Elder Abuse: How The Moderns Mistreat Classical Realism: Analytical Essays: Evaluation, Synthesis, Reflections

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 21

International Studies Review (2011) 13, 193213

ANALYTICAL ESSAYS: EVALUATION,


SYNTHESIS, REFLECTIONS

Elder Abuse: How the Moderns Mistreat


Classical Realism1
Joseph M. Parent
University of Miami
Joshua M. Baron
Cambridge Advisors
Neorealists narrate their origins by explaining that classical realists committed a multitude of sins and were therefore displaced. The classics
unscientifically explained world politics primarily through individual-level
characteristics, typically a will to power that drove state behavior and international outcomes. In short, classical realism was inadequately structural
and theoretical; thus, neorealists revised them by prioritizing structural
factors and putting the paradigm on sound scientific footing. We argue
that this narrative is generally incorrect. Classical realists were supremely
structural and competently theoretical. Consequently, the realist tradition
has much more continuity and richness than presently believed.

Neorealists often preach some version of the following story:


Human nature realism, which is sometimes called classical realism, dominated the
study of international relations from the late 1940s, when Morgenthaus writings
began attracting a large audience, until the early 1970s. Human nature realists recognize that international anarchythe absence of a governing authority over the great
powerscauses states to worry about the balance of power. But that structural constraint is treated as a second-order cause of state behavior. The principal driving force
in international politics is the will to power inherent in every state in the system2

By the late 1970s, neorealism swept the field, bringing structure and theory to
the fore of realism.3 So goes the neorealist narrativebut is it correct? If it is,
1
Deep thanks to three anonymous referees, Beth Baron, Richard Betts, Marc Dodge, Erik Gartzke, Robert Jervis,
Paul MacDonald, P. Rogers Nelson, Abigail Parent, Stefano Recchia, Jack Snyder, William Wohlforth, and especially
Kenneth Waltz. Responsibility for recalcitrant errors is remanded to the joint custody of the authors.
2
Mearsheimer (2001:19). For similar recapitulations of the neorealist narrative, see Waltz (1979:47, 6165;
1990:2138); Elman (1996:2021); Mearsheimer (2001:407409); Walt (2002:202203, 207); Barkin (2003:328);
Freyberg-Inan, Harrison, and James (2009:4); Levy and Thompson (2010:3132, 128); cf. Haslam (2002:912, 250).
3
On neorealism see, for example, Waltz (1979); (Walt 1987); Posen (1984); Buzan, Jones, and Little (1993:9).
On classical realism, see, for example, Carr (1995); Morgenthau (1967); Spykman and Rollins (1939:391410);
Meinecke (1998); Fox (1959); Thompson (1955).

doi: 10.1111/j.1468-2486.2011.01021.x
 2011 International Studies Association

194

Elder Abuse

how can there be a realist tradition worthy of the name when there has been a
monumental shift in explanatory emphasis from internal desire to external
compulsion? How is it that a paradigm stressing historical continuity features
profound discontinuity?
We argue that classical realist theory may not be highly systematic, but it is systemic and scientific. While there is some truth to the neorealist narrative, it is
overall an unrealistic presentation of realism. A comparison of classical and neorealist thought on the same level of analysis shows that the two are more fraternal complements than generational substitutes. The vast majority of classical
realists are not human nature realists, and the realist tradition is much more
structural, theoretical, and consistent across time than neorealists contend.
Previous work has not dedicated sustained attention to why the neorealist narrative is incorrect on its own grounds. Other scholarship has restored stress on
moral elements in realism (Rosenthal 1991; Williams 2005; Recchia 2007; Bell
2008; Scheuerman 2009), furnished interesting interdisciplinary perspectives
(Craig 2003:164165; Goddard and Nexon 2005:961), or provided views
from other paradigms (Donnelly 2000:193200; Barkin 2003:325342; Lebow
2004:346348). Our argument adds value by sharpening the intra-realist debate
and clarifying the contributions of classical realism.
This work unfolds in six sections. The first section lays the groundwork of the
study. Then, in the second section, we elaborate our arguments about the continuity of realist thought and in the third expand on the classical realist contributions in theory and method. The fourth section offers explanations of why
classical and human nature realism were conflated, and the fifth investigates
implications of our analysis on current scholarship. Lastly, we sum our arguments and appeal for continued attention to classical realists.
Groundwork
Let us start by elaborating the prevailing wisdom on the evolution of realism. In
the beginning, there were classical realists, sometimes called human nature realists, and they tended to see states, and the individuals who ran them, lusting
after power and seeking power as an end in itself, not primarily as a means for
security. Despite adopting the neorealist label to highlight a link with the past,
Kenneth Waltz indicates deep rifts between classical and neorealism:
Like most students of international politics, realists infer outcomes from the salient attributes of the actors producing them. Neorealism contends that international politics can be understood only if the effects of structure are added to
traditional realisms unit-level explanations. Realists cannot handle causation
at a level above states because they fail to conceive of structure as a force that
shapes and shoves the units.4

This, in the parlance of neorealism, made classical realists reductionist,


which means they explain outcomes based on domestic or unit-level traits. It is
not that the classics did not value structuremost agree that classical realists see
structure creating incentives for statesit is that structural factors have inferior
explanatory power to unit-level factors. Alternate ways of phrasing the charge of
reductionism are asserting that classical realists favor agency over structure,
dispositional variables over situational variables, or inside-out accounts over
outside-in accounts (Primat der Innenpolitik over Aussenpolitik).5
4
See Waltz (1990:34); also 37. For realisms assumptions, see Keohane (1986b:163165); Mearsheimer (2001:30
31); Grieco (1990:34).
5
On reductionist theories, see Waltz (1979):chap. 2. On dispositional versus situational explanations, see Mercer
(1995:6, 4549, 6869); Larson (1985:37).

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

195

Waltz also takes classical realists to task for their shortcomings in transforming
analytical accounts into theory. For him, classical realists do not just lack structure as a concept; they inadequately structure their ideas into proper theory.
They do not bound the system under investigation, and without a closed system
or autonomous realm, classical realist thought cannot graduate to true theory.
Absent such rigor, classical realists could not draw the appropriate causal relationships and so could not explain a big anomalyalternations between war and
peace.6
Neorealism superseded classical realism around 1979, when Waltz published
his seminal Theory of International Politics. Also known as structural realism or systemic realism, the theorys main causal variable is the distribution of power. In
an anarchic structure, the distribution of power homogenizes outcomes and corrals the parameters of the probable, in spite of the efforts and aims of the actors.
With spare and compelling logic, neorealism argues that states are the essential
units of international politics, they interact in anarchy, and they compete for
security. Security competition leads to balancing coalitions forming and reforming, and sameness of the competitors.
So if the realist tradition is a dialogue with classical realists, who are the classical realists? To support the neorealist view quoted at the top of this work, John
Mearsheimer cites Hans Morgenthau heavily. Mearsheimer also mentions Reinhold Niebuhr twice and Friedrich Meinecke once, which implicates Meineckes
countrymen Otto Hintze and Leopold von Ranke, who said much the same
things. But if realist historians count, there is no reason they have to be nineteenth and twentieth century Germans. Xenophon, Livy, and A.J.P. Taylor are
equally qualified to be classical realists. Relatedly, Mearsheimer dismisses classical
realists like E.H. Carr and George Kennan because they have no theory; that
is, they do not have a story to tell about the causes of security competition7
Waltz relies heavily on Morgenthau and Niebuhr, but also names Saint Augustine, Kennan, Henry Kissinger, Martin Luther, John Milton, Thomas Malthus,
Bertrand Russell, Jonathan Swift, some comments by Spinoza, Bismarck, and
Hobbes, and several lesser known figures. Waltz insists that Thucydides, Machiavelli, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Alexander Hamilton, and Ranke are not human
nature realists. Yet the matter is murkier. All of Waltzs non-human nature realists laced their writings with passages equivalent to those that land their peers in
the category of human nature realism. For example, Hobbes joins Morgenthau
in Waltzs discussion of human nature as the root of conflict.8 Since Hobbes borrows his points on human nature and conflict almost verbatim from Thucydides,
it seems the latter counts as a human nature realist after all.
If Mearsheimer means to indict the best classical realists, he has botched the
job. He ducks quite a few great realists of this period, e.g. Raymond Aron and
Arnold Wolfers, and goes mysteriously silent on realists before 1940. For
instance, later in Mearsheimers book, Machiavelli appears twice in passing, once
explicitly because he is a structural theorist.9 Waltz is inconsistent in similar style.
He selects a bevy of writers who are not known or read for their international
politics work and is equivocal about marquee realists like Thucydides and
Hobbes.
6

