisely at this point to thematizing the dialectical principle of giving justification. Resistance to
the demand that justification be given is part and parcel of the
hedonist position. Philebus is consistent when he does not oppose this demand with a logical argument but, instead, dogmatically insists on the unconditional priority of hedone: "That's
what I believe and that's what I always will believe" (dokei kai
doxai) (12a). He bids adieu to the whole thing in order not to do
any harm to his "goddess" Pleasure by accepting any uncomfortable assumptions about her. And when Socrates gives a demonstration of the principle of differentiation, illustrating it with examples of particular technai [grammar and harmony], Philebus
cannot see what that could possibly have to do with his contention, of which he is so completely certain (18a-b). The allusion
is the same at 22c, where we find, "and not your nous (reason)
either!" In this phrasing, "your reason" (ho sos nous) (22c), we
detecteven in the negative Philebus's absolute partiality for
his goddess Hedone. Philebus's intransigence is made all the more
evident by the skirmishing in which Socrates defends the official
cult name. Aphrodite, against Philebus['s attempts to rename her]
(12c). Philebus wants to consecrate Hedone artificially. Socrates,
in contrast, stays with the cult name for Aphroditethat is to
say, he recognizes her as a member of the Olympian family of
gods. In substance, his doing so establishes the merely partial vaHdity and limits of hedone's claim to be the dominant power in
the world. After that Philebus allows himself to open his mouth
just once more, and then solely to reinforce that no limits can be
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
107
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 108
ferentiations in the types of pleasure and thinking, when the issue is as existentially important as the question of the good?
Protarchus is speaking quite Socratically here: one should not remain hidden to oneself, he says (19c). But paradoxically, he says
this in order to evade Socrates' demand that he pursue the
dialectica highly ingenious, ironic twisting by Plato of existential seriousness and the dialectical game. Socrates is surprisingly
willing to go along with seeking an alternative approach to
resolving the dispute. As he so often does, he introduces an argument quite on the sly, which, when all is said and done, will serve
to support his thesis, which here is to prove the priority of nous
over hedone. The argument is the doctrine of the four genera
(23b ff.). From this point on, his partner goes along with him
ever more readily, no longer allowing himself to be misled even
by Philebus's final intervention (28b). Something quite surprising now happens: when the doctrine of the four genera is applied
to the two contestants, hedone and nous, hedone is assigned in
toto to [the first genus,] the apeiron (indeterminate), and nous to
the fourth, the aitia (cause). With this conclusion the argument
might be considered setried. But instead, Socrates asks where
and in what way {en hoi te kai dia ti pathos) these two, hedone
and phronesis, show up in the visible realm (31b). And from this
moment on, no more persuasion is needed to involve his partner
in more and more subtle, and further and further differentiated,
analysis of the most varied forms in which hedone appears (and
later, phronesis too).
This transition is the least obtrusive, yet perhaps also the most
important of all in this dialogue, which is so rich in transitions.
The transition here to the concrete manifold of experience takes
place automatically, so to speak. And the application of the procedure of differentiation, which Protarchus had shied away from
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
109
before, now takes place automatically too, and with his willing
assistance (32c).
It is remarkable how this "guiding of the soul" [psychagge)
is combined with highly theoretical expositions of the principles
of dialectic. Socratesin his typically secretive, oracular way
supports his argument with appeals to obscure sources of knowledge and even vague dreams. Plainly he makes no claim that
what he says is authoritative. Rather, he sets the listener free
once again to recognize himself in what is said.^ In this way
Socrates does indeed get his partner to enter into the dialectical
movement voluntarily.
After all, dialectic, as the art of differentiating rightly, is really
not some kind of secret art reserved for philosophers. Whoever is
confronted with a choice must decide. Being confronted with
choices, however, is the unalterable circumstance of human beings. Their having to make choices removes them from the realm
of the rest of living things, which unquestioningly follow their
animal desires {therion erotes) (67b) wherever theselike forces
of naturemay drive them. To be a human being means always
to be confronted with choices. As Aristotle puts it, human beings
"have" prohairesis (choice). They must choose. Having to
choose, however, entails wanting to know, that is, to know what
is best, to know what is good. And that means knowing reasons
why, knowing grounds, and using grounds to differentiate.
Socrates' partners in the discussion experience this: they learn
3. Gadamer maintains that Plato's myths are a sort of mirror in which we are
meant to recognize ourselves. (See ch. 2. n. 9, on self-knowledge and the Socratic
gnthi s*auton.) Their validity, accordingly, is not dependent upon any authorities to whom they might appeal, but upon their pertinence and accuracy in portraying the phenomena of human existence, and their efficacy in helping one to
achieve self-knowledge, TRANSLATOR.
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 110
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
111
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 112
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
113
the peras and apeiron themselves (and just as there "is" necessarily a cause for the third, mixed genus). Not only hedone and lype
(pain) appear in this mixed genus of the "real" (31c). In a decisive passage it is emphasized that the good is to be sought here
too (61b). At issue, to be sure, is solely the good in human life.
The good in human life, however, is just as much the good in the
state and in the cosmos too. That the good is the same in all three
is confirmed when Plato reminds us of hygeia (health) and harmonia (harmony) and points out their cosmic relevance (for example, at 31c). The doctrine of the four genera thus proves to be
both the ontological preparation for, and prerequisite of, the
debate in the Philebus. Only when the mixture is no longer
thought of as a diminution and clouding of the pure, true, and
unmixed, but as a genus of its own, can it be the place where we
see how the being of the good and the true is constituted. In this
way we arrive at the metaphor of the potion of life: the way is
prepared for it ontologically by the differentiation of the four
genera of being.
This doctrine has far-reaching consequences for any appropri^:
ate understanding of Plato's dialectic and of the problems of
chorismos (separation) and methexis (participation). If limit and
determinacy do not exist apart, for themselves, then neither does
the entire noetic realm of the ideasany more than do the ingredients of this potion of life that is supposed to be mixed. That the
noetic world of numbers and pure relationships belongs together
with their dialectical opposite, the apeiron, implies that they are
only abstracted aspects of this third thing called the "mixed" {ex
amphoin symmisgomenon, meikton [combined from both,
mixed]) (23d, 25b). It is established expressly at 27b that our
Hfethis life, mixed from pleasure and knowledgebelongs in
the third genus. But that it does is, after all, virtually self-evident.
