Calculus Course
Calculus Course
Pete L. Clark
Contents
Foreword
Spivak and Me
What is Honors Calculus?
Some Features of the Text
7
7
10
10
13
13
17
25
25
27
29
31
32
34
35
39
40
43
43
49
53
53
54
56
58
62
Chapter 5. Differentiation
1. Differentiability Versus Continuity
2. Differentiation Rules
3. Optimization
4. The Mean Value Theorem
5. Monotone Functions
6. Inverse Functions I: Theory
7. Inverse Functions II: Examples and Applications
8. Some Complements
3
71
71
72
77
81
85
92
97
104
CONTENTS
Chapter 6. Completeness
1. Dedekind Completeness
2. Intervals and the Intermediate Value Theorem
3. The Monotone Jump Theorem
4. Real Induction
5. The Extreme Value Theorem
6. The Heine-Borel Theorem
7. Uniform Continuity
8. The Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem For Subsets
9. Tarskis Fixed Point Theorem
105
105
113
116
117
119
119
120
122
123
125
125
128
136
Chapter 8. Integration
1. The Fundamental Theorem of Calculus
2. Building the Definite Integral
3. Further Results on Integration
4. Riemann Sums, Dicing, and the Riemann Integral
5. Lesbesgues Theorem
6. Improper Integrals
7. Some Complements
149
149
152
161
170
176
179
182
185
185
185
187
194
196
199
200
201
203
203
206
208
211
214
216
217
225
229
229
233
236
241
CONTENTS
5.
6.
7.
8.
247
250
254
260
265
265
266
269
271
277
281
281
283
288
291
291
293
302
306
310
313
315
321
321
323
325
327
333
334
342
Bibliography
351
Foreword
Spivak and Me
The document you are currently reading began its life as the lecture notes for a year
long undergraduate course in honors calculus. Specifically, during the 2011-2012
academic year I taught Math 2400(H) and Math 2410(H), Calculus With Theory,
at the University of Georgia. This is a course for unusually talented and motivated
(mostly first year) undergraduate students. It has been offered for many years at
the University of Georgia, and so far as I know the course text has always been
Michael Spivaks celebrated Calculus [S]. The Spivak texts take on calculus is
sufficiently theoretical that, although it is much beloved by students and practitioners of mathematics, it is seldomed used nowadays as a course text. In fact, the
UGA Math 2400/2410 course is traditionally something of an interpolation between
standard freshman calculus and the fully theoretical approach of Spivak. My own
take on the course was different: I treated it as being a sequel to, rather than an
enriched revision of, freshman calculus.
I began the course with a substantial familiarity with Spivaks text. The summer after my junior year of high school I interviewed at the University of Chicago
and visited Paul Sally, then (and still now, as I write this in early 2013, though
he is 80 years old) Director of Undergraduate Mathematics at the University of
Chicago. After hearing that I had taken AP calculus and recently completed a
summer course in multivariable calculus at Johns Hopkins, Sally led me to a supply closet, rummaged through it, and came out with a beat up old copy of Spivaks
text. This is how we do calculus around here, he said, presenting it to me. During
my senior year at high school I took more advanced math courses at LaSalle University (which turned out, almost magically, to be located directly adjacent to my
high school) but read through Spivaks text. And I must have learned something
from it, because by the time I went on to college of course at the University of
Chicago I placed not into their Spivak calculus course, but the following course,
Honors Analysis in Rn . This course has the reputation of sharing the honor with
Harvards Math 55 of being the hardest undergraduate math course that American
universities have to offer. I cant speak to that, but it was certainly the hardest
math course I ever took. There were three ten week quarters. The first quarter was
primarily taught out of Rudins classic text [R], with an emphasis on metric spaces.
The second quarter treated Lebesgue integration and some Fourier analysis, and
the third quarter treated analysis on manifolds and Stokess theorem.
However, that was not the end of my exposure to Spivaks text. In my second
year of college I was a grader for the first quarter of Spivak calculus, at the (even
then) amazingly low rate of $20 per student for the entire 10 week quarter. Though
7
FOREWORD
the material in Spivaks text was at least a level below the trial by fire that I had
successfully endured in the previous year, I found that there were many truly difficult problems in Spivaks text, including a non-negligible percentage that I still
did not know how to solve. Grading for this course solidified my knowledge of this
elementary but important material. It was also my first experience with reading
proofs written by bright but very inexperienced authors: often I would stare at
an entire page of text, one long paragraph, and eventually circle a single sentence
which carried the entire content that the writer was trying to express. I only graded
for one quarter after that, but I was a drop in tutor for my last three years of
college, meaning that I would field questions from any undergraduate math course
that a student was having trouble with, and I had many further interactions with
Spivaks text. (By the end of my undergraduate career there were a small number
of double-starred problems of which I well knew to steer clear.)
Here is what I remembered about Spivaks text in fall of 2011:
(i) It is an amazing trove of problems, some of which are truly difficult.
(ii) The text itself is lively and idiosyncratic.1
(iii) The organization is somewhat eccentric. In particular limits are not touched
until Chapter 5. The text begins with a chapter basic properties of numbers,
which are essentially the ordered field axioms, although not called such. Chapter
3 is on Functions, and Chapter 4 is on Graphs. These chapters are essentially contentless. The text is broken up into five parts of which the third is Derivatives
and Integrals.
After teaching the 2400 course for a while, I lost no esteem for Spivaks text,
but increasingly I realized it was not the ideal accompaniment for my course. For
one thing, I realized that my much more vivid memories of the problems than the
text itself had some basis in fact: although Spivak writes with a lively and distinct
voice and has many humorous turns of phrase, the text itself is rather spare. His
words are (very) well chosen, but few. When one takes into account the ample
margins (sometimes used for figures, but most often a white expanse) the chapters
themselves are very short and core-minded. When given the chance to introduce a
subtlety or ancillary topic, Spivak almost inevitably defers it to the problems.
I have had many years to reflect on Spivaks text, and I now think its best use
is in fact the way I first encountered it myself: as a source of self study for bright,
motivated students with little prior background and exposure to university level
mathematics (in our day, this probably means high school students, but I could
imagine a student underwhelmed by an ordinary freshman calculus class for which
Spivaks text would be a similarly mighty gift). Being good for self study is a
high compliment to pay a text, and any such text can a fortiori also be used in a
course...but not in a completely straightforward way. For my course, although the
1In between the edition of the book that Sally had given me and the following edition, all
instances of third person pronouns referring to mathematicians had been changed from he to
she. Initially I found this amusing but silly. More recently I have begun doing so myself.
SPIVAK AND ME
students who stuck with it were very motivated and hard-working, most (or all) of
them needed a lot of help from me in all aspects of the course. I had been informed
in advance by my colleague Ted Shifrin that signing on to teach this course should
entail committing to about twice as many office hours as is typical for an undergraduate course, and this did indeed come to pass: I ended up having office hours
four days a week, and I spent the majority of them helping the students make their
way through the problems in Spivaks text. Even the best students who, by the
way, I thought were awfully good could not solve some of the problems unassisted.
There were many beautiful, multi-part problems introducing extra material that I
wanted my students to experience: and eventually I figured out that the best way
to do this was to incorporate the problems into my lectures as theorems and proofs.
All in all I ended up viewing Spivaks book as being something of a deconstruction2 of the material, and much of my teaching time was spent reconstructing it.
For me, the lightness of touch of Spivaks approach was ultimately something I
appreciated aesthetically but could see was causing my students difficulty at various key points. My experience rather convinced me that more is more: students
wanted to see more arguments in complete detail, and also simply more proofs overall. Aside from the (substantial) content conveyed in the course, a major goal is to
give the students facility with reading, understanding, constructing and critiquing
proofs. In this regard being in a classroom setting with other motivated students is
certainly invaluable, and I tried to take advantage of this by insisting that students
present their questions and arguments to each other as well as to me.
But students also learn about how to reason and express themselves mathematically by being repeatedly exposed to careful, complete proofs. I think experienced
mathematicians can forget the extent to which excellent, even brilliant, students
benefit from this exposure. Of course they also benefit immensely, probably more
so, by working things out for themselves. The value of this is certainly not in
question, and there is no competition here: the amount of things to do in honors
calculus is infinite and the repository of problems in Spivaks text is nearly so
so by working out more for herself, the instructor is not leaving less for the students
to do, but only different things for them to do.
This brings me to the current text. As explained above, it is heavily indebted
to [S]. However, it is or at least, I mean it to be a new honors calculus text,
and not merely a gloss of [S]. Indeed:
The text is indebted to [S], but not uniquely so. It is also heavily indebted
to Rudins classic text [R], and it borrows at key points from several other sources,
e.g. [A], [Go], [H], [L].
I do not view this borrowing as being in any way detrimental, and I certainly do
not attempt to suppress my reliance on other texts. The mathematics exposed here
is hundreds of years old and has been treated excellently in many famous texts. An
undergraduate mathematics text which strove to be unlike its predecessors would
2My conception of the meaning of deconstruction in the sense of academic humanities is
painfully vague. I am more thinking of the term in the sense that chefs use it.
10
FOREWORD
11
and harder (or phrased more positively: one merit of abstraction is to make certain
arguments shorter and easier ).
I am a fan of abstraction, but I have come to believe that it is much less useful and moreover, much less educational in basic real analysis than in most
other branches of pure mathematics. A turning point in my feelings about this
was a second semester undergraduate real analysis course I taught at McGill University in 2005. When preparing to teach the course I was quite surprised at how
pedestrian the syllabus seemed: an entire year of real analysis was restricted to
the one-dimensional case, and there was no topology or set theory whatsoever.3 I
was strictly forbidden from talking about metric spaces, for instance. The topics of
the course were: infinite series, the Riemann integral, and sequences and series of
functions, including uniform convergence. By the end of the course I had acquired
more respect for the deep content inherent in these basic topics and the efficacy of
treating them using no more than - arguments and the completeness axiom. This
was also the first course I taught in which I typed up lecture notes, and portions of
these notes appear here as parts of Chapters 11 through 14.
Exception: We begin our treatment of the Riemann integral with an axiomatic approach: that is, we list some reasonable properties (axioms) that an area functional
should satisfy, and before we do the hard work of constructing such a functional
we explore the consequences of these axioms. In particular, less than two pages
into our discussion of integration we state and prove (given the axioms!) the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. This approach to the Riemann Integral resonates
deeply with me, as it addresses concerns that bubbled up over several years of my
teaching this material in the context of freshman calculus. I came up with this
approach in late 2004 while preparing for the McGill analysis course. Just a few
days later I noticed that Lang had done (essentially) the same thing in his text [L].
I was encouraged that this idea had been used by others, and I endorse it still.
Given the choice between pounding out an - argument and developing a more
abstract or softer technique that leads to an easier proof, in this text we usually
opt for the former. Well, thats not strictly true: sometimes we do both.
We often spend time giving multiple proofs and approaches to basic results.
For instance, there are two distinct approaches to the Riemann integral: Riemanns
original approach using tagged partitions and Riemann sums, and Gaston Darbouxs later simplification using upper and lower sums and integrals. Most texts at
this level cover only one of these in detail, but here we cover both: first Darboux,
then Riemann. I got permission to do so while teaching the analysis class at
McGill, since this was done in the official course text of R. Gordon [Go]. Later I
realized that Gordon is in real life an integration theorist!
More significantly, we prove the Interval Theorems using - arguments and later
come back to give much quicker proofs using sequences and the Bolzano-Weierstrass
Theorem. One may well say that this is evidence that sequences should be treated
3In fact, I didnt find out until just after the course ended that the students did not know
about countable and uncountable sets. Without conscious thought I had assumed otherwise.
12
FOREWORD
at the beginning of the course rather than towards the end, and many texts do
take this approach, most notably [R]. However I endorse Spivaks ordering of the
material, in which honors calculus essentially begins with a thorough grappling
with the - definition of limit. Although there are easier and especially, softer
approaches to most of the key theorems, I feel that manipulation of inequalities
that characterized hard analysis is a vitally important skill for students to learn
and this is their best chance to learn it.
We view the completeness axiom as the star of the show. Thus we do not put it
on the stage in Act I, Scene I, when people are still settling into their seats.
CHAPTER 1
14
Z+ N Z Q R C.
1. INTRODUCTION
15
lowest terms, i.e., with a and b not both divisible by any integer n > 1.2 Thus in
Q we have an additive identity 0, every element has an additive inverse, we have a
multiplicative identity 1, and every nonzero element has a multiplicative inverse.
What then are the real numbers R? The geometric answer is that the real numbers
correspond to points on the number line, but this does not make clear why there
are such points other than the rational numbers. An answer that one learns in high
school is that every real number has an infinite decimal expansion, not necessarily
terminating or repeating, and conversely any integer followed by an infinite decimal expansion determines a real number. In fact this is perfectly correct: it gives a
complete characterization of the real numbers, but it is not a cure-all: in order to
pursue the implications of this definition and even to really understand it one
needs tools that we will develop later in the course.
Finally, the complex numbers C are expressions of the form a + bi where a and
b are real numbers and i2 = 1. They are extremely important in mathematics
generally e.g. one needs them in order to solve polynomial equations but in this
course they will play at most a peripheral role.
Back to R: let us nail down the fact that there are real numbers which are not
rational. One way to see this is as follows: show that the decimal expansion of
every rational number is eventually periodic, and then exhibit a decimal expansion
which is not eventually periodic, e.g.
x = 0.16116111611116111116 . . .
where the number of 1s after each 6 increases by 1 each time. But this number x
reeks of contrivance: it seems to have been constructed only to make trouble. The
ancient Pythagoreans discovered a much more natural irrational real number.
Theorem 1.4. The square root of 2 is not a rational number.
Proof. The proof is the most famous (and surely one of the first) instances
of a certain important kind of argument, namely a proof by contradiction. We
assume that what we are trying to prove is false, and from that we reason until we
reach an absurd conclusion. Therefore what we are trying
to prove must be true.
2
is
rational:
then
Here goes: seeking a contradiction,
we
suppose
there are
integers a, b with b > 0 and 2 = ab . Since the defining property of 2 is that its
square is 2, there is really nothing to do but square both sides to get
2=
a2
.
b2
16
or
b2 = 2A2 .
Thus b2 is divisible by 2, so as above b = 2B for some B Z. Substituting, we get
4B 2 = (2B)2 = b2 = 2A2 ,
or
2B 2 = A2 .
Thus we are back where we started: assuming that 2b2 = a2 , we found that both
a and b were divisible by 2. This is suspect in the extreme, and we now have our
choice of killing blow. One ending is to observe that everything we have said above
applies to A and B: thus we must also have A = 2A1 , B = 2B2 , and so forth.
We can continue in this way factoring out as many powers of 2 from a and b as we
wish. But the only integer which is arbitrarily divisible by 2 is 0, so our conclusion
is a = b = 0, whereas we assumed b > 0: contradiction.
Alternately and perhaps more simply each rational number may be written
in lowest terms, so we could have assumed this about ab at the outset and, in particular,
that a and b are not both divisible by 2. Either way we get a contradiction,
so 2 must not be a rational number.
1.3. Why do we not do calculus on Q?
To paraphrase the title question, why do we want to use R to do calculus? Is
there something stopping us from doing calculus over, say, Q?
The answer to the second question is no: we can define limits, continuity, derivatives and so forth for functions f : Q Q exactly as is done for real functions. The
most routine results carry over with no change: it is still true, for instance, that
sums and products of continuous functions are continuous. However most of the
big theorems especially, the Interval Theorems become false over Q.
For a, b Q, let [a, b]Q = {x Q | a x b}.
Example: Consider the function f : [0, 2]Q Q given by f (x) = 1 if x2 <
2
and f (x) = 1 if x2 > 2. Note that we do not need to define f (x) at x = 2,
because by the result of the previous section these are not rational numbers. Then
f is continuous in fact it is differentiable and has identically zero derivative. But
f (0) = 1 < 0, f (2) = 1 > 0, and there is no c [0, 2]Q such that f (c) = 0. Thus
the Intermediate Value Theorem fails over Q.
Example: Consider the function: f : [0, 2]Q Q given by f (x) = x212 . Again, this
function is well-defined at all points of [0, 2]Q because 2 is not a rational number.
It is also a continuous function. However it is
not bounded above: by taking rational numbers which are arbitrarily close to 2, x2 2 becomes arbitrarily small
and thus f (x) becomes arbitarily large.3 In particular, f certainly does not attain
a maximum value. Thus the Extreme Value Theorem fails over Q.
Moreover, it can be shown (and will be later) that any function on a closed,
bounded interval which is either uniformly continuous or integrable is bounded, so
3We will be much more precise about this sort of thing later on. This is just an overview.
17
the above function f is neither uniformly continuous nor integrable. If you have
had second semester
freshman calculus, you should think about why the analogous
function f : [0, 2] \ { 2} R
is not improperly Riemann integrable: it builds up
infinite area as we approach 2.
The point of these examples is in order to succeed in getting calculus off the ground,
we need to make use of some fundamental property of the real numbers not possessed by (for intance) the rational numbers. This property, which can be expressed
in various forms, is called completeness, and will play a major role in this course.
2. Some Properties of Numbers
2.1. Axioms for a Field.
In order to do mathematics in a rigorous way, one needs to identify a starting
point. Virtually all mathematical theorems are of the form A = B. That is,
assuming A, B must follow. For instance, in Euclidean geometry one lays down a
set of axioms and reasons only from them. The axioms needed for calculus are a
lot to swallow in one dose, so we will introduce them gradually. What we give here
is essentially a codification of high school algebra, including inequalities.
Specifically, we will give axioms that we want a number system to satisfy. At
this point we will take it for granted that in our number system we have operations
of addition, multiplication and an inequality relation <, and that there are distinguished numbers called 0 and 1. We require the following properties:
(P0) 0 6= 1.
(P1) (Commutativity of +): For all numbers x, y, x + y = y + x.
(P2) (Associativity of +): For all numbers x, y, z, (x + y) + z = x + (y + z).
(P3) (Identity for +): For all numbers x, x + 0 = x.
(P4) (Inverses for +): For all numbers x, there exists y with x + y = 0.
(P5) (Commutativity of ): For all numbers x, y, x y = y x.
(P6) (Associativity of ): For all numbers x, y, z (x y) z = x (y z).
(P7) (Identity for ): For all numbers x, x 1 = x.
(P8) (Inverses for ) For all numbers x 6= 0, there exists a number y with xy = 1.
(P9) (Distributivity of over +): For all numbers x, y, z, x (y + z) = (x y) + (x z).
Although it is not important for us now, the above axioms (P0) through (P9)
are called the field axioms, and a structure which satisfies them is called a field.
Example: Both Q and R satisfy all of the above field axioms. (We take this as
known information.)
Example: The complex numbers C satisfy all of the above field axioms. The only
one which is not straightforward is the existence of multiplicative inverses. For this:
if z = x + iy is a nonzero complex number i.e., the real numbers x and y are not
both zero then if w = xxiy
2 +y 2 , zw = 1.
Example: Let F2 = {0, 1} be a set consisting of two elements, 0 and 1. We define
18
0 + 0 = 0, 0 + 1 = 1 + 0 = 1, 1 + 1 = 0, 0 0 = 0 1 = 1 0 = 0, 1 1 = 1. Then F2
satisfies all of the above field axioms. It is sometimes called the binary field.
Proposition 1.5. In every system satisfying the field axioms, for every number
x we have x 0 = 0.
Proof. We have x 0 = x (0 + 0) = (x 0) + (x 0). Subtracting (x 0) from
both sides gives 0 = x 0.
Proposition 1.6. In every system satisfying the field axioms:
a) The only additive identity is 0.
b) Every number x has a unique additive inverse. If 1 denotes the additive inverse
of 1, then the additive inverse of x is (1) x.
c) The only multiplicative identity is 1.
b) Every nonzero number has a unique multiplicative inverse.
Proof. a) Note that 0 is an additive identity by (P3). Suppose that z is
another additive identity, and consider 0+z. Since 0 is an additive identity, 0+z = z.
Since z is an additive identity, 0 + z = 0. Thus z = 0.
b) Suppose y and z are both additive inverses to x: x + y = x + z = 0. Adding y
to both sides gives
y = 0 + y = (x + y) + y = (y + x) + y = y + (x + y)
= y + (x + z) = (y + x) + z = (x + y) + z = 0 + z = z,
so y = z. Moreover, for any number x,
(1) x + x = ((1) x) + (1 x) = (1 + 1) x = 0 x = 0.
c), d) The proofs of these are the same as the proofs of parts a) and b) but with
all instances of + replaced by and all instances of 0 replaced by 1.
Proposition 1.7. In every system satisfying the field axioms, (1)2 = 1.
Proof. By Proposition 1.6, 11 is the additive inverse of 1, namely 1.
Note that a logically equivalent formulation of Proposition 1.8 is: in any system
satisfying the field axioms, if xy = 0 then x = 0 or y = 0.
2.2. Axioms for an ordered field.
The remaining properties of numbers concern the inequality relation <. Instead
of describing the relation < directly, it turns out to be simpler to talk about the
properties of positive numbers. If we are given the inequality relation <, then we
say that x is positive if x > 0, thus knowing < we know which numbers are positive. Conversely, suppose that we have identified a subset P of numbers as positive.
Then we can define x < y if y x P. Now we want our set of positive numbers
19
20
and thus x1 = ( 1
x ) is negative.
d) Suppose x is positive and y is negative. In particular x and y are not zero,
so xy 6= 0. To show that xy is negative, by part b) it is enough to rule out the
possibility that xy is positive. Suppose it is. Then, by part c), since x is positive,
1
1
x is positive, and thus y = xy x would be positive: contradiction.
e) Suppose x and y are both negative. Then xy 6= 0, and we need to rule out the
possibility that xy is negative. Suppose it is. Then xy is positive, x1 is negative,
so by part d) y = xy x1 is negative and thus y is positive: contradiction.
a)
b)
c)
d)
e)
21
Since every positive real number is less than or equal to some integer, and every positive rational number is, in particular, a positive real number, then also
every positive rational number is less than or equal to some integer. That is, Q also
satisfies the Archimedean property. (Or, directly: any positive rational number
may be written in the form ab with a, b Z+ , and then ab a.)
This Archimedean property is so natural and familiar (not to mention useful...)
that the curious student may be well wonder: are there in fact systems of numbers
satisfying the ordered field axioms but not the Archimedean property?!? The answer is yes, there are plenty of them, and it is in fact possible to construct a theory
of calculus based upon them (in fact, such a theory is in many ways more faithful to
the calculus of Newton and Leibniz than the theory which we are presenting here,
which is a 19th century innovation). But we will not see such things in this course!
The next property does provide a basic difference between Q and R.
Theorem 1.12. Let x be a real number and n Z+ .
22
Proof. If x 0 then x = |x|. If x < 0 then x < 0 < x = |x|, so x < |x|.
Theorem 1.15. (Triangle Inequality) For all numbers x, y, |x + y| |x| + |y|.
Proof. Since |x| is defined to be x if x 0 and x if x < 0, it is natural to
break the proof into cases.
Case 1: x, y 0. Then |x + y| = x + y = |x| + |y|.
Case 2: x, y < 0. Then x + y < 0, so |x + y| = (x + y) = x y = |x| + |y|.
Case 3: x 0, y < 0. Now unfortunately we do not know whether |x + y| is
non-negative or negative, so we must consider consider further cases.
Case 3a: x + y 0. Then |x + y| = x + y |x| + |y|.
Case 3b: x + y < 0. Then |x + y| = x y | x| + | y| = |x| + |y|.
Case 4: x < 0, y 0. The argument is exactly the same as that in Case 3. In fact,
we can guarantee it is the same: since the desired inequality is symmetric in x
and y meaning, if we interchange x and y we do not change what we are trying
to show we may reduce to Case 3 by interchanging x and y.5
The preceding argument is definitely the sort that one should be prepared to make
when dealing with expressions involving absolute values. However, it is certainly
not very much fun. Spivak gives an alternate proof of the Triangle Inequality
which is more interesting and thematic. First, since both quantities |x + y| and
|x| + |y| are non-negative, the inequality will hold iff it holds after squaring both
sides (Proposition 1.11e). So it is enough to show
(|x + y|)2 (|x| + |y|)2 .
now (|x+y|)2 = (x+y)2 = x2 +2xy +y 2 , whereas (|x|+|y|)2 = |x|2 +2|x||y|+|y|2 =
x2 + |2xy| + y 2 , so subtracting the left hand side from the right, it is equivalent to
show that
0 (x2 + |2xy| + y 2 ) (x2 + 2xy + y 2 ).
But
(x2 + |2xy| + y 2 (x2 + 2xy + y 2 ) = |2xy| 2xy 0
by Proposition 1.14. So this gives a second proof of the Triangle Inequality.
A similar argument can be used to establish the following variant.
Proposition 1.16. (Reverse Triangle Inequality)
For all numbers x, y, ||x| |y|| |x y|.
Proof. Again, since both quantities are non-negative, it is sufficient to prove
the inequality after squaring both sides:
(||x| |y||)2 = (|x| |y|)2 = |x|2 2|x||y| + |y|2 = x2 |2xy| + y 2
x2 2xy + y 2 = (x y)2 = (|x y|)2 .
Exercise: Let x, y be any numbers.
a) Show that |x| |y| |x y| by writing x = (x y) + y and applying the usual
triangle inequality.
b) Deduce from part a) that ||x| |y|| |x y|.
5Such symmetry arguments can often by used to reduce the number of cases considered.
23
LHS =
n
X
i6=j
x2i yi2 + 2
i=1
xi yi xj yj ,
i<j
so
RHS LHS =
X
i6=j
x2i yj2 2
X
i<j
xi yj xj yi =
X
(xi yj xj yi )2 0.
i<j
Theorem 1.19. (Arithmetic-Geometric Mean Inequality, n = 2)
For all numbers 0 < a < b, we have
2
a+b
2
a < ab <
< b2 .
2
Proof. First inequality: Since a > 0 and 0 < a < b, a a < a b.
Second inequality: Expanding out the square and clearing denominators, it is equivalent to 4ab < a2 + 2ab + ab2 , or to a2 2b + b2 > 0. But a2 2ab + b2 = (a b)2 ,
so since a 6= b, (a b)2 > 0.
a+b
Third inequality: Since a+b
2 and b are both positive, it is equivalent to 2 < b and
thus to a + b < 2b. But indeed since a < b, a + b < b + b = 2b.
Later we will use the theory of convexity to prove a signficant generalization of
Theorem 1.19, the Weighted Arithmetic-Geometric Mean Inequality.
CHAPTER 2
Mathematical Induction
1. Introduction
Principle of Mathematical Induction for sets
Let S be a subset of the positive integers. Suppose that:
(i) 1 S, and
(ii) n Z+ , n S = n + 1 S.
Then S = Z+ .
The intuitive justification is as follows: by (i), we know that 1 S. Now apply (ii) with n = 1: since 1 S, we deduce 1 + 1 = 2 S. Now apply (ii) with
n = 2: since 2 S, we deduce 2 + 1 = 3 S. Now apply (ii) with n = 3: since
3 S, we deduce 3 + 1 = 4 S. And so forth.
This is not a proof. (No good proof uses and so forth to gloss over a key point!)
But the idea is as follows: we can keep iterating the above argument as many times
as we want, deducing at each stage that since S contains the natural number which
is one greater than the last natural number we showed that it contained. Now it
is a fundamental part of the structure of the positive integers that every positive
integer can be reached in this way, i.e., starting from 1 and adding 1 sufficiently
many times. In other words, any rigorous definition of the natural numbers (for
instance in terms of sets, as alluded to earlier in the course) needs to incorporate,
either implicitly or (more often) explicitly, the principle of mathematical induction.
Alternately, the principle of mathematical induction is a key ingredient in any axiomatic characterization of the natural numbers.
It is not a key point, but it is somewhat interesting, so let us be a bit more specific.
In Euclidean geometry one studies points, lines, planes and so forth, but one does
not start by saying what sort of object the Euclidean plane really is. (At least
this is how Euclidean geometry has been approached for more than a hundred years.
Euclid himself gave such definitions as: A point is that which has position but
not dimensions. A line is breadth without depth. In the 19th century it was
recognized that these are descriptions rather than definitions, in the same way that
many dictionary definitions are actually descriptions: cat: A small carnivorous
mammal domesticated since early times as a catcher of rats and mice and as a pet
and existing in several distinctive breeds and varieties. This helps you if you are
already familiar with the animal but not the word, but if you have never seen a cat
before this definition would not allow you to determine with certainty whether any
particular animal you encountered was a cat, and still less would it allow you to
reason abstractly about the cat concept or prove theorems about cats.) Rather
25
26
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
point, line, plane and so forth are taken as undefined terms. They are
related by certain axioms: abstract properties they must satisfy.
In 1889, the Italian mathematician and proto-logician Gisueppe Peano came up
with a similar (and, in fact, much simpler) system of axioms for the natural numbers. In slightly modernized form, this goes as follows:
The undefined terms are zero, number and successor.
There are five axioms that they must satisfy, the Peano axioms. The first four
are:
(P1) Zero is a number.
(P2) Every number has a successor, which is also a number.
(P3) No two distinct numbers have the same successor.
(P4) Zero is not the successor of any number.
Using set-theoretic language we can clarify what is going on here as follows: the
structures we are considering are triples (X, 0, S), where X is a set, 0 is an element
of X, and S : X X is a function, subject to the above axioms.
From this we can deduce quite a bit. First, we have a number (i.e., an element
of X) called S(0). Is 0 = S(0)? No, that is prohibited by (P4). We also have a
number S(S(0)), which is not equal to 0 by (P4) and it is also not equal to S(0),
because then S(0) = S(S(0)) would be the successor of the distinct numbers 0
and S(0), contradicting (P3). Continuing in this way, we can produce an infinite
sequence of distinct elements of X:
(3)
In particular X itself is infinite. The crux of the matter is this: is there any element
of X which is not a member of the sequence (3), i.e., is not obtained by starting at
0 and applying the successor function finitely many times?
The axioms so far do not allow us to answer this question. For instance, suppose
that the numbers consisted of the set [0, ) of all non-negative real numbers, we
define 0 to be the real number of that name, and we define the successor of x to be
x + 1. This system satisfies (P1) through (P4) but has much more in it than just
the natural numbers we want, so we must be missing an axiom! Indeed, the last
axiom is:
(P5) If Y is a subset of the set X of numbers such that 0 Y and such that
x Y implies S(x) Y , then Y = X.
Notice that the example we cooked up above fails (P5), since in [0, ) the subset
of natural numbers contains zero and contains the successor of each of its elements
but is a proper subset of [0, ).
Thus it was Peanos contribution to realize that mathematical induction is an axiom for the natural numbers in much the same way that the parallel postulate is
an axiom for Euclidean geometry.
27
On the other hand, it is telling that this work of Peano is little more than one
hundred years old, which in the scope of mathematical history is quite recent.
Traces of what we now recognize as induction can be found from the mathematics
of antiquity (including Euclids Elements!) on forward. According to the (highly
recommended!) Wikipedia article on mathematical induction, the first mathematician to formulate it explicitly was Blaise Pascal, in 1665. During the next hundred
years various equivalent versions were used by different mathematicians notably
the methods of infinite descent and minimal counterexample, which we shall discuss later and the technique seems to have become commonplace by the end of
the 18th century. Not having an formal understanding of the relationship between
mathematical induction and the structure of the natural numbers was not much
of a hindrance to mathematicians of the time, so still less should it stop us from
learning to use induction as a proof technique.
Principle of mathematical induction for predicates
Let P (x) be a sentence whose domain is the positive integers. Suppose that:
(i) P (1) is true, and
(ii) For all n Z+ , P (n) is true = P (n + 1) is true.
Then P (n) is true for all positive integers n.
Variant 1: Suppose instead that P (x) is a sentence whose domain is the natural numbers, i.e., with zero included, and in the above principle we replace (i) by
the assumption that P (0) is true and keep the assumption (ii). Then of course the
conclusion is that P (n) is true for all natural numbers n. This is more in accordance
with the discussion of the Peano axioms above.1
Exercise 1: Suppose that N0 is a fixed integer. Let P (x) be a sentence whose
domain contains the set of all integers n N0 . Suppose that:
(i) P (N0 ) is true, and
(ii) For all n N0 , P (n) is true = P (n + 1) is true.
Show that P (n) is true for all integers n N0 . (Hint: define a new predicate Q(n)
with domain Z+ by making a change of variables in P .)
2. The First Induction Proofs
2.1. The Pedagogically First Induction Proof.
There are many things that one can prove by induction, but the first thing that
everyone proves by induction is invariably the following result.
Proposition 2.1. For all n Z+ , 1 + . . . + n =
n(n+1)
.
2
Proof. We go by induction on n.
Base case (n = 1): Indeed 1 = 1(1+1)
.
2
+
Induction step: Let n Z and suppose that 1 + . . . + n =
IH
1 + . . . + n + n + 1 = (1 + . . . + n) + n + 1 =
n(n+1)
.
2
Then
n(n + 1)
+n+1
2
1In fact Peanos original axiomatization did not include zero. What we presented above is a
28
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
n2 + n 2n + 2
n2 + 2n + 3
(n + 1)(n + 2)
(n + 1)((n + 1) + 1)
+
=
=
=
.
2
2
2
2
2
Here the letters IH signify that the induction hypothesis was used.
=
Induction is such a powerful tool that once one learns how to use it one can prove
many nontrivial facts with essentially no thought or ideas required, as is the case in
the above proof. However thought and ideas are good things when you have them!
In many cases an inductive proof of a result is a sort of first assault which raises
the challenge of a more insightful, noninductive proof. This is certainly the case
for Proposition 2.1 above, which can be proved in many ways.
Here is one non-inductive proof: replacing n by n 1, it is equivalent to show:
(n 1)n
.
(4)
n Z, n 2 : 1 + . . . + n 1 =
2
We recognize the quantity on the right-hand side as the binomial coefficient n2 :
it counts the number of 2-element subsets of an n element set. This raises the
prospect of a combinatorial proof, i.e., to show that the number of 2-element
subsets of an n element set is also equal to 1 + 2 + . . . + n 1. This comes out
immediately if we list the 2-element subsets of {1, 2, . . . , n} in a systematic way:
we may write each such subset as {i, j} with 1 i n 1 and i < j n. Then:
The subsets with least element 1 are {1, 2}, {1, 3}, . . . , {1, n}, a total of n 1.
The subsets with least element 2 are {2, 3}, {2, 4}, . . . , {2, n}, a total of n 2.
..
.
The subset with least element n 1 is {n 1, n}, a total of 1.
Thus the number of 2-element subsets of {1, . . . , n} is on the one hand n2 and
on the other hand (n 1) + (n 2) + . . . + 1 = 1 + 2 + . . . + n 1. This gives a
combinatorial proof of Proposition 2.1.
2.2. The (Historically) First(?) Induction Proof.
Theorem 2.2. (Euclid) There are infinitely many prime numbers.
Proof. For n Z+ , let P (n) be the assertion that there are at least n prime
numbers. Then there are infinitely many primes if and only if P (n) holds for all
positive integers n. We will prove the latter by induction on n.
Base Case (n = 1): We need to show that there is at least one prime number. For
instance, 2 is a prime number.
Induction Step: Let n Z+ , and assume that P (n) holds, i.e., that there are at
least n prime numbers p1 < . . . < pn . We need to show that P (n + 1) holds, i.e.,
there is at least one prime number different from the numbers we have already
found. To establish this, consider the quantity
Nn = p1 pn + 1.
Since p1 pn p1 2, Nn 3. In particular it is divisible by at least one prime
number, say q.2 But I claim that Nn is not divisible by pi for any 1 i n. Indeed,
n
Z. Then kpi = p1 pn + 1 =
if Nn = api for some a Z, then let b = p1 p
pi
2Later in these notes we will prove the stronger fact that any integer greater than one may
be expressed as a product of primes. For now we assume this (familiar) fact.
29
30
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
LHS(n) = RHS(n). In this case to make the induction proof work you need only
(i) establish the base case and (ii) verify the equality of successive differences
LHS(n + 1) LHS(n) = RHS(n + 1) RHS(n).
We give two more familiar examples of this.
Proposition 2.3. For all n Z+ , 1 + 3 + . . . + (2n 1) = n2 .
Proof. Let P (n) be the statement 1 + 3 + . . . + (2n 1) = n2 . We will show
P (n) holds for all n Z+ by induction on n. Base case (n = 1): indeed 1 = 12 .
Induction step: Let n be an arbitrary positive integer and assume P (n):
(5)
1 + 3 + . . . + (2n 1) = n2 .
n(n+1)(2n+1)
.
6
Proof. By induction on n.
Base case: n = 1.
Induction step: Let n Z+ and suppose that 12 + . . . + n2 =
IH
1 + . . . + n2 + (n + 1)2 =
n(n+1)(2n+1)
.
6
Then
n(n + 1)(2n + 1)
+ (n + 1)2 =
6
4. INEQUALITIES
31
3 21
2
, so n2 3n 3 > 0 if
The roots of the polynomial x 3x 3 are x =
2
32
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
n > 4 = 3+2 25 > 3+2 21 . In particular, the desired inequality holds if n 10, so
by induction we have shown that 2n n3 for all n 10.
We leave it to to the student to convert the above analysis into a formal proof.
Remark: More precisely, 2n n3 for all natural numbers n except n = 2, 3, 4, 6, 7, 8, 9.
It is interesting that the desired inequality is true for a little while (i.e., at n = 0, 1)
then becomes false for a little while longer, and then becomes true for all n 10.
Note that it follows from our analysis that if for any N 4 we have 2N N 3 , then
this equality remains true for all larger natural numbers n. Thus from the fact that
29 < 93 , we can in fact deduce that 2n < n3 for all 4 n 8.
Proposition 2.7. For all n Z+ , 1 +
1
4
+ ... +
1
4
1
n2
2 n1 .
+ ... +
1
n2
2 n1 . Then
1
1
1
1
1
+ ... + 2 +
2 +
.
4
n
(n + 1)2
n (n + 1)2
1
n+1 ,
1
1
1
+
<2
.
2
n (n + 1)
n+1
Equivalently, it suffices to show
1
1
1
+
< .
n + 1 (n + 1)2
n
But we have
1
1
n+1+1
n+2
+
=
=
.
n + 1 (n + 1)2
(n + 1)2
(n + 1)2
Everything in sight is positive, so by clearing denominators, the desired inequality
is equivalent to
2
33
all have the same color. Consider now a set of n + 1 horses, which for specificity
we label H1 , H2 , . . . , Hn , Hn+1 . Now we can split this into two sets of n horses:
S = {H1 , . . . , Hn }
and
T = {H2 , . . . , Hn , Hn+1 }.
By induction, every horse in S has the same color as H1 : in particular Hn has
the same color as H1 . Similarly, every horse in T has the same color as Hn : in
particular Hn+1 has the same color as Hn . But this means that H2 , . . . , Hn , Hn+1
all have the same color as H1 . It follows by induction that for all n Z+ , in any
set of n horses, all have the same color.
Proof analysis: Naturally one suspects that there is a mistake somewhere, and
there is. However it is subtle, and occurs in a perhaps unexpected place. In fact the
argument is completely correct, except the induction step is not valid when n = 1:
in this case S = {H1 } and T = {H2 } and these two sets are disjoint: they have
no horses in common. We have been misled by the dot dot dot notation which
suggests, erroneously, that S and T must have more than one element.
In fact, if only we could establish the argument for n = 2, then the proof goes
through just fine. For instance, the result can be fixed as follows: if in a finite set
of horses, any two have the same color, then they all have the same color.
There is a moral here: one should pay especially close attention to the smallest
values of n to make sure that the argument has no gaps. On the other hand,
there is a certain type of induction proof for which the n = 2 case is the most
important (often it is also the base case, but not always), and the induction step
is easy to show, but uses once again the n = 2 case. Here are some examples of this.
The following is a fundamental fact of number theory, called Euclids Lemma.
Proposition 2.8. Let p be a prime, and let a, b Z+ . If p | ab, p | a or p | b.
Later in this chapter we will give a proof (yes, by induction!). Lets assume it for
now. Then we can swiftly deduce the following useful generalization.
Proposition 2.9. Let p be a prime number, n Z+ and a1 , . . . , an Z+ . If
p | a1 an , then p | ai for some 1 i n.
Proof. This is trivial for n = 1. We show it for all n 2 by induction.
Base case: n = 2: This is precisely Euclids Lemma.
Induction Step: We assume that for a given n Z+ and a1 , . . . , an Z+ , if a prime
p divides the product a1 an , then it divides at least one ai . Let a1 , . . . , an , an+1
Z, and that a prime p divides a1 an an+1 . Then p | (a1 an )an+1 , so by Euclids
Lemma, p | a1 an or p | an+1 . If the latter, were done. If the former, then by
our inductive hypothesis, p | ai for some 1 i n, so we are also done.
Corollary 2.10. Let p be a prime, and let a, n Z+ . Then p | an = p | a.
1
Exercise 5: Use Corollary 2.10 to show that for any prime p, p n is irrational.
34
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
35
In other words, if one can deduce statement C from statement A, then one can
also deduce statement C from A together with some additional hypothesis or hypotheses B. Specifically, we can take A to be P (n), C to be P (n + 1) and B to be
P (1) P (2) . . . P (n 1).
Less obviously, one can use our previous PMI to prove PS/CI. The proof is not
hard but slightly tricky. Suppose we know PMI and wish to prove PS/CI. Let P (n)
be a sentence with domain the positive integers and satisfying (i) and (ii) above.
We wish to show that P (n) holds for all n Z+ , using only ordinary induction.
The trick is to introduce a new predicate Q(n), namely
Q(n) = P (1) P (2) . . . P (n).
Notice that Q(1) = P (1); (ii) above tells us that Q(n) = P (n + 1). But if we
know Q(n) = P (1) . . . P (n) and also P (n + 1), then we know P (1) . . . P (n)
P (n + 1) = Q(n + 1). So Q(1) holds and for all n, Q(n) = Q(n + 1). So by PMI,
Q(n) holds for all n, hence certainly P (n) holds for all n.
Exercise 6: As for ordinary induction, there is a variant of strong/complete induction where instead of starting at 1 we start at any integer N0 . State this explicitly.
Here is an application which makes full use of the strength of PS/CI.
Proposition 2.11. Let n > 1 be an integer. Then there exist prime numbers
p1 , . . . , pk (for some k 1) such that n = p1 pk .
Proof. We go by strong induction on n.
Base case: n = 2. Indeed 2 is prime, so were good.
Induction step: Let n > 2 be any integer and assume that the statement is true for
all integers 2 k < n. We wish to show that it is true for n.
Case 1: n is prime. As above, were good.
Case 2: n is not prime. By definition, this means that there exist integers a, b, with
1 < a, b < n, such that n = ab. But now our induction hypothesis applies to both
a and b: we can write a = p1 pk and b = q1 ql , where the pi s and qj s are all
prime numbers. But then
n = ab = p1 pk q1 ql
is an expression of n as a product of prime numbers: done!
This is a good example of the use of induction (of one kind or another) to give a
very clean proof of a result whose truth was not really in doubt but for which a
more straightforward proof is wordier and messier.
7. Solving Homogeneous Linear Recurrences
Recall our motivating problem for PS/CI: we were given a sequence defined by
a1 = 1, a2 = 2, and for all n 1, an = 3an1 2an2 . By trial and error we
guessed that an = 2n1 , and this was easily confirmed using PS/CI.
But this was very lucky (or worse: the example was constructed so as to be easy
to solve). In general, it might not be so obvious what the answer is, and as above,
this is inductions Kryptonite: it has no help to offer in guessing the answer.
36
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
1+ 5
=
.
2
37
However, lets consider a more general problem and make a vaguer guess. Namely,
for real numbers b, c we consider an recurrence of the form
(6)
In all the cases weve looked at the solution was (roughly) exponential. So lets
guess an exponential solution xn = Crn and plug this into the recurrence; we get
Crn+2 = xn+2 = b(Crn+1 ) + c(Crn ),
which simplifies to
r2 br cr = 0.
Evidently the solutions to this are
r=
b2 + 4c
.
2
2
Some cases to be concerned about are the case c = b4 , in which case we have
2
only a single root r = 2b , and the case c < b4 in which case the roots are complex
numbers.
case: b = c = 1. Then
But for the moment lets look at the Fibonacci
1 5
= 1 = .618033988749894848204586834 . . . .
2
So we have two different bases what do we do with that? A little thought shows
that if r1n and r2n are both solutions to the recurrence xn+2 = bxn+1 cxn (with any
initial conditions), then so is C1 r1n + C2 r2n for any constants C1 and C2 . Therefore
we propose xn = C1 r1n + C2 r2n as the general solution to the two-term homogeneous linear recurrence (6) and the two initial conditions x1 = A1 , x2 = A2 provide
just enough information to solve for C1 and C2 .
Trying this for the Fibonacci sequence, we get
1 = F1 = C1 + C2 (1 ).
1 = F2 = C1 ()2 + C2 (1 )2 .
Multiplying the first equation by and subtracting it from the second equation
will give us a linear equation to solve for C2 , and then we plug the solution into
either of the equations and solve for C1 . It turns out that
1
1
C1 = , C2 = .
5
5
interlude: This is easily said and indeed involves only high school algebra. But
we can do something slicker. Instead of determining the constants by evaluating
Fn at n = 1 and n = 2, its easier to evaluate at n = 1 and n = 0: then we have
F0 = C1 0 + C2 (1 )0 = C1 + C2 .
But for this to work we need to know F0 , which we have not defined. Can it be
defined in a sensible way? Yes! Writing the basic recurrence in the form Fn+1 =
Fn + Fn1 and solving for Fn1 gives:
Fn1 = Fn+1 Fn .
38
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
1
1
1
1
=
= , C2 = .
1+
5
2 1
5
5
2
1
2
where =
1+ 5
2 .
1
Fn = (n (1 )n ) ,
5
39
It certainly looks as though xn = n for all n. Indeed, assuming it to be true for all
positive integers smaller than n + 2, we easily check
xn+2 = 2xn+1 xn = 2(n + 1) n = 2n + 2 n = n + 2.
The characteristic polynomial is r2 2r + 1 = (r 1)2 : it has repeated roots. One
solution is C1 1n = C1 (i.e., xn is a constant sequence). This occurs iff x2 = x1 , so
clearly there are nonconstant solutions as well. It turns out that in general, if the
characteristic polynomial is (x r)2 , then the two basic solutions are xn = rn and
also xn = nrn . It is unfortunately harder to guess this in advance, but it is not hard
to check that this gives a solution to a recurrence of the form xn+2 = 2r0 xn+1 r02 xn .
These considerations will be eerily familiar to the reader who has studied differential equations. For a more systematic exposition on discrete analogues of calculus
concepts (with applications to the determination of power sums as in 3), see [DC].
8. The Well-Ordering Principle
There is yet another form of mathematical induction that can be used to give what
is, arguably, an even more elegant proof of Proposition 2.11.
Theorem 2.13. (Well-Ordering Principle) Let S be a nonempty subset of Z+ .
Then S has a least element, i.e., there exists s S such that for all t S, s t.
Intutitively, the statement is true by the following reasoning: first we ask: is 1 S?
If so, it is certainly the least element of S. If not, we ask: is 2 S? If so, it is
certainly the least element of S. And then we continue in this way: if we eventually
get a yes answer then we have found our least element. But if for every n the
answer to the question Is n an element of S? is negative, then S is empty!
The well-ordering principle (henceforth WOP) is often useful in its contrapositive form: if a subset S Z+ does not have a least element, then S = .
We claim WOP is logically equivalent to the principle of mathematical induction (PMI) and thus also to the principle of strong/complete induction (PS/CI).
First we will assume PS/CI and show that WOP follows. For this, observe that
WOP holds iff P (n) holds for all n Z+ , where P (n) is the following statement:
P (n): If S Z+ and n S, then S has a least element.
Indeed, if P (n) holds for all n and S Z is nonempty, then it contains some
positive integer n, and then we can apply P (n) to see that S has a least element.
Now we can prove that P (n) holds for all n by complete induction: first, if 1 S,
then indeed 1 is the least element of S, so P (1) is certainly true. Now assume P (k)
for all 1 k n, and suppose that n + 1 S. If n + 1 is the least element of S,
then were done. If it isnt, then it means that there exists k S, 1 k S. Since
we have assumed P (k) is true, therefore there exists a least element of S.
Conversely, let us assume WOP and prove PMI. Namely, let S Z and suppose
that 1 S, and that for all n, if n S then n + 1 S. We wish to show that
S = Z+ . Equivalently, putting T = Z+ \ S, we wish to show that T = . If not,
40
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
then by WOP T has a least element, say n. Reasoning this out gives an immediate
contradiction: first, n 6 S. By assumption, 1 S, so we must have n > 1, so that
we can write n = m + 1 for some m Z+ . Further, since n is the least element of
T we must have n 1 = m S, but now our inductive assumption implies that
n + 1 = n S, contradiction.
So now we have shown that PMI PS/CI = WOP = PMI.
Let us give another proof of Proposition 2.11 using WOP. We wish to show that
every integer n > 1 can be factored into primes. Let S be the set of integers n > 1
which cannot be factored into primes. Seeking a contradiction, we assume S is
nonempty. In that case, by WOP it has a least element, say n. Now n is certainly
not prime, since otherwise it can be factored into primes. So we must have n = ab
with 1 < a, b < n. But now, since a and b are integers greater than 1 which are
smaller than the least element of S, they must each have prime factorizations, say
a = p1 pk , b = q1 ql . But then (stop me if youve heard this one before)
n = ab = p1 pk q1 ql
itself can be expressed as a product of primes, contradicting our assumption. therefore S is empty: every integer greater than 1 is a product of primes.
This kind of argument is often called proof by minimum counterexample.
These two proofs of Proposition 2.11 are very close: the difference between a proof
by PS/CI and a proof by WOP is more a matter of taste than technique.
9. The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic
9.1. Euclids Lemma and the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic.
The following are the two most important theorems in beginning number theory.
Theorem 2.14. (Euclids Lemma) Let p be a prime number and a, b be positive
Suppose that p | ab. Then p | a or p | b.
Theorem 2.15. (Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic) The factorization of
any integer n > 1 into primes is unique, up to the order of the factors: suppose
n = p1 pk = q1 ql ,
are two factorizations of n into primes, with p1 . . . pk and q1 . . . ql . Then
k = l and pi = qi for all 1 i k.
A prime factorization n = p1 pk is in standard form if p1 . . . pk . Every
prime factorization can be put in standard form by ordering the primes from least
to greatest. Dealing with standard form factorizations is a convenient bookkeeping
device, since otherwise our uniqueness statement would have to include the proviso
up to the order of the factors.
Given Proposition 2.11 i.e., the existence of prime factorizations Theorems
2.14 and 15.13 are equivalent: each can be easily deduced from the other.
41
EL implies FTA: Assume Euclids Lemma. As seen above, this implies Proposition 2.9: if a prime divides any finite product of integers it must divide one of
the factors. Our proof will be by minimal counterexample: suppose that there are
some integers greater than one which factor into primes in more than one way, and
let n be the least such integer, so
(7)
n = p1 pk = q1 ql ,
42
2. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
k
q
a
q
b, so p |
a
q b.
But 1 <
a
q
which Euclids Lemma fails for p and a, so it must be that p | aq (so in particular
p | a) or p | b. Contradiction. So Euclids Lemma holds for all primes p.
9.3. The Lindemann-Zermelo Inductive Proof of FTA.
Here is a proof of FTA using WOP, following Lindemann [Li33] and Zermelo [Ze34].
We claim that the standard form factorization of a positive integer is unique.
Assume not; then the set of positive integers which have at least two different
standard form factorizations is nonempty, so has a least element, say n, where:
(9)
n = p1 pr = q1 qs .
Here the pi s and qj s are prime numbers, not necessarily distinct from each other.
However, p1 6= qj for any j. Indeed, if we had such an equality, then after relabelling
the qj s we could assume p1 = q1 and then divide through by p1 = q1 to get a smaller
positive integer pn1 . By the assumed minimality of n, the prime factorization of pn1
must be unique: i.e., r 1 = s 1 and pi = qi for all 2 i r. Then multiplying
by p1 = q1 we see that we didnt have two different factorizations after all.
In particular p1 6= q1 . Without loss of generality, assume p1 < q1 . Then, if we
subtract p1 q2 qs from both sides of (9), we get
(10)
CHAPTER 3
f : x 7 an xn + . . . + a1 x + a0
44
Pn
Then every polynomial expression f = i=0 ai xi determines a polynomial function x 7 f (x). But it is at least conceivable that two different-looking polynomial
expressions give rise to the same function. To give some rough idea of what I mean
here, consider the two expressions f = 2 arcsin x + 2 arccos x and g = . Now it
turns out for all x [1, 1] (the common domain of the arcsin and arccos functions) we have f (x) = . (The angle whose sine is x is complementary to the
angle whose cosine is x, so arcsin x + arccos x = + = 2 .) But still f and g are
given by different expressions: if I ask you what the coefficient of arcsin x is in
the expression f , you will immediately tell me it is 2. If I ask you what the coefficient of arcsin x is in the expression , you will have no idea what Im talking about.
One special polynomial expression is the zero polynomial. This is the polynomial whose ith coefficient ai is equal to zero for all i 0.
Every nonzero polynomial expression has a degree, which is a natural number,
the largest natural number i such that the coefficient ai of xi is nonzero. Thus in
(11) the degree of f is n if and only if an 6= 0: otherwise the degree is smaller than n.
Although the zero polynomial expression does not have any natural number as
a degree, it is extremely convenient to regard deg 0 as negative, i.e., such that deg 0
is smaller than the degree of any nonzero polynomial. This means that for any
d N the set of polynomials of degree at most d includes the zero polynomial.
We will follow this convention here but try not to make too big a deal of it.
Let us give some examples to solidify this important concept:
The polynomials of degree at most 0 are the expressions f = a0 . The corresponding
functions are all constant functions: their graphs are horizontal lines. (The graph
of the zero polynomial is still a horizontal line, y = 0, so it is useful to include the
zero polynomial as having degree at most zero.)
The polynomials of degree at most one are the linear expressions L = mx + b.
The corresponding functions are linear functions: their graphs are straight lines.
The degree of L(x) is one if m 6= 0 i.e., if the line is not horizontal and 0 if
m = 0 and b 6= 0.
Similarly the polynomials of degree at most two are the quadratic expressions
q(x) = ax2 + bc + c. The degree of q is 2 unless a = 0.
We often denote the degree of the polynomial expression f by deg f .
Theorem 3.1. Let f, g be nonzero polynomial expressions.
a) If f + g 6= 0, then deg(f + g) max(deg f, deg g).
b) We have deg(f g) = deg f + deg g.
Proof. a) Suppose that
f (x) = am xm + . . . + a1 x + a0 , am 6= 0
and
g(x) = bn xn + . . . + b1 x + b0 , bn 6= 0
1. POLYNOMIAL FUNCTIONS
45
m
X
i=0
n
X
ai (
bj xj )n .
j=0
46
Thus we may take q(x) = q1 (x) +. . . +qk (x), so that r(x) = a(x)q(x)b(x) = rk (x)
and deg r(x) = deg rk (x) < deg b(x).
Step 2: We prove the uniqueness of q(x) (and thus of r(x) = a(x) q(x)b(x)).
Suppose Q(x) is another polynomial such that R(x) = a(x) Q(x)b(x) has degree
less than the degree of b(x). Then
a(x) = q(x)b(x) + r(x) = Q(x)b(x) + R(x),
so
(q(x) Q(x))b(x) = R(x) r(x).
Since r(x) and R(x) both have degree less than deg b(x), so does r(x) R(x), so
deg b(x) > deg(R(x)r(x)) = deg((q(x)Q(x))b(x)) = deg(q(x)Q(x))+deg b(x).
Thus deg(q(x) Q(x)) < 0, and the only polynomial with negative degree is the
zero polynomial, i.e., q(x) = Q(x) and thus r(x) = R(x).1
Exercise: Convince yourself that the proof of Step 1 is really a careful, abstract
description of the standard high school procedure for long division of polynomials.
Theorem 3.2 has many important and useful consequences; here are some of them.
Theorem 3.3. (Root-Factor Theorem) Let f (x) be a polynomial expression and
c a real number. The following are equivalent:
(i) f (c) = 0. (c is a root of f .)
(ii) There is some polynomial expression q such that as polynomial expressions,
f (x) = (x c)q(x). (x c is a factor of f .)
Proof. We apply the Division Theorem with a(x) = f (x) and b(x) = x c,
getting polynomials q(x) and r(x) such that
f (x) = (x c)q(x) + r(x)
and r(x) is either the zero polynomial or has deg r < deg x c = 1. In other
words, r(x) is in all cases a constant polynomial (perhaps constantly zero), and its
constant value can be determined by plugging in x = c:
f (c) = (c c)q(c) + r(c) = r(c).
The converse is easier: if f (x) = (x c)q(x), then f (c) = (c c)q(c) = 0.
Corollary 3.4. Let f be a nonzero polynomial of degree n. Then the corresponding polynomial function f has at most n real roots: i.e., there are at most n
real numbers a such that f (a) = 0.
Proof. By induction on n.
Base case (n = 0): If deg f (x) = 0, then f is a nonzero constant, so has no roots.
Induction Step: Let n N, suppose that every polynomial of degree n has at
most n real roots, and let f (x) be a polynomial of degree n + 1. If f (x) has no
real root, great. Otherwise, there exists a R such that f (a) = 0, and by the
Root-Factor Theorem we may write f (x) = (x a)g(x). Moreover by Theorem
3.1, we have n + 1 = deg f = deg(x a)g(x) = deg(x a) + deg g = 1 + deg g, so
deg g = n. Therefore our induction hypothesis applies and g(x) has m distinct real
1If you dont like the convention that the zero polynomial has negative degree, then you
can phrase the argument as follows: if q(x) Q(x) were a nonzero polynomial, these degree
considerations would give the absurd conclusion deg(q(x) Q(x)) < 0, so q(x) Q(x) = 0.
1. POLYNOMIAL FUNCTIONS
47
48
Proof. We know
b
b
bn
0=P
= an n + . . . + a1 + a0 .
c
c
c
Multiplying through by cn clears denominators, giving
an bn + an1 bn1 c + . . . + a1 bcn1 + a0 cn = 0.
Rewriting this equation as
an bn = c(an1 bn1 . . . a0 cn1 )
shows that an bn is divisible by c. But since b and c have no prime factors in
common and bn has the same distinct prime factors as does b, bn and c have no
prime factors in common and are thus coprime. So Theorem 2.16 applies to show
that an is divisible by c. Similarly, rewriting the equation as
a0 cn = b(an bn1 an1 bn2 c . . . a1 cn1 )
shows that a0 cn is divisible by b. As above, since b and c are coprime, so are b and
cn , so by Theorem 2.16 a0 is divisible by b.
In high school algebra the Rational Roots Theorem is often used to generate a finite
list of possible rational roots of a polynomial with integer coefficients. This is nice,
but there are more impressive applications. For instance, taking an = 1 and noting
that 1 is divisible by c iff c = 1 we get the following result.
Corollary 3.8. Let a0 , . . . , an1 Z, and consider the polynomial
P (x) = xn + an1 xn1 + . . . + a1 x + a0 .
Suppose c is a rational number such that P (c) = 0. Then c is an integer.
So what? Let p be any prime number, let n 2, and consider the polynomial
P (x) = xn p.
By Corollary 3.8, if c Q is such that P (c) = 0, then c Z. But if c Z is such
that P (c) = 0, then cn = p. But this means that the prime number p is divisible
by the integer c, so c = 1 or c = p. But (1)n = 1 and (p)n = pn , so
2. RATIONAL FUNCTIONS
49
2. Rational Functions
A rational function is a function which is a quotient of two polynomial functions:
P (x)
f (x) = Q(x)
, with Q(x) not the zero polynomial. To be sure, Q is allowed to have
roots; it is just not allowed to be zero at all points of R.
P (x)
The natural domain of Q(x)
is the set of real numbers for which Q(x) 6= 0,
i.e., all but a finite (possibly empty) set of points.
50
Exercise: Show that every monic polynomial of positive degree factors uniquely into
a product of monic irreducible polynomials.
Corollary 3.12. Let n Z+ , and let p, P, Q0 be polynomials, such that p is
irreducible and that p does not divide Q0 .
a) There are polynomials B, A such that we have a rational function identity
A(x)
P (x)
B(x)
+
=
.
p(x)n Q0 (x)
p(x)n
p(x)n1 Q0 (x)
(12)
P = A1 p + BQ0 .
A1
A1 p + BQ0
B
= n + n1 .
n
p Q0
p
p
Q0
The identity of Corollary 3.12 can be applied repeatedly: suppose we start with a
P
, with Q a monic polynomial (as is no loss of generality;
proper rational function Q
we can absorb the leading coefficient into P ). Then Q is a polynomial of positive
degree, so we may factor it as
Q = pa1 1 par r ,
where p1 , . . . , pr are distinct monic irreducible polynomials. Let us put Q0 =
pa2 2 par r , so Q = pa1 1 Q0 . Applying Corollary 3.12, we may write
Ba
Aa1
P
= a11 + n1
Q
p1
p1 Q0
with deg Ba1 < deg p1 and deg Aa1 < deg(pn1
Q0 ). Thus Corollary 3.12 applies to
1
Aa1
,
as
well,
giving
us
overall
a1 1
p1
Q0
P
Ba
Ba 1
Aa1 1
= a11 + a111 + n2
.
