Identity in Difference Reading Nishida S
Identity in Difference Reading Nishida S
Identity in Difference Reading Nishida S
TITLE
iii
28
Pacific World
29
30
Pacific World
term appears . . . it is reading too much into it to think that Nishida had
accomplished any kind of Buddhist-philosophical synthesis by using it.
It was his disciples, beginning with Nishitani, who developed Nishidas
intimations into philosophical ideas and related them to Buddhist
ideas.17 In this brief quotation Heisigperhaps inadvertentlyleads
us to consider to what extent Nishitanis development of Nishidas
ideas has influenced the study of Nishida. In other words, at present,
is Nishidas thought being understood through the lens of Nishitanis
ideas? Heisig notes that Nishida was diligent in his efforts to ensure
that Zen was not a grist for his scholarly career.18
More recently, another of Nishidas commentators, Robert J.J.
Wargo, makes clear that Nishida, although influenced by Zen, was not
seeking to provide a philosophic account of Zen experience. Wargo
explains: Nishidas aims are different. He is not out to translate the
content of enlightenment in academic terms or anything of the sort.
While it seems clear that he regards the religious experience as the
deepest and most meaningful of experiences, he is not attempting
to lead the reader to such an experience nor to relate accounts of
the experience to others. What he does try to do is give a precise
formulation of the structure of the world that takes into account
this kind of experience.19 Wargos understanding of Nishidas goals
provides a useful point from which to begin a reexamination of
Nishida. One can acknowledge that Zen Buddhism influenced Nishidas
philosophic project without claiming Nishidas philosophy is a Zen
Buddhist philosophy. This allows for and acknowledges the need to
explore other areas of influence on Nishidas philosophic project.
While not the focus of this essay, given the tremendous impact
Nishidas philosophy had at the time of the Japanese imperial campaign, it is imperative that studies of Nishidas work consider what if
any role Nishidas philosophy had in these efforts. In this vein, Faure
argues that the rhetoric of the Kyoto school, including that of Nishida,
has remained trapped in Orientalist and nativist structures.20 Nishida
often refers to the emperor and the imperial throne as being central to
the kokutai (national polity, ) of Japan. However, as Agustn Jacinto
Zavala claims, the imperial throne that Nishida locates at the center of
his philosophical project is mythical rather than historical.21 Nishidas
language, however, when talking about the role of the emperor, is at
best ambiguous. Consider the following passage from a lecture Nishida
31
32
Pacific World
33
discusses with ease Zen, Jdo Shinsh, and Christianity. Takemura explains that upon closer examination he came to believe that the roots
of this essay were not found in Zen, but rather in Pure Land Buddhism.34
That Nishida would devote considerable energies to Pure Land
Buddhism when detailing his philosophy of religion shows the influence that Pure Land Buddhism had on his life. Nishidas family, as
Takemura points out, were followers of Pure Land Buddhism. The
house where Nishida was born was near Chraku Temple, a temple
of the tani sect of Pure Land Buddhism.35 In the very first sentence
of his Gutoku Shinran, Nishida notes that his mother was a devout
Pure Land Buddhist.36 Yusa, in her biography of Nishida, describes his
mother, Tosa, as a woman of iron will, a devout Pure Land Buddhist,
with a heart of gold. Nishida, according to Yusa, as a young child grew
up imbibing his mothers generosity and religious devotion through
her milk (which he did not give up until the age of three or four).37
Yusas use of language is more than poetic waxing, as Takemura details: When Nishida would pester his mother to breastfeed him, his
mother usually would say, If you can recite Rennyos Letters, I will
feed you. Then Nishida would easily recite one of Rennyos letters, rub
his mothers bosom, and then his mother, satisfied, would breastfeed
him.38 While this is highly anecdotal, and other similar stories substitute Tannish for Rennyos Letters, the point is that from a young age
Nishida was aware of, and on a basic level influenced by, Jdo Shinsh
teachings.
That Tannish is often substituted for Rennyos Letters in the above
stories is not surprising, given that in his later years Nishida would
express great interest in the Tannish. Takemura notes that there is
a genuine lack of consensus as to when Nishida first read Tannish:
some claim Nishida encountered it for the first time while enrolled as
a special student in the philosophy department of Tokyo University;
others claim he read it on his own. However, it is known that when
Nishida was teaching at the Fourth Higher School he would on occasion
skim through its pages.39
In spite of his family background and early exposure to Shin
thought, scholars have tended to focus on Nishidas philosophic
project almost exclusively as a philosophy of Zen. Jdo Shinsh, we
have already seen, was a salient presence in his childhood home.
Contrast this with Nishidas experience with Zenhe began serious
practice in 1897, was given the lay Buddhist name Sunshin in
34
Pacific World
1901, and in 1905 ceased practicing Zen; from 1907 there is no mention
of Zen in Nishidas diary.40 In 1910, Nishida and his family moved to
Kyoto as Nishida had been appointed assistant professor of ethics at
Kyoto Imperial University (present-day Kyoto University). During his
first week in Kyoto Nishida and his family spent some time sightseeing.
Notable on the list of places Nishida and his family visited was the
Higashi-honganji , head temple of the Shinshu tani-ha
sect of Pure Land Buddhism.41 Absent from this list are
the famous Zen temples of Kyoto. Finally, after Nishidas death, his
ashes and bones were divided into thirds and buried at three sites: his
familys temple in Unoke (Jdo Shinsh), Tkeiji in Kamakura (Rinzai
Zen), and Myshinji in Kyoto (Rinzai Zen).42
From this we can conclude that Zen and Pure Land Buddhism both
occupied prominent roles in Nishidas life. The near exclusive focus on
the influence of Zen on Nishidas philosophy, or the idea that Nishida
had as his goal elucidating a Zen philosophy, thus ignores the impact
and influence that Jdo Shinsh thought and practice had on his life.
While acknowledging the influence of Zen on Nishidas thought,
particularly his early philosophic thought, there is an increasing recognition of a need to understand how Nishida uses Shinrans conceptions of Pure Land Buddhist thought in his philosophic project. At the
same time it is not the case that Nishidas thought is an example of
a Shin philosophy, any more than it is of a Zen philosophy. Rather,
Nishidas philosophy was influenced by his experiences of growing up
in a Pure Land Buddhist household, and Jdo Shinsh doctrinal concepts provide a useful hermeneutic lens for understanding Nishidas
philosophy because he himself made use of Shin concepts to understand Zen.
Shin Buddhist scholars, according to Heisig, have historically dismissed Nishidas thought for having disagreed with traditional interpretations of Shinran.43 In the rare instances when scholars have
documented a connection between Pure Land thought and Nishidas
philosophy, it has become all too common to simply note the connection in passing without further development. For example, Hirota,
explaining the dualism of self-power and other-power in Pure Land
Buddhism, states, Nishida Kitar sketches a broad vision of the advance of human knowledge as an overcoming of subjective delusions
and a move toward true knowledge that is also love, employing the dichotomy of self-power and other-power.44 After noting the connection
35
in this one sentence Hirota returns to his discussion of Shinran without probing further Nishidas understanding of Shinrans thought or
even explaining why the inclusion of Nishidas thought was necessary
in the scheme of Hirotas paper.