It was indeed difficult for Protarchus to grasp this third genus
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 114
and precisely because it is ubiquitous: "Its numerousness {plethos) startled you" (26c). Plato is pointing to a self-evident truth,
namely, the obvious fact that the particular participates in the
universal. After the confusions of a dialectic of making one many
and vice versa, a dialectic that ended in vacuity, the third genus
of the mixed now appears as the reality, or being, that has come
into being (gegenemene ousia) (27b). The fourth genus, the
"cause" of the mixture, makes clear that this third genus is a genus of its own and is not to be derived from the eidetic opposition of peras and apeiron, but is instead a special kind of being.
The doctrine of the four aspects of being developed here is a
universal ontological doctrine, which is to say, that it extends far
beyond the particular occasion for which it was introduced
herenamely, the question of the good in human Hfeand embraces the whole cosmos and its constitution. We may go even
further: nowhere in the entirety of Plato's dialogues are we as
close as we are here to Aristotle's parallel account of the two
principles, the one and indeterminate duality. If one starts here
in Plato, even something like a physicsthat is, an eidetic science
of what, in its essence, coming-into-being isno longer seems
completely impossible. Coming-into-being, becoming, is, after
all, becoming being. It is being that has come to be. Even so, the
Socratic question about the good in hiiman life is included here
too. Physics and ethics can still appear here, undifferentiated
from each other, as mere applications of the basic ontological
structure of the good. And the mode of discourse that is used
here to describe both these ways in which the good appears,
could, if viewed in relation to Aristotle's technique of conceptualization, be termed_inythical, A world whose origination and
determinate order are caused and executed by a master craftsman who possesses reaspn, or a human life whose ingredients are
knowledgeably and expertly combined into a blended potion by
an ideal drink-mixerthese are mythical metaphors. And it
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
115
seems to me that Aristotle's physics and ethics achieve a translation of them into concepts.
If the good is accepted as the cause of any mixture being
goodand ultimately this means, as the cause of everything real
being good (64d)the famous "beyond all being" {epeikena tes
ousias) takes on a new meaning. The good is no longer the one.
On the contrary, it is explicitly conceived of according to the
ideal of mixture and as having three aspects (syntrisi [in three together]). The dynamis (power) of the good has taken refuge in
the physis (nature) of the beautiful: measure and measuredness
constitute what beauty and arete are everywhere {^^metriotes gar
kai symmetria, kallos depou kai arete pantachou symbainei
gignesthaV) (64e).
We are far removed here from some esoteric, abstract, dialectical doctrine. It is stated expressly that all human beings know
what is meant (64d). For this reason there is no terminological
precision in this description whatsoever. Beauty, symmetry or
measuredness, and truth {aletheia) are named as the three structural components of the good, which appears as the beautiful.
Thus, in the intrinsic connection between the good and the
beautiful, which is brought out so emphatically here, we can see
an indication that "the good," which is at the same time "the
beautiful," does not exist somewhere apart for itself and in itself,
somewhere "beyond." Rather, it exists in everything that we recognize as a beautiful mixture. What is viewed from the perspective of the Republic (or the Symposium) as the pure unmixed
good or beautiful "beyond being" is here determined to be the
structure of "the mixed" itself. In each case it would seem to be
found only in what is concretely good and beautiful. And precisely the unity and integration of the appearance itself would
thus appear to constitute its being good. This thesis, it seems to
me, does not represent a change in Plato's teaching, a change
that would have led him to abandon the doctrine of ideas or the
T H E D I A L E C T I C O F T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 116
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
117
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 118
for itself, but "in that in which it exists and which it effects"
{eph' hoi te esti kai hoi apergazetai) {Republic 477c-d). That
holds universally. Hence, one must look for the dynamis of the
good in the manifold of what the dynamis of the good brings
aboutas, for instance, the dynamis of seeing consists in the
manifold of sights and nothing else. In conceptual language, that
means that we are dealing here with the inseparability of the one
from the many. True reality, or "being," is one but nevertheless
in all the many things. And that means that it is separated from
itself "which, however, seems to be the most impossible thing of
all" {Philebus 15b). Since it is one and the same in many things
that are separate from each other, it is simultaneously in them
completely, and hence it is separate from itself. This circumstance is the seemingly nonsensical state of affairs with which
Socrates is confronted in the Parmenides. He seeks a way out by
referring to the light of day, which is everywhere at once and yet
one and the same, not separated from itself (131b). In the Parmenides^ of course, he does not succeed in keeping a proper hold
on his thesis. He is still too young. But in the Philebus, Socrates
characterizes precisely this problem as the source of all perplexity {aporia) if it is not properly allowed for, and the way to all felicitous advance {euporia) if it is {Philebus 15c).
And in fact the felicitous, good way of reaching an understanding, which the discussion in the Philebus traverses, gets
completely beyond the danger that Socrates had warned against
at the beginning, namely, the eristic tricks of sophistic pseudodialectic. This sophistic dialectic is not real thinking, for in pursuing it one succumbs to the blind desire for success in contentious argument: ^hyph' hedones enthousiai te kai panta kinei
logon asmenos"" (enthused with pleasure he delightedly sets
every sort of argument in motion) (15e).
To be sure,-the way toward reaching an understanding and
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
119
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 120
cases]. After all, the art of differentiating only reaches its goal
when one finds no more specifiable unitstones, phonemes,
and so forth. So one might see in all dialectical division of a one
into many a certain approximation to Plato's coordination of
idea and number.
Differentiation takes place here within the noetic one, and it
is the principle of number that the Philebus introduces in this
context as the truly illuminating Promethean fire. Here, the Pythagorean heritage, the identification of being with number, is
explicated on the new level of noetic being. In this way the multiplicity that the one contains receives numerical determination. It
is many but not indefinitely many, rather so and so many. The
numerical determination of what constitutes tones and tonal relationships in music, this ancient Pythagorean inheritance, has
its correlate in the ideality of language and writing, both of
which articulate the whole of human phonemes and, by doing
so, put them at our disposal.^
Hence it is an eidetic-ideal structure, a relationship of ideas,
that underlies the knowledge and skill in which any techne consists. This ideality certainly does not eliminate techne's relationship to the production of something in perceptible reality, for example, tones and music or articulated speech and what is fixed in
writing. But the thing produced in this way retains a special kind
of ideality itself. It is a world of signs and indices that directs us
to the ideal. Accordingly we are not dealing here with just any
particular handcraft among many others, one that Plato would
say is less a techne than a mere routine (tribe). Rather, we have
here two arts which were later called "free" (liberales) because
5. Even within the book of aporiai at Metaphysics, Beta 4,999b30, the ideality of letters becomes clear, and this ideality entails that they have an ideal universality v^^hich takes multiple forms in the individual instances to which they are
applied^
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
121
each in its own way is subordinate to no particular aims, and because each is so comprehensive.