Q
p1
p1 Q0
p1
2. RATIONAL FUNCTIONS
51
P (x)
Q(x)
be a proper
c
)
(x
c
)
q
(x)
ql (x)j
1
k
1
i=1
j=1
i=1
j=1
Exercise: Show that the constants in (15) are unique.
CHAPTER 4
54
easy to see that an ordered field admits infinitesimal elements iff it does not satisfy
the Archimedean axiom, whereas the real numbers R do satisfy the Archimedean
axiom. So at best Lebiniz was advocating a limiting process based on a different
mathematical model of the real numbers than the standard modern one. And
at worst, Lebinizs writing on infinitesimals seems like equivocation: at different
stages of a calculation the same quantity is at one point vanishingly small and at
another point not. The calculus of both fluxions and infnitesimals required, among
other things, some goodwill: if you used them as Newton and Leibniz did in their
calculations then at the end you would get a sensible (in fact, correct!) answer.
But if you wanted to make trouble and ask why infinitesimals could not be manipulated in other ways which swiftly led to contradictions, it was all too easy to do so.
The calculus of Newton and Leibniz had a famous early critic, Bishop George
Berkeley. In 1734 he published The Analyst, subtitled A DISCOURSE Addressed
to an Infidel MATHEMATICIAN. WHEREIN It is examined whether the Object,
Principles, and Inferences of the modern Analysis are more distinctly conceived,
or more evidently deduced, than Religious Mysteries and Points of Faith. Famously, Berkeley described fluxions as the ghosts of departed quantities. I havent
read Berkeleys text, but from what I am told it displays a remarkable amount of
mathematical sophistication and most of its criticisms are essentially valid!
So if the mid 17th century is the birth of systematic calculus it is not the birth
of a satisfactory treatment of the limiting concept. When did this come? More
than 150 years later! The modern definition of limits via inequalities was given by
Bolzano in 1817 (but not widely read), in a somewhat imprecise form by Cauchy
in his influential 1821 text, and then finally by Weierstrass around 1850.
2. Derivatives Without a Careful Definition of Limits
Example 2.1: Let f (x) = mx + b be a linear function. Then f has the following
property: for any x1 6= x2 , secant line between the two points (x1 , f (x1 )) and
(x2 , f (x2 )) is the line y = f (x). Indeed, the slope of the secant line is
mx2 + b (mx1 + b)
m(x2 x1 )
f (x2 ) f (x1 )
=
=
= m.
x2 x1
x2 x1
x2 x1
Thus the secant line has slope m and passes through the point (x1 , f (x1 )), as does
the linear function f . But there is a unique line passing through a given point with
a given slope, so that the secant line must be y = mx + b.
Using this, it is now not at all difficult to compute the derivative of a linear function...assuming an innocuous fact about limits.
Example 2.2: Let f (x) = mx + b. Then
f 0 (x) = lim
h0
f (x + h) f (x)
mh
= lim m(x + h) + b (mx + b)h = lim
= lim m.
h0
h0 h
h0
h
The above computation is no surprise, since we already saw that the slope of any
secant line to a linear function y = mx + b is just m. So now we need to evaluate
the limiting slope of the secant lines. But surely if the slope of every secant line
55
is m, the desired limiting slope is also m, and thus f 0 (x) = m (constant function).
Let us record the fact about limits we used.
Fact 4.1. The limit of a constant function f (x) = C as x approaches a is C.
Example 2.3: Let f (x) = x2 . Then
f (x + h) f (x)
(x + h)2 x2
= lim
h0
h0
h
h
f 0 (x) = lim
x2 + 2xh + h2 x2
h(2x + h)
= lim
= lim 2x + h.
h0
h0
h0
h
h
Now Leibniz would argue as follows: in computing the limit, we want to take h
infinitesimally small. Therefore 2x + h is infinitesimally close to 2x, and so in the
limit the value is 2x. Thus
f 0 (x) = 2x.
= lim
But these are just words. A simpler and equally accurate description of what we
(x)
until we
have done is as follows: we simplified the difference quotient f (x+h)f
h
got an expression in which it made good sense to plug in h = 0, and then we
plugged in h = 0. If you wanted to give a freshman calculus student practical
instructions on how to compute derivatives of reasonably simple functions directly
from the definition, I think you couldnt do much better than this!
Example 2.4: f (x) = x3 . Then
f (x + h) f (x)
(x + h)3 x3
x3 + 3x2 h + 3xh2 + h3 x3
= lim
= lim
h0
h0
h0
h
h
h
f 0 (x) = lim
h(3x2 + 3xh + h2 )
= lim 3x2 + 3xh + h2 .
h0
h0
h
Again we have simplified to the point where we may meaningfully set h = 0, getting
= lim
f 0 (x) = 3x2 .
Example 2.5: For n Z+ , let f (x) = xn . Then
Pn n ni i
x h xn
f (x + h) f (x)
(x + h)n xn
f (x) = lim
= lim
= lim i=0 i
h0
h0
h0
h
h
h
Pn n ni ii
n
X n
h i=1 i x h
n n1
= lim
x
+h
xni hi2
= lim
h0
h0 1
h
i
i=2
n n1
=
x
= nxn1 .
1
At this point we have seen many examples of a very pleasant algebraic phenomenon.
Namely, for y = f (x) a polynomial function, when we compute the difference
(x)
quotient f (x+h)f
we find that the numerator, say G(h) = f (x + h) f (x),
h
always has h as a factor: thus we can write it as G(h) = hg(h), where g(h) is
another polynomial in h. This is exactly what we need in order to compute the
derivative, because when this happens we get
0
f (x + h) f (x)
hg(h)
= lim
= lim g(h) = g(0).
h0
h0
h0
h
h
f 0 (x) = lim
56
ha
(This generalizes our first fact above, since constant functions are polynomials.)
Differentiating polynomial functions directly from the definition is, evidently, somewhat tedious. Perhaps we can establish some techniques to streamline the process?
For instance, suppose we know the derivative of some function f : what can we say
about the derivative of cf (x), where c is some real number? Lets see:
cf (x + h) cf (x)
f (x + h) f (x)
lim
= lim c
.
h0
h0
h
h
If we assume limxa cf (x) = c limxa f (x), then we can complete this computation:
the derivative of cf (x) is cf 0 (x). Let us again record our assumption about limits.
Fact 4.3. If limxa f (x) = L, then limxa cf (x) = cL.
This tells for instance that the derivative of 17x10 is 17(10x9 ) = 170x9 . More generally, this tells us that the derivative of the general monomial cxn is cnxn1 .
Now what about sums?
Let f and g be two differentiable functions. Then the derivative of f + g is
f (x + h) + g(x + h) f (x) g(x)
f (x + h) f (x) g(x + h) g(x)
lim
= lim
+
.
h0
h0
h
h
h
If we assume the limit of a sum is the sum of limits, we get
(f + g)0 = f 0 + g 0 .
Again, lets record what weve used.
Fact 4.4. If limxa f (x) = L and limxa g(x) = M , then limx (f + g)(x) =
L + M.
Exercise 2.6: Show by mathematical induction that if f1 , . . . , fn are functions with
derivatives f10 , . . . , fn0 , then (f1 + . . . + fn )0 = f10 + . . . + fn0 .
Putting these facts together, we get an expression for the derivative of any polynomial function: if f (x) = an xn + . . . + a1 x + a0 , then f 0 (x) = nan xn1 + . . . + a1 . In
particular the derivative of a degree n polynomial is a polynomial of degree n 1
(and the derivative of a constant polynomial is the zero polynomial).
3. Limits in Terms of Continuity
We have been dancing around two fundmaental issues in our provisional treatment
of derivatives. The first is, of course, the notion of the limit of a function at a point.
The second, just as important, is that of continuity at a point.
In freshman calculus it is traditional to define continuity in terms of limits. A
57
true fact which is not often mentioned is that this works just as well the other way
around: treating the concept of a continuous function as known, one can define
limits in terms of it. Since I think most people have at least some vague notion
of what a continuous function is very roughly it is that the graph y = f (x) is a
nice, unbroken curve and I know all too well that many students have zero intuition for limits, it seems to be of some value to define limits in terms of continuity.
Let f : R R be a function. For any x R, f may or may not be continuous at x. We say f is simply continuous if it is continuous at x for every x R.3u
Here are some basic and useful properties of continuous functions. (Of course
we cannot prove them until we give a formal definition of continuous functionsu.)
Fact 4.5. a) Every constant function is continuous at every c R.
b) The identity function I(x) = x is continuous at every c R.
c) If f and g are continuous at x = c, then f + g and f g are continuous at x = c.
d) If f is continuous at x = c and f (c) 6= 0, then f1 is continuous at x = c.
e) If f is continuous at x = c and g is continuous at x = f (c), then g f is
continuous at x = c.
From this relatively small number of facts many other facts follow. For instance,
since polynomials are built up out of the identity function and the constant functions by repeated addition and multiplication, it follows that all polynomials are
continuous at every c R. Similarly, every rational function fg is continuous at
every c in its domain, i.e., at all points c such that g(c) 6= 0.
We now wish to define the limit of a function f at a point c R. Here it is
crucial to remark that c need not be in the domain of f . Rather what we need
is that f is defined on some deleted interval Ic, about c: that is, there is some
> 0 such that all points in (c , c + ) except possibly at c, f is defined. To see
that this a necessary business, consider the basic limit defining the derivative:
f (x + h) f (x)
.
h
Here x is fixed and we are thinking of the difference quotient as a function of h.
Note though that this function is not defined at h = 0: the denominator is equal
to zero. In fact what we are trying to when differentiating is to find the most reasonable extension of the right hand side to a function which is defined at 0. This
brings us to the following definition.
f 0 (x) = lim
h0
58
59
60
= .
|A|
b) Fix > 0. We must show that there exists > 0 such that |x c| < implies
|f (x) + g(x) (f (c) + g(c))| < . Now
|f (x)+g(x)(f (c)+g(c))| = |(f (x)f (c))+(g(x)g(c))| |f (x)f (c)|+|g(x)g(c)|.
This is good: since f and g are both continuous at c, we can make each of |f (x)
f (c)| and |g(x) g(c)| as small as we like by taking x sufficiently close to c. The
sum of two quantities which can each be made as small as we like can be made as
small as we like!
Now formally: choose 1 > 0 such that |x c| < 1 implies |f (x) f (c)| < 2 .
Choose 2 > 0 such that |x c| < 2 implies |g(x) g(c)| < 2 . Let = min(1 , 2 ).
Then |x c| < implies |x c| < 1 and |x c| < 2 , so
|f (x) + g(x) (f (c) + g(c))| |f (x) f (c)| + |g(x) g(c)| < + = .
2 2
c) Fix > 0. We must show that there exists > 0 such that |x c| < implies
|f (x)g(x) f (c)g(c)| < . The situation here is somewhat perplexing: clearly we
need to use the continuity of f and g at c, and to do this it stands to reason that we
should be estimating |f (x)g(x)f (c)g(c)| in terms of |f (x)f (c)| and |g(x)g(c)|,
but unfortunately we do not yet see these latter two expressions. So we force them
to appear by adding and subtracting f (x)g(c):
|f (x)g(x) f (c)g(c)| = |f (x)g(x) f (x)g(c) + f (x)g(c) f (c)g(c)|
|f (x)||g(x) g(c)| + |g(c)||f (x) f (c)|.
This is much better: |g(c)||f (x) f (c)| is a constant times something which can
be made arbitrarily small, so can be made arbitarily small. Moreover in the term
|f (x)||g(x) g(c)| we can make |g(x) g(c)| arbitarily small by taking x sufficiently
close to c, and then, by continuity of f , |f (x)| gets arbitrarily close to |f (c)|. So
|f (x)| is nonconstant but bounded, and something which is bounded times something
which can be made arbitarily small can be made arbitrarily small!
Now formally:
61
Using Lemma 4.6a) and taking = 1, there exists 1 > 0 such that |x c| < 1
implies |f (x)| |f (c)| + 1. There exists 2 > 0 such that |x c| < 2 implies
|g(x) g(c)| < 2(|f (c)|+1)
. Finally, there exists 3 > 0 such that |x c| < 3 implies
|f (x) f (c)| < 2|g(c)| . (Here we are assuming that g(c) 6= 0. If g(c) = 0 then we
simply dont have the second term in our expression and the argument is similar
but easier.) Taking = min 1 , 2 , 3 , for |x c| < then |x c| is less than 1 , 2
and 3 so
|f (x)g(x) f (c)g(c)| |f (x)||g(x) g(c)| + |g(c)||f (x) f (c)|
< (|f (c)| + 1)
+ |g(c)|
= + = .
2(|f (c)| + 1)
2|g(c)|
2 2
d) Since fg = f g1 , in light of part c) it will suffice to show that if g is continuous
at c and g(c) 6= 0 then g1 is continuous at c. Fix > 0. We must show that there
exists > 0 such that |x c| < implies
1
1
|
| < .
g(x) g(c)
Now
1
|g(c) g(x)|
|g(x) g(c)|
1
|=
=
.
|
g(x) g(c)
|g(x)||g(c)|
|g(x)||g(c)|
Since g is continuous at x = c, we can make the numerator |g(x) g(c)| as small
as we like by taking x sufficiently close to c. This will make the entire fraction as
small as we like provided the denominator is not also getting arbitrarily small as x
approaches c. But indeed, since g is continuous at c and g(c) 6= 0, the denominator
is approaching |g(c)|2 6= 0. Thus again we have a quantity which we can make
arbitarily small times a bounded quantity, so it can be made arbitrarily small!
Now formally:
We apply Lemma 4.6b) with = 12 : there exists 1 > 0 such that |x c| < 1
implies |g(x)| |g(c)|
and thus also
2
2
1
.
|g(x)||g(c)|
|g(c)|2
Also there exists 2 > 0 such that |x c| < 2 implies |g(x) g(c)| <
|g(c)|2
2
.
|=
|g(x) g(c)| <
= .
g(x) g(c)
|g(x)||g(c)|
|g(c)|2
2
e) Fix > 0. Since g(y) is continuous at y = f (c), there exists > 0 such that
|y f (c)| < implies |g(y) g(f (c))| < . Moreover, since f is continuous at c,
there exists > 0 such that |xc| < implies |f (x)f (c)| < . Thus, if |xc| < ,
|f (x) f (c)| = |y f (c)| < and hence
|g(f (x)) g(f (c))| = |g(y) g(f (c))| < .
Corollary 4.8. All rational functions are continuous.
Proof. Since rational functions are built out of constant functions and the
identity by repeated addition, multiplication and division, this follows immediately
from Theorem 4.7.
62
Other elementary functions: unfortunately if we try to go beyond rational functions to other elementary functions familiar from precalculus, we run into the issue
that we have not yet given complete, satisfactory definitions
of these functions! For
instance, take even the relatively innocuous f (x) = x. We want this function to
have domain [0, ), but this uses the special property of R that every non-negative
number has a square root: we havent proved this yet! If > 0is irrational we
have not given any definition of the power function x . Similarly we do not yet
have rigorous definitions of ax for a > 1, log x, sin x and cos x, so we are poorly
placed to rigorously prove their continuity. However (following Spivak) in order
so as not to drastically limit the supply of functions to appear in our examples
and exercises, we will proceed for now on the assumption that all the above
elementary functions are continuous. We hasten to make two remarks:
Remark 4.5: This assumption can be justified! That is, all the elementary functions above are indeed continuous atevery point of their domain (with the small
proviso that for power functions like x we will need to give a separate definition
of continuity at an endpoint of an interval, coming up soon). And in fact we will
prove this later in the course...much later.
Remark 4.6: We will not use the continuity of the elementary functions as an
assumption in any of our main results (but only in results and examples explicitly
involving elementary functions; e.g. we will use the assumed continuity of the sine
function to differentiate it). Thus it will be clear that we are not arguing circularly
when we finally prove the continuity of these functions.
5. Limits Done Right
5.1. The Formal Definition of a Limit.
In order to formally define limits, it is convenient to have the notion of a deleted
interval Ic, about a point c, namely a set of real numbers of the form
0 < |x c| <
for some > 0. Thus Ic consists of (c , c) together with the points (c, c + ),
or more colloquially it contains all points sufficiently close to c but not equal to c.
Now comes the definition. For real numbers c and L and a function f : D R R,
we say limxc f (x) = L if for every > 0 there exists > 0 such that for all x in
the deleted interval Ic, i.e., for all x with 0 < |x c| < f is defined at x and
|f (x) L| < .
Among all the many problems of limits, perhaps the following is the most basic
and important.
Theorem 4.9. The limit at a point is unique (if it exists at all): that is, if L
and M are two numbers such that limxc f (x) = L and limxc f (x) = M , then
L = M.
Proof. Seeking a contradiction, we suppose L 6= M ; it is no loss of generality
to suppose that L < M (otherwise switch L and M ) and we do so. Now we take
= M 2L in the definition of limit: since limxc f (x) = L, there exists 1 > 0 such
63
that 0 < |x c| < 1 implies |f (x) L| < M 2L ; and similarly, since limxc f (x) =
M , there exists 2 > 0 such that 0 < |x c| < 2 implies |f (x) M | < M 2L .
Taking = min(1 , 2 , then, as usual, for 0 < |x c| < we get both inequalities:
M L
|f (x) L| <
2
M L
.
|f (x) M | <
2
However these inequalities are contradictory! Before we go further we urge the
reader to draw a picture to see that the vertical strips defined by the two inequalities above are disjoint: they have no points in common. Let us now check
this formally: since |f (x) L| < M 2L , f (x) < L + M 2L = M 2+L . On the other
hand, since |f (x) M | < M 2L , f (x) > M M 2L = M 2+L . Clearly there is not
a single value of x such that f (x) is at the same time greater than and less than
M +L
2 , let alone a deleted interval around c of such values of x, so we have reached
a contradiction. Therefore L = M .
We have now given a formal definition of continuity at a point and also a formal
definition of limits at a point. Previously though we argued that each of limits and
continuity can be defined in terms of the other, so we are now in an overdetermined situation. We should therefore check the compatibility of our definitions.
Theorem 4.10. Let f : D R R, and let c R.
a) f is continuous at x = c if and only if f is defined at c and limxc f (x) = f (c).
b) limxc f (x) = L iff f is defined in some deleted interval Ic, around x and,
defining f on (c , c + ) by f (x) = f (x), x 6= c, f (c) = L makes f continuous at
x = c.
Proof. All the pedagogical advantage here comes from working through this
yourself rather than reading my proof, so I leave it to you.
5.2. Basic Properties of Limits.
Most of the basic properties of continuity discussed above have analogues for limits.
We state the facts in the following result.
Theorem 4.11. Let f and g be two functions defined in a deleted interval Ic,
of a point c. We suppose that limxc f (x) = L and limxc g(x) = M .
a) For any constant A, limxc Af (x) = AL.
b) We have limxc f (x) + g(x) = L + M .
c) We have limxc f (x)g(x) = LM .
(x)
L
d) If M 6= 0, then limxc fg(x)
=M
.
We leave the proof to the reader. It is possible to prove any/all of these facts in
one of two ways: (i) by rephrasing the definition of limit in terms of continuity and
appealing to Theorem 4.7 above, or (ii) adapting the proofs of Theorem 4.7 to the
current context.
Now what about limits of composite functions? The natural analogue of Theorem 4.7e) above would be the following:
If limxc f (x) = L and limxL g(x) = M , then limxc g(f (x)) = M .
64
xc
xc
In other words, one can pull a limit through a continuous function. In this form
the result is actually a standard one in freshman calculus.
It happens that one can say exactly when the above statement about limits of
composite funtions holds. I dont plan on mentioning this in class and you neednt
keep it in mind or even read it, but I recently learned that this question has a rather
simple answer so I might as well record it here so I dont forget it myself.
Theorem 4.13. (Marjanovic [MK09]) Suppose limxc f (x) = L and limxL g(x) =
M . The following are equivalent:
(i) limxc g(f (x)) = M .
(ii) At least one of the following holds:
a) g is continuous at L.
b) There exists > 0 such that for all 0 < |x c| < , f (x) 6= L.
Proof. (i) = (ii): We will argue by contradiction: suppose that neither a)
nor b) holds; we will show that limxc g(f (x)) 6= M . Indeed, since b) dooes not
hold, for every > 0 there exists x with 0 < |x c| < such that f (x) = L. For
such x we have g(f (x)) = g(L). But since a) does not hold, g is not continuous at
L, i.e., M 6= g(L). Thus g(f (x)) = g(L) 6= M . Taking = |g(L) M | this shows
that there is no > 0 such that 0 < |x c| < implies |g(f (x)) M | < , so
limxc g(f (x)) 6= M .
(ii) = (i). The case in which a) holds i.e., g is continuous at L is precisely
Theorem 4.12. So it suffices to assume that b) holds: there exists some > 0 such
that 0 < |x c| < implies f (x) 6= L. Now fix > 0; since limxL g(x) = M ,
there exists > 0 such that 0 < |y L| < implies |g(y) M | < . Similarly (and
familiarly), since limxc f (x) = L, there exists 1 > 0 such that 0 < |x c| < 1
implies |f (x)L| < . Here is the point: for 0 < |xc| < 1 , we have |f (x)L| < .
65
If in addition 0 < |f (x) L| < , then we may conclude that |g(f (x)) M | < .
So our only concern is that pehaps f (x) = L for some c with 0 < |x c| < 1 ,
and this is exactly what the additional hypothesis b) allows us to rule out: if we
take = min(1 , ) then 0 < |x c| < implies 0 < |f (x) L| < and thus
|g(f (x)) M | < .
Remark 5.2: The nice expository article [MK09] gives some applications of the
implication (ii)b) = (i) of Theorem 4.13 involving making an inverse change of
variables to evaluate a limit. Perhaps we may revisit this point towards the end of
the course when we talk about inverse functions.
5.3. The Squeeze Theorem and the Switching Theorem.
Theorem 4.14. (Squeeze Theorem) Let m(x), f (x) and M (x) be defined on
some deleted interval I = (c , c + ) {c} about x = c. We suppose that:
(i) For all x I , m(x) f (x) M (x), and
(ii) limxc m(x) = limxc M (x) = L.
Then limxc f (x) = L.
Proof. Fix > 0. There exists 1 > 0 such that 0 < |x c| < 1 implies
|m(x) L| < and 2 > 0 such that 0 < |x c| < 2 implies |M (x) L| < . Let
= min(1 , 2 ). Then 0 < |x c| < implies
f (x) M (x) < L +
and
f (x) m(x) > L ,
so L < f (x) < L + , or equivalently |f (x) L| < .
sin( x1 ),
x 6= 0 and
Example 5.3: For 0, define f : R R by f (x) = x
f (0) = 0. By our assumption about the continuity of sign and our results on
continuity of rational functions and compositions of continuous functions, f is
continuous at all x 6= 0. We claim that f is continuous at x = 0 iff > 0. . . .
Example 5.4: The function f defined above is differentiable at x = 0 iff > 1. . . .
Example 5.5: limx0 sinx x = 1.
Solution: This will be a 17th century solution to the problem: i.e., we will assume that the trigonometric functions are continuous and use geometric reasoning,
including properties of angles and arclength. (Nevertheless, this solution seems a
lot better than not giving any proof at all until much later in the course...)
Consider the unit circle and the point on it Px = (cos x, sin x). There is a right
triangle T1 with vertices (0, 0), (cos x, 0), Px . This right triangle is contained in
the circular sector determined by all points on or inside the unit circle with angle
between 0 and x. In turn this circular sector is contained in a second right triangle
T2 , with vertices (0, 0), (1, 0), (1, tan x). Now let us write down the inequalities expressing the fact that since T1 is contained in the circular sector which is contained
in T2 , the area of T1 is less than or equal to the area of the circular sector, which
is less than or equal to the area of T2 .
The area of T1 is (one half the base times the height)
1
2
66
x
the circular sector is 2
times the area of the unit circle, or
1
1 sin x
of T2 is 2 tan x = 2 cos x . This gives us the inequalities
x
2
x
2.
The area
1
1
1 sin x
cos x sin x x
,
2
2
2 cos x
or equivalently, for x 6= 0,
x
1
.
sin x
cos x
Taking reciprocals this inequality is equivalent to
1
sin x
cos x.
cos x
x
Now we may apply the Squeeze Theorem: since cos x is continuous at 0 and takes
the value 1 6= 0 there, we have
1
= lim cos x = 1.
lim
x0
x0 cos x
Therefore the Squeeze Theorem implies
sin x
(16)
lim
= 1.
x0 x
cos x
x
Example 5.6: We will evaluate limx0 1cos
= 0. The idea is to use trigonometric
x
identities to reduce this limit to an expression involving the limit (16). Here goes:
1 cos x
1 cos x 1 + cos x
cos2 x 1
sin2 x
lim
= lim
= lim
= lim
x0
x0
x0 x(1 + cos x)
x0 x(1 + cos x)
x
x
1 + cos x
sin x
sin x
0
= lim
) = 0.
lim
=1(
x0 x
x0 1 + cos x
2
x
Of course we also have limx0 cos xx1 = limx0 1cos
= 0 = 0. In summary:
x
(17)
lim
x0
cos x 1
1 cos x
= lim
= 0.
x0
x
x
Before doing the next two examples we remind the reader of the composite angle formulas from trigonometry: for any real numbers x, y,
sin(x + y) = sin x cos y + cos x sin y,
cos(x + y) = cos x cos y sin x sin y.
Example 5.7: If f (x) = sin x, then we claim f 0 (x) = cos x. Indeed
f (x + h) f (x)
sin(x + h) sin x
sin x cos h + cos x sin h sin x
f 0 (x) = lim
= lim
= lim
h0
h0
h0
h
h
h
1 cos h
sin h
= sin x lim
+ cos x lim
= ( sin x) 0 + (cos x) 1 = cos x.
h0
h0 h
h
Example 5.8: If f (x) = cos x, then we claim f 0 (x) = sin x. Indeed
f (x + h) f (x)
cos(x + h) cos x
= lim
=
h0
h
h
cos x cos h sin x sin h cos x
lim
h0
h
f 0 (x) = lim
h0
= cos x
67
1 cos h
sin h
sin x lim
= ( cos x)0+( sin x)1 = sin x.
h0
h0 h
h
lim
68
x is right continuous at x = 0.
As above, it is necessary to require left/right continuity when discussing behavior at right/left endpoints of an interval. On the other hand one may still discuss
left/right continuity at interior points of an interval, and it is sometimes helpful to
do so.
Example: Let f (x) = bxc be the greatest integer function. Then f is continuous at c for all c R \ Z, whereas for any c Z, f is right continuous but not left
continuous at c.
This example suggests the following simple result.
Proposition 4.16. For a function f : D R R and c D, the following
are equivalent:
(i) f is left continuous at c and right continuous at c.
(ii) f is continuous at c.
We leave the proof to the reader.
In a similar way we can define one-sided limits at a point c.
We say limxc f (x) = L and read this as the limit as x approaches c from
the left of f (x) is L if for all > 0 there exists > 0 such that for all x with
c < x < c + , |f (x) L| < .
We say limxc+ f (x) = L and read this as the limit as x approaches c from
the right of f (x) is L if for all > 0, there exists > 0 such that for all x with
c < x < c, |f (x) L| < .
Proposition 4.17. For a function f : D R R and c D, the following
are equivalent:
69
(i) The left hand and right hand limits at c exist and are equal.
(ii) limxc f (x) exists.
Again we leave the proof to the reader.
Example: Let f (x) = bxc be the greatest integer function, and let n Z. Then
limxn f (x) = n 1 and limxn+ f (x) = n, so f is not continuous at n.
There is some terminology here not essential, but sometimes useful. If for a
function f and c R, the left and right hand limits at c both exist but are unequal,
we say that f has a jump discontinuity at c. If the left and right hand limts at
c both exist and are equal i.e., if limxc f (x) = L exists but still f (x) is not
continuous c (this can happen if either f (c) 6= L or, more plausibly, if c is not in
the domain of f ) we say that f has a removable discontinuity at c. This terminology comes from our earlier observation that if we (re)define f at c to be the
limiting value L then f becomes continuous at c. One sometimes calls a discontinuity which is either removable or a jump discontinuity a simple discontinuity: i.e.,
this is the case whenever both one-sided limits exist at c but f is not continuous at c.
Infinite limits: Consider limx0 x12 . This limit does not exist: indeed, if it did,
then there would be some deleted interval I0, on which f is bounded, whereas
just the opposite is happening: the closer x is to 0, the larger f (x) becomes. In
freshman calculus we would say limx0 f (x) = . And we still want to say that,
but in order to know what we mean when we say this we want to give an - style
definition of this. Here it is:
We say limxc f (x) = if for all M R, there exists > 0 such that 0 <
|x c| < = f (x) > M .
Geometrically, this is similar to the - definition of limit, but instead of picking two horizontal lines arbitrarily close to y = L, we pick one horizontal line which
is arbitrarily large and require that on some small deleted interval the graph of
y = f (x) always lie above that line. Similarly:
We say limxc f (x) = if for all m R, there exists > 0 such that 0 <
|x c| < implies f (x) < m.
Example: Let us indeed prove that limx0 x12 = . Fix M R. We need to
find such that 0 < |x| < implies x12 > M . It is no loss of generality to assume
M > 0 (why?). Then x12 > M |x| < 1M , so we may take = 1M .
CHAPTER 5
Differentiation
1. Differentiability Versus Continuity
Recall that a function f : D R R is differentiable at a D if
f (a + h) f (a)
h0
h
lim
exists, and when this limit exists it is called the derivative f 0 (a) of f at a. Moreover, the tangent line to y = f (x) at f (a) exists if f is differentiable at a and is
the unique line passing through the point (a, f (a)) with slope f 0 (a).
Note that an equivalent definition of the derivative at a is
lim
xa
f (x) f (a)
.
xa
One can see this by going to the - definition of a limit and making the substitution h = x a: then 0 < |h| < 0 < |x a| < .
Theorem 5.1. Let f : D R R be a function, and let a D. If f is
differentiable at a, then f is continuous at a.
Proof. We have
f (x) f (a)
(x a)
xa
f (x) f (a)
lim x a = f 0 (a) 0 = 0.
= lim
xa
xa
xa
lim f (x) f (a) = lim
xa
xa
Thus
0 = lim (f (x) f (a)) =
xa
lim f (x) f (a),
xa
so
lim f (x) = f (a).
xa
The converse of Theorem 5.1 is far from being true: a function f which is continuous at a need not be differentiable at a. An easy example is f (x) = |x| at a = 0.
In fact the situation is worse: a function f : R R can be continuous everywhere yet still fail to be differentiable at many points. One way of introducing
points of non-differentiability while preserving continuity is to take the absolute
value of a differentiable function.
71
72
5. DIFFERENTIATION
f (a + h) f (a)
h0
h
lim
= Cf 0 (a).
Theorem 5.4. (Sum Rule) Let f and g be functions which are both differentiable at a R. Then the sum f + g is also differentiable at a and
(f + g)0 (a) = f 0 (a) + g 0 (a).
Proof. Again, no biggie:
(f + g)(a + h) (f + g)(a)
f (a + h) f (a) g(a + h) g(a)
= lim
+
h0
h
h
h
f (a + h) f (a)
g(a + h) g(a)
= lim
+ lim
= f 0 (a) + g 0 (a).
h0
h0
h
h
h0
These results, simple as they are, have the following important consequence.
Corollary 5.5. (Linearity of the Derivative) For any differentiable functions
f and g and any constants C1 , C2 , we have
(C1 f + C2 g)0 = C1 f 0 + C2 g 0 .
2.2. Product Rule(s).
Theorem 5.6. (Product Rule) Let f and g be functions which are both differentiable at a R. Then the product f g is also differentiable at a and
(f g)0 (a) = f 0 (a)g(a) + f (a)g 0 (a).
Proof.
f (a + h)g(a + h) f (a)g(a)
h
f (a + h)g(a + h) f (a)g(a + h) + (f (a)g(a + h) f (a)g(a))
= lim
h0
h
f (a + h) f (a)
g(a + h) g(a)
= lim
lim g(a + h) + f (a) lim
.
h0
h0
h0
h
h
(f g)0 (a) = lim
h0
2. DIFFERENTIATION RULES
73
74
5. DIFFERENTIATION
the surface area of the cylinder with the top and bottom faces included, although
dimensional considerations wont tell you that.
Something similar can be applied to the formula (f g)0 = f 0 g 0 . Let f = f (t)
and view t as being time, say measured in seconds. Since f 0 (t) is a limit of quo(t)
tients f (t+h)f
, its dimension is the dimension of f divided by time. Now suppose
h
both f (t) and g(t) are lengths, say in meters. Then f 0 (t) and g 0 (t) both have units
meters per second, so f 0 (t) g 0 (t) has units meters squared per second squared.
On the other hand, the units of (f g)0 are meters squared per second. Thus the
formula (f g)0 = f 0 g 0 is asserting that some number of meters squared per second
is equal to some number of meters squared per second squared. Thats not only
wrong, its a priori meaningless.
By contrast the correct formula (f g)0 = f 0 g + f g 0 makes good dimensional
sense: as above, (f g)0 is meters squared per second; so is f 0 g and so is f g 0 , so we
can add them to get a meaningful number of meters squared per second. Thus the
formula at least makes sense, which is good because above we proved it to be correct.
Taking these ideas more seriously suggests that we should look for a proof of the
product rule which explicitly takes into account that both sides are rates of change
of areas. This is indeed possible, but we omit it for now.
Suppose we want to find the derivative of a function which is a product of not
two but three functions whose derivatives we already know, e.g. f (x) = x sin xex .
We can of course? still use the product rule, in two steps:
f 0 (x) = (x sin xex )0 = ((x sin x)ex )0 = (x sin x)0 ex + (x sin x)(ex )0
= (x0 sin x + x(sin x)0 )ex + x sin xex = sin x + x cos xex + x sin xex .
Note that we didnt use the fact that our three differentiable functions were x,
sin x and ex until the last step, so the same method shows that for any three
functions f1 , f2 , f3 which are all differentiable at x, the product f = f1 f2 f3 is also
differentiable at a and
f 0 (a) = f10 (a)f2 (a)f3 (a) + f1 (a)f20 (a)f3 (a) + f1 (a)f2 (a)f30 (a).
The following result rides this train of thought to its final destination.
Theorem 5.7. (Generalized Product Rule) Let n 2 be an integer, and let
f1 , . . . , fn be n functions which are all differentiable at a. Then f = f1 fn is also
differentiable at a, and
(18)
(f1 fn )0 (a) = f10 (a)f2 (a) fn (a) + . . . + f1 (a) fn1 (a)fn0 (a).
Proof. By induction on n.
Base Case (n = 2): This is precisely the ordinary Product Rule (Theorem 5.6).
Induction Step: Let n 2 be an integer, and suppose that the product of any n
functions which are each differentiable at a R is differentiable at a and that the
derivative is given by (18). Now let f1 , . . . , fn , fn+1 be functions, each differentiable
at a. Then by the usual product rule
0
(f1 fn fn+1 )0 (a) = ((f1 fn )fn+1 )0 (a) = (f1 fn )0 (a)fn+1 (a)+f1 (a) fn (a)fn+1
(a).
2. DIFFERENTIATION RULES
75
0
= f10 (a)f2 (a) fn (a)fn+1 (a) + . . . + f1 (a) fn (a)fn+1
(a).
Example: We may use the Generalized Product Rule to give a less computationally
intensive derivation of the power rule
(xn )0 = nxn1
for n Z+ . Indeed, taking f1 = = fn = x, we have f (x) = xn = f1 fn , so
applying the Generalized Power rule we get
(xn )0 = (x)0 x x + . . . + x x(x)0 .
Here in each term we have x0 = 1 multiplied by n 1 factors of x, so each term
evaluates to xn1 . Moreover we have n terms in all, so
(xn )0 = nxn1 .
No need to dirty our hands with binomial coefficients!
Theorem 5.8. (Generalized Leibniz Rule) Let n Z+ , and let f, g be functions
which are each n times differentiable at a R. Then f g is is n times differentiable
at a and
n
X
n (k) (nk)
(f g)(n) =
f g
.
k
k=0
f 0 (a)
g 0 (a)
g(a)f 0 (a) g 0 (a)f (a)
f (a)
=
.
2
g(a)
g(a)
g(a)2
76
5. DIFFERENTIATION
(g f )0 (a) = lim
xa
xa
xa
f (x) f (a)
xa
g(f (x)) g(f (a))
f (x) f (a)
= lim
lim
xa
xa
f (x) f (a)
xa
g(f (x)) g(f (a))
f (x) f (a)
=
lim
lim
= g 0 (f (a))f 0 (a).
xa
f (x) f (a)
xa
f (x)f (a)
The replacement of limxa . . . by limf (x)f (a) . . . in the first factor above is
justified by the fact that f is continuous at a. However, this argument has a gap:
when we multiply and divide by f (x) f (a), how do we know that we are not
dividing by zero?? The answer is that we cannot rule this out: it is possible for
f (x) to take the value f (a) on arbitarily small deleted intervals around a: again,
this is exactly what happens for the function f (x) of the above example near a = 0.
I maintain that the above gap can be mended so as to give a complete proof.
The above argument is valid unless for all > 0, there is x with 0 < |x a| <
such that f (x) f (a) = 0. In this case, it follows from Lemma 5.10 that if
f (x) f (a)
xa
exists at all, it must be equal to 0. But we are assuming the above limit exists, since
we are assuming f is differentiable at a. So f 0 (a) = 0, and therefore, since the Chain
Rule reads (g f )0 (a) = g 0 (f (a))f 0 (a), here we are trying to show (g f )0 (a) = 0.
For x R we have two possibilities: the first is f (x) f (a) = 0, in which case
also g(f (x)) g(f (a)) = g(f (a)) g(f (a)) = 0, so the difference quotient is zero at
these points. The second is f (x) f (a) 6= 0, in which case
lim
xa
f (x) f (a)
xa
holds, and the above argument shows this expression tends to g 0 (f (a))f 0 (a) = 0
(a))
as x a. So whichever holds, the difference quotient g(f (x))g(f
is close to (or
xa
equal to!) zero. Thus the limit tends to zero no matter which alternative obtains.
Somewhat more formally, if we fix > 0, then the first step of the argument
shows that there is > 0 such that for all x with 0 < |x a| < such that
(a))
f (x) f (a) 6= 0, | g(f (x))g(f
| < . On the other hand, when f (x) f (a) = 0,
xa
3. OPTIMIZATION
77
(a))
then | g(f (x))g(f
| = 0, so it is certainly less than ! Therefore, all in all we have
xa
(a))
| < , so that
0 < |x a| < = | g(f (x))g(f
xa
lim
xa
we will develop the right tools to prove stronger assertions. But when given a new definition, it is
always good to find ones feet by considering some examples and nonexamples of that definition.
78
5. DIFFERENTIATION
If one looks back at the previous examples and keeps in mind that we are supposed to be studying derivatives (!), one is swiftly led to the following fact.
Theorem 5.12. Let f : I R. Suppose f is differentiable at a I .
a) If f 0 (a) > 0, then f is increasing at a.
b) If f 0 (a) < 0, then f is decreasing at a.
c) If f 0 (a) = 0, then no conclusion can be drawn: f may be increasing at a, decreasing at a, or neither.
Proof. a) We use the - interpretation of differentiability at a to our advantage. Namely, take = f 0 (a): there exists > 0 such that for all x with
(a)
f 0 (a)| < f 0 (a), or equivalently
0 < |x a| < , | f (x)f
xa
0<
f (x) f (a)
< 2f 0 (a).
xa
(a)
> 0, so: if x > a, f (x)f (a) >
In particular, for all x with 0 < |xa| < , f (x)f
xa
0, i.e., f (x) > f (a); and if x < a, f (x) f (a) < 0, i.e., f (x) < f (a).
b) This is similar enough to part a) to be best left to the reader as an exercise.2
c) If f (x) = x3 , then f 0 (0) = 0 but f is increasing at 0. If f (x) = x3 , then
f 0 (0) = 0 but f is decreasing at 0. If f (x) = x2 , then f 0 (0) = 0 but f is neither
increasing nor decreasing at 0.
3. OPTIMIZATION
79
below: equivalently, there exists B 0 such that for all x D, |f (x)| B: i.e.,
the graph of f is trapped between the horizontal lines y = B and y = B.
Exercise: Let f : D R be a function.
a) Show: if f has a maximum value, it is bounded above.
b) Show: if f has a minimum value, it is bounded below.
Exercise: a) If a function has both a maximum and minimum value on D, then it
is bounded on D: indeed, if M is the maximum value of f and m is the minimum
value, then for all x B, |f (x)| max(|m|, |M |).
b) Give an example of a bounded function f : R R which has neither a maximum
nor a minimum value.
We say f assumes its maximum value at a if f (a) is the maximum value
of f on D, or in other words, for all x D, f (x) f (a). Simlarly, we say f
assumes its minimum value at a if f (a) is the minimum value of f on D, or in
other words, for all x D, f (x) f (a).
Example: The function f (x) = sin x assumes its maximum value at x = 2 , because sin 2 = 1, and 1 is the maximum value of the sine function. Note however
that 2 is not the only x-value at which f assumes its maximum value: indeed, the
sine function is periodic and takes value 1 precisely at x = 2 + 2n for n Z.
Thus there may be more than one x-value at which a function attains its maximum
3
value. Similarly f attains its minimum value at x = 3
2 f ( 2 ) = 1 and f takes
3
no smaller values and also at x = 2 + 2n for n Z.
Example: Let f : R R by f (x) = x3 + 5. Then f does not assume a maximum or minimum value. Indeed, limx f (x) = and limx f (x) = .
Example: Let f : [0, 2] R be defined as follows: f (x) = x + 1, 0 x < 1.
f (x) = 1, x = 1.
f (x) = x 1, 1 < x 2.
Then f is defined on a closed, bounded interval and is bounded above (by 2) and
bounded below (by 0) but does not have a maximum or minimum value. Of course
this example of a function defined on a closed bounded interval without a maximum
or minimum value feels rather contrived: in particular it is not continuous at x = 1.
This brings us to one of the most important theorems in the course.
Theorem 5.13. (Extreme Value Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R be continuous.
Then f has a maximum and minimum value, hence is bounded above and below.
The proof will be given in the next chapter, following a discussion of completeness.
Ubiquitously in (pure and applied) mathematics we wish to optimize functions:
that is, find their maximum and or minimum values on a certain domain. Unfortunately, as we have seen above, a general function f : D R need not have a
maximum or minimum value! But the Extreme Value Theorem gives rather mild
hypotheses on which these values are guaranteed to exist, and in fact is a useful
tool for establishing the existence of maximia / minima in other situations as well.
80
5. DIFFERENTIATION
81
Often one lumps cases (ii) and (iii) of Theorem 5.15 together under the term critical point (but there is nothing very deep going on here: its just terminology).
Clearly there are always exactly two endpoints. In favorable circustances there
will be only finitely many critical points, and in very favorable circumstances they
can be found exactly: suppose they are c1 , . . . , cn . (There may not be any critical
points, but that only makes things easier...) Suppose further that we can explicitly
compute all the values f (a), f (b), f (c1 ), . . . , f (cn ). Then we win: the largest of
these values is the maximum value, and the smallest is the minimum value.
Example: Let f (x) = x2 (x 1)(x 2) = x4 3x3 + 2x2 . Above we argued
that there is a such that |x| > = |f (x)| 1: lets find such a explicitly.
We intend nothing fancy here:
f (x) = x4 3x2 + 2x2 x4 3x3 = x3 (x 3).
So if x 4, then
x3 (x 3) 43 1 = 64 1.
On the other hand, if x < 1, then x < 0, so 3x3 > 0 and thus
f (x) x4 + 2x2 = x2 (x2 + 2) 1 3 = 3.
Thus we may take = 4.
Now let us try the procedure of Theorem 5.15 out by finding the maximum and
minimum values of f (x) = x4 3x3 + 2x2 on [4, 4].
Since f is differentiable everywhere on (4, 4), the only critical points will be the
stationary points, where f 0 (x) = 0. So we compute the derivative:
f 0 (x) = 4x3 9x2 + 4x = x(4x2 9x + 4).
The roots are x =
9 17
,
8
or, approximately,
x1 0.6094 . . . , x2 = 1.604 . . . .
f (x1 ) = 0.2017 . . . , f (x2 ) = 0.619 . . . .
Also we always test the endpoints:
f (4) = 480, f (4) = 96.
So the maximum value is 480 and the minimum value is .619 . . ..
4. The Mean Value Theorem
4.1. Statement of the Mean Value Theorem.
Our goal in this section is to prove the following important result.
Theorem 5.16. (Mean Value Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R be continuous on
[a, b] and differentiable on (a, b). Then there is at least one c with a < c < b and
f 0 (c) =
f (b) f (a)
.
ba
82
5. DIFFERENTIATION
Remark:3 I still remember the calculus test I took in high school in which I was
asked to state the Mean Value Theorem. It was a multiple choice question, and I
didnt see the choice I wanted, which was as above except with the subtly stronger
assumption that fR0 (a) and fL0 (b) exist: i.e., f is one-sided differentiable at both
endpoints. So I went up to the teachers desk to ask about this. He thought for
a moment and said, Okay, you can add that as an answer if you want, and so
as not to give special treatment to any one student, he announced to all that he
was adding a possible answer to the Mean Value Theorem question. So I marked
my added answer, did the rest of the exam, and then had time to come back to
this question. After more thought I decided that one-sided differentiability at the
endpoints was not required. So in the end I selected this pre-existing choice and
submitted my exam. As you can see, my final answer was correct. But many other
students figured that if I had successfully lobbied for an additional answer then
my answer was probably correct, so they changed their answer from the correct
answer to my added answer. They were not so thrilled with me or the teacher, but
in my opinion he behaved admirably: talk about a teachable moment!
One should certainly draw a picture to go with the Mean Value Theorem, as it
has a very simple geometric interpretation: under the hypotheses of the theorem,
there exists at least one interior point c of the interval such that the tangent line
at c is parallel to the secant line joining the endpoints of the interval.
And one should also interpret it physically: if y = f (x) gives the position of
(a)
is nothing less than the
a particle at a given time x, then the expression f (b)f
ba
average velocity between time a and time b, whereas the derivative f 0 (c) is the instantaneous velocity at time c, so that the Mean Value Theorem says that there is at
least one instant at which the instantaneous velocity is equal to the average velocity.
Example: Suppose that cameras are set up at checkpoints along an interstate
highway in Georgia. One day you receive timestamped photos of yourself at two
checkpoints. The two checkpoints are 90 miles apart and the second photo is taken
73 minutes after the first photo. You are issued a ticket for violating the speeed
limit of 70 miles per hour. Your average velocity was (90 miles) / (73 minutes)
(60 minutes) / (hour) 73.94 miles per hour. Thus, although no one saw you
violating the speed limit, they may mathematically deduce that at some point your
instantaneous velocity was over 70 mph. Guilt by the Mean Value Theorem!
4.2. Proof of the Mean Value Theorem.
We will deduce the Mean Value Theorem from the (as yet unproven) Extreme
Value Theorem. However, it is convenient to first establish a special case.
Theorem 5.17. (Rolles Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R. We suppose:
(i) f is continuous on [a, b].
(ii) f is differentiable on (a, b).
(iii) f (a) = f (b).
Then there exists c with a < c < b and f 0 (c) = 0.
Proof. By Theorem 5.13, f has a maximum M and a minimum m.
Case 1: Suppose M > f (a) = f (b). Then the maximum value does not occur
3Please excuse this personal anecdote.
83
f (b) f (a)
,
ba
and thus
f 0 (c) =
f (b) f (a)
.
ba
84
5. DIFFERENTIATION
Exercise: Which choice of g recovers the ordinary Mean Value Theorem?
The Cauchy Mean Value Theorem can be used to vindicate the head-tilting argument contemplated before the formal proof of the Mean Value Theorem. To do
so takes us a bit outside our wheelhouse (i.e., a seriously theoretical approach to
single variable calculus), but it is interesting enough to be worth sketching here.
First recall (if possible) the notion of a parameterized curve: this is given
by a function f with domain an interval I in R and codomain the plane R2 : we
may write v : t 7 (x(t), y(t)), where t 7 x(t) and y 7 y(t) are each functions
from I to R. We say that v is continuous at t if both x and y are continuous at t.
Further, when both x and y are differentiable at t we decree that v is differentiable
at t and set v 0 (t) = (x0 (t), y 0 (t)), which we think of as being a vector in the plane
with tail at the point (x(t), y(t)). When x0 (t) = y 0 (t) = 0 we get the zero vector,
which we dont want: lets call this a singular point. For any nonsingular point
(x(t), y(t)) we can define the tangent line to be the unique line passing through
the points (x(t), y(t)) and (x(t) + x0 (t), y(t) + y 0 (t)). (When x0 (t) 6= 0, we can
define the tangent line in a more familiar way, as the unique line passing through
0
(x(t), y(t)) with slope xy 0 (t)
(t) ; the above definition is phrased so as to make sense also
if x0 (t) = 0 and y 0 (t) 6= 0, in which case we get a vertical tangent line.)
Example: Let v : [0, 2] R2 by v(t) = (cos t, sin t). This point traces out a
path which winds once around the unit circle counterclockwise. We have v 0 (t) =
( sin t, cos t): since for all t, ( sin t)2 + (cos t)2 = 1, in particular v 0 (t) is never
zero: there are no singular points. At the points t = 0, , 2, x0 (t) = 0 and the
tangent line is vertical at the points (1, 0) (as you would certainly expect from
contemplation of the unit circle). When t = 0, 2 , , 3
2 , 2, one of (x(t), y(t)) and
(x0 (t), y 0 (t)) is horizontal and the other is vertical, so in particular the tangent line
at v(t) is perpendicular to v(t). This holds at all other points as well, e.g. by noting
y(t)
sin t
that the slope of the radial line from (0, 0) to v(t)) is x(t)
= cos
t and the slope of
4Dont be so impressed: we wanted a constant C such that if h(x) = f (x) Cg(x), then
h(a) = h(b), so we set f (a) Cg(a) = f (b) Cg(b) and solved for C.
5. MONOTONE FUNCTIONS
85
cos t
the tangent line to v(t) is xy 0 (t)
(t) = sin t and observing that these two slopes are
opposite reciprocals. Thus we get a derivation using calculus of a familiar (or so I
hope!) fact from elementary geometry.
Here is a version of the Mean Value Theorem for nonsingular parameterized curves.
Theorem 5.19. (Parameteric Mean Value Theorem) Let v : I R2 , t 7
(x(t), y(t)), be a nonsingular parametrized curve in the plane, i.e., for all t I,
x0 (t) and y 0 (t) both exist and are not both 0. Let a < b I, and suppose that either
x(a) 6= x(b) or y(a) 6= y(b). Then there is c (a, b) such that the tangent vector
(x0 (c), y 0 (c)) at c is parallel to the secant line from (a, f (a)) to (b, f (b)).
Proof. We apply the Cauchy Mean Value Theorem with f = x and g = y:
there is c (a, b) such that
(x(b) x(a))y 0 (c) = (y(b) y(a))x0 (c).
By assumption, x0 (c) and y 0 (c) are not both 0.
Case 1: Suppose x0 (c) 6= 0. Then we must have x(b) x(a) 6= 0: if not,
0 = (x(b) x(a))y 0 (c) = (y(b) y(a))x0 (c)
and thus, since x0 (c) 6= 0, y(b) y(a) 6= 0, and then we have x(a) = x(b) and
y(a) = y(b), contrary to our hypothesis. So we may divide to get
y(b) y(a)
y 0 (c)
=
,
x0 (c)
x(b) x(a)
which says that the tangent line to v at c has the same slope as the secant line
between (x(a), y(a)) and (x(b), y(b)), hence these two lines are parallel.
Case 2: Suppose x0 (c) = 0, i.e., the tangent line to v at c is vertical. By our
nonsingularity assumption y 0 (c) 6= 0, so
0 = (y(b) y(a))x0 (c) = (x(b) x(a))y 0 (c)
implies x(a) = x(b), so the secant line from (x(a), x(b)) to (y(a), y(b)) is vertical,
hence the two lines are parallel.
Conversely, it is possible (indeed, similar) to deduce the Cauchy Mean Value Theorem from the Parametric Mean Value Theorem: try it. Thus really we have one
theorem with two moderately different phrasings, and indeed it is common to also
refer to Theorem 5.19 as the Cauchy Mean Value Theorem.
5. Monotone Functions
A function f : I R is monotone if it is weakly increasing or weakly decreasing.
5.1. The Monotone Function Theorems.
The Mean Value Theorem has several important consequences. Foremost of all
it will be used in the proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus, but thats for
later. At the moment we can use it to establish a criterion for a function f to be
monotone on an interval in terms of sign condition on f 0 .
86
5. DIFFERENTIATION
5. MONOTONE FUNCTIONS
87
the derivative of some other function. It turns out that every continuous function
has an antiderivative: this will be proved later. (Much more subtly, there are also
some discontinuous functions which have antiderivatives...)
Corollary 5.23. Let f : I R be a function whose nth derivative f (n) is
identically zero. Then f is a polynomial function of degree at most n 1.
Proof. Exercise. (Hint: use induction.)
88
5. DIFFERENTIATION
exists b > a with f (b) < f (a), contradicting the fact that f is weakly decreasing.
(ii) = (i): Immediate from the Increasing Function Theorem and Theorem 5.24.
b) (i) = (ii): Suppose f is weakly increasing on I but not increasing on I. By
Theorem 5.24 f is still not increasing on I , so there exist a, b I with a < b
such that f (a) = f (b). Then, since f is weakly increasing, for all c [a, b] we have
f (a) f (c) f (b) = f (a), so f is constant on [a, b].
(ii) = (iii): If f is constant on [a, b], f 0 is identically zero on [a, b].
(iii) = (i): If f 0 is identically zero on some subinterval [a, b], then by the Zero
Velocity Theorem f is constant on [a, b], hence is not increasing.
The next result follows immediately.
Corollary 5.26. Let f : I R. Suppose f 0 (x) 0 for all x I, and
f 0 (x) > 0 except at a finite set of points x1 , . . . , xn . Then f is increasing on I.
Example: A typical application of Theorem 5.26 is to show that the function f :
R R by f (x) = x3 is increasing on all of R. Indeed, f 0 (x) = 3x2 which is strictly
positive at all x 6= 0 and 0 at x = 0.
5.2. The First Derivative Test.
We can use Theorem 5.24 to quickly derive another staple of freshman calculus.
Theorem 5.27. (First Derivative Test) Let I be an interval, a an interior
point of I, and f : I R a function. We suppose that f is continuous on I and
differentiable on I \ {a}. Then:
a) If there exists > 0 such that f 0 (x) is negative on (a , a) and is positive on
(a, a + ). Then f has a strict local minimum at a.
b) If there exists > 0 such that f 0 (x) is positive on (a , a) and is negative on
(a, a + ). Then f has a strict local maximum at a.
Proof. a) By the First Monotone Function Theorem, since f 0 is negative on
the open interval (a, a) and positive on the open interval (a, a+) f is decreasing
on (a , a) and increasing on (a, a + ). Moreover, since f is differentiable on its
entire domain, it is continuous at a , a and a + , and thus Theorem 5.24 applies
to show that f is decreasing on [a , a] and increasing on [a, a + ]. This gives
the desired result, since it implies that f (a) is strictly smaller than f (x) for any
x [a , a) or in (a, a + ].
b) As usual this may be proved either by revisiting the above argument or deduced
directly from the result of part a) by multiplying f by 1.
Remark: This version of the First Derivative Test is a little stronger than the
familiar one from freshman calculus in that we have not assumed that f 0 (a) = 0
nor even that f is differentiable at a. Thus for instance our version of the test
applies to f (x) = |x| to show that it has a strict local minimum at x = 0.
5.3. The Second Derivative Test.
Theorem 5.28. (Second Derivative Test) Let a be an interior point of an interval I, and let f : I R. We suppose:
(i) f is twice differentiable at a, and
(ii) f 0 (a) = 0.
Then if f 00 (a) > 0, f has a strict local minimum at a, whereas if f 00 (a) < 0, f has
a strict local maximum at a.
5. MONOTONE FUNCTIONS
89
f 0 (x)
xa
(x)
> 0 and x a > 0, so
On the other hand, suppose x (a, a + ). Then fxa
0
f (x) > 0. So f has a strict local minimum at a by the First Derivative Test.
Remark: When f 0 (a) = f 00 (a) = 0, no conclusion can be drawn about the local
behavior of f at a: it may have a local minimum at a, a local maximum at a, be
increasing at a, decreasing at a, or none of the above.
5.4. Sign analysis and graphing.
When one is graphing a function f , the features of interest include number and
approximate locations of the roots of f , regions on which f is positive or negative,
regions on which f is increasing or decreasing, and local extrema, if any. For these
considerations one wishes to do a sign analysis on both f and its derivative f 0 .
Let us agree that a sign analysis of a function g : I R is the determination of regions on which g is positive, negative and zero.
The basic strategy is to determine first the set of roots of g. As discussed before,
finding exact values of roots may be difficult or impossible even for polynomial
functions, but often it is feasible to determine at least the number of roots and
their approximate location (certainly this is possible for all polynomial functions,
although this requires justification that we do not give here). The next step is to
test a point in each region between consecutive roots to determine the sign.
This procedure comes with two implicit assumptions. Let us make them explicit.
The first is that the roots of f are sparse enough to separate the domain I into
regions. One precise formulation of of this is that f has only finitely many roots
on any bounded subset of its domain. This holds for all the elementary functions we
know and love, but certainly not for all functions, even all differentiable functions:
we have seen that things like x2 sin( x1 ) are not so well-behaved. But this is a convenient assumption and in a given situation it is usually easy to see whether it holds.
The second assumption is more subtle: it is that if a function f takes a positive value at some point a and a negative value at some other point b then it must
take the value zero somewhere in between. Of course this does not hold for all
functions: it fails very badly, for instance, for the function f which takes the value
90
5. DIFFERENTIATION
5. MONOTONE FUNCTIONS
91
R is
disat a
each
92
5. DIFFERENTIATION
f (x) f (a)
= lim+ f 0 (cx ) = lim+ f 0 (x) = L.
xa
xa
xa
93
94
5. DIFFERENTIATION
95
Proof. [S, Thm. 12.3] Parts a) through c) simply recap previous results. The
new result is part d), that f 1 : J I is continuous. By part c) and Proposition
5.37, either f and f 1 are both increasing, or f and f 1 are both decreasing. As
usual, we restrict ourselves to the first case.
Let b J. We must show that limyb f 1 (y) = f 1 (b). We may write b = f (a)
for a unique a I. Fix > 0. We want to find > 0 such that if f (a) < y <
f (a) + , then a < f 1 (y) < a + .
Take = min(f (a + ) f (a), f (a) f (a )). Then:
f (a ) f (a) , f (a) + f (a + ),
and thus if f (a) < y < f (a) + we have
f (a ) f (a) < y < f (a) + f (a + ).
Since f 1 is increasing, we get
f 1 (f (a )) < f 1 (y) < f 1 (f (a + )),
or
f 1 (b) < f 1 (y) < f 1 (b) + .
Remark: To be honest, I dont find the above proof very enlightening. After reflecting on my dissatisfaction with it, I came up with an alternate proof that I find
conceptually simpler, but which depends on the Monotone Jump Theorem, a
characterization of the possible discontinuities of a monotone function. The proof
uses the completeness of the real numbers, so is postponed to the next chapter.
6.5. Inverses of Differentiable Functions.
In this section our goal is to determine conditions under which the inverse f 1
of a differentiable funtion is differentiable, and if so to find a formula for (f 1 )0 .
Lets first think about the problem geometrically. The graph of the inverse function y = f 1 (x) is obtained from the graph of y = f (x) by interchanging x and
y, or, put more geometrically, by reflecting the graph of y = f (x) across the line
y = x. Geometrically speaking y = f (x) is differentiable at x iff its graph has
a well-defined, nonvertical tangent line at the point (x, f (x)), and if a curve has
a well-defined tangent line, then reflecting it across a line should not change this.
Thus it should be the case that if f is differentiable, so is f 1 . Well, almost. Notice
the occurrence of nonvertical above: if a curve has a vertical tangent line, then
since a vertical line has infinite slope it does not have a finite-valued derivative.
So we need to worry about the possibility that reflection through y = x carries a
nonvertical tangent line to a vertical tangent line. When does this happen? Well,
1
(x b)
the inverse function of the straight line y = mx + b is the straight line y = m
1
i.e., reflecting across y = x takes a line of slope m to a line of slope m . Morever,
it takes a horizontal line y = c to a vertical line x = c, so that is our answer: at
any point (a, b) = (a, f (a)) such that f 0 (a) = 0, then the inverse function will fail
to be differentiable at the point (b, a) = (b, f 1 (b)) because it will have a vertical
tangent. Otherwise, the slope of the tangent line of the inverse function at (b, a) is
precisely the reciprocal of the slope of the tangent line to y = f (x) at (a, b).
96
5. DIFFERENTIATION
Well, so the geometry tells us. It turns out to be quite straightforward to adapt
this geometric argument to derive the desired formula for (f 1 )0 (b), under the assumption that f is differentiable. We will do this first. Then we need to come back
and verify that indeed f 1 is differentiable at b if f 0 (f 1 (b)) exists and is nonzero:
this turns out to be a bit stickier, but we are ready for it and we will do it.
Proposition 5.41. Let f : I J be a bijective differentiable function. Suppose that the inverse function f 1 : J I is differentiable at b J. Then
1
1
is differentiable at b then f 0 (f 1 (b)) 6=
(f 1 )0 (b) = f 0 (f 1
(b)) . In particular, if f
0.