One final reason that may lead many scholars to avoid a sustained
discussion of Nishidas thought is the difficulty of reading Nishida. Ueda
Shizuteru has suggested that it is as if the 5,000 pages of Nishidas
writings were a single essay which took him a lifetime to write, so that
the conclusion of any particular published unit is a mere fiction, soon
to turn into the starting point for the next step in the argument.45
The Relationship of Self and Other as a Concept for Understanding Nishida
Nishidas philosophic project was influenced by a number of
sources, including Pure Land and Zen. Recognizing that there are few
works that have explored the influence of Jdo Shinsh thought on
Nishidas philosophy, this essay attempts to explore the relationship
of self (religious practitioner) and other (Amida Buddha) as it relates
to Nishidas concept of the self-identity of absolute contradiction.
The self-identity of absolute contradiction, according to Gereon
Kopf, is the key to understanding Nishidas philosophy.46 Nishida explains the self-identity of absolute contradiction as follows:
The self is that which acts. Action arises in, and from, a mutual relationship between things. Action presupposes a relationship of mutual
negation, wherein one negates the other and the other negates the
first. This mutual negation is simultaneously a mutual affirmation.
Each thing realizes its own uniqueness. That is, each thing becomes
itself. That two things stand opposed to each other and negate each
other means that they are mutually conjoined and compose one
form.47
Scholars have already noted the compatibility of this idea with general
Mahyna theories of non-duality. For example, Kopf explains the selfidentity of absolute contradiction means that the absolute is defined
by and expresses itself in its opposite the relative, and the transcendence in immanence.48 In other words, that which is absolute does not
exist apart from the relative, and the relative does not exist apart from
the absolute. This description seems to be rooted in and echoing the
well-known theory of the two truths.49
Although conforming to general Mahyna descriptions of
Buddhism, Nishida often refers to Pure Land doctrine and concepts
36
Pacific World
when explaining the self-identity of absolute contradiction. It is therefore necessary to examine how Shin Buddhism explains the relationship between the absolute and the relative.
The Shin Buddhist tradition seems to have understood the relationship between religious practitioner and buddha in two radically different ways.50 First, Shinran believes that a person of shinjin is equal
to the buddhas. 51 Shinran makes this clear in a letter to Jshin when he
states: the person of true shinjin is said to be equal to the Buddhas. He
is also regarded as being the same as Maitreya, who is in [the rank of]
succession to Buddhahood.52 Similarly, Rennyo (, 14151499), the
eighth head priest of Jdo Shinsh, describes the relationship between
religious practitioners and buddha using the cryptic phrase butsu-bon
ittai (, the oneness of Buddhas mind and foolish beings).
However, Yuien-bo, the author of the Tannish, records that Shinran
gives himself as an example in order to make us realize that we are
in delusion, knowing nothing at all of the depths of our karmic evil or
the vastness of Amidas benevolence.53 Similarly in the Postscript
of the Kygyshinsh , Shinran, quoting Daochuo, describes a
process in which those who have been born first [in the Pure Land]
guide those who come later.54 Shinran throughout his writings argues,
Nirvana is attained without severing blind passions.55 In these statements, it becomes clear that within the Pure Land Buddhist tradition
we find two seemingly contradictory conceptions concerning the relationship of sentient beings with Amida, the Pure Land, and nirvana;
the first statement is that of equality, the second is one of inequality.
These contradictory understandings of the relationship between
sentient beings and buddha can be used to illuminate Nishidas explanation of the self-identity of absolute contradiction. For example,
Nishida states, That two things stand opposed to each other and
negate each other means that they are mutually conjoined and compose one form. Shinran maintains that sentient beings are both equal
and not equal to the buddhas. Nishida similarly argues that through
a process of mutual negation and affirmation, a unity between the
absolute and the relative is achieved and the uniqueness of both self
and other are maintained. The goal of this essay is to show in greater
detail how Jdo Shinsh doctrinal concepts are useful in elucidating
the meaning of Nishidas philosophy.
37
Overview
The following sections expand on and seek to substantiate the claims
outlined above. The next section explores how Nishida conceived of
the relationship of self and other by examining Nishidas thought and
the Shin Buddhist influences on his thought. Recognizing that philosophic work does not occur in a vacuumthat there is no Archimedean
point from which philosophizing occursNishidas works will be read
in light of certain events in his life. Reading Nishidas philosophy in
this way will point to possible influences of Shinrans thought and Jdo
Shinsh religious experiences in Nishidas life.
In order to understand the significance of this aspect of Nishidas
philosophy more fully, we next focus on Shinran and Jdo Shinsh
thought concerning the relationship of self and other. The notion that
sentient beings are both equal to and different from buddhas will be
explored further. Additionally, a discussion of the metaphors Shinran
uses when describing Amida and the Pure Land path will be explored.
Special consideration will be given to the idea that the Pure Land path
is an intersubjective path. Intersubjectivity in this context is understood as the recognition that the individual grows in and through relationships with others. Furthermore, intersubjectivity maintains that
in recognizing the other, we need to see the other as both different
and alike.56 This theory will be especially useful in elucidating the
concept of butsu-bon ittai in that the oneness is not a mystical union between sentient beings and buddha, but rather a non-dual one in which
differences are maintained. Up until now, Shin Buddhist scholars have
largely ignored this concept, in part because the necessary hermeneutic tools have not been available. Thus, in this section the concept of
butsu-bon ittai will be read in light of feminist psychoanalyst Jessica
Benjamins theory of intersubjectivity, and doing so will help to clarify
the idea of oneness between sentient beings and buddha.
In the last section these twoShin thought and intersubjectivityare brought together, allowing us to reread Nishida in light of
Jdo Shinsh thought. This rereading and reconsideration of Nishidas
thought fills a lacuna present in both studies of Nishidas philosophy
and Shin Buddhist studies, giving sustained attention to Nishidas understanding and use of Pure Land Buddhist sources. This study also
contributes to the field of Buddhist studies more generally, exploring
the dynamics of the intersubjective relationship between religious
practitioner and buddha.57 Even more broadly, this study contributes
38
Pacific World
39
40
Pacific World
41
42
Pacific World
with Kiyozawas work and in his dairies had expressed a basic agreement with Kiyozawas understanding of religion.76 Additionally, it is
worth mentioning that Nishida references Shinran twice in An Inquiry
into the Good, in conjunction with quotes from the Tannish.77 While this
number is not striking on its own, combined with the fact that Nishida,
as mentioned above, does not reference Dgen , Rinzai, or Zen thought
in An Inquiry into the Good, we once again see that at this stage in his life,
although practicing Zen Nishida was familiar with and continued to be
influenced by Shin Buddhism.