Now the mixing of the potion of life also has an inclusive, universal aspect. The ingredients, which one after the other, are
found acceptable for the mixture, have something to do with
number insofar as the examination and testing of them is supposed to be comprehensive and exhaustive, *that is, is supposed
to include just the right number of them's-. Nevertheless, the
thought here cannot be that one learns how to live in the right
way, and is finally capable of it, in the manner in which one
learns how to sing, speak, or write.
Or should we say only that one leams about the right and just
life in the way one learns about giving justification for something
and in the end is finally able to give it? But that is just what the
discussion [in the Philebus] teaches us: dialectic is not a techne
that one learns like writing, not something that others (illiterates) cannot do. Thinking, to be sure, is an art, but an art that is
practiced by everyone and that one is never finished learning.
And how to live is just as little an art that one could ever be finished learning. Futhermore, right thoughts about Ufe and the
idea of the right and just lifethe highest thing that one could
learn {megiston mathema)only become visible in general
outlines *and not in regard to specifics (cf. Aristotle, EN
1098a21)'^. Aristotle knows that the theoretical reflections that
he calls "ethics" have to be of use in Hfe as it is actually lived.
Similarly, it is clear to Plato and to the reader of the Philebus
that what results from this dialogue, the ideal of a life harmonized rightly, isprecisely as the result of dialoguea logos
(statement in words), which directs us to an ergon (deed), to
choosing what is right in the moment of choice.
This is not the place to pursue the intrinsic connections between the dialectic of the one and the many and the doctrine of
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 122
the ideal numbers. Of interest to us here is only the fact that human life, just as all other being, belongs to the mixed genus, and
that what is called "being-good" appears in the reality of what is
mixed. That it does so must mean that everything that exists has
reality only in its concrete determinacy. And that means precisely that it is set in, and surrounded by, the unlimitedly variablegenesis. Similarly the conduct of human life that is
guided by practical reason, also has the good in it only insofar as
the good is concretized in the actual doing of it, that is, in giving
preference to one thing over another (prohairesis). That would
mean too that any deed, to the extent that it is decision, always
includes a component of uncertainty, for it must move in an element that exceeds all determinacy and delimitation, which is
therefore called ^'apeiron" (indefinite).
Consequently, human life is eo ipso dialectical.^ It is one and
many at the same time. At every moment it is itself and, exactly
for that reason, separated from itself, just as the "what-it-is" {ti
estin) of every existent thing ultimately exists in such a way that
it is in all that participates in it {to metechon). The aporiai for6. The use of the word dialectic in Gadamer shifts. Here the reference is to
the inner tension in human existence between order and disorder, the rational
and the bestial. Our task is to maintain unity of self, integrity, within ever threatening disintegration into boundless chaos. Thus we must be constant in holding
to one thing (Kierkegaard) through the vicissitudes of our life (cf. PD and ch.
1, n. 22) Dialectic in this sense also has to do with dialogue insofar as the Socratic
"art" of leading a discussion is an "art" of keeping it from getting lost in the
indefiniteness of many things that are not important and of holding to the one
thing that isthe one subject matter under discussion. Gadamer shows that
phronesis is the requisite virtue for both these forms of constancy in holding to
one definite thing within threatening indeterminacyin moral practice and in
discussion. And it is the "dialectical" nature of its content in both these applications that distinguishes phronesis from any techne whose content is a systematic
whole that we could ever be finished learning, TRANSLATOR.
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
123
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS 124
T H E D I A L E C T I C OF T H E G O O D I N T H E PHILEBUS
125
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF
THE IDEA OF THE G O O D
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
127
some sort of copy by someone else, that is, not with the text of the "author," but
with carefully reworked class notes. In particular, the "logical concern" of the
text, of which Dirlmeier correctly takes note, can be easily explained as a consequence of the lecture's skeletal treatment of its topic. And many "deviations" in
the line of thought in MM [from EE and EN], for example, the delayed introduction of eudaimonia, would not be all that surprising if we are dealing with a rendering of a live lecture which was not intended as a text to be read.
3. Is MM 1182a25 ff. an allusion to the lost lecture on the good or, rather, a
polemic against the Republic} Can apedken hekasti (assigned to each [part of
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 128
Also, let us keep away from any hypothesis about the relationship of these three ethical treatises to each other. We find the critique of the idea of the good at the beginning of all three, and in
all three that critique is aimed precisely at the universal ontological claim which Plato makes *for his idea of the good'^. In all
three the decisive argument is that knowledge of such a good can
have no relevance for the philosophy of human practice. In the
Magna Moralia (1182a25 ff.) Plato is criticized precisely for having introduced the question of arete (virtue) at all into his universal ontological doctrine of the agathon (the good)as he did in
his famous lecture "On the Good." According to this argument,
for Aristotle, the Socratic question about arete would be wholly
incompatible with the universal question of the good, to which
Platonic dialectic is addressed. Here Aristotle in fact raises the
very same question that we put to the text of the Republic^
* namely, how the Socratic question about the good and the ascent to dialectic through and past the mathematical sciences relate
to each other. In what follows I intend to show that Aristotle, the
creator of physics and founder of practical philosophy, holds
fast to the Socratic heritage in Plato: the good is the practically
good. On the other hand, as the creator of physics, Aristotle also
fulfills the demand made by Plato's Socrates, that is, that we understand the world starting with the experience of the good. The
good thus appears in Aristotle's physics as well as his practical
the soul]) be anything other than an allusion to book 4 of the Republic} Above
all, the phrase at 1182a27, kai synezeuxen (and coupled [arete and the good]),
speaks for such an understanding of the allusion. In substance the critical observation would then amount to a rejection of Plato's having extended the so-called
four-book Republic, Or perhaps one must read the note as follows: Plato's lecture on the good would have been just fine had he only omitted all references to
the aretai. That would fit well with the account of Aristoxenus. To be sure, I am
of the opinion that in this case no one other than Aristotle himself said this, and
that he was attempting to reverse popular expectations with such sarcasm.
