PhA 072 - POLYHISTOR - Studies in The History An Historiography of Ancient Philosophy PDF
PhA 072 - POLYHISTOR - Studies in The History An Historiography of Ancient Philosophy PDF
PhA 072 - POLYHISTOR - Studies in The History An Historiography of Ancient Philosophy PDF
PHILOSOPHIA ANTIQUA
A SERIES OF STUDIES
ON ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
FOUNDED BY J.H. WASZINK AND W.J. VERDENIUS
EDITED BY
VOLUME LXXII
POLYHISTOR
STUDIES IN THE HISTORY AND HISTORIOGRAPHY
OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
POLYHISTOR
STUDIES IN THE HISTORY AND
HISTORIOGRAPHY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
KEIMPE A. ALGRA
PIETER w. VAN DER HORST
DAVID T. RUNIA
EJ. BRILL
The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the
Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library
Resources.
ISSN 0079-1687
ISBN 90 04 10417 8
All rights reserved. No part qf this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in
a retrieval .rystem, or transmitted in ai!JI form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written
permission .from the publisher.
Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal
use is granted by EJ. Brill provided that
the appropriate fies are paid direct!J to The Copyright
Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 91 0
Danvers MA 01923, USA.
Fees are subject to change.
PRINTED IN THE NETHERLANDS
CONTENTS
Introduction......................................................................................
vii
de Chio .........................................................................................
21
41
61
76
J.
169
185
206
220
231
vi
CONTENTS
PART FIVE: Imperial Philosophy
243
265
284
300
313
J.
333
345
363
J.
385
407
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Stepping into the Stream: a Bibliography of the Publications of
Jaap Mansfeld 1964-1995...........................................................
418
INDICES
Index of Ancient Authors..............................................................
Index of Modern Scholars ..... ...... .... .... ... ........... ............. ... .... ..... ...
431
434
INTRODUCTION
XPll yap EU flUAa 7t0AAOOV Yotopa~ cptA.oo6cpou~ aviipa~ dvm ...
viii
INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION
lX
correspond not only to Jaap's own interests and research, but also to
a major concentration of effort by other scholars at the present
time. A special section is reserved for papers in the area of doxography, in which-as various scholars point out-Jaap's influence
is perhaps more dominant than in any other. At the end of the
volume we include a complete bibliography of Jaap's scholarly
writings up to the end of 1995. Here too we felt a Heraclitean title
was appropriate, for, given the large number of contributions
awaiting publication and other works in progress, we cheerfully
predict that this bibliography will one day deis volentibus appear to
be very incomplete.
For the editors it has been particularly gratifying that there
turned out to be a common thread through most of the papers submitted, i.e. the indissoluble link between the ideas and themes of
ancient philosophers and the writings in which those ideas and
themes have been presented, whether directly or through the
intermediation of the tradition. This has been the chief insight
which Jaap has developed in a myriad of ways during the past
thirty years. Its continued exploration has given the collection of
essays a modicum of unity and an additional sense of purpose.
The chief purpose of the volume, however, is to honour Jaap. We
hope that this gift will inspire and challenge him in the continuation of his scholarly activities. May he long remain faithful to the
saying of Heraclitus that forms the Leitmotiv for this collection.
INTRODUCTION
The editors
Utrecht & Leiden, May 1996
PART ONE
Very short papers are not what his readers most immediately
associate with the name of Jaap Mansfeld. But his piece entitled
'Anaxagoras' Other World' runs to less than three full pages of text,
and the notes cover only half a page more. 1 Perhaps its brevity is
one of the reasons for its neglect. Schofield in his light revision of
Raven's chapter on Anaxagoras in The Presocratic Philosophers does
not refer to it.2 Nor do more recent articles such as Inwood's or
Furth's. 3 The neglect is unfortunate. Of the difficult text Mansfeld
takes as his topic, 'Anaxagoras' Other World' seems to me much
the most persuasive account available in the scholarly literature. In
what follows I shall advance further considerations in favour of its
interpretation of the mysterious 'other world', and against some of
the alternatives favoured in other quarters.
The text in question is as usual preserved by Simplicius, and
since its analysis by Hermann Frankel known to afficionados as
Fragment 4a. 4 Here is the text, followed by a translation. Anaxagoras' prose as often contains ambiguities. For example, in the first
sentence there is a present infinitive in oratio obliqua, which I have
taken as probably representing a present indicative, although I
once thought it reflected an imperfect. My version borrows from
Furley's and Raven's5 (in KRS):6
'tOU'tCOV & ou'tco<; x6v'tcov XPil 001ce\v EVEtVat noA.A.a 'tE Kat
nav'tota EV nncrt 'tOt<; cruyKptvOJ.lEVOt<; Kat (J1tEpJ.la'ta 7tUV'tCOV
XPTJJ.lU'tCOV Kat iOEa<; 1taV'tOta<; EXOV'ta Kat xpota<; Kat ft&ova<;. Kat
av8pc07tOU<; 'tE OUJ.17tayi\vat Kat 'tU aAAa scpa ocra 'lfUXilV EXEt. Kat
Mansfeld (1980) 1-4.
Kirk, Raven and Schofield (1983) 352-89.
3 Inwood (1986) 17-33; Furth (1991) 95-129.
4 Frankel (1955) 287 and n. 1. For information about Simplicius' citations
see Diels-Kranz (1952) 59 B4: the relevant passages are in his commentaries
on De Caelo 609.3-11 and Physics 34.28-35.9 and 156.2-4, 157.9-16.
5 Furley (1989) 56; Raven in Kirk, Raven and Schofield (1983) 369 and
379.
6 Text as in KRS nos. 483 and 498, except as indicated in n. 7.
I
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
'
"
,...
,..
";'
on
These things being so, it is right to think that there are, in all
the aggregates, many things, of all kinds, and seeds of all
things-[seeds] having forms and colours and savours of
every kind; and that human beings were formed and the
other living creatures that have soul; and that among the
humans there are cities that have been constructed and
buildings that have, been manufactured, as is the case with
us;7 and that they have sun and moon and the rest, as is the
case with us; and that the earth grows for them many things,
of all kinds, of which they collect together the best into their
dwelling and make use of them. This, then, is my story about
the separation: that separation would have taken place not
only with us, but elsewhere too.
1. Simplicius' interpretation
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
14 In Physica 35.13.
concluding that this is Simplicius' 'considered view'. Vlastos (1975) 358 tries
to downplay the importance and reduce the scope of Simplicius' doubts, referring inter alia to their absence in the De Caelo commentary (608.31-609.12).
But that commentary probably antedates the Physics commentary: so Hadot
(1990) 289-90. Vlastos is right however that Simplicius betrays no sign of
being tempted by a plurality of worlds interpretation.
2. A plurality of universes?
In his discussions of Fr. 4a Simplicius nowhere entertains the
possibility that Anaxagoras was arguing for the existence of other
physical and in principle perceptible worlds like our own, such as
are very clearly attested for the atomists Leucippus and Democritus,23 and more controversially for e.g. Anaximander.24 This is
surprising, since prima facie it is an obvious way to read the passage.
But Anaxagoras does not appear on standard ancient lists of proponents of a plurality of worlds, nor does Aristotle ever number
him in that company (although he does not explicitly attribute to
him the belief that there is only one world, as Simplicius and
Aetius do). 25 It is true that Simplicius once cites a passage of
Theophrastus which in a comparison between Anaximander's
infinite and Anaxagoras' mixture credits Anaxagoras with the
generation of 'the worlds' as a result of the activity of mind. But he
does not exploit this claim of Theophrastus; and we can probably
not determine whether it was Theophrastus' considered view of
20 As argued by Schofield (1975) 11.
21
A40).
2 4 E.g. Stob. Eel. 1.22.3 (= DK 12 A 17), Simp. Phys. 1121.5-9. For a case
against the correctness of this attribution see e.g. Kirk in Kirk, Raven and
Schofield (1983) 122-6. I believe the attribution to be sound: see Schofield
(1997) for a brief statement for the defence, Burnet (1930) 58-61 for a fuller
argument, and Conche (1991) ch. 5 for a thorough refutation of scepticism on
the issue.
25 For the standard lists see the texts cited in n. 24; for Anaxagoras as
proponent of a single world see Stob. Eel. 1.22.2 (= DK 59 A63), Simp. Phys.
178.23-6. The grounds on which Anaxagoras was regarded as a one world
theorist may well have been dubious: very likely the mention of 'the one
kosmos' in Fr. 8, which however is probably primarily a reference to its
internal unity.
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
3. A Gedankenexperiment?
A novel attempt at interpretation, taking a quite different approach,
was offered by Frankel in the 1950s.3I His proposal found some
weighty supporters in the shape of Gregory Vlastos and David
Furley.32 In essence Frankel's Anaxagoras says not that there is a
world besides our own (as in Simplicius) or a plurality of such
worlds (as on the view examined in Section 2), but that given the
initial conditions of an original mixture operated on by the
separating activity of mind, any other world it created would be just
like ours. I.e if mind decided to intervene at some other point of the
original mixture, exactly the same process of separation would
occur there as resulted in our universe. On this reading of
Anaxagoras the point of Fr. 4a could be expressed in terms of
contemporary possible worlds metaphysics as follows: what is true
in our world is true in every possible world-which is a way of
arguing that things in our world are necessarily the way they are.
Frankel's interpretation puts a lot of emphasis on two features of
the Greek. First, it stresses that Fr. 4a begins with a thesis not about
reality, but about the correct theory of reality. Starting from the
assumption that 'these things are so', it states what we must then
suppose (8oKetv) to be the case.33 In effect this is already a claim not
that things happened in a certain way, but that given the conditions specified in the theory elaborated so far, no other outcome is
31
32 Vlastos (1975) 354-60; Furley (1989) 56. I accepted the Frankel interpre-
10
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
35 Mansfeld (1980) 1.
36 Mansfeld (1980) 1.
37 Mansfeld (1980) 1.
11
39 As
12
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
when he reiterates 'as is the case with us', this is the 'as' not of
comparison but of exemplification or illustration.42
This highly ingenious reinterpretation of Fr. 4a, mostly tucked
away in a footnote, is of course rather startling. Everybody-Simplicius and modern readers alike-has supposed that the fragment
is talking about another world or another civilization. The disagreement has been over the identity and status of that world or
civilization. On Furley's view everybody (including Frankel) has
got the passage wrong. It is not about another world at all.
The part of Fr. 4a which is hardest to accommodate within
Furley's exegesis is the concluding sentence:
This, then, is my story about the separation: that separation would
have taken place not only with us, but elsewhere too.
The contrast 'not only with us, but elsewhere too' seems designed
to round off an account of another world that has been compared
with our own: first Anaxagoras tells us about another world just
like ours that is also produced by the separation, then like the
preacher he tells us that he has told us. Furley has to give a more
convoluted explanation of the role of the sentence. 43 He must say
that the point of the main part of the fragment is to argue that the
initial conditions must produce a world such as ours is. We can
then infer that if those conditions were to obtain at some other
place or time, the same would happen or have happened there.
Anaxagoras has not spelled out that inference in the main passage:
it is not 'the story about separation' he has actually told. But if we
assume it was in his sights all along, Furley might suggest, it is
not too hard to understand why he should have claimed that he
has. As I say, this is pretty convoluted.
There is also a whole cluster of difficulties with the suggestion
that by 'it is right to think (8oKEtv)' Anaxagoras means 'it is only
(i.e. uniquely) reasonable to expect', i.e. something amounting to a
claim that what follows is the necessary consequence of the conditions just referred to ('these things being so'). The expression could
in appropriate circumstances mean something as strong as that, but
it cannot be said to be obvious that it does here. It is also rather
puzzling that Anaxagoras should wish to make such a strong claim
4 2 My gloss on Furley: not his own formulation.
43 Again, this account of Furley's position is partly extrapolation from his
very brief discussion of the text.
13
5. Microscopic worlds
'I believe', said Mansfeld, 'that the inquiry should start elsewhere' .46
The Anaxagorean idea he proposed as the key to Fr. 4a is what he
identified as a theory about the infinity, or more specifically the
44 Plato Phaedo 97B-99D; cf. Arist. Metaph. 985a18-21.
45 Frankel ( 1955) 285-6, 292-3.
46 Mansfeld (1980) 2.
14
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
infinitely small, but which I should prefer to call the thesis that
complexity is no function of size. 47 It is the idea not merely that
there is no lower limit on how small a thing can be ('there is no
least', Fr. 3 and 6), but that the small is just as complex as the large
(Fr. 6). The crucial text is Fr. 6.
And since, too, there are portions equal in number belonging to
both the large and the small, in this way too all things will be in
everything. Since the least cannot be, none of them could be
separated, nor come to be on its own; but as in the beginning, so too
now all things must be together. And in all things there are many
even of the things that are separating off, equal in number in both
the larger and the smaller.
15
16
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
These things being so, it is right to think that there are, in all the
aggregates, many things, of all kinds, and seeds of all things.
Given that the aggregates are things in a world or worlds where
separation has taken place and is still occurring, it is hard to see
how Anaxagoras could justify the claim he makes here unless
'these things being so' includes a reference to the contention that
in everything there still is something of everything, even though
the original mixture is no more. But so paradoxical is that
contention that he must have mentioned some arguments in its
favour when introducing it. The reference to seeds at the beginning of Fr. 4a makes it likely that among them was a proof of the
sort reflected in the scholium which gives us Fr. 10: 'How could
hair come to be out of not hair, and flesh out of not flesh?', and
which specifically talks about seeds containing such bodily parts.52
Our evidence, however, suggests that when Anaxagoras argued for
the doctrine of everything in everything he presented a set of
proofs, 53 so the one recorded in Fr. 6 (which announces itself as
one of a series: 'And since, too, ... in this way too') was probably one
of those accompanying the proof from seeds. The reference to
separation in Fr. 6 is also consistent with its having occurred in the
same part of Anaxagoras' book as Fr. 2 and Fr. 4a. It is perhaps
significant that Fr. 4a begins in argumentative fashion. This too is
a feature it shares with the material in the fragments and testimonia on the everything in everything doctrine, in contrast with
the explanatory narrative style used to propound the major claims
about the original mixture and about the cosmogonic activity of
mind. 54
Mansfeld's proposal that Fr. 4a is in effect an elaboration of
Anaxagoras' conception of 'smaller' things equal in complexity to
'larger' things suggests an explanation of some opaque locutions in
Fr. 12. Anaxagoras speaks there of mind's control of 'all the things
that have soul, both the larger and the smaller', and again of how
all mind is the same, 'both the larger and the smaller'. It sounds as
though he has something specific in view when he employs these
5 2 Fr. 10 is contained in a scholium on Gregory of Nazianzus (see PG
XXXVI 911; cf. 521). I discuss it in Schofield (1975) 14-24 and Schofield (1980)
133-43. My use of Fr. 10 here is, I think, in line with the valuable
observations in Mansfeld (1982) 361-3.
53 Cf. e.g. Arist. Phys. 187a26-b7.
54 Anaxagoras' expository and argumentative styles are one of the major
themes of Schofield (1980).
17
55 Mansfeld's account of Fr. 4a thus presents a strong challenge to the contention of Inwood (1986) 17-33 (especially 22) that the small is by definition
mixed and as such not 'separated out', or of Furth (1991) 95-129 (especially
111-112) that (i) the latent is 'small' (ii) that is latent of which there are
'few' or 'less' (iii) latent things are 'together' and 'commingled', not 'separated out' or 'distinguished'. On the other hand Mansfeld's interpretation is
consistent with the suggestion in Sorabji ( 1988) 61-66 that for Anaxagoras,
'the small' is like an infinitesimal powder.
18
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
19
Vlastos wrote:57
Had Anaxagoras travelled further along the road of infinity, he
might have glimpsed the enchanting prospect of a world in
every seed, and so worlds within worlds ad infinitum, matching or
bettering Leibniz's doctrine that 'each portion of matter may be
conceived as like a garden full of plants and like a pond full of
fishes; but each branch of every plant, each member of every
animal, each drop of its liquid parts is also some such garden or
pond' (Monadology 67). Anaxagoras' imagination took him far, but
not so far.
If Mansfeld is right-and I have tried to show why and that he isin Fr. 4a we see Anaxagoras' imagination taking him exactly
where Vlastos thinks it did not reach.58
20
MALCOLM SCHOFIELD
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Barnes, J. (1979) The Presocratic Philosophers, Vol. 2 (London).
Burnet, J. ( 1930) Early Greek Philosophy, 4th edn. (London).
Conche, M. ( 1991) Anaximandre: Fragments et Temoinages (Paris).
Cornford, F.M. (1934) "Innumerable Worlds in Presocratic Cosmogony",
Classical Quarterly 28:1-14.
Denyer, N.C. (1983) "Plato's Theory of Stuffs", Philosophy 58: 315-27.
Diels, H. and Kranz, W. (1951-2) Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th edn., 2
vols. (Berlin).
Fninkel, H. (1955) Wege und Formen Jrilhgriechischen Denkens (Munich).
Furley, DJ. (1989) Cosmic Problems (Cambridge).
Furth, M. (1991) "A 'Philosophical Hero'? Anaxagoras and the Eleatics",
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 9: 95-129.
Guthrie, W.K.C. (1965) A History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. 2 (Cambridge).
Hadot, I. (1990) "The Life and Work of Simplicius in Greek and Arabic
Sources", in Aristotle Transformed, ed. R. Sorabji (London) 275-303.
Inwood, B. (1986) "Anaxagoras and Infinite Divisibility", Illinois Classical
Studies 11: 17-33.
Kirk, G.S., Raven, J.E. and Schofield, M. (1983) The Presocratic Philosophers,
2nd edn. (Cambridge).
Lanza, D. (1966) Anassagora (Florence).
Leon, P. (1927) "The Homoeomeries of Anaxagoras", Classical Quarterly 21:
133-41.
Mansfeld, J. (1979) "Providence and the Destruction of the Universe in early
Stoic Thought", in Studies in Hellenistic Religions, ed. M.J. Vermaseren
(Leiden). Reprinted in his Studies in Later Greek Philosophy and Gnosticism
(London 1989).
- - (1980) "Anaxagoras' Other World", Phronesis 25: 1-4.
- - ( 1982) Review of Schofield ( 1980), Mnemosyne 35: 360-366.
Schofield, M. (1975) "Doxographica Anaxagorea", Hermes 103: 1-24.
- - (1980) An Essay on Anaxagoras (Cambridge).
- - (1997) "The lonians", in The Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. 1, ed.
C.C.W. Taylor (London).
Sider, D. (1981) The Fragments of Anaxagoras (Meisenheim am Glan).
Sorabji, R. ( 1988) Matter, Space and Motion (London).
Strang, C. (1975) "The Physical Theory of Anaxagoras", in Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, Vol. 2, ed. R.E. Allen and DJ. Furley (London) 361-80.
Vlastos, G. (1975) "One World or Many in Anaxagoras?", in Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, Vol. 2, ed. R.E. Allen and DJ. Furley (London) 354-60.
22
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
juger par les nombreuses references et allusions qui lui sont faites
dans Ia doxographie.
La ran~on de cette celebrite est que Ia parole de Metrodore nous
est transmise sous des formes tres diverses, plus diverses qu'on ne
le dit parfois.s La tache que je me fixe, et qui ne semble pas avoir ete
faite jusqu'ici de fa~on systematique,6 est d'etudier les temoignages
qui Ia concernent, de les comparer, et d'essayer de voir si l'on peut
identifier Ia version qui a les meilleures chances d'etre authentique.Je presente d'abord ces temoignages, dans un ordre qui n'est
pas chronologique (ni a l'endroit ni meme a l'envers), mais qui est
plutot celui de leur longueur et de leur complexite croissantes.7
A= !J.T)OEva !J.T)aEv en(cnacrSm (Epiphane, Adv. haer. III 2,9 = DK 70
A 23, DDG 590,35).
B = !-LD [doe]vm !J.T)l>' m'rro Tou[To (Philodeme, Rhet. fr. inc., Pap.
Here. 224, II 169 Sudhaus = DK 70 A 25).
c = eA.eye !J.T)O' m'rro TOUT' ELOEV<ll, <5n oul>Ev oToe (Diogene Laerce,
IX 58= DK69A2, 72 A 1).8
etre sur Ia tradition selon laquelle Metrodore et Protagoras auraient ete tous
deux les disciples de Democrite (Clem. Alex., Strom. I 64 = DK 70 A 1).
5 Pour presenter Ia parole de Metrodore, beaucoup de commentateurs se
contentent de citer l'un des temoignages disponibles. D'autres traitent assez
cavalierement Ia question de savoir comment les harmoniser. Ainsi ZellerMondolfo (1969) 314 n. 69 cite Eusebe et ajoute que !'on trouve "Ia meme
chose" chez Sextus, Diogene Laerce, Epiphane et Ciceron; cf. aussi, entre
autres, Ernout et Robin (1926) 2.227. Le plus influent de cet ecrasement des
differences a certainement ete le collage opere par DK 70 B 1 entre le texte
d'Eusebe et une retroversion partielle du texte de Ciceron. J'y reviendrai
naturellement. Je signale en passant que Shorey (1919) 393-394 porte, malgre
son titre aujourd'hui trompeur, sur ce qui est maintenant DK 70 B 2.
6 Ce qui s'en approche le plus est Langerbeck (1935) 121-123.
7 Je ne compte pas ici parmi les temoignages sur Ia parole de Metrodore
Ia celebre refutation du scepticisme chez Lucrece (IV 469-477), bien qu'un
nombre considerable de commentateurs aient considere que Ia version du
scepticisme visee par Lucrece (et deja par Epicure) etait celle de Metrodore
(voir entre autres Ernout et Robin (1926) 2.226-227, Bailey (1947) 3.1238,
DeLacy (1971) 605 n. 30, Burnyeat (1978) 204, Isnardi-Parente (1984) 106-121,
Gigante ( 1990) 79). Je me rangerai plutot parmi les rares qui en doutent
(Vander Waerdt ( 1989) 242 n. 48). En effet, Lucrece objecte a son adversaire
sceptique qu'il "ne peut pas savoir qu'on ne peut rien savoir, puisqu'il professe
ne rien savoir"; puis il lui concede tactiquement ( 473) qu'il possede un tel
savoir au second degre. Cet adversaire, contrairement a Metrodore, pretend
done savoir qu'on ne peut rien savoir. Metrodore parait avoir voulu precisement desarmer, par anticipation, ce genre d'objection (cf. Straume-Zimmermann et aL (1990) 414).
8 Curieusement, C n'est pas repris dans DK 70, le chapitre consacre a
Metrodore.
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
23
on
24
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
25
nacrt TETUXTat, et celle qui est ici pretee a Metrodore, ooxf}cret yap
ecrn Ta TTU'VT<l. 16 Mais on peut certainement aller plus loin que ce
rapprochement ponctuel: 1' Ia position resumee ci-dessus peut en
effet constituer une interpretation tout a fait decente du fragment de
Xenophane. 18 Ce ne serait pas le seul exemple d'un rapprochement
ancien entre Metrodore et Xenophane: Mansfeldl9 a brillamment
montre que plusieurs anomalies de Ia doxographie d'Hippolyte20
(Xenophane y vient apres Democrite, et son explication de Ia salinite de Ia mer est mise en contraste, en plein milieu du chapitre qui
lui est consacre, avec celle de Metrodore) viennent de ce que, dans
l'esprit d'Hippolyte, les deux penseurs devaient etre associes pour
une raison plus importante que leur divergence d'avis a propos de
Ia salinite de Ia mer: a savoir, leur commune inclination au scepticisme. Mansfeld ne cite pas A dans ce contexte; mais on peut assez
aisement voir en A le resultat d'une sorte de contamination doxographique, explicitant le sens du scepticisme affiche en Ai par des
considerations (Aii et Aiv) d'inspiration plus ou moins directement
xenophanienne.
B
26
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
27
c
Diogene Laerce ne consacre aucune notice a Metrodore, et c'est
dommage. 11 est impossible de savoir pourquoi il ne l'a pas fait,
puisque le philosophe de Chio ne lui est pas inconnu. 11 le mentionne au debut de sa notice sur Anaxarque (IX 58), a l'interieur
d'une "succession" democriteenne qui fait de lui, d'une part le
maitre de Diogene de Smyrne, lui-meme maitre d'Anaxarque,
d'autre part l'eleve de Nessas de Chio, ou selon certains, de Democrite lui-meme.26 A cette occasion, Diogene Laerce mentionne
!'opinion sans doute la plus frappante de Metrodore: "il disait ne
meme pas savoir cela meme, qu 'il ne savait rien". 27
26 Sur les variantes de cette succession, cf. Eus. Praep. Ev. XIV 17 10 = DK 69
A 1 (Metrodore eJeve de Nessas, lui-meme eJeve de Democrite), id. ibid. XIV
17 8 = DK 70 B 1 (Metrodore eJeve de Democrite), Clem. Alex., Strom. I 64 =
DK 70 A 1 (Metrodore eleve de Democrite). Ces variantes sont sans doute
Iiees a des incertitudes sur Ia chronologie exacte de Metrodore. Je ne puis
m 'attarder ici sur ce probleme (voir aussi DK 70 A 2 et Alfieri ( 1953) 28); une
datation relativement haute (fixant Ia naissance de Metrodore vers Ia fin des
annees -420) semble etre Ia seule compatible avec Ia mention faite de lui par
Ant~hane (cf. n. 23), dans une comedie que les specialistes datent de -388.
2
MrrcpoMpou
TOU
TOUT'
dMvm,
on oMEv oT6.
28
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
Par rapport a A, C introduit d'abord une variante qui ne se retrouvera nulle part ailleurs, et qui est en elle-meme assez suspecte: elle
fait parler Metrodore de sa propre ignorance, non de celle des
hommes en general. Faut-il supposer qu'a tel ou tel moment de la
transmission a circule une version de l'enonce de Metrodore qui,
comme B, ne contenait aucune precision a ce propos, et que la
version de Diogene Laerce resulte d'une conjecture destinee a
combler cette lacune ? On peut au moins se poser la question.
On observe aussi et surtout, en C, un embryon d'expression
autonome de l'ignorance 1 ("cela meme, qu'il ne savait rien"). Cette
expression met dans une lumiere plus vive la difficulte deja
evoquee: si je ne sais2 meme pas que je ne saisl rien, pourquoi
designer par 'je ne sais 1 rien" 1' objet sur lequel porte mon ignorance2, plutot que, par exemple, par 'je sais 1 quelque chose" ? Une
position coherente, semble-t-il, serait plutot de dire: 'je ne sais2 pas
si je sais 1 quelque chose ou si je ne sais 1 rien ".
D
30
UUTO TOUTO
'(OfJ.E\1
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B I DE METRODORE DE CHIO
29
sur le plan historique-peut-etre meme au contraire, bien entendu). On y voit notamment que I' incertitude qui affecte le sujet de
I' en once en B, et qui etait levee au profit de Ia premiere personne
du singulier en C, se trouve maintenant levee au profit (assurement
plus plausible) de Ia premiere personne du pluriel: c'est nous, les
hommes en general, qui sommes les victimes d'une ignorance
redoublee.
Mais surtout, D contient (pour Ia premiere fois dans l'ordre de
notre examen) une expression explicite et parfaitement assertorique
de notre ignorance 1 universe lie (Di), ainsi qu 'une expression claire
de Ia subsomption de cette ignorance 1 par une ignorance 2 (Dii).
II importerait beaucoup, pour notre enquete, de savoir quelle a ete
Ia genese de cette formulation. En suivant Ia suggestion de
Burnyeat, je tenterai de replacer le probleme dans un contexte
dialectique. On peut au mains imaginer, entre Metrodore et un
interlocuteur que je nommerai Antidore, deux enchainements de
dialogue qui auraient pu aboutir au meme resultat, par des voies
tres differentes.
Le premier enchainement serait le suivant:
Metrodore: "Nous ne savons 1 rien" (= Di).
Antidore: "Si tu l'affirmes, c'est que nous savons2 au mains ceci,
que nous ne savons 1 rien (ton scepticisme est inevitablement ce
qu'on appellera un jour un metadogmatisme negatif) ",31
Metrodore: "Non, nous ne savons2 meme pas cela, que nous ne
savons 1 rien" (= Dii).32
3! Barnes (1992) 4252 n. 54 et 4254 n. 72 a tres utilement distingue le
"dogmatisme negatir, qui consiste a soutenir des doctrines, mais seulement
des doctrines de forme negative, et le "metadogmatisme", qui consiste a
soutenir des doctrines, positives ou negatives, sur le statut cognitif de certaines
propositions. Bien entendu, comme le souligne Barnes, on peut etre metadogmatique negatif, si l'on soutient des doctrines negatives sur le statut cognitif
de certaines propositions. Si l'on ne distingue pas les niveaux de savoir ou
d'ignorance, !'objection d'Antidore tend a montrer que Ia position initiate
de Metrodore se refute elle-meme.