Nishida closes the fourth section of An Inquiry into the Good with a
chapter titled Knowledge and Love (Chi to ai, ), which was
originally published as an independent article in the August 1907 issue
of Seishinkai , a journal founded by Kiyozawa in 1901.78 The goal
of Seishinkai was promoting Kiyozawas religious ideals, namely the
need for spiritual reform.79 Yusa notes that Nishida wrote this chapter
while grieving the death of his second daughter, Yko, from bronchitis. She was five years old, and her death shook Nishida profoundly.80
Further, Yusa asserts that Nishida realized that by means of philo
sophy alone he could not find a reason for Ykos death, and that it
was Nishidas mother, sustained by her faith in Amida Buddha, who
consoled Nishida. As a result, Nishida threw himself into the ocean of
divine compassion.81 That Nishida would find solace in Shin Buddhism
suggests that Shin Buddhism, although not satisfying him intellectuallyas is evidenced by the fact that Nishida does not credit Shin as
functioning in his philosophic projectwas a pneumatic force, that is a
vital energy, in Nishidas life.
Shortly after the publication of An Inquiry into the Good, Nishida
published Gutoku Shinran (Foolish Stubble-Haired Shinran,
) in April 1911 as part of collection of essays compiled by the alumni
of tani University in commemoration of the six hundred fiftieth anniversary of Shinrans deathfurther indication that Nishida was actively involved in Shin intellectual circles at this time. Coincidentally,
1911 also marked the year Nishida began teaching part time at tani,
in addition to his position at Kyoto University.82
In Gutoku Shinran, Nishida places great emphasis on the role of
religious transformation. For example, Nishida writes: Every person,
no matter who he is, must return to the original body of his own naked
self; he must let go from the cliffs ledge and come back to life after perishing, or he cannot know them [wisdom and virtue]. In other words,
43
only the person who has been able to experience deeply what it is to
be foolish/stubble-haired can know wisdom and virtue.83 There are
a number of ways in which to interpret this paragraph. Those familiar
with Zen may find similar concepts within Nishidas writing, particularly the phrase let go from the cliffs ledge and come back to life after
perishing with the concept of shinjin datsuraku (, casting off
of body and mind).84 Shin Buddhists, on the other hand, may find this
phrase echoing the transformation that occurs upon the abandoning
of ones own efforts at enlightenment and entrusting in the workings
of Amida Buddhas primal vow.
This Nishida article gives two examples to explain his point, one
from Zen used to introduce the problem, and one from Shinrans writing to explain the effect and meaning of religious transformation.
Nishidas citation of Shinran is the oft-quoted passage from Tannish,
in which Shinran says: When I consider deeply the Vow of Amida,
which arose from five kalpas of profound thought, I realize that it was
entirely for the sake of myself alone! Then how I am filled with the
gratitude for the Primal Vow, in which Amida resolved to save me,
though I am burdened with such heavy karma.85 Nishida argues in this
quote one finds the fundamental significance of Shin Buddhism. That
is, no matter how evil a person is, he or she can be saved by the workings of Amida Buddha, and that at the moment of religious transformation one realizes that Amidas vow was made specifically for ones self
alone.86
One final consideration of Gutoku Shinran shows Nishida was interested in and influenced by Shin thought and scholarship. As Fujita
points out, Nishidas writing style in Gutoku Shinran is similar to
Kiyozawas style of writing in the Seishinkai.87
From the above, it is clear that Nishida was familiar with both
Zen and Pure Land texts. We also see that Nishida was influenced by
his contemporaries with ties to both Zen and Pure Land thinkers.
Based on this it is possible to conclude that Nishida was familiar with
both Zen and Pure Land religiosity. As Nishidas philosophic project
progressed, following the publication of An Inquiry into the Good and
Gutoku Shinran, Nishida would not make any explicit reference to
Shin Buddhism in his writing for thirty-four years, until The Logic of
Topos and the Religious Worldview (1945).
44
Pacific World
45
46
Pacific World
and Nishida philosophy. For example, Kosaka argues that Nishida was
not aware that his thought bore any resemblance to Pure Land thought
until it was pointed out to him by D. T. Suzuki and Mudai Risaku, another
of Nishidas students.98 It thus comes as a surprise to see that Kosaka
writes that the inspiration for gyakutai is found in the Tannish.99
Kosaka believes that the inspiration for this idea comes from Shinrans
oft-quoted phrase, Even a good person attains birth in the Pure Land,
so it goes without saying that an evil person will.97 Kosaka argues that
this phrase shows there is no limit to the Buddhas compassion.100
Thus, Kosaka suggests a correspondence between Nishidas non-dualism of absolute and relative (gyakutai) and the idea that Amidas vow
is made for the evil person.
Nishidas thought here resembles the well-known Shin Buddhist
concept of nishu jinshin (two aspects of [the] deep mind, ).
Nishu jinshin is the description of the realization that ones own person
is unable to awaken the aspiration for birth in the Pure Land due to
ones karmic evilness. Simultaneous with this realization is total entrusting and rejoicing in the fact that one has attained birth in the
Pure Land, brought about by the activity of Amida Buddhas primal
vow. Simply put, at the very moment one rejoices in the assurance of
birth in the Pure Land through the activity of Amida Buddha, one also
realizes that ones existence is controlled by samsaric delusions and
passions.101
Turning our attention to The Logic of Topos itself we see that,
not counting the sections devoted to Pure Land and Zen Buddhism,
the number of times Nishida explicitly refers to Pure Land and Zen
are nearly equal (17 Pure Land, and 18 Zen). What is most striking is
the language Nishida uses when discussing Pure Land and Zen. For example, when Nishida begins describing the logic of Zen Buddhism he
states, Regarding Zen Buddhism, which has exerted a great deal of
influence on Japanese culture, I must defer to specialists.100 Later in
this same section Nishida attempts to use Shinrans teaching to explain
his understanding of Zen. Nishida writes, The logic of paradox is not
irrationality. It is, in Shinrans words, to take as the discriminating
principal that which goes beyond discrimination.103 As shown above
regarding the concept mu, Nishida understood Zen through Shinrans
teaching. Perhaps realizing that he did not understand Zen in the
terms of Zen, Nishida defers to experts regarding Zen.
47
48
Pacific World
49
50
Pacific World
the role of the other in Shin Buddhism, both philosophically and psychologically. Following Kopf, Manimala, and Ziporyn, this discussion of
otherness will be grounded in philosophic and psychoanalytic theories
of intersubjectivity.
Following a general overview of the theory of intersubjectivity
the recognition that an individual grows in and through relationships
with otherswe will then briefly look at the role of the self and other
in Mahyna Buddhism, particularly as developed in The Awakening
of Faith in Mahyna and the Huayan school (Kegon, ).116 This
will establish a basis for a detailed examination of intersubjectivity in
Shin Buddhism. Particular attention will be paid to the Shin Buddhist
path as presented by Shinran and Rennyo. In addition, traditional
Shin Buddhist scholarship concerning the role of self and other will be
analyzed.
Recognizing the Need for Multiple Subjects: Intersubjectivity
Intersubjectivity, simply put, is the philosophical and psychological theory that individuals are affected by other individuals (subjects).