For Waltzs criticism of classical realism on theoretical grounds, see Waltz (1990:2432).
See Mearsheimer (2001:18). For a similar listing of classical realists that adds Walter Lippmann, see Gaddis
(1998:384). On modern human nature realism, see Thayer (2000); Bell and MacDonald (2001); cp. Rosen (2004);
Kagan (1995).
8
For Waltzs view of who constitutes human nature realism, see Waltz (1954:chaps. 23; 1959:chaps. 23, esp. 3,
24, 3439; 1979:65). On Thucydides, Machiavelli, and Ranke, see Waltz (1959:7, 157, 212216). On Waltzs view of
Hobbes and Morgenthau, see Waltz (1959:3435; 1990:35); cf. Smith (1986:136).
9
On Machiavellis influence on Carr, Meinecke, and Morgenthau, see Gilbert (1988:70); Meinecke (1998);
Haslam (2002:18690).
7

196

Elder Abuse

It would take a massive book to trace realism from Thucydides to Waltz and is
not a feat that can be attempted here. Fortunately, it is not necessary. Because
the continuity between classical realists is high, and few scholars posit a significant break in classical realist thought along the dimensions considered here, we
may safely restrict the scope. Our focus will be on twentieth century classical realistswhat holds true for realists after 1900 holds true for realists before that
date.10 But we aim to improve on Mearsheimer and Waltzs treatment by
assessing what we believe to be a representative sample. Our cohort includes:
Aron, Carr, John Herz, Hintze, Kennan, Kissinger, Walter Lippmann, Meinecke,
Morgenthau, Niebuhr, Nicholas Spykman, Taylor, and Wolfers.11
One of the chief stumbling blocks to sensible comparisons of realists has to do
with the levels of analysis. All realists, at some time or another, explain outcomes
on different levels of analysis, and it would be unproductive to contrast arguments on dissimilar levels. What are those levels?12 It may be helpful to think of
the levels of analysis as covering a continuum.
At one extreme are theories of international politics. Theories of international
politics attempt to deduce broad, long-term patterns produced by the interaction
of units within a system, such as the extent to which a group of states will tend
to coexist in peace or fight wars.13 At the other extreme are theories of decision
making. They offer, if not point predictions, then point explanations. Often
through complex models, they detail how specific choices were made and the
processes that produced them.14 Between theories of international politics and
theories of decision making are theories of foreign policy, which focus on the
grand strategic behavior of individual states.15 To keep the field level, unless
otherwise noted, we seek to compare theories of international politics because
these engage basic issues in realism, and it is at this level that neorealism claims
to be most distinct.
Summing up, the neorealist narrative makes two accusations. One is that the
classical realists are human nature realists who find human nature the primary
cause of international politics and structure at best a secondary cause. The other
is that the classics are theoretically jejune. To inquire into the validity of these
charges, we bound the scope of analysis to representative twentieth century classical realists. And we also laid down that, unless otherwise noted, we will be
comparing realist theories of international politics.

10
Naturally, there are many ways to divide classical realists, but these are generally outside the purview of this
paper. See, for example, Boucher (1998); Brown, Nardin, and Rengger (2002). Readers need not take on faith our
claim that classics we do not consider are fundamentally structural. See, for example, Machiavelli (1998:chaps. 3,
25); Parent (2005:627n.7); Hobbes (1991:35, 8990, 99, 100, 115, 118, 223; 1998:83); Tuck (2001:130); Thucydides
(1998:V.105); Monten (2006:15, 23); Ober (1998:53, 5758, 68); cf. Lebow (2004:342); Betts (2007). If we leave the
Western realist tradition, we may include structural thinkers like Kautilya (1992:624).
11
Space constraints prohibit a fuller treatment of other founding scholars, such as Bernard Brodie, Abbie Rollins Caverly, G. Lowes Dickinson, Frederick S. Dunn, E.M. Earle, William T.R. Fox, Charles Merriam, Frederick L.
Schuman, Kenneth W. Thompson, Martin Wight, and Quincy Wright. At base, we claim our list is adequately representative to establish classical realist trends, and those we omit are also generally support our arguments. For example, although he had a more cultural view of structure than Waltz, Schuman asserts (1970, 404): If war be viewed
in the light here suggested, international conflict cannot helpfully be regarded as an act of God, nor as a result of
the machinations of wicked statesmen, nor yet as a consequence of the vices and imperfections of human nature.
12
The level of analysis often refers to the level of the independent variable, whereas here we are discussing the
level of the dependent variable. There is dispute on the levels of analysis, and we claim only to be presenting our
personal views.
13
For theories of international politics, see Copeland (1996:47n63); Taliaferro (2000 2001:149); Wolfers
(1962:13); Brooks (1997:445477).
14
Examples of this category include more historically minded thinkers, e.g., Robert Jervis (1976); Trachtenberg
(1991).
15
On the differences between theories of international relations and theories of foreign policy, see Elman
(1996); Rose (1998:145); Powell (1994:313344); Jervis (1999:4263); cp. Waltz (1967).

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

197

The Continuity of Core Realist Arguments


We argue that classical realists are neither human nature realists nor theoretical
simpletons. The sound bitessuch as the animus dominandi16are well known, but
less well known is that the classics are tightly allied with structural analysis and
extremely consistent with neorealism. It is unjust to reduce classical realisms thrust
to human nature; classical realists believed states were the main actors in international relations, that they competed for security in anarchy, that power was the
central variable explaining their behavior, that states pursued it more as a means
than an end, and that balancing and sameness were repetitive consequences of
the quest for autonomy. Most neorealist arguments can be found in classical
realismthough the reverse is not true.17 Neorealist parsimony has its advantages,
but so does the breadth and detail of classical realism. To make our case, we lay out
the fundamental beliefs of classical realists, organizing their thoughts around the
topics of anarchy, the consequences of anarchy, and state motivations.
Anarchy
Our first and most important point is that the classical realists believed there was
no more fundamental cause than the anarchic structure of international politics.
Internal traits may be significant, but they rarely trump systemic imperatives.
Classical realists did not, in Waltzs words, fail to conceive of structure as a force
that shapes and shoves the units. In fact, structure reigns in classical realism.18
To them, the structure of anarchy made power primarily a means to security,
and it caused balancing, the security dilemma, and sameness in the competitors.
For Morgenthau, the animus dominandi represents only a secondary explanation for why states seek to maximize power. Just as Waltz argues that sources of
particular conflicts must be found in the first and second images even though it
is the third image that makes such conflicts possible, Morgenthau asserts that it
is the absence of central authority that translates the desire to dominate into
reality. In his words:
And since no nation can foresee how large its miscalculations will turn out to be, all
nations must ultimately seek the maximum of power obtainable under the circumstances. Only thus can they hope to attain the maximum margin of safety commensurate with the maximum of errors they might commit. The limitless aspiration for
power, potentially always present in the power drives of nations, finds in the
balance of power a mighty incentive to transform itself into an actuality.19
16
Morgenthau made the term famous, but he was not the only one to use it. See Morgenthau (1946:192);
Meinecke (1998:5); Thucydides (1998:130, 166, 229).
17
See Recchia (2007). Classical realism harbors enormous diversity of views. At the extremes, many classical realists flirted with or converted to positions associated with liberal thinkers like David Mitrany and Ernst Haas. To various degrees, Carr, Kennan, Lippmann, Morgenthau, and Spykman were skeptical of the nation-states future and
predicted greater political integration. See Spykman (1942:471); Carr (1945:47, 5159); Herz (1957:473); Kennan
(1954:106107; 1993: 190, 234, 245); Kennan (1996:121, 217); Lippmann (1963:77); Morgenthau (1966). After
1945, Meinecke grew estranged from power politics; his biographer notes, Meinecke, in the Weimar period, was
on his way to the political never-never land of cosmopolitan Romanticism, a destination he attained after the second German catastrophe had taken place. As some varieties of fish die, they display, as if in pathetic defiance, all
the colors of the rainbow. Pois (1972:48); cf. Stern (1987:176178); Carr (1961:131132).
18
Although we may develop the argument, we are not the only ones to claim that classical realists are first and
foremost structural. See Smith (1986:3, 9, 224); Grieco (1990:3n3); Reus-Smit (1996:168); Rose (1998:145146);
Williams (2005:14).
19
Morgenthau (1967:201202). Oddly, Mearsheimer makes exactly Morgenthaus point when describing how he
is different from Morgenthau. The key difference between Mearsheimers offensive realism and Morgenthaus
human nature realism, the former asserts, is that offensive realists reject Morgenthaus claim that states are naturally endowed with Type A personalities. On the contrary, they believe that the international system forces great
powers to maximize their relative power because that is the optimal way to maximize security. In other words, survival mandates aggressive behavior. See Mearsheimer (2001:21).

198

Elder Abuse

He underscores his causal priority, stating that drives to live, to propagate,


and to dominate are common to all men. Their relative strength is dependent
upon social conditions that may favor one drive and tend to repress another
(1993:37). Motives matter for Morgenthau, but they seldom outstrip structure.
And Morgenthau is hardly alone in this ordering of causes. Herz asserts
(1962:7):
I believe that in international politics it is relationships among basic units of
international affairs, rather than behavior patterns of agents, that lend themselves most properly to theoretical investigation. I suggest, therefore, that the primary method of studying international politics should be one that deals with the
structures and systems of international relations as the basic data.

