of Man's Last End: First Part of The Second Part (Qq. 1-114)
of Man's Last End: First Part of The Second Part (Qq. 1-114)
1-114)
Question
1. Of Man's Last End
ARTICLE 1. Whether it belongs to man to act for an end?
(Human Acts - free will act is any thought, word, deed, desire, or omission which comes
from a man acting with full knowledge of what he is doing, who is free to act or to refrain from
action, and who gives the full assent of his will to the act.
Acts of Man - Other acts performed by a man, but inadvertently, or without full
knowledge, freedom, and choice, are indeed acts of a man, but they are not human acts. )
It is evident that human acts are acts for an end, that is, acts done for the purpose of attaining
an end.
all
his
ultimate and perfect fulfillment. This is a single end; man cannot possibly tend to several last
ends.)
human operations. Therefore all men have the same last end, the same ultimate goal. This last
end is complete and enduring satisfaction or fulfillment; such fulfillment is called beatitude or
happiness.)
3.
What
Is
Happiness
ARTICLE 1. Whether happiness is something uncreated?
ARTICLE 2. Whether happiness is an operation?
ARTICLE 3. Whether happiness is an operation of the
sensitive part, or of the intellective part only?
ARTICLE 4. Whether, if happiness is in the intellective part,
it is an operation of the intellect or of the will?
ARTICLE 5. Whether happiness is an operation of the
speculative, or of the practical intellect?
ARTICLE
act?
ARTICLE
ARTICLE
ARTICLE
ARTICLE
ARTICLE
Whether
Whether
Whether
Whether
Whether
involuntariness?
7.
Of
the
Circumstances
of
Human
Acts
ARTICLE 1. Whether a circumstance is an accident of a
human act?
ARTICLE 2. Whether theologians should take note of the
circumstances of human acts?
ARTICLE 3. Whether the circumstances are properly set
forth in the third book of Ethics?
ARTICLE 4. Whether the most important circumstances are
"why" and "in what the act consists"?
8.
Of
the
Will,
in
Regard
to
What
It
Wills
ARTICLE 1. Whether the will is of good only?
ARTICLE 2. Whether volition is of the end only, or also of the
means?
ARTICLE 3. Whether the will is moved by the same act to the
end and to the means?
9.
Of
That
Which
Moves
the
Will
ARTICLE 1. Whether the will is moved by the intellect?
ARTICLE 2. Whether the will is moved by the sensitive
appetite?
ARTICLE 3. Whether the will moves itself?
ARTICLE 4. Whether the will is moved by an exterior
principle?
ARTICLE 5. Whether the will is moved by a heavenly body?
ARTICLE 6. Whether the will is moved by God alone, as
exterior principle?
10. Of the Manner in Which the Will Is Moved
ARTICLE 1. Whether the will is moved to anything naturally?
ARTICLE 2. Whether the will is moved, of necessity, by its
object?
1.
2.
3.
4.
Whether
Whether
Whether
Whether
use
use
use
use
INTROOOOOOOO!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!~
Treatise on habits in particular (qq. 55 to 89): Good habits, i.e., virtues (qq. 55 to 70)
Content in general[edit]
The first part of the Summa is summed up in the premise that God governs the world as the
"universal first cause". God sways the intellect; he gives the power to know and impresses the species
intelligibiles on the mind, and he sways the will in that he holds the good before it as aim, creating
the virtus volendi. "To will is nothing else than a certain inclination toward the object of the volition which
is the universal good." God works all in all, but so that things also themselves exert their proper
efficiency. Here the Areopagitic ideas of the graduated effects of created things play their part in St.
Thomas's thought. The second part of the Summa (two parts, Prima Secundae and Secunda
Secundae) follows this complex of ideas. Its theme is man's striving for the highest end, which is the
blessedness of the visio beata. Here, St. Thomas develops his system of ethics, which has its root
in Aristotle.
In a chain of acts of will, man strives for the highest end. They are free acts, insofar as man has in
himself the knowledge of their end (and therein the principle of action). In that the will wills the end, it
wills also the appropriate means, chooses freely and completes the consensus. Whether the act is
good or evil depends on the end. The "human reason" pronounces judgment concerning the character
of the end; it is, therefore, the law for action. Human acts, however, are meritorious insofar as they
promote the purpose of God and his honor.
By repeating a good action, man acquires a moral habit or a quality that enables him to do the good
gladly and easily. This is true, however, only of the intellectual and moral virtues (which St. Thomas
treats after the manner of Aristotle); the theological virtues are imparted by God to man as a
"disposition", from which the acts here proceed; while they strengthen, they do not form it. The
"disposition" of evil is the opposite alternative. An act becomes evil through deviation from the reason
and from divine moral law. Therefore, sin involves two factors: its substance (or matter) is lust; in form,
however, it is deviation from the divine law.
Sin has its origin in the will, which decides (against reason) for a "changeable good". Since, however,
the will also moves the other powers of man, sin has its seat in these too. By choosing such a lower
good as its end, the will is misled by self-love, so that this works as cause in every sin. God is not the
cause of sin since, on the contrary, he draws all things to himself; but from another side, God is the
cause of all things, so he is efficacious also in sin as actio but not as ens. The devil is not directly the
cause of sin, but he incites the imagination and the sensuous impulse of man (as men or things may
also do).
