Article On Transfinite Numers
Article On Transfinite Numers
ARTICLE
Transfinite Numbers
What is Infinity?
S M Srivastava
In a series of revolutionary articles written during the
last quarter of the nineteenth century, the great German mathematician Georg Cantor removed the age-old
mistrust of infinity and created an exceptionally beautiful and useful theory of transfinite numbers. This is
an introductory article on this topic. 1
S M Srivastava is with the
Indian Statistical
Institute, Calcutta. He
received his PhD from the
Indian Statistical Institute
in 1980. His research
interests are in
Descriptive Set Theory.
Introduction
How many points are there on a line? Which is more in numberpoints on a line or lines in a plane? These are some natural
questions that have occurred to us sometime or the other. It is
interesting to note the difference between the two questions. Do
we have to know how many points and lines there are to answer
the second question? Even primitive man could see whether he
had more cows than his neighbour without knowing the actual
number of cows they had-he would just pair off his cows with
his neighbour's. So, to compare the size of two sets, we can start
pairing off their elements. If one of them exhausts first we say
that that particular set has fewer elements than the other one.
Otherwise we say that the two sets have the same number of elements. If we are considering finite collections only, everything
seems to be alright. Now imagine yourself walking into a hotel
with infinitely many rooms which are all occupied. The receptionist shifts the guest in Room 1 to Room 2, the one in Room
2 to Room 3 and so on. Now Room 1 falls vacant and she gives
it to you. As we can pair off the two sets of guests, question
arises: are there more guests in the hotel now? Thus we see
that the idea of pairing off elements leads to counterintuitive
results for infinite sets, e.g., an infinite set can have as many
elements as a part of it. Georg Cantor (1845-1918) showed that
this is a characteristic difference between finite and infinite sets
and created an immensely useful branch of mathematics based
on this idea which had a great impact on the whole of mathematics. For example, the question of what is a number (finite or
infinite) is almost a philosophical one. However Cantor's work
turned it into a precise mathematical concept.
--------~~------
GENERAL
ARTICLE
Countable Sets
are there on a
line? Which is
more in numberpoints on a line or
lines in a plane?
Examples
We can enumerate the set N x N of ordered pairs of natural numbers by the diagonal method as shown in the following
diagram
(1,2)
(2,1)
(2,2)
That is, we enumerate the elements of NxN as (0,0), (1, 0), (0, 1),
(2,0), (1,1), (0,2), .... By induction we see that the set of all
k-tuples of natural numbers is also countable.
An argument similar to the one above shows that if Ao, AI, A2, ...
is a sequence of countable sets then their union A = UO An is
also countable.
The set Q of all rational numbers is countable. (Exercise: Try
to deduce this from the first example.)
The most natural question that arises now is: are there uncountable sets? The answer is yes. Here is an example.
If a < b are real numbers then the interval [a, b] is uncountable.
--------~--------
GENERAL I ARTICLE
bn
Equinumerosity-Order of Infinity
An algebraic number is a
complex number which is a root
ofa polynomial having rational
numbers for coefficients. For
eg: Ii is an algebraic number;
it satisfies XZ-2=O.
2
I ifXEA
0 otherwise.
---+ XA
--------~--------
GENERAL
ARTICLE
Is there an
uncountable set of
real numbers of
cardinality less
than that of 1{?
A <==> xo A.
== Y.
-RE-S-O-N-A-N-C-E--I-M-a-rc-h-1-9-97--------------~-------------------------------~
GENERAL
ARTICLE
--+
--+ Y
--+
P(X)
X.
Then
i) A C B eX==? 1t(A) c 1t(B), and
ii) 1t(Un An) = Un 1t(An).
Now, let
Ao =
0, and
An+l
Let E
Define h: X ~ Y by
h(x) = { lex)
if x E E
9 -1 (x) otherwise.
The map h : X
--+
_ _ _ _ _ _ _ _LAAAAAA_ _ _ _ _ __ _
62
V VVV
RESONANCE I March 1997
v
GENERAL I ARTICLE
The Axiom of Choice (AC): If {Aihel is a family of nonempty sets then there is a function I : 1 --+ U Ai such that
I{i) E Ai for every i E 1.
Such a function I is called a choice function. Note that if 1
is finite then by induction on the number of elements in 1 we
can show that a choice function exists. If 1 is infinite then we
do not know how to prove the existence of such a map. The
problem can be explained by the following example of Russell.
Let Ao, Al, A2,'" be a sequence of pairs of shoes. Let I{n)
be the left shoe in the n-th pair An and so the choice function
in this case certainly exists. Instead, let Ao, Al, A2, . .. be a
sequence of pairs of socks. Now we are unable to give a rule to
define a choice function for the sequence of socks Ao, All A2, .. .!
AC asserts the existence of a function without giving any rule
or any construction for defining such a function. Because of its
non-constructive nature, AC met with serious criticism. For an
excellent account of AC see Gregory Moore's book mentioned in
Suggested Readings. We only remark that AC is indispensable
not only for the theory of cardinal numbers but for the whole
of mathematics. Note that while proving that the union of a
sequence of countable sets Ao, A 1, ... is countable we have used
AC. For each n, we chose an enumeration of An. But there are
infinitely many such enumerations and we did not specify any
rule to choose them. The next result shows that every infinite
set has a proper equinumerous subset. In its proof we use AC.
Theorem If X is infinite and A C X finite then X \ A and X
have the same cardinality.
Proof. By AC, fix a choice function J : P(X) \ {0} --+ X such
that f (E) E E for every non-empty subset E of X. Let A =
{ao, al, .. , an}. Inductively define an+l, a n +2, ... such that
an+k+l
N ow define h : X
--+
= f(X
X \ A by
otherwise.