For Herz, anarchy homogenizes state preferences to a remarkable degree.


In the final analysis (1962:243), nothing short of global rule can ultimately
satisfy the security interests of any one power, and particularly any superpower.
So too with Niebuhr. States, like people, are power-hungry; what differentiated
moral man from immoral society were the circumstances of each (Niebuhr
1959:135, 287289; 1986). Aron and Spykman strike similar chords. In a chapter
entitled The Anarchical Order of Power, Aron remarks (1985:255256; cf.
Hassner 2007:500), the conditions, constant throughout history, of the political
organization of mankind suffice to explain the precariousness of peace and the
frequency of wars. Peace could be safeguarded only, and always temporarily, by
the balance of rival powers or the victory of the strongest and the establishment
of empire. Spykman espouses vintage structural realism:
The international community is without government, without a central authority
to preserve law and order, and it does not guarantee the member states either
their territorial integrity, their political independence, or their rights under
international law. States exist, therefore, primarily in terms of their own strength
or that of their protector states and, if they wish to maintain their independence,
they must make the preservation or improvement of their power position the
principal objective of foreign policy. (1942:446; cf. Aron 1966:610, 6465, 306)

This not obiter dicta; Spykman is concluding his signature work by placing
primary and principal stress on the distribution of power.
The more historically inclined agree. Carr illustrates how structure disciplined
Russia after the revolution, curtailing its excesses, shaping its ideology, and driving its diplomacy. Meinecke praises Rankes primacy of structure: Hence arose
Rankes heuristic principle (which was so very fruitful in general) of investigating, always and everywhere, those motives in the statesmans conduct, which
sprang from the pressure of the universal state of affairs, and of setting aside the
trivial (and yet so very ineradicable and very human) habit of dwelling on personal errors and weaknesses. Taylor makes a structural argument in perhaps the
hardest of cases, the Second World War in Europe: Powers will be Powers. My
book has really little to do with Hitler.20 For the classicsas well as for the
modernsstructure is not omnipotent, but it still rules.
The Consequences of Anarchy
The structure of anarchy leads to the same consequences for the same reasons
in classical and neorealism. Consider the security dilemma, a solidly classical
20
Carr (1979:9, 85; 1985:42); Meinecke (1998:388); cf. 403; Taylor (1996:xiii, also xxv). In addition, Taylor
explicitly assumes (1977:xxi) the state as the main political actor in his The Struggle for Mastery in Europe.

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

199

concept. Herz, an original formulator of it, maintains (1950:157; cf. 1962:21,


157, 231, 234n5) that this dilemma, and not such (possibly additional) factors
as aggressiveness, or desire to acquire the wealth of others, or general depravity
of human nature, constitutes the basic cause of what is commonly referred to as
the urge for power and resulting power politics. Carr relates (1985:345) the
dynamics between the young USSR and Britain in explicitly security dilemma language: both sides, undeterred by the agreement, continued to regard the activities of their own agents as legitimate retaliation or legitimate self-defense and
those of the other party as unprovoked aggression.
Kennan likewise saw in the U.S.-Soviet crises of 1948 the defensive motivations
and escalating spiral of the security dilemma. Elsewhere he chronicles (1967:401;
1979:248, 12, 16, 20) several security spirals, but describes them as In accordance with that law of reciprocal momentum that seems to govern, at all times
and in all places, such things as competitive military preparations and professed
military fears Taylor conveys (1977:361, 112) the essence of the security
dilemma when he says, the plans of both sides, which appeared aggressive to
the other, were alike based on fear and had a purely defensive motive. This did
not make them any less alarming to others.
Another consequence of anarchy is a classical realist hallmark: balancing
behavior. Spykman understood well that states do not really want to achieve a
balance; they want to attain a margin of safety, to be somewhat imbalanced,
more powerful than their rivals, and retain greater freedom of action. The consequence of all states acting this way is that power tends to be balanced by countervailing coalitions. Again, Carr demonstrates that even revolutionary states catch
on to the necessity of balancing. Kennan and Kissinger gained fame as proponents of balance of power politics. Meinecke sees balancing as a blessed stabilizer
of states, and in Taylors dignified phrasing, the balance of power is a perpetual
quadrille in which, because of anarchic security competition, great powers may
never cool their heels.21
Classical realists commonly noted that in an anarchic environment, states tend
to imitate each other. Since states compete they have to keep up with their rivals
if they want to be secure, and this predisposes them to copy innovations. This is
now called the sameness effect, but before the present term came into vogue the
concept was covered extensively. For example, Hintze and Meinecke demonstrate
how Prussia was driven to copy its brawniest competitor, France, to stay safe
(Hintze 1975:153; Meinecke 1977:3839, 9596). Kennan showcases (1979:224)
the same phenomenon with Russia elites after the Crimean War; the losers swiftly
copied the methods of the winners.
In addition, because the distribution of power drives states and relative power
changes slowly, internal transformations are unlikely to shake up continuity in
world politics. Kissinger marvels (1995:802) that, during the Cold War, the overall direction of American policy was remarkably farsighted and remained remarkably consistent throughout changes in administration and an astonishingly
varied array of personalities. Carr 1985 comments (1985:292) how even a revolutionary state like the USSR quickly reverted to traditional tsarist diplomacy.
Morgenthau observes (1946:6566): The fundamental foreign policies of the
Great Powers have survived all changes in the form of government and in
domestic policies. Continuity in foreign affairs is not a matter of choice but
necessity Like neorealists, classical realists saw the security dilemma, balancing, imitation, and policy continuity as consequences of the anarchic structure
of world politics.
21
See Spykman (1942:2124); Carr (1985:381, 434); Kennan and Kissinger in Gaddis (2005:31, 278); Meinecke
(1998:431); Taylor (1977:xix). On states reluctance to balance, see Kissinger (1995:21, 834); Sheehan (1996:11);
Gulick (1967).

200

Elder Abuse

State Motivations
The neorealist narrative has it that classical realists made their obsession with the
will to power paramount. Again, the neorealist narrative leads us astray. The animus dominandi is certainly present but does not dominate classical explanations;
the pursuit of power represents less an end in itself than a means to security.
The vast majority of realists cohere around the notion that survivaldefined in
terms of maintenance of independenceis the highest objective of states.22
While Morgenthau does discuss the urge toward expansion which knows no
rational limits, he also portrays the moral principle of national survival. Tellingly, none of his inducements to imperialism (read revising the status quo)
relate to the internal traits of states (Morgenthau 1967:53, 10, 5152). Wolfers
makes a similar argument about state aims being potentially limitless, but propelled by relative power. At the height of the Cold War, he wisely predicted
(quoted in Haslam 2002:209):
Once the balance of power is broken, once a particular nation secures a predominant position in the state system, it will be tempted to continue to expand its
power vis-a`-vis the other states. If the United States broke through the present
bi-polar balance, its objectives (for example, of eliminating tyranny) would
probably become unlimited too.

Spykman privileges security in terms almost identical to neorealism. Because


independence is of the essence of the state, self-preservation also means fighting for independent status. This explains why the basic objective of the foreign
policy of all states is the preservation of territorial integrity and political independence. And he goes on: Power means survival, the ability to impose ones will
on others (Spykman 1942:1718, 7). In his historical survey of realism, Jonathan
Haslam comes to the conclusion (2002:9) that most traditional realists like
todays neorealists believed that security was the most vital concern.
The classics disagreed about whether maximizing or optimizing relative power
was the best road to security, but this tension is present in neorealism and is no
rupture in realist tradition. Classical realists realized that power was addictive
and sometimes became an end in itself, but they did not base their explanations
on pathological power-mongers any more than economists based theirs on misers. Power, like money, was a means to other ends.23
The classics were mindful of unintended effects and constantly cautioned
against putting too much stock in state motivation and traits. In a note to his discussion of status quo states, Morgenthau mentions that, we are exclusively concerned with the actual character of the policies pursued and not with the
motives of those who pursue them. He also contends that, The concept of
interest defined as power creates that astounding continuity in foreign policy
regardless of the different motives, preferences, and intellectual qualities of
successive statesmen. A realist theory of international politics, then, will guard
against two popular fallacies, the concern with motives and the concern for ideological preferences. Where Morgenthau saved space for motivations, Carr goes
further: Freud has driven the last nail into the coffin of the ancient illusion that
the motives from which men allege or believe themselves to have acted are in
fact adequate to explain their action24
22
See, for example, Mearsheimer (1990:44); Grieco (1993:127; 1997:166, 16970); Jervis (1978:174); Gilpin
(1996:78); Waltz (2000:38); Donnelly (2000:54).
23
For the classical and neorealist debates on maximizing versus optimizing relative power, see Morgenthau
(1967:201202); Kennan (1954:passim); cp. Mearsheimer (2001:33); Waltz (1979:126). On assumptions of wealth
and power maximization, see Coase (1995:3031); Wolfers (1962:89); Simmel (1971:185).
24
For the quotes in this paragraph, see Morgenthau (1967:37n3, 5); Carr (1961:185). See also Rose (1998:146);
Morgenthau (1993:6); Kissinger (1995:295, 301, 813).