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
129
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 130
the Eudemian Ethics also has the broad sense of a comprehensive agathon very much in mind. Thus we can estabHsh that in all
three treatises Aristotle does not limit himself to what for him is
the decisive argument concerning the practical relevance of the
idea of the good. Instead, he finds himself forced beyond the
confines of his theme of practice.^
ticesit remains to be investigated in how many ways "the best of all" [applies]).
The last part could have been appended by an editor who wished, after this summary, to remind us of the larger universal ontological horizons here. But in any
case, in our text {1218a25 ff.), the contrast between to ariston tn praktn (the
best of practices) and to ariston pantn (the best of all) is manifest.
Here, a general observation concerning the status of our texts is in order.
Gigon likes to speak of an editor but leaves open the question of whether this editor was Aristotle himself. He is entirely right insofar as one may not always apply
the yardstick of stylistic consistency appropriate to a literary exposition of doctrineeven to the ethical treatises. But his predicates (negligent, careless, imprecise, and so forth) go too far. One should not allow oneself to be deceived in such
fashion that one mistakes single locutions, often subtly and cleverly formulated,
for a text. To be specific: the composition is indeed often "careless," or better
said, dependent on the kind of care that would be given to it in oral presentation.
5. Things like this occur elsewhere in Aristotle. For example, his definition of
physics ought, strictly speaking, to prohibit any discussion of Eleatic philosophy
whatsoever within the framework of physics, for Eleatic philosophy, after all,
denies the existence of motion altogether. Nevertheless, he inserts his critique of
the Eleatics in his lectures on physics (Alpha 3,4). In the case we are considering
the definition of practical philosophy ought, strictly speaking, to preclude a detailed discussion of Plato's idea of the good. Nonetheless, he takes it up, even if
he constantly points out that it actually belongs in another context. It would
seem that he is somehow uncertain of just where to find an appropriate place for
such things. Ultimately one must say, then, that such uncertainties, which often
occur in Aristotle, reflect the larger uncertainty we call "metaphysics." The stack
of papers that later received this name is, so to speak, a collection of uncertainties
that share this character of being marginal. Once one is clear about this fact, it is
no longer very puzzling that the start made in Book Gamma, which gives the impression that the science to be pursued is a formal ontology, does not quite fit
with what is begun in Books Zeta and Eta (the doctrine of substance and of
dynamis and energeia) and in Book Lambda (the so-called theology), and that the
book of aporiai. Beta, stands by itself in a peculiar way. The fact that Book Epsilon ultimately provides a certain editorial harmonization of what precedes it,
does not contradict what I have said here.
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
131
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 132
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
133
the synholon (underlying whole). Still, the question remains: despite these differences,* is it not possible that what Plato truly intended becomes visible in Aristotle's discussion, nevertheless
against the latter's will, as it were?^
6. Gadamer grants that this chapter in particular often needs to be filled out.
The argument as stated here, for instance, is somewhat compressed. As I understand it, the line of thought that Gadamer is pursuing is as follows: Aristode
wishes to include the idea of the good in his general critique of the ideas, which
argues that Plato unnecessarily doubles the world by postulating that the ideas
have a christon reality apart from the things that they inform. For Aristode, being christon is indeed a characteristic of anything that is; for anything that is,
exists for itself and in itself, which is to say, exists as "what it is" {ti estin) apart
from changing accidental predications (the kategoroumena or symbebekota). A
horse is a horse in itself, apart from (christon) being brown or old, here or there,
next to this or smaller than that. But, according to Aristode, Plato is guilty of a
misplaced concretion, so to speak, insofar as he assigns precisely this being christon to the ideas themselves, as if they too were realities, while in fact only a thissomething {tode ti) is real and christon. When Aristode comes to the idea of the
good in Plato, he finds the same mistake that Plato makes with all the ideas:
Plato, he says, treats the good as if it were a thing in itself, and that leads to an
empty abstraction: "We say first, then, that to say there is an idea not only of the
good, but of anything else whatever, is to say something abstract and empty"
{EE 1217b20).
This criticism, of course, accords with Aristotie's overall project, but it must
systematically suppress the fact that Plato himself argues that the good transcends all existence, that is, that it is epekeina tes ousias. As Gadamer has shown,
despite all the differences, Plato's aim is to make just Aristotle's point: the idea of
the good is precisely not another thing alongside things that are good; rather, it is
the structural order in any thing that is good. We call the good, insofar as it exists, the beautifula shining forth in things, an appearance. Aristotle's intended
criticism thus actually reinforces Plato's point.
One should not overlook the fact that, for the purposes of his critique, Aristotle shifts the weight of christon ever so slightly. As Gadamer has shown
above, christon in Plato implied independence from contingencies, as circularity
is independent of the aberrations that may occur in any particular circles we may
draw (see "Dialectic and Sophism in Plato's Seventh Letter^'), Aristode, too,
would not deny that what a thing is in essence is separate, or distinct, from the
variable things that might be said of it.
But since his starting point is the living thing (tode tt)^ not mathematics, he also
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 134
In interpreting the idea of the good, the Eudemian Ethics^ Alpha 8, begins with two interpretive formulations of the idea of
the good, which, in tying into Plato's assertions, are as faithful to
him as one could possibly imagine. The first states that the good
is that which is first {proton)^ the negation (anhairein) of which
also negates everything else [to heteron) that follows from what
is first and is therefore "good" *just as when there is no longer
such a thing as line, for instance, there can no longer be a triangle composed of lines*. Although it does not occur in the dialogues themselves, this formulation has an undeniably Platonic
stamp, as P. Wilpert, in particular, has demonstrated.^ Konrad
Gaiser, whose argument we touched on above, has convincingly
shown that tfie system of the mathematical disciplines is a sequential order of number, point, line, plane, and solid, and he
takes this mathematical system to be a kind of schema for Plato's
overall systematization. It is obvious that the numbers stand or
takes christon to mean "unto itself" in the way that a thing exists self-identically apart from other things. Thus the chra (space) in christon is much more
present in Aristotle's understanding of the word, albeit in a transfigured sense. As
a "physical" thinker, Aristotle has an ear for this chra, or "spatial" separation,
of whatever is christon.