Clearly, h : X
--+
-E-S-O-N-A-N-C-E--I-M-a-rc-h-1-9-97----------------~~-----------------------------63-
GENERAL I ARTICLE
i) x Rx (reflexive),
ii) xRy and yRz implies xRz (transitive), and
iii) xRy and yRx implies x = y (anti-symmetric).
A set P with a partial order is called a partially ordered set or
simply a poset. A linear order on a set X is a partial order R
on X such that any two elements of X are comparable, i.e., for
every x, y EX, at least one of xRy or yRx holds. H X is a
set with more than one element then the inclusion relation c
on 'P(X) is a partial order which is not a linear order. Another
example of a partial order which is not a linear order is obtained
as follows. Let X and Y be sets with Y having more than one
element. Let l' be the set of all partial functions from X to Y
(functions with domain a subset of X and range contained in
Y). Order l' by 'extension' (if I, 9 E l' then 9 extends I if the
domain of f is contained in the domain of 9 and I(x) = g(x)
for every x in the domain of f).
Fix a poset (P, R). A chain in P is a subset C of P such that
R restricted to C is a linear order, i.e., for any two elements x,
y of C either xRy or yRx must be satisfied. HAc P then an
upper bound for A is an x E P such that y Rx for all yEA. An
x E P is called a maximal element of P if for no yEP different
from x, xRy holds. In the second example above, any partial
function I with domain X or range Y is a maximal element.
So, there may be many maximal elements in a poset which is
not linearly ordered.
_ _ _ _ _ _ _ _LAAAAAA_ _- - - - - 64
v V VVV v
RESONANCE I March 1997
GENERAL
ARTICLE
Since Ii's are consistent and one-one, I is well defined and oneone. Thus, I is an upper bound of C. By Zorn's lemma, P
has a maximal element, say 10. We must have domain(/o) =
X or range(/o) = Y. Otherwise, choose a E X.\ domain(/o)
and b E Y\ range(fo). We get a one-one extension of 10 to
domain(/o) U{ a} by assigning b to a. This contradicts the
maxima1ity of 10. H domain(/o) = X then X ~c Y and if
range(/o) = Y then Y ~c X.
A hotel with
infinitely many
rooms even when
full can
accommodate as
many new guests
as already there!
The next result shows that a hotel with infinitely many rooms
even when full can accommodate 88 many new guests as are
already there!
Theorem For every infinite set X, X x {O, I}
== X.
Proof. Let
P
{(A, f) : A
c X and
f: A x {O, I}
--+
a bijection}.
== X.
Proof. Let
P
{(A, f) : A C X
and f: A x A
--+
A a bijection}.
Partially order P by 'extension'. By Zorn's lemma take a maximal element (A, f) of P. Note that A must be infinite. To
complete the proof, we shall show that A == X. Suppose not.
Then A <c X.
We first show that X \ A == X. If possible, suppose X \ A <c X.
Either A ~c X \ A or X \ A ~c A. Assume first X \ A ~c A.
Take two disjoint sets Al, A2 of the same cardinality as A. Now,
---------~---------
GENERAL
ARTICLE
The Continuum Hypothesis (CH) Every uncountable subset of a:l is of the same cardinality as ~.
The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis (GCH) If X is
an infinite set then there is no set A such that X <c A <c P(X).
CH says that a:l is the least numerous uncountable set. If GCH
were true then every infinite set is equinumerous to one of the
sets obtained by iterating the power set operation on N. Are
these statements true? These turned out to be very hard problems and their solutions were startling. In 1938 Kurt Godel
obtained deep results on models of set theory and showed that
based on certain axioms for sets (the so calledZermelo-Praenkel
axioms), CH and GCH cannot be disproved by producing a
'model' of set theory satisfying the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms
where CH and GCH are satisfied.This was the first time metamathematics entered in a non-trivial way to answer a problem
in mathematics.Godel's result does not say that CH and GCH
can be proved.In 1963 Paul Cohen developed a very powerful
technique, known as forcing, to build models of set theory and
--------~--------
GENERAL I ARTICLE
== Y then
iii) if X == Y and
ii) if X
Y
Y
== X, and
== Z then X == z.
== Y
<::=:}
IXI
and
IYI
lXI,
called its
Definition
a) A + J-L = I(X
b) A./L = IX X
c) )..11- = IXYI
{o}) U(Y
{1})I
YI
d) A ~ J-L if X ~c Y
e) ).. <
J-L
if X < c Y
--------~--------
GENERAL
ARTICLE
=
=
S M Srivastava
Stat-Math Unit
Indian Statistical Institute
203 B T Road
Calcutta 700 035
e-mail: [email protected]
(since 2 ~ c)
(2 o)' (since c = 2l-tO)
2l-to.'
(since, for non-empty sets
X, Y, Z, (XY) Z == XYXZ)
"
2'"
(since No < c)
2'
(since C.c = c).
So, by the Schroder-Bernstein theorem 2' = ,'. From this we
conclude that there are as many 0-1 valued maps of real numbers
as real valued ones!
$;
Suggested Reading
K Kuratowski and A Mostowski. Set theory. North-Holland publishing company. Amsterdam, New York,
Oxford,1976.
Gregory Moore. Zermelo's axiom of choice -its origin, dewlopment and influertCS. Springer.. Verlag. New
York., 1982
Georg Cantor. Contributiom to thefo;unding of the theory of transfinite numbers. Dover Publications Inc.
New York, 1992.
Nicolas Bourbaki. Elements of the history of mathematics. Springer-Verlag. Berlin, Heidelberg, New
York,1994.
Yiannis N Moschovakis. Notes on set theory. UTM. Springer-Verlag. New York, Berlin, Heidelberg, 1994
--------~--------