Proof. We need only implicitly differentiate the equation
f 1 (f (x)) = x,
getting
(f 1 )0 (f (x))f 0 (x) = 1,
(20)
or
1
.
f 0 (x)
To apply this to get the derivative at b J, we just need to think a little about our
variables. Let a = f 1 (b), so f (a) = b. Evaluating the last equation at x = a gives
1
1
(f 1 )0 (b) = 0
= 0 1
.
f (a)
f (f (b))
(f 1 )0 (f (x)) =
b + h = f (a + kh )
for a unique kh I. Since b + h = f (a + kh ), f 1 (b + h) = a + kh ; lets make this
substitution as well as h = f (a + kh ) f (a) in the limit we are trying to evaluate:
6
a + kh a
kh
= lim
= lim
h0 f (a + kh ) b
h0 f (a + kh ) f (a)
h0
(f 1 )0 (b) = lim
1
f (a+kh )f (a)
kh
6Unlike Spivak, we will include the subscript k to remind ourselves that this k is defined in
h
terms of h: to my taste this reminder is worth a little notational complication.
97
We are getting close: the limit now looks like the reciprocal of the derivative of f
at a. The only issue is the pesky kh , but if we can show that limh0 kh = 0, then
we may simply replace the limh0 with limkh 0 and well be done.
But kh = f 1 (b + h) a, so since f 1 is continuous by Theorem 5.40 we
have
lim kh = lim f 1 (b + h) a = f 1 (b + 0) a = f 1 (b) a = a a = 0.
h0
h0
So as h 0, kh 0 and thus
(f 1 )0 (b) =
1
limkh 0 f (a+kkhh)f (a)
1
f 0 (a)
1
f 0 (f 1 (b))
.
7.1. x .
In this section we illustrate the preceding concepts by defining and differentiat1
ing the nth root function x n . The reader should not now be surprised to hear that
we give separate consideration to the cases of odd n and even n.
Either way, let n > 1 be an integer, and consider
f : R R, x 7 xn .
Case 1: n = 2k +1 is odd. Then f 0 (x) = (2k +1)x2k = (2k +1)(xk )2 is non-negative
for all x R and not identically zero on any subinterval [a, b] with a < b, so by
Theorem 5.25 f : R R is increasing. Moreover, we have limx f (x) = .
Since f is continuous, by the Intermediate Value Theorem the image of f is all of
R. Moreover, f is everywhere differentiable and has a horizontal tangent only at
x = 0. Therefore there is an inverse function
f 1 : R R
which is everywhere continuous and differentiable at every x R except x = 0. It
1
is typical to call this function x n .
Case 2: n = 2k is even. Then f 0 (x) = (2k)x2k1 is positive when x > 0 and
negative when x < 0. Thus f is decreasing on (, 0] and increasing on [0, ). In
particular it is not injective on its domain. If we want to get an inverse function,
we need to engage in domain restriction. Unlike codomain restriction, which can
be done in exactly one way so as to result in a surjective function, domain restriction brings with it many choices. Luckily for us, this is a relatively simple case: if
D R, then the restriction of f to D will be injective if and only if for each x R,
at most one of x, x lies in D. If we want the restricted domain to be as large as
possible, we should choose the domain to include 0 and exactly one of x, x for
all x > 0. There are still lots of ways to do this, so lets try to impose another
desirable property of the domain of a function: namely, if possible we would like
it to be an interval. A little thought shows that there are two restricted domains
which meet all these requirements: we may take D = [0, ) or D = (, 0].
98
5. DIFFERENTIATION
We have
f 0 (x) = L0 (xy)(xy)0 L0 (x) =
1
y
1
1
y =
= 0.
xy
x
xy x
By the zero velocity theorem, the function f (x) is a constant (depending, a priori
on y), say Cy . Thus for all x (0, ),
L(xy) = L(x) + L(y) + Cy .
If we plug in x = 1 we get
L(y) = 0 + L(y) + Cy ,
and thus Cy = 0, so L(xy) = L(x) + L(y).
99
E 0 (x)
.
E(x)
100
5. DIFFERENTIATION
f (x)
E(x) .
f
E
In other words, if there really is a function f (x) = ex out there with f 0 (x) = ex and
f (0) = 1, then we must have ex = E(x) for all x. The point of this logical maneuver
is that although in precalculus mathematics one learns to manipulate and graph
exponential functions, the actual definition of ax for irrational x is not given, and
indeed I dont see how it can be given without using key concepts and theorems of
calculus. But, with the functions E(x) and L(x) in hand, let us develop the theory
of exponentials and logarithms to arbitrary bases.
Let a > 0 be a real number. How should we define ax ? In the following slightly
strange way: for any x R,
ax := E(L(a)x).
Let us make two comments: first, if a = e this agrees with our previous definition:
ex = E(xL(e))) = E(x). Second, the definition is motivated by the following
desirable law of exponents: (ab )c = abc . Indeed, assuming this holds unrestrictedly
for b, c R and a > 1, we would have
ax = E(x log a) = ex log a = (elog a )x = ax .
But here is the point: we do not wish to assume that the laws of exponents work
for all real numbers as they do for positive integers...we want to prove them!
Proposition 5.47. Fix a (0, ). For x R, we define
ax := E(L(a)x).
If a 6= 1, we define
L(x)
.
L(a)
a) The function ax is differentiable and (ax )0 = L(a)ax .
1
b) The function loga x is differentiable and (loga x)0 = L(a)x
.
x
c) Suppose a > 1. Then a is increasing with image (0, ), loga x is increasing
with image (, ), and ax and loga x are inverse functions.
d) For all x, y R, ax+y = ax ay .
e) For all x > 0 and y R, (ax )y = axy .
f ) For all x, y > 0, loga (xy) = loga x + loga y.
g) For all x > 0 and y R, loga (xy ) = y loga x.
loga (x) =
Proof. a) We have
(ax )0 = E(L(a)x)0 = E 0 (L(a)x)(L(a)x)0 = E(L(a)x) L(a) = L(a)ax .
b) We have
0
(loga (x)) =
L(x)
L(a)
0
=
1
.
L(a)x
101
c) Since their derivatives are always positive, ax and loga x are both increasing
functions. Moreover, since a > 1, L(a) > 0 and thus
lim ax = lim E(L(a)x) = E() = ,
L(x)
=
= .
x
x L(a)
L(a)
Thus ax : (, ) (0, ) and loga x : (0, ) (, ) are bijective and thus
have inverse functions. Thus check that they are inverses of each other, it suffices
to show that either one of the two compositions is the identity function. Now
lim loga (x) = lim
loga (ax ) =
L(E(L(a)x))
L(a)x
L(ax )
=
=
= x.
L(a)
L(a)
L(a)
d) We have
ax+y = E(L(a)(x + y)) = E(L(a)x + L(a)y) = E(L(a)x)E(L(a)y) = ax ay .
e) We have
(ax )y = E(L(ax )y) = E(L(E(L(a)x))y) = E(L(a)xy) = axy .
f) We have
loga (xy) =
L(x) + L(y)
L(x) L(y)
L(xy)
=
=
+
= loga x + loga y.
L(a)
L(a)
L(a) L(a)
g) We have
loga xy =
L(xy )
L(E(L(x)y))
L(x)y
=
=
= y loga x.
L(a)
L(a)
L(a)
Having established all this, we now feel free to write ex for E(x) and log x for L(x).
Exercise: Suppose 0 < a < 1. Show that ax is decreasing with image (0, ),
loga x is decreasing with image (0, ), and ax and loga x are inverse functions.
Exercise: Prove the change of base formula: for all a, b, c > 0 with a, c 6= 1,
logc b
loga b =
.
logc a
2
Proposition 5.48. Let f (x) = ex . Then for all n Z+ there exists a polynomial Pn (x), of degree n, such that
2
dn
f (x) = Pn (x)ex .
dxn
Proof. By induction on n.
Base case (n = 1):
2
2
d x2
= 2xex = P1 (x)ex , where P1 (x) = 2x, a degree one polynomial.
dx e
Inductive step: Assume that for some positive integer n there exists Pn (x) of degree
2
dn x2
dn+1 x2
n such that dx
= Pn (x)ex . So dx
=
ne
n+1 e
2
2
2
2
d dn x2 IH d
e =
Pn (x)ex = Pn0 (x)ex + 2xPn (x)ex = (Pn0 (x) + 2xPn (x)) ex .
n
dx dx
dx
102
5. DIFFERENTIATION
Now, since Pn (x) has degree n, Pn0 (x) has degree n 1 and 2xPn (x) has degree
n + 1. If f and g are two polynomials such that the degree of f is different from
the degree of g, then deg(f + g) = max(deg(f ), deg(g)). In particular, Pn+1 (x) :=
Pn0 (x) + 2xPn (x) has degree n + 1, completing the proof of the induction step.
7.3. Some inverse trigonometric functions.
We now wish to consider inverses of the trigonometric functions: sine, cosine, tangent, and so forth. Right away we encounter a problem similar to the case of xn for
even n: the trigonometric functions are periodic, hence certainly not injective on
their entire domain. Once again we are forced into the art of domain restriction
(as opposed to the science of codomain restriction).
Consider first f (x) = sin x. To get an inverse function, we need to restrict the
domain to some subset S on which f is injective. As usual we like intervals, and a
little thought shows that the maximal possible length of an interval on which the
sine function is injective is , attained by any interval at which the function either
increases from 1 to 1 or decreases from 1 to 1. This still gives us choices to make.
The most standard choice but to be sure, one that is not the only possible one
positive on (
2 , 2 ). We have f ([ 2 , 2 ]) = [1, 1]. The inverse function here is often called arcsin x (arcsine of x) in an attempt to distinguish it from sin1 x = csc x.
This is as good a name as any: lets go with it. We have
arcsin : [1, 1] [
, ].
2 2
As the inverse of an increasing function, arcsin x is increasing. Moreover since sin x
103
negative on (0, ) and 0 and 0 and , f (x) is decreasing on [0, ] and hence injective
there. Its image is f ([0, ])) = [1, 1]. Therefore we have an inverse function
arccos : [1, 1] [0, ].
Since cos x is continuous, so is arccos x. Since cos x is differentiable and has zero
derivative only at 0 and , arccos x is differentiable on (1, 1) and has vertical tangent lines at x = 1 and x = 1. Morever, since cos x is decreasing, so is arccos x.
We find a formula for the derivative of arccos just as for arcsin: differentiating
cos arccos x = x
gives
sin(arccos x) arccos0 x = 1,
or
1
.
sin arccos x
Again, this may be simplified. If = arccos
x, then x = cos , so if we are on the
unit circle then the y-coordinate is sin = 1 x2 , and thus
1
arccos0 x =
.
1 x2
Remark: It is hard not to notice that the derivatives of the arcsine and the arccosine
are simply negatives of each other, so for all x [0, 2 ],
arccos0 x =
arccos0 x + arcsin0 x = 0.
By the Zero Velocity Theorem, we conclude
arccos x + arcsin x = C
for some constant C. To determine C, simply evaluate at x = 0:
C = arccos 0 + arcsin 0 = + 0 = ,
2
2
and thus for all x [0, 2 ] we have
arccos x + arcsin x = .
2
So the angle whose sine is x is complementary to the angle whose cosine is x.
sin x
Finally, consider f (x) = tan x = cos
x . The domain is all real numbers for which
cos x 6= 0, so all real numbers except 2 , 3
2 , . . .. The tangent function is periodic with period and also odd, which suggests that, as with the sine function, we
should restrict this domain to the largest interval about 0 on which f is defined and
f ((
2 , 2 )) = R. Therefore we have an inverse function
arctan : R
,
.
2 2
Since the tangent function is differentiable with everywhere positive derivative, the
same is true for arctan x. In particular it is increasing but bounded: limx arctan x =
2 . In other words the arctangent has horizontal asymptotes at y = 2 .
104
5. DIFFERENTIATION
8. Some Complements
The Mean Value Theorem and its role in freshman calculus has been a popular
topic of research and debate over the years.
A short paper of W.J. Knight improves upon the Zero Velocity Theorem.
Theorem 5.49. (Right-Handed Zero Velocity Theorem [Kn80]) Let f : [a, b]
0
R be continuous. If the right-hand derivative f+
(x) exists and is 0 for all x (a, b),
then f is constant.
The proof is modelled upon the usual one: one starts with a right-handed Rolles
Theorem, deduces a right-handed Mean Value Inequality, and then Theorem 5.49.
CHAPTER 6
Completeness
1. Dedekind Completeness
1.1. Introducing (LUB) and (GLB).
Gather round, my friends: the time has come to tell what makes calculus work.
Recall that we began the course by considering the real numbers as a set endowed
with two binary operations + and together with a relation <, and satisfying a
longish list of familiar axioms (P0) through (P12), the ordered field axioms. We
then showed that using these axioms we could deduce many other familiar properties of numbers and prove many other identities and inequalities.
However we did not claim that (P0) through (P12) was a complete list of axioms
for R. On the contrary, we saw that this could not be the case: for instance the
rational numbers Q also satisfy the ordered field axioms but as we have taken
great pains to point out most of the big theorems of calculus are meaningful
but false when regarded as results applied to the system of rational numbers. So
there must be some further axiom, or property, of R which is needed to prove the
three Interval Theorems, among others.
Here it is. Among structures F satisfying the ordered field axioms, consider the
following further property:
(P14): Least Upper Bound Axiom (LUB): Let S be a nonempty subset of
F which is bounded above. Then S admits a least upper bound.
This means exactly what it sounds like, but it is so important that we had better
make sure. Recall a subset S of F is bounded above if there exists M R such
that for all x S, x M . (For future reference, a subset S of R is bounded
below if there exists m F such that for all x S, m x.) By a least upper
bound for a subset S of F , we mean an upper bound M which is less than any
other upper bound: thus, M is a least upper bound for S if M is an upper bound
for S and for any upper bound M 0 for S, M M 0 .
There is a widely used synonym for the least upper bound of S, namely the
supremum of S. We also introduce the notation lub S = sup S for the supremum
of a subset S of an ordered field (when it exists).
The following is a useful alternate characterization of sup S: the supremum of
105
106
6. COMPLETENESS
S is an upper bound M for S with the property that for any M 0 < M , M 0 is not
an upper bound for S: explicitly, for all M 0 < M , there exists x S with M 0 < x.
The definition of the least upper bound of a subset S makes sense for any set
X endowed with an order relation <. Notice that the uniqueness of the supremum
sup S is clear: we cannot have two different least upper bounds for a subset, because one of them will be larger than the other! Rather what is in question is the
existence of least upper bounds, and (LUB) is an assertion about this.
Taking the risk of introducing even more terminology, we say that an ordered field
(F, +, , <) is Dedekind complete1 if it satisfies the least upper bound axiom.
Now here is the key fact lying at the foundations of calculus and real analysis.
Theorem 6.1. a) The ordered field R is Dedekind complete.
b) Conversely, any Dedekind complete ordered field is isomorphic to R.
Part b) of Theorem 6.1 really means the following: if F is any Dedekind complete
ordered field then there is a bijection f : F R which preserves the addition,
multiplication and order structures in the following sense: for all x, y F ,
f (x + y) = f (x) + f (y),
f (xy) = f (x)f (y), and
If x < y, then f (x) < f (y).
This concept of isomorphism of structures comes from a more advanced course
abstract algebra so it is probably best to let it go for now. One may take part
b) to mean that there is essentially only one Dedekind complete ordered field: R.
The proof of Theorem 6.1 involves constructing the real numbers in a mathematically rigorous way. This is something of a production, and although in some
sense every serious student of mathematics should see a construction of R at some
point of her career, this sense is similar to the one in which every serious student
of computer science should build at least one working computer from scratch: in
practice, one can probably get away with relying on the fact that many other people
have performed this task in the past. Spivak does give a construction of R and a
proof of Theorem 6.1 in the Epilogue of his text. And indeed, if we treat this
material at all it will be at the very end of the course.
After discussing least upper bounds, it is only natural to consider the dual concept of greatest lower bounds. Again, this means exactly what it sounds like but it
is so important that we spell it out explicitly: if S is a subset of an ordered field F ,
then a greatest lower bound for S, or an infimum of S, is an element m F
which is a lower bound for S i.e., m x for all x S and is such that if m0
is any lower bound for S then m0 m. Equivalently, m = inf S iff m is a lower
bound for S and for any m0 > m there exists x S with x < m0 . Now consider:
(P140 ): Greatest Lower Bound Axiom (GLB): Let S be a nonempty subset
of F which is bounded below. Then S admits a greatest lower bound, or infimum.
1It is perhaps more common to say complete instead of Dedekind complete. I have my
reasons for preferring the lengthier terminology, but I wont trouble you with them.
1. DEDEKIND COMPLETENESS
107
108
6. COMPLETENESS
1. DEDEKIND COMPLETENESS
109
110
6. COMPLETENESS
1. DEDEKIND COMPLETENESS
111
To give a name to what we have done, we define the extended real numbers
[, ] = R {} to be the real numbers together with these two formal
symbols and . This extension is primarily order-theoretic: that is, we may
extend the relation to the extended real numbers in the obvious way:
x R, < x < .
Conversely much of the point of the extended real numbers is to give the real
numbers, as an ordered set, the pleasant properties of a closed, bounded interval
[a, b]: namely we have a largest and smallest element.
The extended real numbers [, ] are not a field. In fact, we cannot even
define the operations of + and unrestrictedly on them. However, it is useful to
define some of these operations:
x R, + x = , x + = .
x (0, ), x = , x () = .
x (, 0), x = , x () = .
= , () = , () () = .
1
1
=
= 0.
None of these definitions are really surprising, are they? If you think about it,
they correspond to facts you have learned about manipulating infinite limits, e.g.
if limxc f (x) = and limxc g(x) = 17, then limxc f (x) + g(x) = . However,
certain other operations with the extended real numbers are not defined, for similar
reasons. In particular we do not define
,
0 ,
Why not? Well, again we might think in terms of associated limits. The above are
indeterminate forms: if I tell you that limxc f (x) = and limxc g(x) = ,
then what can you tell me about limxc f (x) + g(x)? Answer: nothing, unless you
know what specific functions f and g are. As a simple example, suppose
1
1
f (x) =
+ 2011, g(x) =
.
(x c)2
(x c)2
Then limxc f (x) = , limxc g(x) = , but
lim f (x) + g(x) = lim 2011 = 2011.
xc
xc
So cannot have a universal definition independent of the chosen functions.3 In a similar way, when evaluating limits 0 is an indeterminate form:
if limxc f (x) = 0 and limxc g(x) = , then limxc f (x)g(x) depends on how
fast f approaches zero compared to how fast g approaches infinity. Again, consider
2011
112
6. COMPLETENESS
X n;
n=0
in other words, every element of X is a subset of X n for some n (this is precisely the
Archimedean property). Applying Proposition 6.7, we get that for every nonempty
subset X of R,
sup X 0 sup X 1 sup X 2 . . . sup X n . . . .
Suppose moreover that X is bounded above. Then some N Z+ is an upper
bound for X, i.e., X = X N = X N +1 = . . ., so the sequence sup X n is eventually
constant, and in particular limn sup X n = sup X. On the other hand, if X
is bounded above, then the sequence sup X n is not eventually constant; in fact it
takes increasingly large values, and thus
lim sup X n = .
Thus if we take as our definition for sup X, limn sup X n , then for X which is
unbounded above, we get sup X = limn sup X n = . By reflection, a similar
discussion holds for inf X.
113
There is, however, one last piece of business to attend to: we said we wanted
sup S and inf S to be defined for all subsets of R: what if S = ? There is an
answer for this as well, but many people find it confusing and counterintuitive at
first, so let me approach it again using Proposition 6.7. For each n Z, consider
the set Pn = {n}: i.e., Pn has a single element, the integer n. Certainly then
inf Pn = sup Pn = n. So what? Well, I claim we can use these sets Pn along with
Proposition 6.7 to see what inf and sup should be. Namely, to define these
quantities in such a way as to obey Proposition 6.7, then for all n Z, because
{n}, we must have
sup sup{n} = n
and
inf inf{n} = n.
There is exactly one extended real number which is less than or equal to every
integer: . Similarly, there is exactly one extended real number which is greater
than or equal to every integer: . Therefore the inexorable conclusion is
sup = , inf = .
Other reasonable thought leads to this conclusion: for instance, in class I had a lot
of success with the pushing conception of suprema and infima. Namely, if your
set S is bounded above, then you start out to the right of every element of your
set i.e., at some upper bound of S and keep pushing to the left until you cant
push any farther without passing by some element of S. What happens if you try
this with ? Well, every real number is an upper bound for , so start anywhere
and push to the left: you can keep pushing as far as you want, because you will
never hit an element of the set. Thus you can push all the way to , so to speak.
Similarly for infima, by reflection.
2. Intervals and the Intermediate Value Theorem
2.1. Convex subsets of R.
We say that a subset S of R is convex if for all x < y S, the entire interval
[x, y] lies in S. In other words, a convex set is one that whenever two points are in
it, all in between points are also in it.
Example 2.1: The empty set is convex. For any x R, the singleton set {x} is
convex. In both cases the definition applies vacuously: until we have two distinct
points of S, there is nothing to check!
Example 2.2: We claim any interval is convex. This is immediate or it would
be, if we didnt have so many different kinds of intervals to write down and check.
One needs to see that the definition applies to invervals of all of the following forms:
(a, b), [a, b), (a, b], [a, b], (, b), (, b], (a, ), [a, ), (, ).
All these verifications are trivial appeals to things like the transitivity of and .
Are there any nonempty convex sets other than intervals? (Just to be sure, we
114
6. COMPLETENESS
count {x} = [x, x] as an interval.4) A little thought suggests that the answer should
be no. But more thought shows that if so we had better use the Dedekind completeness of R, because if we work over Q with all of the corresponding definitions
then there are nonempty convex sets which are not intervals, e.g.
S = {x Q | x2 < 2}.
This
Q by R we would get an interval, namely
has
a familiar theme: replacing
( 2, 2), but once again 2 6 Q. When one looks carefully at the definitions
it is no trouble to check that working solely in the rational numbers S is a convex
set but is not an interval.
Remark: Perhaps the above example seems legalistic, or maybe even a little silly.
It really isnt: one may surmise that contemplation of such examples led Dedekind
to his construction of the real numbers via Dedekind cuts. This construction
may be discussed at the end of this course. Most contemporary analysts prefer
a rival construction of R due to Cauchy using Cauchy sequences. I agree that
Cauchys construction is simpler. However, both are important in later mathematics: Cauchys construction works in the context of a general metric space (and,
with certain modifications, in a general uniform space) to construct an associated complete space. Dedekinds construction works in the context of a general
linearly ordered set to construct an associated Dedekind-complete ordered set.
Theorem 6.8. Every nonempty convex subset D of R is an interval.
Proof. We are given a nonempty convex subset D of R and we want to show
it is an interval, but as above an interval can have any one of nine basic shapes. It
may be quite tedious to argue that one of nine things must occur!
So we just need to set things up a bit carefully: here goes: let a [, ) be
the infimum of D, and let b (, ] be the supremum of D. Let I = (a, b), and
let I be the closure of I, i.e., if a is finite, we include a; if b is finite, we include b.
Step 1: We claim that I D I. Let x I.
Case 1: Suppose I = (a, b) with a, b R. Let z (a, b). Then, since z > a =
inf D, there exists c D with c < z. Similarly, since z < b = sup D, then there
exists d D with z < d. Since D is convex, z D. Now suppose z D. We must
have inf D = a z b = sup D.
Case 2: Suppose I = (, b), and let z I. Since D is unbounded below,
there exists a D with a < z. Moreover, since z < sup D, there exists b D such
that z < b. Since D is convex, z D. Next, let z D. We wish to show that
z I = (, b]; in other words, we want z b. But since z D and b = sup D,
this is immediate. Thus I D I.
Case 3: Suppose I = (a, ). This is similar to Case 2 and is left to the reader.
Case 4: Suppose I = (, ) = R. Let z R. Since D is unbounded below,
there exists a D with a < z, and since D is unbounded above there exists b D
with z < b. Since D is convex, z D. Thus I = D = I = R.
Step 2: We claim that any subset D which contains I and is contained in I is an
interval. Indeed I and I are both intervals, and the only case in which there is any
subset D strictly in between them is I = (a, b) with a, b R in this case D could
also be [a, b) or (a, b], and both are intervals.
4However, we do not wish to say whether the empty set is an interval. Throughout these
notes the reader may notice minor linguistic contortions to ensure that this issue never arises.
115
116
6. COMPLETENESS
f (c) = L. If f (a) = f (b) there is nothing to show. If f (a) > f (b), then we may
replace f by f (this is still a continuous function), so it is enough to treat the case
f (a) < L < f (b). Now consider the function g(x) = f (x)L. Since f is continuous,
so is g; moreover g(a) = f (a) L < 0 and g(b) = f (b) L > 0. Therefore by Step
1 there exists c (a, b) such that 0 = g(c) = f (c) L, i.e., such that f (c) = L.
Step 3: By Step 2 and Theorem 6.9, f (I) is an interval.
Remark: Theorem 6.10 is in fact a mild improvement of the Intermediate Value
Theorem we stated earlier in these notes. This version of IVT applies to continuous
functions with domain any interval, not just an interval of the form [a, b], and
includes a result that we previously called the Interval Image Theorem.
2.3. The Intermediate Value Theorem Implies Dedekind Completeness.
Theorem 6.11. Let F be an ordered field such that every continuous function
f : F F satisfies the Intermediate Value Property. Then F is Dedekind complete.
Proof. We will prove the contrapositive: suppose F is not Dedekind complete,
and let S F be nonempty and bounded above but without a least upper bound
in F . Let U(S) be the set of upper bounds of S. We define f : F F by:
f (x) = 1, if x
/ U(S),
f (x) = 1, x U(S).
Then f is continuous on F indeed, a point of discontinuity would occur only at
the least upper bound of S, which is assumed not to exist. Moreover f takes the
value 1 at any element s S, which cannot be an upper bound for S because
then it would be the maximum element of S and the value 1 at any upper bound
for S (we have assumed that S is bounded above so such elements exist), but it
never takes the value zero, so f does not satisfy IVP.
Exercise 2.3: Show in detail that the function f : F F constructed in the proof
of Theorem 6.11 is continuous at every element of F .
3. The Monotone Jump Theorem
Theorem 6.12. (Monotone Jump) Let f : I R be weakly increasing.
a) Let c be an interior point of I. Then limxc f (x) and limxc+ f (x) exist, and
lim f (x) f (c) lim f (x).
xc
xc+
b) Suppose I has a left endpoint a. Then limxa+ f (x) exists and is at least f (a).
c) Suppose I has a right endpoint b. Then limxb f (x) exists and is at most f (c).
Proof. a) Step 0: As usual, we may f is weakly increasing. We define
L = {f (x) | x I, x < c}, R = {f (x) | x I, x > c}.
Since f is weakly increasing, L is bounded above by f (c) and U is bounded below
by f (c). Therefore we may define
l = sup L, r = inf R.
Step 1: For all x < c, f (x) f (c), f (c) is an upper bound for L, so l f (c). For
all c < x, f (c) f (x), so f (c) is a lower bound for R, so f (c) r. Thus
(22)
l f (c) r.
4. REAL INDUCTION
117
Step 2: We claim limxc f (x) = l. To see this, let > 0. Since l is the least upper
bound of L and l < l, l is not an upper bound for L: there exists x0 < c
such that f (x0 ) > l . Since f is weakly increasing, for all x0 < x < c we have
l < f (x0 ) f (x) l < l + .
Thus we may take = c x0 .
Step 3: We claim limxc+ f (x) = r: this is shown as above and is left to the reader.
Step 4: Substituting the results of Steps 2 and 3 into (22) gives the desired result.
b) and c): The arguments at an endpoint are routine modifications of those of part
a) above and are left to the reader as an opportunity to check her understanding.
Theorem 6.13. For a monotone function f : I R, TFAE:
(i) f (I) is an interval.
(ii) f is continuous.
Proof. As usual, it is no loss of generality to assume f is weakly increasing.
(i) = (ii): If f is not continuous on all of I, then by the Monotone Jump
Theorem f (I) fails to be convex. In more detail: suppose f is discontinuous at c.
If c is an interior point then either limxc f (x) < f (c) or f (c) < limxc+ f (x).
In the former case, choose any b I, b < c. Then f (I) contains f (b) < f (c) but
not the in-between point limxc f (x). In the latter case, choose any d I, c < d.
Then f (I) contains f (c) < f (d) but not the in-between point limxc+ f (x). Similar
arguments hold if c is the left or right endpoint of I: these are left to the reader.
Thus in all cases f (I) is not convex hence is not an interval.
(ii) = (i): This follows immediately from Theorem 6.10.
With Theorems 6.10 and 6.13 in hand, we get an especially snappy proof of the
Continuous Inverse Function Theorem. Let f : I R be continuous and injective.
By Theorem 6.10, f (I) = J is an interval. Moreover f : I J is a bijection, with
inverse function f 1 : J I. Since f is monotone, so is f 1 . Moreover f 1 (J) = I
is an interval, so by Theorem 6.13, f 1 is continuous!
4. Real Induction
Theorem 6.14. (Principle of Real Induction) Let a < b be real numbers, let
S [a, b], and suppose:
(RI1) a S,
(RI2) for all x S, if x 6= b there exists y > x such that [x, y] S.
(RI3) For all x R, if [a, x) S, then x S.
Then S = [a, b].
Proof. Seeking a contradiction we suppose not: S 0 = [a, b] \ S is nonempty.
It is bounded below by a, so has a (finite!) greatest lower bound inf S 0 . However:
Case 1: inf S 0 = a. Then by (RI1), a S, so by (RI2), there exists y > a such that
[a, y] S, and thus y is a greater lower bound for S 0 then a = inf S 0 : contradiction.
Case 2: a < inf S 0 S. If inf S 0 = b, then S = [a, b]. Otherwise, by (RI2) there
exists y > inf S 0 such that [inf S 0 , y 0 ] S, contradicting the definition of inf S 0 .
Case 3: a < inf S 0 S 0 . Then [a, inf S 0 ) S, so by (RI3) inf S 0 S: contradiction!
Example 4.1: Let us reprove the Intermediate Value Theorem. Recall that the key
special case of IVT, from which the full theorem easily follows, is this: if f : [a, b]
118
6. COMPLETENESS
R is continuous, f (a) < 0 and f (b) > 0, then there exists c (a, b) with f (c) = 0.
We prove this by real induction, as follows. Let S = {x [a, b] | f (x) 0}. We
know that S is proper in [a, b], so applying real induction shows that one of (RI1),
(RI2) and (RI3) must fail. We have a S so (RI1) holds and if a continuous
function is non-negative on [a, c), then it is also non-negative at c: (RI3). So (RI2)
must fail: there exists y (a, b] such that f (y) 0 but there is no > 0 such that
f is non-negative on [y, y + ). This implies f (y) = 0.
Example 4.1, redux: In class I handled the proof of IVT by Real Induction differently, and in a way which I think gives a better first example of the method (most
Real Induction proofs are not by contradiction). This strategy follows [Ka07].
Namely, IVT is equivalent to: let f : [a, b] R be continuous and nowhere zero. If
f (a) > 0, then f (b) > 0. We prove this by Real Induction. Let
S = {x [a, b] | f (x) > 0}.
Then f (b) > 0 iff b S. We will show S = [a, b] by real induction, which suffices.
(RI1) By hypothesis, f (a) > 0, so a S.
(RI2) Let x S, x < b, so f (x) > 0. Since f is continuous at x, there exists > 0
such that f is positive on [x, x + ], and thus [x, x + ] S.
(RI3) Let x (a, b] be such that [a, x) S, i.e., f is positive on [a, x). We claim
that f (x) > 0. Indeed, since f (x) 6= 0, the only other possibility is f (x) < 0,
but if so, then by continuity there would exist > 0 such that f is negative on
[x, x], i.e., f is both positive and negative at each point of [x, x]: contradiction!
The following result shows that Real Induction does not only uses the Dedekind
completeness of R but actually carries the full force of it.
Theorem 6.15. In an ordered field F , the following are equivalent:
(i) F is Dedekind complete: every nonempty bounded above subset has a supremum.
(ii) F satisfies the Principle of Real Induction: for all a < b F , a subset S [a, b]
satisfying (RI1) through (RI3) above must be all of [a, b].
Proof. (i) = (ii): This is simply a restatement of Theorem 6.14.
(ii) = (i): Let T F be nonempty and bounded below by a F . We will show
that T has an infimum. For this, let S be the set of lower bounds m of T with
a m. Let b be any element of T . Then S [a, b].
Step 1: Observe that b S b = inf T . In general the infimum could be
smaller, so our strategy is not exactly to use real induction to prove S = [a, b].
Nevertheless we claim that S satisfies (RI1) and (RI3).
(RI1): Since a is a lower bound of T with a a, we have a S.
(RI3): Suppose x (a, b] and [a, x) S, so every y [a, x) is a lower bound for T .
Then x is a lower bound for T : if not, there exists t T such that t < x; taking
any y (t, x), we get that y is not a lower bound for T either, a contradiction.
Step 2: Since F satisfies the Principle of Real Induction, by Step 1 S = [a, b] iff S
satisfies (RI2). If S = [a, b], then the element b is a lower bound for T , so it must
be the infimum of T . Now suppose that S 6= [a, b], so by Step 1 S does not satisfy
(RI2): there exists x S, x < b such that for any y > x, there exists z (x, y) such
that z
/ S, i.e., z is not a lower bound for T . In other words x is a lower bound
for T and no element larger than x is a lower bound for T ...so x = inf T .
119
Remark: Like Dedekind completeness, Real Induction depends only on the ordering relation < and not on the field operations + and . In fact, given any ordered
set (F, <) i.e., we need not have operations + or at all it makes sense to speak
of Dedekind completeness and also of whether an analogue of Real Induction holds.
In [Cl11], I proved that Theorem 6.15 holds in this general context: an ordered set
F is Dedekind complete iff the only it satisfies a Principle of Ordered Induction.
5. The Extreme Value Theorem
Theorem 6.16. (Extreme Value Theorem)
Let f : [a, b] R be continuous. Then:
a) f is bounded.
b) f attains a minimum and maximum value.
Proof. a) Let S = {x [a, b] | f : [a, x] R is bounded}.
(RI1): Evidently a S.
(RI2): Suppose x S, so that f is bounded on [a, x]. But then f is continuous
at x, so is bounded near x: for instance, there exists > 0 such that for all
y [x , x + ], |f (y)| |f (x)| + 1. So f is bounded on [a, x] and also on [x, x + ]
and thus on [a, x + ].
(RI3): Suppose that x (a, b] and [a, x) S. Now beware: this does not say that
f is bounded on [a, x): rather it says that for all a y < x, f is bounded on [a, y].
1
is bounded on [0, y]
These are really different statements: for instance, f (x) = x2
for all y < 2 but it is not bounded on [0, 2). But, as usual, the key feature of this
counterexample is a lack of continuity: this f is not continuous at 2. Having said
this, it becomes clear that we can proceed almost exactly as we did above: since f
is continuous at x, there exists 0 < < x a such that f is bounded on [x , x].
But since a < x < x we know also that f is bounded on [a, x ], so f is
bounded on [a, x].
b) Let m = inf f ([a, b]) and M = sup f ([a, b]). By part a) we have
< m M < .
We want to show that there exist xm , xM [a, b] such that f (xm ) = m, f (xM ) = M ,
i.e., that the infimum and supremum are actually attained as values of f . Suppose
that there does not exist x [a, b] with f (x) = m: then f (x) > m for all x [a, b]
1
and the function gm : [a, b] R by gm (x) = f (x)m
is defined and continuous. By
the result of part a), gm is bounded, but this is absurd: by definition of the infimum,
f (x) m takes values less than n1 for any n Z+ and thus gm takes values greater
than n for any n Z+ and is accordingly unbounded. So indeed there must exist
xm [a, b] such that f (xm ) = m. Similarly, assuming that f (x) < M for all x
1
[a, b] gives rise to an unbounded continuous function gM : [a, b] R, x 7 M f
(x) ,
contradicting part a). So there exists xM [a, b] with f (xM ) = M .
6. The Heine-Borel Theorem
Let S R, and let {XiS
}iI be a family of subsets of R. We say that the family
{Xi } covers S if S iI Xi : in words, this simply means that every element
x S is also an element of Xi for at least one i.
Theorem 6.17. (Heine-Borel) Let {Ui }iI be any covering of the closed,
bounded interval by open intervals Ui . Then the covering {Ui }iI has a finite
120
6. COMPLETENESS
subcovering: there is a finite subset J I such that every x [a, b] lies in Uj for
some j J.
Proof. For an open covering U = {Ui }iI of [a, b], let
S = {x [a, b] | U [a, x] has a finite subcovering}.
We prove S = [a, b] by Real Induction. (RI1) is clear. (RI2): If U1 , . . . , Un covers
[a, x], then some Ui contains [x, x + ] for some > 0. (RI3): if [a, x) S, let ix I
be such that x Uix , and let
S > 0 be such that [x , x] Uix . Since x S,
there is a finite J I with iJ Ui [a, x ], so {Ui }iJ Uix covers [a, x].
Exercise: The formulation of the Heine-Borel Theorem given above is superficially
weaker than the standard one. A subset of R is called open if it is a union of open
intervals. In the usual statement of the Heine-Borel Theorem the Ui s are allowed
to be arbitrary open subsets of R. Show that this apparently more general version
can be deduced from Theorem 6.17. (Suggestion: for each x [a, b], there is an
open subset Ux containing x. By definition of open subset, Ux must contain some
open interval Ix containing x. Apply Theorem 6.17 to the open covering {Ix }.)
7. Uniform Continuity
7.1. The Definition; Key Examples.
noindent Let I be an interval and f : I R. Then f is uniformly continuous on I if for every > 0, there exists a > 0 such that for all x1 , x2 I, if
|x1 x2 | < then |f (x1 ) f (x2 )| < .
In order to show what the difference is between uniform continuty on I and mere
continuity on I i.e., continuity at every point of I let us rephrase the standard
- definition of continuity using the notation above. Namely:
A function f : I R is continuous on I if for every > 0 and every x1 I, there
exists > 0 such that for all x2 I, if |x1 x2 | < then |f (x1 ) f (x2 )| < .
These two definitions are eerily (and lets admit it: confusingly, at first) similar:
they use all the same words and symbols. The only difference is in the ordering
of the quantifiers: in the definition of continuity, player two gets to hear the value
of and also the value of x1 before choosing her value of . In the definition of
uniform continuity, player two only gets to hear the value of : thus, her choice of
must work simultaneously or, in the lingo of this subject, uniformly across
all values of x1 I. Thats the only difference. Of course, switching the order of
quantifiers in general makes a big diffference in the meaning and truth of mathematical statements, and this is no exception. Lets look at some simple examples.
Example 6.1: Let f : R R by f (x) = mx + b, m 6= 0. We claim that f is
uniformly continuous on R. In fact the argument that we gave for continuity
. Although we used
long ago shows this, because for every > 0 we took = |m|
this to show that f is continuous at some arbitrary point c R, evidently the
choice of does not depend on the point c: it works uniformly across all values of
c. Thus f is uniformly continuous on R.
7. UNIFORM CONTINUITY
121
Example 6.2: Let f : R R by f (x) = x2 . This time I claim that our usual
proof did not show uniform continuity. Lets see it in action. To show that f is
continuous at c, we factored x2 c into (x c)(x + c) and saw that to get some
control on the other factor x + c we needed to restrict x to some bounded interval
around c, say [c 1, c + 1]. On this interval |x + c| |x| + |c| |c| + 1 + |c| 2|c| + 1.
) we found that if |x c| < then
So by taking = min(1, 2|c|+1
|f (x) f (c)| = |x c||x + c|
(2|c| + 1) = .
2|c| + 1
122
6. COMPLETENESS
123
Example: More generally, let S be a subset such that for all M > 0, S [M, M ]
is finite. Then S has no limit points.
Theorem 6.21. (Bolzano-Weierstrass)
Every infinite subset A of [a, b] has a limit point.
Proof. Let A [a, b], and let S be the set of x in [a, b] such that if A [a, x]
is infinite, it has a limit point. It suffices to show S = [a, b], which we will do by
Real Induction. (RI1) is clear. (RI2) Suppose x [a, b) S. If A [a, x] is infinite,
then it has a limit point and hence so does A [a, b]: thus S = [a, b]. If for some
> 0, A [a, x + ] is finite, then [x, x + ] S. Otherwise A [a, x] is finite but
A [a, x + ] is infinite for all > 0, and then x is a limit point for A and S = [a, b]
as above. (RI3) If [a, x) S, then: either A [a, y] is infinite for some y < x, so
x S; or A [a, x] is finite, so x S; or A [a, y] is finite for all y < x and A [a, x]
is infinite, so x is a limit point of A [a, x] and x S.
Remark: Later we will give a sequential version of Bolzano-Weierstrass and see
that it is equivalent to Theorem 6.21 above.
9. Tarskis Fixed Point Theorem
Mainly as a further showpiece for Real Induction, we give here a special case of
a theorem of the great logician A. Tarski [Ta55]. It is a fixed point theorem:
that is, a theorem which gives conditions on a function f : X X for there to
be a point c X with f (c) = c. Fixed point theorems are ubiquitously useful
throughout mathematics, and further fixed point theorems for functions defined on
subintervals of R will be given when we study infinite sequences later on. However
Tarskis theorem has a quite different flavor from the fixed point theorems to come
in that the function f is not assumed to be continuous!
Theorem 6.22. (Tarski Fixed Point Theorem) Let f : [a, b] [a, b] be a weakly
increasing function. Then f has a fixed point: there is c [a, b] with f (c) = c.
Proof. Seeking a contradiction we suppose f has no fixed point. Let S =
{x [a, b] | f (x) > x}. We will show S = [a, b] by Real Induction. But then b S,
so f (b) > b, contradicting the fact that b is the largest element of [a, b]!
(RI1) Since a = min[a, b], f (a) a; since there is no fixed point, f (a) > a.
(RI2) Let x [a, b) and suppose [a, x] S. Put y = f (x), so y > x by definition
of S. We claim [x, y] S. If not, there is x z y with f (z) < z y; but since
x z, y = f (x) f (z) and we get y f (z) < z y, a contradiction.
(RI3) Let x (a, b] and suppose [a, x) S. We claim x S. If not, y = f (x) < x,
so y S and thus f (y) > y = f (x); but since y < x, f (y) f (x).
Exercise: a) Give another (more standard) proof of Theorem 6.22 by showing that
sup{x [a, b] | f (x) x} is a fixed point of f .
b) Which argument do you prefer?
Exercise: Find an application of Theorem 6.22 to calculus.
I am indebted to J. Propp for alerting me to this application of Real Induction.
CHAPTER 7
Differential Miscellany
1. LH
opitals Rule
We have come to the calculus topic most hated by calculus instructors: LHopitals
.
Rule. This result gives a criterion for evaluating indeterminate forms 00 or
The following succinct formulation is taken from [R, Thm. 5.13], as is the proof.
Theorem 7.1. Let a < b . Let f, g : (a, b) R be differentiable.
a) We suppose that
f 0 (x)
lim 0
= A [, ]
xb g (x)
and also that either
(i) limxb f (x) = limxb g(x) = 0, or
(ii) limxb g(x) = .
(x)
Then limxb fg(x)
= A.
b) The analogous statements with limxb replaced everywhere by limxa+ hold.
Proof. a) Step 1: Suppose that A < , let be any real number which is
greater than A, and let be such that A < < . We will show that there exists
(x)
c (a, b) such that for all x > c, fg(x)
< .
0
(x)
(x)
A < , there is c (a, b) such that for all x > c, fg0 (x)
< .
First, since fg0 (x)
Let c < x < y < b. By Cauchys Mean Value Theorem, there is t (x, y) such that
(23)
f (x) f (y)
f 0 (t)
= 0
<
g(x) g(y)
g (t)
(y)
Suppose first that (i) holds. Then by letting x approach b in (23) we get fg(y)
< for all c < y < b, which is what we wanted to show.
Next suppose that (ii) holds. Fix y in (23) and choose c1 (y, b) such that c1 <
x < b implies g(x) > g(y) and g(x) > 0. Multiplying (23) by g(x)g(y)
gives
g(x)
f (x) f (y)
g(x) g(y)
<
,
g(x)
g(x)
f (x)
g(y) f (y)
<
+
.
g(x)
g(x) g(x)
(x)
Letting x approach b, we find: there is c (c1 , b) such that for all x > c, fg(x)
< .
Step 2: Suppose A > . Then arguing in a very similar manner as in Step 1
we may show that for any < A there exists c (a, b) such that for all x > c,
125
126
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
f (x)
g(x)
f (x)
g(x)
= A.
Remark: Perhaps you were expecting the additional hypothesis limxb f (x) =
in condition (ii). As the proof shows, this is not necessary. But it seems to be
very risky to present the result to freshman calculus students in this form!
n
Example 7.1: We claim that for all n Z+ , limx xex = 0. We show this by
induction on n. First we do n = 1: limx exx = 0. Since limx g(x) = 0
and limx
f 0 (x)
g 0 (x)
= limx
1
ex
n
limx exx = 0. Induction Step: let n Z+ and suppose limx xex = 0. Then
n
n+1
LH
(n+1)xn
= (n + 1) limx xex = (n + 1) 0 = 0.
limx x ex =
= limx
ex
Why do calculus instructors not like LHopitals Rule? Oh, let us count the ways!
(x)
is of the form 00 . Thus many calcu1) Every derivative f 0 (x) = limh0 f (x+h)f
h
lus students switch to applying LHopitals Rule instead of evaluating derivatives
from the definition. This can lead to painfully circular reasoning. For instance,
what is limx0 sinx x ? Well, both numerator and denominator approach 0 and
0
limx0 (sinx0x) = limx0 cos1 x = cos 0 = 1. Whats wrong with this? Well, how
do we know that (sin x)0 = cos x? Thinking back, we reduced this to computing
the derivative of sin x at x = 0, i.e., to showing that limx0 sinx x = 1!
2) Many limits which can be evaluated using LHopitals Rule can also be evaluated in many other ways, and often just by thinking a bit about how functions
actually behave. For intance, try to evaluate the limit of Example 7.1 above without
using LH
opital. There are any number of ways. For instance:
Lemma 7.2. (Racetrack Principle) Let f, g : [a, ) R be two differentiable
functions such that f 0 (x) g 0 (x) for all x a. Then:
a) We have f (x) f (a) g(x) g(a) for all x a.
b) If f 0 (x) > g 0 (x) for all x > a, then f (x) f (a) > g(x) g(a) for all x > a.
Proof. Put h = f g : [a, ) R.
a) Then h0 (x) 0 for all x a, so h is weakly increasing on (a, ), and thus being
continuous, weakly increasing on [a, ): for all x a, f (x) g(x) = h(x) h(a) =
f (a) g(a), and thus f (x) f (a) g(x) g(a).
b) This is the same as part a) with all instances of replaced by >: details may
be safely left to the reader.
Proposition 7.3. Let f : [a, ) R be twice differentiable such that:
(i) f 0 (a) > 0 and
(ii) f 00 (x) 0 for all x a.
Then limx f (x) = .
Proof. Let g be the tangent line to f at x = a, viewed as a function from
[a, ) to R. Because f 00 = (f 0 )0 is non-negative on [a, ), f 0 is weakly increasing
1In fact, [R] states and proves the result with lim
xa+ instead of limxb . I recast it this
way since a natural class of examples concerns limx .
1. LHOPITALS
RULE
127
x
(i) Let fn (x) = xen . One can therefore establish limx xen = by showing that
fn0 (x), fn00 (x) are both positive for sufficiently large x. It is easy to see that fn0 (x) > 0
for all x > n. The analysis for fn00 is a bit messier; we leave it to the reader and try
something slightly different instead.
(ii) Since fn0 (x) > 0 for all x > n, f is eventually increasing and thus tends either
to a positive limit A or to +. But as x , x + 1 , so
ex+1
ex
= e lim
= eA.
n
x (x + 1)
x (x + 1)n
A = lim
3) The statement of LH
opitals Rule is complicated and easy for even relatively
proficient practitioners of the mathematical craft to misremember or misapply. A
classic rookie mistake is to forget to verify condition (i) or (ii): of course in general
f 0 (x)
f (x)
6= lim 0
;
xa g (x)
xa g(x)
lim
try a random example. But there are subtler pitfalls as well. For instance, even
0
(x)
(x)
under conditions (i) and (ii), limxa fg(x)
= A need not imply that limxa fg0 (x)
exists, so you cannot use LHopitals Rule to show that a limit does not exist.
Example 7.2: Let f, g : R R by f (x) = x2 sin( x1 ) and f (0) = 0 and g(x) = x.
Then f and g are both differentiable (for f this involves going back to the limit
definition of the derivative at x = 0 we have seen this example before), and
(x)
limx0 fg(x)
= limx0 x sin( x1 ) = 0. However,
f 0 (x)
1
1
1
lim
= lim 2x sin
cos
= lim cos
,
x0 g 0 (x)
x0
x0
x
x
x
128
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
f (xn )
f 0 (xn )
xn+1 = xn
f (xn )
.
f 0 (xn )
or
(25)
Note that our expression for xn+1 is undefined if f 0 (xn ) = 0, as well it should be:
if the tangent line at xn is horizontal, then either it coincides with the x-axis (in
which case xn is already a root of f and no amelioration is needed) or it is parallel
2. NEWTONS METHOD
129
to the x-axis, in which case the method breaks down: in a sense we will soon make
precise, this means that xn is too far away from the true root c of f .
2.2. A Babylonian Algorithm.
We can use Newtons method to approximate 2. Consider f (x) = x2 2; straightforward calculus tells us that there is a unique positive number c such that f (c) = 2
and that for instance c [1, 2]. We compute the amelioration formula in this case:
2x2 (x2n 2)
x2 + 2
1
2
x2 2
= n
= n
=
xn +
.
(26)
xn+1 = xn n
2xn
2xn
2xn
2
xn
In other words, to get from xn to xn+1 we take the average of xn and
2
xn .
If I now ask my laptop computer to directly compute 2, then it tells me2 that
2 = 1.414213562373095048801688724 . . . .
Thus x5 is accurate to 11 decimal places and x6 is accurate to 23 decimal places.
Looking more carefully, it seems that each iteration of the amelioration process
xn 7 xn+1 roughly doubles the number of decimal places of accuracy. If this holds
true, it means
that the approximations get close to the true root very fast it we
130
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
application
of which with x1 = 1 leads to fantastically good numerical approxima
tions to a. If you ever find yourself on a desert island and needing to compute a
to many decimal placees as part of your engineering research to build a raft that will
carry you back to civilization, then this is probably the method you should use.
And now if anyone asks you whether honors calculus contains any practically
useful information, you must tell them that the answer is yes!
2.3. Questioning Newtons Method.
Of course we havent proven anything yet. Here are two natural questions:
Question 7.4. Let f : I R be differentiable, and let c I be such that
f (c) = 0.
a) Is there some subinterval (c , c + ) about the true root c such that starting
Newtons method with any x1 (c , c + ) guarantees that the sequence of approximations {xn } gets arbitrarily close to c?
b) Assuming the answer to part a) is yes, given some x1 (c , c + ) can we give
a quantitative estimate on how close xn is to c as a function of n?
Questions like these are explored in a branch of mathematics called numerical
analysis. Most theoretical mathematicians (e.g. me) know little about it, which
is a shame because the questions its treats are fundamental and closely related to
pure mathematics. (As well as being useful in applications, of course.)
2.4. Introducing Infinite Sequences.
We will give some answers to these questions. First, the business of the xn s getting
arbitrarily close to c should be construed in terms of a limiting process, but one of
a kind which is slightly different and in fact simpler than the limit of a real-valued
function at a point. Namely, a real infinite sequence xn is simply an ordered list
of real numbers x1 , x2 , . . . , xn , . . ., or slightly more formally, is given by a function
from the positive integers Z+ to R, say f (n) = xn . If L R, we say the infinite
sequence {xn } converges to L and write xn L if for all > 0 there exists
N Z+ such that for all n N , |xn L| < . This is precisely the definition
of limx f (x) = L except that our function f is no longer defined for all (or all
sufficiently large) real numbers but only at positive integers. So it is a very close
cousin of the types of limit operations we have already studied.
Here is one very convenient property of limits of sequences.
Proposition 7.5. Let {xn }
n=1 be a sequence of real numbers, and let f : R
R be a continuous function. Suppose that xn L. Then f (xn ) f (L).
Proof. Fix > 0. Since f is continuous at L, there exists > 0 such that
|x L| < = |f (x) f (L)| < . Moreover, since xn L, there exists a positive
integer N such that for all n N , |xn L| < . Putting these together: if n N
then |xn L| < , so |f (xn ) f (L)| < . This shows that f (xn ) L.
Remark: a) Proposition 7.5 is a close cousin of the fact that compositions are continuous functions are continuous, and in particular the proof is almost the same.
b) At the moment we are just getting a taste of infinite sequences. Later in the
course we will study them more seriously and show that Proposition 7.5 has a very
2. NEWTONS METHOD
131
132
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
2. NEWTONS METHOD
133
f (xn )
.
f 0 (xn )
f (x)
.
f 0 (x)
Now we have to check that our setup does apply to T , quite nicely. First, observe
that a point x is a root of f if and only if it is a fixed point of T . Since by our
assumption c is the unique root of f in [c , c + ], c is the unique fixed point of
T on this interval.
The next order of business is to show that T is contractive, at least in some
smaller interval around c. For this we look at the derivative:
T 0 (x) = 1
134
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
2. NEWTONS METHOD
135
Let x0 [c, c+], and let {xn } be the Newtons Method sequence of iterates.
It will be useful to rewrite the defining recursion as
n N, xn+1 xn =
f (xn )
.
f 0 (xn )
Apply the Mean Value Theorem to f on |[xn , c]|: there is yn |(xn , c)| such that
f (xn )
f (xn ) f (c)
=
= f 0 (yn ).
xn c
xn c
Apply the Mean Value Theorem to f 0 on |[xn , yn ]|: there is zn |(xn , yn ))| such
that
f 0 (xn ) f 0 (yn )
= f 00 (zn ).
xn yn
The rest of the proof is a clever calculation: for n N, we have
f (xn )
f (xn )
+ 0
|xn+1 c| = |(xn+1 xn ) + (xn c)| = 0
f (xn )
f (yn )
f (xn )(f 0 (xn ) f 0 (yn )) f 0 (xn )(xn c)(f 0 (xn ) f 0 (yn ))
=
=
f 0 (xn )f 0 (yn )
f 0 (xn )f 0 (yn )
00
0
f (zn )
f (xn ) f 0 (yn )
=
|xn c| = f 0 (yn ) |xn yn ||xn c|
f 0 (yn )
00
f (zn )
|xn c|2 B |xn c|2 .
0
f (yn )
A
In the second to the last inequality above, we used the fact that since yn lies between
xn and c, |xn yn | |xn c|.
b) This is left as an exercise for the reader.
Exercise: Prove Theorem 7.11b).
Let c be a real number, C a positive real number, and let {xn }
n=0 be a sequence
of real numbers. We say that the sequence {xn } quadratically converges to c if
(QC1) xn c, and
(QC2) For all n N, |xn+1 c| C|xn c|2 .
Exercise:
a) Show that a sequence to satsify (QC2) but not (QC1).
1
b) Suppose that a sequence {xn }
n=0 satisfies |x0 c| < min(1, C ). Show that {xn }
quadratically converges to c.
c) Deduce that under the hypotheses of Theorem 7.11, there is > 0 such that for
all x0 [c , c + ], the Newtons Method sequence quadratically converges to c.
Exercise: Let {xn } be a sequence which is quadrtically convergent to c R. Viewing xn as an approximation to c, one often says that the number of decimal places
of accuracy roughly doubles with each iteration.
a) Formulate this as a statement about the sequence dn = log10 (|xn c|).
b) Prove the precise statement you formulated in part a).
136
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
3. CONVEX FUNCTIONS
137
Exercise: Let T
1 , . . . , n be convex subsets of Rn .
n
a) Show that i=1 i the
Snset of all points lying in every i is convex.
b) Show by example that i=1 i need not be convex.
When n = 1, convex subsets are quite constrained. Recall we have proven:
Theorem 7.12. For a subset R, the following are equivalent:
(i) is an interval.
(ii) is convex.
3.2. Goals.
In freshman calculus one learns, when graphing a function f , to identify subintervals on which the graph of f is concave up and intervals on which it is concave
down. Indeed one learns that the former occurs when f 00 (x) > 0 and the latter
occurs when f 00 (x) < 0. But, really, what does this mean?
First, where freshman calculus textbooks say concave up the rest of the mathematical world says convex ; and where freshman calculus textbooks say concave
down the rest of the mathematical world says concave. Moreover, the rest of the
mathematical world doesnt speak explicitly of concave functions very much because it knows that f is concave exactly when f is convex.
Second of all, really, whats going on here? Are we saying that our definition
of convexity is that f 00 > 0? If so, exactly why do we care when f 00 > 0 and when
f 00 < 0: why not look at the third, fourth or seventeenth derivatives? The answer is
that we have not a formal definition but an intuitive conception of convexity, which
a good calculus text will at least try to nurture: for instance I was taught that a
function is convex (or rather concave up) when its graph holds water and that
it is concave (concave down) when its graph spills water. This is obviously not
a mathematical definition, but it may succeed in conveying some intuition. In less
poetic terms, the graph of a convex function has a certain characteristic shape that
the eye can see: it looks, in fact, qualitatively like an upward opening parabola or
some portion thereof. Similarly, the eye can spot concavity as regions where the
graph looks, qualitatively, like a piece of a downward opening parabola. And this
explains why one talks about convexity in freshman calculus: it is a qualitative,
visual feature of the graph of f that you want to take into account. If you are
graphing f and you draw something concave when the graph is actually convex,
the graph will look wrong and you are liable to draw false conclusions about the
behavior of the function.
So, at a minimum, our task at making good mathematical sense of this portion
of freshman calculus, comes down to the following:
Step 1: Give a precise definition of convexity: no pitchers of water allowed!
Step 2: Use our definition to prove a theorem relating convexity of f to the second
derivative f 00 , when f 00 exists.
In fact this is an oversimplification of what we will actually do. When we try
to nail down a mathematical definition of a convex function, we succeed all too
well: there are five different definitions, each having some intuitive geometric appeal and each having its technical uses. But we want to be talking about one class
138
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
of functions, not four different classes, so we will need to show that all five of our
definitions are equivalent, i.e., that any function f : I R which satisfies any one
of these definitions in fact satisfies all four. This will take some time.
3.3. Epigraphs.
For a function f : I R, we define its epigraph to be the set of points (x, y) IR
which lie on or above the graph of the function. In fewer words,
Epi(f ) = {(x, y) I R | y f (x)}.
A function f : I R is convex if its epigraph Epi(f ) is a convex subset of R2 .
Example: Any linear function f (x) = mx + b is convex.
Example: The function f (x) = |x| is convex.
Example: Suppose f (x) = ax2 + bx + c. Then Epi(f ) is just the set of points
of R2 lying on or above a parabola. From this picture it is certainly intuitively
clear that Epi(f ) is convex iff a > 0, i.e., iff the parabola is opening upward. But
proving from scratch that Epi(f ) is a convex subset is not so much fun.
3.4. Secant-graph, three-secant and two-secant inequalities.
A function f : I R satisfies the secant-graph inequality if for all a < b I
and all [0, 1], we have
(28)
.
xa
ba
bx
A function f : I R satisfies the two-secant inequality if for all a < x < b,
(29)
(30)
f (x) f (a)
f (b) f (a)
.
xa
ba
3. CONVEX FUNCTIONS
139
Proof. We will show (i) = (ii) (iii) = (i) and (iii) (iv).
(i) = (ii): This is immediate.
(ii) (iii): The two-secant inequality
f (x) f (a)
f (b) f (a)
xa
ba
is equivalent to
f (x) f (a) +
f (b) f (a)
ba
(x a) = La,b (x),
say. Now La,b (x) is a linear function with La,b (a) = f (a) and La,b b() = f (b), hence
it is the secant line between (a, f (a)) and (b, f (b)). Thus the two-secant inequality
is equivalent to the secant-graph inequality.
(iii) = (i): As above,
secant line La,b (x) from (a, f (a)) to (b, f (b)) has
snce the
equation y = f (a) +
f (b)f (a)
ba
f (x) f (a)
f (b) f (a)
.
xa
ba
To get the other half of the three-secant inequality, note that we also have
La,b (x) = f (b) +
and the inequality f (x) f (b) +
f (a) f (b)
(b x),
ba
f (a)f (b)
(b
ba
f (b) f (a)
f (b) f (x)
.
ba
bx
(iii) = (iv): Let P1 = (x1 , y1 ), P2 = (x2 , y2 ) Epi(f ). We want to show Epi(f )
contains the line segment joining P1 and P2 . This is clear if x1 = x2 = x in
this case the line segment is vertical, since since y1 and y2 are both greater than or
equal to f (x), so is every point y in between y1 and y2 . So we may assume x1 6= x2
and then that x1 < x2 (otherwise interchange P1 and P2 ). Seeking a contradiction,
we suppose there is 1 (0, 1) such that (1 1 )P1 + 1 P2
/ Epi(f ): that is,
(1 1 )y1 + 1 y2 < f ((1 1 )x1 + 1 x2 ).
But since f (x1 ) y1 and f (x2 ) y2 , we have
(1 1 )f (x1 ) + 1 f (x2 ) (1 1 )y1 + 1 y2
and thus
(1 1 )f (x1 ) + 1 f (x2 ) < f ((1 1 )x1 + 1 x2 ),
violating the secant-graph inequality.