Now if, like Aristotle, one starts with this sense of christon and then applies
the word to the ideas, it does indeed appear that there is a misplaced concretionalmost as if the ideas were said to be things "spatially" apart from the
things that participate in them, and hence Aristode's argument that Plato needlessly doubles the world. Gadamer's point, however, is that thinking of the ideas
as christon in this sense is obviously every bit as much of a mistake in Plato's
eyes too; in fact, it is precisely the mistake in which the young Socrates gets
caught in all his attempts to defend the ideas in the Parmenides. There can be no
doubt that Aristotle knew this. Hence we can only assume that he consciously
slants Plato's thought in order to better articulate his own "physicalist" position;
in fact, he marshals Plato's very own argumentsagain consciouslyto attack
the christon idea (for example, the "third man"), TRANSLATOR.
7. P. Wilpert, Zwei aristotelische Frhschriften ber die Ideenlehre (Regensburg, 1949).
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
135
fall with the oneand, of course, with the two as well. In our
text too, something follows that concurs with this line of argument. Aristotle says {EE 1218al5 ff.) that we may not deduce
the good from the numbers but instead from what everybody acknowledges to be good. Conversely, at the very most, we can
conclude from the being-good of types of order in things (such as
health or harmony of the soul) that the numbers too, on account
of their ordered structure, are good in a certain sense. The numbers are then described as "striving" toward the onea metaphor that Aristotle in his accustomed manner, takes literally {EE
1218a22 ff.). Here too, given my purposes, the concern is not to
establish whether this doctrine is the special teaching of some
Platonist. Even if it were, it would still be a conclusion drawn
from Plato's doctrine of the good and the one, a conclusion that,
in the context of our investigation, has to be of interest to us.
The principle of the proton^ which the Eudemian Ethics takes as
its point of departure, is in any case palpable in the numbers. At
this point a question forces itself upon us: if the numbers have
the central function suggested here, how, exactly, do things
stand with regard to the chrismos of the good? And how do
things stand with regard to the chrismos of the ideas if the ideas
are numbers? After all, are not the numbers in the things? (Again
I refer the reader to the Philebus 16d.) And is not the one, which
resides in all numbers, each being a manifold of ones, actually
"separated from itself" while in them? If one interprets the ideas
8. Instead of agathon^ Aristotle says kalon here (cf. Metaphysics 1078a31 ff.).
But surely he does so solely to reserve agathon here for what is prakton and to
avoid misunderstandings. This, it seems to me, is a minimal terminological differentiation, which Aristotle makes for his own purposes, a modification that accords with the close concatenation of agathon and kalon in Plato's language usage. Hence I would not ground any hypothesis concerning divergent teachings on
the passages bearing on this one that Dirlmeier carefully assembles, and certainly
not any hypothesis concerning Aristotle's "development."
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 136
as numbers, this puzzling and deliberately contradictory formulation of Plato's (cf. Philebus 15b: auten hautes chris^ and
Parmenides 131b) becomes understandable at once: the one-ness
of the one is both for itself and in the numbers.
That brings us to the second formulation, which may count as
good Plato if anything may, and which is solidly documented
precisely in reference to the idea of the good as well as the other
ideas. It is the general formulation for "participation" {methexis), which is also used elsewhere in Plato in speaking of participation in the ideas. Here it is applied to the good, whose presence (parousia) is said to cause all things that are good to be
good (EE 1217b5). Precisely this formulation is used to introduce the idea of the good in the Republic (book 6, 505a). That
the good is the most important subject matter [megiston mathema) because it embraces everything is advanced as a kind of
self-evident argument. It will be recalled, of course, that presence
{parousia)^ participation {methexis)^ and similarity [homiotesY
are always only metaphors, which the young Socrates of the
Parmenides cannot succeed in conceptualizing when the old
Parmenides locks him in his Socratic grip. If one wishes to understand the aims and limits of Aristotle's critique of Plato, one
must constantly keep this fact in mind. Aristotle must have been
aware of it when he repeated the very argument here that, as
Plato himself had shown in the Parmenides, leads to an insoluble
problem {aporia) and an absurdity, that is, the complete separation of the ideas from the appearances.
As I have shown, indications of a substantive answer to the
question of what is there, what is present, when something is
9. Homiotes, incidentally, is the preferred expression in Diogenes Laertius's
account of Alcimus, whose ties with the old academy Gaiser has argued for convincingly {Rheinisches Museum fr Philologie^ Frankfurt, 1975).
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
137
"good," are most likely to be had if, in some vague way, we take
the triad of metrotiy symmetron^ and alethes (measured, symmetrical, and true) that constitutes the beautiful in the Philebus^ to
be what is first (proton) and gives oneness to things. In any case,
the structure of Plato's Republic also implies that somehow the
good is the one: the "oneness" of the ideal city is a unified order
of such a nature that neither strife nor disturbance can occur in
it. That the good is what is first and gives oneness to things is
also implied, incidentally, in Aristotle's critique in the Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle's express praise there of the Pythagoreans for simply putting the one in the series of good things and
consequently, unlike Plato, not equating the one with the good
{EN 1096b5), obviously presupposes that for his part Plato did
think of the good as the one. Of course, Plato's one is not at all a
Neoplatonic hen (One). On the contrary, in the Parmenides insoluble puzzles are displayed in the concepts of being and oneness in order to establish the dialectical unity of the one and the
In returning to Aristotle's introduction of his Plato critique in
the Eudemian Ethics^ which we discussed above, we can now see
that there Aristotle is striving for the least metaphorical exposition possible of what is meant by the idea of the good. Being primary among all those things that are good and being the cause of
everything other than itself by virtue of its presencethese are
obviously two aspects of Plato's methexis metaphor. First, as the
10. The critique in the Metaphysics, Alpha 6, introduces Plato as a Pythagorean and works him into the doctrine of the arche in the same way as in other
places in the first book of the Metaphysics. In contrast, Alpha 9 exceeds this
framework and, for its part, fits perfectly in the arrangement of the doublet of
this passage in Mu: aistheta mathematike-megethe-ideai-arithmoi (perceptiblemathematical-magnitude-ideas-numbers). How the two chapters fit together,
and how the chrismos critique in Alpha 9 is materially connected with the arche
doctrine in Alpha 6 are, of course, not explained by this observation.
