Halliday, M.a.K. - (1992) How Do You Mean2pp
Halliday, M.a.K. - (1992) How Do You Mean2pp
Halliday, M.a.K. - (1992) How Do You Mean2pp
Chapter Thirteen
form of
consciousness
action
reection
1st/2nd person
regulatory
interactional
3rd person
instrumental
personal
domain
of experience
First published in Advances in Systemic Linguistics: Recent Theory and Practice, 1992, edited by
Martin Davies and Louise Ravelli. London: Pinter, pp. 2035.
352
353
I realize that the title might well prompt someone to ask, How do
you mean, How do you mean?? I could have written, How are
meanings made? although I prefer the more personalized version.
The question is meant theoretically; but, like so many theoretical
questions, it becomes relevant in practice the moment we want to
intervene in the processes we are trying to understand. And some
processes of meaning are involved in more or less everything we do.
I shall need to talk about two fundamental relationships, those of
realization and instantiation; so let me begin by distinguishing these
two. Instantiation I take to be the move between the system and the
instance; it is an intrastratal relationship that is, it does not involve a
move between strata. The wording ne words butter no parsnips is an
instance, or an instantiation, of a clause. Realization, on the other hand,
is prototypically an interstratal relationship; meanings are realized as
wordings, wordings realized as sound (or soundings). We often use the
term to refer to any move which constitutes a link in the realizational
chain, even one that does not by itself cross a stratal boundary (for
example, features realized as structures); but the phenomenon of realization only exists as a property of a stratied system. To anticipate the
discussion a little, I shall assume that realization may be formalized as
metaredundancy, as this is dened by Jay Lemke (1985). Instantiation I
shall dene by making reference to the observer; it is variation in the
observers time depth. Firths concept of exponence is the product of
these two relations: his exponent is both instantiation and realization.1
354
355
(cf. Figure 2). Once the original protolinguistic redundancy has been
transformed into metaredundancy in this way, the relation becomes an
iterative one and so opens up the possibilities for construing, not only
the context of situation, but also higher levels such as Hasans symbolic
articulation and theme in verbal art, or Martins strata of genre and
ideology.
The metaredundancy notion thus formalizes the stratal principle in
semogenesis. What makes meaning indenitely extendable is the evolutionary change from protolanguage to language whereby instead of
356
357
l, m, n a, b, c
p, q, r (l, m, n a, b, c)
(p, q, r l, m, n) a, b, c
Figure 2 Metaredundancy
interpretation with a dynamic one. This leads us into the other critical
concept, that of instantiation.
Consider the notion of climate. A climate is a reasonably stable
system; there are kinds of climate, such as tropical and polar, and these
persist, and they differ in systematic ways. Yet we are all very concerned
about changes in the climate, and the consequences of global warming.
What does it mean to say the climate is changing? Climate is instantiated
in the form of weather: todays temperature, humidity, direction and
speed of wind, etc., in central Scotland are instances of climatic
phenomena. As such they may be more, or less, typical: todays
maximum is so many degrees higher, or lower, than average meaning
the average at this place, at this time of year and at this time of day.
The average is a statement of the probabilities: there is a 70 per cent
chance, let us say, that the temperature will fall within such a range.
The probability is a feature of the system (the climate); but it is no
more, and no less, than the pattern set up by the instances (the weather),
and each instance, no matter how minutely, perturbs these probabilities
and so changes the system (or else keeps it as it is, which is just the
limiting case of changing it).
The climate and the weather are not two different phenomena. They
are the same phenomenon seen by two different observers, standing at
different distances different time depths. To the climate observer, the
weather looks like random unpredictable ripples; to the weather
observer, the climate is a vague and unreal outline. So it is also with
language;8 language as system, and language as instance. They are not
two different phenomena; they are the same phenomenon as seen by
different observers. The system is the pattern formed by the instances;
and each instance represents an exchange with the environment an
incursion into the system in which every level of language is involved.
The system is permeable because each instance redounds with the
context of situation, and so perturbs the system in interaction with
the environment. Thus both realization and instantiation are involved
in the evolution of language as a dynamic open system.
Now the relation of system to instance is in fact a cline, a continuous
zoom; and wherever we focus the zoom we can take a look into history.
But to know what kind of history, we have to keep a record of which
end we started from. To the system observer, history takes the form of
evolution; the system changes by evolving, with selection (in the sense
of natural selection) by the material conditions of the environment.