(iv) = (iii): Let x < y I. Since (x, f (x)) and (y, f (y)) lie on the graph of f ,
they are elements of the epigraph Epi(f ). Since Epi(f ) is convex the line segment
joining (x, f (x)) and (y, f (y)) lies inside Epi(f ). But this line segment is nothing
else than the secant line between the two points, and to say that it lies inside the
epigraph is to say that the secant line always lies on or above the graph of f .
Corollary 7.14. (Generalized Two Secant Inequality) Let f : I R be a
convex function, and let a, b, c, d I with a < b c < d. Then
(31)
f (b) f (a)
f (d) f (c)
.
ba
dc
140
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
ba
cb
and applying it to the points b, c, d gives
f (c) f (b)
f (d) f (c)
.
cb
dc
Combining these two inequalities gives the desired result.
.
ca
db
3.5. Continuity properties of convex functions.
Theorem 7.15. Suppose f : I R is convex, and let [a, b] be any subinterval
of I . Then f is a Lipschitz function on [a, b]: there exists a constant C such that
for all x, y [a, b], |f (x) f (y)| C|x y|.
Proof. Choose u, v, w, z I with u < v < a and b < w < z. Applying the
Generalized Two Secant Inequality twice we get
f (v) f (u)
f (y) f (x)
f (z) f (w)
.
vu
yx
zw
Thus
f (v) f (u) f (z) f (w)
|f (x) f (y)|
,
,
max
|x y|
vu zw
so
f (v) f (u) f (z) f (w)
L = max
,
vu zw
is a Lipschitz constant for f on [a, b].
3. CONVEX FUNCTIONS
141
f (x) f (a)
,
xa
S(x) =
f (b) f (x)
.
bx
xb
(a)
(ii) = (i): Let g(x) = f (x)f
. We will show that g is increasing on (a, b]: this
xa
gibes the two-secant inequality and thus the convexity of f . Since f is differentiable,
so is g and
(x a)f 0 (x) (f (x) f (a))
g 0 (x) =
.
(x a)2
(a)
= f 0 (y) for some a < y < x. Since f 0 is
By the Mean Value Theorem, f (x)f
xa
increasing,
f (x) f (a)
= f 0 (y) f 0 (x);
xa
equivalently
(x a)f 0 (x) (f (x) f (a)) 0.
Thus g 0 (x) 0 for all x (a, b], so indeed g is increasing on (a, b].
3Andrew Kane was a student in the 2011-2012 course who suggested this criterion upon being
prompted in class.
142
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
3. CONVEX FUNCTIONS
143
so `c is a supporting line and also that if A < 0, f (x) `c (x) < 0 for all x so
`c is not a supporting line. Note that since f 00 (x) = 2A, f is convex iff A > 0.
Example: Consider the function f : R R given by f (x) = |x|. Since Epi(f )
is a convex subset of R2 , f is convex. For every c > 0, the line y = x is a supporting line, and for every c < 0, the line y = x is a supporting line, and in both
cases these supporting lines are unique. For c = 0, y = 0 is a supporting line, but
it is not the only one: indeed y = mx is a supporting line at c = 0 iff 1 m 1.
Note that the smallest slope of a supporting line is the left-hand derivative at zero:
h
f (0 + h) f (0)
= lim
= 1,
h
h
h0
and the largest slope of a supporting line is the right-hand derivative at zero:
0
f
(0) = lim
h0
0
f+
(0) = lim
h0+
h
f (0 + h) f (0)
= lim
= 1.
+
h
h0 h
Lemma 7.22. Convex functions are closed under suprema. More precisely, if
{fi : I R}iI is a family of convex functions, f : I R is a function such that
for all x I, f (x) = supiI fi (x), then f is convex.
Proof. Let a < b I and (0, 1). Then
f ((1 )a + b) = sup fi ((1 )a + b)
iI
iI
Theorem 7.23. Let I be an open interval. For a function f : I R, TFAE:
(i) f is convex.
(ii) f admits a supporting line at each c I.
Proof. (i) = (ii): Neither property (i) or (ii) is disturbed by translating
the coordinate axes, so we may assume that c = 0 and f (0) = 0. Let I \ {0}.
For all 1 , 2 > 0 such that 1 , 2 I, by the secant-graph inequality we have
1
2
0 = (1 + 2 )f
(2 ) +
(1 ) 1 f (2 ) + 2 f (1 ),
1 + 2
1 + 2
or
f (2 )
f (1 )
.
2
1
It follows that sup2
f (2 )
2
inf 1
f (1 )
1 ,
so there is m R with
f (2 )
f (1 )
m
.
2
1
Equivalently, f (t) mt for all t R such that t I. Thus `(x) = mx is a
supporting line for f at c = 0.
(ii) = (i): For each c I, let `c : I R be a supporting line for f at c. Since
for all x I, f (x) `c (x) for all c and f (c) = `c (c), we have f (x) = supcI `c (x).
Since the linear functions `c are certainly convex, f is the supremum of a family of
convex functions, hence convex by Lemma 7.21
144
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
Before stating the next result, we recall the notion of one-sided differentiability:
if f is a function defined (at least) on some interval [c , c], we say f is left
(c)
differentiable at c if limxc f (x)f
exists, and if so, we denote this limit by
xc
0
f (c), the left derivative of f at c. Similarly, if f is defined (at least) on sme
(c)
interval [c, c + ), we say f is right differentiable at c if limxc+ f (x)f
exists,
xc
0
and if so, we denote this limit by f+ (c), the right derivative of f at c. (As usual
0
0
for limits, f is differentiable at c iff f
(c) and f+
(c) both exist and are equal.)
Theorem 7.24. Let I be an interval, c I , and f : I R be convex.
0
0
a) f is both left-differentiable and right-differentiable at c: f
(c) and f+
(c) exist.
0
0
b) For all c (a, b), f (c) f+ (c).
0
0
c) f
, f+
: I R are both weakly increasing functions.
d) A line ` passing through (c, f (c)) is a supporting line for f iff its slope m satisfies
0
0
f
(c) m f+
(c).
f (x) f (c)
.
xc
Further, put
A = ((a, c)), B = (c, b).
From the three-secant inequality we immediately deduce all of the following: is
weakly increasing on (a, c), is weakly increasing on (c, b), and A B. Thus
0
0
f
(c) = lim (x) = sup A inf B = lim+ (x) = f+
(c).
xc
xc
c) Let x1 , x2 (a, b) with x1 < x2 , and choose v with x1 < v < x2 . Then by part
b) and the three-secant inequality,
f (v) f (x1 )
f (v) f (x2 )
0
0
f
(x2 ) f+
(x2 ).
v x1
v x2
d) The proof of parts a) and b) shows that for x I,
0
0
f
(x1 ) f+
(x1 )
0
f (x) f (c) + f
(c)(x c), if x c,
0
f (x) f (c) + f+
(c)(x c), if x c.
0
0
Thus if f (c) m f+ (c), we have
0
f (x) f (c) + f
(c)(x c) f (c) + m(x c), if x c,
0
f (x) f (c) + f+
(c)(x c) m(xc ) if x c,
so `(x) = f (c) + m(x c) is a supporting line for f at c. That these are the only
possible slopes of supporting lines for f at c is left as an exercise for the reader.
3. CONVEX FUNCTIONS
145
0
(i) f
is continuous at c.
0
(ii) f+
is continuous at c.
(iii) f is differentiable at c, and the tangent line is a supporting line at c.
(iv) f has a unique supporting line at c.
Remark: Because a weakly increasing function can only have jump discontinuities, it can be shown that such functions are continuous at most points of their
domain. For those who are familiar with the notions of countable and uncountable
sets, we may be more precise: the set of discontinuities of a monotone function
must be countable. Since the union of two countable sets is countable, it follows
that a convex function is differentiable except possibly at a countable set of points.
Remark: One can go further: a convex function is twice differentiable at most
points of its domain. The sense of most here is different (and weaker): the set
of points at which f fails to be twice differentiable has measure zero in the sense
of Lebesgue. This result, which is itself due to Lebesgue, lies considerably deeper
than the one of the previous remark.
3.9. Jensens Inequality.
Theorem 7.25. (Jensens Inequality) Let f : I R be continuous and convex.
For any x1 , . . . , xn I and any 1 , . . . , n [0, 1] with 1 + . . . + n = 1, we have
f (1 x1 + . . . + n xn ) 1 f (x1 ) + . . . + n f (xn ).
Proof. We go by induction on n, the base case n = 1 being trivial. So
suppose Jensens Inequality holds for some n Z+ , and consider x1 , . . . , xn+1 I
and 1 , . . . , n+1 [0, 1] with 1 + . . . + n+1 = 1. If n+1 = 0 we are reduced
to the case of n variables which holds by induction. Similarly if n+1 = 1 then
1 = . . . = n = 0 and we have, trivially, equality. So we may assume n+1 (0, 1)
and thus also that 1 n+1 (0, 1). Now for the big trick: we write
1
n
1 x1 +. . .+n+1 xn+1 = (1n+1 )
x1 + . . . +
xn +n+1 xn+1 ,
1 n+1
1 n+1
so that
1
n
x1 +. . .+
xn )+n+1 xn+1 )
1 n+1
1 n+1
1
n
(1 n+1 )f
x1 + . . . +
xn + n+1 f (xn+1 ).
1 n+1
1 n+1
f (1 x1 + . . . + n xn ) = f ((1n+1 )(
1
n
Since 1
, . . . , 1
are non-negative numbers that sum to 1, by induction
n+1
n+1
the n variable case of Jensens Inequality can be applied to give that the above
expression is less than or equal to
1
n
(1 n+1 )
f (x1 ) + . . . +
f (xn ) + n+1 f (xn+1 )
1 n+1
1 n+1
146
7. DIFFERENTIAL MISCELLANY
(32)
1
n,
Taking 1 = . . . = n =
1
n
x
n )
x1 1 xnn = elog(x1
1
p
1
q
= 1. Then
yq
xp
+ .
p
q
Proof. When either x = 0 or y = 0 the left hand side is zero and the right hand
side is non-negative, so the inequality holds and we may thus assume x, y > 0. Now
apply the Weighted Arithmetic-Geometric Mean Inequality with n = 2, x1 = xp ,
x2 = y q , 1 = p1 , 2 = 1q . We get
xy
(33)
xy = (xp ) p (y q ) q = x1 1 x2 2 1 x1 + 2 x2 =
xp
yq
+ .
p
q
Theorem 7.28. (H
olders Inequality)
Let x1 , . . . , xn , y1 , . . . , yn R and let p, q (1, ) satisfy
(34)
1
p
1
p
1
q
= 1. Then
1
3. CONVEX FUNCTIONS
147
|x1 ||x1 +y1 |p1 +. . .+|xn ||xn +yn |p1 +|y1 ||x1 +y1 |p1 +. . .+|yn ||xn +yn |p1
1
(|x1 |p +. . .+|xn |p ) p (|x1 +y1 |p +. . .+|xn +yn |p ) q +(|y1 |p +. . .+|yn |p ) p (|x1 +y1 |p +. . .+|xn +yn |p ) q
1
1
1
= (|x1 |p + . . . + |xn |p ) p + (|y1 |p + . . . |yn |p ) p (|x1 + y1 |p + . . . + |xn + yn |p ) q .
1
CHAPTER 8
Integration
1. The Fundamental Theorem of Calculus
Having finished with continuity and differentiation, we turn to the third main
theme of calculus: integration. The basic idea is this: for a function f : [a, b] R,
Rb
we wish to associate a number a f , the definite integral. When f is non-negative,
Rb
our intuition is that a f should represent the area under the curve y = f (x), or
more precisely the area of the region bounded above by y = f (x), bounded below
by y = 0, bounded on the left by x = a and bounded on the right by x = b.
Unfortunately this is not yet a formal definition, because we do not have a
formal definition of the area of a subset of the plane! In high school geometry
one learns only about areas of very simple figures: polygons, circles and so forth.
Dealing head-on with the task of assigning an area to every subset of R2 is quite
difficult: it is one of the important topics of graduate level real analysis: measure
theory.
Rb
So we need to back up a bit and give a definition of a f . As you probably know,
Rb
the general idea is to construe a f as the result of some kind of limiting process,
wherein we divide [a, b] into subintervals and take the sum of the areas of certain rectangles which approximate the function f at various points of the interval
(Riemann sums). As usual in freshman calculus, reasonably careful definitions
appear in the textbook somewhere, but with so little context and development that
(almost) no actual freshman calculus student can really appreciate them.
But wait! Before plunging into the details of this limiting process, lets take a
Rb
more axiomatic approach: given that we want a f to represent the area under
y = f (x), what properties should it satisfy? Here are some reasonable ones.
Rb
C = C(b a).
Ra b
Rb
(I2) If f1 (x) f2 (x) for all x [a, b], then a f1 a f2 .
Rc
Rb
Rc
(I3) If a c b, then a f = a f + b f .
(I1) If f = C is a constant function, then
Exercise 1.1: Show (I1) implies: for any f : [a, b] R and any c [a, b],
Rc
c
f = 0.
It turns out that these three axioms already imply many of the other properties we
want an integral to have. Even more, there is essentially only one way to define
Rb
f so as to satisfy (I1) through (I3).
a
Well, almost. One feature that we havent explicitly addressed yet is this: for
149
150
8. INTEGRATION
Rb
which functions f : [a, b] R do we expect a f to be defined? For all functions??
A little thought shows this not to be plausible: there are some functions so pathological that there is no reason to believe that the area under the curve y = f (x)
has any meaning whatsoever, and there are some functions for which this area concept seems meaningful but for which the area is infinite.
So it turns out to be useful to think of integration itself as a real-valued function,
with domain some set of functions {f : [a, b] R}. That is, for each a b we
wish to have a set, say R[a, b], of integrable functions f : [a, b] R and for each
Rb
f R[a, b], we wish to associate a real number a f . As to exactly what this set
R[a, b] of integrable functions should be, it turns out that we have some leeway, but
to get a theory which is useful and not too complicated, lets assume the following:
(I0) For all real numbers a < b:
a) Every continuous f : [a, b] R lies in R[a, b].
b) Every function f R[a, b] is bounded.
By the Extreme Value Theorem, every continuous function f : [a, b] R is
bounded. Thus the class C[a, b] of all continuous functions f : [a, b] R is contained in the class B[a, b] of all bounded functions f : [a, b], and axiom (I0) requires
that the set of integrable functions lies somewhere in between:
C[a, b] R[a, b] B[a, b].
Lets recast the other three axioms in terms of our set R[a, b] of integrable functions:
(I1) If f = C is constant, then f R[a, b] and
Rb
a
C = C(b a).
Rb
Rb
(I2) If for f1 , f2 R[a, b] we have f1 (x) f2 (x) for all x [a, b], then a f1 a f2 .
(I3) Let f : [a, b] R, and let c (a, b). Then f R[a, b] iff f R[a, c] and
Rb
Rc
Rb
f R[c, b]. If these equivalent conditions hold, then a f = a f + c f .
If this business of integrable functions seems abstruse, then on the first pass just
imagine that R[a, b] is precisely the set of all continuous functions f : [a, b] R.
Now we have the following extremely important result.
Theorem 8.1. (Fundamental Theorem of Calculus)
Let f R[a, b] be any
Rx
integrable function. For x [a, b], define F(x) = a f . Then:
a) The function F : [a, b] R is continuous at every c [a, b].
b) If f is continuous at c [a, b], then F is differentiable at c, and F 0 (c) = f (c).
c) If f is continuous and F is any antiderivative of f i.e., a function F : [a, b] R
Rb
such that F 0 (x) = f (x) for all x [a, b], then a f = F (b) F (a).
Proof. By (I0), there exists M R such that |f (x)| M for all x [a, b]. If
M = 0 then f is the constant function 0, and then it follows from (I1) that F is
also the constant function zero, and one sees easily that the theorem holds in this
case.
. Indeed, by (I3)
So we may assume M > 0. For all > 0, we may take = M
Z x
Z c
Z x
(36)
F(x) F(c) =
f
f=
f.
a
151
and thus
Z
(37)
f | M (B A).
A
M.
xc
c
= f (c) + ,
f (c) =
xc
xc
xc
and thus
Rx
f
| c
f (c)| .
xc
This shows that F 0 (c) exists and is equalR to f (c).
x
c) By part b), if f is continuous, F(x) = a f is an antiderivative of f . But we have
shown that if antiderivatives exist at all they are unique up to an additive constant.
We have just found an antiderivative F, so if F is any other antiderivative of f we
must have F (x) = F(x) + C for some constant C, and then
Z b
Z a
Z b
F (b) F (a) = (F(b) + C) (F(a) + C) = F(b) F(a) =
f
f=
f.
Rx
c
Remark: Although we introduced the integral axiomatically, as long as we are
only trying to integrate continuous functions we had no choice: the only way to
Rb
assign a value a f to each continuous function f : [a, b] R satisfying the (reaRb
sonable!) axioms (I1) through (I3) is to take a f to be an antidervative F of f
with F (a) = 0, and again, there is at most one such function.
These same considerations answer the conundrum of why the celebrated Theorem 8.1 has such a short and simple proof.1 The theorem assumes that we already
1This is not just florid language. I taught second semester calculus four times as a graduate
student and really did become puzzled at how easy it was to prove the Fundamental Theorem
of Calculus so soon after integration is discussed. I worked out the answer while teaching an
undergraduate real analysis course at McGill University in 2005. The current presentation is an
adaptation of my lecture notes from this older course. Soon after I gave my 2005 lectures I found
that a very similar axiomatic treatment of the integral was given by the eminent mathematician
152
8. INTEGRATION
Rb
have an integral, i.e., an assignment (f : [a, b] R) 7 a f for every continuous
function f . We have shown that there is at most one such integral on the continuous functions, but we have not yet constructed this integral! In other words,
we have settled the problem of uniqueness of the definite integral but (thus far)
assumed a solution to the much harder problem of existence of the definite integral.
And again, this existence problem is equivalent to an existence problem that we
mentioned before, namely that every continuous function has an antiderivative.
Thus: if we could prove by some other means that every continuous function f
is the derivative of some other function F , then by the above we may simply define
Rb
f = F (b) F (a). This is the approach that Newton himself took, although
a
he didnt prove that every continuous function was a derivative but rather merely
assumed it. It is also what freshman calculus students seem to think is taught in
Rb
freshman calculus, namely that the definition of a f is F (b) F (a).2
But I do not know any way to prove that an arbitrary continuous function has
Rb
an antiderivative except to give a constructive definition of a f as a limit of sums
Rx
and then appeal to Theorem 8.1b) to get that a f is an antiderivative of f .
Thus Theorem 8.1 is easy because it diverts the hard work elsewhere: we need to
give a constructive definition of the definite integral via a (new) kind of limiting process and then show from scratch that applied to every continuous f : [a, b] R
Rb
this limiting process converges and results in a well-defined number a f .
2. Building the Definite Integral
2.1. Upper and Lower Sums.
Now we begin the proof of the hard fact lurking underneath the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus: that we may define for every continuous function f : [a, b] R
Rb
a number a f so as to satisfy (I1) through (I3) above. For now, we will make
a simplifying assumption on our class of integrable functions: namely, let us only
consider functions f : [a, b] R such that for every closed subinterval [c, d] [a, b],
f : [c, d] R has a maximum and minimum value. Of course this holds for all
continuous functions, so it will be a good start.
The basic idea is familiar from freshman calculus: we wish to subdivide our interval [a, b] into a bunch of closed subintervals meeting only at the endpoints, and
then we want to consider the lower sum and upper sum associated to f on each
subinterval. Then the lower sum should be less than or equal to the true area
under the curve which should be less than or equal to the upper sum, and by
dividing [a, b] into more and smaller subintervals we should get better and better
Rb
approximations to the true area under the curve, so we should define a f via
some limiting process involving lower sums and upper sums.
Okay, lets do it!
Serge Lang in [L]. So the presentation that I give here is not being given by me for the first time
and was not originated by me...but nevertheless the material is rarely presented this way.
2This is not what the books actually say, but what they actually say they dont say loudly
enough in order for the point to really stick.
153
Step 1: We need the notion of a partition of an interval [a, b]: we choose finitely
many same points in [a, b] and use them to divide [a, b] into subintervals. Formally, a partitition P is given by a positive integer n and real numbers
a = a0 a1 . . . an1 an = b.
That is, we require the first sample point a0 to be the left endpoint of the interval,
the last sample point an to be the right endpoint of the interval, and the other
(distinct) points are absolutely arbitrary but written in increasing order.
Let f : [a, b] R be any function admitting a minimum and maximum value on
every closed subinterval of [a, b] (e.g. any continuous function!). For 0 i n 1,
let mi (f ) denote the minimum value of f on the subinterval [xi , xi+1 ] and let Mi (f )
denote the maximum value of f on the subinterval [xi , xi+1 ]. Then we define the
lower sum associated to f : [a, b] R and the partition P = {x0 , . . . , xn } as
L(f, P) =
n1
X
mi (f )(xi+1 xi )
i=0
n1
X
Mi (f )(xi+1 xi ).
i=0
These sums have a simple and important geometric interpretation: for any 0 i
n 1, the quantity xi+1 xi is simply the length of the subinterval [xi , xi+1 ]. So
consider the constant function mi (f ) on the interval [xi , xi+1 ]: by definition of mi ,
this is the largest constant function whose graph lies on or below the graph of f
at every point of [xi , xi+1 ]. Therefore the quantity mi (f )(xi+1 xi ) is simply the
area of the rectangle with height mi (f ) and width xi+1 xi , or equivalently the
area under the constant function y = mi (f ) on [xi , xi+1 ].
We say the function f : [a, b] R is integrable if there is a unique I R
such that for every partition P of [a, b] we have
L(f, P) I U (f, P).
This definition, although correct, is not ideally formulated: it underplays the most
important part the uniqueness of I while making it annoying to show the existence of I. (It turn outs that there is always at least one I lying between every lower
sum and every upper sum, but this is as yet far from clear.) Here are some examples.
Example 2.1: If f (x) C is a constant function, then for every partition P on
[a, b] we have L(f, P) = U (f, P) = C(b a). Thus the unique I in question is
celarly C(b a): constant functions are integrable.
Example 2.2: Suppose f (x) is constantly equal to 1 on the interval [a, b] except
for one interior point c, at which f (c) = 0. We claim that despite having a disRb
continuity at c, f is integrable, with a f = b a. To see this, first observe that
for any partition P of [a, b] we have U (f, P) = b a. Indeed this is because on
every subinterval of [a, b] f has 1 as its maximum value. On the other hand, for
154
8. INTEGRATION
any sufficiently small > 0, we may choose a partition in which c occurs in exactly
one subinterval (i.e., c is not one of the points of the partition). Then the lower
sum on that subinterval is 0, whereas on every other subinterval the minimum is
again 1, so L(f, P) = (b a)(1 ). This shows that the unique number between
Rb
every L(f, P) and U (f, P) is b a, so a f = (b a).
Exercise 2.3: Show that starting with the constant function C on [a, b] and changing
Rb
its value at finitely many points yields an integrable function f with a f = C(ba).
The previous examples have the property that the upper sums U (f, P) are constant. When this happens, one can show f is integrable by finding a sequence of
partitions for which the lower sums approach this common value U (f, P) which
must then be the integral. But constancy of upper sums only occurs in trivial examples. For instance, suppose we want to show that f (x) = x is integrable on [0, 1].
If we partition [0, 1] into n equally spaced subintervals let us call this partition
Pn then since f is increasing its minimum on each subinterval occurs at the left
endpoint and its maximum on each subinterval occurs at the right endpoint. Thus
n1
n1
Xi 1
1 X
1
(n 1)n
1
i= 2
.
= 2
=1
L(f, Pn ) =
n
n
n
n
2
2n
i=0
i=0
and
U (f, Pn ) =
n1
X
i=0
i+1
n
n
1 X
1 n(n + 1)
1
1
i= 2
.
= 2
=1+
n
n i=1
n
2
2n
1
Since
= limx x+1
2x = 2 , the upper and lower sums can both be
1
made arbitrarily close to 2 by taking n to be sufficiently large. Thus if f (x) = x
is integrable on [0, 1], its integral must be 12 . Unfortunately we have not yet shown
that f is integrable according to our definition: to do this we would have to consider
an arbitrary partition P of [0, 1] and show that L(f, P) 12 U (f, P). For this
very simple function f (x) = x it is possible to grind this out directly, but its quite
a bit of work. And thats just to find the area of a right triangle!
limx x1
2x
155
n1
X
mi (f )(xi+1 xi ) [, ),
i=0
U (f, P) =
n1
X
Mi (f )(xi+1 xi ) (, ].
i=0
Observe though that the lower sum could take the value and the upper sum
could take the value . The following result clarifies when this is the case.
Proposition 8.2. Let f : [a, b] R be any function.
a) The following are equivalent:
(i) For all partitions P of [a, b], L(f, P) = .
(ii) There exists a partition P of [a, b] such that L(f, P) = .
(iii) f is not bounded below on [a, b].
b) The following are equivalent:
(i) For all partitions P of [a, b], U (f, P) = .
(ii) There exists a partition P of [a, b] such that U (f, P) = .
(iii) f is not bounded above on [a, b].
c) The following are equivalent:
(i) For all partitions P of [a, b], L(f, P) > and U (f, P) < .
(ii) f is bounded on [a, b].
Proof. a) (i) = (ii) is immediate.
(ii) = (iii): We prove the contrapositive: suppose that there is m R such that
m f (x) for all x [a, b]. Then for all partitions P = {a = x0 < . . . < xn1 <
xn = b} and all 0 i n 1, we have mi (f ) m > , so L(f, P) > .
(iii) = (i): Suppose f is not bounded below on [a, b], and let P = {a = x0 < . . . <
xn1 < xn = b} be a partition of [a, b]. If mi (f ) > for all 0 i n 1, then
minn1
i=0 mi (f ) is a finite lower bound for f on [a, b], contradicting our assumption.
So there is at least one i such that mi (f ) = , which forces L(f, P) = .
b) This is similar enough to part a) to be left to the reader.
c) If for all partitions P, L(f, P) > and U (f, P) < , then by parts a) and b)
f is bounded above and below on [a, b], so is bounded on [a, b]. Conversely, if f is
bounded on [a, b] then it is bounded above and below on [a, b], so by parts a) and
b), for all partitions P we have L(f, P) > and U (f, P) < .
Let P1 and P2 be two partitions of [a, b]. We say that P2 refines P1 if P2 contains
every point of P1 : i.e., if P1 P2 .
Lemma 8.3. (Refinement Lemma) Let P1 P2 be partitions of [a, b] (i.e., P2
refines P1 ). Then for any bounded function f : [a, b] R we have
L(f, P1 ) L(f, P2 ) U (f, P2 ) U (f, P1 ).
156
8. INTEGRATION
f
a
f.
a
Proof. Recall that if X, Y R are such that x y for all x X and all
y Y , then sup X inf Y . Now, by Lemma 8.4, for any partitions P1 and P2 we
have L(f, P1 ) U (f, P2 ). Therefore
Z
Z
f = sup L(f, P1 ) inf U (f, P2 ) =
P1
P2
f.
a
157
Rb
a
f=
Rb
a
f = ?
Z
L(f, P) L(f, P1 ) >
a
f ,
2
and thus
L(f, P) <
2
(40)
f.
a
f
a
158
8. INTEGRATION
Rb
Rb
Since this holds for all > 0, we have a f f . On the other hand, by Lemma
a
Rb
Rb
Rb
Rb
8.5 we have f a f , so f = a f R and thus f is Darboux integrable.
a
a
Rb Rb
Rb
(i) = (iii): Suppose f is Darboux integrable, so a = f = a f R. Then for
a
all partitions P we have
Z
L(f, P)
Rb
f U (f, P).
a
Rb
f=
Z
f
f=
a
L(f, P)
Rb
a
f,
Rb
a
f U (f, P),
f<
a
b
a
Mi (f ) mi (f ).
n
n
i=0
i=0
159
(I3): Let f : [a, b] R, and let c (a, b). Suppose first that f : [a, b] R is
Darboux integrable: thus, for all > 0, there exists a partition P of [a, b] with
U (f, P) L(f, P) < . Let Pc = P {c}. By the Refinement Lemma,
L(f, P) L(f, Pc ) U (f, Pc ) U (f, P),
so U (f, Pc ) L(f, Pc ) U (f, P) L(f, P) < . Let P1 = Pc [a, c] and P2 =
Pc [c, b]. Then
L(f, Pc ) = L(f, P1 ) + L(f, P2 ), U (f, Pc ) = U (f, P1 ) + U (f, P2 ),
and therefore
(U (f, P1 )L(f, P1 ))+(U (f, P2 )L(f, P1 )) = (U (f, P1 )+U (f, P2 ))(L(f, P1 )+L(f, P2 ))
= U (f, Pc ) L(f, Pc ) < ,
so by Darbouxs criterion f : [a, c] R and f : [c, b] R are Darboux integrable.
Conversely, suppose f : [a, c] R and f : [c, b] R are Darboux integrable; let
> 0. By Darbouxs criterion, there is a partition P1 of [a, c] such that
U (f, P1 ) L(f, P2 ) <
2
and a partition P2 of [c, b] such that
U (f, P2 ) L(f, P2 ) < .
2
Then P = P1 P2 is a partition of [a, b], and
U (f, P) L(f, P) = U (f, P1 ) + U (f, P2 ) (L(f, P1 ) + L(f, P2 ))
= (U (f, P1 ) L(f, P1 )) + (U (f, P2 ) L(f, P2 )) < + = .
2 2
As for the value of the integral: fix > 0. Let P be any partition of [a, b], Pc =
P {c}, P1 = Pc [a, c], P2 = Pc [c, b]. Then
Z c
Z b
L(f, P) L(f, Pc ) = L(f, P1 ) + L(f, P2 )
f+
f U (f, P1 ) + U (f, P2 )
a
160
8. INTEGRATION
Rc
Rb
Thus
f+
161
Suppose now that c is a point in the interior of the domain D of f . We define the
oscillation of f at c to be
(f, c) = lim+ (f, [c , c + ]).
0
162
8. INTEGRATION
Now let f : [a, b] R and let P = {a = x0 < x1 < . . . < xn1 < xn = b}
be a partition of [a, b]. We define3
(f, P) =
n1
X
i=0
Thus this notation is just a way of abbreviating the quantities upper sum minus
lower sum which will appear ubiquitously in the near future. We can restate Darbouxs Criterion especially cleanly with this new notation: a function f : [a, b] R
is integrable iff for all > 0, there exists a partition P of [a, b] with (f, P) < .
3.2. Discontinuities of Darboux Integrable Functions.
At this point, I want to discuss the result that a bounded function f : [a, b] R
with only finitely many discontinuities is Darboux integrable. So I wrote up a direct proof of this and it was long and messy. Afterwards I realized that a better
argument is by induction on the number of discontinuities. One then has to prove
the result for a function with a single discontinuity (base case), and assuming the
result for every function with n discontinuities, prove it for every function with
n + 1 discontinutities (inductive step). Here the inductive step is especially easy:
if f : [a, b] R has n + 1 points of discontinuity, we can choose c (a, b) such
that f |[a,c] has exactly one discontinuity and f |[c,b] has exactly n discontinuities.
The restricted functions are Darboux integrable by the base case and the induction
hypothesis, and as we know, this implies that f : [a, b] R is Darboux integrable.
So really it is enough to treat the case of a bounded function with a single
discontinuity. It turns out that it is no trouble to prove a stronger version of this.
Theorem 8.11. Let f : [a, b] R be bounded. Suppose that for all c (a, b),
f |[c,b] : [c, b] R is Darboux integrable. Then f is Darboux integrable and
Z b
Z b
lim+
f=
f.
ca
Proof. Let M > 0 be such that |f (x)| M for all x [a, b]. Fix > 0 and
consider partitions P of [a, b] with x1 = a + . For such partitions,
(f, P) = (f, P [a, a + ]) + (f, P [a + , b]).
Since the infimum of f on any subinterval of [a, b] is at least M and the supremum
is at most M , (f, [a, a + ]) 2M , which we can make as small as we wish by
taking small enough. Similarly, having chosen , we may make (f, P [a + , b])
as small as we like with a suitable choice of P, since f is assumed to be Darboux
integrable on [a + , b]. Thus we can make the oscillation at most for any > 0,
so f is Darboux integrable on [a, b]. The second statement follows easily:
Z b
Z b
Z c
|
f
f| = |
f | 2M (c a),
a
3For once we do not introduce a name but only a piece of notation. In an earlier course on
this subject I called this quantity the oscillation of f on P, but this is not especially apt. Better
perhaps would be to call (f, P) the discrepancy of f and P, since it is the difference between
the upper and the lower sum. But in fact it is simplest not to call it anything but (f, P)!
163
164
8. INTEGRATION
To see this, observe that for any fixed , there are only finitely many nonzero rational numbers pq in [0, 1] with q : indeed there is at most 1 such with denominator
1, at most 2 with denominator 2, and so forth (and in fact there are less than
this because e.g. in our terminology the denominator of 24 is actually 2, since
1
2
4 = 2 in lowest terms). Suppose then that there are N points x in [0, 1] such that
f (x) . Choose a partition P such that each of these points x lies in the interior
of a subinterval of length at most N . Since the maximum value of f on [0, 1] is 1,
the term of the upper sum corresponding to each of these N bad subintervals is
; since there are N bad subintervals over all, this part of the sum
at most 1 2N
is at most N N = , and the remaining part of the sum is at most times the
length of [a, b] = [0, 1], i.e., at most . Thus U (f, P) + = 2. Since of course
lim0 2 = 0, this shows that f is Darboux integrable.
All of our results so far have been in the direction of exhibiting examples of Darboux
integrable functions with increasingly large sets of discontinuities. What about the
other direction: is there, for instance, a Darboux integrable function which is discontinuous at every point? In fact, no:
Theorem 8.14. Let f : [a, b] R be Darboux integrable. Let S be the set of
x [a, b] such that f is continuous at x. Then S is dense in [a, b]: i.e., for all
a x < y b, there exists z (x, y) such that f is continuous at z.
Proof. Step 1: We show that there is at least one c [a, b] such that f is
continuous at c. We will construct such a c using the Nested Intervals Theorem:
recall that if we have a sequence of closed subintervals [an , bn ] such that for all n,
an bn ,
an an+1 ,
bn+1 bn ,
there is at least one c such that an c bn for all n: indeed supn an inf n bn ,
so any c [supn an , inf n bn ] will do. Since f is Darboux integrable, for all n Z+
there is a partition Pn = {a = x0 < x1 < . . . < xn1 < xn = b} of [a, b] such that
(44)
(f, Pn ) =
n1
X
i=0
ba
.
n
Now (44) implies that for at least one 0 i n 1 we have (f, [xi , xi+1 ]) <
for, if not, (f, [xi , xi+1 ]) n1 for all i and thus
1
n:
1
1
1
xn x0
ba
(x1 x0 ) + (x2 x1 ) + . . . + (xn xn1 ) =
=
,
n
n
n
n
n
contradiction. We will use this analysis to choose a nested sequence of subintervals.
First we take n = 1 and see that there is some closed subinterval [xi , xi+1 ] of [a, b]
on which (f, [xi , xi+1 ]) < 1. We then define a1 = xi , b1 = xi+1 , and instead of
considering f as defined on [a, b], we now consider it as defined on the subinterval
[a1 , b1 ]. Since f is Darboux integrable on [a, b], we know it is also Darboux integrable
on [a1 , b1 ], so the above argument still works: there exists a partition P2 of [a1 , b1 ]
such that for at least one subinterval [xi , xi+1 ] [a1 , b1 ] we have (f, [xi , xi+1 ]) <
1
2 . We then put a2 = xi (this is not necessarily the same number that we were
calling xi in the previous step, but we will stick with the simpler notation) and
b2 = xi+1 and have defined a sub-subinterval [a2 , b2 ] [a1 , b1 ] [ab ] on which
(f, Pn )
165
(f, [a2 , b2 ]) < n1 . Now, continuing in this way we construct a nested sequence
[an , bn ] of closed subintervals such that for all n Z+ , (f, [an , bn ]) < n1 . Now
apply the Nested Intervals Theorem: there exists c R such that c [an , bn ] for
all n Z+ . It follows that for all n Z+
1
(f, c) (f, [an , bn ])) < ,
n
i.e., (f, c) = 0 and thus f is continuous at c by Proposition 8.10.
Step 2: To show f has infinitely many points of continuity, its enough to show that
for all N Z+ f is continuous at at least N distinct points, and we can do this by
induction, the base case N = 1 being Step 1 above. So suppose we have already
shown f is continuous at x1 < x2 < . . . < xN in [a, b]. Choose any A, B R with
a x1 < A < B < x2 b. Once again, since f : [a, b] R is Darboux integrable,
the restriction of f to [A, B] is Darboux integrable on [A, B]. Applying Step 1, we
get c [A, B] such that f is continuous at c, and by construction c is different from
all the continuity points we have already found. This completes the induction step,
and thus it follows that f is continuous at infinitely many points of [a, b].
3.3. A supplement to the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus.
Theorem 8.15. Let f : [a, b] R be differentiable and suppose f 0 is Darboux
Rb
integrable. Then a f 0 = f (b) f (a).
Proof. Let P be a partition of [a, b]. By the Mean Value Theorem there is
ti [xi , xi+1 ] such that f (xi+1 ) f (xi ) = f 0 (ti )(xi+1 xi ). Then we have
mi (f 0 )(xi+1 xi ) f 0 (ti )(xi+1 xi ) Mi (f 0 )(xi+1 xi )
and thus
mi (f 0 )(xi+1 xi ) f (xi+1 ) f (xi ) Mi (f 0 )(xi+1 xi ).
Summing these inequalities from i = 0 to n 1 gives
L(f 0 , P) f (b) f (a) U (f 0 , P).
Rb
Since for the integrable function f , a f is the unique number lying in between all
Rb
lower and upper sums, we conclude f (b) f (a) = a f 0 .
How is Theorem 8.15 different from Theorem 8.1c)? Only in a rather subtle way:
in order to apply Theorem 8.1c) to f 0 , we need f 0 to be continuous, whereas in
Theorem 8.15 we are assuming only that f 0 is Darboux integrable. Every continuous function is Darboux integrable but, as we have seen, there are discontinuous Darboux integrable functions. What about discontinuous, Darboux integrable
derivatives? The possible discontinuities of a monotone function are incompatible
with the possible discontinuities of a derivative: if f 0 is monotone, it is continuous.
So we must look elsewhere for examples. In fact, we return to an old friend.
Example 3.3: Let a, b (0, ) and let fa,b be given by x 7 xa sin( x1b ), x 6= 0
and 0 7 0. Then fa,b is infinitely differentiable except possibly at zero. It is continuous at 0, the sine of anything is bounded, and limx0 xa = 0, so the product
approaches zero. To check differentiability at 0, we use the definition:
ha sin( h1b )
f (h) f (0)
1
= lim
= lim ha1 sin( b ).
h0
h0
h0
h
h
h
f 0 (0) = lim
166
8. INTEGRATION
0
This limit exists and is 0 iff a 1 > 0 iff a > 1. Thus if a > 1 then fa,b
(0) = 0. As
0
for continuity of fa,b at zero, we compute the derivative for nonzero x and consider
the limit as x 0:
1
1
0
fa,b
(x) = axa1 sin( b ) bxab1 cos( b ).
x
x
The first term approaches 0 for a > 1. As for the second term, in order for the
0
limit to exist we need a > b + 1. This calculation shows that fa,b
is continuous at
0 iff a > b + 1; so in this case we can apply the first version of the Fundamental
Theorem of Calculus to conclude for instance that
Z x
0
fa,b
= fa,b (x) fa,b (0) = fa,b (x).
0
0
Next, if a < b + 1, then fa,b
is unbounded near 0, hence is not Darboux integrable
on any interval containing zero. But there is a third case: if a = b + 1, then
0
0
limx0 fa,b
does not exist, but fa,b
is bounded on any closed, bounded interval, say
[0, x]. Therefore Theorem 8.15 applies to give
Z x
0
fb+1,b
= fb+1,b (x) fb+1,b (0) = fb+1,b (x)
0
Proof. a) The idea here is simply that C may be factored out of the lower
sums and the upper sums. The details may be safely left to the reader.
b) Let I [a, b] be a subinterval, and let mf , mg , mf +g be the infima of f , g
167
2
+ = .
2 2
.
b a + 2M
(xi+1 xi )
n1
X
i=0
(xi+1 xi ) = b a.
168
8. INTEGRATION
On the other hand, since M f (x) M for all x [a, b], the oscillation of f on
any subinterval of [a, b] is at most 2M . Thus we get
X
X
(f, [xi , xi+1 ])(xi+1 xi )
(f, [xi , xi+1 ])(xi+1 xi ) +
(g f, P) =
iS2
iS1
X
(b a) + 2M
(xi+1 xi ).
b a + 2M
iS1
iS2
iS2
P
(Note that reasoning as above also gives iS2 xi+1 xi (b a), but this is not
good enough: using it would give us a second term of 2M (b a), i.e., not something
that we can make arbitrarily small.) Here is a better estimate:
X
1 X
1 X
(xi+1 xi ) =
(xi+1 xi ) <
(f, [xi , xi+1 ])(xi+1 xi )
1
(xi+1 xi ) + (2M )
iS2
(xi+1 xi )
iS2
iS2
n1
1
1
1X
(f, [xi , xi+1 ])(xi+1 , xi ) = (f, P) < 2 = .
i=0
(b a)
2M
(b a) + 2M <
+
= .
b a + 2M
b a + 2M
b a + 2M
The proof of Theorem 8.17 becomes much easier if we assume that g is not merely
continuous but a Lipschitz function. Recall that f : I R is Lipschitz if there
exists C 0 such that for all x, y I, |f (x) f (y)| C|x y|.
Example: f : R R by x 7 |x| is a Lipschitz function. Indeed, the reverse
triangle inequality reads: for all x, y R,
||x| |y|| |x y|,
and this shows that 1 is a Lipschitz constant for f .
Exercise: a) For which functions may we take C = 0 as a Lipshitz constant?
b) Let I be an interval. Show that for every Lipshitz function f : I R, there is
a smallest Lipschitz constant.
Proposition 8.18. Let f : [a, b] R be a C 1 -function. Then M = maxx[a,b] |f 0 (x)|
is a Lipschitz constant for f .
Proof. Let x < y [a, b]. By the Mean Value Theorem, there is z (x, y)
such that f (x)f (y) = f 0 (z)(xy), so |f (x)f (y)| |f 0 (z)||xy| M |xy|.
Lemma 8.19. Let f : I [c, d] be bounded and g : [c, d] R a Lipshitz function
with Lipschitz constant C. Then (g f, I) C(f, I).
Exercise: Prove Lemma 8.19.
Theorem 8.20. Let f : [a, b] [c, d] be Darboux integrable, and let g : [c, d]
R be Lipschitz with contant C. Then g f : [a, b] R is Darboux integrable.
169
n1
X
i=0
.
C
Pn1
Corollary 8.21. Let f : [a, b] R be Darboux integrable. Then |f | : [a, b]
R is Darboux integrable, and we have the integral triangle inequality
Z b
Z b
f|
|f |.
|
a
|f |
f
|f |,
a
so
Z
|
Z
f|
|f |.
a
Corollary 8.22. Let f1 , f2 : [a, b] R be Darboux integrable. Then the
product f1 f2 : [a, b] R is Darboux integrable.
Proof. It is really just a dirty trick: we have the identity
(f1 + f2 )2 (f1 f2 )2
.
4
Now, by Theorem 8.15, both f1 + f2 and f1 f2 are Darboux integrable. Since f1
and f2 are Darboux integrable, they are both bounded, so there exists M with
f1 ([a, b]), f2 ([a, b]) [M, M ]. The function g(x) = x2 is C 1 on the closed,
bounded interval [M, M ] and thus Lipschitz there. Thus Theorem 8.20 applies
to show that (f1 + f2 )2 and (f1 f2 )2 are Darboux integrable, and then Theorem
8.16 appplies again to show that f1 f2 is Darboux integrable.
Rb Rb
Rb
Warning: It is usually not the case that a f1 f2 = a f1 a f2 !
f1 f2 =
Example 3.6: Let f : [1, 2] [0, 1] be the function which takes the value 1q at
every rational number pq and 0 at every irrational number, and let g : [0, 1] R
be the function which takes 0 to 0 and every x (0, 1] to 1. Then f is Darboux
integrable, g is bounded and discontinuous only at 0 so is Darboux integrable, but
g f : [1, 2] R takes every rational number to 0 and every irrational number to
1, so is not Darboux integrable. Thus we see that the composition of Darboux integrable functions need not by Darboux integrable without some further hypothesis.
Example 3.7: Above we showed that if g is continuous and f is Darboux integrable then the composition g f is Darboux integrable; then we saw that if g
170
8. INTEGRATION
and f are both merely Darboux integrable, g f need not be Darboux integrable.
So what about the other way around: suppose f is continuous and g is Darboux
integrable; must g f be Darboux integrable? The answer is again no; the easiest
counterexample I know is contained in a paper of Jitan Lu [Lu99].
4. Riemann Sums, Dicing, and the Riemann Integral
We now turn to the task of reconciling G. Darbouxs take on the integral with
B. Riemanns (earlier) work. Riemann gave an apparently different construction
Rb
of an integral a f which also satisfies axioms (I0) through (I3). By virtue of the
Rb
uniqueness of the integral of a continuous function, the Riemann integral R a f of
Rb
a continuous function agrees with our previously constructed Darboux integral a f .
But this leaves open the question of how the class of Riemann integrable functions compares with the class of Darboux integrable functions. In fact, although
the definitions look different, a function f : [a, b] R is Riemann integrable iff it
Rb
Rb
is Darboux integrable and then R a f = a f . Thus what we really have is a rival
construction of the Darboux integral, which is in some respects more complicated
but also possesses certain advantages.
It turns out however to be relatively clear that a Riemann integrable function
is necessarily Darboux integrable. This suggests a slightly different perspective: we
view Riemann integrability as an additional property that we want to show that
every Darboux integrable function possesses. This seems like a clean way to go: one
Rb
the one hand, it obviates the need for things like R a f . On the other, it highlights
what is gained by this construction: namely, further insight on the relationship of
Rb
the upper and lower sums U (f, P) and L(f, P) to the integral a f . At the moment
the theory tells us that if f is Darboux integrable, then for every > 0 there exists
some partition P of [a, b] such that U (f, P ) L(f, P ) < . But this is not very
explicit: how do we go about finding such a P ? In the (few!) examples in which
we showed integrability from scratch, we saw that we could always take a uniform
partition Pn : in particular it was enough to chop the interval [a, b] into a sufficiently
large number of pieces of equal size. In fact, looking back at our first proof of the
integrability of continuous functions, we see that at least if f is continuous, such
uniform partitions always suffice. The key claim that we wish to establish in this
section is that for any integrable function we will have (f, Pn ) < for sufficiently
large n. In fact we will show something more general than this: in order to achieve
(f, P) < , we do not need P to have equally spaced subintervals but only to have
all subintervals of length no larger than some fixed, sufficiently small constant .
Given a function f : [a, b] R and a partition P of [a, b], we will also introduce
Rb
a more general approximating sum to a f than just the upper and lower sums,
namely we will define and consider Riemann sums. The additional flexibility of
Riemann sums is of great importance in the field of numerical integration (i.e.,
the branch of numerical analysis where we quantitatively study the error between
a numerical approximation to an integral and its true value), and it pays some
modest theoretical dividends as well. But the Riemann sums are little more than
a filigree to the main dicing property of the Darboux integral alluded to in the
last paragraph: the Riemann sums will always lie in between the lower and upper
171
sums, so if we can prove that the upper and lower sums are good approximations, in
Rb
whatever sense, to the integral a f , then the same has to be true for the Riemann
sums: they will be carried along for the ride.
4.1. Riemann sums.
Let f : [a, b] R be any function, and let P be a partition of [a, b]. Instead
of forming the rectangle with height the infimum (or supremum) of f on [xi , xi+1 ],
we choose any point xi [xi , xi+1 ] and take f (xi ) as the height of the rectanPn1
gle. In this way we get a Riemann sum i=0 f (xi )(xi+1 xi ) associated to
the function f , the partition P, and the choice of a point xi [xi , xi+1 ] for all
0 i n 1. Given a partition P = {a = x0 < x1 < . . . < xn1 < xn = b},
a choice of xi [xi , xi+1 ] for 0 i n 1 is called a tagging of P and gets
a notation of its own, say = {x0 , . . . , xn1 }. A pair (P, ) is called a tagged
partition, and given any function f : [a, b] R and any tagged partition (P, )
of [a, b], we associate the Riemann sum
R(f, P, ) =
n1
X
f (xi )(xi+1 xi ).
i=0
Let us compare the Riemann sums R(f, ) to the upper and lower sums. Just
because every value of a function f on a (sub)interval I lies between its infimum
and its supremum, we have that for any tagging of P,
L(f, P) R(f, P, ) U (f, P).
(46)
Exercise 4.1: Show that (47) holds even if f is unbounded. More precisely, show:
a) If f is unbounded above, then sup R(f, P, ) = U (f, P) = .
b) If f is unbounded below, then inf R(f, P, ) = L(f, P) = .
From inequalities (46) and (47) the following result follows almost immediately.
Theorem 8.23. For a function f : [a, b] R, the following are equivalent:
(i) f is Darboux integrable.
(ii) For all > 0, there exists a real number I and a partition P of [a, b] such that
for any refinement P of P and any tagging of P we have
|R(f, P, ) I| < .
Rb
If the equivalent conditions hold, then I = a f .
Proof. (i) = (ii): If f is Darboux integrable, then by Darbouxs Criterion
there is a partition P such that (f, P ) = U (f, P ) L(f, P ) < . For any
refinement P of P we have (f, P) (f, P ), and moreover by integrablity
Z b
L(f, P)
f U (f, P).
a
172
8. INTEGRATION
Proof. (Levermore) Let > 0. There exists a partition P of [a, b] such that
Z b
Z b
f L(f, P ) < , 0 U (f, P )
f< .
0
2
2
a
a
Suppose |f (x)| M for all x [a, b]. Let N be the number of subintervals of P .
Choose > 0 such that 2M N < 2 . We claim (48) holds for any partition P with
|P| < . Indeed, let P be any partition with |P| < , and put P 0 = P P . Now
Z b
Z b
(49)
0
f L(f, P) = ( f L(f, P 0 )) + (L(f, P 0 ) L(f, P)),
a
Z
(50)
0 U (f, P)
b
0
f = (U (f, P )
a
173
We will establish the claim by showing that the two terms on the right hand side of
(49) are each less than 2 and, similarly, that the two terms on the right hand side
of (50) are each less than 2 . Using the Refinement Lemma (Lemma 8.3), we have
Z b
Z b
f L(f, P 0 )
f L(f, P ) <
0
2
a
a
and
Z
.
2
a
a
This gives two of the four inequalities. As for the other two: since P 0 is a refinement
of P = {a = x0 < . . . < . . . < xN 1 < xN = b}, for 0 i N 1, Pi0 :=
P [xi , xi+1 ] is a partition of [xi , xi+1 ]. By the Refinement Lemma,
0 U (f, P 0 )
0 L(f, P 0 ) L(f, P) =
f U (f, P )
n1
X
f<
i=0
0 U (f, P) U (f, P 0 ) =
n1
X
i=0
Because P 0 has at most N 1 elements which are not contained in P, there are at
most N 1 indices i such that (xi , xi+1 ) contains at least one point of Pi0 . For all
other indices the terms are zero. Further, each nonzero term in either sum satisfies
0 L(f, Pi0 ) inf(f, [xi , xi+1 ]) 2M (xi+1 xi ) < 2M ,
0 sup(f, [xi , xi+1 ]) U (f, Pi0 ) 2M (xi+1 xi ) < 2M .
Because there are at most N 1 nonzero terms, we get
0 L(f, P 0 ) L(f, P) < 2M N < ,
2
0
0 U (f, P) U (f, P ) < 2M N < .
2
So the last terms on the right hand sides of (49) and (50) are each less than 2 .
We can now deduce the main result of this section.
Theorem 8.26. a) For a function f : [a, b] R, the following are equivalent:
(i) f is Darboux integrable.
(ii) There exists a number I such that for all > 0, there exists > 0 such that for
all partitions P of [a, b] of mesh at most and all taggings of P,
|R(f, P, ) I| < .
(iii) For every sequence (Pn , n ) of tagged partitions of [a, b] such that |Pn | 0,
the sequence of Riemann sums R(f, Pn , n ) is convergent.
Rb
b) If condition (ii) holds for some real number I, then necessarily I = a f .
c) If condition (iii) holds, then for every sequence (Pn , n ) of tagged partitions with
Rb
|Pn | 0, R(f, Pn , n ) a f .
Rb
Rb
Proof. a) (i) = (ii): if f is Darboux integrable, then a f = a f , and
property (ii) follows immediately from the Dicing Lemma (Lemma 8.25).
(ii) = (iii): Indeed, if (ii) holds then for any sequence of tagged partitions
(Pn , n ) with |Pn | 0, we have R(f, Pn , n ) I.
174
8. INTEGRATION
a
b
Z
lim R(f, Pn , Tn ) =
f.
a
Z
lim R(f, P2n , 2n ) =
f.
a
Rb
Rb
Since a f 6= a f , the sequence {R(f, Pn , n )}
n=1 does not converge.
b) This follows from Theorem 8.23: therein, the number I satisfying (ii) was unique.
Our condition (ii) is more stringent, so there can be at most one I satisfying it.
c) This is almost immediate from the equivalence (ii) (iii) and part b): we
leave the details to the reader.
4.3. The Riemann Integral.
By definition, a function f : [a, b] R satisfying condition (ii) of Theorem 8.26 is
Riemann integrable, and the number I associated to f is called the Riemann
integral of f . In this language, what we have shown is that a function is Riemann
integrable iff it is Darboux integrable, and the associated integrals are the same.
As mentioned above, Riemann set up his integration theory using the Riemann integral. Some contemporary texts take this approach as well. It really is a bit messier
though: on the one hand, the business about the taggings creates another level
of notation and another (minor, but nevertheless present) thing to worry about.
175
But more significantly, the more stringent notion of convergence in the definition
of the Riemann integral can be hard to work with: directly showing that the composition of a continuous function with a Riemann integrable function is Riemann
integrable seems troublesome. On the other hand, there are one or two instances
where Riemann sums are more convenient to work with than upper and lower sums.
Example 4.2: Suppose f, g : [a, b] R are both Darboux integrable. We wanted
to show that f + g is also Darboux integrable...and we did, but the argument was
slightly complicated by the fact that we had only inequalities
L(f, P) + L(g, P) L(f + g, P), U (f, P) + U (g, P) U (f + g, P).
However, for any tagging of P, the Riemann sum is truly additive:
R(f + g, P, ) = R(f, P, ) + R(g, P, ).
Using this equality and Theorem 8.23 leads to a more graceful proof that f + g is
Rb
Rb
Rg
integrable and a f + g = a f + a . I encourage you to work out the details.
Example 4.3: Let f : [a, b] R be differentiable such that f 0 is Darboux integrable. Choose a partition P = {a = x0 < x1 < . . . < xn1 < xn = b} of [a, b].
Apply the Mean Value Theorem to f on [xi , xi+1 ]: there is xi (xi , xi+1 ) with
f (xi+1 ) f (xi ) = f 0 (xi )(xi+1 xi ).
Now {xi }n1
i=0 gives a tagging of P. The corresponding Riemann sum is
R(f, P, ) = (f (x1 ) f (x0 )) + . . . + (f (xn ) f (xn1 )) = f (b) f (a).
Thus, no matter what partition of [a, b] we choose, there is some tagging such that
Rb
the corresponding Riemann sum for a f 0 is exactly f (b) f (a)! Since the integral
of an integrable function can be evaluated as the limit of any sequence of Riemann
Rb
sums over tagged partitions of mesh approaching zero, we find that a f 0 is the limit
of a sequence each of whose terms has value exactly f (b) f (a), and thus the limit
is surely f (b) f (a). This is not really so different from the proof of the supplement to the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus we gave using upper and lower sums
(and certainly, no shorter), but I confess I find it to be a more interesting argument.
Remark: By distinguishing between Darboux integrable functions and Riemann
integrable functions, we are exhibiting a fastidiousness which is largely absent in
the mathematical literature. It is more common to refer to the Riemann integral to mean either the integral defined using either upper and lower sums and
upper and loewr integrals or using convergence of Riemann sums as the mesh of a
partition tends to zero. However, this ambiguity leads to things which are not completely kosher: in the renowned text [R], W. Rudin gives the Darboux version of
the Riemann integral, but then gives an exercise involving recognizing a certain
limit as the limit of a sequence of Riemann sums and equating it with the integral
of a certain function: hes cheating! Let us illustrate with an example.
Example 4.4: Compute limn
Pn
n
k=1 k2 +n2 .
Solution: First observe that as a consequence of Theorem 8.26, for any Darboux
176
8. INTEGRATION
Now observe that our limit can be recognized as a special case of this:
n
n
n
n
X
1 X n2
1X
1
n
1X k
=
lim
=
lim
f ( ),
lim
=
lim
n n
n n
n
k 2 + n2
k 2 + n2
n
( nk )2 + 1 n n
k=1
k=1
where f (x) =
1
x2 +1 .
k=1
k=1
= arctan 1 arctan 0 = .
2
2
0 x +1
Anyway, we have done our homework: by establishing Theorem 8.26 we have earned
the right to use Darboux integral and Riemann integral interchangeably. In
fact however we will generally simply drop both names and simply speak of integrable functions and the integral. For us, this is completely safe. However,
as mentioned before, you should be aware that in more advanced mathematical
analysis one studies other kinds of integrals, especially the Lebesgue integral.
5. Lesbesgues Theorem
5.1. Statement of Lebesgues Theorem.
In this section we give a characterization of the Riemann-Darboux integrable functions f : [a, b] R due to H. Lebesgue. Lebesgues Theorem is a powerful, definitive
result: many of our previous results on Riemann-Darboux integrable functions are
immediate corollaries. Here we give an unusually elementary proof of Lebesgues
Theorem following lecture notes of A.R. Schep.
For an interval I, we denote by `(I) its length: for all < a b < ,
`((a, b)) = `([a, b)) = `((a, b]) = `([a, b]) = b a,
`((a, )) = `([a, )) = `((, b)) = `((, b]) = `((, )) = .
We define a subset S R to have measure zero if for all > 0, there is a sequence
PN
{In }Sof open intervals in R such that (i) for all N 1, n=1 `(In ) , and (ii)
5. LESBESGUES THEOREM
177
pairs (n, k) of positive integers. But this is easily solved, simply by reindexing the
terms of a double sequence an,k via a single sequence bn , e.g. as follows:
a1,1 , a1,2 , a2,1 , a1,3 , a2,2 , a3,1 , a1,4 , a2,3 , a3,2 , a4,1 , a1,5 . . . .
Theorem 8.28. (Lebesgue) For a function f : [a, b] R, let D(f ) be the set
of x [a, b] at which f is discontinuous. The following are equivalent:
(i) f is Riemann-Darboux integrable on [a, b].
(ii) f is bounded and D(f ) has measure zero.
Thus a function is Riemann-Darboux integrable on [a, b] iff it is bounded (which
we already know is necessary) and its set of discontinuities is small in the sense
of having measure zero.
Exercise: Let f, g : [a, b] R be Riemann-Darboux integrable functions. Use
Theorem 8.28 to give a quick proof that f + g and f g are both Riemann-Darboux
integrable. (Suggestion: also use Proposition 8.27.)
5.2. Preliminaries on Content Zero.
The notion of sets of measure zero is a vitally important one in the further study
of functions of a real variable. In fact one goes further, by assigning a measure
(to be entirely technicallyPprecise, an outer measure) to any subset S R as the
178
8. INTEGRATION
iI
Thus SC iI [xi , xi+1 ] and iI `([xi , xi+1 ]) < . Thus SC has content zero.
S
b) We have S = n=1 S n1 . Each S n1 has content zero, hence certainly has measure
zero. Now apply Proposition 8.27.
Exercise: Let E be a subset of R, and let E be the set of x R such that for all
> 0, there is y E with |x y| . Show that E has content zero iff E has
measure zero.
5.3. Proof of Lebesgues Theorem.
The proof of Lebesgues Theorem uses Heine-Borel (Theorem 6.17) and also the
fact that a bounded monotone sequence is convergent (Theorem 10.11), which we
will not discuss until Chapter 9. All in all this section should probably be omitted
on a first reading, and only the extremely interested student need proceed.
Step 0: Let P = {a = x0 < x1 < . . . < xn1 < xn = b} be a partition of
[a, b]. As usual, for 0 i n 1, put
mi = inf(f, [xi , xi+1 ]), Mi = sup(f, [xi , xi+1 ],
so that
L(f, P) =
n1
X
n1
X
i=0
i=0
Let , : [a, b] R be the lower and upper step functions, i.e., takes the value mi
on [xi , xi+1 ) and takes the value Mi on [xi , xi+1 ). The functions , are bounded
with only finitely many discontinuities, so are Riemann-Darboux integrable by X.X;
moreover
Z
Z
b
= L(f, P),
a
= U (f, P).
a
a
b
Z
k = U(f, Pk )
f.
a
Further, since Pk Pk+1 for all k, for all x [a, b), the sequence k (x) is increasing
and bounded above, hence convergent, say to (x); and similarly the sequence k (x)
is decreasing and bounded below, hence convergent, say to (x). For all x [a, b),
we have
k (x) (x) f (x) (x) k (x),
6. IMPROPER INTEGRALS
179
and thus
Z
Z
k
Z
f
k .
a
Rb
These inequalities show that and are Riemann-Darboux integrable and a =
Rb
Rb
= a f . Applying Lemma 8.29 to , we get that = except on a set of
a
measure zero. Let
[
E = {x [a, b] | (x) 6= (x)} Pk .
k
Since E is the union of a set of measure zero with a the union of a sequence of
finite sets, it has measure zero. We claim that f is continuous at every point of
[a, b] \ E, which will be enough to complete this direction of the proof.
proof of claim Fix x0 [a, b] \ E. Since (x) = (x), there is k Z+ such
that k (x0 ) k (x0 ) < . Further, since x0
/ Pk , there is > 0 such that k k
is constant on the interval (x0 , x0 + ), and for x in this interval we have
< k (x0 ) k (x0 ) f (x) f (x0 ) k (x0 ) k (x0 ) < ,
so f is continuous at x0 .