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

201

Wolfers avers (1962:1819) that labeling a state as revisionist or status quo


implies little about its underlying motivation: empirical study would validate
that almost any nation which has suffered a loss of territory or has been subjected to discrimination, will, when its power permits, take some action to redress
its grievancesand thus fall into the revisionist category, regardless of the personal characteristics of its leaders or the peculiarities of its national culture.
Hintze underscores (1975:215, cf. 15962, 183): matters will remain as they
have been throughout history: the form and spirit of a states organization will
not be determined solely by economic and social relations and clashes of interests, but primarily by the necessities of defense and offense, that is, by the organization of the army and of warfare.
Classical realists placed supreme stress on necessity, what could also be
called environmental compulsion, incentive structure, or relative power. State
behavior, like individual behavior, is predominantly a product of circumstance.
This is what the classics share with the moderns; this is what makes a realist a
realist. A central realist tenet and perhaps the core insight of international relations is that cupidity correlates with capacity. Classical realists recognized that
structure ruled, that behavior was proportionate to power, and that interacting
states had various appetites, but appetite was more a function of capability than
taste. In Machiavellian language, states conform to the times or are punished.25
With the possible exception of Niebuhr, who was absorbed by sin and pride,
the classical realists may have had a disconcerting view of humanity, but it
derived from their structural view of the world. Morgenthau said that Reinie
and I come out about the same on politics, but I do not need all his metaphysics
to get where we both get.26 One should not overemphasize the familial resemblance of classical realiststhey are a large number of individuals writing over a
long period of time. But they share a broad consensus that causation should not
be found primarily within states. Despite their diverse styles, the classics are first
and foremost structural in substance.
None of this should be taken to mean that classical realists did not value the
role of domestic politics or individuals. On the contrary, classical realists were
intent on countering idealistic tendencies in foreign policy thinking, particularly
in the United States, stopping maniac leaders like Hitler, and averting counterproductive mindsets, especially with respect to nuclear weapons.27 But this makes
them no different from neorealists. To take two examples, Mearsheimer is an
outspoken critic of the Israel lobbys impact on American foreign policy, and
Waltz has advocated the spread of nuclear weapons in the face of the unit-level
fear of nuclear arms (Mearsheimer and Walt 2007; Waltz 1981; cf. Kuklick
2006:6; Guzzini 1998; Schroeder 1994). Because great power politics is an exacting taskmaster, realists worry that domestic factors might painfully push states
afoul of structural incentives.
Realist Theory and Scientific Method
Laws identify invariant or probable associations. Theories show why those associations obtain. (Waltz 1979:5; cf. Weber 1964:88, 107, 111112) By this definition, classical realism is replete with theory. Granted political science methods
have improved over time, but the classics and moderns come very near to connecting the same concepts in the same ways for the same reasons. Whatever their
25
On cupidity correlating with capacity, see Spykman (1942:25); Wolfers(1962:90, 96, 125); Morgenthau
(1967:32); Meinecke (1998:12); Coby (1999:102103); Jervis (2005:9394); cf. Aron (1985:117).
26
Quoted in Smith (1986:134); cf. Lippmann (1997:111113). For similar trajectories in other fields, see Smith
(1984:181185); Knight, 1982:359360; Burckhardt (1999:163); Barzun (2000:xx).
27
See Sterling-Folker (1997); also Lippmann (1999); Kennan (1979:417418, 424; 1984:157167); Gaddis
(2005:299302, 332); Sumner (1992:276277); Reus-Smit (1996:169).

202

Elder Abuse

views on social scienceand some were downright hostileclassical realists have


aggregated an enviable store of useful theory.
It would be a grave loss to demean classical realists as markedly inferior
because they did not have the foresight to practice political science in the present fashion. Thucydides historical work resembles a play, Machiavelli deliberately fictionalized his evidence, Meinecke left us no game theoretical
modelsreaders seeking current standards of organization and method in classical realists are destined to go away disappointed. Conventions always change;
todays scholarship is guaranteed not to conform to tomorrows customs. Yet, if
history is a fair guide, radical breaks in realist theory are improbable.
Standards for the use of evidence have elevated, and causal models have grown
more formal and tidy (sometimes too formal and tidy) in parallel with other sciences. Nevertheless, in international relations, the tools of consequence have
changed little: our eyes are about as discerning, our brains about as keen, our
pens about as mighty. Many very smart realists over many centuries have puzzled
over war and peace, conflict and cooperation, trade and blockade with substantially the same equipment. We ought to be wary of overdrawing the differences
between the ancients and the moderns in a fit of temporal parochialism, estranging ourselves from kindred spirits and inspirational insights.
Classical realists saw people and states as extremely complex, and as self-styled
realists they did not blush to document nuances and complexity. At the same
time, however, they did not abstain from abstracting and theorizing. Morgenthau, for example, opens his most famous work with the statement: This book
purports to present a theory of international politics. He had a sophisticated
understanding of human behavior, butin explicit contradiction to Waltzs
claimthat did not prevent him from fencing off his subject: Intellectually, the
political realist maintains the autonomy of the political sphere. Recognizing
that these different facets of human nature exist, political realism also recognizes
that in order to understand one of them one has to deal with it on its own
terms.28
In spite of his allergy to formal theory, Aron did not question the imperative
for generalizable arguments: Reasonable decision, nonetheless, requires one
apply all of the abstract knowledge at ones disposal to the unique situation as it
exists at the moment, not in order to eliminate but to delineate and isolate the
element of unpredictable uniqueness. Meinecke saw in general causes the
deep and hidden relations of life. And Spykman immersed himself in methodology and theory in his 1925 The Social Theory of Georg Simmel.29
No one would have been more surprised than Carr to hear that he had no
theory, as Mearsheimer words it. Carr saw his task as finding what is general
in the unique, and he believed The study of history is the study of causes,
and Every historical argument revolves around the question of priority of
causes.30 He is right: good history is theory; path dependence is theoretical;
weaving compelling explanations of broad patterns, foreign policy, and particular actions requires sound theory at more than one level of analysis. Although
historical theory is not always as transparent as many would like, it is theory
regardless.
Carrs perspective may be justly extended to many classical realists who also
happened to be historians: e.g. Thucydides, Machiavelli, Meinecke, and Taylor.
If they focused on great power politics, if they used the same concepts we use
28
Morgenthau (1993:3, 13, 16); cf. Machiavelli (1998):Dedicatory Letter; Buzan et al. (1993:10); Jervis (1994);
Tellis (1996); Turner and Mazur (2009).
29
Aron (1985:336); cf. 373; Meinecke (1967:4); Spykman (1925:xiii, 5, 124125, 257). Besides foreshadowing
Theory of International Politics, Spykman also foreshadows Waltzs Man, the State and War in ibid., 4546, 72.
30
Carr (1961:80, 113, 117); cf. Jones (1998: 610, 133, 153). Mearsheimer (2009) also believes that Waltz is
insufficiently theoretical.

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

203

today, if they caught important correlations, and if they described why those correlations hold in the international system, then why make a fetish of form? Does
this mean it is acceptable to demean the arguments of modern historians like
John Lewis Gaddis, Paul Schroeder, and Marc Trachtenberg because they have
no theory? If not, what separates them from Kennan and Carr?31
Finally, it is not our intention to charge our predecessors with maltreating
their predecessors and in the process commit the same sin. Neorealism is a theoretical advance, it is widely read for good reason, and our scholarship owes a
debt to it (full disclosure: both of us have worked under Waltz and one of us
under Mearsheimer.) Neorealism affords a number of advantages. It updated the
theoretical foundations of realism; it sharpened how concepts like agent and
structure were delimited; it is an extraordinarily parsimonious and elegant
option that scholars may use as something of a standard base model, and it provides enduring stimulus for thought and debate. Frankly, these achievements are
stunning. No social science has a longer scholarly history than international politicsthat innovations are still being made is spectacular.
We agree the neorealist view captures some truth. Classical realists do find
human nature a significant element of their worldview.32 Niebuhr especially, as
the sole theologian, was fixated on sin and pride and felt it was an important
part of his explanations. Because they tended to be historians, like Meinecke, or
were strongly influenced by historians, like Morgenthau, or were trying to gain
the ear of policymakers unimpressed by social science, like Kennan, their works
contain a multiplicity of causes for at least as many outcomes on every level of
analysis and a bias against deduction and formal theory.33 But these concerns
should not be pushed far.
Realists of any age invoke a number of causes, but when they discourse on
international politics, they put superlative stress on structure. Unquestionably,
when trying to make detailed explanations, classical causal models were more
complex than structure alone, but that is no different than neorealists. As Waltz
remarks (1959:231; cp. Barkin 2003:330; Schuett 2010:7), We still have to look
to motivation and circumstances in order to explain individual acts. Waltzs
second book (1967), after all, was about domestic politics and foreign policy.
Comparing apples to apples, classical realists and neorealists use the same factors
to explain the same recurrent patterns. And as Stephen Walts work indicates,
neorealists remain about as unfavorably disposed to deduction and formal theory
as their predecessors, but neither should be called atheoretical for that.34
To sum our two main arguments, classical realists did indeed see an urge for
power in international politics, but they saw an urge for power in all aspects of
social life. Realists as a rule toed the Hobbesian line that it is anarchy that differentiates the international realm. Anarchy permitted security-seeking states to get
embroiled in hostility spirals, which led to expansion, balancing, and war. How
states behaved in this dynamic was mostly a function of relative power. By
explaining the same patterns with essentially the same concepts and logic as neorealists, classical realists escape charges of human nature realism and theoretical
incompetence.