32 D a ete souvent rapproche de !'attitude d'Arcesilas par rapport a !'ignorance socratique (Arcesilas negabat esse quidquam quod sciri posset, ne illud quidem
ipsum, quod Socrates sibi reliquisset, Ciceron, Acad. I 45). Mais cela ne signifie
pas necessairement que Metrodore ait influence Arcesilas: Langerbeck (1935)
121-122 estime ajuste titre que les versions D etC peuvent resulter de !'insertion de Ia position de Metrodore dans un environnement platonico-socratique
qui l'eloigne irremediablement de son environnement democriteen originaire. Seton Straume-Zimmermann et al. (1990) 414, l'agnosticisme de Metrodore s'exprime de fa~on a desarmer !'objection de Ia nepLTpom'J, mais sa
formulation parait aussi "in irgendeiner Beziehung zur Aporetik des plato-
30
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
31
32
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
F
11 est temps d'aborder le temoignage de Ciceron, le plus long, le
plus complexe, et aussi le moins eloigne de Metrodore dans le
temps. 11 figure dans une longue enumeration des diverses autorites qui peuvent appuyer, a des titres divers, la position de l'Academie philonienne. Apres avoir parle de Democrite, Ciceron passe a
Metrodore, "celui qui a le plus admire" ce dernier. 37 Confirmant
!'indication d'Eusebe, il dit qu'au debut de son livre Sur la nature,
Metrodore avait ecrit ce que Ciceron traduit en latin de la fa~on
suivante: (i) nego scire nos sciamusne aliquid an nihil sciamus, (ii) ne id
ipsum quidem nescire aut scire <scire> nos, (iii) nee omnino sitne aliquid an
nihil sit. 38
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
33
34
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
35
Devant un texte aussi difficile, on peut s'etonner que les tentatives de correction conjecturale aient ete relativement rares.52 La
plus interessante me parait etre celle de Langerbeck, qui, apres
avoir critique le montage opere par Diels, remarque que !'insertion
de <scirf!> n'arrange rien, et note tres cursivement: "Offenbar ist das
nescire von Cicero der stilistischen blendenden Antithese zuliebe
eingefiigt".53 Dans sa hate, il a oublie de dire que si l'on supprime
nescire, il faut aussi supprimer aut. Mais il me semble que si l'on
suit jusqu'au bout la piste ouverte par Langerbeck, on aboutit a un
texte et a un sens tout a fait satisfaisants. Le texte de Fii devient:
"(nego) ... ne id ipsum quidem scire nos". Le sens qu'on peut donner a
ce texte (Langerbeck lui-meme ne l'explicite pas) est le suivant: 54
"Ue nie) ... que nous sachions3 cela meme (i.e. Fi, i.e. que nous ne
savons 2 pas si nous savons 1 quelque chose ou rien) ".
Les avantages de cette hypothese sont multiples. Tout d'abord, on
peut imaginer sans peine une genese dialectique de l' ensemble Fi
+ Fii, a partir de l'enchainement suivant:
Metrodore: "Nous ne savons 2 pas si nous savons 1 quelque chose
ou rien" (= Fi).
Antidore: "Mais cela, nous le savons3 (i.e. que nous ne savons 2
pas si nous savons 1 quelque chose ou rien) ?"
Metrodore: "Non, nous ne savons3 meme pas cela meme (i.e.
que nous ne savons 2 pas si nous savons 1 quelque chose ou rien) (=
Fii).
Deuxieme avantage: si l'on suppose (plus ou moins litteralement) authentique !'original grec de nego scire nos sciamusne aliquid
an nihil sciamus, ne id ipsum quidem scire nos, on voit assez bien
comment le texte de Ciceron a pu se corrompre en se compliquant:
dans un premier temps, !'alternative nescire aut scire se substitue au
simple scire, soit pour batir une antithese seduisante (comme le
que !'on conserve <scire>("[Io affirmo] ... che non sappiamo neppure se sappiamo o non sappiamo questa cosa stessa"); de meme, mais sans <scire>, Barigazzi
(1969) 291 et Straume-Zimmermann et al. (1990) 189.
52 U ne autre hypothese, suggeree par Carlos Levy (per litteram), serait que
Fi soit Ia traduction du texte de Metrodore par Ciceron, et Fii une traduction
alternative de ce meme texte, effectuee soit par Ciceron lui-meme, soit par un
correcteur posterieur. II n 'y aurait done pas lieu de chercher une difference de
sens entre Fi et Fii. La difficulte est alors que ne id ipsum quidem perd sa valeur
de surenchere par rapport a ce qui precede.
53 Langerbeck (1935) 122.
54 Rappelons qu'en syntaxe latine, quand Ia locution ne ... quidem suit une
negation, elle ne l'annule pas.
36
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
LE FRAGMENT DK
70
B 1 DE METRODORE DE CHIO
37
REFERENCES BIBLIOGRAPHIQUES
Alfieri, V.E. (1936) Gli Atomisti. Frammenti e Testimonianze (Bari).
--(1953) Atomos Idea (Firenze).
Appuhn, Ch. (s.d.) Ciciron: De la Divination - Du Destin - Acadimiques (Paris).
Armstrong, D.M. (1973) Belief, Truth and Knowledge (London).
Bailey, C. (1947) Titi Lucreti Cari De Rerum Natura Lilni Sex (Oxford).
Barigazzi, A. (1969) "Epicure et le scepticisme", in Actes du VIII' Congres de
['Association Guillaume Bude: 286-93.
Barnes, J. (19822) The Presocratic Philosophers (London).
--(1992) "Diogenes Laertius IX 61-116: The Philosophy of Pyrrhonism", in
Aufstieg und Niedergang der romischen Welt, ed. W. Haase (Berlin) 11.36.6,
4241-4301.
Bonjour, L. (1980) "Externalist theories of empirical knowledge", Midwest
Studies in Philosophy 5: 53-73.
Brochard, V. (19232) Les sceptiques grecs (Paris).
Burnyeat, M. F. (1978) "The Upside-Down Back-to-Front Sceptic of Lucretius
IV 472", Philologus 122: 197-206.
Cappelletti, AJ. (1979). Ensayos sobre los Atomistas Griegos (Caracas).
Conche, M. (1984) "Metrodore de Chio", in Dictionnaire des Philosophes, ed. D.
Huisman (Paris) 2.1821.
Cronert, W. ( 1906) Kolotes und Menedemos (Leipzig).
Dal Pra, M. ( 19752) Lo scetticismo greco (Roma-Bari).
5 7 Pour dHendre l'authenticite metrodorienne de Fiii contre les doutes
d'Ernout et Robin, Conche (1984) 1821 ecrit: "Metrodore a pu s'apercevoir de
Ia contradiction qu'il y avait, chez Democrite, a poser des atomes reels pour
expliquer un sensible sans vraie realite, et etre ainsi conduit du scepticisme a
l'egard des sens au nihilisme ontologique". Mais Metrodore, autant que nous
sachions, n'a pas repudie !'ontologie atomistique; de plus, le "nihilisme
ontologique" n'est que l'une des branches de !'alternative dans laquelle Fiii
nous laisse en suspens.
38
JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG
DeLacy, Ph. ( 1971) "Ou !J.MA0\1 and the Antecedents of Ancient Scepticism",
in Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, ed. J.P. Anton and G.L. Kustas
(Albany) 593-606.
Des Places, E. (1987) Eusebe de Cisarie: La Preparation ivangilique, Livres XIVXV (Paris).
DDG = Diels, H. ( 1879) Doxographi graeci (Berlin).
DK = Diels, H. und Kranz, W. ( 19568 ) Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (Berlin).
Dumont, J.P. (1988) Les Prisocratiques (Paris).
Ern out, A. et Robin, L. ( 19622) Lucrece: De Rerum Natura. Commentaire exigitique
et critique (Paris).
Friedlander, P. (1969) Studien zur antiken Literatur und Kunst (Berlin).
Gigante, M. (1981) Scetticismo eEpicureismo (Naples).
- - (1990) "Quelques precisions sur le scepticisme et l'epicurisme", in Le
scepticisme antique - Perspectives historiques et systimatiques, ed. AJ. Voelke
(Geneve-Lausanne-Neuchatel) 69-83.
Goedeckemeyer, A. (1905) Die Geschichte der Griechischen Skeptizismus (Leipzig).
Hankinson, RJ. (1995) The Sceptics (London).
Hussey, E. (1990) "The beginnings of epistemology: from Homer to Philolaus", in Epistemology, ed. S. Everson, Companions to Ancient Thought: 1
(Cambridge) 11-38.
Isnardi-Parente, M. (1984) "I democritei e l'antiscetticismo di Epicuro (Ratae
Sententiae XXIII-XXIV)", in La storia della filosofia come sapere critico - Studi
in onore di Mario Dal Pra , ed. F. Angeli (Milano): 10&-121.
Langerbeck, H. (1935) t.OEIE EIIIPPYEMIH: Studien zu Demokrits Ethik und
Erkenntnislehre (Berlin).
Lesher, J.H. (1978) "Xenophanes' Scepticism", Phronesis 23: 1-21.
- - (1992) Xenophanes of Colophon: Fragments (Toronto).
Mansfeld, J. ( 1992) Heresiography in Context: Hippolytus' Elenchos as a Source for
Greek Philosophy (Leiden).
Plasberg, 0. ( 1922) Academicorum reliquiae cum Lucullo (Leipzig).
Rackham, H. (1933) Cicero: De Natura Deorum - Academica (Cambridge Mass.London).
Reid,J.S. (1885) M. Tulli Ciceronis Academica (London).
Schiiublin, C. und Graeser, A. (1995) Cicero: Academica (Leipzig) (non vidi ).
Sedley, D. (1983) "The Motivation of Greek Skepticism", in The Skeptical
Tradition , ed. M. Burnyeat (Berkeley-Los Angeles-London) 9-29.
Shorey, P. (1919) "Note on Metrodorus, fragm. 1", Classical Philology 14: 393-4.
Straume-Zimmermann L., Broemser F., Gigon 0. (1990) Hortensius - Lucullus
- Academici libri (Miinchen-Ziirich).
Vander Waerdt, P. A. (1989). "Colotes and the Epicurean Refutation of
Scepticism", Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 30: 225-267.
Wilamowitz-Mollendorf, U. v. (1899) "Lesefriichte", Hermes 34: 601-639.
Zeller, E., Mondolfo, R. (1969) La filosofia dei Greci nel suo sviluppo storico. Parte
I, volume V: Empedocle, Atomisti, Anassagora a cura di A. Capizzi (Firenze).
PART TWO
PLATO
42
KEIMPE ALGRA
43
44
KEIMPE ALGRA
will be clear from what follows that I happily endorse the latter
approach.
The present paper is structured as follows. Section 2 contains a
summary which will serve as a basis for the analysis which is to
follow. Section 3 discusses the way the Thrasymachus episode
connects with the rest of the Republic. Section 4 will deal with
Plato's literary and dramatic presentation. Section 5, finally,
contains some observations on how Thrasymachus definitions of
justice interrelate and how they are to be interpreted.
2. After the vivid introduction of Thrasymachus as a persona (336b337a, on which see section ( 4) and after some initial quarrelings
between Thrasymachus and Socrates about method (337a-338c),
the discussion gets started with Thrasymachus' claim (put forward
with characteristic self-consciousness: CJ.')..J..a d oiHc E1t<XtVEtc;) that
justice is 'the advantage of the stronger' ('to wu KpEt't'tovoc; [... ]
OUJ.lq>Epov, 338c). Of course put like this the claim lacks philosophical precision. Hence the Socratic method is applied in order to get
things straight. It turns out that Thrasymachus is not speaking of
corporeal strength, and that by 'the stronger' he means the person
or persons in power ('tO 'ttlc; K<X9EO'tT\1CUtac; apx.ilc; OUJ.lq>Epov, 339al) . 12
In others words, in the context in which he launches this first
definition he is primarily thinking of justice in the political sphere,
of justice in the state.
see also Stokes ( 1986), where, however, the Rep. is not discussed; Muller
(1981) represents a similar approach, but pays little attention to the Thrasymachus episode.
12 Note, first, that the phrase -ro -rl\c; Ka8E1Hl]K'Iliac; &pxl\c; OUJ.upepov clearly
figures as a further specification of the first definition ('the advantage of the
stronger'). as may be inferred from what immediately follows: autl] OE ltOU
KpU'tEl, OOO'tE ou~~aivn -rep 6p8&c; A.oyt~O~Evcp ltavtaxou dvat to auto OiKatOV, tO tOU
KpEi ttovoc; OUJ.HpEpov, 339a2-4). It does not involve any shift of position on
Thrasymachus' part. Secondly Thrasymachus makes it quite clear that he
regards it as an empirical fact that rulers legislate in their own interest
(338e1-2: -ri8Etat OE YE toile; v6~ouc; EKtXOtl];, cXPXft ltpO<; to autfl OU~<pepov). It follows
that, when at 339b7 he assents to Socrates' suggestion that justice is 'obeying
the rulers' (1tEi8eo8at [ ... ] to'ic; iipxouotv) he takes it to be implied all the way
along that these rulers as a matter of course serve their own interest.
Accordingly, pace Maguire (1971) 143, we cannot read 339b7 as containing a
new and independent definition of justice. Thirdly, the notion of to au~<pepov
is prominent right from the beginning of Thrasymachus' account; this
means that the label 'conventionalism' is not very suitable to describe this
position, pace Annas (1981) 40. What may count as justice is never a matter of
mere convention.
45
Socrates now points to the possibility of the rulers being mistaken as to their own interests. Thrasymachus rejects the suggestion of Cleitophon that he can dodge this objection by specifying
that justice consists in whatever the rulers (rightly or wrongly)
think to be in their own interest. Instead he boldly claims that the
rulers qua rulers-i.e. qua possessing their specific skill ('tEXVll)are never mistaken. Interestingly, Socrates does not challenge this
claim as such. He rather takes advantage of the fact that Thrasymachus is willing to speak of the ruler's job as a 'tEXVll, and of a ruler
'in the strict sense', and of the fact that he is prepared to compare
the ruler's art to the art of, say, a doctor. Socrates does so, however,
by shifting the ground. He retorts that anyone exercising a 'tEXVll in
the strict sense is not acting in his own interest. By way of an
elenctic procedure which Thrasymachus is unable to withstand,
he concludes (342e6-ll) that the ruler, qua ruler, will always be
guided by the interests of his subjects. This conclusion is presented
as a reversal of Thrasymachus' own account (o 'tOU Otlcatou /..6yor;
Eir; 'touvav't{ov 1tEptEtO"'tTJKEt, 343a2), which it obviously is to the
extent that the rulers are now said to decree whatever they decree
in the interest not of themselves but of others, viz. their subjects.
However, instead of going along with this conclusion Thrasymachus accuses Socrates of naivete (he doesn't 'know about sheep
and shepherd', 343a8). It is now his turn to shift the focus from the
political level to the level of individual human beings who, he
suggests, are not as Socrates pictures them. And he vigorously
restates his own position in what I shall henceforth refer to as his
'speech' (343bl-344dl). As his primary definition he now proposes
that justice is 'what is good for someone else' ( a'A/..6'tpwv aya06v,
343c2) in the sense that it is contrary to the subjects' own interests.
He contrasts a number of examples of just and unjust behaviour to
show that the unjust, if successful, always gain the advantage, and
repeats that justice is the advantage of the stronger, whereas
injustice is 'one's own profit and advantage' (344c8).
Socrates replies with a series of questions (345b7-347el) designed
to show that the example on which Thrasymachus has based his
case-a shepherd tending his flock in his own interest-was
wrong, because the shepherd (qua shepherd) turns out to act in the
interest of his flock. In general, he argues, this goes for every
'tEXVll, including governing according to the rules (Ka'A&r; 'tTl 'tEXVU,
347al), which is why good rulers are so difficult to get. In fact they
46
KEIMPE ALGRA
47
48
KEIMPE ALGRA
49
50
KEIMPE ALGRA
Cf. Glaucon's words at 357a5: ltOtEpov iJJlCx~ ~OUAEl 001CelV ltEltEllcEVat f\ ro~
UAT]9&~ ltEt<Jill Otllt!lvtl tpomp aJlElVOV eatt oiK:awv dvat f\ aOtKOV. And 358b2-6:
20
E>pacrUJlllXO~ yap
JlOl <patVEtat 1tpcpahepov tOU oeovto~ U1t0 crou WcrltEp O<pl~ KT]AT]Si\vat,
EJlOl o oUltCO Katc'x vouv f] U1t00El~l~ yeyovev ltEpt EK!ltEpoU.
21 Gigon (1976) 82-83.
51
EXElV
52
KEIMPE ALGRA
53
If we now return to Rep. I, we may note that in a number of respects the dramatic picture which Plato draws of Thrasymachus is
reminiscent of other scenes in Platonic dialogues which feature sophists. This goes for Thrasymachus' criticisms of and impatience
with Socrates' dialectical procedure,26 for the way in which Socrates' rational elenchus is opposed to the much more self-assertive
form of reasoning which is typical of the rhetorical practice of the
sophists, i.e. the set speech, 27 for Thrasymachus' scoffing approach,
especially the way he laughs at Socrates,2 8 and for his sullen and
insincere resignation at the end of the conversation of Rep I. 29 But
there is more to it than just the familiar opposition between Socratic
philosophy and sophistical rhetoric. Plato's portrayal of Thrasymachus contains a number of interesting traits which, I believe,
are meant to present this persona as in some respects being himself
an exemplum of the philosophical position he is made to defend.
At 336b-338b Plato starts out with a vivid sketch of Thrasymachus' behaviour during the conversation between Socrates and
Polemarchus, and of the way he interrupts the conversation. He is
pictured as a man who is conspicuously lacking in self-restraint:
he is only prevented from intruding into the conversation between
Socrates and Polemarchus by the others (u1to 'tO>V 1tapaKa8TJJ..lEVrov
OtEKCOA:UE'to) and as soon as he gets the chance he leaps in like a
wild animal, ready to tear his opponents apart ( W<mEp 8TJplOV ... W<;
Otap1taooJ..lEVo<;, 336b2-3). Socrates indirectly compares him to a wolf
in 336 d6-7 ('if I had not seen him before he saw me, I really
believe I should have been struck dumb'), 30 and to a lion in 34lcl
Maior (suggesting, among other things, that Hippias exemplifies a certain
outlook on the theme of the kalon); for a different literary analysis of the
same work, see Ludlam (1991). A most valuable guide in these matters is now
Rutherford (1995).
2 6 Cf. Critias in the Charmides, esp. 165e, and the indignant outbursts of
Polus and Callicles in the Gorgias: 467b10; 473a1, 480e (Polus); and 490d1;
491al; 494 e7; 497b6 (Callicles).
27 Cf. Gorg. 4491>-c; see also Prt. 334c-335a. See also Nicholson (1974) 230.
Thrasymachus himself delivers a kind of set speach of considerable length,
pooring out a flood of words over his company (344d: romtEp paA.aveuc; TtllOOV
KamvtA.ftaac; Kat tiilv ciltrov b.Spoov Kat noA.uv tov Alryov), after which he has to be
prevented by the others from leaving the stage right away.
2B Cf. Polus in the Gorgias. On this 'rhetorical' use of laughter, see
Rutherford (1995) 155; De Vries (1985) 378-381.
29 Cf. the way Callicles is made to behave at the end of his exchange with
Socrates in the Gorgias (esp. 510a1; 513e1; 516b).
30 On this reference to an element of popular superstition, see Adam
(1969) 1. 24.
54
KEIMPE ALGRA
('do you think me foolish enough to beard a lion and to try to outwit Thrasymachus?'). I believe these descriptions and comparisons
are there on purpose. Later on in the Republic the tyrant, after all
Thrasymachus' ideal example of unbridled pleonexia, is compared
to a wolf (565d-566a), and in general Plato is wont to use the
irrational ferocity of animals as a metaphor for the irrational parts
of the soul (the appetitive element drags us romtp SrJpiov (439b4) ,31
the tripartite soul is depicted as a triad of man, lion and manyheaded beast (588b-59la). 3 2 And like Thrasymachus, the raging
bestial tendencies of the lower part of the soul also have to be kept
in check from outside (i.e. by the rational part).33 Thrasymachus,
in other words is depicted as himself being in some ways the
embodiment of the unlimited pleonexia (as against rational
moderation) which he is made to defend.
This general characterization is further supported by what
Thrasymachus is actually made to say. He attacks Socrates for
merely asking questions in his customary way instead of coming
up himself with anything like a detailed account of justice-i.e. for
being not as self-assertive as Thrasymachus himself is-and
makes clear that he regards Socrates and Polemarchus as a couple
of wets who are only too ready to give way to each other (336c: 'tt
E'l>11Hism8 7tpo<; aA.A.fJA.ou<; u7toKa'taKAtVoi1Vot il11'iv au'tO'i<;;). 34 He
proceeds to set the rules for the conversation which is to follow:
Socrates should know that a number of potential definitions of
justice are not allowed (336c6: Kat o1tro<; 110111il Ep'i<; on 'tO 8ov EG'ttV
11118, O'tl 'tO roq>EA1110V 11118, O'tl 'tO AU(J1 'tAOUV 11118, O'tl 'tO Kp8aAov
11118' on 'tO cru11cppov). Socrates' reaction in its turn reinforces the
reader's impression of Thrasymachus as an aggressive character
(336b6: f::yw 't Kat 6 IIoA.11apxo<; 8dcrav't<; 8t7t'tofJ81111V, 336d5: f.yro
aKoucra<; f.~mAaYllv Kat 7tpocr~AE7tOlV au'tov Eq>O~OU1111V, and 336e2,
with what may be a pun on Thrasymachus' name: "Q 8pacru11ax,
3 1 See also 430b8, 535e4, 571c5. At 4llel people whose mind has not been
proferly cultivated by education are also said to be CO<J7tEp !hJptOV.
3
One may also compare the description of the common people, the demos
with their irrational desires, as 'the great beast' (Rep. 493b-c), and the lionlike strong men of which Callicles speaks in Gorg. 483e. See on this Rutherford (1995) 161, who provides an excellent discussion of the animal metaphors.
33 For the use of KroA.unv in this connection, see 439c6-9; and 589b3 (tO. o
&ypux a7toKroA.urov <pumem).
34 For the meaning of Eul](lil;ecree and imoKa.ta.KAtvOJlEVot see Adam (1969) 1.
23 and 24.
55
56
KEIMPE ALGRA
57
on
58
KEIMPE ALGRA
59
the struggle for power resulting from what we might call Thrasymachus' implicit anthropology of pleonexia, 49 can do what they
want. This is why Thrasymachus ends his speech by claiming
that injustice is not only stronger and more powerful than justice,
but also more indicative of freedom (H.eu8eptro'tepov). Justice,
apparently, is a matter of compulsory self-restriction, a matter of
limits and bonds. The really strong and powerful, with the tyrant
as the most shining example, are free of such bonds. For them
justice does not exist. 5o
6. We may summarize our findings as follows. The general
picture which emerges from our analysis is that of Thrasymachus
putting forward, apparently on empirical grounds, the case for
pleonexia. This position foreshadows Plato's vivid sketch of the
quasi-freedom of the tyrant, whose passions rule in complete
lawlessness (EV
avapxig. Kat aVOJ.Ltg., 575al). It thus serves as a
counterpoint to Plato's own insistence in his moral psychology on
limit and moderation, elements which in the last analysis, and in
ways which need not concern us here, appear to be connected to
his metaphysical conception of the Good. 51 The overall dramatic
characterization of Thrasymachus as a persona confirms this
picture by presenting him as animal-like, aggressive and incontinent, in short as in some respects an embodiment of the position he
is made to defend. It appears that Thrasymachus' two definitions of
justice belong together and are both connected with his general
anthropology: justice sets limits to one's tendency towards pleonexia, and one only lets this happen if one has to. Consequently for
the really strong justice does not exist. 52
1tacrn
Utrecht
Schwache dagegen hat die Aussicht, den Starken bei ihm behaften zu
konnen'.
49 This anthropology is made explicit, however, in Glaucon's paraphrase
in book II, 359c4: ou'x Ti]v ltAeOVE~iav' 0 Jtacra lj)UO"tc; OunKEtV ltEij)UKEV roc; tiya86v.
50 We may recall that according to Thrasymachus the ruler 'in the strict
sense' makes no mistakes, i.e. he is always successful in ruthlessly pursuing
his own interests. Note the way this feature is underlined by Plato's use of the
vocabulary of power and success (tov ueyal..a Ouvauevov JtAeOVEKtE'iv, 344al; tiOtKia
tKav&c; ywvouevn, 344c5-6; Ouvacrew o aOtKElV 1\ tcp A.avSavEtv 1\ tcp OtauaxecrSat,
345a5; Ot 'YE 'tEAEwc; [... ) oto{ 'tE aOtKElV, 348d5).
51 On which see especially Rep. 500c.
52 I would like to thank David Runia and Teun Tieleman for their
comments on an earlier draft of this article.
60
KEIMPE ALGRA
References:
Adam, J. (1969) The Republic of Plato: edited with Critical Notes, Commentary
and Appendices by James Adam; second edition with an Introduction by
D. A. Rees, 2 vols. (Cambridge).
Adkins, A. W. H. (1972) Moral Values and Political Behaviour in Ancient Greece
(London).
Annas, J. (1981) An Introduction to Plato's Republic (Oxford).
Arnim, J. von (1914) Platons ]ugenddialoge und die Entstehungszeit des 'Phaidros'
(Leipzig).
--(1927) Platons Dialog 'Thrasymachos', Mededeelingen der Koninklijke Akademie van Wetenschappen, afdeeling letterkunde deel63 (Amsterdam), 201-232.
Classen, C. J. (ed.) (1976) Sophistik (Darmstadt).
Cross, R. C. I Woozley, A. D. (1964) Plato's Republic; A Philosophical
Commentary (London).
Friedlander (1964) Platon, 2 vols., 3. Auflage (Berlin).
Gigon, 0. (1976) Gegenwiirtigkeit und Utopie; eine Interpretation von Platons
'Staat'; Erster Band: Buch I-IV (Ztirich/Mtinchen).
Guthrie, W. K. C. (1975) A Histury of Greek Philosophy, 6 vols. (Cambridge).
Hoerber, R. G. (1945) 'Character Portrayal in Plato's Lysis', The Classical
]oumal41, 271-273.
Kahn, C. H. (1983) 'Drama and Dialectic in Plato's Gorgias', Oxford Studies in
Ancient Philosophy, 1: 75-121.
- - (1993) 'Proleptic Composition in the Republic, or Why Book 1 was never a
separate dialogu~. The Classical Quarterly 43: 131-142.
Kerferd, G. B. (1981) The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge).
- - (1947) 'The Doctrine of Thrasymachus in Plato's Republic', Durham
University ]oumal40; repr. in Classen (1976) 545-563.
Lebeck, A. (1971) The Oresteia: a Study in Language and Structure (Washington
DC).
KOMPSOI ASKLEPIADES:
LA CRITICA DI PLATONE ALLA MEDICINA
NEL III LIBRO DELLA REPUBBUCA
MARIO VEGETTI
Jaap Mansfeld ha sostenuto a piu riprese (cfr. nota 17) che il metodo
di Ippocrate cui Platone si riferisce nel celebre passo di Phaedr.
270c-d trova in Arie acque luoghi il suo testo principale di riferimento. Un'analisi della violenta critica che Platone rivolge nel
libro III della Repubblica alia medicina dietetica contemporanea
non puo portare conferme o smentite dirette a questa tesi, e quindi
contribuire alia soluzione della vexatissima 'questione ippocratica'.
La polemica platonica costituisce tuttavia un documento significativo degli sviluppi della medicina nel IV secolo, e della loro
valutazione nell'ambito della discussione etica e politica. Da questo
punto di vista, qualche indicazione sia pure indiretta su quella
questione puo venir ricavata dalla Repubblica: si tratta, da un lato, del
rilevante impiego platonico del linguaggio diagnostico e psicoetnologico di Arie acque luoghi, dall'altro del principale bersaglio
della polemica del libro III, che, attraverso Erodico, sembra colpire
soprattutto il Regime. Di questi dati andni forse tenuto conto nell'interpretazione della 'testimonianza' del Fedro, e sembra plausibile
pensare che essi possano almeno marginalmente confortare Ia
lettura propostane da Mansfeld.
1. II passaggio dalla prima citta (definita <<Sana, uytfl~. 372e7)'
alia seconda, che <<vive nel lusso>>, le ragioni e le forme della
patologia che affiigge quest'ultima, infine le vie possibili per il suo
risanamento, vengono discussi facendo largamente ricorso aile
categorie diagnostiche e terapeutiche proprie della medicina dietetica del V e IV secolo.
La polis lussuosa soffre di gonfiore da infiammazione (q>AqJl<ltvoucra, 372e8). Non si tratta soltanto dell'impiego metaforico di
termini medici in ambito morale, che e consueto in Platone.
L' eziologia di questa malattia endemica e indicata da Platone nella
cattiva dieta e nella corrispondente mancanza di esercizi (apyia Kat
Otat'ta, 405d); quanto al primo aspetto, si tratta soprattutto della dieta
62
MARIO VEGETTI
63
lCO.t 'tO 'tO.Aat1tropov lCO.t 'tO EJl1tOVOV lCO.t 'tO 9uJlOEt0E<; OUlC av ouvat'tO ev
'tota.U't'[l cpucrn eyyivecr9at).
64
MARIO VEGETTI
Essi sono inoltre pili miti (TtJlEpron:pot) degli Europei, perche non
esposti alle metabolai e alle conseguenti ekplexeis che inselvatichiscono il carattere, eccitano lo thymoeides, tengono desta la mente come accade appunto peri popoli d'Europa (16: 't11v oprf1v ayptoucr8ai 'tE
Kat 'tOU ayvcOJlOVoc; Kat 8UJlOEtOeoc; JlE'tEXEtV (... ] ai. yap JlE'ta~oA.a{ Eicrt
't&v 7tUV't<OV ai. E7tEydpoucrat 'tltV yYcOJlllV). La frequenza e la violenza
dei mutamenti rende al contrario questi uomini selvatici, impulsivi, coraggiosi, disposti agli sforzi (23: 'tO 'tE &yptov Kat 'tO UJlEtK'tOV
Kat 'tO SuJlOEtOec; v 'tOtaU't!l q>UO"Et yyivE'tat [... ] a1to 'tllc; 'taA.amcopillc;
Kat 'tiDV 1tOV<OV ai. avOpEtat), duri, tonici, insonni, indipendenti di
giudizio, acuti nell' esercizio delle tecniche, migliori combattenti
(24: crKATlpouc; 'tE Kat icrxvouc; [... ] Kat ev'tovouc; [... ]. 'tO 'tE pyanKov
EVEOV v 'tft q>UO"Et 'tft 'totaU't'{l Kat 'tO &ypu1tVov [... ] Kat iowyvroJlovac;,
'tOU 'tE aypiou JlUAAov JlE'tEXOV'tac; f\ 'tOU TtJlEpou, ec; 'tE 'tac; 'texvac;
o~u'tepouc; 'tE Kat O"UVE'tco'tepouc; Kat 'tCx 7tOAEJlta aJlEtvouc; EupftcrEtc;).