Theories of intersubjectivity are rooted in the existential philosophies
of the twentieth century. The philosophic position generally referred
to as existentialism was first postulated by Sren Kierkegaard (1813
1855) and Friedrich Nietzsche (18441900), who emphasized the role of
the individual in their critiques of G. W. F Hegels (17701881) ration
alism. Existentialism reached its apex as a movement with Jean-Paul
Sartre (19051980), who transformed the phenomenological methods
of Martin Heidegger in such a way that it was no longer reclusive, but
rather became a starting point for activism.117
Existentialism has been used to describe the philosophies of
Karl Jaspers, Martin Heidegger (although he himself renounced this
label), Martin Buber, Simone de Beauvoir, Maurice Merleau-Ponty,
and Gabriel Marcel, among others. Traces of existentialism can also
be found in the post-structuralism and deconstruction movements
led by such notable figures as Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida. At
present, the influence of existentialism is found in a number of diverse
areas. For example, American philosopher Judith Butlers work has
been foundational in number of diverse areas, including literary criticism, gay and lesbian studies, and queer theory. Butlers work, as we
see below, has been instrumental in shaping Benjamins understanding
of intersubjectivity. Existentialism has also long been influential in the
51
52
Pacific World
ones self as both different and alike, since the other as object is wholly
other. Within this brief explanation of intersubjectivity, it is possible
to identify two fundamental characteristics of the intersubjective encounter: recognition and subjectivity.
Regarding the fundamental need for recognition, Benjamin explains, A person comes to feel that I am the doer who does, I am the
author of my acts, by being with a person who recognizes her acts, her
feelings, her intentions, her independence.123 Based on this need for
recognition it becomes clear that ones sense of self grows out of ones
relationship with an other. As Butler explains, the self never returns
to itself free of the Other . . . relationality becomes constitutive of who
the self is.124 In other words, relationships with others are internalized in that relationships not only connect us to others but also define
who we are or what we will become. Relationships are, therefore, constitutive, that is, they are essential to ones very being.
That recognition from another subject is necessary in establishing
ones understanding of self as subject leads to what Benjamin describes
as the paradox of recognition. Benjamin explains, at the very moment
of realizing our own independence, we are dependent upon another
to recognize it. At the very moment we come to understand the meaning of I, myself, we are forced to see the limitations of that self. At
the moment we realize that separate minds can share the same state,
we also realize these minds can disagree.125 In other words, the very
awareness that we are individuals is dependent upon an awareness of
our limitations. Throughout her work Benjamin provides a number of
examples showing that even in relationships of domination, where one
seeks control of the other, recognition and a sense of otherness must
be maintained, for if one subsumes the other into ones self, both self
and other cease to exist.
The intersubjective relationship does not seek to collapse the relationship of self and other into a unified understanding of self and
other, where the self is all that exists and the other is wholly other or
an object of the selfs psyche. Rather, intersubjective theory sees the
relationship between self and other, with its tension between sameness
and difference, as a continual exchange of influence. It focuses, not
on a linear movement from oneness to separateness, but on the paradoxical balance between them.126 In other words, self and other do not
exist in two wholly separate worlds, as self and other are not wholly
different. Nor are self and other undifferentiated; differences remain.
53
The boundary that separates self and other is, at best, fuzzy. While we
may have shared experiences with the other, that the other remains
an other is what makes these experiences so powerful. Benjamin explains, The fact that self and other are not merged is precisely what
makes experiences of merging have such high emotional impact. The
externality of the other makes one feel one is truly being fed, getting
nourishment from the outside, rather than supplying everything for
oneself.
In her later work Benjamin clarifies that in shared experience the
other, by necessity, remains an other. When self denies the externality
of the other through forced assimilation of the other, one is plunged
into unbearable aloneness . . . creating an identity that demands the
destructive denial of the different.127 Benjamin repeatedly shows how
the denial of difference can lead to abusive situations. Yet, even in relationships of domination, which seek to destroy the other, Benjamin
finds that the need for other subjects remains primary. Relationships
of domination, as Benjamin explains, depend on the other subject
recognizing the power the self wields through submission.128
Intersubjectivity, as presented by Benjamin, makes clear the necessity or other consciousness in forming identity. It is through our
relationships with others that we come to understand what it means
to be. Relationships not only affirm who we think we are but also by
necessity negate conceptions of who we are as well. Ones identity as a
unique individual occurs not in realization of sameness, nor in recognition that the other is different from ones self, but rather in the other
recognizing and confirming that the self is, the self does.
There are, therefore, both philosophic and psychological necessities for understanding the other as both similar to and different from
the self. This discussion, grounded in the feminist psychoanalytic project of Benjamin, will be the heuristic lens used in the following to explore the relationship of self and other in Mahyna Buddhism, with
particular emphasis on the Jdo Shinsh tradition.
Intersubjectivity in Early Mahyna Buddhist Thought
In the American context, Buddhist practice is often understood
and presented as a solitary endeavor. The impact and importance of
other subjects has often been downplayed or denied when describing
Buddhist paths towards awakening (satori, ). For example, in recent
years Jeff Shore, a longtime Rinzai Zen practitioner and professor of
54
Pacific World
55
present others have been an integral part of Buddhist paths of awakening. Second, we again see that with a few notable exceptions, Buddhist
scholars and teachers have had a tendency to downplay the role of self
and other.
However, things are not as nearly as neat as the above indicates.
Brook Ziporyn explains: [C]urrent reconstructions of the early (Pali)
Buddhist doctrine, especially as found in Abhidharmic dharma analysis, reveal an approach to consciousness that can be described as atomistic and empiricist, if not almost solipsistic. . . . The same can be said
for Indian Mahyna doctrine . . . in one way or another, most Indian
Mahyna schools deny the ultimate existence of other minds, either
because all minds are really manifestations of one essence (Tathgatagarbha, Suchness, and the like), or because the category of otherness
(like sameness) belongs to the realm of those delusions dispelled by
an insight into Emptiness.135 Alterity, that is, a state of being other, in
Abhidharmic thought is thus understood as being an example of the
conventional truth of this world. Any sense of alterity, like a sense of
self, thus fades away when one realizes the ultimate truth of emptiness
(Skt. nyat; Jpn. k, ).136
Both Kopf and Ziporyn argue that in Indian Mahyna Buddhism,
with the introduction of the bodhisattva ideal, we find the beginnings
of Buddhist theories of intersubjectivity.137 Simply put, the bodhi
sattva ideal is rejection of individual enlightenment in favor of universal enlightenment. The denial of individual enlightenment usually
occurs through a series of vows often taking the form of If X occurs
and Y does not follow, then I will not attain universal enlightenment.