Sin is original sin. Adam's first sin passes through himself to all the succeeding race; because he is the
head of the human race and "by virtue of procreation human nature is transmitted and along with nature
its infection." The powers of generation are, therefore, designated especially as "infected". The thought
is involved here by the fact that St. Thomas, like other scholastics, believed in creationism; he therefore
taught that souls are created by God. Two things, according to St. Thomas, constituted man's
righteousness in paradise the justitia originalis, or the harmony of all man's powers before they were
blighted by desire, and the possession of the gratis gratum faciens (the continuous, indwelling power of
good). Both are lost through original sin, which, in form, is the "loss of original righteousness." The
consequence of this loss is the disorder and maiming of man's nature, which shows itself in "ignorance;
malice, moral weakness, and especially inconcupiscentia, which is the material principle of original sin."
The course of thought here is as follows: when the first man transgressed the order of his nature
appointed by nature and grace, he (and with him the human race) lost this order. This negative state is
the essence of original sin. From it follow an impairment and perversion of human nature in which
thenceforth lower aims rule, contrary to nature, and release the lower element in man.
Since sin is contrary to the divine order, it is guilt and subject to punishment. Guilt and punishment
correspond to each other; and since the "apostasy from the invariable good which is infinite," fulfilled by
man, is unending, it merits everlasting punishment.
God works even in sinners to draw them to the end by "instructing through the law and aiding by
grace." The law is the "precept of the practical reason." As the moral law of nature, it is the participation
of the reason in the all-determining "eternal reason"; but since man falls short in his appropriation of this
law of reason, there is need of a "divine law"; and since the law applies to many complicated relations,
the practicae dispositiones of the human law must be laid down.
The divine law consists of an old and a new. Insofar as the old divine law contains the moral law of
nature, it is universally valid; what there is in it, however, beyond this is valid only for the Jews. The new
law is "primarily grace itself" and so a "law given within"; "a gift superadded to nature by grace," but not
a "written law." In this sense, as sacramental grace, the new law justifies. It contains, however, an
"ordering" of external and internal conduct and so regarded is, as a matter of course, identical with both
the old law and the law of nature. The consilia show how one may attain the end "better and more
expediently" by full renunciation of worldly goods.
Since man is sinner and creature, he needs grace to reach the final end. The "first cause" alone is able
to reclaim him to the "final end." This is true after the fall, although it was needful before. Grace is, on
one side, "the free act of God", and, on the other side, the effect of this act, the gratia infusa or gratia
creata, a habitus infusus that is instilled into the "essence of the soul," "a certain gift of disposition,
something supernatural proceeding from God into man." Grace is a supernatural ethical character
created in man by God, which comprises in itself all good, both faith and love.
Justification by grace comprises four elements: "the infusion of grace, the influencing of free will toward
God through faith, the influencing of free will respecting sin, and the remission of sins." It is a
"transmutation of the human soul," and takes place "instantaneously". A creative act of God enters,
which, however, executes itself as a spiritual motive in a psychological form corresponding to the nature
of man. Semipelagian tendencies are far removed from St. Thomas. In that man is created anew, he
believes and loves, and now, sin is forgiven. Then begins good conduct; grace is the "beginning of
meritorious works." Aquinas conceives of merit in the Augustinian sense: God gives the reward for that
toward which he himself gives the power. Man can never of himself deserve the prima gratis,"
nor meritum de congruo (by natural ability; cf. R. Seeberg, Lehrbuch der Dogmengeschichte, ii. 105
106, Leipsic, 1898).
After thus stating the principles of morality, in the Secunda Secundae, St. Thomas comes to a minute
exposition of his ethics according to the scheme of the virtues. The conceptions of faith and love are of
much significance in the complete system of St. Thomas. Man strives toward the highest good with the
will or through love; but since the end must first be "apprehended in the intellect," knowledge of the end
to be loved must precede love; "because the will can not strive after God in perfect love unless the
intellect have true faith toward him." Inasmuch as this truth that is to be known is practical, it first incites
the will, which then brings the reason to "assent"; but since, furthermore, the good in question is
transcendent and inaccessible to man by himself, it requires the infusion of a supernatural "capacity" or
"disposition" to make man capable of faith as well as love. Accordingly, the object of both faith and love
is God, involving also the entire complex of truths and commandments that God reveals, insofar as they
in fact relate to God and lead to him. Thus, faith becomes recognition of the teachings and precepts of
the Scriptures and the Church ("the first subjection of man to God is by faith"). The object of faith,
however, is, by its nature, object of love; therefore, faith comes to completion only in love ("by love is
the act of faith accomplished and formed").
Treatise on Law
According to Question 90, Article Four of the Second Part of the Summa, law "is nothing else than an
ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community, and
promulgated." All law comes from the eternal law of Divine Reason that governs the universe, which is
understood and participated in by rational beings (such as men and angels) as the natural law. The
natural law, when codified and promulgated, is the human law. In addition to the human law, dictated by
reason, man also has the divine law, which, according to Question 91, is dictated through revelation,
that man may be "directed how to perform his proper acts in view of his last end," "that man may know
without any doubt what he ought to do and what he ought to avoid," because "human law could not
sufficiently curb and direct interior acts," and since "human law cannot punish or forbid all evil deeds:
since while aiming at doing away with all evils, it would do away with many good things, and would
hinder the advance of the common good, which is necessary for human intercourse." Human law is not
all-powerful; it cannot govern a man's conscience, nor prohibit all vices, nor can it force all men to act
according to its letter, rather than its spirit. Furthermore, it is possible that an edict can be issued
without any basis in law as defined in Question 90; in this case, men are under no compulsion to act,
save as it helps the common good. This separation between law and acts of force also allows men to
depose tyrants, or those who flout the natural law; while removing an agent of the law is contrary to the
common good and the eternal law of God, which orders the powers that be, removing a tyrant is lawful
as he has ceded his claim to being a lawful authority by acting contrary to law.