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 138
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
139
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 140
but also that none] is possible for being as such (1217b34). Obviously, the Nicomachean Ethics, as well as the Magna Moralia,
seeks to avoid this undesired consequence. Hence, when the
Nicomachean Ethics uses the same argument, it speaks only of
the good and rules out that it could be "something universal and
one" {koinon ti katholou kai hen) {EN 1096a28). In general, it is
striking that in the Nicomachean Ethics "being-christon" is
mentioned only once and is used primarily as a synonym for
^koinei kategoroumenon^ (predicable in common) (1096b32
ff.). Here the issue is the koinos logos (common expression).
The kind of argument that follows next is taken from the sciences and based on the category argument. According to it,
knowledge of the good disappears among the particular arts
{technai). Actually, Aristotle thereby touches on the same, familiar difficulty which we uncovered in Plato, that is, the difficulty
which arises when one tries to understand the good taking the
mode of knowing in the arts as a starting point. To be sure,
Aristotle's rejection of a science of the good is meant as a criticism of Platoscholei auto ge to agathon theresai mias (there
can hardly be a sole theorizing about the good itself) {EE
1218al) or en an mia tis episteme there would have to be [but
cannot be] a single science) {EN 1096a30). But in Plato's dialogues too, equating knowledge of the good with the mode of
knowing in the arts tended to miscarry. Accordingly, Aristotle
does not seem so far removed from what Plato had in mind even
when he criticizes him.
There is a difficulty with the second argument {EE 1218al
15). The text of the Eudemian Ethics cannot be right here. The
point is that the good cannot be both something in common and
something for itself {koinon kai choriston). But it seems to me
that the line of thought here is incoherent and cannot be followed out to a logical conclusion. The prteron-hysteron (prior-
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
141
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 142
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
143
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 144
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
145
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 146
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
147
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 148
TRANSLATOR.
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
149
too, there is no altering the fact that the question about the good
is deliberately restricted.
And in similar fashion, the elucidation of the other, inductively derived, concept of the good stays within these confines.
For it is the different aretai that are discovered [by induction] to
be good.
Thus, this first part of the overall argument does not point beyond itself in the direction of the question on which we have focused our inquiry, that is, the relationship between to agathon
(the good) and to on (being). Nevertheless, that the question has
been narrowed to the specific issue of "the good for us" is noted
explicitly in the summary of the Magna Moralia at 1183a7, and
even more explicitly at the climax of that summary: ""hyper tou
agathou ara, kai hyper tou aristou kai hyper tou hemin aristou^^
(about the good and about the best and about the best for us)
(1183a23). In this way we are kept aware of the universal, general reference of "the good."
We are made even more clearly aware of this universal reference in the discussion of the concept of the idea and what this
concept entails. For the postulation of a good in itself plainly derives from Plato's having founded his thinking generally on the
ideas: for Plato, "what a thing is most" means in each case "it
itself" (malista [most] . . . auto [itself]). We find this line of
thought applied here to the good and, as we mentioned at the beginning, Aristotle even grants that Plato's argument has a certain
validity which only in political matters is unimportant and irrelevant. The restricted form that the rejection of Plato's argument
takes here becomes even more conspicuous when it comes time
to take aim at the more general problems that arise in connection
with the universal doctrine of ideas. When it is said then that, in
the realm of politics, we are concerned with a class of goods for
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 150
which the idea of the good has no real relevance as an arche, the
idea of the good as such is not called into questionany more
than the doctrine of the immortality of the soul, for instance, is
called into question when one says that this doctrine has no
place in mathematics.^^
That the overall concern here is with a particular instance of a
more general set of problems is made fully clear by the far more
universal overtones of Aristotle's way of putting things. When
expressions are used here such as dia ten hautou physin haireton
(to be chosen according to the nature of it) (1182b9)which refers back to en hekasti tn ontn (in each of the existent things)
(1182b8)this could easily be taken in a universal teleological
sense such as is implied, for instance, in the Eudemian Ethics at
1218a30, where the reference to Euduxus's doctrine is obvious.
In the Magna Moralia^ to be sure, such general considerations
are not pursued per se, even though Aristotle's formulations virtually invite us to pursue them, and even though in his critique of
the ideas we find such a universal concept as ta noeta (the noetic), which certainly does not make us think primarily of the
practical. Quite the contrary: the allusion of ta noeta to the numbers is patent (1183a24), an allusion that, nonetheless, is not
stated outright. Instead, the text speaks only of the "idea." This
fact notwithstanding, we are dealing here with the same methodological argument that we find in the Eudemian Ethics at
1218al6, where it is expressly pointed out that numbers are not
generally accepted to be the good. The correspondence to the
Eudemian Ethics thus shows that the Magna Moralia too implicitly points beyond the problems of practical philosophy.
16. Dirlmeier makes a convincing case for the dio (therefore) at 1183b7. For
what follows, the simplest emendation, it seems to me, is: ouk oikeian arch en
einai toutn tagathon (the good is not a proper principle of these).
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
151
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 152
fully accords with the aph' henos (from one thing). Accordingly,
in the Metaphysics^ Gamma 2, we find pros hen or pros mian
archen (to one principle), respectively,^^ and the example of
"healthy," which can be said of a human being, a facial color, a
medicine, and so forth. The word "good" could be multivocal in
this way too. That would presuppose something privileged and
primary such as Aristotle's category doctrine specifies [for "to
be"] when it gives priority to "substance" [ousia). The priority
assigned to "substance" is of great significance for Aristotle's
metaphysics, particularly in regard to the theology of the first
mover, which, for its part, is first in the order of substances.
Given this fact, one might expect that here in the Nicomachean
Ethics Aristotle would favor such an attributive relationship
{analogia attributiva) when he sets about grasping the manifold
of agathon. The god or nous (intellect), both of which appear as
examples of substance in the category argument {EN 1096a24),
would then be the summum bonum, the highest good, in which
the attribution terminates. The universal-ontological sense of the
one good would fit perfectly with Aristotle's doctrine of a god.
The 'theological' conclusion of the Eudemian Ethics would also
lead us to expect the same thing.^^
Hence it is all the more surprising that the text continues: "or
rather more according to analogy" (e mallon kaf analogian)
(1096b28) and makes clear by an example that the bare sameness of the relationships, that is, a proportional analogy, is
meant, in which no one thing is given priority over another, and
in which there is consequently no terminus.