Perhaps one of the most well-known vows is the that of Amida Buddha
(Amida Butsu, ), then Dharmkara Bodhisattva (Hz Bosatsu,
), who vowed: If, when I attain Buddhahood, sentient beings
in the lands of the ten directions who sincerely and joyfully entrust
themselves to me, desire to be born in my land, and think of me even
ten times should not be born there, may I not attain perfect enlightenment. Excluded, however are those who commit the grave offenses
and abuse the Right Dharma.138 The bodhisattva vows are thus an act
of great compassion. However, they also seem to introduce a binary
understanding of self and other into the Buddhist discourse. Early
Mahyna Buddhist discourse, as Ziporyn argues above, is somewhat
solipsistic when it comes to understandings self and other. In order
to better understand the role of self and other, consideration must be
56
Pacific World
57
58
Pacific World
the pure lands may be far away, to one with a pure mind even the
ordinary defiled world is itself a pure land.151 In the final section of
the Avatasaka-stra, upon entering Vairocana Buddhas (Birushana
Butsu, ) Tower, Sudhana, the pilgrim, is confronted with
a series of visually overwhelming images. The narrator of the sutra
explains, [Sudhana] also looked inside, [and he saw] numerous, hundreds and thousands of beautiful, fabulous towers. Each tower was
similarly ornamented, very vast and very beautiful. Each tower was
vast as all of space, containing all other towers, yet each tower was distinct. All towers were inside one tower.152 Attempting to understand
this imagery can be a very frustrating and humbling experience. One
quickly finds that everyday spatial and temporal understandings of the
world are simply not equipped to aid in comprehending a world containing multiple towers of infinity. However, what is perhaps the most
surprising attribute about the world of these towers is that it is the
very world in which we find ourselves.
Given the above, one quickly sees why Huayan thinkers focused on
the systematic explanation of the dharmadhtu. One example of this
explanation is Tu-shuns (, 557640) Meditation on the Dharmadhtu
(Ch. I fa-chieh; Jpn. Ikkan hkai, ). Tu-shuns Meditation is helpful in that it begins by explaining the world of our everyday consciousness and then methodologically advances in four steps to an understanding of the world as the Avatasaka-stra presents it. Tu-shuns
four meditations are the dharmadhtu of (1) shih (Jpn. ji, ), (2) li (Jpn.
ri, ),153 (3) non-obstruction of li against shih (Ch. li-shih wu-ai; Jpn. ji ri
muge, ), and (4) non-obstruction of shih against shih (Ch. shihshih wu-ai; Jpn. ji ji muge, ).154
The first dharmadhtu, shih, is the dharmadhtu of particulars or
events. This understanding, one that is ultimately rendered untenable,
creates distinctions and distance between particulars. Individual particulars are seen as being wholly other from all other particulars. All
particulars in this understanding are rendered as individual things
devoid of any similarity and therefore alienated from one another in
an autistic state of existence.
The second dharmadhtu, li, is the realm of suchness, or as Chang
translates it, immanent reality (tathat).155 Li, according to Chang, is
the invisible controller of all events. He goes on to describe li as the
all-inclusive and many-sided principal for all existence.156 However,
as Peter N. Gregory points out, understandings of li as immanent
59
60
Pacific World
Indras net (a net with a jewel tied in at every knot, each jewel reflecting all the other jewels in the net), where each and every shih reflects
all other shih ad infinitum.
Tu-shuns Meditation is one of many attempts by Huayan thinkers to explicate the meaning of the dharmadhtu. Perhaps the most
well-known attempt is Fa-tsangs Treatise on the Golden Lion (Ch. ChinShih-Tzu Chang; Jpn. Kin Shishi Sh, ), delivered at the request
of Empress Wu (, 625705). Williamss summary of Fa-tsangs
teachings is especially illuminating regarding how Huayan thinkers
approached issues of identity and difference. Williams writes,
[P]henomena are nothing more than noumenon in a particular form,
and form does not in itself exist, so all phenomena are identical.
Moreover, noumenon cannot in itself be divided. One piece of gold
and another piece of gold, as gold, are not different. The difference
lies in spatial separation, and that is something to do with shape or
form, not gold qua gold. Since a phenomenon is only a noumenon,
and since between any two instantiations of noumenon there is,
as noumenon, no difference, so each phenomenon is in fact the same
as any other phenomena. Furthermore, since each instantiation of
noumenon is noumenon itself (noumenon cannot be divided), so each
phenomenon is also all phenomena. Hence there is mutual identity
and interpenetration. Second, since the dharmadhtu is a totality
of interdependent elements, and according to Mdhyamika teaching each entity lacks inherent existence and only is in terms of an
infinite network of casual interrelationships so, if any entity were
taken away, the entire Universe would collapse. This means that each
entity is a cause for the totality. Moreover the totality is, of course, a
cause for each entity.161
From this we can surmise that for Fa-tsang, and likely the larger
Huayan tradition as a whole, self and other are not inherently different, nor are they entirely the same. Self and other are different as a
result of not only spatial separation, but also as a result of causes and
conditions that bring self and other into existence through cycles of
birth and death. The reality of otherness is important in that if otherness is subsumed into the self, the entire universe collapses, including
the self.
All too often lost amid the complex philosophy of the Huayan
school is the emphasis on teachers on the Buddhist paths of awakening. McMahans work is a notable exception to this, given that his focus
is not on how Huayan Buddhism developed in China, but rather on how
61
62
Pacific World
63
dualisms of this initial engagement dissolve as one comes to understand the non-duality of the Pure Land path.166
However, some scholars have recently acknowledged the role of
concrete others as a form of dualism that is part of the Shin Buddhist
path to awakening. James Dobbins, a leading Shin Buddhist historian,
has noted that while Shinran does present a non-dual understanding
of the relationship between religious practitioner and Amida Buddha
or the Pure Land, Shinran also teaches a dualistic understanding of the
Pure Land path: There is indisputable evidence that Shinran himself
never actually abrogated this dualistic understanding. At the level of
day-to-day interchanges with his companions he frequently treated
the Pure Land as an otherworldly place where one would be born after
death. For instance, in one of his letters Shinran wrote to a disciple
that, because he himself was advanced in years, he would pass away
first, be born in the Pure Land, and be waiting for his disciple there.167
Shinrans explanation of the Pure Land path as dualistic, as Dobbins
goes on to explain, was fundamental to Pure Land discourse at the
practiced level of religion no matter how important nondualism was
at the idealized level of doctrine.168 That Shinran continued to teach
ideas of dualism suggests that dualistic understandings of the Pure
Land path are far more than immature understandings of the Pure
Land path. Recognizing Shinranss emphasis on the Pure Land as being
otherworldly and Amida as other prompts a reconsideration of issues
of identity and difference in Shin Buddhist thought. This reconsideration must also address arguments that understandings of duality on
the Shin Buddhist path are signs of an immature faith.169
Statements in Shinrans writings demonstrate his idea of the
Pure Land path as one of both duality and non-duality. Of particular
interest to us here is how Shinran describes the relationship between
religious practitioner and Amida Buddha. An examination of Rennyos
writings also reveals a conception of Pure Land Buddhism as both dual
and non-dual.
Shinran on the Relationship between
Religious Practitioner and Amida Buddha
Shinrans conception of the Shin Buddhist path of awakening describes the relationship between religious practitioner and Amida
Buddha in two fundamentally different waysboth in terms of duality and in terms of non-duality. Shin Buddhist scholarship has tended
64
Pacific World
65
of birth and death once more. To say sentient beings are the same as
Maitreya means that it is certain that both will attain buddhahood.
Maitreya and sentient beings must transmigrate through the cycles of
birth and death once more before attaining buddhahood.