31
See Abbott (2001:1727); Weber (1958:138); cf. Wight (2002:2351). See also Gaddis (1986); Schroeder
(1994); Trachtenberg (2003).
32
See, for example, Kennan (1967: 483; 1993:28); Aron (1966:7273, 87, 144, 598); Smith (1986:17, 102104,
110, 130); Morgenthau (1993:45, 290); Niebuhr (2001:18, 35, 46).
33
On the historical bent of classical realism, see Aron (1985:281282); Kennan (1954:92; 1956:vii); Kennan
(1958:83, 209, 383). On the historians bias against highly systematic theory, see Guicciardini (1972:42, 62, 69);
Aron (1966:93); Morgenthau (1946:127).
34
See Walt (1999). On realists reluctance to systematize, see Gilpin (1986:304308); Carr in Haslam (2002:236);
Elman and Fendius Elman (2001).

204

Elder Abuse

Why the Confusion?


A natural question to ask at this point is: why did neorealists conflate classical
and human nature realism? We venture a few conjectures. One is that terms have
changed. Quincy Wrights early survey of human nature explanations for war
found four groups: (i) necessity, the fight for survival, (ii) desire, war as the last
ditch effort for wealth, power, and solidarity, (iii) ideological, fighting for an
ideal, and (iv) war as consumption good, people are bored or pugnacious and
fight for relief or relaxation. (1983:107, chap. 18) Not all of these variants are
still considered human nature realism, or if they are then everyone is a human
nature realist. The meanings of classical and human nature realism have shifted,
and while for a time they were isomorphic they are no longer so.
Another explanation is structural. Conditions impel neorealists to ornament
their contributions to realism and conditions hinder readers from detecting the
embroidery. Addressing each point respectively, the neorealist take on classical
realism does not come from impartial spectators. Our sources are advancing
their own refinements to realist theory, and it is unrealistic to expect people in
this position not to frame their attainments as positively as possible. Motivated
bias is built in to their circumstancesit would only be surprising if they underplayed their originality, which to their credit they occasionally do (Haslam
2002:230). As arch-structuralist George Stigler puts it (1982:111): New ideas are
sold very much the way new automobiles are sold: by exaggerating their superiority over the older models.
Further, the division of labor is limited by the extent of the market. Common
sense suggests, and the evidence supports, the belief that classical realists were
less specialized than modern realists. There was a larger incentive to proffer realism as a theory of international politics, foreign policy, and decision making
simultaneously. It is not only that classical realists were trying to do multiple
tasks at once; they were also, as a rule, prolific individually and collectively. On
top of all this, they are not around to explicate and stand up for their work. If
students are daunted by this aggregation of obstacles, and if they learn that these
authors have no theory or are easily dismissed because they foolishly subordinate structure to human nature, then students are less likely to read them.
Implications and Extensions: Corrupting the Classics?
Certainly, classical realists did not have all the answersnor if they did would
they all remain relevant today. For example, the tendency for states to balance, a
signature feature of realist thought, has come under attack recently (Brooks and
Wohlforth 2008; cf. Paul, Wirtz, and Fortmann 2004; Pape 2005). But while realist writings offer inspiration to diverse audiences, their sturdiest axioms do not
validate all views equally.
In this section, we make the case that neorealists have overstated a disjuncture
in realist tradition, neoclassical realists have embraced and advanced realist tradition, and motivational realists are more usurping imposters than rightful heirs to
realist tradition. The classics ought to be spared the indignity, on one side, of
having their theoretical contributions diminished by neorealists, and, on the
other side, of having their mantle falsely claimed by motivational realists who
exaggerate state agency.
Neorealism: Mostly Old Wine in Neo Bottles
If our analysis is correct, then the critical implication for neorealism is that it is
a valuable step forward, but less of a leap than Mearsheimer and Waltz portray

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

205

it as. And this makes neorealism more realist. Realism is about structure influencing thought and action; so when the structure of international politics does
not change, why would realist thinking on structure change? Realists have
always thought of structure as the deepest cause, and they have always had an
advanced understanding of theory. Thucydides inaugurates this heritage by ridiculing Herodotus methods, Machiavelli has a strong claim to founding modern
social science, and Carr, among others, was deeply involved with theory.35 Realism is a paradigm filled with people who think history is the same damn thing
over and over, yet they do not deny that changesometimes even
progressoccurs over time; they just believe that development is generally
incremental.
No one would mistake classical realists for full-blown neorealists, and this is a
mark, somewhat ironically, of progress. As we laid out in section three, neorealism affords a number of advantages; neorealists have no need to embellish their
accomplishments. Fitting for realists, the modern cohort is quite continuous with
its ancestors, and their debts should be made plain. Structural realism did not
leap fully formed from Thucydides any more than it did from Waltz; there has
been a gradual, painstaking march.
Neoclassical Realism: The Reserves in the Realist Ranks
Up to this point, we have discussed only the intersection of classical and neorealism, yet our analysis has repercussions for other groups working under the banner of realism. From this point until the conclusion, we switch to discussing
theories of foreign policy, to better address these authors on their level of analysis. One band of scholars that evolved out of neorealism is neoclassical realism.
Gideon Rose outlines what this school of thought embodies:
It explicitly incorporates both external and internal variables, updating and systematizing certain insights drawn from classical realist thought. Its adherents
argue that the scope and ambition of a countrys foreign policy is driven first
and foremost by its place in the international system and specifically by its relative material power capabilities. This is why they are realist. They argue further,
however, that the impact of such power capabilities on foreign policy is indirect
and complex, because systemic pressures must be translated through intervening
variables at the unit level. This is why they are neoclassical.36

Neoclassical realists take the spare, versatile foundation of neorealist thought


and add domestic factors to explain foreign policy. They do this because domestic variables provide assistance in two ways: catching details and lag effects. The
more one desires a finer-grained dependent variable, the more one has need of
additional variables; in the extreme, this produces exquisite diplomatic history.
Domestic variables can also tell us a great deal about the timing and magnitude
of state responses to systemic pressures; political winds invariably change and
some states trim their sails better than others. When states react to their environment outside the bounds of a reasonable actortoo little, too late, too much,
too quicklythen it makes sense to probe domestic politics.
Neoclassical research is in the grand realist tradition of theories of foreign policy. We have seen that classical realists were frequently occupied by pressing
problems of their day, and they charted the behavior of states and leaders
by structural stars. They generated explanations of foreign policy and why
35
On Thucydides, see Collingwood (1998:435442); Finley (1977:714); Ober (1998:5363); Bolotin (1987:78).
On Machiavelli, see Butterfield (1967); Olschki (1945). On Carr, see Jones (1998):chap. 6.
36
Rose (1998:146). For examples, see Lobell, Ripsman, and Taliaferro (2009); Hagan (1994); Labs (1997: 11);
Frankel (1996:xvi); Zakaria (1992); cf. Rosecrance and Stein (1993).

206

Elder Abuse

given policies were likely to run aground. Neoclassical realists draw on this lineage of intervening domestic factors while retaining realisms primacy of structure. Whether neoclassical scholarship represents theory in the proper sense is
an issue that has been debated fully elsewhere (Elman 1996; Waltz 1996; Rose
1998). But neoclassical research is a vibrant and promising area of inquiry and
advances the standards of classical realists; along with realist thought on other
levels of analysis, it also gives the lie to critics who bemoan the inherent theoretical poverty of realism (Boix, Codenotti, and Resta 2006:6) or its impoverished conceptions of human motives (Lebow 2006:438).
Motivational Realism: Keeping the Classics Safe from Kidnappers
The corps of modern realism that claims to be most engaged with the classics is
not. Motivational realiststhe name is Andrew Kyddshave attempted to return
to what they see as the origins of realism to create a larger role for diverse state
motivations.37 The provenance of these preferences is manifold, but what these
thinkers have in common is the belief that innate state preferences can trump
system imperatives for longer than the short run. Wolfers aptly frames (1962:18;
cf. Spirtas 1996:398) the analytical choice:
Almost all analysts of international politics distinguish between nations that are
satisfied with the status quo and other that are eager to change it. The controversial question is whether states fall into one category or the other primarily
because of differences in the psychology of their leaders and peoples or because
of differences in the objective conditions in which they find themselves.