Esattamente il quadro dei caratteri, dunque, che Platone richiede
ai suoi <<atleti della guerra>>, preoccupandosi per altro di temperarne l'asprezza <<europea>> con il ricorso all'addolcimento che puo
venire da una buona educazione musicale.
La diagnosi della patologia sociale tracciata nei libri II e III della
Repubblica, la sua eziologia, Ia sua terapia, sembrano cosi largamente ispirate ai testi della medicina dietetica; in particolare, il
rapporto fra il linguaggio psicologico di Platone con quello di Arie
acque luoghi e cosi stretto da rendere improbabile l'ipotesi di una
coincidenza casuale.3 Abbiamo qui, come altrove, un Platone
attento lettore dei testi di medicina, e pronto a fruire della loro concettualizzazione metodica tanto come riferimento metaforico
quanto come strumento analitico.
2. Tanto pili sorprendente risulta il violento attacco alla medicina
contemporanea a base dietetica che Platone Iancia a partire da 405a.
11 punto di partenza e il nesso che viene stabilito fra patologia
sociale e sviluppo della medicina4 (parallelo a quello, in ambito
3 Si puo inoltre rilevare un'eco della critica ai sacrifici di A.A.L. 22 nel
discorso di Adimanto (II 365e sgg.).
4 Puo essere interessante notare che Ia denuncia di Platone non e soltanto
basata su di un'indignazione moralistica. C'e stato in effetti nel IV secolo un
peggioramento della salute pubblica in Grecia dovuto all'abbandono dell'agricoltura, con il conseguente mancato drenaggio delle paludi, e alia sovrappopolazione urbana. Ne consegui un aumento delle malattie malariche, delle
gastro-enteriti, del tifo e della tubercolosi. L'eta media al momento della
65
66
MARIO VEGETTI
67
68
MARIO VEGETTI
69
&vayJCal.ov pya~Ea8at). 11 nuovo regime e invece messo a disposizione dei ricchi, i quali so no piu attenti alla salute (3.69): esattamente, dunque, quello stravolgimento di interesse, dal bene pubblico alia salute privata, che Platone condanna nella medicina
dietetica. E proprio in questo modo che essa si trasforma, da
sintomo ed effetto, in concausa della malattia sociale.
3. L'eroe negativo di questa metamorfosi della nuova medicina,
appropriata alia polis tryphosa, e individuato da Platone nella figura
di Erodico di Selimbria. 12 Erodico era stato accusato nel Protagora,
come si e visto, di essere un sofista travestito>> e potente; nel Fedro
(227d), Platone ironizzava sulle lunghe e faticose passeggiate cui
Erodico sottoponeva se stesso e presumibilmente i suoi pazienti (un
eccesso di esercizi per cui evidentemente era famoso e anche
aspramente criticato da altri medici) . 13 Tutto cio dipendeva probabilmente dalla sua teoria secondo Ia quale era necessaria riportare
il rapporto fra alimentazione ed esercizi al suo equilibria naturale
(Anon. Lond. 9.20 sgg.).
Nella Repubblica, Erodico viene accusato di aver fatto deviare Ia
medicina dalla sua efficace tradizione terapeutica trasformandola
in un controllo minuzioso e ossessivo del regime di vita dei malati.
Fattosi medico dopo esser stato maestro di ginnastica (1tatOo-rpi~rt~),
egli ha mescolato>> e confuso la ginnastica con la medicina
( 406a-b): si allude evidentemente alia cura degli esercizi fisici
raccomandata da Erodico. Ha praticato con rigore ossessivo il
rispetto della dieta consueta e prescritta ( 406b), di lunghissima
durata ( 406d). In questo modo, ha trasformato Ia medicina da
terapia in <<pedagogia delle malattie>> ( 406a), 14 in una voao-rpO<pia
12 Le testimonianze su Erodico sono raccolte in H. Grensemann, Knidische
Medizin. Teil I (Berlin-New York 1975) 15 sgg. Cfr. ora A. Jori, "Platone e Ia
svolta dietetica della medicina greca. Erodico di Selimbria e le insidie della
techne", Studi italiani di filologia classica 11 (1993) 157-95, che propone una
cronologia di Erodico fra il 460-50 e il 380.
13 Cfr. Epidemie 6.3.18. Probabilmente a causa della polemica di Platone,
Erodico era gia diventato proverbiale a! tempo della Retorica di Aristotele (1.5
136lb 4-6: molti sono sani nel senso in cui si dice sano Erodico; nessuno
invidierebbe Ia !oro salute, perche devono astenersi da tutte le soddisfazioni
umane o dalla maggior parte di esse).
14 Nel Timeo, a! contrario, Platone avrebbe raccomandato di Jto:too:yroynv
omito:u; le malattie croniche, invece di irritarle con farmaci, nei limiti di
tutta Ia crxoA.{J disponibile (89c-d): un ritorno 'erodiceo', dunque, da annoverarsi fra le molte tensioni nel pensiero platonico determinate dalla polemica di Repubblica.
70
MARIO VEGETTI
( 407b), che prolungano un' esistenza malaticcia distogliendo I' attenzione e le energie dei cittadini dalla vita sociale per concentrarle in
modo morboso-noi diremmo ipocondriaco-sulle condizioni di
salute e le loro minime variazioni quotidiane.
Va detto che molte delle accuse platoniche colpiscono l'intera
medicina dietetica, compresa quella di ispirazione 'ippocratica', e
non soltanto la figura di Erodico. La continuita fra ginnastica e
medicina era per esempio stata fortemente sottolineata in Antica
medicina (3, 4, 7), e del resto condivisa da Platone (Crito 47b; Gorg.
464b; una contrapposizione tra le due arti, forse proprio in polemica
contra Erodico, era stata pen) stabilita in L.H. 35). I pericoli derivanti
da un mutamento della dieta consueta erano stati enfatizzati nella
stessa opera (10-11), e confermati in Regime delle malattie acute (26).
Perche dunque Platone ha deciso di fare di Erodico il suo principale bersaglio polemico, il capofila emblematico della generazione degli Asclepiadi che li rende complici dei vizi della citta del
lusso?
Una risposta puo forse venire proprio dagli altri due dialoghi in
cui il medico di Selimbria e citato esplicitamente.
Nel Protagora, all'attacco contra Erodico sofista corrisponde la
menzione di Ippocrate di Cos come maestro per antonomasia di
medicina, al pari di Policleto e Fidia per la scultura (3llb-c). II
Fedro, che si apre con !'ironia su Erodico, culmina nel celebre
elogio del metoda di Ippocrate, cui si deve ispirare Ia riforma
dialettica della retorica (270b-c).
Erodico sembra dunque configurarsi come l'anti-lppocrate: concentrare sui suo nome l'aggressione polemica poteva significare
per Platone mettere al riparo da essa Ia medicina ippocratica, che,
nonostante le sue ovvie tendenze dietetiche, manteneva ai suoi
occhi un rilevante val ore metodologico ( e anche, stan do al primo
libro della Repubblica, deontologico).
Del resto, piu specificamente, se e vero-come qui si e cercato di
dimostrare-che Platone individuava gli eccessi degenerativi e
socialmente pericolosi della medicina dietetica in opere come il
Regime, puo darsi che egli fosse al corrente di quello stretto rapporto
fra quest'opera e il pensiero di Erodico, che e stato a piu riprese
ipotizzato dai moderni.I5
15 Un rapporto fra Erodico e il Regime era stato sostenuto gia da C.
Fredrich, "Hippokratische Untersuchungen", Philol. Untersuchungen 15 (Berlin
1899) e in seguito riproposto da K. Deichgraber, "Die Epidemien und das
71
72
MARIO VEGETTI
zione professionale dei moderni Asclepiadi. Se essi non si dedicavano aile raffinatezze dietetiche proprie di questi ultimi, era perch:
avevano ben chiari i compiti sociali e collettivi della loro arte, non
certo per <<l'ignoranza e l'inesperienza>> che i sofisticati medici
moderni attribuiscono ai Ioro predecessori tradizionali ( 406c: e
forse possibile scorgere in queste parole una confutazione polemica
di Male sacro 1-2, che appunto attribuiva a1tupia e ignoranza ai
guaritori ciarlatani legati alia superstizione religiosa).
Ma il richiamo ad Asclepio e ai suoi figli e evidentemente solo
polemico ed ironico. Lo sottolineano due pungenti battute di Glaucone: <<davvero raffinati (KOJ.HJfOt) li descrivi, i figli di Asclepio>>
( 408b); e <<Un politico (7tOAtttJCOV) ne fai di Asclepio>> (407e).
AI contrario, Platone appare molto serio, e perfettamente informato, quando prescrive i requisiti per Ia medicina adatta alia citta
purificata.
(a) Essa deve trattare solo malattie ben circoscritte (v6or11.1.a
a1tOKEKptJ.1.EVov, 407d). Qui Platone si oppone alia tendenza della
medicina moderna, inclusa quella ippocratica, a farsi carico
dell'intero organismo malato, e, al limite, dell'intera esistenza del
paziente, a scopo sia terapeutico sia profilattico. Una tendenza, del
resto, che egli aveva condiviso e approvato. Secondo il Carmide
(156b-c), i <<buoni medici>> (aya8o1. ia1:poi, qui sicuramente gli
'ippocratici'), se si rivolge Ioro uno che ha una malattia agli occhi,
<<gli dicono che non si puo cominciare a curare solo gli occhi, rna
che bisognerebbe curare anche Ia testa se si vuole guarire gli occhi;
e dicono ancora che e un'assurdita pensare di curare Ia testa per se
stessa senza tenere conto dell'intero corpo. Cosi [ ... ] cercano di curare e guarire Ia parte applicando un regime all'intero corpo>>
( otai'tat E7tt 1tiiv 1:0 o&J.I.a). Ma i buoni (e ippocratici) medici del
Carmide, bench: esemplari metodicamente, non sono socialmente
utili nella citta sana>> della Repubblica.
(b) II trattamento di queste malattie locali deve essere rapido e
immediatamente efficace: esso non impieghera dunque diete rna
solo farmaci catartici, cauterizzazioni e incisioni chirurgiche
( 406d). Questa triade e naturalmente canonica, rna anche qui Platone corregge gli ippocratici e se stesso. Arie acque luoghi, per esempio,
aveva sottolineato Ia necessita di astenersi dal somministrare
cpapJ.I.aKov, 'taJ.I.VEtv e JCaiuv durante i mutamenti di stagione (11). E
anche Platone nel Protagora (354a) aveva indicato come rimedi
standard della medicina cpapJ.I.aKov, JCauot<; e 'toJ.I.ft, aggiungendovi
73
tuttavia anche le restrizioni dietetiche (AtJ..LOK'tovia), che qui vengono omesse in polemica contro Ia medicina dietetica e probabilmente come inutili in una polis dove il regime alimentare e gia
politicamente controllato.
(c) La medicina inoltre dovra rifiutarsi di trattare quanti siano di
costituzione malferma e incapaci percio di rendersi socialmente
utili, lasciandoli morire>>, proprio come i giudici dovranno mandare a morte coloro che siano incurabili nell'anima (410a).
II punto di vista di Platone e qui perfettamente chiaro. L'esistenza
individuale non ha alcun valore se non in funzione della sua
utilita sociale; sopravvivere senza essere in grado di contribuire al
benessere comune non ha alcun senso ne personale ne pubblico.
Questo punto di vista non ha naturalmente paralleli nella deontologia medica, anche se vi compare a volte (cfr. peres. p. technes 3) il
rifiuto di affrontare Ia terapia degli incurabili, dovuto soprattutto alia
preoccupazione che la loro morte possa venir addebitata al medico
invece che alia malattia. E qui il caso di accennare che il parallelo
platonico fra medicina e giustizia, 18 con I' obbligo per Ia seconda di
mandare a morte chi sia moralmente irricuperabile, e per Ia prima
di lasciar morire gli invalidi permanenti, era destinato ad inaugurare una lunga tradizione di pensiero tanto etico quanto medico.
Essa sarebbe culminata, con Galeno (Quod animi 11, K 4.815-6}, in
un singolare rovesciamento. 19 Poiche le devianze morali sono
secondo Galeno determinate da malformazioni organiche, spetta al
medico-che si appropria cosi anche della funzione del giudice
platonico-di diagnosticare chi sia incurabile nel corpo e (dunque)
anche nell'anima e di decretare Ia condanna a morte di coloro che
risultano tanto <<irrimediabilmente malvagi>> da non poter essere
rieducati dalle Muse stesse ne migliorati da Socrate o da Pitagora
(e neppure, s'intende, curati dallo stesso Galeno). In Platone, c'e
ancora parallelismo, e non convergenza, fra sentenza di giustizia e
diagnosi medica, anche se, come si e visto, la patologia morale influenza quella organica e viceversa. La nuova medicina, frutto di
una purificazione della citta, contribuira comunque a sua volta a
74
MARIO VEGETTI
75
Von allen Fragen, die der Platonische ''Timaios" aufWirft, ist iiber
keine so viel diskutiert und gestritten worden wie iiber die hier
gestellte. Das gilt fiir die lateinische und griechische Antike, aus
der uns zu diesem Problem mehr AuBerungen erhalten sind als
zu allen anderen 1 Das gilt in ahnlicher Weise fiir das lateinische,
griechische und arabische Mittelalter2, die beginnende Neuzeit
und die neueste Zeit. Wie schon in der Antike, so zeichnet sich
auch unter den heutigen Interpreten kein Konsens ab: Die einen
sind nach wie vor der Meinung, Platon lehre im "Timaios", die
Welt sei zeitlich oder, wenn schon nicht zeitlich, so doch wenigstens in einem einmaligen Schopfungsakt entstanden, wahrend
die Gegenseite ebenso beharrlich die Auffassung vertritt, der
Schopfungsakt, von dem der "Timaios" spricht, sei nur ein bildlicher Ausdruck fiir ein immerwahrendes Schopfungs-Geschehen, fiir eine creatio continua oder perpetua: die Darstellung entfalte
das, was sich im Kosmos immerfort gleichzeitig abspiele, in
einem zeitlichen Nacheinander, urn auf diese Weise die innere
Struktur des Kosmos und der Vorgange in ihm einsichtig zu
machen3. Beide Seiten konnen sich dabei nicht nur auf Passagen
1 Vgl. M. Baltes, Die Weltentstehung des Platonischen Timaios nach den antiken
Interpreten 1-11 (Lei den 1976-78); H. Dorrie - M. Baltes, Der Platonismus in der
Antike III (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstadt 1993) 296 ff.
2 C. Baeumker, "Die Ewigkeit der Welt bei Plato", Philosophische Monatshefte 23 (1887) 514 ff; M.-D. Chenu, "Die Platonismen des XII. Jahrhunderts",
in Platonismus in der Philosophie des Mittelalters, hgg. von W. Beierwaltes
(Darmstadt 1969) 274 ff. 287; M. Fakhry, "A Tenth-century Arabic Interpretation of Plato's Cosmology", journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (1968) 15 ff =
Philosophy, Dogma and the Impact of Greek Thought in Islam (Brookfield, Aldershot
1994) VI 15 ff; F. van Steenberghen, "La controverse sur l'eternite du monde
au Xllle siecle", L 'Academie Royale de Belgique. Bulletin de la Classe des Lettres et
des Sciences Morales et Politiques, 5e serie, 58 (1972) 267 ff; H. Simon, "Weltschopfung und Weltewigkeit in der jiidischen Tradition", Kairos 14 (1972) 31
ff; R. Sorabji, Time, Creation and the Continuum (London 1983) passim; ders.,
Matter, Space and Motion (London 1988) 259 ff; Dorrie-Baltes III 298 mit
Anm.4.
3 Die Hauptvertreter der heiden Richtungen werden vorgestellt bei W.
Scheffel, Aspekte der platonischen Kosmologie (Leiden 1976) XI ff und R. Hackforth, "Plato's Cosmogony (Timaeus 27 D ft)", Class. Quart. N.S. 9 (1959) 17; die
77
des 'Timaios" selbst berufen, sondern auch auf Stellen aus anderen Platonischen Dialogen; vor allem der "Staat", der "Politikos",
der "Philebos", der "Kritias" und die "Nomoi" spielen in dieser
Diskussion eine groBe Rolle 4 Beide Seiten ziehen fiir ihre unterschiedlichen Ansichten zudem die unmittelbaren Platonschiiler
heran, Aristoteles einerseits und Speusipp, Xenokrates und Herakleides Pontikos andererseits 5 Schon in der Schute Platons, der
Akademie, war man sich also offenbar nicht einig dariiber, wie
der Schopfungsbericht im 'Timaios" zu verstehen sei. Wenn nun
aber schon Platons direkte Schuler in dieser Frage uneins waren,
wie sollen wir da in der Lage sein, die Sache zu entscheiden?! Die
Situation scheint vollig verfahren, das Ratsel unlosbar zu sein.
Bei unserem Versuch, das Ratsel zu losen, wollen wir uns ausschlieBlich auf den "Timaios" konzentrieren und zunachst seinen
Aufbau, genauer den Aufbau der Rede des Timaios im "Timaios"
betrachten. Unter dem Gesichtspunkt einer zeitlichen oder einmaligen Schopfung ist dieser Aufbau geradezu chaotisch. Denn
alteren Vertreter werden genannt bei E. Zeller, Die Philosophic der Griechen in
ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung II 1 (Leipzig 19225, Nachdr. Darmstadt 1963)
792, Anm.1; G. Vlastos, "The Disorderly Motion in the Timaeus" (1939), in
Studies in Plato's Metaphysics, ed. R.E. Allen (London 1965) 379 und H.
Cherniss, f..ristotle's Criticism of Plato and the Academy (Baltimore 1944) 424,
Anm.357. Uber die dort Genannten hinaus treten heute ein
- fiir die nichtzeitliche Auffassung der Weltentstehung im "Timaios": M.
Landmann, Ursprungsbild und Schopfertat (Miinchen 1966) 162 ff; E. Ostenfeld,
"Disorderly Motion in the Timaeus", Classica et Mediaevalia 29 (1968) 22 ff; L.
Taran, "The Creation Myth in Plato's Timaeus", in Essays in Ancient Philosophy,
ed. J.P. Anton and G.L. Kustas (State University of New York Press, Albany
1972) 372 ff; L. Brisson, Le meme et l'autr:e dans la structure ontologique du Timee de
Platon (Paris 1974) 82 f; K. Alt, "Die Uberredung der Ananke zur Erklarung
der sichtbaren Welt in Platons Timaios", Hermes 106 (1978) 460 f;
- fiir die zeitliche Auffassung: F. Solmsen, Aristotle's System of the Physical
World (Ithaca, New York 1962) 51; G. Vlastos, "Creation in the Timaeus: Is it a
Fiction?" (1964), in Studies in Plato's Metaphysics, ed. R.E. Allen (London 1965)
401-419; J. Pepin, Theologie cosmique et theologie chretienne (Ambroise, Exam. I 1,1-4)
(Paris 1964) 85 f; HJ. Easterling, "Causation in the Timaeus and Laws X",
Eranos 65 (1967) 25; T.M. Robinson, Plato's Psychology (Toronto 19952) 64-104,
bes. 68 f; ders., "The Argument of Tim. 27 d ff", Phronesis 24 (1979) 105 ff;
W.K.C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy V (Cambridge 1978) 301 ff;
Sorabji, Matter 248-259. 273-282; ders., Time 272 ff; J. Mansfeld, "Rez. Scheffel, Kosmologie", Mnemosyne 35 (1982) 168 ff; R.D. Mohr, The Platonic Cosmology
(Leiden 1985) 64 ff; G. Naddaf, "The Atlantis Myth: An Introduction to Plato's
Later Philosophy of History", Phoenix 48 (1994) 202; vgl. dens., L'origine et
!'evolution du concept grec de 'phusis' (Lewiston 1992) 391 ff, bes. 413;
- fiir eine unzeitliche, aber reale Weltentstehung: Scheffel, Kosmologie.
4 Vgl. Baltes, Weltentstehung I 210. 216 mit Verweisen (s. auch die Indices
I 237 f) und II 166 f.
5 Zu diesen vgl. Taran, "Creation Myth" 389 f (zu Herakleides speziell
404, Anm.113); Baltes, Weltentstehung I 5 ff. 94 ff.
78
MATTHIAS BALTES
1. Die Situation, bevor der Gott eingreift: in dieser existieren drei Dinge,
das Seiende, der Raum und das Werden (ov, xropa, YEvEcrtc;, 51 D 3).
Die yevEcrtc; bezeichnet den Zustand, in dem die Ideen ( ov) auf den
Raum (xropa) wirken und in ihm Spuren {tXVTl ana, 53 B 2) von
Elementen hervorrufen 6 , die sich zwar noch in vollkommener
Unordnung befinden (52 D 3 - 53 A 8), aber doch auch schon
Andeutungen ihrer kunftigen Eigenschaften besitzen (68 E 1 ff),
beispielsweise Schwere, Dichte (53 A 1 f) und Sichtbarkeit (52 E 1). Da
die avroJlaAia in diesem vorkosmischen Chaos zu einer Schuttelbewegung der Chora fUhrt (52 E 1 ff; vgl. 57 D 7 ff), findet in diesem
Stadium sogar schon eine Art Gruppierung der Spurenelemente statt
(52 E 5 fl) 7. Dies ist der Zustand 1tpo tile; tou oupavou YEVEO"Eroc; (48 B 3 ff;
52 D 4; 53 A 7), in dem die avayKTl herrscht (4 7 E 4 f; 68 E 1. 6 f) und
den der Gott vorfindet, bevor er einschreitet (30 A 2-4; 69 B 2 f. 5 ff).
2. Auf der zweiten Stufe tritt der Gott auf, der in dieses Chaos eingreift
und es ordnet, indem er die Spuren der Elemente durch Gestalt und
Zahl formt ( OtEO"XTlJl!lttO"!ltO etOEO"t tE JC(ll apt6jlotc;, 53 B 4 f). Nun erst
gelangen Ordnung und MaBin das Chaos (53 B 1- 7; 69 B 4 f); denn
nun werden die einzelnen Elemente und auch der Kosmos als ganzer
nach den fUnfPlatonischen Korpern gestaltet (53 B 7-56 C 7). Erst auf
dieser Stufe herrschen die mathematischen Gesetze unter den
Elementen ( 69 B 4 f), erst jetzt gibt es einen Kosmos 8 , in dem die
einzelnen Glieder durch Proportion gebunden sind und in
Freundschaft miteinander Ieben (31 B 4-32 C 4). Dies ist der Zustand,
in dem der vouc; die Herrschaft ubernimmt und die UVU'Y1CT1 uberredet,
so daB diese zum Besseren des Ganzen nachgibt (47 E 5-49 A 5; 56 C
5 f). Von nun an herrschen im Kosmos vouc; und q>pOVTlcrtc; (34 A 2; 39
C 2; 47 B 7; 90 C 7 fl).
3. Wo bleibt nun aber in dieser Abfolge die Weltseele? Nach dem, was
der "Timaios" uber die ersten heiden Stufen lehrt, ist die Weltseele
6 Zu diesem Wirken der Ideen auf d_ie xropa vgl. Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I
387,8 ff; 388,16 ff. 28 ff Diehl; L. Robin, "Etudes sur Ia signification et Ia place
de Ia phyique dans Ia philosophie de Platon", in La pensee hellenique des
origines a Epicure, publ. par P.M. Schuh! (Paris 1942, Nachdr.1967) 258; Baltes,
Weltentstehung I 17, Anm.46 und 48; Scheffel, Kosmologie 103 ff. 142, dem ich
jedoch nicht in allen Einzelheiten zustimmen kann.
7 DaB nach dieser Gruppierung der Spurenelemente die ungeordnete
Bewegung aufhoren miiBte, kann ich Tarin, "Creation Myth" 386 ff nicht
zugeben; denn die Ideen wirken ja immerfort weiter auf die xropa; und rufen
in ihr standig neue Spurenelemente hervor, deren aVffiJlClAlCl die xropa;
weiterhin in Bewegung setzt, so daB die Schiittelbewegung andauert. Ebenso
kann ich ihm nicht zugeben, daB die Seele im "Timaios" QueUe aller Bewegungen ist (a.O. 384 u.o.); sie ist nur Quelle aller geordneten Bewegungen.
8" Auf den Gedanken, daB es "the world" schon vor dem Eingreifen des
Demiurgen gibt, kann man nur kommen, wenn man die Leistung des
Demiurgen unerlaubterweise so sehr minimalisiert, wie Mohr, Platonic
Cosmology 66 f es tut.
79
spater als die dort entstehenden Korper, einschlieBlich des Kosmoskorpers. Jedenfalls wird sie auf diesen Stufen nirgends erwahnt.
Dagegen ist der Kosmoskorper nach 30 A 6 - C 1 von Anfang an beseelt,
und nach 34 B 10 ff ist die Weltseele sogar friiher als der Kosmoskorper; dieser wirdja in die schon erstellte Seele hineingebaut (36 D 9 f),
und die Sterne werden erst nach ihrer Erstellung in die Umlaufe der
Seele hineingesetzt (38 C 7 f; 40 A 4 f). Also ist die Weltseele nach
Platon wirklich friiher als die Weltkorper. Aber wann ist sie dann
entstanden? Auf der ersten Stufe oder erst auf einer Zwischenstufe
nach der ersten und vor der zweiten Stufe? Tim. 34 B 10 ff scheint fiir
die zweite Alternative zu sprechen 9.
Auch bei der Erschaffung der Zeit tun sich Schwierigkeiten auf; denn
nach der Erzahlung des Timaios schafft der Gott die Zeit nach der
Weltseele und dem Weltkorper, aber vor den Gestirnen (37 C 6 ff);
doch korrigiert Timaios sich sogleich, indem er sagt, die Zeit sei
zusammen mit dem Himmel entstanden (38 B 6 ff). Obschon also die
Darstellung des Timaios dies zunachst suggeriert, bildet die Erschaffung der Zeit dann doch keine eigene Stufe.
4. Auf der vierten Stufe erfolgt die Erschaffung der Gestirngotter und der
~(lt).lOV~ (39 c 3-41 A 6).
5. Erst danach entsteht auf der fiinften Stufe der unsterbliche Teil der
Menschenseele, der aus den zweit- und drittrangigen Resten der
Ingredienzien der Weltseele geschaffen wird (41 D 3 ff). Dieser Teil
der Menschensede entsteht nach den GOtterseelen (vgl. 38 E 5 f; 40 B
5). Auch die Gotterseelen miissen also aus Resten der Ingredienzien
der Weltseele entstanden sein, doch wird man annehmen konnen,
daB diese Reste nicht zweit- und drittrangig waren. Also ist vor der
Entstehung des gottlichen Teils der Menschenseele und der
Gestirnkorper zwischen der dritten und fiinften Stufe die Entstehung
der Gotterseelen anzusetzen, die der "Timaios" nur voraussetzt, aber
nicht behandelt.
6. Auf der sechsten Stufe zieht der Gott sich zuriick, denn er hat seine
Aufgabe erfiillt, und die Untergotter losen ihn ab. Sie schaffen jetzt
den menschlichen Korper, binden die gottliche Seele in diesen und
fiigen dann den sterblichen Teil der Menschenseele hinzu ( 42 E 5 ff;
69 C 5 ff). Dabei entsteht nur der Mann ( 41 E 3 ff; 90 E 6 ff). Wie die
Stellung des Berichts im Ganzen nahelegt, werden auf derselben
Stufe die Pflanzen erschaffen, die den entstandenen Menschen als
Nahrung dienen sollen (76 E 7-77 C 5).
7. Auf der siebten Stufe entstehen die Frauen und mit ihnen auch die
Fortpflanzungsorgane des Mannes (42 B 5 ff; 76 D 8; 90 E 6 ff).
8. Auf der achten Stufe entstehen die Tiere (42 A 1 - D 2; 76 D 8 ff; 91 D 6
ff).
9 Trotzdem bleibt auch diese Losung schwierig; denn wenn Tim. 48 A
der vouc; die avayJCTl zu iiberreden vermag, muB diese schon von sich aus Seele
besitzen, wenn denn der Satz gelten soli, daB vouc; ohne Seele niemandem
zukommen kann (Tim. 30 B 3). Hat also das vorkosmische Chaos schon vor
dem Eingreifen des Gottes Seele? Oder wird die Seele der avayJCTl in dem
Augenblick mitgegeben, in dem der Gott sie anspricht? Eine unlosbare
Schwierigkeit.
80
MATTHIAS BALTES
81
sogar hervor, daB er urn der Darstellung willen Zusammengehoriges trennen muB (61 C 3-D 5).