However, at the end of the second letter above, Shinran makes
clear that one should not think of ones self-power as being equal to the
tathgatas. Shinran writes, To think in self-power that one is equal to
the Tathagatas is a great error. But it is because of the shinjin of Other
Power that you rejoice; how can self-power enter into it? Please consider this fully.173 Shinran believes that blind passions and delusions
are so strong that it is impossible to entrust in the activity of the vow
through ones own calculation (hakarai, ). It is only through
the calculation (onhakarai, ) of Amida Buddha that shinjin is
attained and enlightenment is ensured. One is fundamentally different
from buddhas in that blind passions still shape the way one acts and
views the world.
Shinrans understanding of identity as being one of change where
the religious practitioner is transformed from a state of delusion to a
state of buddhahood is centered in Mahyna Buddhist thought, particularly the thought of Chih-i (, 538597), the founder and systematizer of the Tiantai school in China, who put forth the doctrine
of the six identities. The doctrine of the six identities clarifies not only
the relationship of identity and difference, but that of doctrine and
practice as well. The six identities, as explained by Neil Donner, are:
1. Identity in principle. This affirms inherent Buddhahood.
2. Verbal identity. Here intellectual understanding that we are
Buddhas is gained.
3. Identity of religious practice. Here behavior and mental state are
brought into correspondence with the prior verbal formulations.
The Mo-ho chi-kuan [Jpn. Maka shikan, ] compares this to the
practice of archery, in which one begins by aiming at large targets,
then gradually reduces the target size until finally one can hit the
hundredth part of a hair.
4. Identity of resemblance. Ones thoughts and evaluations approach
what has been expounded in the stras of previous Buddhas.
5. Identity of partial truth. Ignorance weakens and wisdom becomes
increasingly prominent.
6. Ultimate identity. Buddhahood, the final fruit.174
66
Pacific World
67
68
Pacific World
Within this hymn, we see that Amida Buddha has gone beyond form
and is beyond sentient beings capabilities for expression, thus all the
buddhas praise the light of Amida Buddha. However, sentient beings
can only realize Amida Buddha as form, given the delusions that characterize sentient beings existence. Shinran explains that Amida by
necessity has to take form. In a Ks wasan written in praise of Hnen,
Shinran writes:
Amida Tathagata, manifesting form in this world,
Appeared as our teacher Genk;
The conditions for teaching having run their course,
He returned to the Pure Land.183
Shinran here clearly believes that Amida Buddha, realizing the necessity of taking form in the world, appeared as Hnen. The form that was
made manifest ceased to be in the world, but the teaching remained,
and perhaps even for some of those who were to follow the Pure Land
path at present Shinran has come to be seen as Amida.
In Shinrans thought the absolute, that is, suchness, takes form. In
taking form, the absolute is able to encounter sentient beings in the
midst of their delusions. Shinran and many other Buddhist thinkers
69
felt that the age of mapp (end of the dharma, ) was at hand. Thus it
was no longer possible to realize awakening through practice; one had
to rely on the power of a buddha to bring about awakening. Hnens
appearing in the world as Amida was the formless taking form as a concrete other that Shinran and others could identify with suchness and
thus attain shinjin, assuring birth in the Pure Land. In other words, for
Shinran, Pure Land soteriology is characterized by the formless manifesting form, enlightenment in the midst of delusion.
Rennyo and the Unity of Buddha and Foolish Beings
As the Shin Buddhist tradition developed in Japan, new doctrines
and new hermeneutic devices were used in order to better understand
the relationship between Amida Buddha and sentient beings. Among
Hnens disciples, Shinran was not the only one to put pen to paper
as a means of preserving Hnens teachings.184 Also, in the centuries
following Shinrans death new leaders of the fledgling Jdo Shin movement read and incorporated ideas from Hnens disciples as a means
of understanding Shin Buddhism. One example of this is the doctrine
of kih ittai (unity of individual and dharma [i.e., buddha], )
which was influential for Rennyos teaching. Rennyo was fond of reading the Anjin ketsujsh (Notes on Firm Faith, ), a text of unknown authorship that has its origins in the Seizan Branch of the
Jdo-sh , in which the doctrine of kih ittai is put forth. Rennyo
often alluded to the Anjin ketsujsh in his teachings and described it as
being a fundamental text for the Shin tradition.185
Although Rennyo never mentions kih ittai specifically in his letters,
many scholars have noted a connection between kih ittai and Rennyos
understanding of the relationship between the person of shinjin and
Amida Buddha, particularly when Rennyo writes, the Buddhas mind
and the mind of the ordinary being become one (busshin to bonshin to
hitotsu ni naru ).186
Rennyos doctrine, commonly referred to as butsubon ittai (unity of
buddha and foolish beings, ), although inspired by the doctrine of kih ittai found in the Anjin ketsujsh, is as Nait Chik points
out fundamentally different from kih ittai. Naito explains, kih ittai
represents a fundamental state of unity between the religious practitioner and the dharma. Ki and h , the practitioner and the
dharma, cannot be separated from one another: although they seem
different they are the same. Naito explains this as the difference
70
Pacific World
between steam and ice; visually we see them as being different, yet
fundamentally ice and steam are the same.187 In contrast, butsubon
ittai understands the relationship between practitioner and buddha as
fundamentally distinct.188 Naito elaborates on this by explaining each
character in this phrase individually. Butsu refers to the mind of the
tathgatas, which is true, clear, and real.189 Bon describes the mind
of sentient beings, which is controlled by the delusions of worldly desires.190 Ittai refers to a state of unity where sentient beings are
in a continual process of becoming buddha. In this world, although
butsu and bon appear to be one they are fundamentally different, and
yet butsu and bon are not two. Naito explains: The salvational power
(chikara ) and working of Amida Tathagata cannot be distinguished
from ourselves. We ourselves are the locus (ba ) for the operating of
Amida Tathagatas salvational power and working.191 In other words,
Naito argues, the working of Amida Buddha in the world cannot be
separated from sentient beings. Sentient beings, however, are not the
same as Amida Buddha, nor do they cease being sentient beings in this
relationship. Particularly important is that this understanding does
not deny the reality of sentient beings in the world. Although sentient
beings are the locus of Amidas work, sentient beings still suffer in the
world of samsara. This understanding of unity is representative of East
Asian understandings. Consider for example Ziporyns explication of
the meaning of one in early Chinese thought: [A] one or a unity
is conceived not as a homogenous or abstract mathematical unit but,
rather, as an indivisible harmony of diverse elements. . . . [I]t signifies
a holistic harmony between two identifiably different elements that
nonetheless are virtually present in one another due to the inseparability and reciprocal determination that follows from their foundational holistic relation.192
Read in this way, the doctrine of butsubon ittai implies that the relationship between sentient beings and Amida Buddha can be characterized as not one, not two, but both one and two. In other words,
sentient beings are the locus of Amida Buddhas work in the world and
exist in a relationship of mutual determination that is shinjin. From
the perspective of the religious practitioner, Amida Buddha is wholly
other, true and real; sentient beings suffer due to the fact our very
being is characterized by innumerable passions and cravings. From the
perspective of Amida Buddha, sentient beings are not separate from
71
Amida Buddha as they are the locus for the operating of Amida Buddha
in this world.