Indeed, motivational realists typically phrase a states motivation as either revisionist or status quo, but they furnish the state with a type largely independent
of conditions. Differences in state type cast the shadow of war, cause variation in
systemic outcomes, and generate the preponderance of the security dilemma
(Schweller 1996; Kydd 1997b, 2005).
Motivational realists advance claims that run counter to classical realist
thought. By putting so much weight on state intentions, motivational realists are
definitely motivational but dubiously realist. On balance, classical realists
staunchly oppose shifting the explanatory emphasis from outside in to inside out
factors. Motivational realists believe that non-security-seeking behavior is a major
component of world politics; classical realists do not concur. With so much attention on multiple motives, constructing a compelling theory grows more elusive.
Without a universal assumption about motivation, systemic predictions lurch
toward the indeterminate. Wolfers had (1962:86) a sage skepticism of status quo
and revisionist explanations:
distinctions such as these rob theory of the determinate and predictive character that seemed to give the pure power hypothesis its peculiar value. It can no
longer be said, for example, that a power vacuum cannot exist for any length of
time; a vacuum surrounded by satiated or status quo states would remain as it
is unless its existence were to change the character of these states and put them
into the category of imperialist, unsatiated, or dynamic states.

Motivational arguments pay a punishing penalty for their heavy reliance on


motives.

37
For the motivational realist label, see Kydd (1997b:115). On motivational realist research, see Kydd
(1997a:371400; 2000; 2005). Some of the work of Randall Schweller and Charles Glaser also fits under this rubric.
See Schweller (1997:927930; 1998; 2004:164, 166, 1689, 171); Glaser (1994 1995:56).

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

207

Kydd suggests (1997b:117, 153; cf. Glaser 1997:184; Lebow 2006:437, 442, 447)
that a world of security seekers, in which it was common knowledge that everyone was a security seeker, would be peaceful. The search for security does not
lead to conflict in the absence of genuinely aggressive states. He expands
(1997b:124) on the possibility of permanent peace, based on the idea that a
group of satisfied states can recognize each other as such and avoid the dangers
of anarchy:
a group of security-seeking states has the power to render itself perfectly secure
by simply deciding to refrain from attacking each other for ever. This outcome
would be an equilibrium because no state would have an incentive to attack,
given that all other states refrain from attacking. This outcome also has the
happy characteristic of being the best possible outcome for each state.

This argument may be right, but it is not realist.


Classical realists are skeptical that security seekers would inherently, inevitably, or interminably favor maintaining the status quo. As the classics make clear,
states that seek security have to engage in the competition for power, which
means that even if they wanted to, they cannot consistently pass up opportunities
to surpass rivals. Another problem is that states signaling a peaceable disposition
may invite exploitation, perhaps from an observer, perhaps from a scheming
partner. In international relations, niceness often signifies weakness, and Kydds
argument unravels if this is the case. Paraphrasing R.H. Coase, Kydds model
makes interesting blackboard political science, but because it lacks an essential
feature of reality it is bled of utility.38
Motivational realists emphasize that the solution to security problems lies in
convincing others of ones benign intentions. For instance, Kydd describes how
in 1908 the German ambassador to England recognized two currents within English thought regarding the growth of Germanys fleet. Either its augmentation
was for the purposes of attacking England or that it was not a deliberate
threat of aggression. The naval arms race and security dilemma that ensued,
Kydd posits, was due to the German failure to signal benign intent: By signaling, states can eliminate the uncertainty at the heart of the spiral model and
avoid war.39
But the historical record indicates that the actionreaction could not have
been eliminated had Germany credibly signaled a lack of revisionist intent. Sir
Eyre Crowes influential memorandum in 1907 shows that there was little chance
Germany could signal its plans were not aggressive but defensive: For it is clear
that the second scheme may at any stage, merge into the first40 The British elite and public were threatened by the capacity of the German naval building program and were not mollified by protestations of pacific intent. Asserting
that some states have greedy goals while others do not obscures the unfortunate
fact that power can overshadow motives.

38
See Coase (1990:3, 2830); cf. Taylor (1977:361); Machiavelli (1998:chaps. 1718). Coase continues
(1990:185): In my youth it was said that what was too silly to be said may be sung. In modern economics it may be
put into mathematics. Hirschman seconds (2002:8081): as a result of a long process of refinement, economic
analysis has moved so far away from common sense that to reestablish contact between economics and common
sense while still using the concepts of economics is sometimes no simple matter. In Kydds defense, he appreciates
this deficiency, see Kydd (2005:116).
39
Kydd (1997a:371373). Kydd suggests that While a group of sheep can get along fine with each other if they
were fully convinced that all the animals in the flock were sheep, some may be wolves in sheeps clothing.
See Kydd (1997b:116). He out-of-hand dismisses the problem of savage competition between sheep should they be
comfortable that no wolf was in their midst. But a reason sheep cannot so compete is that they have shepherds.
40
Crowe (1907:417). See also Taylor (1977:458); Friedberg (1988: 179, 184, 200203, esp. 190n195); Mercer
(1995:101103); cf. Edelstein (2002); Mearsheimer (2001:213).

208

Elder Abuse

Conclusion
This paper argued that even on a sympathetic realist reading, neorealists do not
represent their ancestors accurately. Two positions are untenable. One is that
classical realists are human nature realists. What makes a realist a realist is superlative emphasis on the power of external circumstances, and this trait has been
as impressively (or depressively) uniform over time as the prevalent patterns they
have always explained. What has not changed in realism is that states are the primary actors in politics, they compete for security in anarchy, and balancing and
sameness are the usual results.
The other untenable position is that classical realists are atheoretical. They
may not have obeyed modern theoretical canons, but they were intensely
engaged in crafting theory and acquired a valuable stockpile of it over the millennia. Naturally, everyone strives to produce and consume the most robust theory possible, and classical realists made mistakes that are not worth repeating.
But classics are classic because they have been continually relevantwhat better
test of robustness is there? If we insist on retrospectively imposing an austere
vision of what qualifies as theory, the practical effect will be an increasing isolation from some of the best minds in history. No group of scholars is custodian
of a wealthier patrimony than realism; it would be a travesty to fritter away fine
portions of it on minor methodological grounds.
By defending classical realism, we do not desire a return to some supposed
golden age or to put modern realists in some procrustean bed. We wish only to
blunt the twin dangers of alienating students from provocative works that have
stood the test of time and incorporating ideas into realism that suborn the classics. As always, reverence must be balanced with irreverence. And we harbor no
delusions of special status in interpreting classical realism; on the contrary, we
welcome company, competing or concurring. At the end of the day, mainstream
scholarship is strongest when it fights on two fronts: the vanguard engages the
best of the present while the rearguard engages the best of the past. We respectfully urge the rearguard to press its defense with greater ferocity.
References
Abbott, Andrew. (2001) Chaos of Disciplines. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Aron, Raymond. (1966) Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, translated by Richard
Howard, and Annette Baker Fox. New York: Doubeday.
Aron, Raymond. (1985) History, Truth, and Liberty: Selected Writings of Raymond Aron, edited by
Franciszek Draus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Barkin, J. Samuel. (2003) Realist Constructivism. International Studies Review 5: 325342.
Barzun, Jacques. (2000) From Dawn to Decadence: 500 Years of Western Cultural Life, 1500 to the Present.
New York: Harper Perennial.
Bell, Duncan, Ed. (2008) Political Thought and International Relations: Variants on a Realist Theme. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Bell, Duncan, and Paul MacDonald. (2001) Correspondence: Start the Evolution without Us.
International Security 26: 187198.
Betts, Richard K. (2007) Not with My Thucydides You Dont. The American Interest 2: 1444.
Boix, Charles, Bruno Codenotti, and Giovanni Resta. (2006) War, Wealth, and the Formation
of States. Paper presented at the 2006 American Political Science Association Meeting,
Philadelphia, PA.
Bolotin, David. (1987) Thucydides. In History of Political Philosophy, 3rd edition, edited by Leo
Strauss, and Joseph Cropsey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Boucher, David. (1998) Political Theories of International Relations: From Thucydides to the Present. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Brooks, Stephen G. (1997) Dueling Realisms. International Organization 51: 445477.
Brooks, Stephen, and William C. Wohlforth. (2008) World Out of Balance: International Relations
and the Challenge of American Primacy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