Step 2: Suppose now that f is bounded on [a, b] and continuous on [a, b] \ E for a
subset E of measure zero. We must show that f is Riemann-Darboux integrable
on [a, b]. Let M be such that |f (x)| M for all x [a, b]. Fix > 0. Since E has
measure
zero, there is a sequence {In }
n=1 of open intervals covering E such that
P
.
For
x
[a,
b]
\
E,
by
continuity of f there is an open interval
`(I
)
<
n
n=1
4M
Jx containing x such that for all y, z Jx , |f (y) f (z)| 2(ba)
. Applying the
Heine-Borel Theorem (Theorem 6.17) to the open covering {Ik } {Jx }x[a,b]\E of
[a, b], there is a finite subcovering, say {Ik }N
k=1 {Jxi }. Let P = {a = t0 < t1 <
. . . < tN = b} be the partition of [a, b] whose points are the endpoints of I1 , . . . , IN
and the endpoints of the intervals Jxi which lie in [a, b]. or 0 j N 1, the
subinterval (tj , tj+1 ) is contained in some Ik or some Jxi . Let I be the set of i such
that (ti , ti+1 ) is contained in Ik for some k. Then
U(f, P) L(f, P) =
N
1
X
i=0
`([ti , ti+1 ]) 2M +
iI
`([ti , ti+1 ])
iI
/
<
2(b a)
2M + (b a)
= .
4M
2(b a)
6. Improper Integrals
6.1. Basic definitions and first examples.
180
8. INTEGRATION
In other words, the limit exists as a real number iff F is bounded; otherwise, the
limit is : there is no oscillation! We deduce:
Proposition 8.30. Let f : [a,
R ) [0, ) be integrable
R on every finite interval
[a, N ] with N a. Then either a f is convergent or a f = .
InRview of Proposition 8.30, we may write the two alternatives as
a f < (convergent)
R
a f = (divergent).
R
2
Example: Suppose we wish to compute ex . Well, we are out of luck: this
integral cannot be destroyed ahem, I mean computed by any craft that we
here possess.4 The problem is that we do not know any useful expression for the
2
antiderivative of ex (and in fact it can be shown that this antiderivative is not an
elementary function). But because we are integrating a non-negative function,
we know that the integral is either convergent or infinite. Can we at least decide
which of these alternatives is the case?
Yes we can. First, since we are integrating an even function, we have
Z
Z
2
2
ex = 2
ex .
x2
ex .
6. IMPROPER INTEGRALS
181
ex = ex |
e1 ) = .
1 = (e
e
1
1
R x2
R x2
Note that we replaced 0 e
with 1 e
: does that make a difference? Well,
R1
2
yes, the difference between the two quantities is precisely 0 ex , but this is a
proper integral, hence finite, so removing it changes the value of the integral
which we dont know anyway! but not whether it converges. However we can be
2
slightly more quantitative: for all x R, x2 0 so ex 1, and thus
Z 1
Z 1
2
ex
1 = 1,
0
x2
Z
+
e
1
x2
1
= 2.735 . . . .
2 1+
e
The exact value of the integral is known we just dont possess the craft to find it:
Z
2
ex = = 1.772 . . . .
follow: if a g < then a f < , whereas if a f = then a g = .5
Theorem 8.32. (Limit Comparison Test For Improper Integrals)
Let f, g : [a, ) [0, ) be integrable on [a, N ] for all N a. Consider condition
(S): there exists b Ra and M > 0 such
R that f (x) M g(x) for all x b.
182
8. INTEGRATION
d) Suppose there exists b a such that g(x) > 0 for all x b and that limx
L with 0 < L < . Then
Z
Z
g < .
f <
f (x)
g(x)
Proof. For any b a, since f and g are integrable on [a, b], we have
Z
Z
Z
Z
f <
f < ,
g <
g < .
a
R
R
a) If f (x) M g(x) for all x b, then b f b M g = M b g. Thus if
R
R
R
R
g < , b g < , so b f < and thus finally a f < .
a
b) Note that this is precisely the contrapositive of part a)! Or to put it in a
slightly different way: suppose (S) holds. Seeking a contradiction, we also suppose
R
Rf
g < . Then by part a), a f < , contradiction.
a
(x)
(x)
c) Since limx fg(x)
= L < , there is b a such that for all x b, fg(x)
L + 1.
Thus for all x b we have f (x) (L + 1)g(x), so (S) holds.
(x)
d) Suppose limx fg(x)
= L (0, ). By part c), (S) holds, so by part a), if
R
R
1
g < , then a f < . Moreover, since L 6= 0, limx fg(x)
(x) = RL (0, ). So
a
R
part c) applies with the roles of f and g reversed: if a f < then a g < .
Although from a strictly logical perspective part d) of Theorem 8.32 is the weakest,
it is the most useful in practice.
7. Some Complements
Riemann was the first to give a complete, careful treatment of integration as a process that applies to a class of functions containing continuous functions and yields
the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus: he was certainly not the last.
In more advanced analysis courses one studies the Lebesgue integral. This is
a generalization of the Riemann integral that, extremely roughly, is modelled on
the idea of approximations in small ranges of y-values rather than small ranges of
x-values. Suppose for instance that f : [0, 1] R has a finite range y1 , . . . , yN .
Rb
Then the idea is that a f is determined by the size of each of the sets f 1 (yi ) on
which f takes the value yi . For instance this is the perspective of the expected value
in probability theory: given a function defined on a probability space, its expected
value is equal to the sum of each of the values at each possible outcome multipled
by the probability that that outcome occurs. Notice that when f is a step function,
the sets f 1 (yi ) are just intervals, and the size of an interval (a, b), [a, b), (a, b] or
[a, b] is just its length b a. However, a general function f : [0, 1] R with finite
image need not have the sets f 1 (yi ) be intervals, so the first and hardest step in
Lebesgues theory is a rigorous definition of the measure of a much more general
class of subsets of [a, b]. This has grown into a branch of mathematics in its own
right, measure theory, which is probably at least as important as the integration theory it yields. However, Lebesgues integral has many technical advantages
over the Riemann integral: the supply of Lebesgue integrable functions is strictly
larger, and in particular is much more stable under limiting operations. Later we
7. SOME COMPLEMENTS
183
will study sequences of functions fn : [a, b] R and see that a crucial issue is the
permissibility of the interchange of limit and integral: i.e., is
Z
n
lim fn ?
fn =
lim
For the Riemann integral it is difficult to prove general theorems asserting that the
left hand side exists, a phenomenon which evidently makes the identity hard to
prove! Probably the real showpiece of Lebesgues theory is that useful versions of
such convergence theorems become available without too much pain.
In classical probability theory one encounters both discrete and continuous
probability distributions. The idea of a continuous probability distribution on [a, b]
can be modelled by a non-negative integrable function f : [a, b] R such that
Rb
f = 1. This is studied briefly in the next chapter. Lebesgues theory allows for
a
distributions like the Dirac delta function, a unit mass concentrated at a single
point. It turns out that one can model such discrete distributions using a simpler
theory than Lebesgues theory due to the Dutch mathematician T.J. Stieltjes (born
in 1856; Riemann was born in 1826, Lebesgue in 1875). This is a relatively mild
souping up of Riemanns theory which views the dx as referring to the function
f (x) = x and replaces it by dg for a more general function g : [a, b] R. Some
undergraduate texts develop this Riemann-Stieltjes integral, most notably [R].
But this integral adds one extra layer of technical complication to what is already
the most technical part of the course, so I feel like in a first course like this one
should stick to the Riemann integral.
In the twentieth century various generalizations of the Riemann integral were developed which are much more closely related to the Riemann integral than the
Lebesgue integral avoiding any need to develop measure theory but are yet
more powerful than the Lebesgue integral: i.e., with a larger class of integral functions, good convergence theorems, and a simple general form of the Fundamental
Theorem of calculus. This integral is now called the Kurzweil-Henstock integral
although it was also developed by Denjoy, Perron and others. This theory however
is not so widely known, whereas every serious student of mathematics studies the
Lebesgue integral. As alluded to above, the reason is probably that the measure
theory, while a lot to swallow the first time around, is in fact a highly important
topic (in particular making a profound connection between analysis and geometry)
in its own right. It is also extremely general, making sense in contexts far beyond
intervals on the real line, whereas the Kurzweil-Henstock integral is more limited
in scope.
Aside from developing his new and more sophisticated theory of integration, Lebesgue
did much insightful work in the more classical context, as for instance his remarkable characterization of Riemann integrable functions presented above. I want to
mention a further achievement of his which has been almost forgotten until recently: from the perspective of differential calculus, a natural but very difficult
question is Which functions are derivatives? We now know that in particular
every continuous function f : [a, b] R is the derivative of some other function
F , but in order to construct the antiderivative we had to develop the theory of
184
8. INTEGRATION
CHAPTER 9
Integral Miscellany
1. The Mean Value Therem for Integrals
Theorem 9.1. Let f, g : [a, b] R. Suppose that f is continuous and g is
integrable and non-negative. Then there is c [a, b] such that
Z b
Z b
(52)
f g = f (c)
g.
a
fg
Thus aI lies between the minimum and maximum values of the continuous function f : [a, b]R R, so by the Intermediate Value Theorem there is c [a, b] such
b
Rb
fg
that f (c) = Rab g . Multiplying through by a g, we get the desired result.
a
Exercise 9.1.1: Show that in the setting of Theorem 9.1, we may take c (a, b).
Exercise 9.1.2: Show by example that the conclusion of Theorem 9.1 becomes false
even when g 1 if the hypothesis on continuity of f is dropped.
Exercise 9.1.3: Suppose that f : [a, b] R is differentiable and f 0 is continuous on [a, b]. Deduce the Mean Value Theorem for f from the Mean Value Theoem
for Integrals and the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus.1
2. Some Antidifferentiation Techniques
2.1. Change of Variables.
1Since the full Mean Value Theorem does not require continuity of f 0 , this is not so exciting.
But we want to keep track of the logical relations among these important theorems.
185
186
9. INTEGRAL MISCELLANY
Exercise 9.2.1: a) Prove Theorem 9.2. (Yes, the point is that its easy.)
b) Can the hypothesis on continuous differentiability of f and g be weakened?
Exercise 9.2.2: Use Theorem 9.2a) to find antiderivatives for the following functions.
a) xn ex for 1 n 6.
b) log x.
c) arctan x.
d) x cos x.
e) ex sin x.
f) sin6 x.
g) sec3 x, given that log(sec x + tan x) is antiderivative of sec x.
Exercise 9.2.3: a) Show that for each n Z+ , there is a unique monic (= leading
d
(Pn (x)ex ) = xn ex .
coefficient 1) polynomial Pn (x) such that dx
b) Can you observe/prove anything about the other coefficients of Pn (x)? (If you
did part a) of the preceding exercise, you should be able to find patterns in at least
three of the non-leading coefficients.)
Exercise 9.2.4: Use Theorem 9.2a) to derive the following reduction formulas:
here m, n Z+ and a, b, c R.
a)
Z
Z
n1
1
cosn2 x.
cosn x = cosn1 x sin x +
n
n
b)
Z
Z
1
1
x
2n 3
=
+
.
2
2
n
2
2
2
n1
2
2
(x + a )
2a (n 1)(x + a )
2a (n 1)
(x + a2 )n1
c)
Z
m1
1
sinm1 ax cosn+1 ax +
sin ax cos ax =
a(m + n)
m+n
m
sinm2 ax cosn ax
3. APPROXIMATE INTEGRATION
1
n1
sinm+1 ax cosn1 ax +
a(m + n)
m+n
187
Z
= (0 0) + (n + 1)
IH
xn ex dx = (n + 1)n! = (n + 1)!
2.3. Integration of Rational Functions.
3. Approximate Integration
Despite the emphasis on integration (more precisely, antidifferentiation!) techniques
in a typical freshman calculus class, it is a dirty secret of the trade that in practice
many functions you wish to integrate do not have an elementary antiderivative,
i.e., one that can be written in (finitely many) terms of the elementary functions one
learns about in precalculus mathematics. Thus one wants methods for evaluating
definite integrals other than the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. In practice it
Rb
would often be sufficient to approximate a f rather than know it exactly.2
Theorem 9.4. (Endpoint Approximation Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R be differentiable with bounded derivative: there is M 0 such that |f 0 (x)| M for
all x [a, b]. For n Z+ , let Ln (f ) be the left endpoint Riemann sum obtained by dividing
spaced subintervals: thus for 0 i n 1,
[a, b] into n equally
Pn1
ba
and
L
(f
)
=
f
xi = a + i ba
n
i=0 (xi ) n . Then
n
Z
b
(b a)2 M 1
f Ln (f )
a
2
n
Proof. Step 1: We establish the result for n = 1. Note that L1 (f ) = (b
a)f (a). By the Racetrack Principle, for all x [a, b] we have
M (x a) + f (a) f (x) M (x a) + f (a)
2It would be reasonable to argue that if one can approximate the real number R b f to any
a
188
9. INTEGRAL MISCELLANY
and thus
Z
Z
(M (x a) + f (a)))
Z
f
(M (x a) + f (a)).
a
Thus
Z b
M
M
2
(b a) + (b a)f (a)
f
(b a)2 + (b a)f (a),
2
2
a
which is equivalent to
Z
M
b
f L1 (f )
(b a)2 .
a
2
Step 2: Let n Z+ . Then
Z
!
n1
n1
b
X Z xi+1
X Z xi+1
ba
ba
f Ln (f ) = |
f f (xi )(
) |
f f (xi )(
)|
a
n
n
xi
xi
i=0
i=0
L
(f
)
n
a
2
n
2
n
n=0
Exercise 9.3.1: Show that Theorem 9.4 holds verbatim for with left endpoint sums
replaced by right endpoint sums Rn (f ).
Exercise 9.3.2: a) Suppose f : [a, b] R is increasing. Show that
Z b
1
0
f Ln (f ) (f (b) f (a))(b a) .
n
a
b) Derive a similar result to part a) for the right endpoint sum Rn (f ).
c) Derive similar results to parts a) and b) if f is decreasing.
In view of the preceding exercise there is certainly no reason to prefer left endpoint sums over right endpoint sums. In fact, if you stare at pictures of left and
right endpoint sums for a while, eventually it will occur to you to take the average
of the two of them: with = ba
n , we get
(54)
1
1
Tn (f ) = Ln (f )+Rn (f ) = f (a)+f (a+)+f (a+2) . . .+f (a+(n1))+ f (b).
2
2
On each subinterval [xi , xi+1 ] the
average of the left and right endpoint sums is
f (xi )(xi+1 xi )+f (xi+1 )(xi+1 xi )
2
area of the trapezoid whose upper edge is the line segment which joins (xi , f (xi ))
Rb
to (xi+1 , f (xi+1 ). For this reason the approximation Tn (f ) to a f is often called
the trapezoidal rule. Thats cute, but a more useful way of thinking about Tn (f )
is that it is obtained by linearly interpolating f on each subinterval [xi , xi+1 ]
via the line which matches f at the two endpoints of the interval.
Thinking of the trapezoidal rule this way suggests that Tn (f ) should, at least for
Rb
nice f and large n, a better approximation to a f than either the left or right
3. APPROXIMATE INTEGRATION
189
endpoint sums. For instance, if f is linear then on each subinterval we are approxRb
imating f by itself and thus Tn (f ) = a f . This was certainly not the case for
the endpoint rules: in fact, our proof of Theorem 9.4 showed that for each fixed
M , taking f to be linear with slope M (or M ) was the worst case scenario: if
we approximate a linear function `(x) with slope M on the interval [a, b] by the
horizontal line given by the left endpoint (say), then we may as well assume that
Rb
`(a) = 0 and then we are approximating ` by the zero function, whereas a ` is
2
the area of the triangle with base (b a) and height M (b a), hence M
2 (b a) .
Another motivation is that if f is increasing, then Ln (f ) is a lower estimate and
Rn (f ) is an upper estimate, so averaging the two of them gives something which is
closer to the true value.
The following result confirms our intuitions.
Theorem 9.5. (Trapezoidal Approximation Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R be
twice differentiable with bounded second derivative: there is M 0 such that
|f 00 (x)| M for all x [a, b]. Then for all n Z+ we have
Z
b
(b a)3 M
1
f Tn (f )
.
a
12
n2
ba
n ,
Proof. Put =
(55)
Z
i () = Tn (f )
i=0
f.
a
00i =
1 0
1
1
1
f (xi + t) + f 0 (xi + t) + tf 00 (xi + t) = tf 00 (xi + t).
2
2
2
2
Put
A = inf(f 00 , [a, b]) B = sup(f 00 , [a, b]).
Then for all 0 i n 1 and t [0, ] we have
A
B
t 00i (t) t.
2
2
0
Since i (0) = 0, integrating and applying the Racetrack Principle gives
A 2
B
t 0i (t) t2 ;
4
4
doing it again (since i (0) = 0) and plugging in t = gives
A 3
B 3
i ()
.
12
12
190
9. INTEGRAL MISCELLANY
Rb
a
f.
Looking back at the formula (54) for the trapezoidal rule we notice that we have
given equal weights to all the interior sample points but only half as much weight
to the two endpoints. This is an instance of a heuristic in statistical reasoning:
extremal sample points are not as reliable as interior points. This suggests a different kind of approximation scheme: rather than averaging endpoint Riemann sums,
lets consider the Riemann sums in which each sample point xi is the midpoint
of the subinterval [xi , xi+1 ]. Dividing the interval [a, b] into n subintervals of equal
width = ba
n as usual, this leads us to the midpoint rule
Mn (f ) =
n1
X
1
f (a + (i + )).
2
i=0
Rb
a
f = Mn (f ).
The following result concerning the midpoint rule is somewhat surprising: it gives
a sense in which the midpoint rule is twice as good as the trapezoidal rule.
Theorem 9.6. (Midpoint Approximation Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R be twice
differentiable with bounded second derivative: there is M 0 such that |f 00 (x)| M
for all x [a, b]. Then for all n Z+ we have
Z
b
1
(b a)3 M
.
f Mn (f )
a
24
n2
for i = 0, . . . , n 1, let xi = a + (i + 21 ). Also put
Z xi +t
i : [0, /2] R, i (t) =
f 2tf (xi ).
Proof. Put =
ba
n ;
xi t
3. APPROXIMATE INTEGRATION
191
i=0
f 0 (xi + t) f 0 (xi t)
00 (t)
= i ,
2t
2t
or
00i (t) = 2tf 00 (xi,t ).
Put
A = inf(f 00 , [a, b]) B = sup(f 00 , [a, b]).
Then for all 0 i n 1 and t [0,
2 ] we have
2tA 00i (t) 2tB.
Integrate and apply the Racetrack Principle twice as in the proof of Theorem 9.5,
and plug in t =
2 to get
(57)
B 3
A 3
i (/2)
.
24
24
.
f Mn (f )
2
24
n
24
n2
a
Since |A|, |B| M , we get the desired result:
Z
b
(b a)3 M
1
f Mn (f )
.
a
24
n2
For integrable f : [a, b] R and n Z+ , we define Simpsons Rule
2
1
Mn (f ) + Tn (f ).
3
3
Thus S2n (f ) is a weighted average of the midpoint rule and the trapezoidal rule.
Since our previous results suggest that the midpoint rule is twice as good as the
trapezoidal rule, it makes some vague sense to weight in this way.
S2n (f ) =
Exercise: a) Show that for any a, b R such that a+b = 1, aMn (f )+bTn (f )
Rb
b) Deduce that S2n (f ) a f .
Rb
a
f.
Let us better justify Simpsons Rule. As with the other approximation rules, it
192
9. INTEGRAL MISCELLANY
Lemma 9.7. For any quadratic function f (x) = Ax2 + Bx + C, Simpsons Rule
Rb
is exact: a f = S2n (f ) for all n Z+ .
Proof. Let = ba
2n . By splitting up [a, b] into n pairs of subintervals, it sufRb
fices to show a f = S2 (f ). This is done by a direct, if unenlightening, calculation:
Z b
B
A
(Ax2 + Bx + C) = (b3 a3 ) + (b2 a2 ) + C(b a)
3
2
a
A 2
B
= (b a)
(a + ab + b2 ) + (a + b) + C) ,
3
2
whereas
ba
a+b
f (a) + 4f
+ f (b)
6
2
!
2
ba
a+b
a+b
2
2
=
Aa + Ba + C + 4(A
+B
+ C) + (Ab + Bb + C)
6
2
2
ba
A(a2 + (a2 + 2ab + b2 ) + b2 ) + B(a + 2a + 2b + b) + 6C
=
6
A 2
B
= (b a)
(a + ab + b2 ) + (a + b) + C .
3
2
Thus whereas the endpoint rule is an approximation by constant functions and
the trapezoidal rule is an approximation by linear functions, Simpsons rule is an
approximation by quadratic functions. We may therefore expect it to be more accurate than either the Trapezoidal or Midpoint Rules. The following exercise (which
again, can be solved by a direct, if unenlightening, calculation), shows that it is
even a little better than we might have expected.
Exercise 9.3.6: Suppose f is a cubic polynomial. Show that Simpsons Rule is
Rb
exact: S2n (f ) = a f .
3. APPROXIMATE INTEGRATION
193
Since Simpsons Rule is exact for polynomials of degree at most 3 and a function f is a polynomial of degree at most three if and only if f (4) 0, it stands to
reason that Simpsons Rule will be a better or worse approximation according to
the magnitude of f (4) on [a, b]. The following result confirms this.
Theorem 9.8. (Simpson Approximation Theorem) Let f : [a, b] R be four
times differentiable with bounded fourth derivative: there is M 0 such that
|f (4) (x)| M for all x [a, b]. Then for all even n Z+ we have
Z
b
(b a)4 M
1
f Sn (f )
.
a
180
n4
Proof. For 0 i
n
2
i : [0, ] R, i (t) =
1
t(f (xi t) + 4(xi ) + f (xi + t))
3
xi +t
f.
xi t
f.
1
2
2
1 00
t(f (xi t)+f 00 (xi +t))+ (f 0 (xi +t)f 0 (xi t))+ f 0 (xi t) f 0 (xi +t)
3
3
3
3
1
1
= t(f 00 (xi + t) + f 00 (xi t)) (f 0 (xi + t) f 0 (xi t)).
3
3
So 00i (0) = 0 and
00i (t) =
1 000
1
1
1
t(f (xi +t)f 000 (xi t))+ (f 00 (xi +t)+f 00 (xi t)) f 00 (xi +t) f 00 (xi t)
3
3
3
3
1
= t(f 000 (xi + t) f 000 (xi t)).
3
000
So 000
on [xi t, xi + t], there
i (0) = 0. Applying the Mean Value Theorem to f
is (xi t, xi + t) such that
000
i (t) =
3 00
f 000 (xi + t) f 000 (xi t)
i (t)/t2 =
= f (4) ().
2
2t
Let A = inf(f (4) , [a, b]), B = sup(f (4) , [a, b]), so for all i and all t [0, ] we have
2A 2
2B 2
t 000
t .
i (t)
3
3
Integrate and apply the Racetrack Principle three times and plug in t = to get
(59)
A 3
B 3
i ()
.
90
90
194
9. INTEGRAL MISCELLANY
S
(f
)
.
n
180
n4
180
a
ba
n
gives
Exercise 9.3.7: a) In the setting of the Trapezoidal Rule, suppose moreover that
f 00 is continuous on [a, b]. Adapt the proof of Theorem 9.5 to show that there is
[a, b] such that
Z b
(b a)3 f 00 () 1
.
Tn (f )
f=
12
n2
a
b) Derive similar error equalities for the Endpoint, Midpoint and Simpson rules.
The proofs of Theorems 9.5, 9.6 and 9.8 are taken from [BS, Appendix D]. They
are admirably down-to-earth, using only the Mean Value Theorem and the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. However it must be admitted that they are rather
mysterious.
Our motivations for considering the various rules were also a little light, but
I hope the reader can see that they have something to do with polynomial interpolation. This will be taken up in more detail in Chapter 12. For now we
just mention the sobering fact that all these rules and higher-degree analogues
of them were already known to Newton, developed in jointly with his younger
collaborator Roger Cotes in the early years of the 18th century.
4. Integral Inequalities
Theorem 9.9. (The Hermite-Hadamard Inequality) Let f : [a, b] R be convex
and continuous. Then
Rb
f
a+b
f (a) + f (b)
f
.
a
2
ba
2
a+b
Proof. Let s(x) = f ( a+b
2 ) +m(x 2 ) be a supporting line for f at x =
f (b)f (a)
ba
a+b
2 ,
(60)
a .
ba
ba
ba
Now we have
Rb
R b a+b
Z b
s(x)
f ( 2 ) + m(x a+b
a+b
m
a+b
2 )
a
= a
= f(
)+
(x
)
ba
ba
2
ba a
2
2
a+b
m
b
a2
a+b
a+b
m
a+b
= f(
)+
(b a) = f (
)+
0=
,
2
ba 2
2
2
2
ba
2
3Note that there are n terms here half as many as in the previous results. This gives rise
2
to an extra factor of
1
.
2
4. INTEGRAL INEQUALITIES
Rb
S(x)dx
a
=
ba
Rb
a
(f (a) +
f (b)f (a)
ba
(x a))dx
=
ba
Rb
Rb
s
ba
195
f (a) + f (b)
.
2
a
and ba
into (60) gives
Rb
f
a+b
f (a) + f (b)
f(
) a
.
2
ba
2
a
Exercise: Show that the hypothesis of continuity in Theorem 9.9 is not necessary:
the inequality holds for any convex f : [a, b] R.
Let [a, b] be a closed interval, and let P : [a, b] [0, ) be a probability density:
Rb
i.e., P is integrable on [a, b] and a P = 1. For an integrable function f : [a, b] R,
we define the expected value
Z b
f (x)P (x)dx.
E(f ) =
a
dP (x) = d,
Rb
so a f (x)P (x)dx = E(f ) [c, d] and thus (E(f )) is defined. Now put x0 = E(f )
and let s(x) = mx + B be a supporting line for the convex function at x0 , so
s(x) (x) for all x [c, d] and s(x0 ) = (x0 ). Now
Z b
Z b
E((f )) =
(f (x))P (x)dx
(mf (x) + B)P (x)dx
a
Z
=m
Theorem 9.11 (H
olders Integral Inequality). Let p, q R>0 be such that
1
+ q = 1. Let f, g : [a, b] R be Riemann integrable functions. Then
Z
! q1
! p1 Z
Z b
b
b
(61)
f g
|f |p
|g|q
.
a
a
a
1
p
Rb
Proof. Step 1: Suppose a |f |p = 0. Let Mf and Mg be upper bound for f
and g on [a, b]. By Lemma 8.29, the set of x [a, b] such that |f |p > has content
zero: thus, for every > 0 there is a finite collection of subintervals of [a, b], of total
length at most , such that on the complement of those subintervals |f |p . On
1
this complement, |f g| p Mg and thus the sum of the integrals of |f g| over the
196
9. INTEGRAL MISCELLANY
1
complement is at most (b a) p Mg . The sum of the Riemann integrals over the
subintervals of total length of |f g| is at most Mf Mg , so altogether we get
Z b
Z b
1
|
f g|
|f g| (b a) p Mg + Mf Mg .
a
Rb
Since all the other quantities are fixed and , are arbitrary, we deduce | a f g| = 0.
Thus both sides of (61) are zero in this case and the inequality holds. A similar
Rb
argument works if a |g|q = 0. Henceforth we may suppose
Z b
Z b
If =
|f |p > 0, Ig =
|g|q > 0.
a
1
p
1
q
R
b
a
|f |p
p1 R
b
a
|g|q
q1
f2
g2 .
a
197
A similar argument holds for step functions, which become constant functions
when split up into appropriate subintervals. And now the key: the integrable functions are precisely those which can be well approximated by step functions in the
sense that the integral of the difference can be made arbitrarily small.
Okay, lets see the details: fix > 0. By Darbouxs Criterion, there is a partition
P = {a = x0 < x1 < . . . < xn1 < xn = b} of [a, b] such that
Z b
0 L(f, P)
f< .
2
a
Let g be the step function which is constantly equal to mi = inf(f, [xi , xi+1 ]) on
Rb
the subinterval [xi , xi+1 ) of [a, b], so g f and a g = L(f, P), so
Z b
0
(f g) .
2
a
Now
Z
Z
Z
b
b
b
f (x) cos(x)dx
|f (x) g(x)|| cos(x)|dx +
g(x) cos(x)dx
a
a
a
(62)
n1 Z
n1
X xi+1
X mi
+
mi cos(x)dx +
(sin(xi+1 ) sin(xi )) .
2
2 i=0 xi
i=0
Here we have a lot of expressions of the form | sin(A) sin(B)| for which an obvious
upper bound is 2. Using this, the last expression in (62) is at most
Pn1
2 i=0 |mi |
+
.
2
But this inequality holds for any > 0, so taking sufficiently large we can make
Rb
the last term at most 2 and thus | a f (x) cos(x)dx| < .
CHAPTER 10
Infinite Sequences
Let X be a set. An infinite sequence in X is given by a function x : Z+ X.
Less formally but entirely equivalently, we are getting an ordered infinite list of
elements of X: x1 , x2 , x3 , . . . , xn , . . .. Note that the function is not required to be
injective: i.e., we may have xi = xj for i 6= j. In fact, a simple but important example of a sequence is a constant sequence, in which we fix some element x X
and take xn = x for all n.
The notion of an infinite sequence in a general set X really is natural and important
throughout mathematics: for instance, if X = {0, 1} then we are considering infinite sequences of binary numbers, a concept which comes up naturally in computer
science and probability theory, among other places. But here we will focus on real
infinite sequences xbullet : Z+ R. In place of x , we will write {xn }
n=1 or
even, by a slight abuse of notation, xn .
We say that an infinite sequence an converges to a real number L if for all > 0
there exists a positive integer N such that for all n N , we have |an L| < .
A sequence is said to be convergent if it converges to some L R and otherwise divergent. Further, we say a sequence an diverges to infinity and write
limn an = or an if for all M R there exists N Z+ such that
n N = an > M . Finally, we define divergence to negative infinity: I leave it
to you to write out the definition.
This concept is strongly reminiscent of that of the limit of a function f : [1, ) R
as x approaches infinity. In fact, it is more than reminiscent: there is a direct connection. If limx f (x) = L, then if we form the sequence xn = f (n), then it
follows that limn xn = L. If xn = f (x) for a function f which is continuous or
better, differentiable then the methods of calculus can often be brought to bear
to analyze the limiting behavior of xn .
Given a sequence {xn }, we say that a function f : [1, ) R interpolates f
if f (n) = xn for all n Z+ .
Example: Supose xn =
log n
n .
Then f (x) =
log x
x
1
log x
LH
1
=
= lim x =
= 0.
x x
x 1
lim
It follows that xn 0.
Exercise: Let {an }
n=1 be a real sequence. Define f : [1, ) R as follows:
for x [n, n + 1), f (x) = (n + 1 x)an + (x n)an+1 .
199
200
n
X
1
1
1
= 1 + 2 + ... + 2.
bn =
2
i
2
n
i=1
What is the limiting behavior of an and bn ? In fact it turns out that an and
2
bn 6 : whatever is happening here is rather clearly beyond the tools we have at
the moment! So we will need to develop new tools.
1. Summation by Parts
Lemma 10.1. (Summation by Parts) Let {an } and {bn } be two sequences. Then
for all m n we have
n
n
X
X
ak (bk+1 bk ) = (an+1 bn+1 am bm ) +
(ak+1 ak )bk+1 .
k=m
k=m
Proof.
n
X
ak (bk+1 bk ) = am bm+1 + . . . + an bn+1 (am bm + . . . + an bn )
k=m
n
X
(ak+1 ak )bk+1
k=m
= an+1 bn+1 am bm
n
X
(ak+1 ak )bk+1 .
k=m
2. EASY FACTS
201
The proof of Lemma 10.1 could hardly be more elementary or straightforward: literally all we are doing is regrouping some finite sums. Nevertheless the human
mind strives for understanding and rebels against its absence: without any further
explanation, summation by parts would seem (to me at least) very mysterious.
The point is that Lemma 10.1 is a discrete analogue of integration by parts:
Z b
Z b
f 0 g.
f g 0 = f (b)g(b) f (a)g(a)
a
+
Exercise:
Let {a
Pn
Pnn}n=1 and {bn }n=1 be sequences, and for N Z , put An =
i=1 an , Bn =
i=1 bn , A0 = B0 = 0. Show that
N
X
(63)
an bn =
N
1
X
An (bn bn+1 ) + AN bN .
n=1
n=1
N
X
n=1
ab bn | = |
N
1
X
An (bn bn+1 ) + AN bN |
n=1
N
1
X
n=1
We will put Abels Lemma to use...but only much later on. For now though you
might try to prove it without using the summation by parts variant (63): by doing
so, youll probably gain some appreciation that these formulas, though in some
sense trivial, can be used in distinctly nontrivial ways.
2. Easy Facts
The following result collects some easy facts about convergence of infinite sequences.
Theorem 10.3. Let {an }, {bn }, {cn } be real infinite sequences.
a) If an = C for all n a constant sequence then an C.
b) The limit of a convergent sequence is unique: if for L1 , L2 R we have an L1
202
and an L2 , then L1 = L2 .
c) If an L and bn M then:
(i) For all C R, Can CL.
(ii) an + bn L + M .
(iii) an bn LM .
L
(iv) If M 6= 0, abnn M
.
d) If an bn for all n, an L and bn M , then L M .
e) If a b are such that an [a, b] for all n and an L, then L [a, b].
f ) (Three Sequence Principle) Suppose cn = an + bn . Then it is not possible for
exactly two of the three sequences {an }, {bn }, {cn } to be convergent: if any two are
convergent, then so is the third.
g) Suppose there exists N Z+ such that bn = an for all n N . Then for any
L [, ], an L bn L.
Most of these facts are qiute familiar, and the ones that may not be are routine.
In fact, every part of Theorem 10.3 holds verbatim for functions of a continuous
variable approaching infinity. Hence one method of proof would be to establish
these for functions or maintain that we have known these facts for a long time
and then apply the Sequence Interpolation Theorem. But be honest with yourself:
for each part of Theorem 10.3 for which you have an iota of doubt as to how to
prove, please take some time right now to write out a careful proof.
We say that a sequence {an } is eventually constant if there is C R and N Z+
such that an = C for all n N . It is easy to see that if such a C exists then it
is unique, and we call such a C the eventual value of the sequence. Of course
an eventually constant sequence converges to its eventual value e.g. by applying
parts a) and g) of Theorem 10.3, but really this is almost obvous in any event.
Proposition 10.4. Let {an } be an infinite sequence with values in the integers
Z. Then an is convergent iff it is eventually constant.
Proof. As above, it is clear that an eventually constant sequence is convergent.
Conversely, suppose an L R. First we claim that L Z. If not, the distance
from L to the nearest integer is a positive number, say . But since an L, there
exists N Z+ such that for all n N , |an L| < . But the interval (L , L + )
contains no integers: contradiction.
Now take = 1 in the definition of convergence: there is N Z+ such that for
n N , we have |an L| < 1, and since an and L are both integers this implies
an = L. Thus the sequence is eventually constant with eventual value L.
Proposition 10.4 goes a long way towards explaining why we have described a function from Z+ to R as semi -discrete. A function from Z+ to Z+ is fully discrete,
and thus the limiting behavior of such functions is very limited.
Exercise: A subset S R is discrete if for all x S, there is > 0 such that the
only element of S which lies in (x , x + ) is x.
a) Which of the following subsets of R are discrete?
(i) A finite set.
(ii) The integers Z.
(iii) The rational numbers Q.
(iv) The set { n1 | n Z+ } of reciprocals of positive integers.
4. MONOTONE SEQUENCES
203
S
(v) The set { n1 | n Z+ } {0}.
b) For a subset S R, show that the following are equivalent:
(i) S is discrete.
(ii) Every convergent sequence {an } with an S for all n is eventually constant.
It is often convenient to consider sequences whose initial term is something other
than 1. It is certainly no problem to entertain sequences starting at any integer
N0 : informally, they look like
aN0 , aN0 +1 , . . . .
Formally, instead of a function from Z+ to R, we have a function from {n Z | n
N0 } to R. This mild generalization changes nothing we have said so far or will say
later. We leave it to the reader to make her own peace with this.
3. Characterizing Continuity
Theorem 10.5. Let I be an interval, let c be an interior point of I, and let
f : I R be a function. The following are equivalent:
(i) f is continuous at c.
(ii) For every infinite sequence an c, we have f (an ) f (c).
Proof. (i) = (ii): This argument is very similar to the (easy!) proof that
a composition of continuous functions is continuous. Namely, fix > 0. Since f
is continuous at c, there is > 0 such that |x c| < = |f (x) f (c)| < .
Moreover, since an c, there exists N Z+ such that n N = |an c| < .
So if n N we have |an c| < and thus |f (an ) f (c)| < .
(ii) = (i): We prove the contrapositive: that is, we will suppose that f is not
continuous at c and find a sequence an c but such that f (an ) does not converge
to f (c). If f is not continuous at c then there exists > 0 such that for all > 0,
there is a with |a c| < and |f (a ) f (c)| . In particular, for n Z+ we
may take = n1 and choose an with |an c| < n1 and |f (an ) f (c)| , and then
indeed we have an c but f (an ) does not approach f (c).
Spivak gives a slightly more general result, the proof of which (essentially the same
as the one given above) we leave as an exercise.
Theorem 10.6. Let I be an interval, c an interior point of I, and let f :
I \ {c} R be a function such that limxc f (x) = L. Let {an }
n=1 be a real
sequence such that for all n Z+ , an I \ {c} and limn an = c. Then
lim f (an ) = L.
204
4. MONOTONE SEQUENCES
205
We are therefore able to speak of bounded sequences just as for bounded functions: i.e., in terms of the image...um, I mean the term set.
A sequence a : Z+ R is bounded above if its term set is bounded above:
that is, if there exists M R such that an M for all n Z+ . Otherwise we say
the sequence is unbounded above. Similarly, we say a is bounded below if its
term set is bounded below: that is, if there exists m R such that m an for all
n Z+ . Otherewise we say the sequence is unbounded below. Finally, a sequenc
is bounded if it is both bounded above and bounded below, and a sequence is
unbounded if it is not bounded.
Proposition 10.9. Let {an }
n=1 be a weakly increasing sequence.
a) If the sequence converges to L R, then L is the least upper bound of the term
set A = {an | n Z+ }.
b) Conversely, if the term set A has an upper bound L < , then an L.
Proof. a) First we claim L = limn an is an upper bound for the term
set A. Indeed, suppose not: then there is N Z+ with L < aN . But since the
sequence is weakly increasing, this implies that for all n N , L < aN an . Thus
if we take = aN L, then for no n N do we have |an L| < , contradicting
our assumption that an L. Second we claim L is the least upper bound. Indeed,
suppose not: then there is L0 such that for all n Z+ , an L0 < L. Let = L L0 .
For no n do we have |an L| < , contradicting our asumption that an L.
b) Let > 0. We need to show that for all but finitely many n Z+ we have
< L an < . Since L is the least upper bound of A, in particular L an for
all n Z+ , so L an 0 > . Next suppose that there are infinitely many terms
an with L an , or L an + . But if this inequality holds for ifninitely many
terms of the sequence, then because an is increasing, it holds for all terms of the
sequence, and this implies that L an for all n, so that L is a smaller upper
bound for A than L, contradiction.
Remark: In the previous result we have not used the completeness property of
R, and thus it holds for sequences with values in the rationals Q (and where by
converges we mean converges to a rational number !) or really in any ordered field.
By combining this with the least upper bound axiom, we get a much stronger result.
Theorem 10.10. Let {an }
n=1 be a weakly increasing real sequence. Let L
(, ] be the least upper bound of the term set of A. Then an L.
This is so important as to be worth spelling out very carefully. We get:
Theorem 10.11. (Monotone Sequence Theorem) a) Every bounded monotone
real sequence is convergent. More precisely:
b) Let {an } be weakly increasing. Then if {an } is bounded above, it converges to its
least upper bound, and if it is unbounded above it diverges to .
c) Let {an } be weakly decreasing. Then if {an } is bounded below, it converges to its
greatest lower bound, and it is unbounded below it diverges to .
In fact, in proving the Monotone Sequence Theorem we did not just invoke the
completeness of the real field: we used its full force, in the following sense.
206
1, 1, 1, 1, . . .
1, 1, 1, 1, . . .
1, 1, 1, 1, . . . .
There are other choices many other choices. In fact, a real sequence can be obtained as a subsequence of {an } iff it takes values in {1}.
5. SUBSEQUENCES
207
But note that something very interesting happened in the passage from our original
sequence to each of the first two subsequences. The original sequence (64) is not
convergent, due to oscillation. However, the subsequence (65) is constant, hence
convergent to it constant value 1. Similarly, the subsequence (66) converges to
its constant value 1.
Lets recap: we began with a sequence (66) which did not converge due to oscillation. However, by choosing appropriate subsequences we were able to remove the
oscillation, resulting in this case, at least in a convergent subsequence. (There
are also lots of subsequences which are inappropriate for this purpose.)
Example: Let an = n, so the sequence is
(67)
1, 2, 3, 4, . . .
1, 3, 5, 7, . . .
(69)
2, 4, 6, 8, . . .
(70)
1, 4, 9, 16, . . .
(71)
1, 2, 4, 8, . . .
And so forth. Indeed, the subsequences of (67) are precisely the increasing sequences with values in the positive integers. Note moreover that our sequence (67)
fails to converge, but not due to oscillation. It is an increasing sequence which is
not unbounded above, and thus it diverges to infinity. For that matter, so do the
subsequences (68), (69), (70), (71), and a little thought suggests that every subsequence will have this property. Thus, passing to a subsequence can cure divergence
due to oscillation, but not divergence to infinity.
Example (subsequences of a convergent sequence):
We are now well-prepared for the formal definition. In fact, we practically saw
it in the example above. Given a real sequence {an }, we view it as a function
a : Z R, n 7 an . To obtain a subsequence we choose an increasing sequence
n : Z+ Z+ , k 7 nk and form the composite function
a n : Z+ R, k 7 ank .
Less formally, we choose an increasing list n1 < n2 < . . . < nk of positive integers
and use this to tell us which terms of the sequence to take, getting
an1 , an2 , an3 , . . . , ank , . . . .
Lets formalize these observations about what passing to subsequences does for us.
Exercise: Let n : Z+ Z+ be increasing. Show that for all k Z+ , nk k.
Proposition 10.13. Let {an } be a real sequence, L [, ], and suppose
that an L. Then for any subsequence {ank }
k=1 , we have ank L.
208
209
210
211
Our task now is to explain why we have two different results called the BolzanoWeierstrass Theorem. In fact they are really equivalent results, which means
roughly that is much easier to deduce each from the other than it is to prove
either one. Indeed:
Assume the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem for sequences, and let X be an infinite subset of [a, b]. Since X is infinite, we can choose a sequence {xn }
n=1 of
distinct elements of X. Since xn X [a, b], we have a xn b for all n;
in particular, {xn } is bounded, so by Bolzano-Weierstrass for sequences there is a
subsequence xnk converging to some L [a, b]. We claim that L is a limit point for
X: indeed, for any > 0, there is K Z+ such that for all k K, |xnk L| < :
since the terms are distinct, at most one of them is equal to L and thus the interval
(L , L + ) contains infinitely many elements of X.
Assume the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem for subsets, and let {xn } be a bounded
sequence: thus there are a, b R with a xn b for all n Z+ . Let X = {xn | n
Z+ } be the term set of the sequence. If X is finite, then the sequence has a constant (hence convergent) subsequence. Otherwise X is infinite and we may apply
Bolzano-Weierstrass for subsets to get a limit point L of X. This implies: there is
n1 Z+ such that |xn1 L| < 1; having chosen such an n1 , there is n2 Z+ such
that n2 > n1 and |xn2 L| < 21 : continuing in this way we build a subsequence
{xnk } such that for all k Z+ , |xnk L| < k1 , and thus xnk L.
7. Partial Limits; Limits Superior and Inferior
7.1. Partial Limits.
For a real sequence {an }, we say that an extended real number L [, ]
is a partial limit of {an } if there exists a subsequence ank such that ank L.
Lemma 10.23. Let {an } be a real sequence. Suppose that L is a partial limit of
some subsequence of {an }. Then L is also a partial limit of {an }.
Exercise: Prove Lemma 10.23. (Hint: this comes down to the fact that a subsequence of a subsequence is itself a subsequence.)
Theorem 10.24. Let {an } be a real sequence.
a) {an } has at least one partial limit L [, ].
b) The sequence {an } is convergent iff it has exactly one partial limit L and L is
finite, i.e., L 6= .
c) an iff is the only partial limit.
d) an iff is the only partial limit.
Proof. a) If {an } is bounded, then by Bolzano-Weierstrass there is a finite
partial limit L. If {an } is unbounded above, then by Theorem 10.19a), is a
partial limit. It {an } is unbounded below, then by Theorem 10.19b) is a
partial limit. Every sequence is either bounded, unbounded above or unbounded
below (and the last two are not mutually exclusive), so there is always at least one
partial limit.
b) Suppose that L R is the unique partial limit of {an }. We wish to show that
an L. First observe that by Theorem 10.19, {an } must be bounded above and
below, for otherwise it would have an infinite partial limit. So choose M R such
212
213
Case 2: The sequence diverges to . Then is the only partial limit and
thus L = is the largest partial limit.
Case 3: The sequence is bounded above and does not diverge to . Then it
has a finite partial L (it may or may not also have as a partial limit), so
L (, ). We need to find a subsequence converging to L.
For each k Z+ , L k1 < L, so there exists a subsequence converging to some
L0 > L k1 . In particular, there exists nk such that ank > L k1 . It follows from
these inequalities that the subsequence ank cannot have any partial limit which
is less than L; moreover, by the definition of L = sup L the subsequence cannot
have any partial limit which is strictly greater than L: therefore by the process of
elimination we must have ank L.
Similarly we define the limit infimum L of a real sequence to be the infimum of the
set of all partial limits. By reflection, the proof of Theorem 10.25 shows that L is a
partial limit of the sequence, i.e., there exists a subsequence ank such that ank L.
Here is a very useful characterization of the limit supremum of a sequence {an } it is
the unique extended real number L such that for any M > L, {n Z+ | an M }
is finite, and such that for any m < L, {n Z+ | an m} is infinite.
Exercise:
a) Prove the above characterization of the limit supremum.
b) State and prove an analogous characterization of the limit infimum.
Proposition 10.26. For any real sequence an , we have
(72)
L = lim sup ak
n kn
and
(73)
L = lim inf ak .
n kn
214
8. CAUCHY SEQUENCES
215
what number the integral should be. And thats what made Darbouxs criterion
so useful: we used it to show that every continuous function and every monotone
function is integrable, but of course without having to find in any sense the value
of the integral. (This inexplicitness is not entirely a good thing, and the main point
of our discussion of Riemann sums was to make the convergence more explicit.)
Upshot: it would be nice to have some way of expressing/proving that a sequence
is convergent which doesnt have the limit of the sequence built into it. This is
exactly what Cauchy sequences are for.
8.2. Cauchy sequences.
+
A sequence {an }
such
n=1 in is Cauchy if for all > 0, there exists N Z
that for all m, n N , |am an | < .
216
The above proofs did not use completeness, and thus the results hold in any ordered
field. In contrast, the next result does crucially use the Dedekind completeness of
the real numbers, in the form of the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem.
Theorem 10.32. (Cauchy Criterion) Any real Cauchy sequence is convergent.
Proof. Let {an } be a real Cauchy sequence. By Proposition 10.30, {an } is
bounded. By Bolzano-Weierstrass there exists a convergent subequence. Finally,
by Proposition 10.31, this implies that {an } is convergent.
It can be further shown that an Archimedean ordered field F in which every
Cauchy sequence is convergent must be Dedekind complete. However, there are
non-Archimedean and thus necessarily not Dedekind complete ordered fields
in which every Cauchy sequence converges. (In fact there are non-Archimedean
ordered fields in which the only Cauchy sequences are the eventually constant sequences!) But we had better not get into such matters here.
Exercise: Is there a Cauchy criterion for a function to be differentiable at a
point? (Hint: yes. See [Ma56].)
9. Geometric Sequences and Series
A geometric sequence is a sequence {xn }
n=0 of real numbers such that there is
a fixed real number r with xn+1 = rxn . We call r the geometric ratio since, if
= r.
for all n Z+ xn 6= 0 we have xxn+1
n
Theorem 10.33. (Geometric Sequences) Let {xn } be a geometric sequence with
geometric ratio r and x0 6= 0.
a) We have xn = x0 rn .
b) If |r| < 1, then xn 0.
c) If r = 1, then xn x0 .
d) If r = 1, then the sequence is x0 , x0 , x0 , x0 , . . ., which diverges.
e) If |r| > 1, then |xn | .
Proof. a) A simple induction argument which is left to the reader.
Suppose xn L [, ]. Since xn+1 = rxn , L = limn xn+1 =
limn rxn = rL. The solutions to L = rL for r R, L [, ] are: (1, L) for
any L, (r, 0) for any r, (r, ) for positive r and (r, ) for negative r. Now:
b) If |r| < 1, then |xn+1 | = |r||xn | < |xn |, so {|xn |} is decreasing and bounded
below by 0. By the Montone Sequence Lemma, |xn | converges to a finite, nonnegative number L, and by the above analysis L = 0. Since |xn | 0, xn 0.
c), d) These are immediate and are just recorded for easy reference.
e) If |r| > 1, then |xn+1 | = |r||xn | > |xn |, so the sequence {|xn |} is increasing and
bounded below by |x0 |. By the Monotone Sequence Lemma, |xn | L (|x0 |, ],
and by the above analysis we must have L = .
For x0 , r R, we define the finite geometric series
(74)
Sn = x0 + x0 r + . . . + x0 rn .
We claim that quite luckily! we are able to obtain a simple closed-form expression for Sn . We may dispose of the case r = 1: then Sn = (n + 1). When r 6= 1, we
use a very standard trick : multiplying (75) by r gives
(75)
rSn = x0 r + . . . + x0 rn + x0 rn+1 ,
217
Sn =
n
X
x0 r k =
k=0
1 rn+1
.
1r
Having this closed form enables us to determine easily whether the sequence {Sn }
converges, and if so, to what.
Theorem 10.34. (The Geometric Series) For x0 , r R, let
Sn =
n
X
x0 r n = x0 + x0 r + . . . + x0 r n .
k=0
1
.
a) If |r| < 1, then limn Sn = 1r
b) If |r| 1, then {Sn } diverges.
Recall that f : I R is Lipschitz if (77) holds for some C > 0. If so, for
any > 0, we may independently of x choose < C , and then |x y|
= |f (x) f (y)| C < . So a Lipschitz function is uniformly continuous. A
contraction mapping is a Lipchitz mapping with Lipschitz constant C < 1.
A function f : I R is weakly contractive if:
x 6= y I, |f (x) f (y)| < |x y|.
A function f : I R is a short map if 1 is a Lipschitz constant for f , i.e.,
x, y I, |f (x) f (y)| |x y|.
Thus contractive implies weakly contractive implies short map.
Exercise: Let f : I I be differentiable.
218
219
x2 + 1.
x
2,
0<x1
1, x = 0
220
the literature, the term attracting point is often used for a weaker, local property which is studied in the following exercise.
Exercise: Let f : I I be a function. A point L I is a locally attracting
point if there exists > 0 such that f maps [L , L + ] into itself and the
restriction of f to [L , L + ] has L as an attracting point.
Now let f : I I be C 1 , and let L I be a fixed point of f .
a) Show that if |f 0 (L)| < 1, then L is a locally attracting point for f .
b) Show that if |f 0 (L)| > 1, then L is not a locally attracting point for f .
c) Exhibit f : [1, 1] R such that L = 0 is a fixed point, f 0 (0) = 1, and 0 is a
locally attracting point for f .
d) Exhibit f : [1, 1] R such that L = 0 is a fixed point, f 0 (0) = 1 and 0 is not
a locally attracting point for f .
10.3. The Contraction Mapping Theorem.
Theorem 10.39. (Contraction Mapping Theorem) Let I R be a closed interval, and let f : I I be contractive with constant C (0, 1).
a) Then f is attractive: there is a unique fixed point L, and for all x0 I, the
sequence {xn } of iterates of f under x0 converges to L.
b) Explicitly, for all x0 I and all n N,
|x0 f (x0 )|
C n.
(78)
|xn L|
1C
Proof. Step 0: By Theorem 10.36, f has at most one fixed point.
Step 1: Let x0 I, fix > 0, let N be a large positive integer to be chosen (rather
sooner than) later, let n N and let k 0. Then
|xn+k xn | |xn+k xn+k1 | + |xn+k1 xn+k2 | + . . . + |xn+1 xn |
C n+k1 |x1 x0 | + C n+k2 |x1 x0 | + . . . + C n |x1 x0 |
1 Ck
|x1 x0 |
= |x1 x0 |C n 1 + C + . . . + C k1 = |x1 x0 |C n
<
C n.
1C
1C
Since |C|< 1, C n 0, so we may choose N such that for all n N and all k N,
|x1 x0 |
1C
221
Exercise: a) Show that there is a unique real number x such that cos x = x.
b) Explain how to use (say) a handheld calculator to approximate x to as many
decimal places of accuracy as your calculator carries.
Exercise: Let f : [a, b) [a, b) be a contractive map with constant C (0, 1).
a) Show that limxb f (x) exists (as a real number!), and that by defining f at
b to be this limit, the extended function f : [a, b] R remains contractive with
constant C.5
b) Use part a) to extend the Contraction Mapping Principle to contractions f :
[a, b) [a, b), with the proviso that the unique fixed point may be b.
c) Give an example of a contraction mapping on [a, b) with fixed point b.
d) State and prove a version of the Contraction Mapping Principle valid for an
arbitrary interval.
Exercise: Let f : I I be a function. For n Z+ , let f n = f . . . f be
the nth iterate of f . Suppose that for some N Z+ , f N is contractive.
a) Show that any fixed point of f is a fixed point of f N .
b) Show that f N has a unique fixed point L I, and deduce that f has at most
one fixed point in I.
c) Show that f (L) is also a fixed point for f N , and deduce that f (L) = L: thus f
has a unique fixed point in I.
d) Show that in fact L is an attracting point for f .
e) Consider the function f : [0, 1] [0, 1] by
0, 0 x [0, 1]
f (x) =
1, x (1, 2].
Show that f is not a contraction but f f is a contraction.
10.4. Further Attraction Theorems.
Let I be an interval, and let f : I I be continuous. Recall that L I is
attracting for f if for all x0 I, the sequence of iterates of x0 under f converges to
L; above, we showed that if L is attracting for f then L is the unique fixed point
of f . Let us say sup I is an attracting point for f if for all x0 I, the sequence
of iterates of x0 under f approaches sup I (sup I = iff I is unbounded above).
Similarly, we say inf I is an attracting point for f if for all x0 I, the sequence of
iterates of x0 under f approaches inf I (inf I = iff I is unbounded below).
Theorem 10.40. Let I R be an interval, and let f : I I be continuous.
a) At least one of the following holds:
(i) f has a fixed point.
(ii) sup I is an attracting point for f .
(iii) inf I is an attracting point for f .
b) If I = [a, b] then f has a fixed point.
Proof. a) Define g : I R by g(x) = f (x) x. A fixed point of f is precisely
a root of g, so to prove part a) we may assume that g has no roots on I and show
5This is the hardest part of the problem. The result on extension will be much easier after
you have read the next section, which treats similar but more general problems. You may wish to
assume this part for now and come back to it later.
222
that either (ii) or (iii) holds. If the continuous function g has no roots then either
(I) f (x) > x for all x I or (II) f (x) < x for all x I. We will show (I) = (ii);
the very similar proof that (II) = (iii) is left to the reader.
Suppose f (x) > x for all x I. Then, for any x0 I, the sequence of iterates
is increasing. This sequence cannot converge to any element L of I, for by Lemma
10.37, L would then be a fixed point of f , contradiction. So xn must approach
sup I.
b) Let I = [a, b] and let x0 I. If there were no fixed point, then by part a) the
sequence of iterates of x0 under f would approach either sup I = b or inf I = a.
But both are elements of I, so by Lemma 10.37 either a or b is a fixed point.
Theorem 10.41. Let I R be an interval, and let f : I I be weakly
contractive. Then f has an attracting point in [inf I, sup I].
Proof. Step 0: If f has no fixed point in I, then by Theorem 10.40 either
sup I or inf I is an attracting point for f . Thus we may assume that f has a fixed
point L I, and our task is to show that L is attracting for f .
Step 1: Let x0 I, and for n N, put dn = |xn L|. If for some N we have
xN = L, then xn = L for all n N , so the sequence of iterates converges to L.
So we may assume dn > 0 for all n N, and then by weak contractivity {dn } is
decreasing. Since 0 is a lower bound, there is d 0 such that dn d. Observe
that the desired conclusion that xn L is equivalent to d = 0.
Step 2: For all n N, xn [L d0 , L + d0 ], so {xn } is bounded; by BolzanoWeierstrass, there is a convergent subsequence, say xnk y. As k we have:
|xnk L| |y L|, |xnk L| = dnk d,
|f (xnk ) L| = |xnk +1 L| = dnk +1 d, |f (xnk ) L| |f (y) L|,
so |y L| = d = |f (y) L| = |f (y) f (L)|. By weak contractivity, d = 0.
Remark: The case I = R of Theorem 10.41 is due to A. Beardon [Be06]. The case
I = [a, b] is an instance of a general result of M. Edelstein [Ed62] which is described
in the next section. Our proof of Theorem 10.41 draws ideas from Beardons proof
and also from K. Conrads treatment of Edelsteins Theorem in [CdC].
Exercise: Show that the function f : [0, 1] [0, 1] defined by f (x) =
weakly contractive but not contractive.
1
1+x
is
223
224
you will surely learn about systems of differential equations, and the most important result in this area is that with suitable hypotheses and precisions, of course
every system of differential equations has a unique solution. The now standard
proof of this seminal result uses Banachs Fixed Point Theorem!7
Let X be a metric space. Then the statement Every sequence with values in
X admits a convergent subsequence is certainly meaningful, but as is already
the case with intervals on the real line! whether it is true or false certainly depends on X. We say that a metric space is compact if every sequence with values
in X admits a convergent subsequence.
In fact every compact metric space is complete, and the proof again requires no
ideas other than the ones we have already developed: indeed, if {xn } is a Cauchy
sequence in a compact metric space, then by definition of compactness it admits
a subsequence xnk converging to some L X, and then we prove exactly as we
did before that if a subsequence of a Cauchy sequence converges to L then the
Cauchy sequence itself must converge to L.
Above we showed that a weakly contractive map on a closed, bounded (and thus
compact) interval was attractive and attributed this to M. Edelstein. What Edelstein actually showed was the following result.
Theorem 10.43. (Edelstein [Ed62]) Let X be a compact metric space, and let
f : X X be a weakly contractive mapping. Then f is attractive:
a) There is a unique fixed point L of f .
b) For all x0 X, the sequence of iterates of x0 under f converges to f .
Proof. We follow [CdC].
Step 0: The Extreme Value Theorem has the following generalization to compact
metric spaces: if X is a compact metric space, then any continuous function f :
X R is bounded and attains its maximum and minimum values. Recall that
we gave two proofs of the Extreme Value Theorem for X = [a, b]: one using Real
Induction and one using the fact that every sequence in [a, b] admits a convergent
subsequence. Since by definition this latter property holds in a compact metric
space, it is the second proof that we wish to carry over here, and we ask the
interested reader to check that it does carry over with no new difficulties.
Step 1: We claim f has a fixed point. Here we need a new argument: the one we
gave for X = [a, b] used the Intermediate Value Theorem, which is not available in
our present context. So here goes: let g : X R by g(x) = d(x, f (x)). Since f is
continuous, so is g and thus the Extreme Value Theorem applies and in particular
g attains a minimum value: there is L X such that for all y X, d(L, f (L))
d(y, f (y)). But if f (L) 6= L, then by weak contractivity we have d(f (L), f (f (L))) <
d(L, f (L)), i.e., g(f (L)) < g(L), contradiction. So L is a fixed point for f .
Step 2: The argument of Step 2 of the proof of Theorem 10.41 carries over directly
to show that L is an attracting point for f .
7In fact the title of [Ba22] indicates that applications to integral equations are being explicitly
considered. An integral equation is very similar in spirit to a differential equation: it is an
equating relating an unknown function to its integral(s).
225
226
|s1 x1 |, |s2 x2 | < , |f (s1 ) f (x1 )|, |f (s2 ) f (x2 )| < .