Timaios gibt auch klar und deutlich zu verstehen, warum er
dieses Vorgehen wahlt: Er ist iiberzeugt, daB seine Zuhorer auf
diese Weise besser verstehen, was er sagen will (27 C 7 - D 4). Dies
gilt vor allem fiir die Zweiteilung in die Abschnitte "Werke der
Vernunft" und "Werke der Notwendigkeit"; denn erst nachdem
Timaios seine Zuhorer mit den leichter verstandlichen Werken
der Vernunft vertraut gemacht hat, fiigt er die "unerhorte und
ungewohnliche Darlegung" (a:t01t0~ Kat ail~~ ~htl"fll<Jt~, 48 D 5 f)
iiber "die schwierige und dunkle Art" (xaA.e7tov Kat UJ.!UOpov doo~),
die "Aufnehmerin allen Entstehens" (7t<l<Jll~ yevcrero~ t>7toOoxfl, 49
A 3-6) an, eine his dahin vollkommen unbekannte Realitat, iiber
die noch nie jemand gesprochen habe ( 48 B 5 fl).
Die genannte Erklarung gilt in gleicher Weise fiir die Binnenstruktur der einzelnen Teile. So wird im Abschnitt iiber die Werke
der Vernunft die einfachere Entstehung des Kosmoskorpers (29 D
7- 34 A 7) vor der komplizierteren Entstehung der Weltseele (34 A
8 - 36 D 7) behandelt, obschon die Weltseele "friiher" ist als der
Weltkorper 11 Ebenso wird die Entstehung der Zeit nach der Entstehung des Kosmos besprochen (37C6fl),obschon sie doch zusammen
mit dem Kosmos entstanden ist (38 B 6 fl). Aus denselben didaktischen Griinden wird die Entstehung der Gestirnkorper 38 C 3 ff
vor ihrer Belebung behandelt, die erst in 38 E 3 ff erwahnt wird 12.
Mit anderen Worten, die Darstellung der Weltentstehung im
''Timaios" ist durch didaktische Absichten bestimmt; so, wie sie ist,
ist sie OtOacrKaA.ia~ xaptv bzw. craqnweia~ EVEKa. Das haben schon
Speusipp und Xenokrates gesehen. Doch sind diese noch einen
Schritt weitergegangen. Sie haben behauptet, nicht nur die Darstellung der Weltentstehung, sondern auch der dargestellte Akt sei
nichts weiter als ein Zugestandnis an die OtOacrKaA.ia. Wie in der
Geometrie zum Zweck der Unterweisung und der Verdeutlichung
ein Dreieck aus vorgegebenen GroBen konstruiert werde, das doch
niemals entstanden sei, so lasse Platon im ''Timaios" den Kosmos
nur zum Zweck der Unterweisung und urn der groBeren Deutlichkeit willen durch den Demiurgen konstruiert werden. In WirklichVgl. Robinson, Plato's Psychology 65. 68.
Ebenso wird im zweiten Teil des "Timaios" zuniichst die weniger
Vorwissen erfordernde xropa behandelt ( 48 E 2 - 53 B 7), dann erst die
"ungewohnliche Darstellung" (aft611~ A.6yo~) der Elementenlehre, die
erhebliche mathematische Vorkenntnisse voraussetzt (53 B 7 ff).
II
12
82
MATTHIAS BALTES
83
4. Kann man wirklich annehmen, daB der Gott die Weltseele vor dem
Weltleib erschafft, gleichsam eine Seele ohne Aufgabe? Denn diese
Aufgabe erhalt sie ja erst nachtraglich dadurch, daB der Gott den
Weltkorper in sie hineinbaut (36 D 9 f; 38 C 7 f; 40 A 4 f) 15.
5. Kann man wirklich annehmen, daB die Zeit erst mit dem Kosmoskorper entstanden ist? 16 1st dem so, dann waren die vorkosmischen
Bewegungen nicht "in der Zeit". Waren sie dann iiberhaupt noch
Bewegungen? Welchen Sinn hat es dann noch, daB Timaios davon
spricht, daB sie "vor der Entstehung des Himmels" waren (48 B 3 f; 52
D 3; vgl. 37 E 2) und daB der Urzustand und das Eingreifen des Gottes
als zeitliches Nacheinander dargestellt werden (53 A 7 ff; 69 B 2 ff; 30
A 2 fl) 17?
Die Interpreten helfen sich hier mit der Annahme einer ungeordneten vorkosmischen Zeit (so schon der Platoniker Attikos) 18 bzw. mit
einer unendlichen Dauer ("an a1tEtpov of duration"), die nicht periodische Zeit sei, weil sie sich nicht wie diese gemaB der Zahl bewegt
(so Skemp und Hackforth) 19 . Aber kann es in dieser "Dauer"
iiberhaupt ein Friiher und Spater geben, wenn es kein Majl gibt,
woran beides gemessen wird?
Vlastos nimmt analog zu den Spurenelementen "Spuren einer
zeitlichen Ordnung" ('"traces' of temporal order") im vorkosmischen
Dagegen schon Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 287,11 ff; 104,4 ff; 115,2 f Diehl.
Es ist falsch zu behaupten, daB, "when Plato says that the Demiur~
makes time, he means that the Demiurge makes a clock, nothing more
(Mohr, Platonic Cosmology 54); denn die Zeit ist zwar ihrem Wesen nach ein
bewegtes und der Zahl nach fortschreitendes Abbild der Ewigkeit (37 D 6 f;
38 A 7 f), aber sie ist keine Uhr; denn eine Uhr ist nicht Zeit, sie mi}Jt die
Zeit. Die Interpretation Mohrs ist nicht unvoreingenommen; denn sie geht
davon aus, daB es auch vor dem Kosmos eine 'Zeit' gibt: Platon "means that
time is a clock, a clock by which we measure time, where 'time' here is used
in a colloquial sense, as that about motion and rest which is measurable"
(ebd. 59). Platon kennt diese zweite An von 'time' nicht, und es stimmt
nicht, daB "the technical sense of time and this ordinary sense exist side by
side through the text we are discussing (e.g., 38c2: o o' ... xpovov [?])" (a.O.).
Grotesk wird es, wenn neben dieser ersten Art von 'time' eine zweite
eingefiihn wird, namlich 'time' im Sinne von dem, "which is measurable
as actually having been measured" [Hervorhebung von mir], und wenn gesagt
wird, diese Bedeutung von 'time' "appears in the description of the planets as
'the instruments of time(s)' ( 42d5; 41e5)" (a.O. und 64).
Ganz unmoglich ist die Behauptung Mohrs ebd. 67 f, die vom Demiurgen
geschaffene Zeit unterlie~e keinem Wandel und sei ewig. Platon sagt doch
deutlich, sie sei eine Eilcrov 1C1V1lt6r; ttr; airovor; (37 D 5) und ihre do11 Vergangenheit und Zukunft seien Bewegungen (38 A 2). Weder als bewegt noch
als Abbild der Ewigkeit kann sie selbst wirklich ewig und unveranderlich
sein. Die Zeit ist zwar nicht "in der Zeit", aber das heiBt noch lange nicht,
daB sie wirklich ewig (im Sinne des Vorbildes) ist. Siehe unten Anm.33.
17 Vgl. zudem Tarin, "Creation Myth" 378 ff.
18 Plutarch und Attikos bei Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 276,32 ff; 286,26 ff; III
37,11 ff Diehl; dazu Sorabji, Time 273 f (dagegen Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 286,29
ff Diehl; s. Baltes, Weltentstehung II 40 ff). Vgl. schon Epikureer bei Cicero, De
nat. deor. 1,21 und dazu Baltes, Weltentstehung I 26.
19 J. Skemp, The Theory of Motion in Plato's Later Dialogues (Amsterdam
19672) 111; Hackforth, "Plato's Cosmology" 22; ahnlich Guthrie, History V
301 fund Mansfeld, "Rez. Scheffel, Kosmologie" 172.
15
16
84
MATTHIAS BALTES
Chaos an2. Doch von den letzteren sagt der Platontext nichts. An
anderer Stelle2 1 unterscheidet Vlastos die geschaffene Zeit als einen
"einformigen und meBbaren ZeitfluB" ("uniform and measurable
time-flow") von einer vorkosmischen "unumkehrbaren zeitlichen
Abfolge" ("irreversible temporal succession"), einer "quasi-time"22. In
der letzteren gebe es zwar ein Friiher und Spater, aber die Intervalle
zwischen heiden seien nicht meBbar: "If A, B, C, are successive
instants we would have no means of telling if the interval, AB, is as
long as the interval, BC, or longer, or shorter. "23 Ich mochte bestreiten,
daB es iiberhaupt sinnvoll ist, in einem vorkosmischen Chaos von
einem Friiher und Spater zu sprechen. Ein Friiher-und-Spater impliziert in jedem Fall eine zahlbare Abfolge, also ein Voranschreiten der
Zahl nach (Kat' apt8J.I.OV ivat, 37 D 6)2 4 ; d.h. es impliziert eine
Ordnung, die es im vorkosmischen Chaos nicht gibt. Wer immer
also ein Friiher oder Spater im vorkosmischen Chaos konstatiert, kann
selbst nicht zu diesem gehoren, vielmehr betrachtet er das Chaos
gleichsam von auBen, von der Ordnung seines Erkenntnisorgans aus;
er ilbertriigt also etwas auf das Chaos, was nicht in ihm ist.
Auch darf man m.E. nicht hingehen und, wie Vlastos es tut, Vergangenheit, Gegenwart und Zukunft fiir die genannte zeitliche Abfolge ("temporal succession") in Anspruch nehmen2 5 . Denn Platon
bezeichnet diese doch ausdriicklich als xpovou yEyovota EtOTJ, d.h. als
Unterarten der Zeit (37 E 4)2 6 , die zusammen mit dieser entstanden sind:
xp6vou tllUtll ai&va JllJ.I.OUJ.I.EVOU Kilt Kilt' apt8J.I.OV KUKAoUJ.I.EVOU YEYOVEV
dO, (38 A 7 f).
Jedes Postulat einer wie auch immer gearteten Zeit ist fiir das vorkosmische Chaos abzulehnen; denn die einzige Zeit, von der Platon
spricht, ist die Zeit, die "zusammen mit dem Himmel entstanden ist"
und die zusammen mit dem Himmel vergehen kann (38 B 6 f); d.h.
ebensowenig wie es nach einem Vergehen des Himmels Zeit geben
wiirde, hat es vor dem Entstehen des Himmels Zeit gegeben. Die
geordnete Bewegung des Himmels ist ja die Bedingung der
20 Vlastos, "Disorderly Motion" 390. Mansfeld, "Rez. Scheffel, Kosmologie"
171/172 spricht in iihnlichem Sinne von "a faint sort ... of 'matter' of time"
bzw. von "a sort of precosmic time-'matter'".
21 Vlastos, "Creation" 409 ff
22 Vlastos, "Creation" 414. Andere meinen, Platon nehme zwar keine
vorkosmische Zeit, aber eine vorkosmische "duree" an; vgl. Naddaf, L'origine
437 Anm.l. Nichts im '"fimaios" weist auf eine solche hin.
23 Vlastos, "Creation" 411. Ahnlich urteilt Mohr, Platonic Cosmology 58 ff.
63. 64 ff.
24 Das haben selbst Plutarch und Attikos zugegeben; vgl. Prokl. In Plat.
Tim. I 277,6 f Diehl.
25 Vlastos, "Creation" 411 ff
26 Strenggenommen bezeichnet Platon nur "war" und "wird sein" als
Arten der Zeit, aber das schlieBt nicht aus, daB auch das "ist" eine Art der
Zeit ist; denn Platon sagt nicht, daB nur die beiden Arten der Zeit seien,
vielmehr daB sie nur von der Zeit, nicht von der Ewigkeit ausgesagt werden
durfen, fUr die nur das "ist" zuliissig ist (Tim. 37 E 4 fi). DaB dies richtig ist,
zei~t Tim. 38 c 2 f: b ~ (l~ ~l(X tEAoU~ 'tOV 1i7tllV'tll x.p6vov 'YE'YOVOO~ 'tE Kilt rov Kilt
cro~tEVO~. Vgl. C. Eggers Lan, Las nociones de tiempo y eternidad de Homero a Platon
(Mexiko 1984) 177 f.
85
Diese und andere Schwierigkeiten machen die Annahme unmoglich, daB der Kosmos nach Platon sukzessive entstanden ist.
Darf man also daraus schlieBen, daB er iiberhaupt nicht entstanden ist? Das zu behaupten ware voreilig; denn es bleibt ja noch
die Erklarung, er sei in einem realen Schopfungsakt sozusagen auf
27 Platons erste Menschen, die Manner-Generation, werden zwar von den
Untergottern erschaffen, also nicht geboren (42 E ff; 69 C ff), aber wie
entsteht die zweite Generation? Oder praziser: Wie entsteht die erste Frau in
der zweiten Generation?
28 Vgl. Prokl. In Plat. Tim. III 282,27 ff; ~93,32 ff Diehl; dazu Baltes,
Weltentstehung II 199 ff. Zur Ambiguitat der AuBerungen Platons tiber die
Entstehung des Menschen vgl. Naddaf, L'origine 393 ff.
86
MATTHIAS BALTES
29 Vgl. Scheffel, Kosmologie 59. 73 f. 122 f. 130 f. 140 ff. Derselben Ansicht
waren auch manche christlichen Schriftsteller hinsichtlich des Schopfungsberichts der Genesis, beispielsweise Basileios, In Hexaem. 1,6 S.110-112 Giet;
Ioh. Philoponos, De aet. mundi 1,3 S.6,2 ff; 11,13 S.367,19 ff u.o. Rabe.
30 Bei einer schlagartigen Schopfung wiirde der Demiurg des "Timaios"
zudem in ein und demselben Augenblick auftreten und abtreten.
31 Selbst Hackforth, "Plato's Cosmology" 20, der doch der Ansicht ist, daB
die Weltentstehung im "Timaios" im Sinne eines zeitlichen Aktes zu
verstehen sei, halt es fiir "ridiculous" anzunehmen, auch die Mischung der
Weltseele sei als ein einmaliges Geschehen in der Vergangenheit aufzufassen; diese Mischung sei vielmehr nichts weiter als "an analysis of the
cosmic soul's faculties of cognition and motion".
32 Vgl. Prokl. bei Ioh. Philoponos, De aet. mundi II S.24,1 ff Rabe; Baltes,
Weltentstehung I 214 mit Verweisen; II 136. Dieselbe Argumentation IieBe
sich iibrigens auch auf den Demiurgen (vgl. Prokl. a.O. III S.42,1 ff Rabe;
Baltes a.O. II 136 ff) oder die Zeit anwenden (Prokl. a.O. V S.103,20 ff Rabe;
Baltes a.O. II 140).
33 Mit Recht schreibt Tarin, "Creation Myth" 397, Anm.60: "Since the
word airovto~ is applied to the model and to the copy, it cannot mean in the
case of the latter only imperishability: there must be something common to
the model and the copy in order that both may be said to be airovto~. And
Timaeus 37 C 6 - 38 B 5 implies the answer: both model and copy are airovto~,
but whereas the former is et!!rnal and atemporal, the latter possesses the
eternity of infinite duration." Ahnlich urteilt Eggers Lan, Eternidad 175 ff.
Platon selbst ist noch expliziter: Es war nicht moglich, die airovto~ q>'ucrt~
(d.h. den airov) vollkommen auf den Kosmos zu iibertragen (7t<XVttl..ro~ 7tpocra7ttttv}; d.h. der Kosmos konnte nicht schlechthin airovto~ werden; aber ein
KompromiB war moglich: Der Kosmos konnte die til<rov airovo~ anfnehmen,
die Zeit, die selbst wieder airovto~ ist: wei! sie ja nicht "zeitlich" (eyxpovo~)
sein kann. Airovto~ mull auch im letzteren Fall so etwas wie "ewig" heiBen,
d.h. anfangs- und endlos, wei! ja nur so das Ziel erreicht wird, daB die Zeit
der Ewigkeit "moglichst ... ahnlich ist" ('{v' ro~ OJlOtO't<X'tO~ autcp K<Xta OUV<XJltV TI
38 B 8 f; vgl. 37 D 2).
DaB Platon wirklich annimmt, die Zeit sei anfangs- und endlos, zeigt die
Parallelitiit des Satzbaus in Tim. 36 C 1-3:
87
Kosmos verbunden wie die Ewigkeit mit dem Vorbild. Wenn also die
Zeit ein 'ewiges' Abbild der Ewigkeit ist, dann muB der Kosmos ein
'ewiges' Abbild des Vorbildes sein. Folglich ist er nicht entstanden.
4. Spricht schon die Bezeichnung der Zeit als a.irovw<; dKrov gegen _eine
Entstehung derselben, so wird diese Ansicht durch folgende Uberlegung untermauert: Vergangenheit und Zukunft sind Arten der Zeit
(xpovou ... Et&r], 37 E 3- 38 A 8); d. h. sie sind EtOTJ des yvo<; Zeit. Wenn
die Zeit nun gleichsam mit einem Schlag ins Sein gesetzt worden
ware, dann ware sie unvollstandig ins Sein gesetzt worden; denn in
diesem ersten Augenblick hatte es noch keine Vergangenheit gegeben, sondern nur Gegenwart und Zukunft. Das aber ist unmoglich,
denn
a) der Gott hatte in diesem Fall etwas Unvollkommenes geschaffen34,
was undenkbar ist, und
b) es ist unvorstellbar, daB das yf.vo<; Zeit einmal das doo<; Vergangenheit nicht umfaBt.
Also kann die Zeit nicht entstanden sein 35
5. Wenn die Welt das schonste aller entstandenen Dinge und der Gott
die beste aller Ursachen ist (29 A 5 f) und wenn der gute Gott keinen
Neid kennt und alles moglichst gut mach en (29 E 1 ff), ja, wenn er
iiberhaupt in seinem Handeln immer das Schonste will ( 30 A 7 f),
warum hat er dann die Welt nicht schon vorher erschaffen? 36 Dies
gilt urn so mehr, wenn es vor dem Anfang der Welt das vorkosmische Chaos der ersten Stufe gab. Wie konnte der Gott dieses
iiberhaupt mit ansehen, ohne einzugreifen?37 Man wende nicht ein,
daB es nicht sinnvoll sei, vor der Entstehung der Zeit von einem Vor
zu sprechen. GewiB, es gab kein zeitliches Vor, aber doch ein
sachliches: Unordnung vor Ordnung bzw. das Nichts vor dem Sein.
Wie ist das bei einem guten Gott moglich?
6. Gott ist "immer seiend" (34 B 8), ja, er ist das Beste der intelligiblen
Dinge (37 A 1), d.h. er ist keinem Wandel unterworfen (27 D 6- 28 A
2). Wieso kann er sich dann iiberhaupt plotzlich zur Erschaffung der
Welt entschlieBen? Ein solcher EntschluB wiirde doch notwendiger-
0 o' c:xi) ... TOY an-avm xp6vov yeyovroc. t l((lt rov KC:Xt EO"OUEVOC..
Ewigkeit und Zeit existieren parallel.
Anzunehmen, die Zeit sei nur in einer Richtung ewig, wiirde 1. die
Ewigkeit zeitweise ihrer Ursiichlichkeit berauben und 2. sozusagen ein
amputiertes Abbild erzeugen. Vgl. Proklos bei Ioh. Philoponos, De aet.
mundi XVIII S.607 ,24 ff Rabe (Baltes, Weltentstehung II 162) und auch
Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism 419, Anm.350.
34 Spiiter tadelte man dergleichen als T1!11tEA~<; 01]!1\0Upyic:x; Ioh. Philoponos,
De aet. mundi 9,10 S.344,15 f.
35 Vgl. in diesem Zusammenhang auch Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism
419f.
36 Vgl. Porphyrios bei Ioh. Philoponos, De aet. mundi 6,27 S.224,18 ff
Rabe = fg.456a Smith; Porphyrios bei Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 394,12 ff Diehl;
Proklos selbst: In Plat. Tim. I 367,2 ff. 13 ff Diehl; dazu Baltes, Weltentstehung I
90. 92. 159. 160 f; II 74 ff; Proklos bei Baltes, a.O. II 134 ff.
37 Vgl. Tarin, "Creation Myth" 381; Baltes, Weltentstehung I 215 mit
Verweisen.
88
MATTHIAS BALTES
89
aber auch im Kosmos. Denn Pia ton sagt ja ausdriicklich, daB dort, wo
der Gott abwesend ist, Unordnung herrscht (53 B 3 f) 42. 1st somit die
Gegenwart des Gottes unabdingbare Voraussetzung fiir jede Ordnung,
dann auch fiir den Kosmos. Der Gott kann also nicht abtreten, soli der
Kosmos bestehen bleiben 43.
Bestiitigt wird das durch eine wunderliche Aussage des Timaios, die
den modernen Interpreten einiges Kopfzerbrechen bereitet hat.
Timaios sagt 42 E 5 f: Nachdem der Gott den Untergottern seine
Auftriige fiir das weitere Schaffen erteilt hatte, "verharrte er in der
seiner Art entsprechenden gewohnten Haltung/Seinsweise" ( EJlEVEV
f.v tip f.a.utou Ka.ta tpo7tov i18Et). Hier driingt sich doch geradezu die
Frage auf, ob sich der Gott vorher-wiihrend seiner Schopfertiitigkeit
-nicht "in der seiner eigenen Art entsprechenden gewohnten
Haltung/Seinsweise" befunden hat. Da man diese Frage nicht
bejahen kann, hat der Gott immer "in der seiner Art entsprechenden
gewohnten Haltung/Seinsweise verharrt". Das lmperfekt EJlEVEV, das
den Interpreten solche Schwierigkeiten bereitet hat, vermag diese
Interpretation zu stiitzen.
Auch folgendes ist zu bedenken: Wie soli das "intelligible Lebewesen" wirklich Lebewesen sein, ohne zu wirken? Also darf es wohl
als gesichert gelten, daB der Demiurg nichts anderes ist als der
schopferisch-ordnende Aspekt des Seienden, so wie das Vorbild sein
paradigmatischer Aspekt ist 44 . 1st dies richtig, dann versteht man
auch, warum Pia ton eigentlich nur zwei Ursachen gelten liiBt ( oo'
a.hia.c; Ei:on), die notwendige und die gottliche (to JlEV ava.yKa.'iov, to of:
8EtOV' 68 E 6 ff)' den vouc; und die UVcX')'K'Il (4 7 E 3 fi) 45.
Allerdings ist eine Einschriinkung zu machen: Der Gott ist nicht das
aktive Prinzip des Seienden schlechthin, sondern nur das aktiv
ordnende Prinzip. Aktiv sind ja auch schon die Ideen, die auf die xropa.
einwirken (50 C 4 f; 51 A 7 f; 52 D 4 ff) 46
Ein vorletztes Argument kann das bisher Gesagte stiitzen: Das aktiv
ordnende Prinzip des VOTjtOv t;<pov nennt Platon auch einfach vouc;. So
sagt er 39 E 7 ff, daB es der vouc; ist, der die vier Hauptideen der
Lebewesen im VOT]tOV t;ipov sieht und im Kosmos zu verwirklichen
strebt, und 47 E 5 ff hebt er hervor, daB es der vouc; ist, der die ava')'K'Il
iiberredet. An heiden Stellen wird nicht erkliirt, wem der vouc; gehort.
42
43 Vgl. Proklos bei Ioh. Philoponos, De aet. mundi XVIII S.606,9 ff; 608,11
ff Rabe; Baltes, Weltentstehung II 160 ff.
44 Daher kann man denn auch verstehen, daB Aristoteles dem Platonischen Demiurgen kaum Aufmerksamkeit schenkt (Cherniss, Aristotle's
Criticism 609 f; Tarin, "Creation Myth" 382. 391), ja, daB er sogar sagen
kann, Platon verwende nur zwei Ursachen, tft tE tou ti ecrttv Kat tft Kata tl]v
UAfiV, wobei er unter tft tou ti ecrttv die Ideen versteht; vgl. Arist. Met. A 6 988
a 7 ff.
4 5 Ebenso spricht er 48 E 3 ff bei der Rekapitulation von 27 D 5- 47 E 2 nur
von ouo EtOfl, dem napaony~ta und dem lltllfllliX napaoeiy~tatoc;, wahrend er den
Demiurgen vollig iibergeht. Offenbar sind auch hier Demiurg und Paradi~ma identisch.
6 Es stimmt also nicht, daB "the Platonic Ideas are to be viewed as
standards and as nothing else" (Mohr, Platonic Cosmology 55; Hervorhebung von
mir).
90
MATTHIAS BALTES
Natiirlich hat man, wie schon gesagt, an den vou<; des Demiurgen
gedacht, von dem einmal die Rede ist (36 D 8), aber das ist nicht
mehr als eine Vermutung. Nach unserer Interpretation ist dieser vou<;
der demiurgisch schaffende und ordnende Aspekt des intelligiblen
scpov, der mit dem Demiurgen identisch ist.
Als letztes Argument sei schlieBlich die Beobachtung von Theodor
Ebert angefiihrt, daB im sog. 7tpOOtJltOV (27 D 5-29 D 3), ja, im ganzen
'Timaios" nie bewiesen wird, daB es einen Baumeister (~Jltoupy&;) der
Welt gibt, sondern nur, daB es eine Ursache (atnov) fiir sie gibt 47.
Diese Ursache wird unmittelbar nach ihrer ersten Nennung 28 A 4-6
in die Aspekte Demiurg und Vorbild zerlegt (28 A 6 - B 2), ohne daB
dafiir eine Begriindung gegeben wird. Dadurch entsteht sogar ein
Ieichter Bruch im Gedankengang, der den Leser offenbar aufhorchen
lassen und darauf hinweisen soli, daB die Ursache, von der Timaios
spricht, mehrere Facetten hat: Sie ist absichtsvoll planende ( ~Jlt
oupy6<;) und nach einem rationalen Plan (7tapaoetyJla) verfahrende
U rsache (atnov).
Nach all diesen Uberlegungen versteht man es besser, daB Platon
gleich zu Anfang sagt, schon den Schopfer und Vater des Ails zu
finden sei schwierig, und es sei vollig unmoglich, ihn allen Menschen zu verkiinden (tov JlEV ouv 7tOUJtTJV Kat 7tatepa touoe tou 7tavto<;
eupe'iv tE epyov KCll eup6vta ei<; 1tclVtCl<; aouvatov A.eyetv' 28 c 3 ff). Er ist
in der Tat schwer zu finden, wenn er sich im Zustand der Kosmosordnung gleichsam im gottlichen Vorbild versteckt und erst durch
das Hilfsmittel der Kosmogenese wirklich Konturen annimmt48
Dies also sind die Schwierigkeiten, die sich einstellen, wenn man
annimmt, die Welt sei in einem einmaligen Schopfungsakt entstanden. Sie alle sind nur dann zu losen, wenn man zugibt, daB
Platon auch den Schopfungsakt selbst nicht als zeitlich oder einmalig aufgefaBt hat. Wie vor allem das Beispiel des Demiurgen
zeigt, hat Platon in der Kosmogenese nur ein Hilfsmittel gesehen,
urn in dem immer gleichen und daher nur schwer durchschaubaren Geschehen im Kosmos sauber zu unterscheiden, was in
dieser Ordnung auf die gottliche und was auf die notwendige
Ursache zuriickzufiihren ist: Der gottlichen Ursache verdankt sie
alles Gute (29 E 1 ff), der notwendigen Ursache die Einschdinkungen, die der Verwirklichung dieses Guten auferlegt sind ( 48 A
3; 56 C 5 f; 75 A 7 ff; 77 A 1 f). In der gottlichen Ursache ist der
Aspekt des 7tapaonyJla von dem des OTJJ.ltoupy6~ zu unterscheiden.
4 7 T. Ebert, "Von der Weltursache zum Weltbaumeister", Antike und
Abendland 37 (1991) 51 f
48 Die Untergotter des "Timaios", die oft_mit dem Demiurgen zusammenzufallen scheinen, konnen nach diesen Uberlegungen nichts anderes
sein als 'Ausliiufer' des demiurgischen Aspekts des Seienden, die auf
unterster Ebene wirken.
91
Der erstere begriindet die Existenz der Dinge (52 D 2 fl), der letztere
ihre Ordnung (~tcx.KOaiJ.TJOt<;, 'ta~t<;, 53 A 7 ff; 69 B 2 fl).
Die Argumente, die ich bisher fiir die Auffassung vorgetragen
habe, die Welt sei nach Platons ''Timaios" nicht in einem einmaligen Akt entstanden, sind nur die starksten, die der ''Timaios"
zu bieten hat, und sie sind m.E. unwiderlegbar. 1st somit eine
einmalige Weltentstehung in grauer Vergangenheit undenkbar,
so stellt sich nun mit noch groBerer Dringlichkeit die Frage, wie
der entscheidende Passus 28 B 6 - C 2 zu verstehen ist.
Nimmt man den Beweisgang fiir das Entstehen der Welt 27 D 5 28 C 2 ernst, dann wird in ihm nur nachgewiesen, daB die Welt
ein ytyVOIJ.EVOV ist49 ; denn alle entscheidenden Verbalausdriicke
stehen in diesem Abschnitt im Prasens. Die einzige Ausnahme
bildet yf.yov EV (28 B 7) .-Auf den Ausdruck a1t' apxil<; 'ttVO<;
ap~aJ!EVO<; komme ich spater zuriick.-Man beachte nun, wie die
Begriindung fiir dieses yf.yovev wieder auf das Prasens rekurriert:
Die Welt ist entstanden, weil sie sichtbar, tastbar und mit einem
Korper ausgestattet ist und sich alles dergleichen als ytyvOJ!EVC:X Kat
yEVVTJ'ta/yEVTJ'ta gezeigt hatte.
Man wende nicht ein, wie man es zu tun pflegt, daB der
Ausdruck yEVVTJ'ta/yEVTJ'ta die Vergangenheit impliziere. Tate er es,
dann ware der Beweisgang nicht einwandfrei. Aber er tut das
ebensowenig wie bei den im gleichen Satz verwendeten Verbaladjektiven opa'tO<; 'KC:Xt a1t't0<; (28 B 7). feVVTJ'tn/yEVTJ'tn meint dem
Zusammenhang nach nichts anderes, als daB die unter ihm
subsumierten Gegenstande in der einen oder anderen Form die
Fahigkeit zum yEvvaaSat oder yiyvea8at haben5.