Using the lens of intersubjectivity opens up for us the issues of
otherness within Shin Buddhism. Shin Buddhist thought conceives of
the relationship of religious practitioner and Amida Buddha as being
fundamentally different. Due to blind passions and delusions, the religious practitioner is destined to a life of samsaric wanderings. However,
as an other Amida Buddha vows to save all sentient beings, thereby assuring that through entrusting in Amidas primal vow sentient beings
will attain buddhahood. Because of this assurance, sentient beings are
equal to the buddhas. However, as long as sentient beings existence
remains characterized by the wanderings and delusions of samsara
they are fundamentally different from the buddhas. This relationship
is intersubjective in that upon realizing the difference between their
present states of existence and enlightenment, sentient beings also realize what it means that enlightenment is assured by Amida Buddhas
primal vow.
(RE-)READING NISHIDAS PHILOSOPHY THROUGH SHIN THOUGHT
Nishidas philosophy was influenced by both traditional and
contemporaneous Shin thought, and, as exemplified by Shinran and
Rennyo, Shin thought conceives of the relationship between Amida
Buddha and the religious practitioner as being both equal and not
equal. For these reasons Shin thought provides a useful hermeneutic
for understanding Nishidas non-dualism, allowing us to bring into dialogue Shin ideas of the relation between Amida and religious practitioner and Nishidas understanding of the relationship between absolute
and relative.
(Re-)Reading193
As discussed previously, Nishida conceives of the relationship between absolute and relative through the phrase the self-identity of
absolute contradiction. Nishida uses this term to explain that the absolute is included in and expressed by its opposite, the relative. For
Nishida this relationship is dynamic in that absolute and relative are,
as we have already seen, mutually defining and determining. From the
very beginning of his philosophic writings to his final completed work,
Nishida sought to show that all phenomena/forms exist in a unity with
God,194 while simultaneously arguing that at times, when seen from
72
Pacific World
one angle, Gods spirit is unknowable.195 In other words, although sentient beings are one with the absolute (God, Amida Buddha, etc.), they
are differentiated from the absolute in that sentient beings view of
reality is askew and truth is hidden.
Given this difference and the compassionate desire of that which
is absolute to enter into relationship with all that is relative, Nishida
argues, the absolute is only absolute insofar as it contains its own
negation.196 Nishida explains this qua Shin Buddhist soteriology. The
formless that is suchness, through self-negation, takes on form; Amida
Buddha, arising out of suchness, itself takes form in this world. Amida
Buddhas self-negation is so strong that Amida saves sentient beings
even by manifesting himself as a devil.197 Sentient beings, or that
which is relative, although existing in a unity with the absolute, are
incapable of self-negation; they therefore must rely on the activity of
the absolute in order to enter fully into relationship with the absolute.
Nishida derives his understanding of negation from Shinrans
explication of Amidas calculation and the practitioners entrusting.
For example, as the idea that Shinran would be able to attain enlightenment through his own calculations was abandoned, Shinran came to
entrust in the activity of Amida Buddha, and thus realized that Amidas
primal vow was entirely for [Shinrans] sake alone.198 It was through
Amida as suchness taking form that Shinran was able to awaken the
mind of shinjin. The transcendent thus not only identifies with its opposite but takes form and expresses itself as that which is immanent.
Through the nenbutsu sentient beings become expressions of
Amida Buddhas primal vow in that they effortlessly reach a state of
existence described as being artless and one with the working of the
dharma (jinen hni).199 Nishida goes on to explain that through becoming one with the working of the dharma sentient beings are able to
act with true compassion, which means to act without regard for the
I and in accordance with the working of Amida Buddhas primal vow,
being one with the working of the dharma.
The entire universe is for Nishida the expression of suchness itself.
The formless negates itself and takes form. Shinran understood this as
Amida appearing in this world as Hnen at a time when it was no longer
possible, according to Shinran, for sentient beings to awaken aspiration for enlightenment on their own. Eshinnis letters also make clear
that Shinran viewed Hnen and other select individuals in this way.200
Nishida expressed this relationship as the self-identity of absolute
73
74
Pacific World
and Jdo Shinsh doctrinal concepts. While these concepts may not be
unique to Jdo Shinsh, it is through Jdo Shinsh that Nishida learned
about them, and by an understanding of how Jdo Shinsh uses and
talks about such concepts as self/other and non-duality Nishidas ideas
become more intelligible.
As is well known, Nishida wanted to explain the entire world. With
this as his goal, Nishida drew from a wide variety of sources. This, then,
is both the strength and weakness of Nishidas philosophy. It is the
strength, as Kopf explains, because in Nishidas philosophy one finds
a network of terminology, which, when developed carefully, provides
a model for an intercultural philosophy.202 It is a weakness in that
Nishidas philosophy is at times at best ambiguous, and sources are
cut off from the socio-historical context within which they developed.
Conclusions and Opportunities for Future Studies
The study of Nishidas philosophy and its relationship to Buddhism
is messy at best. In the past scholars have tended to see Nishidas philosophy as the philosophy of Zen Buddhism, thus giving a distorted
vision of both Zen and Nishidas philosophy. For example, Steve Odins
The Social Self in Zen and American Philosophy, while an exemplary model
of how comparative philosophy ought to look, deals very little with
Zen and more with the philosophy of the Kyoto school philosophers in
conversation with the Chicago school of American pragmatism, particularly the thought of George Herbert Mead.203 While Odins project of
dialoging the thought of the Kyoto school with American pragmatism is
welcome, the equation of Kyoto school philosophy with Zen Buddhism
is problematic, as is the equation of Meads pragmatism with American
philosophy. Simply put, Odin does not differentiate how or where the
thought of the Kyoto school is different from Zen Buddhism.
While the Shin tradition and Nishidas philosophy do have a
number of commonalities, in essence they are fundamentally different.
As indicated by the quote from Wargo above showed, Nishida was not
interested in leading others to religious awakening; rather, he wanted
to provide an explanation of the world that allowed for religious experience beyond the role of superstition. Shinran and Rennyo set
out to explain a religious path that would lead others to awakening;
whether the path was rational by philosophic standards, frankly, did
not concern them.
75
76
Pacific World
77
78
Pacific World
79
80
Pacific World
81
71. Nishida Kitar, Letter no. 595, 4 January 1930, NKZ 18:396-398, trans.
Yusa Michiko, quoted in Yusa, Zen and Philosophy, 246.
72. Takemura, Nishida Kitar, 6465.
73. Ibid., 52.
74. Nishida Kitar zensh, 1:199; Nishida, An Inquiry into the Good, 176 (modified).
75. Takemura, Nishida Kitar, 52.
76. Fujita Masakatsu , Kiyozawa Manshi to Nishida Kitar
, in Kiyozawa Manshi: Sono hito to shis
, ed. Fujita Masakatsu and Yasutomi Shinya (Kyoto:
Hzkan, 2002), 120.