This concept of proportional analogy, too, is known to us
17. At the same time, the pros hen is characterized as a special case of the
more general kath* hen legesthai (to speak in one regard).
18. To be sure, MM 1182b9 characterizes the question about the good of the
god as an allotria skepsis (another consideration).
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
153
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 154
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
155
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D 156
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E OF T H E G O O D
157
A R I S T O T L E ' S C R I T I Q U E O F T H E G O O D 158
individual order is good. In his eyes, however, the primary reality that he postulates, that which is first (to proton)^ cannot be
something mathematical; rather, it must be a mover, hos to
kinoun poiei (such as induces movement). When everything is
ordered toward this primary reality, that is indeed "the best of
all" {to ariston pantn)^ and this highest being is at the same
time the fulfillment of what being means. Thus, Aristotle puts
the Platonic heritage, which the question about the good represents, on the ground of physics. And starting there, he develops
his doctrine of being in the conceptual form of an attributive
analogy which has a highest terminus (end point). 'Pure,' proportional analogy cannot accomplish thisit would remain too
close to Platonic ideal mathematics. Hence, we are left with a
paradoxical result: the chrismos (separation) that lives on in
Aristode's theology is not Plato's. On the contrary, the ontology
of the physei onta and the entirety of motion as a whole force
Aristotle to a chrismos of his own, which passes beyond Plato's
mathematically oriented interpretation of the transcendence of
the good.
IV
THE IDEA OF
PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY
The question now becomes all the more pressing why here, in the
Nicomachean Ethics^ Alpha 4, Aristotle gives preference to the
mere analogical structure in inquiry about the good. The reasonwhich suggests itself at oncecould be that he finds the
consequence unwelcome that would be implied in pros hen
legesthai (saying, to one [end]) and in the complete parallel that
it establishes. In the Metaphysics^ Book Gamma, namely, such
an attributive proportionality justifies the authority of one and
the same science for the entire semantic field of "to be." The examplary case is medicine: ''kathaper kai tn hygieinn hapantn
mia episteme estin'' (if indeed there is also one science for all
matters of health) (1003bll). Where all things converge on one
goal [for example, health], a single science is always conceivable.
Hence one must obviously interpret the program of a formal ontology elaborated in Book Gamma according to this schema
even if the connection with the books on substance and the theology in Lambda remain obscure by so doing. In any case in regard to the primary science of "being as such" {on hei on)^ which
Aristotle is pursuing, the attributive analogy argument makes
good sense. But it would be absurd to claim that it is relevant to
the practical question about the good. For that would mean that
recognizing a good time for surgery or assessing a good sign in
159
160
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
161 T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
ory), but not "^phronesis^' in a terminological sense. Nevertheless, the question arises whether practical philosophy is teachable in the same sense that every other science or techne may be
said to be. The state of affairs here becomes even more complicated when we observe that Aristotle disputes that Plato's idea of
the good has any practical utility but emphatically asserts that
his own theory of practical philosophy does. He claims explicitly
that such theoretical instruction as his enhances arete itself. That
it does so is emphasized in all three versions of his ethics. And for
just this reason one can see a problem in how practical philosophy is supposed to relate to phronesis.
This problem has been investigated often in recent times. Still,
it probably appears to be a paradox only to someone who has a
modernistic understanding of "theoretical," such as we derive
from the modern conception of science. For such a person things
do indeed appear odd. Plainly, practical philosophy is not a theoretical science in the modern sensea theoretical science, that
is, which might be applied to practice in the way one puts pure
natural science to use in [applied] medical science. Practical philosophy is rather more like knowledge of cures, and accordingly,
Aristotle often draws comparisons with this kind of knowledge.
Any talk of the "application" of theory to practice would presuppose a separation between the theory Aristotle imparts in
such an ethical pragmatics [as his ethics] and lived practice. And
whatever the case, such a separation does not exist here. The
ideal of an objective theory, neutral in regard to all the interests
at stake in any practical application of it, and consequently capable of any application one might wish to make, is neither Platonic nor Aristotelian. Our investigation of Plato's science program in the Republic^ book 7, made clear how secondary the
application of the mathematical sciences is in his eyes. Aristotle
makes the same point by going to the opposite extreme: in the
162
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
163 T H E I D E A O F P R A C T I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y
164
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
165 T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y
166
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
from deinos (clever) turns on this point (EN, Zeta 13). In this
distinction one sees how very much aware Aristotle is of the difference between technical knowing and practical-moral knowing, and I have attempted to show that here he extends a genuinely Platonic motif. Not the least indication that he does so is
the fact that no real teaching is possible here in the way in which
science and technical knowledge can be taught. On the contrary,
in practical matters the general hermeneutical task which figures
in all instances, that is, of concretizing general knowledge,
always implies the opposite task of generalizing something
concrete.
Practical philosophy by itself can give us no assurance that we
know how to "hit" what is right. Such knowledge remains the
end of practice itself and the virtue of a practical reasonableness
(phronesis)^ which is precisely not mere inventiveness {demotes).
This distinction is important for the theory of the sciences. The
comparison with the archer is found in the introduction to Aristotle's whole course on practical philosophy and politics. At the
start, the governing role played by politics is worked out. Politics
is the highest science or art: ""kuritate kai malista architektonike'' (first of the arts, worthiest and greatest) [EN 1094a26).
At first glance this comment bearing on the theory of scientific
knowing would not seem to accord all that well with the subsequent analysis of phronesis and especially not with what is said
about political phronesis. Ever since Burnet, this discrepancy has
been attributed to Aristotle's having accommodated himself to
Plato's use of language. Viewed purely on the surface of it, this
account is certainly accurate. But Aristotle could not possibly
have spoken in any other way. For we saw, after all, that in practical philosophy we are dealing precisely with philosophy, which
is to say with theory. Its object and, accordingly, what it ultimately is aimed at, is, of course, practice. But that only means
167 T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
168
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
169 T H E I D E A O F P R A C T I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y
170
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
171 T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y
losophy in his moral philosophy, insofar as he divorces the practical, moral imperative from the technical imperative of cleverness. But that is not all; his exposition of the transition from
common to philosophical knowledge, has, it seems to me, universal validity. Philosophy never really finds it necessary to justify its existence, since whoever would contest it is also engaging
in the process of reflection that one calls philosophy.