49 Dies ist die Auffassung vieler antiker Interpreten; vgl. Baltes, Weltentstehung I 86 f. 108 mit Anm. 116; 121 f. 128 f.
50 Vgl. R. Kuhner- F. Blass, Ausfii.hrliche Grammatik der griechischen Sprache.
Erster Teil: Elementar- und Formenlehre, II (Leipzig 1 1892, Hannover 1978) 288 f;
E. Bickel, "Die q>EUK'ta der Stoa bei Ausonius", Rhein. Mus. 86 (1937) 287 f; E.
Schwyzer, Griechische Grammatik I (Mtinchen 1939) 501.
Zu diesem Gebrauch des Verbaladjektivs vgl. 1tpt 8e&v opa-rrov mi yevv1)-rrov
( 40 D 4); YVV1J'rOV, TrEfPOP1JJlEVOV aei, ylyvOJlEVOV 'r EV 'ttVt 't01tCp ... (52 A 5 f). In
heiden Fallen ist nicht die Bedeutung "entstanden/geworden" intendiert.
Auffallig ist der Gebrauch in 28 B 1 f: on li' iiv d.; yqov6.; (sc. j3A.1tEt b
liTJ!ltoupyo.;), "fEVVTJ'tcp 1tapalieiy11an 1tpocrxpro11Evo.; ... Wenn hier yqov6.; und
"(EVVTJ'tcp dasselbe bedeuten, dann ist der Ausdruck tautologisch. Der Vergleich
mit 28 A 6 f zeigt jedoch, daB "(EVVTJ'tcp im Gegensatz zu 'tO K!l'tll 't!lU'tlX exov zu
verstehen ist; dann aber liegt die Bedeutung "dem Werden und Entstehen
unterworfen" naher als die Bedeutung "entstanden/geworden". Ambivalent
ist schlieBlich die Ausdrucksweise in 37 D 4, wo mit 'tcp "(EVVTJ'tcp entweder
"das entstandene" oder "das dem Entstehen unterworfene (All)" gemeint
92
MATTHIAS BALTES
Wenn das richtig ist, dann ist auch ye:yovev (28 B 7) nicht im Sinne
eines einmaligen Schopfungsaktes zu verstehen-fiir diesen hatte
man ja auch eher die Form E"(EVE'tO erwartet. reyovev besagt vielmehr, daB das Werden und Entstehen im Zustand der Vollendung ist: Die Welt ist als eine entstandene, yeyovro<; ecrnv, wie
Platon vom Kosmos selbst sagt (31 B 3)51.
DaB dies wirklich so zu verstehen ist, legt eine weitere Uberlegung nahe: Wenn alles, was sichtbar, tastbar und korperlich ist,
in einem einmaligen Akt entstanden ist, dann ist auch das
vorkosmische Chaos in dieser Weise entstanden52, das ebenfalls
sichtbar (30 A 3; 52 E 1), tastbar und korperlich ist (vgl. 30 A 3 ff; 52
E 1 fl) 53. Da das vorkosmische Chaos nach Platon aber offenbar nur
yevecrt<; im Sinne des standigen yiyvecr8a.t ist (52 D 3), folgt daraus,
daB auch die yevecrt<; des Kosmos nur im Sinne des standigen
yiyvecr8a.t zu verstehen ist. 1st dem so, dann versteht man auch
besser, warum 29 D 7 yevecrt<; und 'tO nav gleichgesetzt werden (Ot'
t]vnva. a.i'tia.v YEVeO"tV Ka.t 'tOOe 'tO nav 6 O"UVtO"'ta<; O"UVEO"'tTIO"eV; vgl.
E 4): Der Kosmos ist yevecrt<;.
Man wende nicht ein, das vorkosmische Chaos werde zwar als
yevecrt<; bezeichnet, nicht aber wie der Kosmos als yeyov6<;. Das ist
nicht wahr; denn 28 C 5 ff wird die' Moglichkeit erwogen, daB der
Demiurg die Welt nach einem entstandenen Vorbild (yeyovo<;
na.paOetyJla.) geschaffen hat. Dieses Vorbild kann nur das vorkosmische Chaos sein, in dem schon eine gewisse Ordnung der
Spurenelemente herrschte (52 E 5 ff). Nur diese kann mit dem
entstandenen Vorbild gemeint sein, denn sonst gab es ja nichts
(52 D 2 fl)5 4 .
Nun konnte man darauf hinweisen, daB Platon ja nicht nur
danach fragt, ob der Kosmos entstanden sei oder nicht, sondern
danach, ob er immer war ohne jegliche &.pxn oder ob er geworden
sei, beginnend von einer gewissen &.pxn. Hier scheint der Gegensatz klar und deutlich zeitlich zu sein. Darauf konnte vor allem das
lmperfekt ~v im Gegensatz zu dem Perfekt yeyovev hindeuten. Aber
sein kann.
5! Oder, wie Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 290,23 ff Diehl es wortreich nachweist,
der Kosmos ist ad ytyYOflEVO~ UflU Kat YEYEV1)flEVO~. Vgl. dazu Baltes, Weltentstehung II 52 ff.
52 Vgl. Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 283,31 ff Diehl und dazu Baltes, Weltentstehung II 30 ff; auch Zeller II 1, 793.
53 Beides ist Voraussetzung fiir das 30 A 3 ff und 52 E 1 ff geschilderte
vorkosmische Geschehen; vgl. Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 387,10 ff Diehl.
54 Vgl. Mansfeld, "Rez. Scheffel, Kosmologie" 171.
93
das lmperfekt ist iiberhaupt seltsam; denn nach dem Argumentationszusammenhang erwartet man ein crnv: Ist der Kosmos
immer oder ist er geworden? Also ist das lmperfekt nur kolloquial
zu verstehen wie auch andere lmperfekte im "Timaios" (29 E 1; 37
D 3). 1st dies richtig, dann lautet der Gegensatz: 1st die Welt immer
seiend oder das Ergebnis eines Entstehungsprozesses? Uber den
Beginn des Entstehungsprozesses ist damit noch nichts gesagt,
und auch die zweifache Betonung der apxfJ weist nicht unbedingt
in diese Richtung. Denn schon in der Antike hat man auf den
auffalligen Gegensatz apxilv xrov ou~h:uia.v-a1t' apxflc; nvoc;
ap~aJ.LEVoc; aufmerksam gemacht55 . Es scheint, daB Platon mit
diesen Formulierungen darauf hinweisen wollte, daB der Begriff
apxfJ zu den vieldeutigen Begriffen (7tOAAa.x&c; AeyOJ.LEVa.) gehort
und er apxfJ nur in einem ganz bestimmten Sinne verwendet. Da
die Methode der begrifflichen Differenzierung in Platons Akademie gepflegt wurde56, wuBte jeder Platonschiiler, daB auch der
Begriff apxfJ viele Bedeutungen hat und daB Platon hier nur auf
eine bestimmte apxfJ hinauswill (apxfJ nc;)' ohne allerdings klar
anzugeben, welche apxfJ er wirklich im Sinne hat. Aber immerhin war der Schuler davor gewarnt, apxfJ hier einfach in der
Alltagsbedeutung zu nehmen.
Aber weist nun nicht gerade das ap~aJ.LEVOc; ganz entschieden in
die Richtung der Alltagsbedeutung? Hier haben wir doch den
erwarteten Aorist. Aber was fiir einen Aorist? Keinen Indikativ,
der mit dem Augment als Vergangenheitszeichen allein mit
Sicherheit das einmalige vergangene Ereignis hatte ausdriicken
konnen. Hatte Platon geschrieben: ilp~a.to, so ware klar gewesen,
daB er den einmaligen Akt in der Vergangenheit gemeint hatte;
ebenso wenn er formuliert hatte: EYEVE'tO a7t' apxflc; nvoc; ap~aJ.LEVOc;;
dann namlich hatte das voraufgehende Tempus auch auf das
Partizip abgefarbt. Zusammen mit dem Perfekt yf.yovev besagt das
Partizip ap~aJ.Levoc; nicht mehr, als daB eine apxfJ dem jetzigen
Zustand voraufgeht, d.h. zugrunde liegt.
Auch der Hinweis auf 28 c 2 f: 'tcp o' a.?> YEVOJ.LEV:p <pa.J.LEV U7t' a.hiou
nvoc; avayKT\V dva.t yevf.cr8a.t hilft nicht wirklich weiter; denn auch
hier liegen keine finiten Verbformen vor, und strenggenommen
besagt dieser Satz nicht mehr als: "wenn er nun aber entsteht,
55 Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 279,30 ff; 285,21 ff und Baltes, Weltentstehung I 143 ff
56 Vgl. Arist. Met. !J. 1/2; vgl. z.B. auch E. Heitsch, "Argumentation und
94
MATTHIAS BALTES
48 c 2ff);
2. daB es von seiner Seite eine groBe Anstrengung erfordere, seine
Gedanken adaquat zum Ausdruck zu bringen (27 D 3 f);
3. daB es unmoglich sei, die Darstellung vollkommen widerspruchsfrei
zu halten (29 C 4 ff)5B,ja, daB sie nicht einmal frei von Zufallen sei (34
c 2f);
4. daB die Mitunterredner des Timaios zwar hochgebildete Leute sind59
57 Auffallig ist, daB im Folgenden (28 C 5 - 29 B 1) keine Aoriste vorkommen, sondern nur Imperfekte und Perfekte, die die Dauer und den
Endzustand der Handlung festhalten und nicht auf die Einmaligkeit deuten.
Aoriste begegnen erst wieder ab 29 D 7 ff, d.h. vom Beginn des Schopfungsmythos an. Wie jede Erzahlung muB auch dieser Mythos selbstverstandlich
auf weite Strecken im Aorist erzahlt werden.
58 Dazu gehort etwa, daB Timaios sich gelegentlich unscharfer kolloquialer Ausdrucksweise bedient, so beispielsweise, wenn er 28 B 6 statt n:o'tEpov
ecrttv ad von n:on:pov !Jy_ aei spricht; desgleichen ist das Imperfekt in 29 E 1 und
37 D 3 unscharf gebraucht (vgl. Prokl. In Plat. Tim. I 278,29 ff Diehl und
Baltes, Weltentstehun~ I 133 f).
59 Der "Timaios ist der einzige Dialog Platons, in dem die Unterredner
einigermaBen gleichrangig sind (vgl. Tim. 19 E 8 ff; T. Szlezak, "Gesprache
unter Ungleichen. Zur Struktur und Zielsetzung der platonischen Dialoge",
Antike und Abendland 34 (1988) 99-116), und dennoch betont Timaios immer
95
96
MATTHIAS BALTES
PART THREE
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
jOHN DILLON 1
100
JOHN DILLON
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
101
102
JOHN DILLON
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
103
17 That Speusippus held this (fairly obvious) fact to be the case is attested by
104
JOHN DILLON
sw 3.431.
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
105
106
JOHN DILLON
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
107
that this state was productive of profound satisfaction, not to say joy.
He may, however, for want of a better adjective, have been constrained to describe it as T]ou, 'pleasant', though denying that it
involved any form of T]oovt1, and this could have given his uncle
the chance to stick the knife in.32
Let us look now closely at the crucial passage of the Philebus, and
see if we can divine just what sort of position is being criticized.
We may begin at 43c. Socrates has just secured Protarchus' agreement that not all changes in our constitution produce pleasure or
pain, but only fairly considerable ones. He continues ( 43c8-dl0) :33
Socr.:
become
Prot.:
Socr.:
(aA.um)~
aveu XUPflOVWV).
itllU~
108
JOHN DILLON
like to think that he is being deliberately misrepresented; otherwise, he is being notably careless in his language. Speusippus
does, admittedly, have a problem, as I have suggested above. He
needs some positive value word to characterize his ideal psychic
state, but he must be wary of employing words of the same root as
i]Bovt1 for that purpose. The fact, however, that Plato also uses
XUtpEtV repeatedly 35 in this passage to describe this state might
indicate that this was in fact the preferred term of the supporters of
this position, and that the Stoics were actually anticipated in their
technical use of this term. The difficulty here is, however, that
there is no obvious adjective from xapa available to characterize the
preferred state,36 and this might have led Speusippus to fall back
incautiously on i]Bu, which would allow Plato to win a terminological argument against him.
Let us continue, however (43el-44b3):
Socr.: Take any three things now, say one gold, one silver, one
neither, just to have fine names.
Prot.: All right.
Socr.: Could the one that is neither possibly become either gold
or silver?
Prot.: How on earth could it?
Socr.: Similarly, it would be a mistake for anyone to believe and
therefore to say that the midway life was either pleasant (i]ouc;) or
distressing; at least if we are to be strict.
Prot.: How could it be?
Socr.: Yet we find people who say and believe these things.
Prot.: Certainly.
Socr.: Do they then think they are enjoying themselves ( xaipetv) on the occasions when they are not in a distressed condition?
Prot.: That's what they say, at any rate.
Socr.: So they believe they are then enjoying themselves
(Xaipnv), or they wouldn't say it.
Prot.: Probably.
Socr.: Yet they are making a false judgement about enjoyment
if, that is, enjoyment and lack of distress are two quite different
things.
Prot.: But they turned out to be quite different things.
misrepresented.
35 Five times between 43d3 and 44a5, together with XCXPJ.10vai once, at 43c7.
36 There is, of course, as the editors pointed out to me, xapto~. which,
though a rather poetical word, is actually presented as a synonym for itou~
(along with tEp1tvo~) at Prot. 358a, but Speusippus would still have the problem
of defining a special meaning for this term; otherwise he might as well use
itou~.
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
109
110
JOHN DILLON
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
111
112
JOHN DILLON
SPEUSIPPUS ON PLEASURE
113
114
JOHN DILLON
43 By way of an irreverent concluding footnote, one may record the (doubtless malicious, but possibly accurate) report of Diogenes Laertius in his Life of
Speusippus (4.1) that the philosopher was 'prone to anger and vulnerable to
pleasures' (opyiA.oc; Kat itllovrov i;tto>V ~v). If so, he would not be the first or last
philosopher whose personal life did not quite come up to his principlesthough it must be said that the instances given by Diogenes to back up this
assertion are puerile and incoherent in the extreme.
116
L.M. DE RIJK
117
118
L.M. DE RIJK
2.2. Meaning and Representation: What does nparJ.La properly stand for?
Serious doubts may be raised against the rendering 'actual thing'
for 7tpftnux.6 According to Boethius, Alexander of Aphrodisias
already put forward the question of why-given the claim in De
interpretatione, ch. 1 that expressions act as names referring to
things-, Aristotle says that utterances are primarily (16a6 7tpclnrov)
signs of thoughts rather than of actual things. 7 Alexander thinks
that Aristotle possibly means to say that, although expressions are
names of things, we do not use them in order to signify things, but
rather to signify the thoughts ('affections of the soul') we have of
things in our mind. Aristotle justly claimed, he says, that utterances are primarily signs of thoughts, because they are properly
used to signify the thoughts we have of the things involved.s Some
lines further on, our spokesman Boethius rightly comments that
in calling the OJlOU:OJ.UX'ta 'affections of the soul' Aristotle means to
say that to think is precisely 'to receive an object's proper image in
the soul's reflections'.9
Alexander-speaking for Aristotle-appears to reject the opposition between thinking and reality that is implied in the question
'do the utterances refer to either thoughts or (actual) things?' Not the
objects as such are the proper objects of signifying but the thoughts
that are formed of the (actual) things; in Boethius words 'quae ex
rebus nobis innatae sunt animae passiones'. In other words,
6 E.g. Ackrill's rendering of 1tPcl'YiliXtiX at 16a7 and 17a38 (as in Cat. 5,
4a36ff; 12, 14b19ff.); cf. Boethius II 22.2-6. It is righty rejected by others, e.g.
Weidemann (1994) 138-9.
7 Boethius II, 40.30-41.7: [ ... ] quaerit Alexander: si rerum nomina sunt,
quid causae est ut primorum intellectuum notas esse voces diceret Aristoteles?
Rei enim ponitur nomen, ut cum dicimus 'homo', significamus quidem
intellectum, rei tamen nomen est, idest animalis rationalis mortalis. Cur
ergo non primarum magis rerum notae sunt voces quibus ponuntur potius
quam intellectuum?
8 Ibid., 41.7-13: 'Sed fortasse quidem ob hoc dictum est, inquit, quod, licet
voces rerum nomina sint, tamen non idcirco utimur vocibus ut res significemus, sed ut eas quae ex rebus nobis innatae sunt animae passiones.
Quocirca propter quorum significantiam voces ipsae proferuntur, recte eorum
primorum esse dixit esse notas.' The flavour of innatism ('innatae sunt
passiones animae') in Alexander's exposition would surely not have amused
Aristotle.
9 Ibid., 43.12-16: 'Similitudinem vero passionem animae vocavit, quod
secundum Aristotelem nihil aliud est [omitted by Meiser; see however the
older editions, e.g. Migne, PL 64, 414 B13] intellegere nisi cuiuslibet subiectae rei proprietatem atque imaginationem in animae ipsius reputatione
suscipere.'
119
lO For that matter, also Weidemann's (1994, 148-9) diagram of two dovetailed semiotic triangles is based, it seems, upon a mistaken opposition of
'thing' and thought, and thus seems to obscure the crucial point.
11 Wieland (1970) 170-1 (dealing with Aristotle's Physics): '[ ... ] das pragma seinen Ort nur innerhalb des sprachlichen Horizontes hat'; '[ ... ] es ist nur
das, was man mit dem Wort oder mit der Rede jeweils meint'. See also
Weidemann (1994) 139.
l2 For a more detailed survey of its occurrence in Aristotle see De Rijk
(1987) 36-39.
13 See our note 21 below. In Cat. 10, 12b5-16 and in Metaph. t:. 29, 1024b19ff.
even nonexistent (false) states of affairs are called np&wa. See De Rijk (1987)
38-9; Weid..:mann (1994) 138.
120
L.M. DE RIJK
121
122
L.M. DE RIJK
21
123
124
L.M. DE RIJK
29
For the semantic impact of this dialogue see De Rijk (1986) 217-53.
31 See De int. 10, 19b9: 'for what it signifies is in a way one thing, but
indefinite.' Obviously, when actually used, its denotatum may be quite precise,
e.g. in 'this not-man is a tree'.
32 Ackrill (1963) 118. See also Boethius II, 62.3-19; 69.29-70.3.
33 Boethius II, 62.19-63.14. For Plato too, the indefinite name has a
descriptive force. See De Rijk, (1986) 165ff.; 170ff.
125
126
L.M. DE RIJK
ev
127
44 Ackrill (1963) 120-1; Weidemann (1994) 177. See alsop. 133 below.
128
L.M. DE RIJK
129
make up the specific difference between OVOIJ.CX and Pll!J.CX, viz. the
latter's additional time-reference and its being said of something
else, including its attributive use, as e.g. in 'white man'. On this
assumption, the Pll!J.CX is merely a name, because, just like a name,
it only brings up its significate as an on tic value, 47 detached from
its being immanent in something else and without implying the
subject-substrate of which it is said. The fact that the Pll!J.CX in that
position does signify something does not yet eo ipso imply that the
entity involved is, or is not, the case. This is quite in line with what
has been said earlier (16al3-8) about OVOIJ.CX'ta and p~IJ.a'ta, 'when
nothing further (viz. 'is' or 'is not') is added'.
What remains to be discussed are the final sentences of this
chapter, in which the author tries to support his claim about the
Pll!J.CX when taken on its own, by an 'anticipative refutation'48
concerning the verb 'to be'. Not even the verb 'to be' (or 'not to be'),
which on the face of it seems to really imply 'being-the-case',
affords a counter-example to invalidate my claim, Aristotle
argues,49-not even if you use, without a further addition, the term
('be-ing'), which qua substantivated neuter word does imply the
idea of something actually being there.5 Why not? Because,
according to Aristotle (16b23-5), even the verb 'to be', including its
nominal participle, 'is nothing' (an empty notion, that is), and
merely helps to signify51 a certain cruv8ecrt<;, which cannot be
conceived of without the things combined.
A final remark should be made on the rendering of Pll!J.CX. The
rendering 'verb' does not reflect adequately the semantic function
ov
ouo'
to
130
L.M. DE RIJK
Aristotle has in mind when using pflJ.La, because it indiscriminately stands for any attributive determinant of an entity referred
to by a name, whether it is nominal52 or verbal. Therefore, the
neutral rendering 'attribute' seems to be the most appropriate in
English.53
53 The rendering 'Aussagewort', which some German interpreters rightly prefer to 'Verb' or 'Zeitwort', hits the mark, provided it is not associated
(as in Weidemann, passim) with the notion 'sentential predicate'. That this
association is wrong is clear from 1,16a15, as well as from its function within
the A.6yo~. which has a broader sense than 'sentence'; see our next section.
54 Cf. Poet. 19, 1456bl0-l.
55 For a survey of its various senses see De Rijk (1986) 225-31.
131
132
L.M. DE RIJK
133
7. Conclusion
Aristotle's semantics of the statement-making expression as occurring in De interpretatione is quite modest indeed, but serves its
purpose well enough for the narrow scope of issues he has to deal
with, given his main intention, viz. to set against Plato's ontology
his own view of how to speak about 'things' that really are the
case. 66 The semantics as set out in De interpretatione is suitably supplemented by the semantics of name-giving found in the Categories
and the doctrine of categorisation 67, which enables Aristotle to
develop a method of scientific inquiry, without having to take
recourse to Platonic transcendent Forms.68
BIBLIOGRAPHY
( 1) Primary works
Aristoteles graece ex recensione I. Bekkeri. Edidit Academia Regia Borussica. Aristotelis Opera, vol. I-II (Berlin 1831; reprint Darmstadt 1960)
Ross, W.D. (ed.), The Works of Aristotle translated into English. (Oxford, 1928ff.)
Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber de interpretatione . Recognovit brevique adnotatione
critica instruxit L. Minio Paluello (Oxford, 1949 19562)
A.M.S. Boethii Commentarii in lilnum Aristotelis IIepi. EPflTJVetm;. Recensuit Carolus
Meiser. Pars posterior secundam editionem et indices continens (Lipsiae
1880)
dvat.
134
L.M. DE RIJK
G. Kino
This is an old hobby horse, much ridden and rightly so, for
arguments concerning the eternity or destructibility of the cosmos
became a stock topic over a long period of the history of Greek
philosophy, the response and arguments coloured by the philosophical stance of each proponent. In modern scholarship, this fragment, located at Philo, De aeternitate mundi 117-149, has evoked
widely, not to say wildly conflicting views with regard to context,
provenance, influence and reliability from scholars such as Zeller
and Von Arnim on, 1 and has been much revived in the last
decade, with an important article by David Sedley on 'Theophrastus and Epicurean Physics' about to appear. Since Jaap Mansfeld
has himself richly engaged in the struggle, 2 it will seem imprudent or even impudent for an intruder to this particular paddock to
offer him some thoughts on the matter. The imprudence will be
only too obvious to him, but I hope he may excuse it remembering
our common fascination with the problems of fragmentary
evidence and a shared appreciation of their extreme difficulty and
danger; and the impudence will have to be forgiven in the light of
a long and much-valued friendship. And my contribution is very
limited, and skates over or ignores many detailed issues.
As with all fragments, it is best to keep distinct reporter, context
and reference. Since the only reporter who names Theophrastus
for these arguments is Philo, not only should we allow for Philonic intrusion, but also in general distinguish later influence of the
1 E. Zeller, 'Der Streit Theophrasts gegen Zeno iiber die Ewigkeit der
Welt', Hermes 11 (1976) 422-9; H. von Arnim, SW 1.106; but on the other
hand, H. von Arnim, 'Der angebliche Streit des Zenon und Theophrastos',
Jahrbii.cher fur classische Philologie, 39 (1893) 449-467.
2 E.g. 'Providence and Destruction of the Universe', Studies in Hellenistic
Religions, ed. MJ. Vermaseren (Leiden 1979) 129-188; 'Physikai doxai and
Problemata physika' in Theophrastus, His Psychological, Doxographical and Scientific
Writings, Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities 5 (New Brunswick 1992) 63-111; 'A Theophrastean Excursus on God and Nature and its
Mtermath in Hellenistic Thought', Phronesis 37 (1992) 314-335.
136
IAN G. KIDD
THEOPHRASTUS FR.
184
FHS&G
137
138
IAN G. KIDD
by the rain (12-13, 119). But the Greek for 'flat' is not, as one
would have expected, oj.LaAO<; or 1tdHov, but AEcocp6po<; (13, 119):
everywhere would have been broad highway, or motorway. This
extraordinarily flamboyant phrase9 brought me up short until I
discovered that it was a favourite metaphor in Philo for the smooth
main highway leading to virtue and to God. 10 Of course, later
language does not disprove earlier argument. But some of the
language seems tied up with the argument, like the Stoic (or
Philonic) vocabulary in Argument (iii) (see below). And indeed
some arguments themselves, such as the latter part of the extended
argument in Argument (ii), appear out of tune with the earlier part
(see below). There are suspicious details of examples or illustrations which reappear in later popular clusters (e.g. in the counter
arguments for Argument (ii), see below); and most notoriously,
from animal marvel lore, the extended with graphic and technicolour detail but hardly apposite illustration of nineteen lines to
Argument (iii), of snakes in India twining themselves round
elephants, and by draining their life blood, killing them, only to
perish themselves when the dying elephant fell on top of them
(59-77, 128-129). It is true that Theophrastus himself was into
marvel literature (Frs. 218, 236 FHSG); but much of the strange
illustrative detail in Philo has its cluster of popular echo in
Diodorus Siculus, Strabo, Seneca (NQ), Pliny, Lucan, and Aelian.
But, of course, later embroidery of detail or illustration in the
expanded arguments of Part (2) does not disqualify the spines of
argument from being original. Indeed the transmission of philosophical arguments, like the transmission of anecdotes, invites
such embroidery. And it can be proved with certainty that the
expansion of arguments in Part (2) does not come from Philo,
because the extended argument (iii) is reproduced in Lucretius 5.
235-317, and Philo's extended argument (iv) recurs in Lucretius
5.324-350. Furthermore, these two arguments follow in Philo and
9 In earlier philosophical Greek I can only bring forward the Pythagorean yvro1111= 1:a~ 't A.Ero<p6pou~ lllt Paoi1;;uv (58C6, 1.465.32 D-K; D.L. 8.17). Philo
himself quotes it at Prob. 2.
1
For the metaphorical use relating to the highway leading to virtue and
to God: Opif. 69, 144; Leg. III 253; Post. 31, 102, 154; Deus 61, 143, 165, 182; Agr.
101; Conf 19; Her. 70; Congr. 28; Fug. 203; Abr. 7;jos. 142; Mos. II 138; Decal. 50;
Spec. I 355; Spec. II 202; Spec. III 185; Spec. IV 62, 155, 167; Virt. 51; Legat. 216.
Philo also uses Aro<p6po~ literally, e.g. Det. 2; and twice referring to Moses'
parting of the waters: Mos. I 177; Contempt. 86.
THEOPHRASTUS FR.
184
FHS&G
139
140
IAN G. KIDD
THEOPHRASTUS FR.
184
FHS&G
141
Sen. NQ 6.30.3; Pliny NH 3.86; but these make clear that the
tradition is an old one. For Helice and Bura exampled as cities
swallowed by sea, compare Polyb. 2.41.7; Strabo 8.7.2; Ovid, Metam.
15.293f; Pliny NH 2.206; Pausanias 7.24.5f and 12f; 7.25.8; Amm.
Marc. 17.7.13. Interestingly for Theophrastus, the disappearance of
Helice and Bura was also associated with earthquakes as well as
sea. But although popular around Philo's time, the cited instances
of Bura and Helice are referred by Seneca (NQ 6.23.4; 7.5.3-4)
specifically to Aristotle and Callisthenes, Aristotle's nephew. The
story of Atlantis (150ff, 141) of course comes from Plato, Tim. 24E,
25CD. 15
Argument (iii) (41-79, 124-129) seems a more general argument, that of parts/whole correspondance in genesis and destruction. If parts are perishable, the whole will perish. But all parts of
the cosmos are perishable, therefore the cosmos is perishable. This
is illustrated by running through the four elements, but again by
observation as meteorological phenomena: the strongest stones
crumble and dissolve; water if stagnant become noisome; air can
become tainted, fire extinguished. Historical reference for this
argument surfaces strongly in hellenistic philosophy. It is certainly Epicurean, for it recurs in considerable detail in Lucretius 5.235317; but Stoic too, for Philo presents it in Stoic garb. It is true that
some of the Stoic vocabulary is also Philonic, but it can hardly be
denied that the framework is also Stoic in physical destruction
through the loosening of the 7tVEUJla'tuco<; 1:6vo<; as E~t<; ( 4 7), and the
death of water as if the removal of soul. In any case the argument
is independently given as Stoic by D.L. 7.141 ( SVF 2.589) . 16
However, the main Theophrastean counter argument to this (160ff,
143), is that Argument (iii) would hold if and only if all parts
perished together at the same time. But that is not so in the cosmos
when an element individually changes to another. But that is
normal Aristotelian doctrine frequently expressed,l7
15 D.T. Runia, Philo of Alexandria and the Timaeus of Plato, Philosophia
Antiqua 44 (Leiden 1986) 84f thinks the reference may come from Philo
rather than Theophrastus. But this is debateable, and even if it does come
from Philo, does it matter?