This is seen most clearly, perhaps, in the evolution of particular sub359
362
363
Here for the rst time Nigel is selecting in two systems of meaning at
once, and by this token the initial move into grammar has been made.
Through the second year of life this new stratied system will gradually
replace the protolinguistic one, and all meanings (except for a few
protolanguage remnants that persist into adult life like hi! and ah! and
yum! and ouch!) will come to be stratally and metafunctionally complex.
So in Nigels rst exemplar, just cited, we have (i) proto-metafunctions
(proto-ideational different persons; proto-interpersonal seeking /
nding), and (ii) proto-strata, with the meaning rst construed as
wording (the ideational as contrasting names; the interpersonal as
contrasting mood) and then (re)construed as sounding (names as
articulation, mood as intonation). At this second interface the child can
now combine the segmental and the prosodic choices, in this way both
realizing and also iconically symbolizing the two different modes of
meaning that are combined at the rst interface. The resources for
making meaning are now in place.
It is probably not a coincidence that, as the ideational grammar
evolved, so in the system of transitivity the eld of processes was
construed into different process types along precisely the lines that (if
my understanding is right) went into the making of meaning in the rst
place. If meaning arises out of the impact of the conscious and the
material, as mutually contradictory forms of experience, then it is not
surprising that when experience is construed semantically, these two
types of process, the material and the conscious, should come to be
systematically distinguished. But there is a further twist. The semogenic
process, as we saw, involves setting up a relationship between systems
such that one is the realization of the other that is, they stand to each
other in a relation of Token and Value. This TokenValue relationship
is set up at both interfaces, and it is also what makes it possible to prise
the two apart and wedge in a grammar in between. Here then we nd
the third of the kinds of process construed by the grammar: the relational
process, based on identifying a Token with a Value. The grammar of
natural language, in its ideational metafunction, is a theory of human
experience; thus it may reasonably be expected to take as its point of
departure the very set of contrasts from which its own potential is
ultimately derived.
Let me return once again, nally, to the suggestion that meaning is a
mode of action engendered at the intersection of the material (or
phenomenal) and the conscious, as complementary modes of experience.
Now, the effect of this impact is to construe order. By the act of
meaning, consciousness imposes order on the phenomena of experience.
364
365
366
Notes
1. For Firths concept of exponence see especially his Synopsis of Linguistic
Theory in Firth (1957a).
2. I am speaking here of phylogenesis; but the process is recapitulated in the
growth of the individual, where it can be observed in the form of
behaviour. A child experiences certain phenomena as out there as lying
beyond the boundary between me and non-me: some perturbation seen
or heard, like a ock of birds taking off, or a bus going past, or a coloured
light ashing. At the same time, he also experiences a phenomenon that
is in here: his own consciousness of being curious, or pleased, or
frightened. At rst these two experiences remain detached; but then
(perhaps as a result of his success in grasping an object that is in his line of
sight in Trevarthens terms, when pre-reaching becomes reaching,
typically at about four months) a spark ies between them by which the
material is projected on to the conscious as Im curious about that, I like
that and so on. Now, more or less from birth the child has been able to
address others and to recognize that he is being addressed (Catherine
Batesons proto-conversation). The projection of the material on to the
conscious mode of experience maps readily on to this ability to address an
other; and the result is an act of meaning such as Nigels very highpitched squeak, which he rst produced at ve months, shortly after he
had learnt to reach and grasp.
3. Other microfunctions were added as the protolanguage evolved by degrees
into the mother tongue; but these were the original four. See Halliday
(1975, 1978).
4. At rst labelled, somewhat misleadingly, the level of context. See the
discussion of levels in Halliday, McIntosh and Strevens (1964). See also
Ellis (1966).
5. Based on giving and demanding that is, on exchange. Initially this meant
the exchange of goods-and-services; but eventually, by a remarkable
dialectic in which the medium of exchange became itself the commodity
exchanged, it extended to giving and demanding information. By this
step, meaning evolved from being an ancillary of other activities to being
a form of activity in its own right.
6. See the chapters entitled Towards a model of the instructional process,
The formal analysis of instruction and Action, context and meaning in
Lemke (1984).
7. It is impossible to have metaphor in a protolanguage at all, unless one
chooses to call metaphor (or perhaps proto-metaphor) what is taking
place when, for example, Nigel transfers a particular sign [ggi ggi ggi]
from Im sleepy to lets pretend Im going to sleep. See Halliday (1975:
Chapter 2).
8. The analogy should not, of course, be pressed too far. Specically, while
367
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
368