77. Nishida first uses Shin Buddhism to explain what the true religious
experience is. Nishida writes, Shinran is quoted in the Tannish: The
nembutsu chanted in the heart to increase works leading to rebirth in the
pure land is a practice based on ones own efforts. The second quotation
comes when Nishida explains the unity of absolute and relative. Reflection
is the route along which we attain a profound unity. (Shinran declares in the
Tannish, If even a good person attains rebirth in the Pure Land, how much
more so does an evil person.). Nishida, An Inquiry into the Good, 150, 170.
78. Fujita, Kiyozawa Manshi to Nishida Kitar, 132133.
79. Thomas Kirchner, The Life of Manshi Kiyozawa, in December Fan: The
Buddhist Essays of Manshi Kiyozawa, trans. Nobuo Haneda (Kyoto: Higashi
Honganji, 1984), 87.
80. Yusa, Zen and Philosophy, 86.
81. Ibid., 87.
82. Ibid., 127.
83. Hirota, Nishidas Gutoku Shinran, 243; Nishida Kitar zensh, 1:408.
84. Nakamura Sichi , Zenyaku Shbgenz ikkan
(Tokyo: Seishin Shob, 1971), 2.
85. Collected Works of Shinran, 1:679; Shinsh shgy zensho, 2:792.
86. This quote seems to have intrigued not only Nishida but other members of
the Kyoto school as well. Nishitani Keiji (19001990), the third major
figure of the Kyoto school after Nishida and Tanabe Hajime (18851962),
took up this passage in his article The Problem of Time in Shinran, trans.
Dennis Hirota, The Eastern Buddhist 11, no. 1 (1978): 1326.
87. Fujita, Kiyozawa Manshi to Nishida Kitar, 134.
88. Heisig, Philosophers of Nothingness, 99.
89. Ibid., 100.
82
Pacific World
83
113. Nishida, The Logic of Topos and the Religious Worldview II, 104.
114. Gereon Kopf, Beyond Personal Identity (Richmond, Surrey: Curzon, 2001),
5354; Brook Ziporyn, Evil and/or/as The Good, 199201. Both Kopf and Ziporyn
have published arguments that show the necessity of the role of the Other
in Buddhist thought that are similar to those cited here, see for example
Gereon Kopf, In the Face of the Other, in The Couch and the Tree, ed. Anthony
Molino (New York: North Point Press, 1998), 276289; Brook Ziporyn, What
Is the Buddha Looking At? The Importance of Intersubjectivity in the Tientai Tradition as Understood by Chih-li, in Buddhism in the Sung, ed. Peter N.
Gregory and Daniel A. Getz, Jr. (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1999),
442476; and, Brook Ziporyn, Being and Ambiguity (Chicago: Open Court, 2004)
293294.
115. Varghese J. Manimala, Being, Person and Community (New Delhi:
Intercultural Publications, 1991), 182.
116. Given that Shinran was originally ordained as a Tendai monk, it may
strike the reader as being apropos to explore intersubjectivity and issues of
identity and difference in Tiantai; however, these issues have previously been
explored in great detail. Tiantai and Tendai notions of intersubjectivity that
may have influenced Shinrans thought will be discussed in the section on
Jdo Shinsh conceptions of identity and difference. Although beyond the
scope of this essay, for an excellent account of intersubjectivity in Tibetan
Buddhism see B. Allan Wallace, Intersubjectivity in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism,
Journal of Consciousness Studies 8, nos. 57 (2001): 209230.
117. W. T. Jones and Robert J. Fogelin, A History of Western Philosophy: The
Twentieth Century to Quine and Derrida, 3rd ed. (New York: Harcourt Brace
College Publishers, 1997), 359.
118. Notably absent in much of Benjamins work and the present discussion
is the philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. Benjamin makes clear that she disagrees with any psychological or philosophic theory that conceives of the
Other as transcendent and ineffable. Benjamin, as will become clear in the
ensuing discussion, notes the philosophic and psychological necessity for a
relationship between self and other as interdependent. While Benjamin would
most likely agree with Levinas concerning the danger of subsuming the Other
to the self, Levinass focus on the Other as transcendent and ineffable is ultimately untenable for theories of intersubjectivity. On Benjamins rejection
on an ineffable other, see Jessica Benjamin, Shadow of the Other: Intersubjectivity and Gender in Psychoanalysis (New York: Routledge, 1998), 94. An excellent
overview of Levinass philosophy regarding Otherness is Colin Davis, Levinas:
An Introduction (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996), 3462.
Levinass most well-known and often quoted work regarding the Other is
Emmanuel Levinas, Time and the Other, trans. R. A. Cohen (Pittsburgh: Duquesne
84
Pacific World
85
86
Pacific World
87
88
Pacific World
1997), 7172.
182. Collected Works of Shinran, 1:328; Shinsh shgy zensho, 2:487.
183. Collected Works of Shinran, 1:390; Shinsh shgy zensho, 2:514.
184. Concerning the development of Japanese Pure Land Buddhism following Hnens death, see Mark L. Blum, The Origins and Development of Pure Land
Buddhism: A Study and Translation of Gynens Jdo Hmon Genrush (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2002). It is interesting to note that Gynen does not
include Shinran in his survey of Pure Land Buddhism. Blum notes a number
of reasons why Gynen would not have included Shinran in his survey: (1)
Shinran had a low profile among Hnens senior disciples; (2) Gynens hermeneutic categories would have deemphasized Shinrans uniqueness in that
he would share the position of Ksai and Gyk; (3) Shinran had disdain for
contemplative practices; and (4) Shinran rejected monastic life (Blum, Origins
and Development of Pure Land Buddhism, 4144).
185. Minor L. Rogers and Ann T. Rogers, Rennyo: The Second Founder of Shin
Buddhism (Berkeley: Asian Humanities Press, 1991), 9293.
186. Rogers and Rogers, Rennyo, 184; Shinsh shgy zensho, 3:439. On the
connection of kih ittai and Jdo Shinsh doctrine, see Rogers and Rogers,
Rennyo, 184n25.
187. Nait Chik , Anjin rondai o manabu (Kyoto:
Hongwanji Shuppansha, 2004), 193.
188. Ibid., 315.
189. Ibid., 313.
190. Ibid., 314.
191. Ibid., 319.
192. Ziporyn, Evil and/or/as the Good, 50.
193. Though not explicitly cited, the work of Thomas Kasulis has been influential
in formulating my approach and reading of the work of Shinran, Renny,
and Nishida. In particular, see Thomas Kasulis, Philosophy as Metapraxis,
in Discourse and Practice, ed. Frank Reynolds and David Tracy (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1992), 169195; and Thomas Kasulis, Intimacy
or Integrity: Philosophy and Cultural Difference (Honolulu: University of Hawaii
Press, 2002).
194. Nishida, An Inquiry into the Good, 163.
195. Ibid., 165.
196. Nishida, The Logic of Topos and the Religious Worldview I, 19.
197. Nishida, The Logic of Topos and the Religious Worldview II, 98.
89
p. 90 (blank)