209

Brown, Chris, Terry Nardin, and Nicholas Rengger, Eds. (2002) International Relations in Political
Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Burckhardt, Jacob. (1999) Judgments on History and Historians. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Butterfield, Herbert. (1967) The Statecraft of Machiavelli. New York: Macmillan.
Buzan, Barry, Charles Jones, and Richard Little. (1993) The Logic of Anarchy: Neorealism to
Structural Realism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Carr, E.H. (1945) Nationalism and After. London: Macmillan.
Carr, E.H. (1961) What is History? New York: Vintage Books.
Carr, E.H. (1979) The Russian Revolution: From Lenin to Stalin. New York: Free Press.
Carr, E.H. (1985) The Bolshevik Revolution, 19171923, Vol. 3. New York: Norton.
Carr, E.H. (1995) The Twenty Years Crisis, 19191939. London: Papermac.
Coase, Ronald H. (1990) The Firm, the Market, and the Law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Coase, Ronald H. (1995) Essays on Economics and Economists. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Coby, J.P. (1999) Machiavellis Romans. New York: Lexington Books.
Collingwood, R.G. (1998) Greek Thought and the Writing of History. In The Peloponnesian War,
edited by Walter Blanco, and Jennifer Tolbert Roberts. New York: Norton.
Copeland, Dale. (1996) Neorealism and the Myth of Bipolar Stability: Toward a New Dynamic
Realist Theory of Major War. Security Studies 5: 2989.
Craig, Campbell. (2003) Glimmer of a New Leviathan: Total War in the Realism of Niebuhr, Morgenthau,
and Waltz. New York: Columbia University Press.
Crowe, Eyre. (1907) Memorandum on the Present State of British Relations with France and
Germany. In British Documents on the Origins of War, 18981914, edited by G.P. Gooch, and
Harold Temberley. London: H. M. Stationery Office.
Donnelly, Jack. (2000) Realism and International Relations. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Edelstein, David. (2002) Managing Uncertainties: Beliefs about Intentions and the Rise of the
Great Powers. Security Studies 12: 140.
Elman, Colin. (1996) Horses for Courses: Why Not Neorealist Theories of Foreign Policy? Security
Studies 6: 753.
Elman, Colin, and Miriam Fendius Elman, Eds. (2001) Bridges and Boundaries: Historians, Political
Scientists, and the Study of International Relations. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Finley, Moses. (1977) The Portable Greek Historians. New York: Penguin.
Fox, William T.R., Ed. (1959) Theoretical Aspects of International Relations. South Bend, IN: University
of Notre Dame Press.
Frankel, Benjamin. (1996) Restating the Realist Case: An Introduction. Security Studies 5: ixxx.
Freyberg-Inan, Annette, Ewan Harrison, and Patrick James. (2009) Introduction: What Way
Forward for Contemporary Realism? In Rethinking Realism in International Relations: Between
Tradition and Innovation, edited by Annette Freyberg-Inan et al. Baltimore, MD: The Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Friedberg, Aaron L. (1988) The Weary Titan: Britain and the Experience of Relative Decline. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (1986) The Long Peace: Elements of Stability in the Postwar International
System. International Security 10: 99142.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (1998) We Now Know: Rethinking Cold War History. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (2005) Strategies of Containment: A Critical Reappraisal of American National Security
Policy During the Cold War, Revised edition. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gilbert, Felix. (1988) A European Past: Memoirs 19051945. New York: Norton.
Gilpin, Robert. (1986) The Richness of the Tradition of Political Realism. In Neorealism and Its
Critics, edited by Robert O. Keohane. New York: Columbia University Press.
Gilpin, Robert. (1996) No One Loves a Political Realist. Security Studies 5: 328.
Glaser, Charles L. (1994 1995) Realists as Optimists, Cooperation as Self-Help. In The Perils of
Anarchy, Contemporary Realism and International Security, edited by Michael E. Brown et al.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Glaser, Charles L. (1997) The Security Dilemma Revisited. World Politics 50: 171201.
Goddard, Stacie, and Daniel Nexon. (2005) Paradigm Lost: Reassessing Theory of International
Politics. European Journal of International Relations 11: 961.
Grieco, Joseph M. (1990) Cooperation Among Nations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Grieco, Joseph M. (1993) Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest
Liberal Institutionalism. In Neorealism and Neoliberalism, the Contemporary Debate, edited by David
A. Baldwin. New York: Columbia University Press.

210

Elder Abuse

Grieco, Joseph M. (1997) Realist International Theory and the Study of World Politics. In New
Thinking in International Relations Theory, edited by Michael Doyle, and G. John Ikenberry.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Guicciardini, Francesco. (1972) Maxims and Reflections (Ricordi), translated by Mario Domandi.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Gulick, Edward Vose. (1967) Europes Classical Balance of Power. New York: W. W. Norton.
Guzzini, Stefano. (1998) Realism in International Relations and International Political Economy: The
Continuing Story of a Death Foretold. New York: Routledge.
Hagan, J.D. (1994) Domestic Political Systems and War Proneness. Mershon International Studies Review
38: 183207.
Haslam, Jonathan. (2002) No Virtue Like Necessity: Realist Thought in International Relations Since
Machiavelli. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Hassner, Pierre. (2007) Raymond Aron: Too Realistic to Be a Realist? Constellations 14: 498505.
Herz, John. (1950) Idealist Internationalism and the Security Dilemma. World Politics 2: 157180.
Herz, John. (1957) Rise and Demise of the Territorial State. World Politics 9: 473493.
Herz, John. (1962) International Politics in the Atomic Age. New York: Columbia University Press.
Hintze, Otto. (1975) The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze, edited by Felix Gilbert. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Hirschman, Albert. (2002) Shifting Involvements: Private Interest and Public Action. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Hobbes, Thomas. (1991) Man and Citizen (De Homine and De Cive). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett
Publishing.
Hobbes, Thomas. (1998) Leviathan. New York: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Jervis, Robert. (1976) Perception and Misperception in World Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Jervis, Robert. (1978) Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma. World Politics 30: 167214.
Jervis, Robert. (1994) Hans Morgenthau, Realism, and the Scientific Study of International Politics.
Social Research 61: 853876.
Jervis, Robert. (1999) Realism, Neoliberalism, and Cooperation: Understanding the Debate.
International Security 24: 4263.
Jervis, Robert. (2005) American Foreign Policy in a New Era. New York: Routledge.
Jones, Charles. (1998) E.H. Carr and International Relations: A Duty to Lie. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Kagan, Donald. (1995) On the Origins of War. New York: Doubleday.
Kautilya. (1992) Arthashastra, translated and edited by L.N. Rangarajan. New York: Penguin Books.
Kennan, George F. (1954) Realities of American Foreign Policy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Kennan, George F. (1956) Russia Leaves the War. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kennan, George F. (1958) The Decision to Intervene. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kennan, George F. (1967) Memoirs, 19251950. New York: Pantheon.
Kennan, George F. (1979) The Decline of Bismarcks European Order: Franco-Russian Relations, 1875
1890. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kennan, George F. (1984) American Diplomacy: Expanded Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kennan, George F. (1993) Around the Cragged Hill. New York: Norton.
Kennan, George F. (1996) At a Centurys Ending: Reflections, 19821995. New York: Norton.
Keohane, Robert O. (1986b) Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond. In Neorealism
and Its Critics, edited by Robert O. Keohane. New York: Columbia University Press.
Kissinger, Henry. (1995) Diplomacy. New York: Touchstone Books.
Knight, Frank H. (1982) Freedom and Reform: Essays in Economics and Social Philosophy. Indianapolis,
IN: Liberty Fund.
Kuklick, Bruce. (2006) Blind Oracles: Intellectuals and War from Kennan to Kissinger. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Kydd, Andrew. (1997a) Game Theory and the Spiral Model. World Politics 49: 371400.
Kydd, Andrew. (1997b) Sheep in Sheeps Clothing: Why Security Seekers Do Not Fight Each Other.
Security Studies 7: 114155.
Kydd, Andrew. (2000) Trust, Reassurance, and Cooperation. International Organization 54: 325357.
Kydd, Andrew. (2005) Trust and Mistrust in International Relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Labs, Eric J. (1997) Beyond Victory: Offensive Realism and the Expansion of War Aims. Security
Studies 6: 149.