In returning to Aristotle, we find the intertwining of the theoretical and practical that we have seen at many sorts of cracks
and splits in the structure of his teachings. For one thing, we see
that according to Aristode the highest possibility of awareness,
which the Greeks called ''nous^ (intellection), is to be attributed
to that theoretical knowing which has attained complete selffulfillmentto sophia (wisdom). But the same highest awareness is to be attributed to practical reason as wellnamely, to
phronesis, which in each instance is conscious of the rightness of
its choice and decision. The definitive juxtaposition of theoretical and practical knowing, and hence of the theoretical and practical virtues of knowing, in no way infringes upon the unity of
reason, which governs us in both these directions [in which our
reasoning might move].
Aristotle's conception of a "practical philosophy" is plainly
the consequence of the critique we treated above of Plato's idea
of the good. Nevertheless, his separation of practical philosophy
from theoretical philosophy in no way implies a lack of coherence or an inconsistency in the content [of his thought]. On the
contrary, it is solely out of methodological and argumentative
caution that Aristotle forbids himself any and every extension
[of his practical thought] into more universal considerations.
Not that such a universal, more theoretical background does not
show through in many places. But Aristotle makes use of it in his
argument only where rt is based in universally accepted, given
172
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y
173 T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y
174
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
175 T H E I D E A O F P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
176
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
Practical reasonableness, though, is the precondition for engaging in theory and in developing theoretical reasonableness., At
the same time, practical reasonableness is also something
highest. Indeed, it is this same highest thing, nousalbeit in another application which is not reducible to theory but which is
also a beltiste hexis tou aletheuein (a most excellent disposition
of knowing truly).
With that a final and substantive similarity between Plato's
philosophy and Aristotle's practical philosophy comes into view.
It turns on the relationship [of human life] to the divine, a relationship which both take as the starting point for their thinking
on the finite, conditional, and limited nature of the human being.
Aristotle can repeat genuinely Platonic ways of putting things
when he attempts to describe the approximation of the human
being to the divine. What Hegel claimsnamely, that philosophy itself must surpass its character of striving for knowledge
and become wisdommay not be said for Aristotle.
On that account one may not absolutize the priority given to
the ideal of theoretical life over the ideal of practical-political
life; Aristotle knows just as well as Plato that for human beings
precisely this possibility of the theoretical life is limited and conditional. Human beings cannot devote themselves persistently
and uninterruptedly to thought's pure seeing for precisely the
reason that their nature is composite. Hence, viewed from the
perspective of practical philosophy, the relationship of the two
ideals of life is not such that the complete happiness of practical
life would not be something supreme too. To be sure, Aristotle
calls this happiness a deuteros^ that is, a second best. But this too
is something best, that is, a fulfillment of eudaimonia (happiness). The fulfillment in purely theoretical existence is, after all,
not the full bliss of the gods, since it is a limited fulfillment for
177 T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
human beings. The happiness of nous is in a certain sense separate (kechrismene)beyond all comparison. And precisely for
this reason the practical happiness of human beings is not second
rank, rather precisely what has been apportioned to them. That
holds even if at times they can also rise beyond themselves to the
divine bliss of theria. Does one not find the same thing in
Plato's Republic in regard to how the philosopher-kings will
carry out their office?
Thus the overall result of our investigation is as follows: in
basing the question about being on the physei onta and not on
the universality of the eidos or mathematical-eidetic configurations, Aristotle did indeed subject Plato's teachings to a radical
critique. But in the end did he not carry out what Plato intended
to doindeed, even go beyond it in fulfilling it? There are basic
truths that the Socratic Plato did not lose sight of any more than
did the Platonic Aristotle: in human actions the good we project
as hou heneka (that for the sake of which) is concretized and
defined only by our practical reasonin the euboulia (welladvised-ness) of phronesis. Furthermore, every existent thing is
"good" when it fulfills its telos (purpose, goal). Still, Plato only
anticipated symbolically in his number doctrine what the good
in such a universal sense actually means. Aristotle found conceptual answers to this question. The artificial expression entelecheia^ which Aristotle introduces, is obviously supposed to make
clear precisely that the telos is not a goal that belongs to some
faraway order of perfection. Rather, in each case the telos is realized in the particular existent itself, and realized in such fashion
that the individual contains the telos. Aristotelian metaphysics
keeps this fact in focus as its constant theme. It thinks of the being of what is as the self-mediation of an existent thing with its
"what-it-is" (ti estin), its eidetic determination. I have tried to
178
T H E I D E A OF P R A C T I C A L
PHILOSOPHY
8. Vermittlung von Sein und Werden. Such a mediation is, of course, precisely the task that Hegel sets himself in his Logik. One should not overlook the
Hegelian background in Gadamer's analysis of Plato and Aristotle (cf. "Hegel
and Dialectic of the Ancient Philosophers", TRANSLATOR.
INDEX
180
INDEX
INDEX
181
182
INDEX
Strato, 15
Substance (ousia), 15, 130n, 141; priority of over Ae other categories,
131,152,154n
Sunlight metaphor: in the Parmenides,
11, 87, 118; in the Republic, 28,
76-77, 86-87
Syllogism, practical and theoretical,
165
Symposium, 37n, 115
Temperance (sophrosyne), 27, 69n,
167n
Techne (art), 79; versus arete, phronesis and knowledge of the good,
23, 32, 35, 37, 37n3, 4 6 - 4 9 , 80,
111-12, 131, 165; versus political
practice, 7 8 - 8 0 ; of music and of
letters, 119
Theaetetus, 17, 40, 99; on theria,
39n, 69; on aisthesis, 45, 45nl3
Theognis, 46
Theria: and politics, 67-69; and
praxis, 161,169,171-7^
Theory of scientific knowing, 74,
74n6, 160, 166,168-69
Timaeus, 8,18, 74, 125; on the world
soul, 1 4 3 - 4 4
Topics, 138
The Two, 32, 135, 178. See also Indeterminate duality; Number doctrine; The One
Vico and the rhetorical tradition, 169
Whitehead, A. N., 26
Wissenschaftstheorie. See Theory of
scientific knowing
Wirkung (effect). In; Wirkungsgeschichte (history of effects). In, Wirkungseinheit (unitary effect). In, 2,
5,13n, 173n
Xenophon, 22, 37n, 46, 4 9 - 5 0