16 Which incidentally displays exactly the same reaction to the Theophrastean counter argument that Sedley claims for Lucretius and Epicurus, i.e.
change of elements into each other is destruction.
17 Ar. GC 11.4, 33lal2ff; De Caelo I.IO, 280al6ff; III.6, 304b23ff; Meteor. II.3,
357b27ff.
142
IAN G. KIDD
-~
THEOPHRASTUS FR.
184
FHS&G
143
144
IAN G. KIDD
23 H. Daiber, 'The Meteorology of Theophrastus in Syriac and Arabic Translation;' in Theophrastus: His Psychological, Doxographical and Scientific Writings,
16&-293.
24 Kidd, art. cit. (n. 22). So also, J. Mansfeld, 'A Theophrastean Excursus
on God and Nature and its Aftermath in Hellenistic Thought', Phronesis 3 7
(1992) 314-335.
25 Theophrastus of Eresus, Sources for his Life, Writings Thought & Influence, edd.
W.W. Fortenbaugh, P.M. Huby, R.W. Sharples, D. Gutas, 2 vols., Philosophia
Anti qua 54 (Lei den 1992).
Chi abbia una qualche familiarita con I' opera di Jaap Mansfeld sa
bene come anche una sola sua nota possa celare quantomai
inaspettati e suggestivi spunti per ulteriori succose ricerche. Questa
e il caso del mio contributo il cui germe e gia tutto nella frase di
una nota dell'articolo: 'Physikai doxai e problemata physica: Da
Aristotele ad Aezio (ed oltre) ': 1
Cio che vale per questa trattatello [scil. lo pseudo-aristotelico nept
apet&v Kilt K!lKtrov 0 nept apetilc;] vale anche per i Placita e per le
Divisioni aristoteliche. Bisogna tentare di rendere conto delle pluralita
delle tradizioni in gioco; ha poco senso cercare di ricostruire una
singola Urquelle.
E prendendo lo spunto da questa frase che vorrei, dunque, indagare Ia tradizione delle cosi dette Divisioni aristoteliche (d'ora in poi:
DA) in vista di una nuova edizione-mia o di altri-che sostituisca
quella vecchia e ormai superata di Hermann Mutschmann.2
La trasmissione delle DA e duplice. Da un lato esse sopravvivono
in tre codici medievali, dall'altro sono conservate, in maniera
affatto indipendente, da Diogene Laerzio. Si tratta di redazioni
diverse di un unico corpus o, forse, di singoli e distinti corpora, che
Caro ]aap ti chiederai perchi anch'io ti abbia "tradito" accogliendo ['invito a
partecipare a questo volume miscellanea: "ll cui diritto all'esistenza" tu-wilamowitzianamente-riterrai "non ancora del tutto accertato". Ma come dimostrare, seppure in
maniera affatto inadeguata, un minimo della affettuosa riconoscenza e della stima
infinita che mi legano a ter Il tema del mio intervento trova origine in una delle tue
illuminanti ricerche e ha come recondita speranza quella di aprire un dialogo con te: che
non sia solo ideate! Perchi-e mi auguro di non apparire troppo presuntuoso e irriverente
nella mia scoperta allusione-almeno una volta l'anno bisogna io appaghi il desiderio,
che mi tormenta tutto l'anno, di discutere con te di storia della filosofia antica.
I Mansfeld (1993) 370 n. 80.
2 Mutschmann (1906).
146
TIZIANO DORANDI
Knoepfler (1991).
DIVISIONI ARISTOTELICHE
147
148
TIZIANO DORANDI
DIVISIONI ARISTOTELICHE
149
150
TIZIANO DORANDI
DIVISIONI ARISTOTELICHE
151
152
TIZIANO DORANDI
DIVISIONI ARISTOTELICHE
153
discutere nei dettagli tutti i casi i cui Moraux ha operato sulle DA.
Noto solo che talvolta i suoi tentativi hanno dato origine a una
ricostruzione dubbia sia dal punto di vista testuale sia soprattutto dal
punto di vista filosofico, come ha chiarito la Rossitto nelle pagine
del suo commento.
Piu cautamente e con maggiore verisimiglianza, argomenta la
Rossitto:2 4
L compie interventi molto significativi sui testo, dando l'impressione di volerlo rendere piu coerente, o addirittura di correggerlo:
ad esempio esso ripristina spesso nella spiegazione l'ordine in cui i
termini appaiono succedersi negli elenchi iniziale o finale, o risulta "confermare" congetture di studiosi moderni, il che puo essere
considerato piuttosto una prova di congettura da parte del copista,
che non tradizione genuina o non inquinata del manoscritto.
Riserve avrei, semmai, sulle sue ulteriori conclusioni-ma di
questo in seguito:
II grado di "perfezione" che (L) sembra presentare parla a sfavore di
una sua maggiore fedelta a! testo primitivo rispetto aM, il quale, in
virtu delle sue non infrequenti, rna nemmeno decisive, incongruenze, e della sua rozzezza, rimane in fin dei conti Ia versione
delle Divisioni, tuttora maggiormente affidabile.
(1910).
26 Cf. Rossitto (1989) 213-215.
27 Gigon (1987) 318.
154
TIZIANO DORANDI
DIVISION/ ARISTOTELICHE
155
156
TIZIANO DORANDI
di Aristotele. Favorevole alia paternita aristotelica delle DA sembrerebbe fosse Ross, a meno a quanto si puo ricavare dalla sua
edizione degli Aristotelis Fragmenta selecta, dove le due redazioni
dello scritto (M e DL) vengono menzionate nella sezione sulle
opere di logica sotto il titolo ~tatptaEt~.35 I rapporti con l'insegnamento orale di Platone ha ulteriormente sviluppati Kramer36 per M
[67]-[68] e DL [32], divisioni nelle quali lo studioso individua una
probabile relazione delle dottrine non scritte di Platone elaborata da
Aristotele.37 E accanto a queste, le DA mostrano corrispondenze
anche con il pensiero di altri Academici antichi, talvolta rivisitato
attraverso il ripensamento di Aristotele. Una svalutazione globale
delle DA ha riproposto Moraux:3 8 si tratterebbe di un manuale
mediocre, senza originalita, ricolmo di piattezze, banalita e inezie,
anche se fondato su un sostrato che alia lontana risale a Platone e a
Aristotele. Per Gigon,39 le DA sono un excerptum, con fini protrettici,
di materiale derivato da distinti dialoghi di Aristotele; il loro
carattere prevalentemente etico mostra stretti parallelismi non solo
con i trattati aristotelici, rna anche con i dialoghi platonici. Esse
sono, dunque, da restituire a Aristotele e da ricondurre nell'ambito
della Academia Antica dove egli soggiorno a lungo, restandone
influenzato e a sua volta influenzandola. Infine, Ia Rossitto 40 ha
cercato di dimostrare che le DA hanno un grado di "aristotelicita"
non inferiore a quello delle altre opere scritte da Aristotele durante
il periodo academico e ne ha spiegato Ia peculiare natura con Ia
loro destinazione scolastica. Innanzitutto le DA mostrano numerose
coincidenze di contenuto con quanto Aristotele afferma nelle sue
opere, soprattutto quelle che possono essere fatte risalire al periodo
giovanile sia quelle frammentarie (Protreptico) sia quelle conservate (i Topici, il libro ~ della Metafisica e le Categorie); rna non
mancano neppure significativi paralleli con le due Etiche e Ia
Retorica. In secondo luogo, le DA presentano analoghe coincidenze
sia con le dourine degli Academici antichi (Speusippo, Senocrate,
Ermodoro) sia soprattutto con alcuni Dialoghi di Platone e con le sue
dourine orali; e, nondimeno, influssi dalla Rhetorica ad Alexandrum
35 Ross (1955) 101-102 = F 12 (DL) e 3 (M).
36 Kramer (1983) 141-142.
37 Gaiser-seguito da Kramer, in studi successivi-allarga il numero a M
DIVISIONI ARISTOTELICHE
157
158
TIZIANO DORANDI
159
DIVISION/ ARISTOTELICHE
48
tario.
Pagina destra
M
160
TIZIANO DORANDI
(s. IV a.C. ?)
(?)
a
(s. III d.C.)
DL
(?)
(s. XIII)
(s. XIII/XIV)
(s. XIV)
M
L
DIVISION/ ARISTOTELICHE
161
162
TIZIANO DORANDI
[10] DLMAL
DL
Titulus deest
ouup1-tm of. i] tuyivtta E~ tt&, 'tCttapa. v J.l.Ev, W.v cktv oi. ltpOyOVOt K:aAot Kaya&i Kat
OtK:Cl101, touc; EK: toutrov 'YEYEVVl]J.l.EVOUc; EilyEvEic; <j)CliHV dvat &A.A.o o, eav c1otv oi.
ltp6yovm Otouvau'tEUK:Ottc; Kai iipxovttc; 'YE'YEVTJJ.l.EvOt, touc; eK 'tOUtrov tuytvtic; <pautv
Eivat. &AM> o, eav cktv oi. ltpoyovot OVOJ.l.ClO''tOt, olov altO O"tpCltl]ytac;, altO O'tE<pClVtt&v
ayrovrov. K:Cll yap touc; EK: tOUtrov 'YYEVV1]J.l.EVOUc; EUyEvEic; ltpouayopEUOJ.l.EV. &AM> tiooc;,
eav autoc; nc; Uytvvaoac; tf\v 'lfUVlV K:Clt J.l.YClAO'IfUXOc;, K:Cll toutov Euytvf\ <pClO'tV ivat
K:Cll tf\c; 'YE ruytvdac; ClUtl] K:pattO'tl]. tf\c; iipa EUyEvdac; to ~v altO ltpoyovrov Elt1E1K:IDV. to
OE OUVClO"tiDV. to OE EVOO~rov. to OE altO tf\c; ClUtOU K:ClAoK:aya9\ac;
Bibl Mutschmann (1906) 12-13; Boudreaux (1909) 223-224; Moraux (1977) 106;
Rossitto (1984) 151-158
[36] DLML
DL
Titulus deest
to aya9ov de; tEttapa YEV1] 01CllpEitCl1' J>v Ev J.l.EV AEyOJ.l.EV EtVCll tOV tftV apEtftV E~Vt(l
io{~ aya96v . &AM> OE autilv tilv apttilv K:Cll tftV 01K:Cl10uUV1]V AEyOJ.l.EV aya9ov ElVCll.
tpttOV OE, OlOV O'lttCl K:Cll 'YlJJ.l.VllO'lCl tft ltpOO<popCl K:Cll <plipJ.l.ClK:Cl' tCtClptOV OE <j)ClJ.l.EV lvat
&ya96v, otov auA.l]nK:i]v K:al. ultoKpmK:i]v mi ta totauta. &ya9ou &pa tE-ttapa tt&, eu't{
tO J.l.EV to tftV apttilv EXElV, ettpov OE autil i] apttil. tpttOV OE O'lttCl K:Cll 'YlJJ.l.VllO'lCl ta
ID<pEA.tJ.l.Cl' tEtClptOV OE ClUAl]ttK:i]v K:Cll UnOK:ptnK:T]v K:Cll lt011]ttK:i]v aya9ov AEyoJ.l.EV dvm
Bibl Mutschmann (1906) 30-31; Moraux (1977) 110, 121; Rossitto (1984) 244-247
163
DIVISION/ ARISTOTELICHE
Titulus deest
Titulus deest
Olaipemc; e\ryeveiac;
ev
ev
ev
,...
ML
Ol!XlpEtt!Xl tO aya8ov de; tEcrcrapa ecrn yap IXUtOU Ev !1Ev a pEtit Kilt OlK!XlooUVTJ' EV OE tO
exov apEtlJV' Ev OE tO O"ll!l<pEpov' Ev OE tO tEp7tVOV Kilt tO ~OEcr81Xl1tOlOUV. olov apEtlt !lEV
Kilt OlK!XlOOUVTJ on toutrov EKUtEpov aya8ov AEyEt(lt Etvat I' Ev OE to f:xov apEtf,v' OlOV
t1t7tOc; Kill &v8p(l)1toc; Kill ta tOl!XUta Kilt yap tootrov EKIXO"tOV AZyEt!Xl aya8ov dvat, eav
xn tlJV apEtf!v. tO OE O"ll!l<JlEpov' otov YlJ!lVIXO"ta Kat <pap!laKEia Kat t&Ua ta 7tpoc;
irydav Kat EUE~iav. Kat yap tOOtrov EKacrtov AZyEtal aya80v dval ~2&v O"llll<JlEPU. to OE
tEp1tVov Kal. to ~OEcr8at 1towuv, otov imoKpttitc; Kat auATJtilc; Kat t&v ~projl.litrov evta Kat
ta tOtaUta 0 yap {moKpttitc; Kill llUATJtftc;, ou tip ro<pEAElV aya8ov AEyEtal 3 &Ua tip
tEp7tElv [tou &ya8ou dval]
1 M: AZyEtal L - 2M: roc; L - 3M: aya8ov dvat A.tyetal L
164
TIZIANO DORANDI
[30] MAL
M
Titulus deest
A
Titulus deest
ounpei:mt to &A.,eE~ d~
t pia. ecrtt yap autou EV !lEV
to 7tpiXY!la &A.,SE~ dvat, ev
OE tov A.Oyov, v oE Kat to
cruvall<pOtEpOV. ecrtt OE tg
7tp&Yila &A.,eE~ omv
outro~ exov Kat OUK liA.A.ro~.
otov to tov Seov aSavatov
dvat outro~ yap exu to
7tpilylla Kat ouK liUro~. to
oe A.f.yuv 'outo~ f.crttv
aA.11ffit~ A.Oyo~' tou aA.118ou~
E<JttV. ecrtt yap 0 A.Oyo~
1t p&Yila u1to tov A.Oyov
toutov ov. to OE A.f.yuv on
'oi.liv8pro7tot Ell'VUXOt dcrt'
Kat oA.Oyo~ aA.118Tt~ icrn Kat
to 1tp&ylla
ta crUVall<pOtEpa
L
otaipecrt~ ayaSou
omittit
Bibl Mutschmann (1906) 49-50; Boudreaux (1909) 223; Moraux (1977) 109;
Rossitto ( 1984) 223-230
L'aggiunta dell'elenco finale in A non prova che questo debba essere reintegrato in MeL. Cf. Rossitto (1984), 225-226. Non necessarie le correzioni di
Gigon in M: to OE AEyEtv, (... ) 'oUto~ ecrttv aA.11ffit~ A.Oyo~' [tou cXA118ou~ ecrnv].
[22] M L
Titulus deest in M
ovtrov OVOilacr{a~ L)
OtatpEttat i] trov ovtrov OVOilacr{a Ei~ 1tEVtE. ecrn yap autrov ta !lEV i.Xmep EV 1tp0~ 1tOAAa,
ta OE ro~ 1tOAAa 7tp0~ 1tOAAU Kat 7tp0~ EV' ta OE ro~ clVOilOta 1tp0~ OllOta, ta OE ro~ OllOta
7tp0~ OllOta, ta OE ro~ EV 7tp0~ EV. ecrtt OE to !lEV ro~ EV 7tpo~ 1tOAAU otov taxtcrto~ Kat
llEYtcrtO~ Kat KaAAtcrto~ Kat taUa ta to taut a. ta OE ro~ 1tOAAU 7tp0~ 1tOAAU Kat 7tp0~ EV'
otov 1tA.Eiro taoe trovoe Kat llet/;ro taoe trovoe Kat KaUiou~ o'loe trovoe Kat tliUa tO.
tOtauta. tO. OE ~ cXVOilota 1tp0~ Ollota, otov 1ta~p 1tp0~ ui.ou~ Kat 0Ecr1t0tll~ 7tp0~ oouA.ou~
Kat tliUa tO. totauta. tO. OE ~ OllOta 7tpo~ OllOta, otov clOEAcpOt 7tpo~ aoeA.cpou~ Kat cplA.ot
7tpO~ cplA.ou~ Kat tO. totauta. tO. OE ~ ev 7tp~ ev, otov KaUirov ooe touoe Kat Sacrcrrov ooe
tOUOE Kat ta totauta
BibiMutschmann (1906) 46-7;Moraux (1977) 107-108, 115;Rossitto (1984) 186-192
Ho riprodotto il testo stabilito da Moraux. L conferma Ia lacuna per saut du
mime au mime in M gia individuata e parzialmente restaurata da Rose. II testo
di L puo essere accolto anche se exempli gratia a colmare Ia lacuna; non e
esclusa, infatti, una diversa disposizione degli esempi o un numero variato.
Piu sicura Ia proposta di integrare Ia frase finale nella redazione di L
sfigurato, di nuovo, da una piccola lacuna per saut du mime au mime (oOE ... ooe).
DIVISIONI ARISTOTELICHE
165
Biedl, A. (1955) Das Grosse Excerpt IP. Zur Textgeschichte des Laertios Diogenes
(Citta del Vaticano)
Boudreaux, P. (1909) "Un nouveau manuscrit des Divisiones Aristoteleae", Revue
de Philologie 33: 221-224
Gaiser, K. (1963) Platons ungeschriebene Lehre (Stuttgart) Testimonia Platonica
Gigon, 0. (1987) Aristotelis opera. III: Librorum deperditorum fragmenta (Berolini
et Novi Eboraci)
Hambruch, E. (1904) Logische Regeln der Platonischen Schute in der Aristotelischen
Topik (Berlin)
Heitz, E. ( 1868) in Aristotelis Opera omnia graece et latine (Parisiis)
Knoepfler, D. (1991) La Vie de Menedeme d'i:retrie de Diogene Laifrce. Contribution a
l'histoire et a la critique du texte des Vies des Philosophes (Basel)
Kramer, H.J. ( 1983) Altere Akademie in Flashar, H., ed., Die Philosphie der
Antike, 3. Altere Akademie, Aristoteles, Peripatos (Basel-Stuttgart)
Mansfeld, J. (1993) "Physikai doxai e problemata physica da Aristotele ad Aezio
(ed oltre)" in Battegazzore, A.M., ed., Dimostrazione, argomentazione dialettica e argomentazione retorica nel pensiero antico (Genova) 311-382
Moraux, P. ( 1977) "Temoins meconnus des Divisiones Aristoteleae", L 'Antiquite
Classique 46: 100-127
Mutschmann, H. (1906) Divisiones quae vulgo dicuntur Aristoteleae (Lipsiae)
Pasquali, G. (1910/1986) "Doxographica aus Basiliusscholien", Nachrichten der
Akademie der Wissenschaften in Giittingen, phil.-hist. Kl.: 194-228 = Scritti
filologici (Firenze) 1, 539-574
Praechter, K. (1910) Rec. di Mutschmann (1906), Berliner Philologische Wochenschrift 30: 387-395
Rose, V. (1863) Aristoteles Pseudepigraphus (Lipsiae)
Ross, W.D. (1955) Aristotelis Jragmenta selecta (Oxford)
Rossitto, C. ( 1984) Aristotele e altri. Divisioni. In trod., trad. e comm. (Padova)
--(1989) Rec. di Gigon (1987), Elenchos 10: 213-215
Suckow, F.G.G. (1855) Die wissenschaftliche und kiinstlerische Form der Platonischen
Schriften in ihrer bisher verborgenen Eigenthiimlichkeit dargestellt (Berlin)
Souilhe, J. (1930) Platon, Oeuvres completes. Dialogues apocryphes: 13.3 (Paris)
Wilpert, P. (1941) "Neue Fragmente aus llEpt taya8ov", Hermes 76: 236-241
- - (1949) Zwei aristotelische Friihschriften iiber die Ideenlehre (Regensburg)
CNRS, Paris
Una stesura dell'articolo ha letto con Ia consueta disponibilita e sostanziali suggerimenti, soprattutto per Ia costituzione dello 'stemma', il Prof. R.
Kassel (Koln). Di alcuni punti ho discusso con profitto con i miei colleghi e
amici L. Brisson (Paris), R. Chiaradonna e E. Spinelli (Roma).
PART FOUR
170
JONATHAN BARNES
n. 41.)
171
172
JONATHAN BARNES
published his On Zeno. And if for Aristo, surely also for Zeno and
Cleanthes ... and Chrysippus?
Hence Apollonius did not himself compile the Chrysippean
list-or at any rate, he was not the first to compile such a list.
Perhaps there were catalogues in the library of the Stoa, which
Panaetius and Sosicrates had consulted? Perhaps Apollonius
merely prepared these for public consumption, adding a few
embellishments of his own? 15 All this is lamentably vague; but I
doubt if we should speak with confidence of Apollonius as the
compiler of the Chrysippean catalogue.
However that may be, there are more important questions to
broach: in particular, how close is the catalogue to Chrysippus
himself? Did the compiler arrange the works to reflect the scope
and structure of Chrysippus' logical interests, or does the articulation of the catalogue tell us more about the compiler's own
interests? Did he copy Chrysippus' titles, or did he (in some or all
cases) invent titles of his own? 16 It is generally assumed without
argument that the catalogue gives us reliable information about
Chrysippus. Here is an argument. It starts from a remote origin.
The catalogue presents all the minor problems which beset any
text of Diogenes. There are also two major problems. First, the
logical section of the list ends by observing that the total number of
books in Chrysippus' logical oeuvre was 311 (Of.LOU 'ta 7tUV'ta 'tOU
A.oytKou na': VII 198). But if you count the works which Diogenes
lists you will not readily arrive at that figure. Secondly, the ethical
part of the catalogue-the surviving fraction of the ethical partcontains several titles which apparently point to a logical rather
than an ethical content: On Divisions and On Contraries, for example;
or On Dialectic and On the Objections to the Dialecticians. Can these
really be titles of works whose main effort was devoted to ethics?
Why not amalgamate the two problems? Suppose that a few
pages in a manuscript copy of Diogenes worked loose and were
15 Note that Strabo says that he made them public (h9Ei~). not that he
collected the materials for them.
16 We should not assume without ado that Chrysippus entitled his writings. Note e.g. that Plotinus gave no titles to any of his essays-those of his
pupils who managed to get hold of copies gave them different titles (Porphyry, Vit. Plot. 4: see Brisson et al ( 1982), 283, n.1). Similarly, Galen did not give
titles to writings which he sent to his pupils and friends, and he complained
that these works were later in circulation under different titles (Lib. prop. XIX
10-11 K). Many of Chrysippus' works are addressed to pupils and friends.
173
later replaced in the wrong order; and that this disorderly copy is
the source of our modern text. Then if we cunningly rearrange the
pages we may, at one blow, save the arithmetic at VII 198 and
restore to their proper place the logical works which now appear in
the ethical part of the list.17
First, let us look more closely at the arithmetic. The first four
logical 't07tot contain, by my count, 118 works divided into 263
books. (But in at least three places the manuscripts offer variant
readings for the book numbers, 18 so that the transmitted total is
between 261 and 265.) The total includes four works in eight books
which are marked as spurious; and it is not clear whether they
should be included in the arithmetic. In addition to the contents of
the first four 't07tOt, there are the 39 books mentioned at VII 198.
Hence in all there are 303 books, plus or minus two (or 295, plus or
minus two, if we do not count the spurious items). 19 Thus we are
between 18 and 6 short of the desired total of 311.
It is easy to emend the text: for example, read 'ta' ('301 ') instead
of na', and then take the lower of the variant readings. But the
possibilities are so many, and corruption of numerals is so common,20 that it is a waste of time to play the numbers game. Hence it
is tempting to observe that the transmitted numeral is not wildly
out, to conclude that Chrysippus' logical bibliography contained
about 300 books, and to abandon as delusory the hope of establishing a precise figure.
But this leaves aside the second of the two major problems.
Roughly speaking, the apparently logical items in the ethical part
of the catalogue are the contents of the second, third, fourth and
fifth cruv'ta~n<; of the first ethical 't07tO<; and the contents of the first
and second cruv'ta~n<; of the second 't07tO<;. In all, they amount to 26
works in 70 books. Suppose that the text were rearranged so that all
these items appeared in the logical section: then the total number
of logical books would be about 370. (And should we emend na'to 'toa'?2 1)
17 For an example of this sort of thing see Egli ( 1967) 3.
18 I rely on the notoriously unreliable OCT: doubtless there are variant
174
JONATHAN BARNES
175
On the Soul and Physics (Diogenes Laertius, VII 50, 54, 55).
2 See e.g. Long (1978) 117-118, who appeals to the idea that 'the study of
dialectic, for Chrysippus at least, is an integral part of moral conduct'. Such
an idea might lead you to range all logical titles under the heading of ethics;
but it does not yet explain how you could place some of them under ethics
while leaving most in an independent section on logic.
Ch~sippus'
176
JONATHAN BARNES
constructed on the basis of titles alone: the compiler must have had
some knowledge of the contents of the works he was cataloguinghe must have unrolled at least a few columns of text.
This claim remains plausible even if the catalogue has been
substantially deranged. For some of the titles in the logical section
itself are puzzlingly placed.29 Had the compiler looked no further
than the title of, say, llr8awx IVVTJJ.lJ.lEVa, he could have had no
reason to place the work in the first-and no doubt introductory't07t0~.30 Its position suggests that he must have troubled to form
some idea of its contents.
Secondly, the book-titles must come from Chrysippus and not
from any compiler; for a compiler would surely have given each
work a title appropriate to the position it was to hold in his list. If
you have an untitled work which you intend to place in the first
ethical 't07tO~, you will not call it On Dialectic: you will give it a name
which fits its place-for example, Dialectical Matters bearing on Ethics.
This second claim also remains plausible even if the catalogue
is seriously disturbed. Suppose that the compiler found an untitled
work which, on the basis of its contents, he decided to place in the
first part of the logical section: would he have given it the bald title
Plausible Conditionals?
With these two claims I have returned to my sheep: the
catalogue has an honest pedigree. No doubt the compiler made
mistakes: he certainly missed a few works,3 1 and he probably misplaced others. No doubt the list has been damaged in transit.
Certainly there are titles whose import remains opaque to us. Nonetheless, we may properly boast that we possess a fairly competent
and a fairly well preserved and a fairly intelligible list of Chrysippus' logical writings. In particular, we may confidently use the
titles as evidence of Chrysippus' own logical lexicon; and we may
plausibly discern in the catalogue a general indication of Chrysippus' logical interests-of the topics he did and did not discuss, of
29 You might, of course, hypothesize serious local disruptions (compare the
case of Aristotle's catalogues); but I have not managed to contrive an interestin~ hypothesis in this vein.
0 On the work-the title of which is usually misunderstood (e.g. Hadot
(1994) 338)-see Barnes (1985).-The Mss. give no subtitle to the first 'tonoc;:
von Arnim (1903) II 4, rightly suggested something like 'Aoyu(Qu 'tonou <'tou
1tEpi 't~V ouxp9pcootv 'tiDV A.oyuc&v evvot&v>' (misreported by Hiilser ( 1987) 172).
3! See Hiilser (1987) 190-191.-1 assume that he was trying to give a
bibliography of Chrysippus' works rather than, say, a list of the Chrysippean
holdings in some library.
177
33 See Nachmanson (1941) 50-52; compare Dyroff (1896) 14-15. Note also
178
JONATHAN BARNES
179
I LOGIC
A: Introductory
B: ~YJI't
1. Simple a~tcOJ.UX't(X
2. Complex a~tcOJ.La.ta.
3. Non-&~tcOJ.La.'ta.
4. Incomplete AEK'ta
5. 1t'tc00t<;
C: AS..;
1. Questions of usage
2. Elements and syntax
3. Ambiguity
0: A6yot
1. Forms of argument
2. Arguments
3. J.LE't<X1tl1t'tOV't<;
4. Hypotheses
5. The Liar
6. The Liar
7. Other paradoxes
8. The Nobody
9. Sophisms
10. croV'Tl9da.
E: Miscellaneous
II
ETIHCS
F: Introductory
1. Definitions
2. Definitions etc
3. Definitions etc
4. Etymology
5. Poetics
G: Kotv~~
1. General
39 A-H are the toltot, numbered sections are auvta~Et~. My names for tOltOt
derive from the text; I have invented names for the auvta~Et~.
180
JONATHAN BARNES
2.
3.
H: The
1.
Dialectic
The Virtues
Good and the Bad
Pleasure
A*: Epistemology
1. cpav'tacr{a
2. a\cr6l,crt<;
3. evvota
4. The Kpt't'fJptov
B*: ll@t cprovijc;
1. cprovf)
2. AE~t<;
3. O"'tOtXEta
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
aj!cpt~oJ.{a
6. Puzzles
The Summary (Diogenes Laertius, VII 41-48) :
4. Epistemology
5. Dialectical virtues
181
42
182
JONATHAN BARNES
b. Quasiconditionals
c. Conjunctions
d. Disjunctions
e. Causals
f. Comparatives
g. Conditionals
44 Numerals in bold give the position of the item in the catalogue: the
first logical 't01toc; contains six items, so that [7] is the first item in the second
'to1toc;.
183
h. Quasiconditionals
i. Causals
(iv) Modal a~te.OJ.La'ta
a. Plausible
b. Possible/impossible
B 2: 7tEpt ouva'to>V [22]
c. Necessary/non-necessary
No doubt the differences between the two columns were not as
great in reality as they appear in the table-thus, for example, the
fact that no title in the catalogue corresponds to 'categoricals' in
Diodes' account hardly implies that Chrysippus had nothing to
say on the topic. Nonetheless, real differences remain, and some at
least of them are to be explained by the fact that the account refers
to Stoic logicians who worked after Chrysippus.
From this spattering of factlets, what to infer? Suppose (as seems
pretty plausible) that the arrangement of items in the account
reflects a Stoic handbook on logic. Suppose (as seems mildly plausible) that the arrangement in the catalogue also reflects a Stoic
handbook. 45 In that case, the account certainly reflects a postChrysippean handbook; and the catalogue certainly reflects a
different handbook-and probably an earlier handbook. Hence-a
leap but not an Olympic leap-the catalogue may well reflect a
Chrysippean handbook.