3
3
Then
|s1 s2 | |s1 x1 | + |x1 x2 | + |x2 s2 | < ,
and
2
|f (x1 )f (x2 )| |f (x1 )f (s1 )|+|f (s1 )f (s2 )|+|f (s2 )f (x2 )| +|f (s1 )f (s2 )|.
3
But since f : S R is uniformly continuous, we may take to be sufficiently small
so that |s1 s2 | < = |f (s1 ) f (s2 )| < 3 . For such a we get
|f (x1 ) f (x2 )| <
2
+ = ,
3
3
contradiction.
Theorem 10.47 gives necessary and sufficient conditions for a function f : S R to
admit a uniformly continuous extension to I. When I is closed and bounded, this
solves our extension problem because uniform continuity is equivalent to continuity.
However, for an interval which is not closed and bounded, being uniformly continuous is much stronger than being continuous. For instance, the only polynomial
227
functions which are uniformly continuous on all of R are the linear polynomials.
However there is an easy, but sneaky, way to soup up the Extension Theorem: if I is not closed and bounded, we dont have to extend f to I all at once;
we can do it via an increasing sequence of closed, bounded subintervals of I.
Corollary 10.48. Let S be a dense subset of R, and let f : S R. The
following are equivalent:
(i) For all M > 0, the restriction of f to S [M, M ] is uniformly continuous.
(ii) There is a unique extension of f to a continuous function f : R R.
Proof. (i) = (ii): Applying the Extension Theorem to f on S [M, M ],
we get a unique continuous extension fM : [M, M ] R. Since the extensions
are unique, for any x R, we may choose any M with M |x| and define f(x) =
fM (x): this does not depend on which M we choose. Moreover, since continuity at
a point depends only on the behavior of the function in small intervals around the
point, it is immediate that any function constructed from an expanding family of
continuous functions in this way is continuous on all of R.
CHAPTER 11
Infinite Series
1. Introduction
1.1. Zeno Comes Alive: a historico-philosophical introduction.
Humankind has had a fascination with, but also a suspicion of, infinite processes
for well over two thousand years. Historically, the first kind of infinite process that
received detailed infomation was the idea of adding together infinitely many quantitties; or, to put a slightly different emphasis on the same idea, to divide a whole
into infinitely many parts.
The idea that any sort of infinite process can lead to a finite answer has been
deeply unsettling to philosophers going back at least to Zeno,1 who believed that a
convergent infinite process was absurd. Since he had a sufficiently penetrating eye
to see convergent infinite processes all around him, he ended up at the lively conclusion that many everyday phenomena are in fact absurd (so, in his view, illusory).
We will get the flavor of his ideas by considering just one paradox, Zenos arrow paradox. Suppose that an arrow is fired at a target one stadium away. Can
the arrow possibly hit the target? Call this event E. Before E can take place,
the arrow must arrive at the halfway point to its target: call this event E1 . But
before it does that it must arrive halfway to the halfway point: call this event E2 .
We may continue in this way, getting infinitely many events E1 , E2 , . . . all of which
must happen before the event E. That infinitely many things can happen before
some predetermined thing Zeno regarded as absurd, and he concluded that the arrow never hits its target. Similarly he deduced that all motion is impossible.2
Nowadays we have the mathematical tools to retain Zenos basic insight (that a
single interval of finite length can be divided into infinitely many subintervals)
without regarding it as distressing or paradoxical. Indeed, assuming the arrow
takes one second to hit its target and (rather unrealistically) travels at uniform
velocity, we know exactly when these events Ei take place: E1 takes place after
1
1
1
2 seconds, E2 takes place after 4 seconds, and so forth: En takes place after 2n
seconds. Nevertheless there is something interesting here: we have divided the total
time of the trip into infinitely many parts, and the conclusion seems to be that
(79)
1 1
1
+ + . . . + n + . . . = 1.
2 4
2
1Zeno of Elea, ca. 490 BC - ca. 430 BC.
2One has to wonder whether he got out much.
229
230
So now we have not a problem not in the philosophical sense but in the mathematical
one: what meaning can be given to the left hand side of (79)? Certainly we ought
to proceed with some caution in our desire to add infinitely many things together
and get a finite number: the expression
1 + 1 + ... + 1 + ...
represents an infinite sequence of events, each lasting one second. Surely the aggregate of these events takes forever.
We see then that we dearly need a mathematical definition of an infinite series
of numbers and also of its sum. Precisely, if a1 , a2 , . . . is a sequence of real numbers
and S is a real number, we need to give a precise meaning to the equation
a1 + . . . + an + . . . = S.
So here it is. We do not try to add everything together all at once. Instead, we
form from our sequence {an } an auxiliary sequence {Sn } whose terms represent
adding up the first n numbers. Precisely, for n Z+ , we define
Sn = a1 + . . . + an .
The associated sequence {Sn } is said to be the sequence of partial sums of the
sequence {an }; when necessary we call {an } the sequence
of terms. Finally, we
P
say that the infinite series a1 + . . . + an + . . . = n=1 an converges to S or
has sum S if limn Sn = S in the familiar sense of limits of seqeunces. If
the sequence of partial sums {Sn } converges to some number S we say thePinfinite
series is convergent; if the sequence {Sn } diverges then the infinite series n=1 an
is divergent.
P
Thus the trick of defining the infinite sum n=1 an is to do everything in terms
of the associated sequence
P of partial sums Sn = a1 + . . . + an .
In particular
by
n=1 an = we mean the sequence of partial sums diverges
P
to , and by n=1 an = we mean the sequence
Pof partial sums diverges to
. So to spell out the first definition completely, n=1 an = means: for every
M R there exists N Z+ such that for all n N , a1 + . . . + an M .
Let us revisit the examples above using the formal definition of convergence.
Example 1: Consider the infinite series 1 + 1 + . . . + 1 + . . ., in which an = 1
for all n. Then Sn = a1 + . . . + an = 1 + . . . + 1 = n, and we conclude
1 = lim n = .
n
n=1
1
2
1
4
+ ... +
1
2n
Sn =
+ . . ., in which an =
1
2n
for all n, so
1
1
+ ... + n.
2
2
There is a standard trick for evaluating such finite sums. Namely, multiplying (80)
by 12 and subtracting it from (80) all but the first and last terms cancel, and we get
1. INTRODUCTION
231
1
1
1
1
Sn = Sn Sn = n+1 ,
2
2
2 2
and thus
Sn = 1
It follows that
1
.
2n
X
1
1
= lim (1 n ) = 1.
n
n
2
2
n=1
1
n=1 n2 +n .
We have
1
,
2
1 1
2
S2 = S1 + a2 = + = ,
2 6
3
1
3
2
= ,
S3 = S2 + a3 = +
3 12
4
3
1
4
S4 = S3 + a4 = +
= .
4 20
5
1
n
It certainly seems as though we have Sn = 1 n+1
= n+1
for all n Z+ . If this is
the case, then we have
X
n
an = lim
= 1.
n n + 1
n=1
S1 =
(n +
1)2
=
1
2.
1
n
1
n
1
IH
=
+ 2
=
+
+ (n + 1)
n + 1 n + 3n + 2
n + 1 (n + 1)(n + 2)
(n + 2)n + 1
(n + 1)2
n+1
=
=
.
(n + 1)(n + 2)
(n + 1)(n + 2)
n+2
This approach will work whenever we have some reason to look for and successfully
guess a simple closed form identity for Sn . But in fact, as we will see in the coming
232
sections, in practice it is exceedingly rare that we are able to express the partial
sums Sn in a simple closed form. Trying to do this for each given series would turn
out
Pto be1 a discouraging waste of time. We need some insight into why the series
n=1 n2 +n happens to work out so nicely.
Well, if we stare at the induction proof long enough we will eventually notice how
convenient it was that the denominator of (n+1)21+(n+1) factors into (n + 1)(n + 2).
1
Equivalently, we may look at the factorization n21+n = (n+1)(n)
. Does this remind
us of anything? I certainly hope so: this is a partial fractions decomposition. In
this case, we know there are constants A and B such that
1
A
B
= +
.
n(n + 1)
n
n+1
I leave it to you to confirm in whatever manner seems best to you that we have
1
1
1
=
.
n(n + 1)
n n+1
This makes the behavior of the partial sums much more clear! Indeed we have
1
S1 = 1 .
2
1
1 1
1
S2 = S1 + a2 = (1 ) + ( ) = 1 .
2
2 3
3
1
1 1
1
S3 = S2 + a3 = (1 ) + ( ) = 1 ,
3
3 4
4
1
and so on. This much simplifies the inductive proof that Sn = 1 n+1
. In fact
induction is not needed: we have that
1
1 1
1
1
1
Sn = a1 + . . . + an = (1 ) + ( ) + . . . + (
)=1
,
2
2 3
n n+1
n+1
the point being that every term
cancelled out by some
Pexcept the first and last is
1
other term. Thus once again n=1 n21+n = limn 1 n+1
= 1.
Finite sums which cancel in this way are often called telescoping sums, I believe P
after those old-timey collapsible nautical telescopes. In general an infinite
233
lucky), then in order to prove it you do not need to do anything so fancy as mathematical induction (or fancier!). Rather, it will suffice to just compute that S1 = a1
and for all n 2, Sn RSn1 = an . This is the discrete analogue of the fact that if
you want to show that f dx = F i.e., you already have a function F which you
believe is an antiderivative of f then you need not use any integration techniques
whatsoever but may simply check that F 0 = f .
Pn
Exercise: Let n Z+ . We define the nth harmonic number Hn = k=1 k1 =
1
1
1
1 + 2 + . . . + n . Show that for all n 2, Hn Q \ Z. (Suggestion: more specifically,
show that for all n 2, when written as a fraction ab in lowest terms, then the
denominator b is divisible by 2.)3
+
Exercise:
P Let1 k Z . Use the method of telescoping sums to give an exact formula
for n=1 n(n+k) in terms of the harmonic number Hk of the previous exercise.
of these questions: for a geometric series n=N crn , we know that the series concr N
. We should keep this success
verges iff |r| < 1 and in that case its sum is 1r
story in mind, both because geometric series are ubiquitous and turn out to play
a distinguished role in the theory in many ways, but also because other examples
of series in which we can answer Question 11.1b) i.e., determine the sum of a
convergent series are much harder to come by. Frankly, in a standard course
on infinite series one all but forgets about Question 11.1b) and the game becomes
simply to decide whether a given series is convergent or not. In these notes we try
to give a little more attention to the second question in some of the optional sections.
In any case, there is a certain philosophy at work when one is, for the P
moment,
234
P
Thus if limn Tn = n=N +1 an exists, so does limn SN +n = limn Sn =
P
P
PN
an . Conversely if
n=1 an exists, then
Pn=1
Pso does limn k=1 ak + Tn =
n
k=1 ak + limn Tn , hence limn Tn =
n=N +1 an exists.
Similarly, if we are so inclined (and we will be, on occasion), we could add finitely
many terms to the series, or for that matter change finitely many terms of the
series, without affecting the convergence. We record this as follows.
Proposition 11.2. The addition, removal or altering of any finite number of
terms in an infinite series does not affect the convergence or divergence of the series
(though of course it may change the sum of a convergent series).
As the reader has probably already seen for herself, reading someone elses formal
proof of this result can be more tedious than enlightening, so we leave it to the
reader to construct a proof that she finds satisfactory.
P
Because the convergence or divergence of a series n=1 an is not affected by changing
P the lower limit 1 to any other integer, we often employ a simplified notation
n an when discussing series only up to convergence.
P
P
Proposition 11.3. Let n=1 an , n=1 bn be two infinite series, and let be
any real
Pnumber.
P
P
a) If n=1 an = A and n=1 bn = B are both convergent, then the series n=1 an +
bn is P
also convergent, with sum A + B.
P
235
We will often apply theP
contrapositive form of Theorem 11.4: if for a series
we have an 9 0,4 then n an diverges.
an
Warning: The P
converse of Theorem 11.4 is not valid! It may well be the case
that an 0 but n an diverges. Later we will see many examples. Still, when put
under duress (e.g. while taking an exam) many students can will themselves into
believing that the converse might be true. Dont do it!
P (x)
be a rational function. The polynomial Q(x) has only finitely
Exercise: Let Q(x)
many roots, so we may choose N Z+ such that for all n N , Q(x) 6= 0. Show
P P (n)
that if deg P deg Q, then n=N Q(n)
is divergent.
an | .
n=N
PN +k
In other words the supremum of the absolute values of the finite tails | n=N an |
is at most . This gives a nice way of thinking about the Cauchy criterion.
4This means: a L 6= 0, or a diverges.
n
n
236
P
Proposition 11.6. An infinite series n=1 an converges
P if and only if: for all
> 0, there exists N0 Z+ such that for all N N0 , | n=N an | < .
In other (less precise) words, an infinite series converges iff by removing sufficiently
many of the initial terms, we can make what remains arbitrarily small.
3. Series With Non-Negative Terms I: Comparison
3.1. The sum is the supremum.
Starting
in this section we get down to business by restricting our attention to
P
series n=1 an with an 0 for all n Z+ . This simplifies matters considerably
and places an array of powerful tests at our disposal.
Why? Assume an 0 for all n Z+ and consider the sequence of partial sums:
S1 = a1 a1 + a2 = S2 a1 + a2 + a3 = S3 ,
and so forth. In general, Sn+1 Sn = an+1 0, so the sequence of partial sums
{Sn } is increasing. Applying the Monotone Sequence Lemma we get:
P
Proposition 11.7. Let n an be an infinite series with an 0 for all n. Then
the series converges if and only if the partial sums are bounded above, i.e., if and
only if there exists M R such that for all n, a1 + . . . + an M . Moroever if the
series converges, its sum is precisely the least upper bound of the sequence of partial
sums. If the partial sums are unbounded, the series diverges to .
Because of this, when dealing
with series with non-negative terms
P
P we may express
convergence by writing n an < and divergence by writing n an = .
3.2. The Comparison Test.
P
Example: Consider the series n=1 n21n . Its sequence of partial sums is
1
1
1
1
1
Tn = 1
+
+ ... +
.
2
2
4
n
2n
Unfortunately we do not (yet!) know a closed form expression for Tn , so it is
not possible for us to compute limn Tn directly. But if we just want P
to decide
whether the series converges, we can compare it with the geometric series n=1 21n :
Sn =
1 1
1
+ + ... + n.
2 4
2
Since n1 1 for all n Z+ , we have that for all n Z+ , n21n 21n . Summing these
inequalities from k = 1 to n gives Tn Sn for all n. By our work with geometric
series we know that Sn 1 for all n and thus also TnP
1 for all n. Therefore our
given series has partial sums bounded above by 1, so n=1 n21n 1. In particular,
the series converges.
P
Example:
conside the series n=1 n. Again, a closed form expression for Tn =
237
P
P
Theorem 11.8. (Comparison Test) Let n=1 an , n=1 bn be two series with
non-negative terms, and suppose that an bn for all n Z+ . Then
In particular: if
n bn
< then
an
bn .
n=1
n=1
an < , and if
an = then
n bn
= .
Proof. There is really nothing new to say here, but just to be sure: write
Sn = a1 + . . . + an , Tn = b1 + . . . + bn .
Since ak bk for all k we have Sn Tn for all n and thus
an = sup Sn sup Tn =
n=1
bn .
n=1
X
1
1
1
1
1
=1+1+ +
+
+ ... +
+ ....
n!
2
2
3
2
4
2
... n
n=0
We would like to show that the series converges by comparison, but what to compare
it to? Well, there is always the geometric series! Observe that the sequence n!
grows faster than any geometric rn in the sense that limn rn!n = . Taking
1
reciprocals, it follows that for any 0 < r < 1 we will have n!
< r1n not necessarily
+
for all n Z , but at least for all sufficiently large n. For instance, one easily
1
1
establishes by induction that n!
< 21n if and only if n 4. Putting an = n!
and
1
bn = 2n we cannot apply the Comparison Test because we have an bn for all
n 4 rather than for all n 0. But this objection is more worthy of a bureaucrat
than a mathematician: certainly the idea of the Comparison Test is applicable here:
X
X
X
X
1
1
1
1
8 1
67
=
+
8/3 +
= + =
< .
n
n!
n!
n!
2
3
8
24
n=0
n=0
n=4
n=4
So the series converges. More than that, we still retain a quantitative estimate on
the sum: it is at most (in fact strictly less than, as a moments thought will show)
67
24 = 2.79166666 . . .. (Perhaps this reminds you of e = 2.7182818284590452353602874714 . . .,
which also happens to be a bit less than 67
24 . It should! More on this later...)
We record the technique of the preceding example as a theorem.
238
P P
Theorem 11.9. (Delayed Comparison Test) Let n=1 , n=1 bn be two series
with non-negative terms. Suppose that there exists N Z+ such that for all n > N ,
an bn . Then
!
X
X
X
an
an bn +
bn .
n=1
In particular: if
n bn < then
n=1
Pn=1
P
P
a
<
,
and
if
n
n
n an = then
n bn = .
X
X
1
1
1
=
= 1,
n2 + n n=1 n n + 1
n=1
P
and in particular that n n21+n converges. For large n, n21+n is close to n12 . More
precisely, putting an = n21+n and bn = n12 we have an bn , i.e.,
an
n2
1
= lim 2
= lim
n bn
n n + n
n 1 +
lim
1
n
= 1.
239
P
P
Applying Theorem 11.11, we find that n n21+n and n n12 converge or diverge
P
together. Since the former series converges, we deduce that n n12 converges, even
though the Comparison Test does not directly apply.
Exercise: Let
P (x)
Q(x)
n=0
an and
n=0 bn
In order to forestall possible confusion, let us point out that many students are
tempted to consider the following product operation on series:
!
!
X
X
X
??
an
bn =
an bn .
n=0
n=0
n=0
In other words, given two sequences of terms {an }, {bn }, we form a new sequence
of terms {an bn } and then theP
associated series.
P In fact this is not a very useful
candidate for the product. If n an = A and n bn = B, we want our product
series to converge to AB. But for instance, take {an } = {bn } = 21n . Then
an =
n=0
bn =
n=0
1
1
1
2
= 2,
so AB = 4, whereas
X
n=0
Unfortunately
4
3
an bn =
X
1
1
=
n
4
1
n=0
1
4
4
.
3
Plenty! We have ignored the laws of algebra for finite sums: e.g.
(a0 + a1 + a2 )(b0 + b1 + b2 ) = a0 b0 + a1 b1 + a2 b2 + a0 b1 + a1 b0 + a0 b2 + a1 b1 + a2 b0 .
The product is different and more complicated and indeed, if all the terms are
positive, strictly larger than just a0 b0 + a1 b1 + a2 b2 . We have forgotten about
the cross-terms which show up when we multiply one expression involving several
terms by another expression involving several terms.5
Let us try again at formally multiplying out a product of infinite series:
(a0 + a1 + . . . + an + . . .)(b0 + b1 + . . . + bn + . . .)
= a0 b0 + a0 b1 + a1 b0 + a0 b2 + a1 b1 + a2 b0 + . . . + a0 bn + a1 bn1 + . . . + an b0 + . . . .
5To the readers who did not forget about the cross-terms: my apologies. But it is a common
enough misconception that it had to be addressed.
240
The notation is getting complicated. In order to shoehorn the right hand side into
a single infinite series, we need to either (i) choose some particular ordering of the
terms ak b` or (ii) collect some terms together into an nth term.
For the moment we choose the latter: we define for any n N
n
X
cn =
ak bnk = a0 bn + a1 bn1 + . . . + an bn
k=0
X
n=0
cn =
n
X
n=0
k=0
n=0
an and
!
ak bnk
n=0 bn
to be the series
Theorem
11.12. LetP{an }
n=0 , {bn }n=0 be two series
P
Pnwith non-negative terms.
Let
a
=
A
and
b
=
B.
Putting
c
=
n
n
n
n=0
k=0 ak bnk we have that
P n=0
c
=
AB.
In
particular,
the
Cauchy
product
series
converges iff the two
n
n=0
P
P
factor series n an and n bn both converge.
So the box product clearly converges to the product of the sums of the two series.
This suggests that we compare the Cauchy product to the box product. The entries
of the box product can be arranged to form a square, viz:
N = a0 b0 + a0 b1 + . . . + a0 bN
+a1 b0 + a1 b1 + . . . + a1 bN
..
.
+aN b0 + aN b1 + . . . + aN bN .
On the other hand, the terms of the N th partial sum of the Cauchy product can
naturally be arranged in a triangle:
CN =
a0 b0
+a0 b1 + a1 b0
+ a0 b2 + a1 b1 + a2 b0
+a0 b3 + a1 b2 + a2 b1 + a3 b0
..
.
+a0 bN + a1 bN 1 + a2 bN 2 + . . . + aN b0 .
Thus while N is a sum of (N + 1)2 terms, CN is a sum of 1 + 2 + . . . + N + 1 =
(N +1)(N +2)
terms: those lying on our below the diagonal of the square. Thus in
2
considerations involving the Cauchy product, the question is to what extent one
can neglect the terms in the upper half of the square i.e., those with ai bj with
i + j > N as N gets large.
Here, since all the ai s and bj s are non-negative and N contains all the terms
of CN and others as well, we certainly have
CN N = AN BN AB.
Thus C = limN CN AB. For the converse, the key observation is that if we
make the sides of the triangle twice as long, it will contain the box: that is, every
term of N is of the form ai bj with 0 i, j N ; thus i + j 2N so ai bj appears
as a term in C2N . It follows that C2N N and thus
C = lim CN = lim C2N lim N = lim AN BN = AB.
N
X
X
X
C=
an = AB =
an
bn .
n=0
n=0
n=0
4. Series With Non-Negative Terms II: Condensation and Integration
P
We have recently been studying criteria for convergence of an infinite series n an
which are valid under the assumption that an 0 for all n. In this section we place
ourselves under more restrictive hypotheses: that for all n N, an+1 an 0,
i.e., that the sequence of terms is non-negative and decreasing.
Remark: Its no loss of generality to assume an > 0 for all n. If not, aN = 0 for
some N and, since the terms are assumed decreasing we have 0 = aN = aN +1 = . . .
PN 1
and our infinite series reduces to the finite series n=1 an : this converges!
4.1. The Harmonic Series.
P 1
Consider
n=1 n , the harmonic series. Does it converge? None of the tests
we have developed so far are up to the job: especially, an 0 so the Nth Term
Test is inconclusive.
Let us take a computational approach by looking at various partial sums. S100
is approximately 5.187. Is this close to a familiar real number? Not really. Next
we compute S150 5.591 and S200 5.878. Perhaps the partial sums never exceed
6? (If so, the series would converge.) Lets try a significantly larger partial sums:
S1000 7.485, so the above guess is incorrect. Since S1050 7.584, we are getting
the idea that whatever the series is doing, its doing it rather slowly, so lets instead
start stepping up the partial sums multiplicatively:
S100 5.878.
S103 7.4854.
S104 9.788.
S105 12.090.
Now there is a pattern for the perceptive eye to see: the difference S10k+1 S10k
appears to be approaching 2.30 . . . = log 10. This points to Sn log n. If this is so,
then since log n the series would diverge. I hope you notice that the relation
between n1 and log n is one of a function and its antiderivative. We ask the reader
to hold this thought until we discuss the integral test a bit late on.
242
For now, we give the following brilliant and elementary argument due to Cauchy.
Consider the terms arranged as follows:
1
1 1
1 1 1 1
+
+
+
+ + +
+ ...,
1
2 3
4 5 6 7
i.e., we group the terms in blocks of length 2k . The power of 21 which begins each
block is larger than every term in the preceding block, so if we replaced every term
in the current block the the first term in the next block, we would only decrease
the sum of the series. But this latter sum is much easier to deal with:
X
1
1 1
1 1 1 1
1 1 1
1
+
+
+
+ + +
+ . . . = + + + . . . = .
n
2
4
4
8
8
8
8
2
2 2
n=1
P
Therefore the harmonic series n=1 diverges.
Exercise: Determine the convergence of
1
1
n1+ n
P (x)
Exercise: Let Q(x)
be a rational function with deg Q deg P = 1. Show that
P P (n)
6
n=N Q(n) diverges.
P (x)
Q(x) ,
the series
P (n)
n=N Q(n)
con
a) We have n=1 P
an n=0 2n a2n 2 n=1 an .
P
b) Thus the series n an converges iff the condensed series n 2n a2n converges.
Proof. We have
X
an = a1 + a2 + a3 + a4 + a5 + a6 + a7 + a8 + . . .
n=1
a1 + a2 + a2 + a4 + a4 + a4 + a4 + 8a8 + . . . =
2n a2n
n=0
X
=2
an .
n=1
6Take N larger than any of the roots of Q(x), so that every term in the sum is well defined.
The Cauchy Condensation Test is, I think, an a priori interesting result: it says
that, under the given hypotheses, in order to determine whether a series converges
we need to know only a very sparse set of the terms of the series whatever is
happening in between a2n and a2n+1 is immaterial, so long as the sequence remains
decreasing. This is a very curious phenomenon, and of couse without the hypothesis
that the terms are decreasing, nothing like this could hold.
On the other hand, it may be less clear thatP
the Condensation Test is of any
practical use: afterP
all, isnt the condensed series n 2n a2n more complicated than
the original series n an ? In fact the opposite is often the case: passing from the
given series to the condensed series preserves the convergence or divergence but
tends to exchange subtly convergent/divergent series for more obviously (or better:
more rapidly) converging/diverging series.
Example: Fix a real number p and consider the p-series7
is to find all values of p for which the series converges.
1
n=1 np .
Our task
Step 1: The sequence an = n1p has positive terms. The terms are decreasing iff
the sequence np is increasing iff p > 0. So we had better treat the cases p 0 separately. First, if p < 0, then limn n1p = limn n|p| = , so the p-series diverges
P
P
by the nth term test. Second, if p = 0 then our series is simply n n10 = n 1 = .
So the p-series obviously diverges when p 0.
Step 2: Henceforth we assume P
p > 0, so that the hypotheses
Cauchys
P n nofp
P nCondenp
np
sation
Test
apply.
We
get
that
n
converges
iff
2
(2
)
=
=
n
n
n2 2
P 1p n
(2
)
converges.
But
the
latter
series
is
a
geometric
series
with
geometric
n
ratio r = 21p , so it converges iff |r| < 1 iff 2p1 > 1 iff p > 1.
Thus we have proved the following important result.
P
Theorem 11.15. For p R, the p-series n n1p converges iff p > 1.
Example (p-series continued): Let
Pp > 1. By applying part b) of Cauchys Condensation Test we showed that n=1 n1p < . What about part a)? It gives an
explicit upper bound on the sum of the series, namely
X
X
X
1
1
n n p
2
(2
)
=
(21p )n =
.
p
n
1 21p
n=0
n=0
n=1
X
1
1
= 2.
2
n
1
212
n=1
1024
X
n=1
1
= 1.643957981030164240100762569 . . . .
n2
244
P
So it seems like n=1 n12 1.64, whereas the Condensation Test tells us that it
is at most 2. (Note that since the terms are positive, simply adding up any finite
number of terms gives a lower bound.)
The following
exercise gives a technique for using the Condensation Test to esP
timate n=1 n1p to arbitrary accuracy.
Exercise: Let N be a non-negative integer.
a) Show that under the hypotheses of the Condensation Test we have
an
2n a2n+N .
n=0
n=2N +1
1
1
Example:
n=2 n log n . an = n log n is positive and decreasing (since its reciprocal
is positive and increasing) so the Condensation Test applies. We get that the
convergence of the series is equivalent to the convergence of
X
1 X1
2n
=
= ,
n
n
2 log 2
log 2 n n
n
P 1
so the series diverges. This is rather subtle: we know that for any > 0, n nn
converges, since it is a p-series with p = 1 + . But log n grows more slowly than
n for any > 0, indeed slowly enough so that replacing n with log n converts a
convergent series to a divergent one.
1
n log(n!)
converges.
Exercise: Let P
p, q, r be positive real numbers.
a) Show that n n(log1 n)q converges iff q > 1.
P
1
b) Show that n np (log
n)q converges iff p > 1 or (p = 1 and q > 1).
P
c) Find all values of p, q, r such that n np (log n)q1(log log n)r converges.
The pattern of Exercise X.X can be continued indefinitely, giving series which converge or diverge excruciatingly slowly, and showing that the difference between
convergence and divergence can be arbitarily subtle.
4.3. The Integral Test.
Theorem 11.16. (Integral Test) Let f : [1, ) R be a positive decreasing
function, and for n Z+ put an = f (n). Then
Z
X
X
an
f (x)dx
an .
n=2
n=1
R
1
f (x)dx converges.
n=1
Remark: The Integral Test is due to Maclaurin8 [Ma42] and later in more modern
form to Cauchy [Ca89].
Among series which arise naturally in undergraduate analysis, it usually holds that
the Condensation Test can be successfully applied to determine convergence / divergence of a series if and only if the Integral Test can be successfully applied.9
Example:
Let us use the Integral Test to determine the set of p > 0 such
that
R dx
P 1
converges.
Indeed
the
series
converges
iff
the
improper
integral
is
p
n n
1 xp
finite. If p 6= 1, then we have
Z
x1p x=
dx
=
|
.
p
x
1 p x=1
1
The upper limit is 0 if p 1 < 0 p > 1 and is if p < 1. Finally,
Z
dx
= log x|
x=1 = .
x
1
So, once again, the p-series diverges iff p > 1.
Exercise: Verify that all of the above examples involving the Condensation Test
can also be done using the Integral Test.
Given the similar applicability of the Condensation and Integral Tests, it is perhaps
not so surprising that many texts content themselves to give one or the other. In
calculus texts, one almost always finds the Integral Test, which is logical since often
integration and then improper integation are covered earlier in the same course in
which one studies infinite series. In elementary analysis courses one often develops
sequences and series before the study of functions of a real variable, which is logical because a formal treatment of the Riemann integral is necessarily somewhat
involved and technical. Thus many of these texts give the Condensation Test.
The Condensation Test and the Integral Test have a similar range of applicability: in most textbook examples, where one test succeeeds, so will the other.
From an aesthetic standpoint, the Condensation Test is more appealing (to me).
On the other hand, under a mild additional hypothesis the Integral Test can be
used to give asymptotic expansions for divergent series. Our treatment of the
8Colin Maclaurin, 1698-1746
9Why this should be so is not clear to me: the observation is purely empirical.
246
an =
K1
X
n=1
K1
X
n=1
an
an +
n=1
K1
X
N
X
an
(1 + )bn
n=1
N
X
an +
n=1
n=K
K1
X
N
X
(1 + )bn
n=K
(1 + )bn = C,K + (1 + )
n=1
N
X
bn ,
n=1
PN
say, where C,K does not depend on N . Dividing both sides by n=1 bn and using
PN
PN
an
limN n=1 bn = , we find that Pn=1
is at most 1 + 2 for all sufficiently
N
n=1 bn
P
P
large N . Because our hypotheses are symmetric in n an and n bn , we also have
that
PN
n=1 bn
PN
n=1 an
Theorem P
11.18. Let f : [1, ) (0, ) be continuous and monotone. Suppose the series n f (n) diverges and that as x , f (x) f (x + 1). Then
Z N
N
X
f (n)
f (x)dx.
n=1
Proof.
R n+1 Case 1: Suppose f is increasing. Then, for n x n + 1, we have
f (n) n f (x)dx f (n + 1), or
R n+1
f (x)dx
f (n + 1)
.
1 n
f (n)
f (n)
By assumption we have
lim
f (n + 1)
= 1,
f (n)
247
R n+1
Applying Lemma 11.17 with an = f (n) and bn = n f (x)dx, we conclude
Z N +1
N Z k+1
N
X
X
f (x)dx =
f (x)dx
f (n).
1
k=1
n=1
Further, we have
R N +1
1
lim
RN
f (x)dx
f (x)dx
f (N + 1)
= lim
= 1,
N f (N )
where in the starred equality we have applied LHopitals Rule and then the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. We conclude
Z N
Z N +1
N
X
f (x)dx
f (x)dx
f (n).
1
n=1
or
R n+1
f (x)dx
f (n + 1)
n
1.
f (n)
f (n)
Once again, by our assumption that f (n) f (n + 1) and the Squeeze Principle we
get (82); the remainder of the proof proceeds as in the previous case.
5. Series With Non-Negative Terms III: Ratios and Roots
P
We continue our analysis of series n an with an 0 for all n. In this section we
introduce two important tests based on a very simple yet powerful idea: if for
sufficiently large n an is bounded above by a non-negative constant M times rn for
0 rP
< 1, then the series converges by comparison to the convergent geometric
series n M rn . Conversely, if for sufficiently large n an is bounded below by a
positive constant M times rn for
P r 1, then the series diverges by comparison to
the divergent geometric series n M rn .
5.1. The Ratio Test.
P
Theorem 11.19. (Ratio Test) Let n an be a series with an > 0 for all n.
a) Suppose there exists N Z+ and 0 < r < 1 such that for all n N , aan+1
r.
n
P
Then the series n an converges.
b) Suppose there exists N Z+ and r 1 such that for all n N , aan+1
r. Then
n
P
the series n an diverges.
c) The hypothesis of part a) holds if = limn aan+1
exists and is less than 1.
n
exists
and is greater than 1.
d) The hypothesis of part b) holds if = limn aan+1
n
Proof. a) Our assumption is that for all n N , aan+1
r < 1. Then
n
an+2 an+1
2
= an+1 an r . An easy induction argument shows that for all k N,
an+2
an
aN +k
rk ,
aN
so
aN +k aN rk .
248
X
X
X
ak =
aN +k
aN rk < ,
k=N
k=0
k=0
an+1
an
xn+1
(n+1)!
xn
n!
x
.
n+1
a) Suppose therePexists N Z+ and 0 < r < 1 such that for all n N , ann r.
Then the series n an converges.
1
n
b) Suppose
P that for infinitely many positive integers n we have an 1. Then the
series n an diverges.
1
c) The hypothesis of part a) holds if = limn ann exists and is less than 1.
1
d) The hypothesis of part b) holds if = limn ann exists and is greater than 1.
Exercise: Prove Theorem 11.20.
5.3. Ratios versus Roots.
It is a fact a piece of calculus folklore that the Root Test is stronger than
the Ratio Test. That is, whenever the ratio test succeeds in determining the convergence or divergence of a series, the root test will also succeed.
In order to explain this result we need to make use of the limit infimum and limit
249
supremum. First we recast the ratio and root tests in those terms.
Exercise: Let
Exercise: Let
P
a) Show that if < 1, the series n an converges.
P
b) Show that if > 1, the series n an diverges.10
Exercise: Consider the following conditions on a real sequence {xn }
n=1 :
(i) lim supn xn > 1.
(ii) For infinitely many n, xn 1.
(iii) lim supn xn 1.
a) Show that (i) = (ii) = (iii) and that neither implication can be reversed.
b) Explain why the result of part b) of the previous Exercise is weaker than part
b) of Theorem 11.20.
1
P
c) Give anPexample of a non-negative series n an with = lim supn ann = 1
such that n an = .
P
Proposition 11.21. For any series n an with positive terms, we have
1
1
an+1
an+1
= lim inf
= lim inf ann lim sup ann = lim sup
.
n
n
an
an
n
n
Exercise: Let A and B be real numbers with the following property: for any real
number r, if A < r then B r. Show that B A.
Proof. Step 1: For any sequence {xn }, lim inf xn lim sup xn , hence .
Step 2: We show that . For this, suppose r > , so that for all sufficiently
large n, aan+1
r. As in the proof of the Ratio Test, we have an+k < rk an for all
n
k N. We may rewrite this as
a
n
an+k < rn+k n ,
r
or
1
a n+k
1
n
n+k
an+k
<r n
.
r
Now
1
a n+k
1
1
n
k
= lim sup ann = lim sup an+k
lim sup r n
= r.
r
n
k
k
By the preceding exercise, we conclude .
Step 3: We must show that . This is very similar to the argument of Step 2,
and we leave it as an exercise.
10This is not a typo: we really mean the limsup both times, unlike in the previous exercise.
250
Thus the Ratio Test limit exists (no need for liminfs or limsups) and is equal to 0,
so the series converges. If instead we tried the Root Test we would have to evaluate
1
1 n
limn ( n!
) . This is not so bad if we keep our head e.g. one can show that for
1
1
1 n
any fixed R > 0 and sufficiently large n, n! > Rn and thus ( n!
) ( R1n ) n = R1 .
Thus the root test limit is at most R1 for any positive R, so it is 0. But this is
elaborate compared to the Ratio Test computation, which was immediate.
Turning these ideas around, Proposition 11.21 can be put to the following
sneaky use.
Corollary 11.22. Let {an }
n=1 be a sequence of positive real numbers. Assume
that limn
an+1
an
Proof. Indeed, the hypothesis gives that for the infinite series
= L, so by Proposition 11.21 we must also have = L.
an we have
b) For R, limn n n .
1
c) limn (n!) n .
6. Absolute Convergence
6.1. Introduction to absolute convergence.
We turn now to the serious study of series with both positive and negative terms.
6. ABSOLUTE CONVERGENCE
251
It turns out that under one relatively mild additional hypothesis, virtually all of
our work on series with non-negative terms can be usefully applied in this case. In
this section we study this wonderful hypothesis: absolute convergence. (In the next
section we get really serious by studying series in the absence of absolute convergence. This will lead to surprisingly delicate and intricate considerations.)
P
P
A
P real series n an is absolutely convergent if n |an | converges. Note that
it is convergent
n |an | is a series with non-negative terms, so to decide whether
P
we may use allP
the tools of the last three sections. A series n an which converges
but for which n |an | diverges is said to be nonabsolutely convergent.11
The P
terminology absolutely convergent suggests that the convergence
P of the series n |an | is somehow better than the convergence of the series n an . This is
indeed the case, although it is not obvious. But the following result already clarifies
matters a great deal.
Proposition 11.23. Every absolutely convergent real series is convergent.
Proof. We shall give two proofs of this
result. P
P important
P
First Proof : Consider
the
three
series
a
,
|a
n |. Our
n n
n n | and
n an + |aP
P
hypothesis is that n |an | converges. But we claim that this implies that n an +
|an | converges as well. Indeed, consider the expression an + |an |: it is equal to
2an =P
2|an | when an is non-negative and 0 when
Pan is negative.PIn particular the
series
a
+
|a
|
has
non-negative
terms
and
n
n n
n an +
P
P|an | n 2|an | < . So
a
+
|a
|
converges.
By
the
Three
Series
Principle,
n
n n
n an converges.
Second Proof : The above argument
is
clever
maybe
too clever! Lets try
P
something more fundamental: since
|a
|
converges,
for
every
> 0 there exists
P n n
N Z+ such that for all n N , n=N |an | < . Therefore for all k 0,
|
N
+k
X
n=N
and
an |
N
+k
X
n=N
|an |
|an | ,
n=N
n=1
|an | is
The main idea is that when we try to extend our rich array of convergence tests for
non-negative series to series with both positive and negative terms, a sufficient (and
often necessary) hypothesis is that the series be not just convergent but absolutely
convergent.
11We warn the reader that the more standard terminology is conditionally convergent.
We will later on give a separate definition for conditionally convergent and then it will be a
theorem that a real series is conditionally convergent if and only if it is nonabsolutely convergent.
The reasoning for this which we admit will seem abstruse at best to our target audience is
that in functional analysis one studies convergence and absolute convergence of series in a more
general context, such that nonabsolute converge and conditional convergence may indeed differ.
252
Exercise: State and prove a Comparison Test and Limit Comparison Test for absolute convergence.
lute series n=1 |an | and n=1 |bn |, we get that n=1 an is absolutely convergent
and thus convergent, contradicting (ii). Moreover
lim
an bn
an
= lim
1 = 0.
n bn
bn
limn | abnn |
r,
then
the
series
large n, | aan+1
n an is absolutely convergent.
n
b) Assume an 6= 0 for allP
n. If there exists r > 1 such that for all sufficiently large
n, | aan+1
| r, the series n an is divergent.
n
1
c) If there exists r < 1 such that for all sufficiently large n, |an | n r, the series
P
n an is absolutely convergent.
1
d) If there are infinitely many n for which |an | n 1, then the series diverges.
Proof. Parts a) and
Pc) are immediate: applying Theorem 11.19 (resp. Theorem 11.20) we find that P n |an | is convergent and the point is that by Theorem
11.23, this implies that n an is convergent.
P There is something to say in parts
P b) and d), because in general just because
|a
|
=
does
not
imply
that
n
n
n an diverges. (We will study this subtlety
later on in detail.) But recall that whenever
the Ratio or Root tests establish the
P
divergence of a non-negative series n bn , they do so by showing that bn 9 0.
Thus
P under the hypotheses of parts b) and d) we have |an | 9 0, hence also an 9 0
so n an diverges by the Nth Term Test (Theorem 11.4).
P
In particular, for a real series n an define the following quantities:
an+1
| when it exists,
an
an+1
= lim inf |
|,
n
an
an+1
= lim sup |
|,
an
n
= lim |
n
6. ABSOLUTE CONVERGENCE
253
and then all previous material on Ratio and Root Tests applies to all real series.
P
P
Theorem 11.26. Let Pn=0 an = A and n=0 bn = B be two absolutely
P conn
vergent series, and let cn = k=0 ak bnk . Then the Cauchy product series n=0 cn
is absolutely convergent, with sum AB.
Proof. We have proved this result already when an , bn 0 for all n. We wish,
of course, to reduce to that case. As far as the convergence of the Cauchy product,
this is completely straightforward: we have
|cn | =
n=0
X
n
X
n
X
X
|
ak bnk |
|ak ||bnk | < ,
n=0 k=0
n=0 k=0
P Pn
the last inequality following from the fact
|ak ||bnk | is the Cauchy
Pthat n=0 Pk=0
product of P
the two non-negative series n=0 |an | and n=0 |bn |, hence it converges.
P
Therefore n |cn | converges by comparison, so the Cauchy product series n cn
converges.
P
We now wish to show that limN CN = n=0 cn = AB. Recall the notation
X
N =
ai bj = (a0 + . . . + aN )(b0 + . . . + bN ) = AN BN .
0i,jN
We have
|CN AB| |N AB| + |N CN |
= |AN BN AB| + |a1 bN | + |a2 bN 1 | + |a2 bN | + . . . + |aN b1 | + . . . + |aN bN |
!
!
X
X
X
X
|AN BN AB| +
|an |
|bn | +
|bn |
|an | .
n=0
n=0
nN
nN
Fix > 0; since AN BN AB, for sufficiently large N |AN BN AB| < 3 . Put
A=
|an |, B =
n=0
|bn |.
n=0
nN
|bn | <
3A
and
254
N
X
an , BN =
n=0
N
X
bn , CN =
n=0
N
X
cn
n=0
nN N0
|N | |0 aN + . . . + N0 aN N0 | + |N0 +1 aN N0 1 + . . . + N a0 |
|0 aN + . . . + N0 aN N0 | +
M
2
nN N0
So N 0.
|an | +
+ = .
2
2 2
7. Non-Absolute Convergence
P
We say that
Pa real series n an is nonabsolutely convergent if the series converges but n |an | diverges, thus if it is convergent but not absolutely convergent.13
A series which is nonabsolutely convergent is a more delicate creature than any
we have studied thus far. A test which can show that a series is convergent but
nonabsolutely convergent is necessarily subtler than those of the previous section.
In fact the typical undergraduate student of calculus / analysis learns exactly one
such test, which we give in the next section.
13One therefore has to distinguish between the phrases not absolutely convergent and
nonabsolutely convergent: the former allows the possibility that the series is divergent, whereas
the latter does not. In fact our terminology here is not completely standard. We defend ourselves
grammatically: nonabsolutely is an adverb, so it must modify convergent, i.e., it describes
how the series converges.
7. NON-ABSOLUTE CONVERGENCE
255
X
(1)n+1
1 1
= 1 + ....
n
2 3
n=1
Upon taking the absolute value of every term we get the usual harmonic series,
which diverges, so the alternating harmonic series is not absolutely convergent.
However, some computations with partial sums suggests that the alternating harmonic series is convergent, with sum log 2. By looking more carefully at the partial
sums, we can find a pattern that allows us to show that the series does indeed
converge. (Whether it converges to log 2 is a different matter, of course, which we
will revisit much later on.)
It will be convenient to write an = n1 , so that the alternating harmonic series
n+1
P
is n (1)
n+1 . We draw the readers attention to three properties of this series:
(AST1) The terms alternate in sign.
(AST2) The nth term approaches 0.
(AST3) The sequence of absolute values of the terms is weakly decreasing:
a1 a2 . . . an . . . .
These are the clues from which we will make our case for convergence. Here it is:
consider the process of passing from the first partial sum S1 = 1 to S3 = 1 21 + 13 =
5
6 . We have S3 1, and this is no accident: since a2 a3 , subtracting a2 and then
adding a3 leaves us no larger than where we started. But indeed this argument is
valid in passing from any S2n1 to S2n+1 :
S2n+1 = S2n1 (a2n a2n+1 ) S2n1 .
Thus the sequence of odd-numbered partial sums {S2n1 } is decreasing. Moreover,
S2n+1 = (a1 a2 ) + (a3 a4 ) + . . . + (a2n1 | |a2n ) + a2n1 0.
Therefore all the odd-numbered terms are bounded below by 0. By the Monotone
Sequence Lemma, the sequence {S2n+1 } converges to its greatest lower bound, say
Sodd . On the other hand, just the opposite sort of thing happens for the evennumbered partial sums:
S2n+2 = S2n + a2n+1 a2n+2 S2n
and
S2n+2 = a1 (a2 a3 ) (a4 a5 ) . . . (a2n a2n+1 |) a2n+2 a1 .
Therfore the sequence of even-numbered partial sums {S2n } is increasing and
bounded above by a1 , so it converges to its least upper bound, say Seven . Thus we
have split up our sequence of partial sums into two complementary subsequences
and found that each of these series converges. Now the sequence {Sn } converges iff
Sodd = Seven , and the inequalities
S2 S4 . . . S2n S2n+1 S2n1 . . . S3 S1
256
EN = |(
n+1
(1)
an ) (
n=1
N
X
(1)n+1 an )|.
n=1
n=1
(1)n+1
np
is:
P (x)
be a rational function. Give necessary and sufficient condiExercise: Let Q(x)
P
n P (x)
tions for n (1) Q(x) to be nonabsolutely convergent.
n=1
EN = |S
N
X
an |.
n=1
7. NON-ABSOLUTE CONVERGENCE
257
X
1
(1)n+1 X (1)n+1
|
.
|
n
n
1001
n=1
n=1
(1)n+1
= 0.6926474305598203096672310589 . . . .
n
Again, later we will show that the exact value of the sum is log 2, which my software
package tells me is14
log 2 = 0.6931471805599453094172321214.
Thus the actual error in cutting off the sum after 1000 terms is
E1000 = 0.0004997500001249997500010625033.
It is important to remember that this and other error estimates only give upper
bounds on the error: the true error could well be much smaller. In this case we
1
were guaranteed to have an error at most 1001
and we see that the true error is
about half of that. Thus the estimate for the error is reasonably accurate.
Note well that although the error estimate of Theorem 11.28b) is very easy
to apply, if an tends to zero rather slowly (as in this example), it is not especially
efficient for computations. For instance, in order to compute the true sum of the alternating harmonic series to six decimal place accuracy using this method, we would
need to add up the first million terms: thats a lot of calculation. (Thus please be
assured that this is not the way that a calculator or computer would compute log 2.)
n
P
Example: We compute n=0 (1)
to six decimal place accuracy. Thus we need to
n!
1
choose N such that aN +1 = (N +1)! < 106 , or equivalently such that (N +1)! > 106 .
A little calculation shows 9! = 362, 880 and 10! = 3, 628, 800, so that we may take
N = 9 (but not N = 8). Therefore
9
X
(1)n X (1)n
1
|
|<
< 106 .
n!
n!
10!
n=0
n=0
258
n
X
n
X
ak bk | = |
k=m
ak (Bk Bk1 )| = |
k=m
=|
n1
X
k=m
n1
X
n
X
ak Bk
k=m
n1
X
ak+1 Bk |
k=m1
k=m
M(
n1
X
k=m
Therefore
n1
X
!
(ak ak+1 ) + an + am
k=m
= M (am an + an + am ) = 2M am 2M aN < .
a
bn converges by the Cauchy criterion.
n
n
In the preceding proof, without saying what we were doing, we used the technique
of summation by parts.
If we take bn = (1)n+1 , then B2n+1 = 1 for all n and B2n = 0 for all n,
so {bn } has bounded partial sums. Applying Dirichlets Test with a sequence
an which decreases
to 0 and with this sequence {bn }, we find that the series
P
P
n+1
an converges. We have recovered the Alternating Series
n an bn =
n (1)
Test!
In fact Dirichlets Test yields the following Almost Alternating Series Test:
let {an } be a sequence decreasing to 0, and for all n let bn {1} be a sign sequence which is almost alternating in the sense P
that the sequence of partial
sums Bn = b1 + . . . + bn is bounded. Then the series n bn an converges.
15Johann Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet, 1805-1859
7. NON-ABSOLUTE CONVERGENCE
259
sin(n + 12 ) sin(n 21 )
2 sin( 21 )
n=1
sin n
n
is nonabsolutely convergent.
Remark: Once we know about series of complex numbers and Eulers formula
eix = cos x + i sin x, we will be able to give a trigonometry-free proof of the preceding two exercises.
Dirichlet himself applied his test to establish the convergence of a certain class
of series of a mixed algebraic and number-theoretic nature. The analytic properties of these series were used to prove his celebrated theorem on prime numbers in
arithmetic progressions. To give a sense of how influential this work has become, in
modern terminology Dirichlet studied the analytic properties of Dirichlet series
associated to nontrivial Dirichlet characters. For more information on this work,
the reader may consult (for instance) [DS].
7.3. Cauchy Products III: A Divergent Cauchy Product.
Let us give an example due to Cauchy! of a Cauchy product of two nonabsolutely
P
P
P (1)n
convergent series which fails to converge. Take n=0 an = n=0 bn = n=0
.
n+1
The nth term in the Cauchy product is
X
1
1
cn =
(1)i (1)j
.
i+1 j+1
i+j=n
Now (1)i (1)j = (1)i+j = (1)n , so cn is equal to (1)n times a sum of positive
1
1
1
n+1
terms. Since i, j n, i+1
, j+1
, and thus each term in cn has absolute
1
1
2
value at least ( n+1 ) = n+1 . Since we are summing from i = 0 to n there are
n +P1 terms, all of the same size, we find |cn | 1 for all n. Thus the general term
of n cn does not converge to 0, so the series diverges.
7.4. Decomposition into positive and negative parts.
For a real number r, we define its positive part
r+ = max(r, 0)
260
an we have a decomposition
X
X
X
an =
a+
a
n
n,
n
P
P
at least if all three series converge.
Let us call n a+
n and P n an the positive
P
part and negative part of n an . Let us now suppose that n an converges. By
the Three Series Principle there are two cases:
P +
P
P
P +
Case 1: Both
P n an and n an converge. Hence n |an | = n (an + an ) converges: i.e., n an is absolutely convergent.
P
P
P
P
Case 2: Both n a+
| = n a+
n and
n + an diverges:
n an diverge. Hence
n |an
P
indeed,
if it converged,
n an we would get that
P
P then adding and subtracting
2 n a+
and
2
converge,
contradiction.
Thus:
a
n
n n
P
Proposition 11.30. If a series nPis absolutely convergent, both its positive
and negative parts converge. If a series n is nonabsolutely convergent, then both
its positive and negative parts diverge.
P
Exercise: Let P
n an be a real series. P
P
a) Show that if Pn a+
n converges andP n an diverges then Pn an = .
b) Show that if n a+
n diverges and
n an converges then
n an = .
8. Power Series I: Power Series as Series
8.1. Convergence of Power Series.
P
n
Let {an }
n=0 be a sequence of real numbers. Then a series of the form
n=0 an x
is called a power series.
Thus, for instance, if we had an = 1 for all n we would
P
1
.
get the geometric series n=0 xn which converges iff x (1, 1) and has sum 1x
Pn
k
The nth partial sum of a power series is k=0 ak x , a polynomial in x. One
of the major themes of Chapter three will be to try to view power series as infinite
polynomials: in particular, we will regard x as a variable and be interested in the
propeties
continuity, differentiability, integrability, and so on of the function
P
f (x) = n=0 an xn defined by a power series.
P
However, if we want to regard the series n=0 an xn as a function of x, what is
its domain? The natural domain of a power series is the set of all values of x for
which the series converges. Thus the basic question about power series that we will
answer in this section is the following.
Question 11.31. For a P
sequence {an }
n=0 of real numbers, for which values of
261
There is one value of x for which the answer is trivial. Namely, if we plug in x = 0
to our general power series, we get
an 0n = a0 + a1 0 + a2 02 = a0 .
n=0
n=0
(n + 1)!xn+1
= lim (n + 1)|x|.
n
n
n!xn
The last limit is 0 if x = 0 and otherwise is +. Therefore the Ratio Test shows
that (as we already knew!) the series converges absolutely at x = 0 and diverges
at every nonzero x. So it is indeed possible for a power series
P to converge only at
x = 0. This is disappointing if we are interested in f (x) = n an xn as a function
of x, since in this case it is just the function from {0} to R which sends 0 to a0 .
There is nothing interesting going on here.
lim
Example 2: Consider
xn
n=0 n! .
lim |
xn+1
n!
|x|
|| | = lim
= 0.
n n + 1
(n + 1)! xn
1
n
n=1 nRn x .
nRn
|x|n+1
n+1 1
|x|
= |x| lim
=
.
n+1
n
n (n + 1)R
n
|x|
n
R
R
lim
Therefore the series converges absolutely when |x| < R and diverges when |x| > R.
We must look separately at the
P case |x| = R i.e., when x = R. When x = R, the
series is the harmonic series n n1 , hence divergent. But when x = R, the series
n
P
is the alternating harmonic series n (1)
n , hence (nonabsolutely) convergent. So
the power series converges for x [R, R).
P (1)n n
Example 5: Fix R (0, ); consider
n=1 nRn x . We may rewrite this seP
1
n
ries as n=1 nR
n (x) , i.e., the same as in Example 4 but with x replaced by x
throughout. Thus the series converges iff x [R, R), i.e., iff x (R, R].
Example 6: Fix R (0, ); consider
1
n
n=1 n2 Rn x .
n2 R n
|x|n+1
= |x| lim
2
n+1
n (n + 1) R
n
|x|n
lim
=
.
n
R
R
So once again the series converges absolutely when |x| < R, diverges when |x|
P> R,
and we must look separately at x = R. This time plugging in x = R gives n n12
n
P
which is a convergent p-series, whereas plugging in x = R gives n (1)
n2 : since
262
the p-series with p = 2 is convergent, the alternating p-series with p = 2 is absolutely convergent. Therefore the series converges (absolutely, in fact) on [R, R].
Thus the convergence set of a power series can take any of the following forms:
In each case the set of values is an interval containing 0 and with a certain radius,
i.e., an extended real number R [0, ) such that the series definitely converges
for all x (R, R) and definitely diverges for all x outside of [R, R]. Our goal is
to show that this is the case for any power series.
This goal can be approached at various degrees of sophistication. At the calculus level, we have already said what is needed: we use the Ratio Test to see that
the convergence set isPan interval around 0 of a certain radius R. Namely, taking a
general power series n an xn and applying the Ratio Test, we find
an+1
|an+1 xn+1 |
= |x| lim
.
n an
n
|an xn |
lim
So if = limn aan+1
, the Ratio Test tells us that the series converges when
n
|x| < 1 i.e., iff |x| < 1 and diverges when |x| > 1 i.e., iff |x| > 1 . That
is, the radius of convergence R is precisely the reciprocal of the Ratio Test limit ,
1
with suitable conventions in the extreme cases, i.e., 01 = ,
= 0.
So what more is there to say or do? The issue here is that we have assumed
exists. Although this is usually the case in simple examples of
that limn aan+1
n
interest, it is certainly does not happen in general (we ask the reader to revisit X.X
for examples of this). This we need to take a different approach in the general case.
P
P
n
n
Lemma 11.32.
A > 0 and let
n an x be a power series. If
n an A
P Let
n
converges, then n x converges absolutely for all x (A, A).
P
Proof. Let 0 < BP< A. It is enough to
show n an B n is absolutely conP
vergent, for then so is n an (B)n . Since n an An converges, an An 0: by
omitting finitely many terms, we may assume |an An | 1 for all n. Since 0 < B
A < 1,
n
n
X
X
X B
B
|an B n | =
|an An |
< .
A
A
n
n
n
P
263
d) If 0 < R < , the convergence set of the power series is either (R, R), [R, R),
(R, R] or [R, R].
a) Let R be the least upper bound of the set of x 0 such that
P Proof.
n
a
x
converges.
If y is such that |y| < R, then there exists A with |y| < A <
n n
P
R such that n an An converges, so by Lemma 11.32 the power series converges
absolutely on (A, A), so in particular it converges absolutely at y. Thus RPsatisfies
property (i). Similarly, suppose there exists y with |y| > R such that n an y n
converges. Then there exists A with R < A < |y| such that the power series
converges on (A, A), contradicting the definition of R.
We leave the proof of parts b) through d) to the reader as a straightforward exercise.
Exercise: Prove parts) b), c) and d) of Theorem 11.33.
P
P
Exercise: Let n=0 an xn and n=0 bn xn be two power seriesPwith positive radii
n
of convergence Ra and Rb . Let R = min(Ra , Rb ). Put cn = k=0 ak bnk . Show
that the formal identity
!
!
X
X
X
n
n
an x
bn x
=
cn xn
n=0
n=0
n=0
is valid for all x (R, R). (Suggestion: use past results on Cauchy products.)
The drawback of Theorem 11.33 is that it does not give an explicit description
of the radius of convergence R in terms of the coefficients of the power series, as is
|
exists. In order to achieve this
the case when the ratio test limit = limn |a|an+1
n|
in general, we need to appeal instead to the Root Test and make use of the limit
supremum. The following elegant result is generally attributed to J.S. Hadamard,16
who published it in 1888 [Ha88] and included it in his 1892 PhD thesis. This seems
remarkably late in the day for a result which is so closely linked to (Cauchys) Root
Test. It turns out that the result was established by our most usual suspect: it was
first proven by Cauchy in 1821 [Ca21] but apparently had been nearly forgotten.
P
Theorem 11.34. (Cauchy-Hadamard) Let n an xn be a power series, and put
1
1
:
Proof. We have lim supn |an xn | n = |x| lim supn |an | n = |x|. Put
R = 1 . If |x| < R, choose A such that |x| < A < R and then A0 such that
1
1
< A0 < .
R
A
1
Then for all sufficiently large n, |an xn | n A0 A < 1, so the series converges absolutely by the Root Test. Similarly, if |x| > R, choose A such that R < |x| < A and
then A0 such that
1
1
< A0 <
= .
A
R
=
264
Remark: For the reader who is less than comfortable with limits infimum and supre|
mum, we recommend simply assuming that the Ratio Test limit = limn | aan+1
n
exists and proving Theorem 11.36 under that additional assumption using the Ratio
Test. This will be good enough for most of the power series encountered in practice.
P
Exercise: Let n an xn be a power
P series with interval of convergence I. Let J
be the interval of convergence of n nan xn1 .
a) Show that J I.
b) Give an example in which J 6= I.
CHAPTER 12
P (n) (c)
n!
for all 0 n N .
N
1
X
bn (t c)n .
n=0
Then
P (t) = b0 + b1 (t c) + . . . + bN 1 (t c)N 1 + aN (t c)N .
265
266
P (x) =
N
X
n=0
P (k) (c)
.
k!
N
X
f (k) (c)
k=0
k!
(x c)k .
Then TN (x) is the unique polynomial function of degree at most N such that
(k)
TN (c) = f (k) (c) for all 0 k N .
Proof. Applying Theorem 0 to TN (x) =
(k)
TN (c)
,
k!
(k)
TN (c)
PN
k=0
f (k) (c)
k! (x
c)k gives
f (k) (c)
k!
(k)
hence
= f (c) for all 0 k N . As for the uniqueness: let P (x) be
any polynomial of degree at most N such that P (k) (c) = f (k) (c) for 0 k N , and
let Q = TN P . Then Q is a polynomial of degree at most N such that Q(k) (c) = 0
PN Q(k) (c)
for 0 k N ; applying Theorem 12.1 we get Q(x) =
(x c)k =
k=0
k!
PN
k
k=0 0 (x c) = 0, i.e., Q is the zero polynomial and thus P = TN .
By definition, TN (x) is the degree N Taylor polynomial of f at c.
2. Taylors Theorem Without Remainder
For n N and c I , we say two functions f, g : I R agree to order n at c if
lim
xc
f (x) g(x)
= 0.
(x c)n
267
xc
f (x) g(x)
= lim f (x) g(x) = f (c) g(c).
xc
(x c)0
The converse, that if f (c) = g(c) then limxc f (x) g(x) = 0, is equally clear.
Example 1: We claim that two differentiable functions f and g agree to order
1 at c if and only if f (c) = g(c) and f 0 (c) = g 0 (c). Indeed, by the exercise above
both hypotheses imply f (c) = g(c), so we may assume that, and then we find
f (x) g(x)
f (x) f (c) g(x) g(c)
= lim
= f 0 (c) g 0 (c).
xc
xc
xc
xc
Thus assuming f (c) = g(c), f and g agree to order 1 at c if and only f 0 (c) = g 0 (c).
lim
xc
The following result gives the expected generalization of these two examples. It
is generally attributed to Taylor,1 probably correctly, although special cases were
known to earlier mathematicians. Note that Taylors Theorem often refers to a
later result (Theorem 12.4) that we call Taylors Theorem With Remainder, even
though it is Theorem 12.3 (only) that was proved by Brook Taylor.