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

211

Larson, Deborah Welch. (1985) Origins of Containment: A Psychological Explanation. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Lebow, Richard Ned. (2004) Constructive Realism. International Studies Review 6: 346348.
Lebow, Richard Ned. (2006) Fear, Interest and Honour: Outlines of a Theory of International
Relations. International Affairs 82: 431448.
Levy, Jack S., and William Thompson. (2010) Causes of War. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Lippmann, Walter. (1963) The Essential Lippmann, edited by Clinton Rossiter, and James Lare. New
York: Random House.
Lippmann, Walter. (1997) Public Opinion. New York: Free Press.
Lippmann, Walter. (1999) The Phantom Public. New Brunswick, NJ: Transactions.
Lobell, Steven, Norrin Ripsman, and Jeffrey Taliaferro, Eds. (2009) Neoclassical Realism, the
State, and Foreign Policy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Machiavelli, Niccolo. (1988) The Letters of Machiavelli, edited and translated by Allan Gilbert.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Machiavelli, Niccolo. (1998) The Prince, translated by Harvey C. Mansfield. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Mearsheimer, John J. (1990) Back to the Future: Instability in Europe After the Cold War. International Security 15: 556.
Mearsheimer, John J. (2001) The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York: Norton.
Mearsheimer, John J. (2009) Reckless States and Realism. International Relations 23: 241256.
Mearsheimer, John, and Stephen M. Walt. (2007) The Israel Lobby and U.S. Foreign Policy. New York:
Farar, Straus and Giroux.
Meinecke, Friedrich. (1967) The German Catastrophe, translated by Sidney Fay. Boston: Beacon Press.
Meinecke, Friedrich. (1977) The Age of German Liberation, 17951815, translated by Peter Paret, and
Helmuth Fischer. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Meinecke, Friedrich. (1998) Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison DEtat and Its Place in Modern
History, translated by Douglas Scott. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Mercer, Jonathan. (1995) Reputation and International Politics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Monten, Jonathan. (2006) Thucydides and Modern Realism. International Studies Quarterly 50: 325.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (1946) Scientific Man Versus Power Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (1966) Introduction. In A Working Peace System, edited by David Mitrany.
Chicago: Quadrangle Books.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (1967) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 4th edition. New
York: Knopf.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (1993) Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, Revised edn.
New York: McGraw Hill.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. (1959) The Structure of Nations and Empires. New York: Scribner.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. (1986) The Essential Reinhold Niebuhr, edited by Robert Brown. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. (2001) Moral Man & Immoral Society. New York: Scribner.
Ober, Josiah. (1998) Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Olschki, Leonardo. (1945) Machiavelli the Scientist. Berkeley, CA: Gillick Press.
Pape, Robert. (2005) Soft Balancing Against the United States. International Security 30: 745.
Parent, Joseph M. (2005) Machiavellis Missing Romulus and the Murderous Intent of The Prince.
History of Political Thought 26: 625645.
Paul, T.V., James Wirtz, and Michel Fortmann, Eds. (2004) Balance of Power: Theory and Practice in
the 21st Century. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Pois, Robert. (1972) Friedrich Meinecke and German Politics in the Twentieth Century. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Posen, Barry. (1984) The Sources of Military Doctrine. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Powell, Robert. (1994) Anarchy in International Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal
Debate. International Organization 48: 313344.
Recchia, Stefano. (2007) Restraining Imperial Hubris: The Ethical Bases of Realist International
Relations Theory. Constellations 14: 531556.
Reus-Smit, Christian. (1996) Beyond Foreign Policy. In The State in Question, edited by Paul W.
James. St Leonards, NSW Australia: Allen and Unwin.
Rose, Gideon. (1998) Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy. World Politics 5: 144172.
Rosecrance, Richard, and Arthur Stein, Eds. (1993) The Domestic Bases of Grand Strategy. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.

212

Elder Abuse

Rosen, Stephen P. (2004) War and Human Nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rosenthal, Joel H. (1991) Righteous Realists: Political Realism, Responsible Power, and American Culture
in the Nuclear Age. Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press.
Scheuerman, William E. (2009) Hans Morgenthau: Realism and Beyond. Malden, MA: Polity Press.
Schroeder, Paul. (1994) Historical Reality vs. Neo-realist Theory. International Security 19: 108148.
Schuett, Robert. (2010) Political Realism, Freud, and Human Nature in International Relations: The
Resurrection of the Realist Man. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Schuman, Frederick. (1970) War and Diplomacy in the French Republic. New York: AMS Press.
Schweller, Randall. (1996) Neorealisms Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma? Security Studies
5: 90121.
Schweller, Randall. (1997) New Realist Research on Alliances: Refining, Not Refuting, Waltzs
Balancing Proposition. American Political Science Review 91: 927930.
Schweller, Randall. (1998) Deadly Imbalances: Tripolarity and Hitlers Strategy of World Conquest. New
York: Columbia University Press.
Schweller, Randall. (2004) Unanswered Threats: A Neoclassical Realist Theory of Underbalancing.
International Security 29: 159201.
Sheehan, Michael. (1996) The Balance of Power: History and Theory. London: Routledge.
Simmel, Georg. (1971) The Miser and the Spendthrift. In On Individuality and Social Forms, edited by
Donald N. Levine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Smith, Adam. (1984) The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Smith, Michael J. (1986) Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger. Baton Rouge, LA: University of
Louisiana State Press.
Spirtas, Michael. (1996) A House Divided: Tragedy and Evil in Realist Theory. Security Studies 5:
409412.
Spykman, Nicholas J. (1925) The Social Theory of Georg Simmel. New York: Athaneum.
Spykman, Nicholas J. (1942) Americas Strategy in World Politics: The United States and the Balance of
Power. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.
Spykman, Nicholas, and Abbie Rollins. (1939) Geographic Objectives in Foreign Policy. American
Political Science Review 33: 391410.
Sterling-Folker, Jennifer. (1997) Realist Environment, Liberal Process, and Domestic-Level
Variables. International Studies Quarterly 41: 125.
Stern, Fritz. (1987) Dreams and Delusions: The Drama of German History. New York: Knopf, 1987.
Stigler, George J. (1982) The Economist as Preacher and Other Essays. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Sumner, William Graham. (1992) On Liberty, Society, and Politics, edited by Roger C. Bannister. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.
Taliaferro, Jeffrey, Peter D. Feaver, Gunther Hellman, Randall L. Schweller, William C.
Wohlforth, Jeffrey W. Legro, and Andrew Moravcsik. (2000 2001) Security-Seeking under
Anarchy: Defensive Realism Reconsidered. International Security 25: 128161.
Taylor, A.J.P. (1977) The Struggle for Mastery in Europe 18481918. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Taylor, A.J.P. (1996) The Origins of the Second World War. New York: Touchstone.
Tellis, Ashley. (1996) Reconstructing Political Realism: The Long March to Scientific Theory. In
Roots of Realism, edited by Benjamin Frankel. Portland, OR: Frank Cass.
Thayer, Bradley. (2000) Bringing in Darwin: Evolutionary Theory, Realism, and International Politics. International Security 25: 124151.
Thompson, Kenneth W. (1955) Toward a Theory of International Politics. American Political Science
Review 49: 733746.
Thucydides. (1998) The Peloponnesian War, edited by Walter Blanco, and Jennifer Tolbert Roberts.
New York: Norton.
Trachtenberg, Marc. (1991) History and Strategy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Trachtenberg, Marc. (2003) The Question of Realism: A Historians View. Security Studies 13: 156
194.
Tuck, Richard. (2001) The Rights of War and Peace: Political Thought and the International Order from
Grotius to Kant. New York: Oxford University Press.
Turner, Stephen, and George Mazur. (2009) Morgenthau as Weberian Methodologist. European
Journal of International Relations 15: 477504.
Walt, Stephen M. (1987) The Origins of Alliances. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Walt, Stephen M. (1999) Rigor or Rigor Mortis?: Rational Choice and Security Studies. International
Security 23: 548.

Joseph M. Parent and Joshua M. Baron

213

Walt, Stephen M. (2002) The Enduring Relevance of the Realist Tradition. In Political Science: The
State of the Discipline, edited by Ira Katznelson, and Helen V. Milner. New York: Norton.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1954) Man, the State, and the State System in Theories of the Causes of War.
Ph.D. Dissertation, Columbia University.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1959) Man, the State, and War: A Theoretical Analysis. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1967) Foreign Policy and Democratic Politics: The American and British Experience.
Boston: Little Brown.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1979) Theory of International Politics. Reading, Mass: Addison-Wesley.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1981) The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: More May Better. Adelphi Papers 171.
London: International Institute for Strategic Studies.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1990) Realist Thought and Neorealist Theory. Journal of International Affairs 44:
2138.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1996) International Politics is Not Foreign Policy. Security Studies 6: 753.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (2000) Structural Realism after the Cold War. International Security 25: 541.
Weber, Max. (1958) Science as a Vocation. In From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, edited by H.H.
Gerth, and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press.
Weber, Max. (1964) The Theory of Social and Economic Organization, edited by Talcott Parsons. New
York: Free Press.
Wight, Colin. (2002) The Philosophy of Social Science and International Relations. In Handbook of
International Relations, edited by Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse, and Beth Simmons. New York:
Sage.
Williams, Michael C. (2005) The Realist Tradition and the Limits of International Relations. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Wolfers, Arnold. (1962) Discord and Collaboration: Essays on International Politics. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins Press.
Wright, Quincy. (1983) A Study of War, 2nd edition. edited by L.L. Wright. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Zakaria, Fareed. (1992) Realism and Domestic Politics: A Review Essay. International Security 17:
177198.

You might also like