In truth, this final argument is made of gossamer. But the
question of the structure of the catalogue is in any event of less
concern that the questions of its scope and its terminology.
Small beer, alas. And I had wished to offer a large vodka.
Geneva
BIBLIOGRAPHY
184
JONATHAN BARNES
Brisson, L., Goulet-Caze, M.-0., Goulet, R., and O'Brien, D. (edd.) (1982)
Porphyre: la vie de Plotin, I (Paris)
Brunschwig, J. (1991) 'On a Book-Title by Chrysippus: "On the Fact that the
Ancients Admitted Dialectic along with Demonstrations"', in Blumenthal and Robinson (1991)
Celluprica, V. ( 1989) 'Diode di Magnesia fonte della dossografia stoica di
Diogene Larzio', Orpheus: 10, 58-79
Cronert, W. (1906) Kolotes und Menedemos (Munich)
Dorrie, H. ( 1970) 'Chrysippos', Paulys Realencyclopiidie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft suppt XII (Stuttgart)
Dorandi, T. (1990), 'Filodemo storico del pensiero antico', in Haase (1990)
Dorandi, T. (1991) Ricerche sulla cronologia dei filosofi ellenistici, Beitriige zur
Altertumskunde 19 (Stuttgart)
Dorandi, T. (1992) 'Considerazioni sull'index locupletior di Diogene Laerzio',
Prometheus 18: 121-126
Dorandi, T. (1994) Filodemo: storia dei filosofi-la Stoa da Zenone a Panez.io (PHerc.
1018), Philosophia Antiqua 60 (Leiden)
Dyroff, A. (1896) Uber die Anlage der stoischen Biicherkataloge, Programm des ...
Gymnasiums zu Wurzburg (Wurzburg)
Egli, U. (1967) Zur stoischen Dialektik (Basel)
Giannattasio Andria, R. (1989) I frammenti delle 'Successioni dei filosofi', Universita degli studi di Salerno, quaderni del dipartimento di scienze
dell'antichitii 5 (Naples)
Gigante, M. ( 1983) Diogene Laerz.io: Vite dei filosofi (Rome/Bari, 2nd edn.)
Goulet, R (1989a) 'Apollonios de Tyr', in Goulet (1989b) 294
Goulet, R. (1989b) (ed.) Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques I (Paris)
Goulet, R. (1994) (ed.) Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques II (Paris)
Haase, W. (1990) (ed.) Aufsteig und Niedergang der romischen Welt II.36.4
(Berlin)
Haase, W. (1992) (ed.) Aufsteig und Niedergang der romischen Welt 11.36.6
(Berlin)
Hadot, P. (1994) 'Liste commentee des oeuvres de Chrysippe (D.L. VII 189202)', in Goulet (1994) 336-356
Hahm, D. (1992) 'Diogenes Laertius VII: On the Stoics', in Haase (1992)
Hulser, K.-H. (1987/8) Die Fragmente zur Dialektik der Stoiker (Stuttgart/Bad
Cannstatt)
Ierodiakonou, K. (1993) 'The Stoic Division of Philosophy', Phronesis 38: 57-74
Long, A.A. (1978) 'Dialectic and the Stoic Sage', in Rist (1978)
Mansfeld, J. ( 1986) 'Diogenes Laertius on Stoic Philosophy', Elenchos 7: 295382 (reprinted in Mansfeld ( 1990))
Mansfeld, J. (1990) Studies in the Historiography of Greek Philosophy (Assen)
Mejer, J. (1978) Diogenes Laertius and his Hellenistic Background, Hermes
Einzelschriften 40 (Wiesbaden)
Nachmanson, E. (1941) Der griechische Buchtitel, Goteborgs Hogskolas Arsskrift
47 (GOteborg)
Rist, J.M. (ed.) (1978) The Stoics (Berkeley/Los Angeles/London)
Tieleman, T.L. (1992) Galen and Chrysippus-Argument and Refutation in the De
Placitis Books II-III, Quaestiones Infinitae 3 (Utrecht)
CICERO'S ROPE
R. j.
HANKINSON
186
R.
J.
HANKINSON
CICERO'S ROPE
187
188
R.
J.
HANKINSON
<in the past>. This, then, will be the source of what happens by
chance, and will have nothing else as the cause of its coming to be.
(1: Metaph. Z 3, 1027a29-1027bl4)
This text has been much discussed, and there is little agreement as
to its import. My translation is tendentious (although not I hope
unwarrantedly so). What Aristotle is saying here (if I am right) is
not that some occurrences are uncaused or unnecessitated, 5 but
rather that some cannot be properly explained, where proper
explanation has to do, as we have seen, with the propagation (in
one way or another) of form. It is not that the hapless individual's
death is uncaused-it is rather that the causal chain (as we might
say) that leads from his predilection for hot foods via his
consequent thirst and his desire to slake it to his unfortunate
meeting with the ruffians at the well is not such as to instantiate, in
its totality, any generally-repeating process. 6 That is why the
causes in such chains come to be without any process of
generation: there is nothing, prior to the coincidence, which can
be said in any generally illuminating way to be leading up to it. In
this sense, nothing leads up to it.
The crucial point is that coincidences are intersections of processes: JCtvftcrw;. 7 Aristotle devotes most of the second half of the
Physics to an analysis of JCtvftcretc;: but for our purposes the important
thing about them is that they have beginnings, middles and (most
importantly) ends (Phys. V 1, 224a34-b16, 225a12-34). Not all
5 These do not (necessarily) come to the same thing: see Sorabji (op. cit.,
n. 3), chs. 1-3; I do not, however, agree with Sorabji's interpretation of this
passage. See D. Frede, 'Aristotle on the limits of determinism: accidental
causes in Metaphysics E 3', in A. Gotthelf (ed.) Aristotle on Nature and Living
Things (Bristol/New Brunswick) 1985, for an account with which I am more
in sympathy.
6 Compare Aristotle's other canonical example of coincidence: happening
to run into someone who owes you money and recovering your debt: Phys. II
5, 196b24-197a5; see W. Charlton, Aristotle's Physics I, II (Oxford 1970) 105-11,
for a useful discussion of this and related passages.
7 It is not clear that all such intersections are coincidences for Aristotle,
since some might be held to be predictable from within the working-out of a
particular process-indeed I am tempted to see the generation of substantial
form as having this structure. Here two processes (that in the male and that
in the female) intersect; but while the particular manner, time and place of
their intersection is not predictable from within either process, that there
will be such intersections presumably is; moreover, in the appropriate way,
the creation of a new substantial form is instantaneous, and not itself the subject of generation in time. This is speculative, and needs more working out
than I can give it here. However I note, proleptically, that if this is right,
then the Aristotelian and the Stoic accounts will be even more closely related.
CICERO'S ROPE
189
changes are Ktv-ftcretc;, however (Phys. V 2); in particular, instantaneous changes from one state to another do not qualifY (although
they may, as in the case of the generation of substances, occur as a
result of processes). Processes have an internal cohesion and a
natural direction. They may be as simple as the falling of earth to
its natural place 8 or as complex as those involved in animal
metabolism; but they share a crucial characteristic. Once begun,
their progress towards their ends is natural, intrinsic to the order of
things, and will (other things being equal) result in the process's
successful completion.
When the process fails to fulfil itself, that failure will be neither
uncaused nor utterly inexplicable; but it will be attributable to
factors external to the development of the form itself. Thus not all
acorns become saplings and not all saplings oaks; in some cases
the oak form will have been insufficiently firmly imprinted in the
original woody matter (for various reasons: Gen. Anim. IV 4-6), in
others external conditions will have been unpropitious (drought,
insufficient sunlight) or directly inimical (lightning, squirrels).
All of this suggests that for Aristotle it is the processes which are
basic. 9 Processes are not simply aggregates of discrete events,
describable in some suitable four-dimensional spatio-temporal
language 10 (indeed, I am inclined to think that the concept of an
event, at least as it is deployed in contemporary analytical philosophy, is quite alien to the ancients). And while processes evidently
have temporal stages which stand in relations of succession to one
another, on this metaphysical view there is no temptation to suppose with Hume that what causation amounts to is the mere
sequence of discrete events (and hence to make the causal relation
utterly mysterious), nor either to imagine that somehow each
such event is metaphysically dependent in some way upon its
predecessor. Equally, the difficulty that Russell felt to be fatal to the
entire concept of causation, namely that causally-significant events
8 The fact that Aristotle refers to such natural motions as involving the
perfection of form becomes perfectly intelligible on the interpretation being
offered: Cael. IV 3, 310a32-b1; cf. I 8, 276a23ff.
9 This may sound bizarre: of course on Aristotle's own account it is the
category of substance which is fundamental, and in terms of which
everything else must be explained (cf. e.g. Cat. 1-5; Metaph. H); but the upshot
of my suggestion is that Aristotelian substances (or most of them) may be
re'iarded as processes.
For a sophisticated modern defence of this philosophical position, see
D.Wiggins, Sameness and Substance (Oxford 1980), esp. 25-6.
190
R.
J.
HANKINSON
CICERO'S ROPE
191
process or change, what drives it; and such sources are coeval with
their effects.I 4
n
Metaphor is strikingly absent from Aristotle's treatment of these
issues; 15 not so from the Stoics'. For the Stoics, everything that
occurred in the world was the result of the working out of fate,
iJ,.UXpj.LEvT]:
Chrysippus described (in the second book of his On the Cosmos) the
substan~e (o~cria) of fate as t~e pnel!matic power I~ which goyerns
everythmg m orderly fashiOn (ta~Et tou navtoc; OtOlKTitlKTIV) ....
Elsewhere he describes it in several ways, as the logos of the
cosmos, the logos of the things which are governed by providence
in the cosmos, or the logos according to which things that have
occurred have occurred, things which are occurring are occurring
and things which will occur will occur. ( 2: Stobaeus I 79.1-12, = S VF
2.913, = 55M L&S)
That image of government, OtotlCT]crtc;, is found elsewhere in texts
reporting the Stoic position:
Fate is a continuous cause ( aitia dpOIJ.EVTl) of things, or the logos in
virtue of which the world is administered. (3: DL 7.149; cf. 8 below)
But more important for our purposes is the metaphor of the continuous thread, the a.itia dpoj.LEVT] (cf. the /..6yoc; dp6j.LVoc; of Arius
Didymus Fr. 29, = SW 2.528). Hicks in the Loeb translates: 'Fate is
defined as an endless chain of causation, whereby things are, or
as the reason or formula by which the world goes on', which
seems to me to be multiply misleading. Nothing in the Greek
corresponds to Hicks' 'endless'; 17 'whereby things are' is a needless
14 This is partly what causes Aristotle's notorious difficulties with projectile motion: if the spear continues to move after it leaves contact with the
thrower's hand, something must still be pushing it (Phys. VIII 10, 266b29267all).
15 Unless you count as metaphoric the apxi] in his standard expression for
the efficient cause, UPXTJ lClVlt0'(1)~.
16 I.e. the power manifested in the pneuma, the all-pervasive dynamic
constituent of the universe which is responsible for its cohesion: cf. e.g. D.L.
7.138-9 (= SW 2.634, 470 LS); Cicero, ND 2 22 (= 47C LS); Galen, Plen. VII 524
Kuhn (= SW 2.439, 47F L&S); Plutarch, Comm. Not. 1085c-d (= SW 2.444, 47G
L&S); see also 47 1-M L&S; and see further below.
17 Although the Stoics do think that the sequence of causes is endless (see
n. 18, and text 10, below): Alexander fastens upon this aspect of their theory
in order to argue that such an infinite sequence of causes would render the
cause (or explanation) unknowable, since knowledge just is knowledge of the
primary cause: Fat. 25, 196.1ff Bruns,= SW 2.949. Alexander here confuses the
192
R.
J.
HANKINSON
CICERO'S ROPE
193
the chain is perfectly appropriate. The Stoics will, after all, be seeking to emphasize the fact that causal sequences are sequences of
distinct events, like the beads on a necklace, somehow joined
together.
I think that this conclusion can and should be resisted. It is
worth reiterating the connection of eipJ.lO<; with etpro and etpOJ.iat: it
is a verbal noun, capturing the process of the stringing together.
More significantly, however, consider the other expressions that
are used alongside eipJ.lO<; ainrov, presumably by way of exegesis.
In the texts cited above (SW 2.917-20), we have ta~t<;, (mcruv8ecrt<;,
and UKOAou8ia. Gellius reports that:
in the fourth book of his On Providence, Chrysippus says that 'fate is a
certain natural, eternal ordering of the whole, in which things are
consequent upon and follow one another, and in which the interweaving is ineluctable'. (7: Noct. Att. 7.2.3, = SW2.1000, = 55KL&S).
Plotinus writes that those who believe in:
the interweaving ( E7tt7tAOKtl) of causes with one another, the etpiJ.~
from above, and the invariable consequence of later occurrences
upon earlier ones ... evidently introduce fate in another manner [sc.
from that of the astrologers]. 19 (8: Enn. 3.1.2, = SW 2.946; cf. ibid.
3.1.4, = SW2.934)
In the course of elaborating an objection (unjustified as it will
turn out) to the Stoic account, namely that it makes every prior
event a cause of every subsequent one, absurdly (since thereby day
would be the cause of night, and summer of winter: Fat. 25, 194.
25ff., 195.13ff. = SW2.948; 22 below), Alexander speaks of them as:
positing a certain binding together ( em<rUvBmt<;) and cohesion
(cruVEXEta) of causes, and holding this to be the reason why nothing
comes to be causelessly. (9: Fat. 25, 195.4-5 Bruns,= SVF2.948).
194
R.
J.
HANKINSON
member? (10: ibid. 196.1 Bruns,= SVF 2.949; see 14 below; and nn.
17, 18 above)
'Binding together', 'cohesion' and 'interweaving', along with
'ordering' and 'consequence', clearly do not emphasize the supposedly discrete nature of each cause in the sequence.
Latin texts reporting or reflecting Stoic doctrine support this.
Cicero writes:
I call 'fate' what the Greeks call EiJla.pJlEVT]: and ordering and
sequence of causes ( ordinem seriemque causarum), since cause being
connected to cause brings things to be out of itself; it is an everlasting truth which flows from all eternity. (11: Cicero, Div. 1 125, =
SW2.921, = 55L L&S; cf. Servius ad Verg. Aen. 3.376, = SW2.920)
And Augustine:
'Those (i.e. the Stoics) who call by the name of 'fate' not the
arrangement of the stars but rather the connection and sequence of
causes ( conexionem seriemque causarum) .... attribute the ordering of
causes itself and that particular connection to the will and power of
God the supreme'. (12: m 5.8, = SW2.932)
Moreover, this emphasis is buttressed by considerations deriving from the Stoics' analysis of the causal relation.2 Sextus
Empiricus reports that
the Stoics say that every cause is a body which becomes a cause to a
body of something incorporeal. For instance the scalpel, a body,
becomes the cause to the flesh, a body, of the incorporeal predicate
'being cut'. ( 13: Adv. Math. 9.211, = SW2.341, = 55B L&S; cf. SW 1.89,
2.336)
Causes are bodies, effects are predicates (or rather attributes). Thus
it cannot be the case in any straightforward manner that the effect
of a previous cause may itself in turn be the cause of a subsequent
effect.2 1 Causation is not, then, to be understood on the model of a
sequence of events, each of which brings about its successor, as in a
row of falling dominoes.22 That may be how opponents such as
20 On the Stoic analysis of causation, see M. Frede, 'The original notion of
cause' in J. Barnes et aL (eds.) Doubt and Dogmatism (Oxford 1980); see also
J. Barnes, 'Skepticism and causation', in M.F. Burnyeat (ed.) The Skeptical Tradition (California 1983); and RJ. Hankinson, The Ancient Concept of Explanation,
Oxford, forthcoming, ch. 7; and 'Causation and explanation' and 'Determinism and indeterminism, both in J. Barnes, J. Mansfeld, M. Schofield
(eds.) Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy (Cambridge, forthcoming).
2l As noted by F.H. Sandbach, The Stoics (Bristol 19892) 81-2; I disagree
with Sandbach, however, in his characterization of Stoic effects as events.
22 Although there are ancient analogues to such a notion: cf. Galen, On the
Differences of Symptoms VII 47-9 Kiihn. In such sequences, Galen stipulates that
CICERO'S ROPE
195
each item causes its immediate successor 'primarily and essentially', its more
remote consequents 'secondarily and incidentally', 'thirdly and incidentally', and so on.
23 Reading evEpy&c; with Usener and von Arnim, against the MSS.
reading vapy&c; preferred by Long and Sedley.
196
R.
J.
HANKINSON
CICERO'S ROPE
197
198
R.
J.
HANKINSON
CICERO'S ROPE
199
200
R.
J.
HANKINSON
SW2.916)
III
What is the upshot of all of this? First of all, I have been trying to
bring out the Stoics' own emphasis on the essential continuity of
the processes involved. Where the working out of one process abuts
spatia-temporally against a suitably-disposed body, another process
is set in motion: and here the one (or rather the object in which the
process is embodied) may be said to be the cause to the other of the
new process (entirely congruently with the canonical form of
Stoic causal sentences: see above, p. 194). Thus the Stoics are by no
means committed to supposing, as Alexander would have them
absurdly do, that every temporally precedent stage of every process
is the cause of every subsequent stage,3I although for the Stoics any
particular stage of a process will in a sense be causally relevant to
others, since they will, other things being equal, be inferable from
30 Or 'change', or 'process':
KtVTJC1t<;.
CICERO'S ROPE
201
202
R.
J.
HANKINSON
their first thesis [cf. 14 above], namely that of all the things that are,
some become causes of things after them, 35 and things depend
upon one another in this way, namely with the second depending
upon the first in the manner of a chain ( OtKi)v aJ.:uaE~), which is
what they take to be the essence of fate ... ( 22: Fat. 23, 193.4-8, = SVF
2.945)
The second passage occurs immediately after his explanation of
the true causes of summer and winter:
nor is it the case, because day is not the cause of night and nor is
winter of summer, and these things are not interwoven ( EJl7tE7tAEKtat) with one another in the manner of a chain ( aA:uaEroc; OtKi)v ),
that they would come to be without a cause,3 6 nor that if they did
not come to be in this way the unity of the cosmos and of
everything which exists and comes to be within it, would be torn
apart. (23: ibid. 25, 195.13-16, = SW2.948; cf. 14 above)
What are we to make of this? Even if the chain-metaphor as it is
34 Cf. Hdt. 9 74 (the Athenian hero Sophanes secures himself to the
ground in battle with an anchor tied to his corslet by means of a chain);
Polybius 3 82 8, 32 3 6, of chains used for securing captives: note the idiom eis
halusin agein, to throw into chains: ibid. 4.76.5, 20.10.7-8, 21.5.3.
35 Both text and translation here are problematic. Sharples (Alexander of
Aphrodisias on Fate, London, 1983, 71) accepts Bruns' text (ro~ 1t<Xvtmv toJV ovtmv
ait{mv ttvmv ytvollevmv t&v !lEta tauta) and translates 'that all the things that
are become causes of some of the things after them' (i.e. everything that exists
comes to be a cause for at least something subsequent to it); but this seems to
me to be an impossible construal of the Greek. On the other hand, my
translation, while a good deal less tendentious as an interpretation of Stoic
doctrine, does not seem capable of doing the work Alexander requires of it
(his subsequent counterexamples consist of cas.es where something fails to be
the cause of anything subsequent, cases which would not be ruled out by my
translation of the thesis here). Sharples is no doubt influenced by considerations of what Alexander needs to say for his argument (and text 8, to which
Alexander refers here, certainly suggests, although it does not explicitly
state, that the thesis in question is that everything is a cause for some subsequent event). There is an alternative textual tradition (ro~ t&v t&v ovtmv aitimv,
etc.) which would encourage the translation 'of the causes of things, some
occur of things subsequent to them', i.e. some causes precede their effects,
would be equally unexceptionable as an account of Stoic doctrine, but equally
incapable of bearing the weight of Alexander's argument here. Alexander
may perhaps have intended first to argue, on general Peripatetic principles,
against the thesis that any cause can precede its effect, before turning to attack
the stronger claim that everything has some subsequent effect.
36 The text is once again problematic, but the difficulties are not pertinent
to our purposes. See Sharples (op. cit. n. 32) for useful comments ad Zoe., as
elsewhere.
CICERO'S ROPE
203
204
R.
J.
HANKINSON
IV
I hope, then, to have demonstrated that the Stoics did not adopt the
chain as a metaphor for continuing causal sequence and dependence: and for good reasons. John Venn sought an alternative
metaphor, that of the rope. If I am right, this is, in effect, very
much the force of the Stoic eipJloc;, properly interpreted. There is,
however, one text which explicitly mentions ropes:
it is not the case that the things which are going to be simply
spring into existence; rather the passage of time is like the unwinding of a rope ( rudentis explicatio), 38 producing nothing new, but
merely unrolling each thing for the first time. ( 25: Cicero, Div. 1
127, = sw 2.944, = 550 L&S)
The unfolding of time simply brings to light what is already
implicit in the structure of things, a picture reinforced by a passage
a page or so earlier:
since this is the case, nothing occurs which was not going to be,
and in the same way nothing is going to be for which nature does
not already contain causes productive of it. (26: ibid. 1.125-6, = SVF
2.921 = 55L L&S: follows 11 above)
Wesley Salmon, who quotes Venn as the envoi to his article ('Causality', art.cit., n. 2 above), might as felicitously have cited Cicero.
In this article he seeks to undo what he takes to be the damage
done to our philosophical accounts of causation by an uncritical
acceptance of the Humean model. Causation, in his view ('Causality' 155-6), primarily involves two types of process, production and
propagation. Production involves the creation of something new,
propagation the transmission of something already existing. Moreover, production consists in the interaction of processes, 'the means
by which structure and order are propagated or transmitted from
one space-time region of the universe to other times and places'
(169). For Salmon, processes, not events, are ontologically fundamental (170-1).
There is, of course, much in Salmon's position which has nothing whatever to do with the Stoics. Salmon is expressly concerned
with developing an account that will apply to probabilistic causation, 39 a concept without parallel in the ancient world, not least
Intriguingly, von Arnim's index to SVF reads: rudens: = O:A.\}(nc;, repeatGellius's mistake.
9 Cf. the articles cited in n. 2 above.
38
in~
CICERO'S ROPE
205
Die Letzten, die sich zur Lebensweise des Aristipp und den Lehren
seiner Anhfmger bekannteni, waren-etwa in der Zeit des ersten
Ptolemaerkonigs-Hegesias, Annikeris und Theodoros und eine
Generation spater deren Schuler, die uns fast ausnahmslos nicht
mehr namentlich bekannt sind2. Seit der Mitte des dritten
Jahrhunderts v. Chr. gibt es in den uns erhaltenen Quellen keine
Hinweise mehr auf eine weitere, jungere Generation von
Kyrenaikern, und bezeichnenderweise findet schon kurz vorher
der Spott uber sie mit Alexis sein Ende3. Unter den ubrigen Dichtern erinnert nur der gelehrte Elegiker Hermesianax an Aristipp
und zwar an dessen Liebe zu Lais (frg. IV A 94 Giannantoni = frg.
2, 95-98 Diehl)' wahrend Timon Aristipp und dessen 'tpU<j>Epi] <jlucrt~
ebensowenig verschont wie andere Philosophen (frg. IV A 51
Giannantoni = frg. 27 di Marco).
Von den Philosophen selbst werden in den ersten heiden
Generationen nach Aristoteles-sieht man von Epikur ab-nur
biographische Einzelheiten uberliefert etwa von Phainias in der
Schrift uber die Sokratiker (frg. IV A 1 Giannantoni = frg. 31
Wehrli), vielleicht beilaufig von Chamaileon (frg. IV H 11 Giannantoni4) und von Philipp dem Megariker (frg. IV E 5 Giannantoni = frg. 164 A Doring5); dasselbe gilt auch fur Kallimachos (frg.
IV H 27 Giannantoni = frg. 438 Pfeiffer). Nur Bion von Borysthenes, der zeitweilig Schuler des Theodoros war (frg. IV H 28 =
1 Die Zeugnisse und Fragmente sind zusammengestellt und teilweise
auch erliiutert von E. Mannebach (1961) und G. Giannantoni (1990).
2 Annikeris hatte noch einen Bruder Nikoteles und einen Schuler
Poseidonios (frg. IV G 2 Giannantoni).
3 Frg. IV A 9 Giannantoni = frg. 37 Kassel Austin; zur Bezeichnung
croqncrn\~ s. Giannantoni (1958) 21; 31-32; Classen (1986) 193; 212. Alexis frg.
IV A 71 Giannantoni = frg. 241 Kassel Austin liil3t sich nicht mit Sicherheit
auf Aristipp beziehen.
4 Wehrli schreibt Chamaileon die Bemerkung iiber Theodoros' Tod
nicht mehr zu (frg. 35), s. auch Manne bach ( 1961) frg. 266. Zu den iilteren
Berichten iiber Aristipp s. Classen (1986) 267-271 mit Anm. 13-39 (zuerst
1958) und Doring (1988) 62-69.
5 Eine genaue Datierung ist nicht moglich.
207
208
209
Schriften 12. Lucilius ist dann der erste Romer, der-soweit die
triimmerhafte Uberlieferung uns zu urteilen erlaubt-Aristipp
erwahnt (frg. IV A 145 Giannantoni = frg. 800 Krenke}l3) und zwar
ein Buch, das Aristipp dem Tyrannen Dionys geschickt habe,
wieder ein Stiick Biographie oder wohl eher eine Anekdote. So
stellt sich die Frage, welche Kenntnisse die Romer spater von
Aristipp und seinen Anhangern hatten und wie sie zu ihnen
gelangt sein mogen.
In seinen friihen Schriften spielt Cicero nur einmal auf Aristipp
an, und zwar auf einen der Ausspriiche iiber den Umgang mit
iiberfliissigem Reich tum ( inv. 2, 176 = frg. IV A 83 Giannantoni);
und eine Anekdote, die z.B. Vitruv (6,1, 1) und Galen (Protr. 5) auf
Aristipp beziehen, fiihrt er sogar nur mit der unbestimmten
Formulierung ut mihi Platonis illud, seu quis dixit alius, perelegans esse
videtur (rep. 1,29 = frg. IV A 50 Giannantoni) ein. Auch spater
begegnen Anekdoten fast nie, nur in den Tuskulanen eine kiihne
Antwort des Theodoros auf eine Drohung des Konigs Lysimachos
(1,102 = frg. IV H 8 Giannantoni) und in einem Brief an Paetus
Aristipps beriihmter Ausspruch iiber sein Verhaltnis zu Lais (Jam.
9,26, 2 = frg. IV A 95 Giannantoni).
Von der Philosophic Aristipps und der Kyrenaiker spricht
Cicero zum ersten Mal in seiner Ubersicht iiber die sokratischen
Schulen (de orat. 3, 61-62 = frg. I H 4 Giannantoni): Neben Platon
und Antisthenes nennt er Aristipp, begniigt sich hier allerdings
nicht (wie bei Antisthenes) mit einem Hinweis auf die besondere
Vorliebe fiir bestimmte Inhalte der sokratischen Dialoge und
einem weiteren auf die von ihm ausgehende Cyrenaica philosophia;
er charakterisiert auBerdem Aristipps und seiner Schiiler Umgang
mit den eigenen Anschauungen knapp, ehe er sie den zeitgenossischen Vertretern ahnlicher Lehren gegeniiberstellt 14 : Das offene
Bekenntnis zur Lust, das jene friiher einmal ablegten (simpliciter
defenderunt), scheint ihm den Vorzug zu verdienen gegeniiber
210
denen, qui nunc voluptate omnia metiuntur, also den Epikureern, die
sich doch weder voll zur voluptas noch zur dignitas (der Menschen)
bekennen.
Erst in den philosophischen Schriften der letzten Jahre spricht
Cicero ein wenig haufiger von Aristipp, dessen Lebensweise,
dessen Anschauungen und den Lehren der Schuler. Allerdings
beriihrt er nur wenige Aspekte und seine Formulierungen bleiben
meistens sehr allgemein. Eine Priifung der einzelnen Stellen zeigt
zunachst, daB bald Aristipp allein, bald Aristipp und die Kyrenaiker, bald diese allein genannt werden, und zwar oft so, daB sie
mit anderen Philosophen verglichen oder kontrastiert werden.
Genaueres Hinsehen lehrt, daB Cicero nur einmal die Schrift
eines Kyrenaikers anfiihrt, den 'A1t01capn:prov des Hegesias ( Tusc.
1, 84 = frg. IV F 4 Giannantoni), also nie ein Werk des alteren oder
des jiingeren Aristipp, und sehr vorsichtige Formulierungen
wahlt, wenn er die Meinungen oder Lehren Aristipps oder der
Kyrenaiker erwahnt. Wo er sich auf den alteren oder jiingeren
Aristipp bezieht, gebraucht er gern Wendungen wie Aristippi est
oder voluptas illa Aristippi15 oder Ellipsen 16, ahnlich bisweilen auch
bei den Kyrenaikern 17. Fiir den alteren oder jiingeren Aristipp
wahlt er dan eben je einmal dicit und dicere (jin. 2, 19 und Tusc. 2, 15
= frg. IV A 183 und 204 Giannantoni), einmal ducit, einmal ponit in
voluptate ... non dolere: (jin. 2, 41 und 2, 19 = frg. IV A 185 und 183
Giannantoni) und einmal sententia (jin. 2, 19, s. auch Tusc. 2,15 =
frg. IV A 183 und 204 Giannantoni), das er daneben auch einmal
fiir Aristipp und die Kyrenaiker verwendet (sententiae ... :fin. 2, 39 =
frg. IV A 185 Giannantoni) 18, einmal fiir diese allein ( Tusc. 3, 52 =
frg. IV A 208b Giannantoni); fiir sie finden sich auBerdem posuerunt, censuerunt und censent19 , non recusant und negant (jin. 2, 114 und
15 Fin. 1, 23 (= frg. IV A 180 Giannantoni) und 2, 35 (nicht bei Giannantoni); s. ferner fin. 2, 18 und 20 illud Aristippeum (genus); fin. 2, 34-35 ... fines ...