Theorem 12.3. (Taylor) Let n N and f, g : I R be two n times differentiable functions. Let c be an interior point of I. The following are equivalent:
(i) We have f (c) = g(c), f 0 (c) = g 0 (c), . . . , f (n) (c) = g (n) (c).
(ii) f and g agree to order n at c.
Proof. Set h(x) = f (x) g(x). Then (i) holds iff h(c) = h0 (c) = . . . =
h(x)
h (c) = 0 and (ii) holds iff limxc (xc)
n = 0. So we may work with h instead of
f and g. Since we dealt with n = 0 and n = 1 above, we may assume n 2.
h(x)
0
(i) = (ii): L = limxc (xc)
opitals Rule gives
n is of the form 0 , so LH
(n)
h0 (x)
,
xc n(x c)n1
L = lim
provided the latter limit exists. By our assumptions, this latter limit is still of the
form 00 , so we may apply LHopitals Rule again. We do so iff n > 2. In general,
we apply LH
opitals Rule n 1 times, getting
h(n1) (x)
1
h(n1) (x) h(n1) (c)
L = lim
=
lim
,
xc n!(x c)
n! xc
xc
provided the latter limit exists. But the expression in parentheses is nothing else
than the derivative of the function h(n1) (x) at x = c i.e., it is h(n) (c) = 0 (and,
in particular the limit exists; only now have the n 1 applications of LHopitals
Rule been unconditionally justified), so L = 0. Thus (ii) holds.
(ii) = (i): Let Tn (x) be the degree N Taylor polynomial to h at c. By Corollary
1Brook Taylor, 1685 - 1731
268
12.2, f and Tn agree to order n at c, so by the just proved implication (i) = (ii),
h(x) and Tn (x) agree to order n at x = c:
lim
xc
h(x) Tn (x)
= 0.
(x c)n
h00 (c)
2 (x
c)2 + . . . +
(x c)n
h00 (c)
2 (x
c) + . . . + h
(x c)n1
(n)
h(n) (c)
n! (x
Tn (x)
(xc)n
(c)
n! (x
c)n
= 0.
c)n1
= 0.
xc
(n)
so h
h(n) (c)
n! (x
c)n
h(n) (c)
=
,
n
(x c)
n!
(c) = 0.
L = lim
assuming this limit exists. But to assume this last limit exists and is equal to h(n) (0)
is to assume that nth derivative of h is continuous at zero, which is slightly more
than we want (or need) to assume.
f (x)
For n N, a function f : I R vanishes to order n at c if limxc (xc)
n = 0.
Note that this concept came up prominently in the proof of Theorem 12.3 in the
form: f and g agree to order n at c iff f g vanishes to order n at c.
269
Rn (x) =
f (n+1) (z)
(x z)n (x c).
(n + 1)!
Rn (x) =
f (n+1) (z)
(x c)n+1 .
(n + 1)!
270
d) We have
|Rn (x)| = |f (x) Tn (x)|
||f (n+1) ||
|x c|n+1 .
(n + 1)!
We apply the Mean Value Theorem to S on |[c, x]|: there is z |(c, x)| such that
f (n+1) (z)
S(x) S(c)
= S 0 (z) =
(x z)n .
xc
n!
Noting that S(x) = Rn,x (x) = 0 and S(c) = Rn,c (x) = Rn (x), this gives
f (n+1) (z)
(x z)n (x c).
n!
b) Apply the Cauchy Mean Value Theorem to S(t) and g(t) = (x t)n+1 on |[c, x]:
there is z |(c, x)| such that
Rn (x) = S(c) S(x) =
(n+1)
f
(z)
(x z)n
S(x) S(c)
S 0 (z)
f (n+1) (z)
Rn (x)
n!
=
=
=
=
,
(x c)n+1
g(x) g(c)
g 0 (z)
(n + 1)(x z)n
(n + 1)!
so
f (n+1) (z)
(x c)n+1 .
(n + 1)!
c) If f (n+1) is integrable on |[c, x]|, then
Z x
Z x (n+1)
f
(t)(x t)n dt
.
Rn (x) = (S(x) S(c)) =
S 0 (t) =
n!
c
c
Rn (x) =
d) This follows almost immediately from part b); the proof is left to the reader.
Exercise: Show that Theorem 12.4 (Taylors Theorem With Remainder) implies
Theorem 12.3 (Taylors Theorem) under the additional hypothesis that f (n+1) exists
and is continuous3 on the interval |[c, x]|.
3Thanks to Nick Fink for pointing out the hypothesis of continuity seems to be needed here.
4. TAYLOR SERIES
271
4. Taylor Series
4.1. The Taylor Series. Let f : I R be an infinitely differentiable function, and let c I. We define the Taylor series of f at c to be
X
f (n) (c)(x c)n
T (x) =
.
n!
n=0
Thus T (x) = limn Tn (x), where Tn is the degree n Taylor polynomial at c. In
particular T (x) is a power series, so all of our prior work on power series applies.
Just as with power series, it is no real loss of generality to assume that c = 0,
in which case our series takes the simpler form
X
f (n) (0)xn
;
T (x) =
n!
n=0
indeed, to get from this to the general case one merely has to make the change of
variables x 7 x c. It is traditional to call Taylor series centered around c = 0
Maclaurin series. But I know no good reason for this Taylor series were introduced by Taylor in 1721, whereas Colin Maclaurins Theory of fluxions was not
published until 1742 and makes explicit attribution is made to Taylors work.4 Using separate names for Taylor series centered at 0 and Taylor series centered at c
often suggests misleadingly! to students that there is some conceptual difference
between the two cases. So we will not use the term Maclaurin series here.
1
272
T (x) =
0xn
n=0 n!
n=0
So it comes down to being able to give upper bounds on Rn (x) which tend to zero as
n . According to Taylors Theorem with Remainder, this will hold whenever
we can show that the norm of the nth derivative ||f (n) || does not grow too rapidly.
Example: We claim that for all x R, the function f (x) = ex is equal to its
Taylor series expansion at x = 0:
X
xn
x
.
e =
n!
n=0
First we compute the Taylor series expansion: f (0) (0) = f (0) = e0 = 1, and f 0 (x) =
ex , hence every derivative of ex is just ex again. We conclude that f (n) (0) = 1 for
P n
all n and thus the Taylor series is n=0 xn! , as claimed. Next note that this power
series converges for all real x, as we have already seen: just apply the Ratio Test.
Finally, we use Taylors Theorem with Remainder to show that Rn (x) 0 for each
fixed x R. Indeed, Theorem 12.4 gives us
Rn (x)
||f (n+1) ||
|x c|n+1 ,
(n + 1)!
where ||f (n+1) || is the supremum of the the absolute value of the (n+1)st derivative
on the interval |[0, x]|. But lucky us in this case f (n+1) (x) = ex for all n and
the maximum value of ex on this interval is ex if x 0 and 1 otherwise, so in either
way ||f (n+1) || e|x| . So
n+1
x
.
Rn (x) e|x|
(n + 1)!
And now we win: the factor inside the parentheses approaches zero with n and is
being multiplied by a quantity which is independent of n, so Rn (x) 0. In fact a
4. TAYLOR SERIES
273
moments thought shows that Rn (x) 0 uniformly on any bounded interval, say
on [A, A], and thus our work on the general properties of uniform convergence of
power series (in particular the M -test) is not needed here: everything comes from
Taylors Theorem With Remainder.
Example continued: we use Taylors Theorem With Remainder to compute e = e1
accurate to 10 decimal places.
A little thought shows that the work we did for f (x) = ex carries over verbatim
under somewhat more general hypotheses.
Theorem 12.6. Let f (x) : R R be a smooth function. Suppose that for all
A [0, ) there exists a number MA such that for all x [A, A] and all n N,
|f (n) (x)| MA .
(n)
P
(0)xn
converges absolutely for all x R.
a) The Taylor series T (x) = n=0 f n!
b) For all x R we have f (x) = T (x): that is, f is equal to its Taylor series
expansion at 0.
X
()( 1) ( (n 1)) n
x .
n!
n=1
274
n , and this ought not to be surprising because for N, expanding out T (x)
simply gives the binomial theorem:
X
n
N, (1 + x) =
x .
n
n=0
So lets extend our definition of binomial coefficients: for any R, put
= 1,
0
()( 1) ( (n 1))
+
.
n Z ,
=
n!
n
Exercise: For any R, n Z+ , show
1
1
(89)
=
+
.
n
n1
n
Finally, we rename the Taylor series to f (x) as the binomial series
X
n
x .
B(, x) =
n
n=0
The binomial series is as old as calculus itself, having been studied by Newton in the
17th century.5 It remains one of the most important and useful of all power series.
For us, our order of business is the usual one when given a Taylor series: first, for
each fixed we wish to find the interval I on which the series B(, x) converges.
Second, we would like to show if possible! that for all x I, B(, x) = (1 + x) .
Theorem 12.7. Let R \ N, and consider the binomial series
X
X
n
n
B(, x) =
x =1+
x .
n
n
n=0
n=1
a)
b)
c)
d)
n
n n + 1
n
4. TAYLOR SERIES
275
1
Step 1: Suppose (0, 1). Choose an integer m 2 such that m
< . Then
(1 ) (n 1 )
1
1 1
|
|=
< 1(1 ) (n 1 )
n
n!
m
m n!
m 1 2m 1
(n 1)m 1 1
1
= an ,
m
2m
(n 1)m n
n
say. Using Step 0, we get
=
am1
<
n
m
2m
(n 1)m
2m 1 3m 1
nm 1
m
2m
(n 1)m m 1
1 1
m1
2m 1
(n 1)m 1 nm 1
an n
1
1
It follows that an < 1 , so | n | < 1+ 1 , so
nm
n m
X
X 1
|
|
1 < .
1+ m
n
n
n n
n
This shows that B(, 1) is absolutely convergent; since |
n (1) | = | n |, it also
shows that B(, 1) is absolutely convergent.
Step 2: Using the identity (89), we find
X
X
n
1
1
S(, x) = 1 +
x = 1+
+
xn = (1 + x)S( 1, x).
n
n
1
n
n=1
n=1
=
n
(1, 0);
/
=
n+1
n+1
n
P
this shows simultaneously that the sequence of terms of B(, 1) =
n=0 n is
decreasing in absolute value and alternating in sign. Further, write = 1, so
1
that (0, 1). Choose an integer m 2 such that m
< . Then
(1 )(2 ) (n 1 ) n
n
|
|=
= bn
.
(n 1)!
n
n
n
Arguing as in Step 1 of part b) shows that bn < 11 , and hence
nm
n
= 0 1 = 0.
lim |
| = lim bn lim
n
n
n
n
n
Therefore the Alternating Series Test applies to show that S(, 1) converges.
d) The absolute value of the nth term of both B(, 1) and B(, 1) is |
n |. If
1, then | n| n + 1 and thus
n
|
/
|=|
| 1,
n+1
n
n+1
and thus
n 6 0. By the N th term test, S(, 1) and S(, 1) diverge.
276
Exercise*: Show that for (1, 0), the binomial series B(, 1) diverges.
Remark: As the reader has surely noted, the convergence of the binomial series
S(, x) at x = 1 is a rather delicate and tricky enterprise. In fact most texts at
this level even [S] do not treat it. We have taken Step 1 of part b) from [Ho66].
Remark: There is an extension of the Ratio Test due to J.L. Raabe which simplifies much the of the above analysis, including the preceding exercise.
Theorem 12.8. Let R \ N; let f (x) = (1 + x) , and consider its Taylor
series at zero, the binomial series
X
n
B(, x) =
x .
n
n=0
a) For all x (1, 1), f (x) = B(, x).
b) If > 1, f (1) = B(, 1).
c) If > 0, f (1) = B(, 1).
Proof. [La] Let Tn1 (x) be the (n 1)st Taylor polynomial for f at 0, so
B(, x) = lim Tn1 (x)
n
is the Taylor series expansion of f at zero. As usual, put Rn1 (x) = f (x)Tn1 (x).
a) By Theorem 12.4b),
Z x
Z x n
1
f (t)(x t)n1 dt
=
(1) (n+1)(1+t)n (xt)n1 dt.
Rn1 (x) =
(n 1)!
(n 1)! 0
0
By the Mean Value Theorem for Integrals, there is (0, 1) such that
Rn1 (x) =
( 1) ( n + 1)
(1 + x)n (x x)n1 (x 0).
(n 1)!
Put
1
t=
, cn (s) =
1 + x
1 n1
s
.
n1
Then
(1 + s)1 =
cn (s)
n=1
and
Rn1 (x) = cn (xt)x(1 + x)1 .
P
Since x (1, 1), we have t (0, 1), so |xt| < 1. It follows that
n=1 cn (xt)
converges, so by the nth term test cn (xt) 0 as n and thus Rn1 (x) 0.
b) The above argument works verbatim if x = 1 and > 1.
c) IfP > 0, then by Theorem 12.7b), S(, 1) is convergent. Moreover, 1 > 1,
so
n=1 cn (1) converges and thus cn (1) 0. But |cn (1)| = |cn (1)|, so also
cn (1) 0 and thus Rn1 (1) 0.
5. HERMITE INTERPOLATION
277
5. Hermite Interpolation
It is a well-known fact that two points determine a line. One version of this
is: given real numbers x1 < x2 and real numbers f1 , f2 , there is a unique linear
function f : R R such that f (x1 ) = f1 and f (x2 ) = f2 . In a similar way, three
points determine a parabola: given real numbers x1 < x2 < x3 and real numbers
f1 , f2 , f3 , there is a unique quadratic polynomial P (x) = ax2 + bx + c such that
P (xi ) = fi for i = 1, 2, 3. The following is a generalization of this.
Theorem 12.9. (Polynomial Interpolation) Let n Z+ , let x0 < . . . < xn be
real numbers, and let y0 , . . . , yn be real numbers. Then there is a unique polynomial
P of degree at most n such that P (xi ) = yi for 0 i n. Indeed, there are real
numbers A0 , . . . , An such that
(90) P (x) = A0 + A1 (x x0 ) + A2 (x x0 )(x x1 ) + . . . + An (x x0 ) (x xn1 ).
Proof. Uniqueness: Suppose that f and g are two such polynomials. Then
the polynomial h = f g has degree at most n and vanishes at the n + 1 points
x0 , . . . , xn . Since a nonzero polynomial cannot have more roots than its degree, we
must have h 0 and thus f = g.
Existence: Often the way to find something is to postulate (i.e., guess) a certain
form that the solution should take, while leaving certain parameters undetermined,
then algebraically solve for these parameters. (This is sometimes called the method
of undetermined coefficients.) The present result is an instance of this: (90)
gives the general form of the solution. If we plug in x = x0 we find
y0 = P (x0 ) = A0 .
Plugging in x = x1 we find
y1 = P (x1 ) = A0 + A1 (x1 x0 ),
which we can uniquely solve for A1 : explicitly
A1 =
y1 y0
y1 A0
=
.
x1 x0
x1 x0
In fact, following Lagrange, we can give a more explicit formula for the interpolating
polynomial of Theorem 12.9. (Why didnt we start with this? Because often it is
useful to make a distinction between proving the existence of something and giving
an explicit construction of it. The former is often easier, whereas the latter is often
more useful. In fact we will not need the explicit formula for most of our work here,
but in our study of quadrature we will want to have it.)
Theorem 12.10. (Lagrange Interpolation Formula) Let n Z+ , let x0 < . . . <
xn be real numbers, and let y0 , . . . , yn be real numbers. For 0 j n, define
Y
x x0
x xj1 x xj+1
x xn
x xn
=
.
`j (x) =
xj xn
xj x0
xj xj1 xj xj+1
xj xn
0in, i6=j
278
Then an explicit formula for the unique polynomial P (x) of degree at most n such
that P (xi ) = yi for all 0 i n of Theorem 12.9 is
(91)
P (x) =
n
X
yj `j (x).
j=0
5. HERMITE INTERPOLATION
279
Let us now try to switch back to the old notation: we give ourselves n + 1 real
numbers with multiplicity: x0 x1 . . . xn , a and n + 1 real numbers
f0 , . . . , fn . We write the interpolation problem as above as f (xi ) = fi , but with the
understanding that when a root is repeated more than once, the further conditions
are conditions on the derivatives of f . In this case we claim that the interpolation
polynomial can be taken in the same form as above: namely, there are unique real
numbers A0 , . . . , An such that
f = f (x) = A0 + A1 (x x0 ) + A2 (x x0 )(x x1 ) + . . . + An (x x0 ) (x xn1 ).
At the moment we will prove this by linear algebraic considerations (which is cheating: we are not supposed to be assuming any knowledge of linear algebra in this
text!). Namely, since we have already shown the existence of an interpolating polynomial f of degree at most n, it suffices to show that the set of polynomials
S = {1, x x0 , (x x0 )(x x1 ), . . . , (x x0 ) (x xn1 )}
spans the R-vector space Pn of all polynomials of degree at most n. The set S is
linearly independent: indeed, the polynomials have distinct degrees, so a nontrivial
linear indeendence relationship would allow us to write a nonzero polynomial as
a linear combination of polynomials of smaller degree, which is absurd. Further,
#S = n + 1. But Pn has dimension n, so S must be a basis for Pn : in paticular S
spans Pn .
Having billed Theorem 12.11 as generalizing Theorem 12.9, let us now call attention to the other extreme: suppose x0 = . . . = xn = c, say. Then the interpolating
polynomial P is precisely the degree n Taylor polynomial at c to any n times differentiable function f with f (j) (c) = fj for 0 j n. This brings up a key
idea in general: let I be an interval containing the points x0 . . . xn , and let
f : I R be an n times differentiable function. We define the Hermite interpolation polynomial P (x) to be the unique polynomial of degree at most n such
that for all 0 i n, P (xi ) = f (xi ): here we are using the above slightly shady
convention that when the xi s occur with multiplicity greater than 1, the conditions
P (xi ) = f (xi ) are actually conditions on the derivatives of P and f at xi .
Let us define the remainder function: for x I,
R(x) = f (x) P (x).
Following [CJ], we will now give an expression for R which generalizes one form of
Taylors Theorem With Remainder. We begin with one preliminary result.
Theorem 12.12. (Generalized Rolles Theorem) Let f : I R be n times differentiable, and assume that f has at least n+1 roots on I, counted with multiplicity.
Then there is I with f (n) () = 0.
Exercise: Prove Theorem 12.12.
Theorem 12.13. (Hermite With Remainder) Let x0 . . . xn I, and let
f : I R be (n + 1) times differentiable. Let P be the Hermite Interpolation
Polynomial for f . Then, for all x I, there is I in fact, lying in any closed
interval containing x, x0 , . . . , xn such that
(x x0 ) (x xn ) (n+1)
f
().
(92)
R(x) = f (x) P (x) =
(n + 1)!
280
Proof. If x = xi for some i, then both sides of (92) are 0, so equality holds.
We may thus assume x 6= xi for any i. Let c R, and consider
K(x) = R(x) c(x x0 ) (x xn ).
There is a unique value of c such that K(x) = 0: namely,
R(x)
.
(x x0 ) (x xn )
The function K : I R thus vanishes at least n + 2 times on I with multiplicity,
so by the Generalized Rolles Theorem there is I such that
c=
f (n+1) ()
.
(n + 1)!
(x x0 ) (x xn ) (n+1)
f
().
(n + 1)!
Remark: Restricting to Taylor polynomials, our earlier argument for the existence
of the interpolating polynomial is certainly easier: recall this consisted of simply
writing down the answer and checking that it was correct. However this proof of
part b) of Taylors Theorem with Remainder seems easier.
Exercise: a) Let x0 . . . xn , and let m n. Let
Pn (x) = A0 + A1 (x x0 ) + . . . + An (x x0 ) (x xn1 )
be the Hermite interpolation polynomial for a function f . Show that the Hermite
interpolation polynomial for f with respect to the approximation points x0 . . .
xk is
Pm (x) = A0 + A1 (x x0 ) + . . . + Am (x x0 ) (x xm1 ).
b) Suppose xn1 6= xn . Show that there is [x0 , xn ] such that
f (n) ()
.
n!
c) Show that there is a sequence {k } taking values in I such that
An =
f (n) (k )
.
k
n!
d) Suppose that f has a continuous (n + 1)st derivative. Use part c) to recover the
formula or the nth Taylor series coefficient.
An = lim
CHAPTER 13
282
The great mathematicians of the 17th, 18th and early 19th centuries encountered
many sequences and series of functions (again, especially power series and Taylor
series) and often did not hesitate to assert that the pointwise limit of a sequence of
functions having a certain nice property itself had that nice property.2 The problem
is that statements like this unfortunately need not be true!
Example 1: Define fn = xn : [0, 1] R. Clearly fn (0) = 0n = 0, so fn (0) 0. For
any 0 < x 1, the sequence fn (x) = xn is a geometric sequence with geometric
ratio x, so that fn (x) 0 for 0 < x < 1 and fn (1) 1. It follows that the
sequence of functions {fn } has a pointwise limit f : [0, 1] R, the function which
is 0 for 0 x < 1 and 1 at x = 1. Unfortunately the limit function is discontinuous
at x = 1, despite the fact that each of the functions fn are continuous (and are
polynomials, so really as nice as a function can be). Therefore the pointwise
limit of a sequence of continuous functions need not be continuous.
Remark: Example 1 was chosen for its simplicity, not to exhibit maximum pathology. It is possible to construct a sequence {fn }
n=1 of polynomial functions converging pointwise to a function f : [0, 1] R that has infinitely many discontinuities!
(On the other hand, it turns out that it is not possible for a pointwise limit of
continuous functions to be discontinuous at every point. This is a theorem of R.
Baire. But we had better not talk about this, or well get distracted from our stated
goal of establishing the wonderful properties of power series.)
One can also find assertions in the math papers of old that if fn converges to
Rb
Rb
f pointwise on an interval [a, b], then a fn dx a f dx. To a modern eye, there
are in fact two things to establish here: first that if each fn is Riemann integrable,
then the pointwise limit f must be Riemann integrable. And second, that if f is
Riemann integrable, its integral is the limit of the sequence of integrals of the fn s.
In fact both of these are false!
Example 2: Define a sequence {fn }
n=0 with common domain [0, 1] as follows. Let
f0 be the constant function 1. Let f1 be the function which is constantly 1 except
f (0) = f (1) = 0. Let f2 be the function which is equal to f1 except f (1/2) = 0.
Let f3 be the function which is equal to f2 except f (1/3) = f (2/3) = 0. And
so forth. To get from fn to fn+1 we change the value of fn at the finitely many
rational numbers na in [0, 1] from 1 to 0. Thus each fn is equal to 1 except at a finite
set of points: in particular it is bounded with only finitely many discontinuities,
so it is Riemann integrable. The functions fn converges pointwise to a function f
which is 1 on every irrational point of [0, 1] and 0 on every rational point of [0, 1].
Since every open interval (a, b) contains both rational and irrational numbers, the
function f is not Riemann integrable: for any partition of [0, 1] its upper sum is
1 and its lower sum is 0. Thus a pointwise limit of Riemann integrable functions
need not be Riemann integrable.
2This is an exaggeration. The precise definition of convergence of real sequences did not come
until the work of Weierstrass in the latter half of the 19th century. Thus mathematicians spoke of
functions fn approaching or getting infinitely close to a fixed function f . Exactly what they
meant by this and indeed, whether even they knew exactly what they meant (presumably some
did better than others) is a matter of serious debate among historians of mathematics.
2. UNIFORM CONVERGENCE
283
0 n
Thus
lim fn0 (1) 6= ( lim fn )0 (1).
284
n xc
xc
xc n
Proof. Step 1: We show that the sequence {Ln } is convergent. Since we dont
yet have a real number to show that it converges to, it is natural to try to use the
Cauchy criterion, hence to try to bound |Lm Ln |. Now comes the trick: for all
x I we have
|Lm Ln | |Lm fm (x)| + |fm (x) fn (x)| + |fn (x) Ln |.
By the Cauchy criterion for uniform convergence, for any > 0 there exists N Z+
such that for all m, n N and all x I we have |fm (x) fn (x)| < 3 . Moreover,
the fact that fm (x) Lm and fn (x) Ln give us bounds on the first and last
terms: there exists > 0 such that if 0 < |x c| < then |Ln fn (x)| < 3
and |Lm fm (x)| < 3 . Combining these three estimates, we find that by taking
x (c , c + ), x 6= c and m, n N , we have
|Lm Ln | + + = .
3 3 3
So the sequence {Ln } is Cauchy and hence convergent, say to the real number L.
Step 2: We show that limxc f (x) = L (so in particular the limit exists!). Actually
the argument for this is very similar to that of Step 1:
|f (x) L| |f (x) fn (x)| + |fn (x) Ln | + |Ln L|.
Since Ln L and fn (x) f (x), the first and last term will each be less than 3
for sufficiently large n. Since fn (x) Ln , the middle term will be less than 3 for
x sufficiently close to c. Overall we find that by taking x sufficiently close to (but
not equal to) c, we get |f (x) L| < and thus limxc f (x) = L.
Corollary 13.3. Let fn be a sequence of continuous functions with common
u
domain I and suppose that fn f on I. Then f is continuous on I.
2. UNIFORM CONVERGENCE
285
Since Corollary 13.3 is easier than Theorem 13.2, we include a separate proof.
Proof. Let x I. We need to show that limxc f (x) = f (c), thus we need to
show that for any > 0 there exists > 0 such that for all x with |x c| < we
have |f (x) f (c)| < . The idea again! is to trade this one quantity for three
quantities that we have an immediate handle on by writing
|f (x) f (c)| |f (x) fn (x)| + |fn (x) fn (c)| + |fn (c) f (c)|.
By uniform convergence, there exists n Z+ such that |f (x) fn (x)| < 3 for
all x I: in particular |fn (c) f (c)| = |f (c) fn (c)| < 3 . Further, since fn (x)
is continuous, there exists > 0 such that for all x with |x c| < we have
|fn (x) fn (c)| < 3 . Consolidating these estimates, we get
|f (x) f (c)| < + + = .
3 3 3
Exercise: Consider again fn (x) = xn on the interval [0, 1]. We saw in Example 1
above that fn converges pointwise to the discontinuous function f which is 0 on
[0, 1) and 1 at x = 1.
a) Show directly from the definition that the convergence of fn to f is not uniform.
b) Try to pinpoint exactly where the proof of Theorem 13.2 breaks down when
applied to this non-uniformly convergent sequence.
Exercise: Let fn : [a, b] R be a sequence of functions. Show TFAE:
u
(i) fn f on [a, b].
u
(ii) fn f on [a, b) and fn (b) f (b).
Theorem 13.4. Let {fn } be a sequence of (Riemann-Darboux) integrable funcu
tions with common domain [a, b]. Suppose that fn f . Then f is integrable and
Z b
Z b
Z b
lim
fn =
lim fn =
f.
n
a n
a
u
n1
X
i=0
n1
X
(xi+1 xi ) = (b a),
i=0
and similarly,
|L(fn , P) L(f, P)| (b a).
Since fN is integrable, by Darbouxs Criterion there is a partition P of [a, b] such
that U (fN , P) L(fN , P) < . Thus
|U (f, P)L(f, P)| |U (f, P)U (fn , P)|+|U (fn , P)L(fn , P)|+|L(fn , P)L(f, P)|
(b a) + + (b a) = (2(b a) + 1).
286
Since > 0 was arbitrary, Darbouxs Criterion shows f is integrable on [a, b].
Step 2: If f, g : [a, b] R are integrable and |f (x) g(x)| for all x [a, b], then
Z b
Z b
Z b
Z b
|
f
g| = |
f g|
|f g| (b a).
a
a
u
From this simple observation and Step 1 the fact that fn f implies
is almost immediate. The details are left to you.
Rb
a
fn
Rb
a
f
Exercise: It follows from Theorem 13.4 that the sequences in Examples 2 and 3
above are not uniformly convergent. Verify this directly.
Corollary 13.5. Let {fn } be a sequence of continuous functions defined on
P
u
the interval [a, b] such that n=0 fn f . For each n, let Fn : [a, b] R be the
0
unique function with Fn = fn and Fn (a) = 0, and similarly let F : [a, b] R be the
P
u
unique function with F 0 = f and F (a) = 0. Then n=0 Fn F .
Exercise: Prove Corollary 13.5.
Our next order of business is to discuss differentiation of sequences of functions.
For this we should reconsider Example 4: let g : R R be a bounded differentiable
function such that limn g(n) does not exist, and let fn (x) = g(nx)
n . Let M be
u
M
such that |g(x)| M for all R. Then for all x R, |fn (x)| n , so fn 0. But
as we saw above, limn fn0 (1) does not exist.
Thus we have shown the following somewhat distressing fact: uniform convergence of fn to f does not imply that fn0 converges.
Well, dont panic. What we want is true in practice; we just need suitable hypotheses. We will give a relatively simple result sufficient for our coming applications.
Theorem 13.6. Let {fn }
n=1 be a sequence of functions on [a, b]. We suppose:
(i) Each fn is continuously differentiable on [a, b],
(ii) The functions fn converge pointwise on [a, b] to some function f , and
(iii) The functions fn0 converge uniformly on [a, b] to some function g.
Then f is differentiable and f 0 = g, or in other words
( lim fn )0 = lim fn0 .
n
u
fn0
a n
X
X
(93)
(
fn )0 =
fn0 .
n=0
n=0
2. UNIFORM CONVERGENCE
287
n (t) =
fn (t) fn (x)
tx
and
f (t) f (x)
,
tx
so that for all n Z+ , limxt n (t) = fn0 (x). Now by (94) we have
|m (t) n (t)|
2(b a)
(t) =
for all m, n N , so once again by the Cauchy criterion n converges uniformly for
u
u
all t 6= x. Since fn f , we get n for all t 6= x. Finally we apply Theorem
13.2 on the interchange of limit operations:
f 0 (x) = lim (t) = lim lim n (t) = lim lim n (t) = lim fn0 (x).
tx
tx n
n tx
2.2. The Weierstrass M-test.
We have just seen that uniform convergence of a sequence of functions (and possibly,
of its derivatives) has many pleasant consequences. The next order of business is to
give a useful general criterion for a sequence of functions to be uniformly convergent.
288
In (more) words, ||f || is the least M [0, ] such that |f (x)| M for all x I.
Theorem 13.9. (Weierstrass M-Test) Let {fn }
n=0 be a sequence of functions
defined on an interval I.PLet {Mn }
be
a
non-negative
sequence such that ||fn ||
n=0
P
n=N +1
n>N
X
f 0 (x) =
nan xn1 .
n=1
0
c) Since the power series f has the same radius of convergence R > 0 as f , f is
in fact infinitely differentiable.
d) For all n N, f (n) (0) = (n!)an .
Proof.
a) Let P
0 < A < R, so f defines a function from [A, A] to R. We claim that
the series n an xn converges to f uniformly on [A,
as a function
P A]. Indeed,
P
n
n
on [A, A], we have ||an xn || = |an |An , and thus
||a
x
||
=
<
n
n
n |an |A
, because power series converge absolutely on the interior of their interval of
convergence.
Pn Thus by the Weierstrass M -test f is the uniform limit of the sequence
Sn (x) = k=0 ak xk . But each Sn is a polynomial function, hence continuous and
infinitely differentiable. So by Theorem 13.2 f is continuous on [A, A]. Since any
x (R, R) lies in [A, A] for some 0 < A < R, f is continuous
R).
P on (R, P
b) According to Corollary 13.7, in order to show that f = n an xn = n fn is
differentiable and the derivative may be compuited termwise,
it is enough to check
P
that (i) each fn is continuously differentiable and (ii) n fn0 is uniformly convergent.
But (i) is trivial, since fn = an xn of course
Pmonomial
P functions are
P continuously
differentiable. As for (ii), we compute that n fn0 = n (an xn ) = n nan1 xn1 .
By X.X, this power series also has radius of convergence R, hence by the result of
part a) it is uniformly
convergent on [A, A]. Therefore Corollary 13.7 applies to
P
show f 0 (x) = n=0 nan xn1 .
c) We have just seen that for a power series f convergent on (R, R), its derivative
f 0 is also given by a power series convergent on (R, R). So we may continue in
289
an n+1
F (x) = n=0 n+1 x
is an anti-derivative of f .
The following exercise drives home that uniform convergence of a sequence or series
of functions on all of R is a very strong condition, often too much to hope for.
P
Exercise: Let n an xn be a power series with infinite radius of convergence, hence
defining a function
P f : R R. Show that the following are equivalent:
(i) The series n an xn is uniformly convergent on R.
(ii) We have an = 0 for all sufficiently large n.
P
Exercise: Let f (x) = n=0 an xn be a power series with an 0 for all n. Suppose
that the radius of convergence is 1, so that f defines a function on (1, 1). Show
that the following
are equivalent:
P
(i) f (1) = n an converges.
(ii) The power series converges uniformly on [0, 1].
(iii) f is bounded on [0, 1).
The fact that for any power series f (x) =
f
(n)
(0)
n!
The upshot of Corollary 13.11 is that the only way that two power series can be
equal as functions even in some very small interval around zero
P is if allPoftheir
coefficients are equal. This is not obvious, since in general n=0 an = n=0 bn
does not imply an = bn for all n. Another way of saying this is that the only power
series a function can be equal to on a small interval around zero is its Taylor series.
CHAPTER 14
Serial Miscellany
1.
2
1
n=1 n2 = 6
P 1
n=1 np converges
2
2 X 1
.
6
n2
4(N + 1)
n=1
An
An1
=
.
2n 1
2n
292
= (2n 1)
0
= (2n 1)(An1 An ).
Thus
An
= An1 An ,
2n 1
and
1
An1
=
2n
2n
An +
An
2n 1
=
1
2n
(2n 1)An + An
2n 1
Z
=n
=
An
.
2n 1
x2 cos x cos2n1 x (2n 1) sin2 x cos2(n1) x dx
Z
= nBn + n(2n 1)
.
2
n
nAn
An
An1
An
Thus for all n Z+ we have
N
N
X
X
2Bn1
1
2Bn
2BN
2B0
=
.
=
2
n
An1
An
A0
AN
n=1
n=1
Since
Z
A0 =
, B0 =
2
dx =
0
we have
x2 dx =
3
,
24
2B0
2
=
.
A0
6
.
2
n
6
AN
n=1
Equivalently
N
(97)
2 X 1
2BN
=
> 0.
2
6
n
AN
n=1
1This time we leave it to the reader to check that the boundary terms uv | 2 evaluate to 0.
0
293
and thus
2
sin2 x.
x2
2
Exercise: Prove Lemma 14.4. (Hint: use convexity!)
Using Lemma 14.4 and Lemma 14.3a) with N = n 1 we get
Z 2
N
2 X 1
2BN
2
0<
=
=
x2 cos2N xdx
2
6
n
A
A
N
N
0
n=1
Z
2 2
AN
2
2 2 2
=
,
sin2 x cos2N xdx =
AN 2
AN 2
2(N + 1)
4(N + 1)
0
which proves Theorem 14.2.
sequence. However, if we reorder the terms {an } of an infinite series n=1 an , the
corresponding change in the sequence An of partial sums is not simply a reordering,
as one can see by looking at very simple examples. For instance, if we reorder
1
1 1 1
+ + + ... + n + ...
2 4 8
2
as
1 1 1
1
+ + + ... + n + ...
4 2 8
2
Then the first partial sum of the new series is 14 , whereas every nonzero partial sum
of the original series is at least 12 .
Thus there is some evidence to fuel suspicion that reordering the terms of an infinite series may not be so innocuous an operation as for that of an infinite seuqence.
All of this discussion is mainly justification for our setting up the rearrangement
problem carefully, with a precision that might otherwise look merely pedantic.
Namely, the formal notion of rearrangement of a series
n=0
an begins with a
294
permuation
of N, i.e., a bijective function
P : N N. We define the rearrangeP
ment of n=0 an by to be the series n=0 a(n) .
2.2. The Rearrangement Theorems of Weierstrass and Riemann.
The most basic questions on rearrangements of series are as follows.
P
Question 14.5. Let n=0 an = S is a convergent infinite series, and let be
a permutation of N. Then: P
as S ranges over all finite subsets of N, then A0 A. On the other hand, for all
N N, AN = a0 + . . . + aN = A{0,...,N } : in other words, each partial sum AN
arises as AS for a suitable finite subset S. Therefore A A0 and thus A = A0 .
P
The point here is that the description n=0 an = supS AS is manifestly unchanged
by rearranging the terms of the series by any permutation : taking S 7 (S)
gives a bijection on the set of all finite subsets of N, and thus
X
X
a(n) .
an = sup AS = sup A(S) =
n=0
n=0
The case of absolutely convergent series follows rather easily from this.
P
Lemma 14.6. Let n an be a real series with an 0 for all n P
and sum A
[0, ]. Then A is the supremum of the set of all finite sums AS = nS an as S
ranges over all nonempty finite subsets of N.
Proof. Let A be the supremum of the finite sums AS . For N N, let
PN
AN =
n=0 an . Since an 0 for all n, the sequence AN is increasing, so
A = limN AN = supN AN . Since AN = A{0,...,N } , we have A = supN AN
supS AS = A. On the other hand, for any nonempty finite subset S of N, let N be
P
PN
the largest element of S. Then S {0, . . . , N } so AS = nS an n=0 aN =
AN A, so A = sup AS A. Thus A = A.
The point of Lemma 14.6 is that we have expressed the sum of a series with nonnegative terms in a way which is manifestly independent of the ordering of the
terms:2 for any bijection of N, as S = {n1 , . . . , nk } ranges over all finite subsets
2This is a small preview of unordered summation, the subject of the following section.
295
an =
n=0
a(n) [0, ],
n=0
i.e., rearrangement of a series with non-negative terms does not disturb the convergence/divergence or the sum.
P
Theorem 14.7. (Weierstrass) Let n=0 an be an absolutely convergent
P series
with sum A. Then for every permutation of N, the rearranged series n=0 a(n)
converges to A.
P
P
Proof. Put A = n=0 an . Fix > 0 and let N0 N be such that n=N0 |an | <
. Let M0 N be sufficiently large so that the terms a(0) , . . . , a(M0 ) include all
the terms a0 , . . . , aN0 1 (and possibly others). Then for all M M0 ,
|
M
X
n=0
a(n) A| = |
M
X
n=0
a(n)
X
n=0
an |
|an | < .
n=N0
Indeed: by our choice of M we know that the terms a0 , . . . , aN0 1 appear in both
PM
P
n=0 a(n) and
n=0 an and thus get cancelled; some further terms may or may
not be cancelled, but by applying the triangle inequality and summing the absolute
values we get an upper bound by assuming no further cancellation. This shows
P
PM
n=0 a(n) = limM
n=0 a(n) = A.
Exercise: a) Give a proof of Step 1 of Theorem 14.7 that bypasses Lemma 14.6.
(Suggestion:
Pby reasoning as in Step 2, argue that for each > 0 and all sufficiently
large N , n=N |a(n) | < .
P
P +
b) Use the decomposition
of
n an into its series of positive parts
n an and
P
negative parts n an to give a second proof of Step 2 of Theorem 14.7.
P
Theorem 14.8. (Riemann Rearrangement Theorem) Let n=0 an be a nonabsolutely convergent
P series. For any B [, ], there exists a permutation
of N such that n=0 a(n) = B.
Proof. P
Step 1: Since n an is convergent, we have an 0 and thus that {an } is bounded,
so we may choose M such that |an | M for all n. We are not going to give an
explicit formula for ; rather, we are going to describe by a certain process.
For this it is convenient to imagine that the sequence {an } has been sifted into a
disjoint union of two subsequences, one consisting of the positive terms and one
consisting of the negative terms (we may assume without loss of generality that
there an 6= 0 for all n). If we like, we may even imagine both of these subseqeunce
ordered so that they are decreasing in absolute value. Thus we have two sequences
p1 p2 . . . pn . . . 0,
n1 n2 . . . nn . . . 0
so that together {pn , nn } comprise the terms of the series. The key point
Phere is
Proposition
11.30
which
tells
us
that
since
the
convergence
is
nonabsolute,
n pn =
P
, n nn = . So we may specify a rearangement as follows: we specify a choice
of a certain number of positive terms taken in decreasing order and then a choice
of a certain number of negative terms taken in order of decreasing absolute value
296
and then a certain number of positive terms, and so on. As long as we include a
finite, positive number of terms at each step, then in the end we will have included
every term pn and nn eventually, hence we will get a rearrangement.
Step 2 (diverging to ): to get a rearrangement diverging to , we proceed as
follows: we take positive terms p1 , p2 , . . . in order until we arrive at a partial sum
which is at least M + 1; then we take the first negative term n1 . Since |n1 | M ,
the partial sum p1 + . . . + pN1 + n1 is still at least 1. Then we take at least one
more positive term pN1 +1 and possibly further terms until we arrive at a partial
sum which is at least M + 2. Then we take one more negative term n2 , and note
that the partial sum is still at least 2. And we continue in this manner: after the
kth step we have used at least k positive terms, at least k negative terms, and all
the partial sums from that point on will be at least k. Therefore every term gets
included eventually and the sequence of partial sums diverges to +.
Step 3 (diverging to ): P
An easy adaptation of the argument of Step 2 leads to
a permutation such that n=0 a(n) = . We leave this case to the reader.
Step 4 (converging to B R): if anything, the argument is simpler in this case. We
first take positive terms p1 , . . . , pN1 , stopping when the partial sum p1 + . . . + pN1
is greater than B. (To be sure, we take at least one positive term, even if 0 >
B.) Then we take negative terms n1 , . . . , nN2 , stopping when the partial sum
p1 + . . . + pN1 + n1 + . . . + nN2 is less than B. Then we repeat the process, taking
enough positive terms to get a sum strictly larger than B then enough negative
terms to get a sum strictly less than B, and so forth. Because both the positive
and negative parts diverge, this construction can be completed. Because the general
term an 0, a little thought shows that the absolute value of the difference between
the partial sums of the series and B approaches zero.
The conclusion of Theorem 14.8 holds under somewhat milder hypotheses.
P
P +
P
Exercise: Let n an be a real series such that an 0,
n an = and
n an =
. Show that the conclusion of Theorem
14.8
holds:
for
any
A
[,
],
there
P
exists a permutation of N such that n=0 a(n) = A.
P
P
Exercise: Let n an be a real series such that n a+
n = .
a) Suppose that the sequence
{a
}
is
bounded.
Show
that there exists a permutan
P
tion of N such that n a(n) = .
b) Does the conclusion of part a) hold without the assumption that the sequnece
of terms is bounded?
Theorem 14.8 exposes the dark side of nonabsolutely convergent series: just by
changing the order of the terms, we can make the series diverge to or converge
to any given real number! Thus nonabsolute convergence is necessarily of a more
delicate and less satisfactory
P nature than absolute convergence. With these issues
in mind, we define a series n an to be unconditionally convergent if it is convergent and every rearrangement converges to the same sum, and a series to be
conditionally convergent if it is convergent but not unconditionally convergent.
Then much of our last two theorems may be summarized as follows.
Theorem 14.9. (Main Rearrangement Theorem) A convergent real series is
unconditionally convergent if and only if it is absolutely convergent.
297
Many texts do not use the term nonabsolutely convergent and instead define a series to be conditionally convergent if it is convergent but not absolutely convergent.
Aside from the fact that this terminology can be confusing to students to whom
this rather intricate story of rearrangements has not been told, it seems correct to
make a distinction between the following two a priori different phenomena:
P
P
Pn an converges but n |an | does not, versus P
n an converges to A but some rearrangement n a(n) does not.
As we have seen, these two phenomena
are equivalent for real series. However
P
the notion of an infinite series
a
,
absolute
and unconditional convergence
n
n
makes sense in other contexts, for instance3 for series with values in an infinitedimensional Banach space or with values in a p-adic field. In the former case
it is a celebrated theorem of Dvoretzky-Rogers [DR50] that there exists a series
which is unconditionally convergent but not absolutely convergent, whereas in the
latter case one can show that every convergent series is unconditionally convergent
whereas there exist nonabsolutely convergent series.
P
Exercise: Let n=0 an be any nonabsolutely convergent real series, and let
a A . Show
P that there exists a permutation of N such that the set of
partial limits of n=0 a(n) is the closed interval [a, A].
2.3. Unordered summation.
It is very surprising that the ordering of the terms of a nonabsolutely convergent
series affects both its convergence and its sum it seems fair to say that this phenomenon was undreamt of by the founders of the theory of infinite series.
ArmedP
now, as we are, with the full understanding of the implications of our defini
ion of n=0 an as the limit of a sequence of partial sums, it seems reasonable to
ask: is there an alternative definition for the sum of an infinite series, one in which
the ordering of the terms is a priori immaterial?
The answer to this question is yes and is given by the theory of unordered
summation.
To be sure to get a definition of the sum of a series which does not depend on
the ordering of the terms, it is helpful to work in a context in which no ordering is
present. Namely, let S be a nonempty set, and define an S-indexed sequence of
real numbers to be a function a : S R. The point here is that we recover the
usual definition of a sequence by taking S = N (or S = Z+ ) but whereas N and Z+
come equipped with a natural ordering, the naked set S does not.
P
We wish to define
sS as , i.e., the unordered sum of the numbers as as s
ranges over all elements
P of S. Here it is: for every finite subset T = {s1 , . . . , sN }
of S, we define aT = sT as = as1 + . . . + aP
sN . (We also define a = 0.) Finally,
for A R, we say that the unordered sum sS as converges to A if: for all
3Both of these are well beyond the scope of these notes, i.e., you are certainly not expected
to know what I am talking about here.
298
> 0, there exists a finite subset T0 S such that for allPfinite subsets T0 T S
we
P have |aT A| < . If there exists A R such that sS as = A, we say that
sS as is convergent or that the S-indexed sequence a is summable. (When
S = ZN we already have a notion of summability, so when we need to make the
distinction we will say unordered summable.)
Notation: because we are often going to be considering various finite subsets T
of a set S, we allow ourselves the following time-saving notation: for two sets A
and B, we denote the fact that A is a finite subset of B by A f B.
Exercise: Suppose S is finite.PShow that every S-indexed sequence a : S R
is summable, with sum aS = sS as .
Exercise: If S = , there is a unique function a : R, the
P empty function. Convince yourself that the most reasonable value to assign s as is 0.
Exercise: Give reasonable definitions for
sS
as = and
sS
as = .
Confusing Remark: We say we are doing unordered summation, but our sequences take values in R, in which the absolute value is derived from the order
structure. One could also consider unordered summation of S-indexed sequences
with values in an arbtirary normed abelian group (G, | |).4 A key feature of R is
the positive-negative part decomposition, or equivalently the fact that for M R,
|M | A implies M A or M A. In other words, there are exactly two
ways for a real number to be large in absolute value: it can be very positive or very
negative. At a certain point in the theory considerations like this must be used in order to prove the desired results, but we delay such arguments for as long as possible.
The following result holds without using the positive-negative decomposition.
Theorem 14.10. (Cauchy Criteria for Unordered Summation) Let a : S R
be an S-index sequence, and consider the following assertions:
(i) The S-indexed sequence a is summable.
(ii) For all > 0, there exists a finite subset T S such that for all finite subsets
T, T 0 of S containing T ,
X
X
|
as
as | < .
sT
sT 0
299
sT 0
sT
sT0
(iii) = (ii): Fix > 0, and let T f S be such that for all finite subsets T of S
with T T = , |aT | < 2 . Then, for any finite subset T 0 of S containing T ,
|aT 0 aT | = |aT 0 \T | < .
2
From this and the triangle inequality it follows that if T and T 0 are two finite
subsets containing T ,
|aT aT 0 | < .
(iii) = (iv): Using (iii), choose T1 f S such that for all T 0 f S with T1 T 0 =
, |aT 0 | 1. Then for any T f S, write T = (T \ T1 ) (T T1 ), so
X
X
X
as | + |
as | 1 +
|as |,
|aT | |
sT T1
sT \T1
so we may take M = 1 +
sT1
|as |.
sT1
300
from which it follows that max |aTn+ , aTn | 2 , so we may define for all n a subset
Tn0 Tn such that |aTn0 | 2 and the sum aTn0 consists either entirely of non-negative
0
, then by
elements of entirely of negative elements. If we now consider T10 , . . . , T2n1
the Pigeonhole Principle there must exist 1 i1 < . . . < in 2n 1 such that all
the terms
Ti0 are non-negative or all the terms in each Ti0 are negative. Let
Sn in each
0
Tn = j=1 Tij . Then we have a disjoint union and no cancellation, so |Tn | n
2 :
the finite sums aT are not uniformly bounded.
Proposition 14.12. Let a : S R be an S-indexed sequence with as 0 for
all s S. Then
X
as = sup aT .
sS
T f S
sT
Suppose |a | is not summable. Then by Proposition 14.12, for every M > 0, there
exists T f S such that |a|T 2M . But as in the proof of Theorem 14.11, there
must exist a subset T 0 T such that (i) aT 0 consists entirely of non-negative terms
or entirely of negative terms and (ii) |aT 0 | M . Thus the partial sums of a are
not uniformly bounded, and by Theorem 14.11 a is not summable.
Theorem 14.14. For
P a : N R an ordinary sequence and A R, TFAE:
(i) The unordered sum nZ+ an is convergent, with sum A.
P
(ii) The series n=0 an is unconditionally convergent, with sum A.
Proof. (i) = (ii): Fix > 0. Then there exists T f S such that for every
finite subset T of N containing T weP
have |aT A| < . Put N = maxnT n. Then
n
for all P
n N , {0, . . . , n} T so | k=0 ak A| < . It follows that the infinite
301
Exercise: Fill in the missing details of (ii) = (i) in the proof of Theorem 14.14.
Exercise*: Can one prove Theorem 14.14 without appealing to the fact that |x| M
implies x M or x M ? For instance, does Theorem 14.14 holds for S-indexed
sequences with values in any Banach space? Any complete normed abelian group?
Comparing Theorems 14.12 and 14.13 we get a second proof of the portion of
the Main Rearrangement Theorem that says that a real series is unconditionally
convergent iff it is absolutely convergent. Recall that our first proof of this depended on the Riemann Rearrangement Theorem, a more complicated result.
On the other hand, if we allow ourselves to use the previously derived result
that unconditional convergence and absolute convergence
coincide, then we can get
P
an easier
proof
of
(ii)
=
(i):
if
the
series
a
is
unconditionally
convergent,
n
n
P
then n |an | < , so by Proposition 14.10 the unordered sequence |a | is summable, hence by Theorem 14.12 the unordered sequence a is summable.
To sum up (!), when we apply the very general definition of unordered summability to the classical case of S = N, we recover precisely the theory of absolute
(= unconditional) convergence. This gives us a clearer perspective on exactly what
the usual, order-dependent notion of convergence is buying us: namely, the theory
of conditionally convergent series. It may perhaps be disappointing that such an
elegant theory did not gain us anything new.
However when we try to generalize the notion of an infinite series in various
ways, the results on unordered summability become very helpful. For instance,
often in nature one encounters biseries
X
an
n=
am,n .
m,nN
We may treat the first case as the unordered sum associated to the Z-indexed sequence n 7 an and the second as the unordered sum associated to the NN-indexed
sequence (m, n) 7 am,n and we are done: there is no need to set up separate theories of convergence. Or, if we prefer, we may shoehorn these more ambitiously
indexed series into conventional N-indexed series: this involves choosing a bijection
b from Z (respectively N N) to N. In both cases such bijections exist, in fact
in great multitude: if S is any countably infinite set, then for any two bijections
b1 , b2 : S N, b2 b1
: N N is a permutation of N. Thus the discrepancy
1
between two chosen bijections corresponds precisely to a rearrangement of the series. By Theorem 14.13, if the unordered sequence is summable, then the choice of
bijection b is immaterial, as we are getting an unconditionally convergent series.
The theory of products of infinite series comes out especially cleanly in this unordered setting (which is not surprising, since it corresponds to the case of absolute
convergence, where Cauchy products are easy to deal with).
Exercise: Let S1 and S2 be two sets, and let a : S1 R, b : S2 R. We
302
s1 S1
s2 S2
Let n=0 an be
series.
Pa convergent
n
a) The series n=0 aP
n x is uniformly
Pconvergent on [0, 1].
N
+k
X
an xn | xN M xN < .
n=N
PN
u
By the Cauchy P
Criterion (Lemma 13.1), n=0 an xn f on [0, 1).
n
n
a
x
is
continuous
at
x
=
1:
lim
a
x
=
n
n
x1
n=0
n=0
n=0 an .
P
Remark: Usually Abels Theorem means part b) of the above result: n=0 an =
limx1 an xn . But this is an immediate consequence of the uniformity of the
convergence on [0, 1], so having this statement be part of Abels Theorem gives a
stronger and also more conceptually transparent result.
5Here we are following our usual convention of allowing individual exercises to assume knowledge that we do not want to assume in the text itself. Needless to say, there is no need to attempt
this exercise if you do not already know and care about uncountable sts.
3. ABELS THEOREM
303
Above we followed an exercise in the text [C] of Cartan.6 For comparison, here
is a different proof of Theorem 14.15b) from a famous text of Rudin.
P
Proof. [R, Thm. 8.2] Since n an converges,
{an } is bounded, so by CorolP
lary 11.35 the radius of convergence of f (x) = n an xn is at least
P1. Put A1 = 0;
for n 0, put An = a0 + . . . + an ; and put A = limn An = n=0 an . Then
N
X
an xn =
n=0
N
X
n=0
N
1
X
An x n + AN x N .
n=0
an xn = (1 x)
n=0
An x n .
n=0
Now fix > 0, and choose N such that n N implies |A An | < . Then, since
(1 x)
(98)
xn = 1
n=0
An x A(1 x)
n=0
(1 x)
N
X
n=0
|An A|xn +
x | = |(1 x)
n=0
2
(1 x)
X
n=N +1
xn (1 x)
(An A)xn |
n=0
N
X
|An A|xn + .
n=0
The last quantity above approaches as x approaches 1 from the left. Since was
arbitrary, this shows limx1 f (x) = A.
As you can see, Rudins proof uses much less than Cartans: rather than relying on
Abels Lemma, a bit of partial summation is done on the fly. Moreover, most of the
appeals to the theory of power series and uniform convergence are replaced by a
clever introduction of the geometric series! Nevertheless I must say that, although
Rudins argument is easy enough to follow line by line, in terms of whats going
on in the proof I find it absolutely impenetrable.
The rest of this section is an extended exercise in Abels Theorem appreciation.
First of all, it may help to restate the result in a form which is slightly more general
and moreover makes more clear exactly what has been established.
P
Theorem 14.16. (Abels Theorem Mark II) Let f (x) = n an (x c)n be a
power series with radius of convergence R > 0, hence convergent at least for all
x (c R, c + R).
a) Suppose that the power series converges at x = c + R. Then the function f :
(c R, c + R] R is continuous at x = c + R: limx(c+R) f (x) = f (c + R).
b) Suppose that the power series converges at x = c R. Then the function f :
[c R, c + R) R is continuous at x = c R: limx(cR)+ f (x) = f (c R).
6Henri Cartan (1904-2008) was one of the leading mathematicians of the 20th century.
304
x1
X
1 1 1
(1)n+1
= 1 + + . . . = log 2.
n
2 3 4
n=1
(99)
X
(1)n
1 1 1
= 1 + + ... = .
2n + 1
3 5 7
4
n=0
(100)
The identity (100) was known to Leibniz (as would be logical, given that the
convergence of both series follows from Leibnizs Alternating Series Test), where
the quotation marks are meant to suggest that Leibniz probably did not have an
argument we would accept as a rigorous proof. Suppose someone shows you such
identities, as I now have: what would you make of them?
A good first reaction is to attempt numerical verification. Even this is not as
easy as one might expect, because the convergence of both series is rather slow.
(In particular, among all ways one might try to numerically compute , (100) is
one of the worst I know.) Like any series which is shown to be convergent by the
Alternating Series Test, there is a built in error estimate for the sum: if we cut off
after N terms the error is in absolute value at most |aN +1 |. The problem with this
is that the N th terms of these series tend to zero quite slowly! So for instance,
4
S104
10
X
(1)n+1
= 0.6930971830599452969172323714 . . .
=
n
n=1
3. ABELS THEOREM
305
(Using a software package I asked for the exact sum of the series, which is of course
a rational number, but a very complicated one: it occupies more than one full screen
on my computer. The amount of time spent to compute this rational number was
small but not instantaneous. In fact the reason I chose 104 is that the software managed this but had trouble with S105 . Then I converted the fraction to a decimal.
Of course a much better way to do this would be to convert the fractionals to decimals as we go along, but this needs to be done carefully to prevent rounding errors:
to be serious about this sort of thing one needs to know some numerical analysis.)
By the Alternating Series Test, the difference between the infinite sum and the
1
, so we are guaranteed (roughly) four decimal places
finite sum S104 is at most 1001
of accuracy. For comparison, computing log 2 e.g. by writing it as log( 12 ) and
using the Taylor series for log(1 + x) we get
log 2 = 0.6931471805599453094172321214 . . . .
So indeed the identity (99) holds true at least up to four decimal places. If we
wanted to do much more numerical verification than this, we would probably have
to do something a little more clever.
Similarly, we have
4
10
X
(1)n
= 0.78542316 . . . ,
2n + 1
n=0
and by the Alternating Series test this approximates the infinite sum
to at least four decimal places of accuracy, whereas
= 0.7853981633974483096156608458 . . . ,
4
which shows that (100) holds true at least up to four decimal places.
(1)n
n=0 2n+1
f 0 (x) =
X
X
1
1
(1)n xn .
(x)n =
=
=
1+x
1 (x) n=0
n=0
X
X
(1)n xn+1
(1)n xn+1
=
.
n+1
n+1
n=1
n=1
X
(1)n
.
n+1
n=1
But not so fast. Although you will find this explanation in many freshman calculus
books, it is not yet justified. We were being sloppy in our above work by writing
down power series expansions and not keeping track of the interval of convergence.
The identity (101) holds for x (1, 1), and thats really the best we can do, since
the power series on the right hand side does not converge for any other values of x.
306
Integrating this term by term, we find that (102) holds for x (1, 1). Above, in
our excitement, we plugged in x = 1: so close, but out of bounds. Too bad!
But dont despair: its Abels Theorem for the win! Indeed, because the series
converges at x = 1 and the function log x is defined and continuous at x = 1,
X
(1)n xn+1 AT X (1)n
log(2) = log(1 + 1) = lim log x = lim
=
.
n+1
n+1
x1
x1
n=1
n=1
Exercise: Establish (100) similarly, starting with the function f (x) = arctan x.
3.4. Abel Summability.
Abels Theorem gives rise to a summability
method: a way to extract numerical
P
values out of certain divergent series n an as though they converged. Instead
of forming the sequence of partial sums
P An = a0 + . . . + an and taking
P the limit,
suppose instead we look at limx1 n=0 ax xn . We say the series
P n an is Abel
summable if this limit exists, in which case we write it as A n=0 an , the
PAbel
sum of the series. The point of this is that by Abels theorem, if a series n=0 an
is actually convergent, say to A, then it is also Abel summable and its Abel sum is
also equal to A. However, there are series which are divergent yet Abel summable.
P
Example 14.1. Consider the series n=0 (1)n . As we saw, the partial sums
alternate between 0 and 1 so the series does not diverge. We mentioned earlier
that (the
great) L. Euler believed that nevertheless the right number to attach to the
P
series n=0 (1)n is 21 . Since the two partial limits of the sequence of partial sums
are 0 and 1, it seems vaguely plausible to split the difference.
Theorem provides a much more convincing argument. The power series
P Abels
n n
(1)
x
converges for all x with |x| < 1, and moreover for all such x we have
n
(1)n xn =
lim
x1
(x)n =
n=0
n=0
and thus
n (1)
1
1
=
,
1 (x)
1+x
(1)n xn = lim
n=0
n
x1
1
1
= .
1+x
2
307
converges to f on (c c , c + c ).
This good news builds up a strong intuition that smooth functions should have
well-behaved Taylor series. In fact this is far from the case. To fix ideas, consider
smooth functions f : R R. Then there are two ways for f to fail to be analytic:
(i) At some c R, Tf,c converges only at 0.
(ii) At some c R, Tf,c has positive radius of convergence, but there is no interval
(c c , c + c ) about c on which Tf,c = f .
Both of these pathologies occur. In the second case, an example was constructed
by Cauchy in 1823 and remains well known to this day.
(
2
ex x 6= 0
Proposition 14.18. Let f (x) =
. Then:
0
x=0
a) f : R R is smooth.
b) For all n N, f (n) (0) = 0.
c) Thus the Taylor series expansion of f at 0 is the identically zero function. It
has infinite radius of convergence and is equal to f only at the central point x = 0.
Exercise: Prove Proposition 14.18.
That a smooth function can have a Taylor series which converges only at the central
point which we may certainly assume to be 0 is more subtle. The first example
of such a function was given by du Bois-Reymond in 1876 [dBR76], [dBR83].
P
It is no problem to construct a power series
an xn which converges only at 0. By
1
n
the Cauchy-Hadamard formula we need only select a sequence with lim sup |a
Pn | =
an+1
, which as we have seen is implied by = limn an = , so e.g.
n!xn
works. But is this power series a Taylor series? It is if and only if we can find a
(n)
smooth function f : R R with f n!(0) = n!, i.e., that
n N, f (n) (0) = (n!)2 .
Thus the essential problem is to construct a smooth function f : R R whose
sequence of derivatives at 0 grows (at least along a subsequence) sufficiently rapidly,
and in particular much more rapidly than n!.
It is not so auspicious to search in nature for a function with such rapidly
growing derivatives. It turns out to be simpler solve a more general problem: show
that any real sequence whatsoever can serve as the sequence of derivatives at 0 of a
smooth function f : R R. This is the content of the following remarkable result.
Theorem 14.19. (Peano-Borel) Let {cn }
n=0 be a real sequence. Then there
is an infinitely differentiable function f : R R such that for all n N we have
f (n) (0) = cn .
Exercise: Show that the Peano-Borel Theorem is equivalent to the statement that
every power series is a Taylor series. More precisely, for any c R and any real
sequence {an }
differentiable function f : R R such
n=0 , show there is an infinitely P
308
Exercise: Prove du Bois-Reymonds Theorem that there is an infinitely differentiable function f : R R whose Taylor series expansion at 0 converges only at
x = 0.
Exercise: Let {an }
n=0 be a real sequence.
a) Show that
S = {infinitely differentiable f : R R | the Taylor series of f at 0 is
an xn }
n=0
is infinite.
b) (This part is for those who know some linear algebra.) Let f0 S. Show:
{f f0 | f S} is a real vector space of infinite dimension.
Theorem 14.19 is generally known as Borels Theorem. It was proved along
Borel [Bo95]. But acwith the Heine-Borel Theorem in the doctoral thesis of E.
cording to a recent article of A. Besenyei [Be14] the result was in fact first proved
by G. Peano in 1884, so we speak of the Peano-Borel Theorem.
In fact Besenyeis article is the source of this entire section, both the historical
material and the account of Peanos proof that we will now give.
4.2. Proof.
The following argument uses a bit of complex numbers, which are presented in
more detail in a later chapter.
f (x) =
X
k=0
ak xk
.
1 + bk x 2
Later we will show how this can be achieved with suitable choices of the sequences
{an } and {bn }. Now we have
|bk x2 | < 1 =
X
X
ak xk
k
j j 2j
=
a
x
(1)
b
x
=
(1)j ak bjk x2j+k .
k
k
1 + bk x 2
j=0
j=0
Thus
ak xk
1 + bk x2
(n)
(
n!(1)j an2j bjn2j
(0) =
0
if k = n 2j for some j
otherwise.
Thus
(103)
309
b2c
X
f (n) (0)
n 2,
= an +
(1)j an2j bjn2j .
n!
j=1
(104)
From (103) and (104) it follows that given {bn } and {cn }, there is a uniquely
determined sequence {an } such that f (n) (0) = cn for all n N.
Step 2: Let b > 0 and consider
xk1
1
1
xk
=
+
.
b2 + x 2
2
x + bi x bi
By the Generalized Leibniz Rule, we have
xk
b2 + x2
(n)
n
1X n
=
(k 1) (k 1 n + j)xk1n+j
2 j=0 j
(1)j j!
(1)j j!
+
(x + bi)j+1
(x bi)j+1
n
n! kn2 X
xj+1
xj+1
j (k 1) (k 1 n + j)
= x
(1)
+
.
2
(n j)!
(x + bi)j+1
(x bi)j+1
j=0
We have (see the following exercise)
xj+1
xj+1
(105)
(x + bi)j+1 + (x bi)j+1 2.
It follows that
(106)
(n)
ak xk
(n + 1)!k!|ak | kn2
k n + 2,
|x|
.
1 + bk x2
bk
(n
+
1)!
.
1 + bk x2
k!
kn+2
kn+2
The right hand side of (107) is uniformly convergent on every bounded interval,
hence for every n N the convergence of
(n)
X
ak xk
1 + bk x 2
k=0
follows from the Weierstrass M-Test. Applying Theorem 13.6 establishes the fact
that the given series of nth derivatives converges to the nth derivative of f . This
completes the proof.
Exercise: a) Let w C. Show that if |w| 1, then for all n Z+ , |wn + wn | 2.
b) Verify equation (105).
310
7http://www.math.harvard.edu/elkies/M55b.10/index.html
311
.
2
2
(iii) One may, for instance, go by induction on the number of corners of f .
max(f, g) =
Then
n=0 an = L, and the convergence of the series to the limit function is
uniform on [0, 1].
Exercise: Prove Lemma 14.23. Two suggestions:
(i) Reduce to the case in which an 0 for all n N.
(ii) Use the Weierstrass M-Test.
Proposition 14.24. For any > 0, the function f (x) = |x| on [, ] can be
uniformly approximated by polynomials.
312
Proof. Step 1: Suppose that for all > 0, there is a polynomial function
P : [1, 1] R such that |P (x) |x|| < for all x [1, 1]. Put x = y . Then for
all y [, ] we have
y
y
|P ( ) | || = |Q(y) |y|| < ,
(1 + y) =
y
n
n=0
valid for all R and all y (1, 1). Taking = 21 and substituting y for y, we
1
and limN TN (y) = 1 y for y [0, 1). Further, (1)n n2 < 0 for n 1, and
p
lim f (y) = lim 1 y = 0.
y1
y1
u
Thus we may apply Elkies Lemma to get TN (y) 1 y on [0, 1]. For x [1, 1],
y = 1 x2 [0, 1], so making this substitution we find that on [1, 1],
1
N
X
u p
2
n 2
TN (1 x ) =
(1)
(1 x2 )n 1 (1 x2 ) = x2 = |x|.
n
n=0
5.4. Proof of the Weierstrass Approximation Theorem.
For a < b R, let C[a, b] be the set of all continuous functions f : [a, b] R,
and let P be the set of all polynomial functions f : [a, b] R. Let PL([a, b]) denote
the set of piecewise linear functions f : [a, b] R.
For a subset S C[a, b], we define the uniform closure of S to be the set S
of all f C[a, b] which are uniform limits of sequences in S: precisely, for which
u
there is a sequence of functions fn : [a, b] R with each fn S and fn f .
Lemma 14.25. For any subset S C[a, b], we have S = S.
Proof. Simply unpacking the notation is at least half of the battle here. Let
u
f S, so that there is a sequence of functions gi S with gi f . Similarly, since
u
each gi S, there is a sequence of continuous functions fij gi . Fix k Z+ :
1
1
choose n such that ||gn f || < 2k
and then j such that ||fnj gn || < 2k
; then
||fnj f || ||fnj gn || + ||gn f || <
1
1
1
+
= .
2k 2k
k
1
k
and thus fk f .
313
Choose > 0 such that for all 1 i n, if x [a, b], then mi x + bi [, ]. For
each 1 i n, by Lemma 14.24 there is a polynomial Pi such that
Pn for all x [a, b],
|Pi (mi x+bi )|mi x+bi || < n . Let P : [a, b] R by P (x) = b+ i=1 Pi (mi x+bi ).
Then P P and for all x [a, b],
n
n
X
X
= .
|P (x) f (x)| =
(Pi (mi x + bi ) |mi x + bi |) <
n
i=1
i=1
6. A Continuous, Nowhere Differentiable Function
We are going construct a function f : R R with the following striking property:
for all x0 R, f is continuous at x0 but f is not differentiable at x0 . In short, we
say that f is continuous but nowhere differentiable.
The first such construction (accompanied by a complete, correct proof) was given
in a seminal 1872 paper of Weierstrass. Weierstrasss example was as follows: let
(0, 1), and let b be a positive odd integer such that b > 1 + 3
2 . Then the
function f : R R given by
X
(108)
f (x) =
n cos(bn x)
n=0
314
X
X
3
fk (x) =
f (x) =
S(4k x).
4
k=0
k=0
3 k
Since k=0 ||fk || = k=0 4 < , the series defining f converges uniformly by
the Weierstrass M-Test. This also gives that f is continuous, since f is a uniform
limit of a sequence of continuous functions. We claim however that f is nowhere
differentiable. To see this, fix x0 R. We will define a sequence {n } of nonzero
real numbers such that n 0 and the sequence
Dn =
f (x0 + n ) f (x0 )
n
4n
,
2
and the reason for our choice is that the interval (4n x0 , 4n (x0 + n )) contains no
integers. Let k, n N. We claim the following inequalities:
(109)
(110)
(111)
k = n, |S(4k x0 + 4k n ) S(4k x0 )| =
315
1
.
2
S(4
x
)
0
n
0
=
n
4
n
k=0
n
n1
X 3 k S(4k x0 + 4k n ) S(4k x0 )
3
n
4
4
4
n
k=0
3n
n1
X
k=0
3k = 3n
3n 1
3n
.
2
2
316
special functions than you do...and this may not be a good thing.
In this section we will study one of the most ubiquitous special functions of
them all, the Gamma function.
7.1. Definition and Basic Properties.
For x (0, ) we define
Z
(x) =
tx1 et dt.
b) Deduce that
(113)
1
( ) = 2
2
x2
e
0
dx =
ex dx.
(x + 1) = x(x).
317
1
1 :
Z
x1 t
= log
(t
y1 t 1
e ) (t
e )
dt
Z
log
Z
e dt
x1 t
1 !
e dt
y1 t
(x)(y)
.
(x + y)
318
Making the substitution t = sin2 in the integral defining B(x, y) and applying
Theorem 14.31 we get
Z 2
(x)(y)
2x1
2y1
(115)
2
(sin )
(cos )
d =
.
(x + y)
0
Taking x = y =
1
2
in (115) we deduce:
Theorem 14.32.
(116)
Z
2
1
=
ex dx = .
2
1
N
1
N
Z
|fn (x)|dx +
+
0
f (x)dx.
1
N
n
!
1
N
+
0
f (x)dx
Z
N
|f (x)|dx +
(fn (x) f (x))dx
1
N
+ + = 3.
Since was arbitrary, the proof is complete.
319
lim
(x + 1)
= 1.
(x/e)x 2x
CHAPTER 15
322
f1
f2
is continuous.
323
324
this section we provide a review of complex numbers and the rudiments of complex
power series. This theory can be developed to an amazing extent further than the
theory of real power series, in fact! but such qualitatively different developments
are the subject of another course. Here we just want to develop the theory enough
so that we can make sense of plugging complex numbers into power series.
Recall that a complex number is an expression of the form z = a + bi. Here a
and b are real numbers and i is a formal symbol having the property that i2 = 1.
For many years people had philosophical difficulties with complex numbers; indeed, numbers of the form ib were called imaginary, and the prevailing view was
that although they did not exist, they were nevertheless very useful.
From a modern point of view this is neither acceptable (we cannot work with
things that dont exist, no matter how useful they may be!) nor necessary: we can
define the complex numbers entirely in terms of the real numbers. Namely, we may
identify a complex number a + bi with the ordered pair (a, b) of real numbers, and
we will define addition and multiplication. Since we would want (a + bi) + (c + di) =
(a + c) + (b + d)i, in terms of ordered pairs this is just (a, b) + (c, d) = (a + c, b + d).
In other words, this is the usual addition of vectors in the plane. The multiplication
operation is more interesting but still easy enough to write down in terms of only
real numbers: to compute (a + bi)(c + di), we would want to use the distributive
law of multiplication over addition and the relation i2 = 1. In other words, we
would like (a + bi) (c + di) = ac + bci + adi + bdi2 = (ac bd) + (ad + bc)i. Thus
in terms of ordered pairs we define a multiplication operation
(a, b) (c, d) = (ac bd, ad + bc).
Note that with this convention, we may identify real numbers a (i.e., those with
b = 0) with pairs of the form (a, 0); moreover, what we were calling i corresponds
to (0, 1), and now any ordered pair a + bi can be expressed as (a, 0) + (b, 0) (0, 1).
Exercise: Show that the above operations of addition and multiplication on ordered pairs satisfy all the field axioms (P0) through (P9). The resulting structure
is called the complex numbers and denoted C.
Exercise: Show that because of the relation i2 = 1, C cannot be endowed with
the structure of an ordered field.
Two other important operations on the complex numbers are conjugation and taking the modulus. For any complex number z = a + bi, we define its complex
conjugate to be z = a bi. Conjugation fits in nicely with the rest of the algebraic
structure: one has z1 + z2 = z1 + z2 and (z1 z2 ) = z1 z2 .
For any complex number
z = a + bi, we define its modulus (or norm, or abso
lute value) to be |z| = a2 + b2 . This is just the usual norm of an element of RN
specialized to the case N = 2. In particular, we have the triangle inequality
z1 , z2 C, |z1 + z2 | |z1 | + |z2 |.
However, the norm also behaves nicely with respect to the multiplicative structure.
325
X
zn
.
E(z) :=
n!
n=0
1
1
Because the ratio test limit is limn (n+1)!
= limn n+1
= 0, the radius of
1
n!
convergence is infinite: the series converges for all complex numbers z.
n
X
n
X
X
1 X n k nk X (z + w)n
z k wnk
=
z w
=
= E(z+w).
E(z)E(w) =
k!(n k)! n=0 n!
k
n!
n=0
n=0
k=0
k=0
Since E(0) = 1, we have for all z that
E(z)E(z) = E(z z) = E(0) = 1,
1
E(z) .
X
(1)n x2n+1
.
S(x) :=
(2n + 1)!
n=0
326
C(x) :=
X
(1)n x2n
.
(2n)!
n=0
Of course we would like to say S(x) = sin x and C(x) = cos x, but we do not
want to have to resort to discussions involving angles, lengths of arcs and other
such things. We want to see how much can be derived directly from the power series expansions themselves. For instance, we would like the show that C 2 + S 2 = 1.
Unfortunately, although this identity does hold, showing it directly from the power
series expansions involves some rather unpleasant algebra (try it and see).
This is where complex numbers come in to save the day:
Proposition 15.10. For all real x, we have the following identities:
1
C(x) = (E(ix) + E(ix)),
2
1
S(x) = (E(ix) E(ix)),
2i
E(ix) = C(x) + iS(x).
Exercise: Prove Proposition 15.10.
Now we are in business: since the coefficients of E(z) are real, we have E(ix) =
E(ix) = E(ix) for all real x, hence
C(x)2 + S(x)2 = |E(ix)|2 = E(ix)E(ix) = E(ix)E(ix) = E(ix ix) = E(0) = 1.
Were not done yet: wed like to prove that S(x) and C(x) are periodic functions,
whose period is a mysterious number approximately equal to 2 3.141592653 . . ..
This can also be worked out from the power series expansions, with some cleverness:
We first claim that there exists x0 > 0 such that C(x0 ) = 0. Otherwise, since
C(0) = 1 > 0, wed have C(x) > 0 for all x, hence S 0 (x) = C(x) > 0 for all x, hence
S would be strictly increasing on the entire real line. Since S(0) = 0, it follows that
S(x) > 0 for all x > 0. Now, if 0 < x < y, we have
Z y
S(x)(y x) <
S(t)dt = C(x) C(y) 2.
But now for fixed x and y > x +
x
2
S(x) ,
Lemma 15.11. Let f : [0, ) R be continuous such that f (0) > 0 and
f (x) = 0 for some x > 0. Then there is a least positive number x0 such that
f (x0 ) = 0.
Proof. Left to the reader.
Now we define the number by = 2x0 . where x0 is the lesat positive number x
such that C(x) = 0. The relation C(x)2 + S(x)2 = 1 together with C( 2 ) = 0 shows
that S( 2 ) = 1. On the other hand, since C(x) = S 0 (x) is non-negative on [0, 2 ],
S(x) is increasing on this interval, so it must be that S( 2 ) = 1. Thus E( i
2 ) = i.
Using the addition formula for E(z) we recover Eulers amazing identity
i 2
ei = e 2
= 1,
327
and also e2i = 1. In general, ez+2i = ez e2i = ez , so E is periodic with period 2i.
Using the periodicity of E and the formula of Proposition 2, we get that for all
x C(x + 2) = C(x) and S(x + 2) = S(x).
Since for all real t, |eit | = 1, the parameterized curve
r(t) = eit = C(t) + iS(t) (C(t), S(t)) = (x(t), y(t))
has image contained in the unit circle. We claim that every point on the unit circle
is of the form eit for a unique t [0, 2). To see this, start at the point 1 = ei0 ,
and consider t [0, 2 ]. The function C : [0, 2 ] R is continuous and decreasing,
hence injective, with C(0) = 1 and C( 2 ) = 0. By the Intermediate Value Theorem, all values in [0, 1] are assumed for a (necessarily unique, by the injectivity)
t [0, pi
2 ], and every point in the first quadrant of the unit circle is of the form
(x, y) for a unique x [0, 1]. By making similar arguments in the intervals [ 2 , ],
3
[, 3
2 ], [ 2 , 2] we establish the claim.
Finally, if we grant that by the arclength of the parameterized curve r(t) = (x(t), y(t))
from t = a to t = b we mean the integral
Z b r
dx
dy
| |2 + | |2 dt
dt
dt
t=a
it is easy to show that C(x) = cos x and S(x) = sin x.
(C(t), S(t)), the arclength integral is
Z
S 2 (t) + C 2 (t)dt = ,
t=0
so the point r() = (C(), S()) really is the point that we arrive at by starting at
the point (1, 0) on the unit circle and traversing units of arc.
S(x)
Exercise: Show that for all x (0, /2), S(x) < x < C(x)
.
(Show this directly from the power series definitions: no pictures involving the unit
circle! Hint: use the power series representation for arctan x.)
1
1
has a positive kth root, denoted r k . Thus if w = r k ei / k ,
1
wk = (r k ei / k )k = r(ei k )k = rei = z.
Exercise: Let z be a nonzero complex number and k a positive integer. Show that
there are preciesly k complex numbers w such that wk = z.
4. The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra
4.1. The Statement and Some Consequences.
328
P (z) = an (z 1 )(z 2 ) (z n ).
Proof. First observe that if the result holds for P (z) then it holds for P (z)
for any C \ {0}. It is therefore no loss of generality to assume that the leading
coefficient an of P (z) is equal to 1. Let us do so.
We now prove the result by induction on n, the degree of the polynomial P .
Base Case (n = 1): A degree one polynomial with leading coefficient 1 is of the
form z + a0 = z 1 , with 1 = a0 .
Induction Step: Let n Z+ , suppose the result holds for all polynomials of degree
n, and let P (z) be a polynomial of degree n + 1. By Theorem 15.13, there is
z0 C such that P (z0 ) = 0. By the Root-Factor Theorem, we may write P (z) =
(z z0 )Q(z), with Q(z) a polynomial of degree n and leading coefficient 1. By
induction, Q(z) = (z 1 ) (z n ), so putting n+1 = z0 we get
P (z) = (z 1 ) (z n )(z n+1 ).
More generally, let F be a field: that is, a set endowed with two binary operations
denoted + and and satisfying the field axioms (P0) through (P9) from Chapter
1. We say that F is algebraically closed if every nonconsant polynomial P (x)
with coefficients in F has a root in F , i.e., there is x0 F such that P (x0 ) = 0. In
this terminology, the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra asserts precisely that the
complex field C is algebraically closed.
Exercise: Let F be an algebraically closed field. Show that the conclusion of Corollary 15.14 holds for F : that is, every nonconstant polynomial factors as a product
of linear polynomials.
Since every real number is, in particular, a complex number, Corollary 15.14 applies
in particular to polynomials over R: if P (x) = an xn + . . . + a1 x + a0 with an 6= 0,
then there are complex numbers 1 , . . . , n such that
P (x) = an (x 1 )(x 2 ) (x n ).
But since the coefficients of P are real, it is natural to ask whether or to what
extent some or all of the roots i must also be real. Recall that we need not have
any real roots (that is, the field R is not algebraically closed), for any n Z+ , the
polynomial Pn (x) = (x2 + 1)n is positive for all real x, so has no real roots. And
indeed, its factorization over C is (x2 + 1)n = (x + i)n (x i)n .
However, the polynomials Pn all had even degree. Recall that, as a consequence
329
of the Intermediate Value Theorem, every polynomial of odd degree has at least
one real root (and need not have more than one, as the family of examples xPn (x)
shows). So there is some relation between the parity (i.e., the evenness or oddness)
of the degree of a real polynomial and its real and complex roots. This observation
can be clarified and sharpened in terms of the operation z = a + bi 7 a bi = z of
complex conjugation.
Lemma 15.15. a) For z, a0 , . . . , an C, we have
an z n + . . . + a1 z + a0 = an z n + . . . + a1 z + a0 .
b) Thus, if a0 , . . . , an R, we have
an z n + . . . + a1 z + a0 = an z n + . . . + a1 z + a0 .
c) Let a0 , . . . , an R and put P (z) = an z n + . . . + a1 z + a0 . If z0 C is such that
P (z0 ) = 0, then also P (z0 ) = 0.
Proof. We have already observed that for any z1 , z2 C, z1 + z2 = z1 +z2 and
z1 z2 = z1 z2 . Keeping these identities in mind, the proof becomes a straightforward
exercise which we leave to the reader.
It is part c) of Lemma 15.15 that is important for us: this well-known result often
goes by the description The complex roots of a real polynomial occur in conjugate
pairs. To see why this is relevant, consider the following extremely simple but
extremely important result.
Lemma 15.16. For a complex number z, z R z = z.
Proof. If z R, then z = z + 0i, so z = z 0i = z. Conversely, let z = a + bi.
IF a bi = z = z = a + bi, then (2i)b = 0. Multiplying through by (2i)1 = i
2 ,
we get b = 0, so z = a + 0b R.
Let us say that C is properly complex if it is not a real number. If P (x)
is a polynomial with real coefficients and has the properly complex number as a
root, then by Lemma 15.16 it also has the (distinct!) properly complex number
as a root. By the Root-Factor Theorem, we may write P (z) = (z )(z )P2 (z).
Now wake up! something interesting is about to happen. Namely, if we write
P1 (z) = (z )(z ),
then we claim both P1 (z) and P2 (z) have real coefficients, so we have obtained a
factorization of real polynomials
P (x) = P1 (x)P2 (x).
For P1 (z) we need only write = a + bi and multiply it out:
(z )(z ) = z 2 ( + )z + = z 2 (2a)z + (a2 + b2 ).
For P2 (z) we have to argue a bit more abstractly. Namely, for polynomials over R
(and really, over any field) we can always perform division with remainder: there
are unique real polynomials Q(x), R(x) such that
(119)
We claim R(x) 0 (i.e., it is the zero polynomial). To see this, we use the uniqueness part of the division algorithm in a slightly sneaky way: namely, consider P (x)
330
and P1 (x) as polynomials with complex coefficients and perform the division algorithm there: there are unique complex polynomials, say QC (x) and RC (x), such
that
(120)
Heres the point: on the one hand, real polynomials are complex polynomials, so
comparing (119) and (120) we deduce Q(x) = QC (x) and R(x) = RC (x). On
the other hand, the identity P (x) = P1 (x)P2 (x) of complex polynomials shows
that we may take QC (x) = P2 (x) and RC (x) 0. Putting these together, we get
Q(x) = P2 (x) and R(x) 0, so indeed P (x) = P1 (x)P2 (x) is a factorization of real
polynomials.
A positive degree polynomial P (x) over a field F is called irrreducible if it cannot
be factored as P (x) = P1 (x)P2 (x) with deg P1 , deg P2 < deg P . (This last condition
is there to prevent trivial factorizations like x2 + 1 = (2) ( 21 x2 + 12 .) A polynomial
of positive degree which is not irreducible is called reducible.
Exercise: Let F be a field, and let P (x) be a polynomial with coefficients in F .
a) Show that if P is irreducible, it has no roots in F .
b) Suppose P has degree 2 and no roots in F . Show that P is irreducible.
c) Suppose P has degree 3 and no roots in F . Show that P is irreducible.
d) For each n 4, exhibit a degree n polynomial with coefficients in R which is
reducible, but has no real roots.
Theorem 15.17. Let P (x) be a real polynomial of degree n 1.
a) There are natural numbers r, s N such that r + 2s = n, linear polynomials
L1 (x), . . . , Lr (x) and irreducible quadratic polynomials Q1 (x), . . . , Qs (x) such that
P (x) = L1 (x) Lr (x)Q1 (x) Qs (x).
b) If n is odd, then P has at least one real root.
Proof. Its harmless to assume that P has leading coefficient 1, and we do so.
a) We go by strong induction on n. When n = 1, P (x) is a linear polynomial, so
we may take r = n = 1, s = 0 and P (x) = L(x). Suppose n 2 and the result
holds for all polynomials of degree less than n, and let P (x) be a real polynomial
of degree n. By the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra, P (x) has a complex root .
If R, then by the Root-Factor Theorem P (x) = (x )P2 (x) and we are done
by induction. If is properly complex, Q(x) = (x )(x ) is a real, irreducible
quadratic polynomial and P (x) = Q(x)P2 (x), and again we are done by induction.
b) Since r + 2s = n, if n is odd we cannot have r = 0. Thus P has at least one
linear factor and thus at least one real root.
The partial fractions decomposition rests on the foundation of Theorem 15.17.
Exercise:1 Let f (z) = an z n + . . . + a1 z + a0 be a complex polynomial with positive
degree. Suppose that for all z C, we have z R f (z) R.
a) Show: a0 , . . . , an R.
b) Show: n = 1.
1Taken from http://math.stackexchange.com/questions/1332641/
331
Thus is a non-negative real number and our job is to show (i) that is actually
attained as a value of M and (ii) = 0.
Step 1: Since for z 6= 0,
|a0 |
|an1 |
+ ... + n ,
|P (z)| = |z|n 1 +
|z|
|z|
it follows that
lim |P (z)| = 1 = .
z
Thus there is R > 0 such that for all z C with |z| > R, |P (z)| > |P (0)|. By
Theorem 15.7, the continuous function |P (z)| assumes a minimum value on the
closed, bounded set {z C | |z| R}, say at z0 . But R was chosen so that
|P (z)| > |P (0)| |P (z0 )| for all z with |z| > R, so altogether |P (z)| |P (z0 )| for
all z C and thus = inf zC |P (z)| = |P (z0 )|.
Step 2: Seeking a contradiction, we suppose > 0. Define Q : C C by
0)
Q(z) = PP(z+z
(z0 ) . Thus Q is also a degree n polynomial function, Q(z) = 1, and by
minimality of z0 , |Q(z)| 1 for all z C. We may write Q(z) = 1+bk z k +. . .+bn z n
with bk 6= 0 for some 1 k n. Let w C be such that
|bk |
wk =
;
bk
the existence of such a w is guaranteed by Lemma 15.12. Then for r (0, ),
Q(rw) = 1 + bk rk wk + bk+1 rk+1 wk+1 + . . . + bn rn wn
= 1 rk |bk | rwk+1 bk+1 . . . rnk wn bn = 1 rk (|bk | + C(r)) ,
where we have set C(r) = rwk+1 bk+1 . . . rnk wb bn . Thus
|Q(rw)| = |1 rk (|bk | + C(r))| |1 rk |bk || + |rk C(r)|.
As r approaches 0 from the right, rk |bk | and C(r) both approach 0. Thus for
sufficiently small r, we have rk |bk | < 1 and |C(r)| < |bk | and then
|Q(rw)| |1 rk |bk || + |rk C(r)| = 1 rk (|bk | |C(r)|) < 1.
This contradicts the fact that minzC |Q(z)| = 1 and completes the proof.
CHAPTER 16
Foundations Revisited
The reader should picture a street mime juggling non-existent balls. As the mime
continues, the action of juggling slowly brings the balls into existence, at first in
dim outline and then into solid reality. T.W. Korner1
An ordered field F is Dedekind complete if every nonempty subset which is
bounded above has a least upper bound (or supremum).
Exercise 16.0: Show that an ordered field is Dedekind complete iff every nonempty
subset which is bounded below has a greatest upper bound (or infimum).
Our initial definition of R was precisely that it was a Dedekind complete ordered
field. Practically speaking, this is a great foundation for honors calculus and real
analysis, because it contains all the information we need to know about R.
In other words, we have put a neat little black box around our foundational problems. Real analysis works perfectly well without ever having to look in the box.
But curiosity is a fundamental part of mathematics, and at some point most of us
will want to look in the box. This chapter is for those who have reached that point,
i.e., who want to understand a proof of the following theorem.
Theorem 16.1. (Black Box Theorem)
a) There is a Dedekind complete ordered field.
b) If F1 and F2 are Dedekind complete ordered fields, they are isomorphic: that is,
there is a bijection : F1 F2 such that:
(i) For all x, y F1 , (x + y) = (x) + (y).
(ii) For all x, y F1 , (xy) = (x)(y).
(iii) For all x, y F1 , x y (x) (y).
c) The isomorphism of part b) is unique: there is exactly one such map between
any two Dedekind complete ordered fields.
The Black Box Theorem explains why we never needed any further axioms of R
beyond the fact that it is a Dedekind complete ordered field: there is exactly one
such structure, up to isomorphism.2
1Thomas William K
orner, 1946
2The student unfamiliar with the notion of isomorphism should think of it as nothing else
than a relabelling of the points of R. For instance consider the x-axis Rx = {(a, 0) | a R}
and the y-axis Ry = {(0, a) | a R} in the plane. These are two copies of R. Are they the
same? Not in a hard-nosed set-theoretic sense: they are different subsets of the plane. But
they are essentially the same: the bijection which carries (a, 0) 7 (0, a) preserves the addition,
multiplication and order relation. So really we have two slightly different presentations of the same
333
334
We will prove the Black Box Theorem...eventually. But rather than taking the
most direct possible route we broaden our focus to a study of the structure of
ordered fields, not just Q and R.
1. Ordered Fields
1.1. Basic Definitions.
In this section we revisit the considerations of 1.2 from a somewhat different perspective. Before we listed certain ordered field axioms, but the perspective there
was that we were collecting true, and basic, facts about the real numbers for use in
our work with them. This time our perspective is to study and understand the collection of all ordered fields. One of our main goals is to construct the real numbers
R in terms of the rational numbers Q and to understand this in terms of a more
general process, completion, which can be applied in any ordered field.
A field is a set F endowed with two binary operations + and which satisfy
all of the field axioms (P0) through (P9). To a first approximation, these axioms
simply encode the usual rules of addition, subtraction, multiplication and division
of numbers, so any field can be thought of as a kind of generalized number system. The most important basic examples are the rational numbers Q, the real
numbers R, and the complex numbers C. But there are other examples which seem
farther removed from the usual numbers: e.g. finite fields like F2 = {0, 1} are
smaller than what we normally think of as a number system, whereas the set R(t) of
all rational functions (with real coefficients) is a field whose elements are naturally
regarded as functions, not as numbers.
Field theory is an active branch of mathematical research, with several texts and
thousands of papers devoted to it (e.g. [FT]). Nevertheless the very simple properties of fields established in 1.2.1 will be sufficient for our needs here, in part
because we are not interested in fields per se but rather ordered fields. An ordered
field is a field equipped with the additional structure of a total order relation,
namely a binary relation which satisfies:
(TO1)
(TO2)
(TO3)
(TO4)
1. ORDERED FIELDS
335
336
Proof. Assume to the contrary that there are x 6= y F with f (x) = f (y).
Then f (x y) = f (x) f (y) = 0. Since x 6= y, x y 6= 0, and thus we have a
1
multiplicative inverse xy
. Then
1 = f (1) = f ((x y)
1
1
1
) = f (x y)f (
) = 0 f(
) = 0,
xy
xy
xy
1. ORDERED FIELDS
337
338
in a non-Archimedean field.
By definition, an ordered field K is Archimedean if Z is cofinal in K. Equivalently, K is Archimedean iff Q is cofinal in K.
Let F be a subfield of the ordered field F . We say that F is dense in K if
for all x < y K, there is z F such that x < z < y.
Lemma 16.4. Let K be an ordered field, and let F be a subfield of K. If F is
dense in K, then F is cofinal in K.
Proof. We show the contrapositive: suppose F is not cofinal in K: there is
x K such that for all y F , y x. Then the interval (x, x + 1) contains no
points of F , so F is not dense in K.
More generally, let f : F F 0 be a homomorphism of ordered fields. We say that
f is cofinal if the image f (F ) is a cofinal subfield of F 0 . We say that f is dense
if the image f (F ) is a dense subfield of F 0 .
Exercise 16.10: Let K be a subfield of F .
a) Suppose that for every F , there is a sequence {xn } of elements of K such
that xn . Show that K is a dense subfield of F .
b) Does the converse of part a) hold? (Hint: no, but counterexamples are not so
easy to come by.)
Lemma 16.5. For a homomorphism f : F F 0 of ordered fields, TFAE:
(i) f is cofinal.
(ii) For every positive 0 F 0 , there is a positive F such that f () < 0 .
Exercise 16.11: Prove Lemma 16.5. (Hint: take reciprocals!)
Lemma 16.6. For an ordered field F , the following are equivalent:
(i) F is Archimedean.
(ii) Q is a dense subfield of F .
Proof. (i) = (ii): Suppose F is Archimedean and let x < y F . Let
1
n Z+ be such that yx
< n; then 0 < n1 < y x, so
1
< y.
n
(ii) = (i): If Q is dense in F then by Lemma 16.4, Q is cofinal in F .
x<x+
1. ORDERED FIELDS
339
340
On the other hand, in an arbitrary ordered field a Cauchy sequence need not be
convergent. For instance the Babylonian
sequence
{xn } of VII.2.2 is a sequence
Since = f () is a positive element of F 0 , this shows that {f (xn )} is not Cauchy.
Thus we get a method for producing nonconvergent Cauchy sequences in an ordered
field F : find a sequence {xn } in F and a homomorphism f : F F 0 such that
f (xn ) converges to an element of F 0 \ f (F ). In fact every nonconvergent Cauchy
sequence arises this way, as we will see later on.
Let F and F 0 be ordered fields, and let f : F F 0 be a map between them.
We say that f is continuous at c F if for all positive 0 F 0 , there is a positive F such that for all x F with |x c| < , |f (x) f (c)| < 0 . We say
that f : F F 0 is continuous if it is continuous at every c F . We say that
f : F F 0 is uniformly continuous if for all positive 0 F 0 there is a positive
F such that for all x, x0 F , if |x x0 | < then |f (x) f (x0 )| < 0 .
Lemma 16.12. Let f : F F 0 be a function.
a) If f is continuous and xn is a sequence in F which converges to x F , then
f (xn ) f (x) in F 0 .
b) If f is uniformly continuous and {xn } is a Cauchy sequence in F , then {f (xn )}
is a Cauchy sequence in F 0 .
Proof. Left to the reader.
1. ORDERED FIELDS
341
342
P
in K consists of, for each m Z+ a formal Laurent series xm = nZ am,n tn , so in
fact for each n Z we have a real sequence {am,n }
m=1 . Now consider the following
conditions on a sequence {xm } in K:
(i) There is an integer N such that for all m Z+ and n < N , am,n = 0, and
(ii) For each n Z the sequence am,n is eventually constant: i.e., for all sufficiently
large m, am,n = Cn R. (Because of (i) we must have Cn = 0 for all n < N .)
Then condition (i) is equivalent to boundedness of the sequence.
P
I claim that if the sequence converges say xm x = n=N an tn F then (i)
and (ii) both hold. Indeed convergent sequences are bounded, so (i) holds. Then for
all n N , am,n is eventually constant in m iff am,n an is eventually constant in m,
so we may consider xm x instead of xm and thus we may assume that xm 0 and
try to show that for each fixed n, am,n is eventually equal to 0. As above, this holds
iff for all k 0, there exists Mk such that for all m Mk , |xm | tk . This latter
condition holds iff the coefficient am,n of tn in xn is zero for all N < k. Thus, for all
m Mk , am,N = am,N +1 = . . . = am,k1 = 0, which is what we wanted to show.
Conversely, suppose (i) and (ii) hold. Then since for all n N the sequence
am,n is eventually constant, we may define an to be this P
eventual value, and an
argument very similar to the above shows that xm x = nN an tn .
Next I claim that if a sequence {xn } is Cauchy, then it satisfies (i) and (ii) above,
hence is convergent. Again (i) is immediate because every Cauchy sequence is
bounded. The Cauchy condition here says: for all k 0, there exists Mk such
that for all m, m0 Mk we have |xm x0m | tk , or equivalently, for all n < k,
am,n am0 ,n = 0. In other words this shows that for each fixed n < k and all
m Mk , the sequence am,n is constant, so in particular for all n N the sequence
am,n is eventually constant in m, so the sequence xm converges.
Exercise 16.15: Show that the subfield R((t2 )) of R((t)) is cofinal but not dense.
2. The Sequential Completion
2.1. Sequentially Complete Fields.
An ordered field F is sequentially complete if every Cauchy sequence in F converges to an element of F . We have seen that a Dedekind complete ordered field is
sequentially complete. Here we wish to examine the converse.
Theorem 16.14. For an Archimedean ordered field F , TFAE:
(i) F is Dedekind complete.
(ii) F is sequentially complete: every Cauchy sequence converges.
Proof. The implication (i) = (ii) is the content of Theorem 10.32, since
the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem holds in any ordered field satisfying (LUB).
(ii) = (i): Let S F be nonempty and bounded above, and write U(S) for
the set of least upper bounds of S. Our strategy will be to construct a decreasing
Cauchy sequence in U(S) and show that its limit is sup S.
343
so an
1
2n
kn 1
2n
The proof of (ii) = (i) in Theorem 16.14 above is taken from [HS] by way of
[Ha11]. It is rather unexpectedly complicated, but I do not know a simpler proof
at this level. However, if one is willing to introduce the notion of convergent and
Cauchy nets, then one can show first that in an Archimedean ordered field, the
convergence of all Cauchy sequences implies the convergence of all Cauchy nets,
and second use the hypothesis that all Cauchy nets converge to give a proof which
is (in my opinion of course) more conceptually transparent. This is the approach
taken in my (more advanced) notes on Field Theory [FT].
In fact there are (many!) non-Archimedean sequentially complete ordered fields.
We will attempt to describe two very different examples of such fields here. We
hasten to add that this is material that the majority of working research mathematicians are happily unfamiliar with, and which is thus extremely rarely covered
in undergraduate courses. Only the exceptionally curious need the next section.
2.2. Sequential Completion I: Statement and Applications.
We will now establish one of our main results: for every ordered field F , there
is a sequentially complete ordered field R and a homomorphism f : F R.
In fact we can, and will prove, even more than this. The point is that there will
be many (nonisomorphic) sequentially complete fields into which any given ordered
344
field embeds. For example, when we construct the real numbers we will have an
embedding Q , R. But we also have an embedding R , R((t)), so taking the
composite gives an embedding Q R((t)). (There is no way that R and R((t)) are
isomorphic, since the former is Archimedean and the latter is not.)
We would like a general definition which allows us to prefer the embedding
Q , R to the embedding Q , R((t)). The key observation is that, since R is
Archimedean, the embedding of Q into R is dense, whereas since R((t)) is not
Archimedean, the embedding of Q into R is not dense. This leads to the following
important definition.
A sequential completion of an ordered field F is a dense embedding F , R
into a sequentially complete ordered field.
Lemma 16.15. For an ordered field F , the following are equivalent.
(i) F is Dedekind complete.
(ii) The inclusion : Q , F makes F into a sequential completion of Q.
Proof. (i) = (ii): By Theorem 16.14, F is sequentially complete and
Archimedean. By Lemma 16.6, Q = (Q) is a dense subfield of F , and it follows
that F is a sequential completion of Q.
We will prove that every ordered field admits a sequential completion. And again,
we will in fact prove a bit more.
Theorem 16.16. Let F be an ordered field.
a) F admits a sequential completion : F R.
b) If L is any sequentially complete ordered field and f : F L is a cofinal ordered
field homomorphism, then there is a unique ordered field homomorphism g : R L
such that f = g .
Corollary 16.17. Two sequential completions of the same ordered field are
isomorphic.
Proof. Let 1 : F R1 and 2 : F R2 be two sequential completions.
Applying Theorem 16.16 with R = R1 and f = 2 : F R2 , we get a unique
homomorphism g : R1 R2 such that 2 = g 1 . Interchanging the roles of R1
and R2 we also get a unique homomorphism g 0 : R2 R1 such that 1 = g 0 2 .
Now consider g 0 g : R1 R . We have
(g 0 g) 1 = g 0 (g 1 ) = g 0 2 = 1 .
Applying Theorem 16.16 with L = R = R1 we get that there is a unique homomorphism G : R R1 such that G1 = 1 , but clearly the identity map 1R1 has this
property. Thus we must have g 0 g = 1R1 . Similarly considering g g 0 : R2 R2 ,
then in view of
(g g 0 ) 2 = g (g 0 2 ) = g 1 = 2 ,
we deduce that g g 0 = 1R2 . In other words, g and g 0 are mutually inverse isomorphisms...so R1 and R2 are isomorphic.
Applying Theorem 16.16 to the ordered field Q, we get a sequential completion R
of Q. Since R is Archimedean and sequentially complete, by Theorem 16.14, R is
Dedekind complete. Conversely, by Lemma 16.15any Dedekind complete ordered
345
field R0 is isomorphic to R. Thus the existence and uniqueness statements of Theorem 16.16 imply the existence and uniqueness up to isomorphism of a Dedekind
complete ordered field.
The uniqueness statement can be strengthened: let R1 and R2 be two Dedekind
complete ordered fields. We claim that not only are they isomorphic, but that the
isomorphism between them is unique. Indeed, for i = 1, 2 let i : Q Ri be the
inclusion maps. We saw above that there is a unique map g : R1 R2 such that
g 1 = 2 and this g is an isomorphism. But any isomorphism h : R1 R2
will satisfy h 1 = 2 , since in fact there is exactly one embedding from Q into
any ordered field. Thus whereas in general there is an isomorphim g between two
sequential completions of a given ordered field F which is unique such that blah
blah blah (more precisely, such that g 1 = 2 ), in this case the blah blah blah
is vacuous and the isomorphism is unique full stop.
In abstract mathematics, uniqueness up to a unique isomorphism is as close to
identical as we can reasonably ask for two structures to be. (Even the horizontal
copy of R and the vertical copy of R are different sets, but the obvious isomorphism between them is the only isomorphism, so no trouble can arise by identifying
the two.) We denote this unique field by R and call it the real numbers...of course.
2.3. Sequential Completion II: The Proof.
Now we are properly motivated to roll up our sleeves and endure the rather lengthy,
technical proof of Theorem 16.16. The essential idea (which is indeed due to A.L.
Cauchy) is to build the sequential completion directly from the set C of all Cauchy
sequences in F .
We can observe that C itself has some structure reminiscent of an ordered field
but that things do not quite work out: it is somehow too large to itself be an ordered field. Namely, it makes perfectly good sense to add, subtract and multiply
Cauchy sequences in F . For that matter, it makes perfectly good sense to add,
subtract and multiply arbitrary sequences in F : we simply put
{xn } + {yn } = {xn + yn },
{xn } {yn } = {xn yn },
{xn } {yn } = {xn yn }.
It remains to check that these operations take Cauchy sequences to Cauchy sequences. At the very beginning of our study of sequences we showed this for
convergent sequences (in R, but the proofs certainly did not use any form of the
completeness axiom). It is no more difficult to establish the analogue for Cauchy
sequences in F .
Lemma 16.18. Let F be any ordered field, and let a , b be Cauchy sequences.
Then a + b and a b are both Cauchy.
Proof. Since a and b are both Cauchy, for > 0 there is N Z+ such that
for m, n N , |am an | < and and |bm bn | < . Then
|(am + bm ) (an + bn )| |am an | + |bm bn | < 2.
346
Further, since the sequences are Cauchy, they are bounded: there are Ma , Mb F
such that |an | Ma and |bn | Mb for all n Z+ . Then for m, n N ,
|am bm an bn | |am an ||bm | + |an ||bm bn | (Ma + Mb ).
So does this addition and multiplication endow C with the structure of a field?
There is an additive identity, namely the sequence with xn = 0 for all n. There
is also a multiplicative identity, namely the sequence with xn = 1 for all n. It all
works well until we get to multiplicative inverses.
Exercise 16.16: Let {xn } be a sequence in the ordered field F .
a) Show that there is a sequence {yn } with {xn } {yn } = {1} if and only if for all
n Z+ , xn 6= 0.
b) Show that if {xn } is Cauchy and xn 6= 0 for all n, then its inverse { x1n } is again
a Cauchy sequence.
Thus there are plenty of Cauchy sequences other than the constantly zero sequence
which do not have multiplicative inverses: e.g. (0, 1, 1, 1, . . .), or indeed any constant
sequence which takes the value 0 at least once. Thus C has many good algebraic
properties, but it is not the case that every nonzero element has a multiplicative
inverse, so it is not a field.5
We also have some order structure on C. For instance, it is tempting to define
{xn } > {yn } if xn > yn for all n. This turns out not to be a good definition in the
sense that it does not lead to a trichotomy: there will be unequal Cauchy sequences
{xn } and {yn } for which neither is less than the other, e.g.
{xn } = {0, 1, 1, . . .}, {yn } = {1, 0, 0, . . .}.
As in the definition of convergence, it is more fruitful to pay attention to what
a Cauchy sequence is doing eventually. Exploiting this idea we can get a sort of
trichotomy result.
Lemma 16.19. (Cauchy Trichotomy) For a Cauchy sequence {xn } in an ordered
field F , exactly one of the following holds:
(i) There is a positive element F and N Z+ such that xn for all n N .
(ii) There is a positive element F and N Z+ such that xn for all n N .
(iii) xn converges to 0.
Proof. It is easy to see that the conditions are mutually exclusive. Let us
suppose that (iii) does not hold: thus there is > 0 and a subsequence {xnk }
such that |xnk | for all k Z+ . By passing to a further subsequence we may
assume either that xnk for all k or xnk for all k. Let us suppose that
the former holds and show that this implies (i): if so, replacing x by x shows
that the latter alternative implies (ii). Since {xn } is Cauchy, there is N Z+ such
that |xm xn | 2 for all m, n N . Putting these two conditions together we get
xn 2 for all n N .
5for those who know some abstract algebra: what weve shown is that (C, +, ) is a commutative ring. There is a very general algebraic method which, when given a commutative ring,
will yield a collection of fields defined in terms of that ring. The present construction is indeed
an instance of this.
347
Unfortunately this is not quite the kind of trichotomy which defines a total order
relation: we have some elements that we regard as positive case (i) above, some
elements that we regard as negative case (ii) above but for an order relation
only the zero element should be neither positive nor negative, whereas case (iii)
above includes the much larger collection of elements converging to zero.
Lemma 16.19 suggests that if we could somehow squash down the subset of
Cauchy sequences which converge to 0 to a single point, then we would actually get
a total order relation. This business of squashing subsets to a point is formalized
in mathematics (more so in algebra and topology than the part of mathematics
weve been studying for most of this text!) by an equivalence relation. Rather
than providing a logically complete but pedagogically useless whirlwind tour of
equivalence relations, we will simply assume that the reader is familiar with them.6
Namely, we regard any two Cauchy sequences which converge to 0 as equivalent.
We are left with the question of when to regard two Cauchy sequences which do
not converge to zero as equivalent. We could simply not squash them, i.e., declare two such sequences to be equivalent exactly when they are equal. But a
little exploration shows that this wont work: well get a total order relation but it
wont interact well with the algebraic structure. For instance, consider the Cauchy
sequences
{xn } = (0, 0, 1, 1, 1, . . .), {yn } = (1, 1, 1, 1, . . .).
The difference {xn } {yn } converges to 0 so is getting identified with 0. Thus we
should identify {xn } and {yn } as well. This leads to the following key definitions.
Let Z be the set of all sequences in F which converge to 0; convergent sequences
are Cauchy, so certainly Z C. For two Cauchy sequences a , b C, we put
a b a b Z.
In words, two Cauchy sequences are equivalent iff their difference converges to zero.
Exercise 16.17 (if you know abstract algebra): Show that Z is a maximal ideal
in the commutative ring C. Why is this an exciting sign that were on the right
track?
Exercise 16.18: Let {xn } be a Cauchy sequence in F , and let {xnk } be any subsequence. Show that {xn } {xnk }.
Now we define R as C/ , that is, the set of equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences. This will be the underlying set of our sequential completion. It remains
to endow it with all the rest of the structure. The idea here is that when we
pass to a quotient by an equivalence relation we can try to simply carry over the
structure we already had, but at every step we must check that the operations are
well-defined, meaning they are independent of the chosen equivalence class. At no
point are these verifications difficult, but we admit they can be somewhat tedious.
Let us check the addition and multiplication induced well-defined operations on
6At UGA they are covered in the transitional Math 3200 course. The reader who has made
it through most of this text will have no problem learning this concept.
348
the set R of equivalence classes. This means: if we have four Cauchy sequences
a , b , c , d and a c , b d , then
a + b c + d , a b c d .
All right: since a c and b d , a c 0 and b d 0, so
(a + b (c + d ) = (a c ) + (b d ) 0 + 0 = 0,
so a + b c + d . Similarly,
a b c d = (a c )b + (b d )c ,
and this converges to 0 because a c , b d 0 and b , c are bounded. Thus
we have equipped our set R with two binary operations + and .
Proposition 16.20. (R, +, ) is a field.
Proof. Most of these axioms are completely straightforward (but, yes, somewhat tedious) to verify and are left to the reader as exercises. Let us single out:
(P3) The additive identity is [0 ], the class of the constant sequence 0.
(P7) The multiplicative identity is [1 ], the class of the constant sequence 1.
(P8) Suppose that x R \ {[0 ]}, and let x be any Cauchy sequence representing
x. Then we must have xn 6= 0 for all sufficiently large n: indeed, otherwise we
would have 0 = (0, 0, 0, . . .) as a subsequence, and if a subsequence of a Cauchy
sequence converges to 0, then the Cauchy sequence itself converges to 0, contradiction. Suppose xn 6= 0 for all n > N . Then define y by yn = 0 for all 1 n N
(or whatever you want: it doesnt matter) and yn = x1n for n > N . Then xn yn = 1
for all n > N , so x y differs from 1 by a sequence which is convergent to zero:
[x ][y = [1 ] = 1, so y = [y ] is the multiplicative inverse of x = [x ].
We now equip R with an ordering. For a , b C, we put [a ] > [b ] if there is a
positive element in F such that an bn for all sufficiently large n. We claim
that this is well-defined independent of the representatives a and b chosen. Indeed,
if x and y converge to zero, then for sufficiently large n we have |xn yn | < 2
and then
an + xn ) (bn + yn ) = (an bn ) + (xn yn ) .
2
Theorem 16.21. The strict ordering < on R endows it with the structure of
an ordered field.
Proof. Step 1: The trichotomy property follows from Lemma 16.19. The
transitive property is easy: if [a ] < [b ] and [b ] < [c ], then there is N Z+
and 1 , 2 > 0 such that for all n N , bn an 1 and cn bn 2 , hence
cn an = (cn bn ) + (bn an ) 1 + 2 . Thus < is a strict ordering on R.
Step 2: If [a ], [b ] > 0, then as above there is N Z+ and 1 , 2 > 0 such that
for all n N , an 1 and bn 2 . Then for all n N , an + bn 1 + 2 and
an bn 1 2 .
Proposition 16.22. For an ordered field F , let : F R by sending x F
to the class of the constant sequence (x, x, . . .). Then is a dense homomorphism
of ordered fields.
Proof. Step 1: It is immediate that is a field homomorphism. Further, if
x > 0, then (x, x, . . .) > 0: indeed, we can take = x. So is a homomorphism of
ordered fields.
349
Existence: We must show that putting g(x) = y as above defines an ordered field
homomorphism from R to L. If x1 = [an ] and x2 = [bn ], let y1 = limn f (an )
and y2 = limn f (bn ). Then an + bn x1 + x2 and f (an + bn ) = f (an ) +
f (bn ) y1 + y2 , so g(x1 + x2 ) = y1 + y2 = g(x1 ) + g(x2 ). Similarly, an bn x1 x2
and f (an bn ) = f (an )f (bn ) y1 y2 , so g(x1 x2 ) = y1 y2 = g(x1 )g(x2 ). Finally, if
350
x = [a ] > 0, then there is a positive F such that an for all sufficiently large
n, so
g(x) = lim f (an ) lim f () = f () > 0.
n
Bibliography
[A]
T.M. Apostol, Calculus. Volume One.
[Ab84] Y.S. Abu-Mostafa, A Differentiation Test for Absolute Convergence. Math. Mag. 57
(1984), 228-231.
[Ac00] F. Acerbi, Plato: Parmenides 149a7-c3. A Proof by Complete Induction? Archive for
History of the Exact Sciences 55 (2000), 5776.
[ADC12] S. Ali and M. Deutsche Cohen, The phi-ratio tests. Elem. Math. 67 (2012), 164-168.
[Al08] S.A. Ali, The mth ratio test: new convergence tests for series. Amer. Math. Monthly 115
(2008), 514-524.
[An95] P. Andrews, Where not to find the critical points of a polynomialvariation on a Putnam
theme. Amer. Math. Monthly 102 (1995), 155-158.
[Ap73] T.M. Apostol, Another Elementary Proof of Eulers Formula for (2n). Amer. Math.
Monthly 80 (1973), 425431.
[As12] J.M. Ash, The Limit Comparison Test Needs Positivity. Math. Magazine 85 (2012), 374
375.
[Ba96] R.G. Bartle, Return to the Riemann integral. Amer. Math. Monthly 103 (1996), 625-632.
[B]
J.C. Bowman, Honours Calculus, online lecture notes.
[Ba70] R. Baer, Dichte, Archimedizit
at und Starrheit geordneter K
orper. Math. Ann. 188 (1970),
165-205.
[Ba22] S. Banach, Sur les op
erations dans les ensembles abstraits et leur applications aux
equations int
egrales. Fund. Math. 3 (1922), 133181.
[Ba98] B. Banaschewski, On proving the existence of complete ordered fields. Amer. Math.
Monthly 105 (1998), 548551.
[Be06] A.F. Beardon, Contractions of the Real Line. Amer. Math. Monthly 113 (2006), 557558.
[Be12] S.J. Bernstein, D
emonstration du th
eor`
eme de Weierstrass fond
ee sur le calcul des probabilit
es. Communications of the Kharkov Mathematical Society 13 (1912), 12.
Besenyei, Lebesgues Road to Antiderivatives. Math. Mag. 86 (2013), 255260.
[Be13] A.
Besenyei, Peanos unnoticed proof of Borels theorem. Amer. Math. Monthly 121
[Be14] A.
(2014), 69-72.
[BM22] H. Bohr and J. Mollerup, Lrebog i matematisk Analyse, vol. 3, Jul. Gjellerups Forlag,
Copenhagen, 1922.
[Bo71] R.P. Boas, Jr., Signs of Derivatives and Analytic Behavior. Amer. Math. Monthly 78
(1971), 10851093.
Borel, Sur quelque points de la th
[Bo95] E.
eorie des fonctions. Ann. Sci. lEcole
Norm. Sup. 12
(1895), 955.
[BS]
R.G. Bartle and D.R. Sherbert, Introduction to real analysis. Second edition. John Wiley
& Sons, Inc., New York, 1992.
[C]
H. Cartan, Elementary theory of analytic functions of one or several complex variables.
Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1995.
[Ca21] A.L. Cauchy, Analyse alg
ebrique, 1821.
[Ca89] A.L. Cauchy, Sur la convergence des s
eries, in Oeuvres compl`
etes S
er. 2, Vol. 7, GauthierVillars (1889), 267279.
[Ch01] D.R. Chalice, How to Differentiate and Integrate Sequences. Amer. Math. Monthly 108
(2001), 911921.
[CJ]
R. Courant and F. John, Introduction to Calculus and Analysis.
[Cl10] P.L. Clark, Real induction. http://math.uga.edu/pete/realinduction.pdf
[Cl11] P.L.
Clark,
Induction
and
completeness
in
ordered
sets.
http://math.uga.edu/pete/induction completeness brief.pdf
351
352
[Co77]
BIBLIOGRAPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHY
353
[K
o91] T.W. K
orner, Differentiable functions on the rationals. Bull. London Math. Soc. 23
(1991), 557-562.
[La]
J. Labute, Math 255, Lecture 22:
Power Series:
The Binomial Series.
http://www.math.mcgill.ca/labute/courses/255w03/L22.pdf
[L]
S. Lang, Undergraduate analysis. Second edition. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics.
Springer-Verlag, New York, 1997.
[Li33] F.A Lindemann, The Unique Factorization of a Positive Integer. Quart. J. Math. 4,
319320, 1933.
[LV06] M. Longo and V. Valori, The Comparison Test Not Just for Nonnegative Series. Math.
Magazine 79 (2006), 205210.
[Lu99] J. Lu, Is the Composite Function Integrable? Amer. Math. Monthly 106 (1999), 763766.
[Ma56] A.M. Macbeath, A criterion for differentiability. Edinburgh Math. Notes (1956), 8-11.
[Ma42] C. Maclaurin, Treatise of fluxions, 1. Edinburgh (1742), 289290.
P
2
1
[Ma61] Y. Matsuoka, An elementary proof of the formula
k=1 k2 = 6 . Amer. Math. Monthly
68 (1961), 485487.
[MK09] M.M.
Marjanovi
c
and
Z.
Kadelburg,
Limits
of
composite
functions.
The
Teaching
of
Mathematics,
XII
(2009),
16.
http://elib.mi.sanu.ac.rs/files/journals/tm/22/tm1211.pdf
[Me08] A. Melman, Bounds on the zeros of the derivative of a polynomial with all real zeros.
Amer. Math. Monthly 115 (2008), 145-147.
[Me72] F. Mertens, Ueber die Multiplicationsregel f
ur zwei unendliche Reihen. Journal f
ur die
Reine und Angewandte Mathematik 79 (1874), 182184.
[MS22] E.H. Moore and H.L. Smith, A General Theory of Limits. Amer. J. of Math. 44 (1922),
102121.
[Mo50] R.K. Morley, Classroom Notes: The Remainder in Computing by Series. Amer. Math.
Monthly 57 (1950), 550551.
[Mo51] R.K. Morley, Classroom Notes: Further Note on the Remainder in Computing by Series.
Amer. Math. Monthly 58 (1951), 410412.
[Mo57] T.E. Mott, Newtons method and multiple roots. Amer. Math. Monthly 64 (1957), 635638.
[Mu63] A.A. Mullin, Recursive function theory (A modern look at a Euclidean idea). Bulletin of
the American Mathematical Society 69 (1963), 737.
[Ne03] Nelsen, R.B. An Impoved Remainder Estimate for Use with the Integral Test. College
Math. Journal 34 (2003), 397399.
[Ne81] D.J. Newman, Differentiation of asymptotic formulas. Amer. Math. Monthly 88 (1981),
526-527.
[NP88] D.J. Newman and T.D. Parsons, On monotone subsequences. Amer. Math. Monthly 95
(1988), 44-45.
[No52] M.J. Norris, Integrability of continuous functions. Amer. Math. Monthly 59 (1952), 244245.
[Ol27] L. Olivier, Journal f
ur die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik 2 (1827), 34.
[PFD] P.L.
Clark,
Partial
Fractions
Via
Linear
Algebra,
http://www.math.uga.edu/pete/partialfractions.pdf.
[Ro63] K. Rogers, Classroom Notes: Unique Factorization. Amer. Math. Monthly 70 (1963),
547548.
[R]
W. Rudin, Principles of mathematical analysis. Third edition. International Series in
Pure and Applied Mathematics. McGraw-Hill, New York-Auckland-D
usseldorf, 1976.
[Sa95] H. Samelson, More on Kummers test. Amer. Math. Monthly 102 (1995), 817-818.
[Sc]
M. Schramm, Introduction to Real Analysis. Dover edition, 2008.
[SP88] D. Scott and D.R. Peeples, The Teaching of Mathematics: A Constructive Proof of the
Partial Fraction Decomposition. Amer. Math. Monthly 95 (1988), 651-653.
[Se59] A. Seidenberg, A simple proof of a theorem of Erd
os and Szekeres. J. London Math. Soc.
34 (1959), 352.
[Sm86] R.S. Smith, Rolle over Lagrange Another Shot at the Mean Value Theorem. College
Math. J. 17 (1986), 403406.
[S]
M. Spivak, Calculus. Fourth edition.
[St95] S.K. Stein, Do Estimates of an Integral Really Improve as n Increases? Math. Mag. 68
(1995), 16-26.
354
[St37]
[St48]
[Str90]
[Ta55]
[To94]
[T]
[Ve02]
[Wa48]
[Wa95]
[Wa36]
[Ze34]
BIBLIOGRAPHY
M.H. Stone, Applications of the theory of Boolean rings to general topology. Trans. Amer.
Math. Soc. 41 (1937), 375-481.
M.H. Stone, The generalized Weierstrass approximation theorem. Math. Mag. 21 (1948),
167-184.
G. Strang, Sums and Differences vs. Integrals and Derivatives. College Math. Journal 21
(1990), 2027.
A. Tarski, A lattice-theoretical fixpoint theorem and its applications. Pacific J. Math. 5
(1955), 285-309.
J.C. Tong, Kummers test gives characterizations for convergence or divergence of all
positive series. Amer. Math. Monthly 101 (1994), 450-452.
J.W. Tukey, Convergence and Uniformity in Topology. Annals of Mathematics Studies,
no. 2. Princeton University Press, 1940.
D.J. Velleman, Partial fractions, binomial coefficients, and the integral of an odd power
of sec . Amer. Math. Monthly 109 (2002), 746-749.
H.S. Wall, A modification of Newtons method. Amer. Math. Monthly 55 (1948), 90-94.
J.A. Walsh, The Dynamics of Newtons Method for Cubic Polynomials. The College
Mathematics Journal 26 (1995), 2228.
M. Ward, A Calculus of Sequences. Amer. J. Math. 58 (1936), 255266.
E. Zermelo, Elementare Betrachtungen zur Theorie der Primzahlen. Nachr. Gesellsch.
Wissensch. G
ottingen 1, 4346, 1934.