Aristippo simplex voluptas, ... unus Aristippi vel Epicuri ... Aristippo voluptas; fin. 5,
20 ... principes: voluptatis Aristippus (= frg. IV A 183, 184 und 187 Giannantoni),
auch ac. pr. 2, 139 Aristippus ... solum corpus tuetur (s. auch fin. 2, 18) = frg. IV A
179 (und 183) Giannantoni.
16 Fin. 1, 26 und 2, 18 (quam Aristippus) = frg. IV A 181 und 183 Giannantoni.
17 Fin. 1, 39: conclusum est ... contra Cyrenaicos; Tusc. 3,31: accipio ... a Cyrenaicis haec arma = Frg. IV A 182 und 208a Giannantoni.
18 Fur sie zusammen auch simpliciter defenderunt (de orat. 3, 62, s.o.); ... esse
voluerunt, quorum princeps Aristippus, ... unde Cyrenaici (ac. pr. 2, 39) = frg. I H 4;
IV A 178 und 185 Giannantoni.
19 Off 3, 116: Cyrenaici atque Annicerii ... omne bonum in voluptate posuerunt
211
ac. pr. 2, 76 = frg. IV A 186 und 209b Giannantoni) sowie putant und
putent (ac. 2, 142; 2, 20 und Tusc. 3, 76 = frg. IV A 209a, 209c und
208c Giannantoni). Fiir Theodoros20 (immer zusammen mit
Diagoras) gebraucht er putaverunt, deorum naturam sustulerunt und
deos esse negabant (nat. deor. 1, 2; 1, 63 und 1, 117 = frg. IV H 19a; 19b
und 19c Giannantoni). Dagegen heiBt es in den Tuskulanen a
Cyrenaica Hegesia sic copiose disputatur (1, 83 = frg. IV F 3 Giannantoni), unmittelbar bevor dessen Buch erwahnt wird.
Auffallig ist weiterhin, daB Cicero gelegentlich, wenn auch
selten genug, den alteren Aristipp eindeutig bezeichnet, etwa als
Schiiler des Sokrates (ac. pr. 2, 131 = frg. IV A 178 Giannantoni2I),
nie jedoch den von den Griechen als jlT]'tpooioax:'toc; charakterisierten Enkel (cf. e.g. Strabo 17, 3, 22 und Diog. Laert. 2, 83 und 86
= frg. IV B 1 und IV A 160) und daB er nur einmal einen Aristipp
(den alteren oder den jiingeren) mit den Kyrenaikern unmittelbar
zusammennimmt (fin. 2, 39 = frg. IV A 185 Giannantoni), ihn
sonst aber deutlich von ihnen absetzt22 oder allein von Aristipp23
oder allein von den Kyrenaikern24 spricht; eine Systematik bei
der Verwendung der einzelnen Bezeichnungen ist nicht erkennbar25.
SchlieBlich tallt auf, daB sich das, was Cicero iiber Aristipp und
die Kyrenaiker sagt, auf sehr wenige Themen beschdinkt, und auf
sehr vage und allgemeine Aussagen iiber diese Themen, und weiter, daB er deren Anschauungen in der Regel neben die anderer
Philosophen riickt, sei es daB diese vergleichbare oder entgegengesetzte Positionen vertreten. Diese Beobachtungen erlauben die
Vermutung, daB Cicero weder je ein Werk des alteren noch des
virtutemque censuerunt; Tusc. 3, 28 und 52 = frg. IV A 189; 208 a und 208 b
Giannan toni.
20 Zweimal erzahlt Cicero Anekdoten von Theodorus, Tusc. 1, 102 und 5,
117 (= frg. IV H 8 und 7 Giannantoni) und einmal von Anti pater ( Tusc. 5, 112
= frf IV C 1 Giannantoni).
2 Vgl. ferner de orat. 3, 62 (s.o.), Tusc. 2, 115 Socraticus Aristippus und auch
off 1, 148 si quid Socrates aut Aristippus contra morem ... fecerint (= frg. I H 4; IV A
204 und 83b Giannantoni).
22 Ac. pr. 2, 131; fin. 1, 23; off 3, 116 = frg. IV A 178; 180; 189 Giannantoni.
23 Cf. ac. pr. 2, 139; fin. 1, 26; 2, 18-20; 34-35; 41; 5, 20; nat. dear. 3, 77 = frg.
IV A 179; 181; 183; 184; 185 (amEnde); 187; 161a Giannantoni.
24 Cf. ac. pr. 2, 20; 76 (Cyrenaei}; 142;fin. 1, 39; 2, 114; Tusc. 3, 28-31; 52; 76
(Konjektur) = frg. IV A 209c; 209b; 209a; 182; 186; 208a; 208b; 208c
Giannan toni.
25 Dort wo die Cyrenaici allgemein genannt werden, wird fast stets gegen
Epikur polemisiert.
212
JUngeren Aristipp gelesen hat, sich aber auch nicht auf Handbiicher mit Darstellungen der einzelnen Philosophenschulen
stiitzt, sondern auf Passagen bei anderen Philosophen, die sich auf
Aristipp und dessen Anhanger berufen oder gegen sie polemiSleren.
Damit wird zugleich die Frage aufgeworfen, welche Anschauungen und Lehren der Kyrenaiker Cicero iiberhaupt kennt und
warum er sie erwahnt.
Die erkenntnistheoretischen Probleme, die Cicero in den Academica erortert, geben ihm AnlaB, mehrfach von den Kyrenaikern
zu sprechen. Zunachst verweist Lucullus in seiner Rechtfertigung
der Moglichkeit von Erkenntnis, die er mit Ausfiihrungen iiber
die Zuverlassigkeit der Sinne beginnt, auf den 'inneren Tastsinn',
der Schmerz oder Lust empfindet und mit dem, wie er hinzufiigt,
fiir die Kyrenaiker das einzige Wahrheitskriterium gegeben ist
( ac. pr. 2, 20 = frg. IV A 209c Giannantoni). Ganz ahnlich klingt
die Beschreibung, die Cicero selbst in seiner Entgegnung von der
Lehre der Kyrenaiker gibt, die er hier als minime contempti philosophi
bezeichnet ( ac. pr. 2, 76 = frg. IV A 209b Giannantoni2 6 ); sie
konnten, wie er sagt, nur erfassen (erkennen), was sie mit dem
inneren Tastsinn spiirten, und er fiigt hinzu, sie wiiBten nicht,
welche Farbe oder welchen Klang etwas habe, sie empf'anden nur,
daB sie irgendwie betroffen seien. Gegen Ende des Dialogs
schlieBlich kommt Cicero noch einmal auf die Position der
26 Die Lesart Cyrenaei iiberrascht (und wurde schon von Lambin 1573
durch Konjektur in Cyrenaici geiindert, das einige Editoren in den Text
aufgenommen haben); denn die Griechen unterscheiden KupT]va\:oc;
(Einwohner von Kyrene) und KupT]Yai:Koc; (Anhiinger der Philosophie der
Kyrenaiker). Doring ( 1988) 35-37 bestreitet dies unter Berufung auf die
Formulierung, mit der Diogenes Laertios 2, 83 (= frg. IV A 144 Giannantoni) die erste Liste der Schriften Aristipps einleitet, und glaubt, daB
Diogenes 2, 86b-93 (= frg. IV A 172 Giannantoni) "referiert, ... was er als
orthodoxe, auf den Auffassungen Aristipps basierende Lehre in seiner Quelle
bzw. seinen Quellen verzeichnet fand" (35). Er erkliirt nicht, warum
Aristipp in den Quellen so oft von den Kyrenaikern getrennt wird (s. auch
o. Anm. 14 und 22) und z.B. iiberall dort, wo es urn erkenntnistheoretische
Probleme geht, Cicero, Plutarch oder Sextus Empiricus nie von Aristipp,
sondern stets nur von den Kyrenaikern sprechen bzw. Aristokles von oi EK
tile; KuptiYTJc; oder oi Kat' 'ApianmtOY (toY KupT]YatoY) (Doring (23): "die nach
allgemeiner Auffassung in der Nachfolge des Aristipp aus Kyrene philosophieren ") und dane ben von oi 1tpl 'tOY 'E1tl1COUpOY ElC tf\c; 'Apt<J'tl1t1t0\J otayroyf\c;
op~tc6~tYOt (frg. IV A 209-219 Giannantoni). Ich bin eher geneigt, an jeweils
einmalige Irrtiimer bei Cicero und Diogenes zu glauben (ac. pr. 2, 76 und
Diog. Laert. 2, 84 = frg. 209 und 144 Giannantoni).
213
214
(2, 15 = frg. IV A 204 Giannantoni28), weil er sich auf die sehr allgemeine Aussage summum malum dolor beschrankt, der er ahnlich
knappe Formulierungen zu anderen Philosophen entgegensetzt.
Auch in seiner einleitenden Kritik an Epikur in de finibus
bedient sich Cicero, sobald er sich der Ethik zuwendet, nur sehr
allgemeiner Formulierungen fiir die Kyrenaiker: Der Grundsatz,
daB voluptas und dolor alles bestimmen, was wir erstreben oder
meiden, wird vor Epikur auch schon von Aristipp vertreten und
von den Kyrenaikern besser und freimiitiger verteidigt (1, 23 = frg.
IV A 180 Giannantoni), eine Bemerkung, die er durch einen sehr
scharf kritisierenden Zusatz erganzt. Ahnlich heiBt kurz darauf ...
voluptatem ... summum bonum ... ante Aristippus, et ille melius (se. quam
Epicurus) (1, 26 = frg. IV A 181 Giannantoni). Damit greift Cicero
auf, was er schon bei der ersten Vorstellung Aristipps und seiner
Anhanger in de oratore iiber sie und Epikur sagte: daB sie zusammengehoren und daB die Kyrenaiker ihre Position freimiitiger,
rigoroser (d.h. wohl ohne Riicksicht auf die Konsequenzen,
mogen sie auch noch so abstoBend sein) vertreten, anders als
Epikur und dessen Anhanger, von denen es dort heiBt dum verecundius id agunt, nee dignitati satis faciunt, quam non aspernantur, nee
voluptatem tuentur, quam amplexari volunt (de orat. 3, 6229 )' wahrend
Cicero hier von dem voluptas-Begriff der Kyrenaiker sagt eius modi
esse iudieo, ut nihil homine videatur indignius (fin. 1, 23).
Dagegen laBt Cicero Torquatus ein wenig spater nicht nur den
Unterschied zu den Kyrenaikern durch den Hinweis betonen, der
mit Hilfe der unbewegten Hand der Chrysippstatue gewonnene
SchluB richte sich gegen sie, nicht gegen Epikur, er legt dem
Epikureer noch eine Uberlegung in den Mund, die die voluptasvorstellung der Kyrenaiker deutlicher werden lassen soli (fin. 1, 39
= frg. IV A 182 Giannantoni): ''Wenn allein das Lust sei, was die
Sinne gleichsam kitzele-um es einmal so zu formulieren-und
mit SiiBigkeit auf sie zustrome und in sie hineingleite, dann ...
konne kein Teil des Korpers zufrieden sein mit der Freiheit vom
Schmerz ohne eine angenehme Lustbewegung." Offensichtlich
ist Cicero mit der Definition der voluptas (iJooviJ) als A.eia KiVT\<n<;
vertraut (cf. Diog. Laert. II 86 = frg. IV A 172 Giannantoni), und
dies wird durch mehrere Passagen im zweiten Buch de finibus
215
216
urn die jeweiligen Grundsatze geht, nicht urn die Einzelheiten der
verschiedenen Systeme34.
Auch die Frage, ob eine These von dem alteren oder dem jiingeren Aristipp oder von allen Kyrenaikern vertreten wurde, stellt
Cicero nicht. Ihm geniigt es, eine ethische Position anfiihren zu
konnen, deren Verfechter die voluptas-simplex, sola, summa-als
summum bonum, als finis ansahen, expers honestatis, quae maxima
dulcedine sensum movet, und entsprechend dolorals summum malum35,
und eine weitere, nach der-im Gegensatz zu anderen-nicht
jedes Unheil Betriibnis aufkommen laBt, sondern nur unvermutetes und nicht erwartetes3 6 , ferner eine erkenntnistheoretische,
nach der der innere Tastsinn als einziges Wahrheitskriterium
anzusehen ist, und eine 'theologische', nach der die Existenz der
Gotter geleugnet wird und fur die es ihm nicht so wichtig ist, sie
mit den iibrigen Anschauungen der Kyrenaiker zu verkniipfen,
als zwei Reprasentanten zu nennen, neben Diagoras auch Theodoros37.
Fassen wir zusammen. Wie andere Romer, friihere, gleichzeitige und spatere, kennt Cicero einige Anekdoten iiber Aristipp und
dessen Anhanger, die deren Lebensklugheit und Unabhangigkeit
illustrieren3 8 AuBerdem ist er mit einigen philosophischen
Grundsatzen Aristipps und der Kyrenaiker vertraut, vor allem mit
ethischen, auf die er sich in der Regel bezieht, urn gegen sie und
Epikur oder mit ihrer Hilfe gegen Epikur zu polemisieren oder urn
Meinungen und Anschauungen anderer Philosophen durch
Vergleich oder Kontrast deutlicher herauszuarbeiten. Den Versuch, alle Lehren der Kyrenaiker zusammen zu erfassen und als
34 Das gilt auch fiir die kurze Bemerkung off. 3, 116 (= frg. IV A 189
Giannantoni).
35 Simplex: fin. 2, 34; sola: fin. 2, 41; summa: fin. 2, 41; summum bonum: fin. 2,
19; finis: ac. pr. 2, 131; expers honestatis: fin. 2, 35; quae maxima dulcedine sensum
movet:fin. 2, 39 (cf. auchfin. 1, 39 undfin. 2, 18); dolor: Tusc: 2, 15 (= frg. IV A
184; 185; 183; 178; 182 und 204 Giannantoni).
36 Cf. Tusc. 3, 28-31; 52; 75-76 (= frg. IV A 208 Giannantoni).
37 Cf. nat. deor. 1, 2; 1, 63; 117 (= frg. IV H 19 Giannantoni).
38 Von den friiheren ist nur Lucilius zu nennen (frg. 800 Krenke! = frg.
IV A 145 Giannantoni), von den gleichzeitigen nur Vitruv (6, 1, 1 = frg. IV A
50 Giannantoni), von den spateren Horaz (frg. IV A 45; 80; 100 Giannantoni), Valerius Maxim us, Seneca, Apuleius, Celli us, Porphyrio, Ausonius und
Ps.-Caesius Bassus (= frg. IV A 47; 65; 104; 49; 45; 80; 100; 81 Giannantoni); zu
Aristipps Lebensart s. Tertullian apol. 46, 16 (= frg. IV A 54 Giannantoni);
Anekdoten aus Ciceros Werken geben Laktanz und (zu Theodoros) Valerius
Maximus und Seneca wieder, aus Gellius (zu Aristipp) Augustin: frg. IV A 83
und 95, H 8 und A 49 Giannantoni.
217
39 Vgl. Kleitomachos frg. 10 Mette; Sotion frg. 7 Wehrli und Sen. epist.
89, 12 (= frg. IV A 172 und 168 Giannantoni). AuBerdem ist, wie Doring
(1988) 69 mit Recht betont, anzunehmen, daB die Lehre der 'eigentlichen'
Kyrenaiker (vor Annikeris, Hegesias und Theodoros) erst allmiihlich ihre
endgiiltige Form in der Generation des jiingeren Aristipp fand. Entsprechend wird sie in den einzelnen Phasen ihrer Entwicklung in verschiedener Weise von ihren Gegnern angegriffen worden sein (zu Aristoteles s.
Doring ( 1988) 69 Anm. 146), was die spiitere Uberlieferung, soweit sie sich
auf polemische AuBerungen stiitzte, gepriigt haben diirfte.
4 ! Wenn Epikur und seine Anhiinger auch oft in die Niihe von Aristipp
und den Kyrenaikern geriickt werden, so ist nicht zu vergessen, daB Epikur
und seine Schiiler immer wieder gegen sie polemisieren, was hier nicht im
einzelnen belegt zu werden braucht.
4 1 Vgl. Val. Max. 8, 9 ext. 3 aus Cic. Tusc. 1, 83 (= frg. IV F 5 und 3 Ginannantoni), ferner Quint. inst. 12, 23-24; Min. Fe I. 8, 1-2; Lact. inst. 3, 7, 7; 3, 8,
6-10; 7, 7, 11; epit. 28, 3; 34, 7; 63, 1; ira 9, 7; 10, 47; Arnob. nat. 4, 29; Aug. c.
acad. 3, 11, 26; c. Julian. 4, 14, 72; civ. 8, 3; 18, 41; Eucher. epist. ad Val. p. 724
Migne (= frg. IV A 190; IV H 21; IV A 191; 193; 194; 195; 192; IV H 20; H 22;
IV A 210; 188; I H 13b; 13c; IV A 196 Giannantoni); s. dazu auch die von mir
angeregte, nicht verOffentlichte Magisterarbeit von B. Ch. Weber, Die Rezeption dcr Lehren des Aristipp und dcr Kyrenaikcr durch die ROmer, Gottingen 1993.
218
so verrat er nicht Kenntnis der Philosophie der Kyrenaiker (praecepta), sondern illustriert seine eigene Unabhangigkeit, die sich
am Aristipp der Anekdoten orientiert und es ihm erlaubt, ebenso
mit dessen Worten iiber Lais zu spielen (18-19) wie auch einmal
eine 'stoische' Position einzunehmen (16-17)42.
Die lebensbejahenden Gedanken und Lehren Aristipps und der
Kyrenaiker, von Epikur verdrangt und zur Bedeutungslosigkeit
verurteilt, noch ehe die griechische Philosophie nach Rom kam,
haben dort nie selbstandig FuB fassen konnen. Sie haben den
Romern allein dazu gedient, die Lehren anderer Schulen klarer
zu beschreiben oder die Philosophie zu bekampfen, der sie selbst
hatten weichen miissen.
Gottingen
219
BIBLIOGRAPHIE
Fragmentsammlungen auBer denen von v. Arnim, Hense, Jacoby, KasselAustin, Muller, Pfeiffer und v. Straaten:
Angeli, A. (1981) 'I frammenti di Idomeneo di Lampsaco',Cronache Ercolanesi
11: 41-101.
DiMarco, M. (1989) Timone di Fliunte. Silli (Roma).
Doring, K. (1972) Die Megariker (Amsterdam).
Giannantoni, G. (1958) I Cirenaici (Firenze).
- - ( 1990) Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae I-IV (Napoli).
Giannattasio Andria, R. ( 1989) I .frammenti delle 'Successioni dei .filoso.fi' (Napoli).
Gigante, M. (1983) 'Frammenti di Ippoboto', in Omaggio a Piero Treves, a cura
di A. Mastrocinque (Padova) 151-193.
Kindstrand, J.F. ( 1976) Bion of Burysthenes (Uppsala).
Krenkel, W. (1970) Lucilius. Satiren 1-11 (Leiden).
Marx, F. (1904-1905) C. Lucilii Carminum Reliquiae 1-11 (Leipzig).
Manne bach, E. (1961) Aristippi et Cyrenaicorum Fragmenta (Lei den).
Mette, H. J. (1985) 'Kleitomachos von Karthago', Lustrum 27: 142-148.
Wehrli, F. (1969) Die Schute des Aristoteles IX: Phainias von Eresos. Chamaileon.
Praxiphanes (Basel).
- - (1978) Die Schute des Aristoteles, Supplement II: Sotion (Basel).
Die Abkurzung frg. ist von mir weitgehend auch dort verwandt worden, wo
genau genommen nur Nachrichten, also testimonia, vorliegen.
Aufsatze und Monographien:
P. H.
ScHRIJVERS
221
been fair because they parcelled out fields to each man and
divided flocks among them, according to their inborn qualities:
beauty, strength, intelligence (5.1110-1111). In accordance with the
ancient, traditional definition of OtKatO<JUVTJ their measures may be
considered an act of distributive justice.3 In spite of the fair
character of their rule these so-called kings did not feel secure;
they founded citadels as strongholds and refuges for themselves
(5.1109 praesidium reges ipsi sibi perfugiumque). Moreover, at a later
moment, this kingship became arrogant (1137 sceptra superba) and
in the end the kings were dreaded overmuch by the population
(1140 nimis ante metutum). Ancient political thought and historical
writing have their stereotyped descriptions: being frightened and
frightening others at the same time is what characterizes the
tyrant. 4 In the view of Lucretius these kingships, good at the start,
changed gradually into tyrannies (second form of government
implied by his text).
In his description of the good kings Lucretius mentions a
category of men distinguished by their inborn qualities, by their
aretai. Here the poet seems to define the class of aristocrats. Mter the
invention of property and the discovery of gold the privileged
position of real aristocracy was taken over by 'the richer men'
(5.1115 divitioris), the plutocrats, and-according to traditional
definitions in the political thought of the Ancients-wealth is the
characteristic feature and basis of oligarchy. 5
These oligarchs (the wealthier people are in my opinion subject
in line 1120: at claros homines voluerunt se atque potentis) wished to be
famous and powerful and started to contest the supremacy of the
called kings compare Polybius 6.7 (and the comm. by Walbank): ... JtOtouvtat
I.I.E'tCx ta\ita 'tlJV atpEOtV 'tCOV ap;(OV'tCIJV Kat jJacnAECIJV ... Kata 'tCx~ tijc; yvW/111<; Kat 'WV
A-ortO/lOV ozmpopac;... !lEV ouv Jtaf..<nov veritpaoKov tai~ pamM:iat~ ol. Kpt6vtt~ ...
'fOirOV<; 'tE Otaq>epovta~ OXVP01J/1EVOI Kat rezxft;ovrec; Kat xropav ICa'falC'fW/lEVOl, cf.
5.1107-1110 and Th. Cole, 'The Sources and Composition of Polybius VI',
Historia 13 (1964) 450-451.
3 Cf. Polybius on the good king (6.6.11) Otavti.I.T)'ttKO~ ... tou Kat'a~iav EKaotot~
and Aristotle w 1250a12 OtKatOOUVT) OE EO'ttV apE'tlJ vuxft~ OtavqtT)'ttKTJ 'tOU
Kat'a~iav, SW3.262 ElttOtTti.I.TI UltOVE1.1.1]'tt~Clj rft~ a~{a~ EKacmp
4 Cf. Polybius 5.11.6 on the tyrant: rvpavvov !lEV yap epyov EO'tt 'tO KaKro~
Jtotouvta tip q~6pcp oroJto/;ttv aKouoirov ./1zaov11evov ~eai 111aovvm toil~ imotattol.l.fvou~.
and Cicero, De rep. 2.45 (rex ille) cum metueret ipse poenam sceleris sui summam,
metui se volebat.
5 Cp. Aristotle, Pol. 2.8.5, 1273a; 6.8, 1294al0, Polybius 6.8.5, Plato, Rep.
8.551a, and in general H.-0. Weber, Die Bedeutung und Bewertung der Pleonexie
von Homer his Isokrates (diss. Bonn 1967).
to
222
P.H. SCHRIJVERS
223
8 Cf. Th. Cole, arl. cit., H. Ryffel, Metabole Politeioon, Der Wandel der Staatsverfassungen (Bern 1949), G. J.D. Aalders, Die Theorie der gemischten Verfassung
im Alterlum (Amsterdam 1968).
9 C. Bailey, Titi Lucreti Cari De Rerum Natura Libri Sex (Oxford 1947, repr.
1963), vol. 3.1498ff., C.D.N. Costa, Lucretius De Rerum Natura V (Oxford 1984).
10 Cf. M.R. Gale, Myth and Poetry in Lucretius (Cambridge 1994) 89-90.
224
P .H. SCHRIJVERS
225
1445
226
P .H. SCHRIJVERS
189.
20 Cf. Horner, Iliad 8.13 i\ JllV UOOv piwro e~ Tapmpov ~ep6evm (cf. Hom.H.
Mere. 256, 374), Lucretius, 3.966 nee quisquam in bar at h rum nee Tartar a
deditur atra, and fliad 8.14 nJAe JlaA ', fiX! f3a8U11:0V lJTCO x8ov~ ecm f3 Ep E8 p 0 V.
21 I am following at this point the dating proposed by 0. Murray and
followed by T. Dorandi, Filodemo, Il huon re seeondo Omero (ed., trans!., cornrn,
1982).
coli. 38 [tov 0' 'A)XtAAEil Kilt KlXAAUJ'tOV, coli. 29 Kilt to ~1]AO'tll1tOV [0') llltElVIll
Oe'i ... (cf. Dorandi ad loe.)." in line 5.1120 the Latin word potentes may be a
translation of the Greek term ouvacrtllt (cf. also GJ.D. Aalders, 'The Political
Faith of Dernocritus', Mnemosyne IV 3 (1950) 304 on the Greek terms Ouvacrtllt
Na~oli
OUVIl<JtEtll).
227
228
P.H. SCHRIJVERS
229
subject and with the gods as object, in the sense of 'being ignored,
escape', is quite unusual in Latin literature and has been built on
the regular use of the Greek verb A.avSavnv ('touc; 8w6c; I 'tOV 8e6v).
By means of this analysis of the paragraph concerning the
origins and the evolution of political life I hope to have shown how
much Lucretius has drawn from an ensemble of common ideas
which were rather widespread in later hellenistic times among
Greek and Roman intellectuals who belonged officially to different philosophical schools. Like Philodemus, Lucretius tried to integrate Epicureanism in the paideia, in the general civilisation of his
times. Leaving aside the relationship between Lucretius and Philodemus, I am not able to point out the direct sources of Lucretius'
argument. Therefore, I used expressions like 'the ensemble of common ideas' or 'ancient thought in general' .29 Methodologically, it
is very important to make a sharp distinction between sources/
ideas attested before or only after Epicurus' lifetime,3 although the
very fragmentary state of the transmission of Epicurus' works
makes the problem of Lucretius' factual dependency on Epicurus
rather intractable. In any case, these direct of indirect sources were
Greek.
Although Lucretius' reconstruction of political change is wholly
anonymous, without any precise chronology or localisation,-and
so without any explicit trace of ethnocentrism. But this impression
is misleading. His theoretical analysis has been inspired by real,
factual history which certainly is not Roman. The change from
kingship to democratic republic by the way of a chaotic, ochlocratic interval is without any parallel in Roman history. Moreover,
Lucretius would have been blatantly anachronistic if, in his reconstruction of the origins of political life, he had referred to Roman
history, the development of which is clearly later in time than
Greek history. Of course, some lines that contain a more generalised moral message about jealousy and wealth may have been
applied to the Roman, late-republican situation (the poet said himself that at a more general level history repeats itself, 5. 1135 nee
230
P .H. SCHRIJVERS
magis id nunc est neque crit mox quam fuit ante) ,31 but chronologically
this history did not start in Rome. Content and style of the first part
of Lucretius' story have more than once a Greek flavour as if the
period of the Homeric kings and their mutual envy hides itself
under the surface of the text. Subsequently, aristocrats, oligarchs,
great legislators who bring the internal troubles and vendettas to a
close, in general tend to evoke events in Greek history: the
legislations introduced by a Solon of Athens or a Dracon, the
bloody revenge, subject of many a Greek tragedy about the House
of Atreus. The cities mentioned in the beginning seem to be Greek
poleis, not Roman urbes which in fact did not yet exist in these
earlier times.
In spite of many a reference I made to the Greek historian
Polybius I do not think that he was a primary source for Lucretius;
this Greek historian combined the doctrine of political change
with the concept of a cyclic return (anakyklosis) which is not
emphasized in Lucretius' story (it is only mentioned in 5.1135). I
think the underlying presence of Greek history and the theory of
J..LE'ta~oA.i't 7tOAt'tet&v point to another Greek scholar, a Peripatetic
who influenced also Lucretius' description of the savage and antisocial life of primitive man (as I tried to prove in my recent article
in Philologus) ,32 a scholar who, in Roman, republican times, was
known as the author of a rather famous Archeology: the first chapters of his Life of Greece; this Greek scholar did make use of poetical
testimonies, had a reputation as a historical critic of the Homeric
epics and was rather well-known for his treatise entitled Tripolitikos
dealing with the three principal forms of government: in short,
once again I am persuaded that Lucretius' story might be influenced-directly or indirectly-by Dicearchus of Messene.33
Leiden
31 In a more general and allusive way, 'Lucretius' model for such a
constitutional development in some ways resembles that of Rome' (Costa, p.
128), and 'superbus was the regular Latin epithet for the tyrant; cf. Tarquinius
Superbus' (Bailey ad 5.1137); for more allusions to the contemporaneous,
Roman situation see D.P. Fowler, 'Lucretius and Politics', in M. Griffin - J.
Barnes (ed.), Philosophia Togata, Essays on Philosophy and Roman Society (Oxford
1989) 120-150.
32 Cited above in note 11.
33 Cf. the collection of testimonies by F.Wehrli (Die Schule des Aristoteles,
Heft 1, Dikaiarchos), the subdivisions of which obscure somewhat the unity of
Dicaearchus' philosophical and scientific activities.
H. B.
GOTTSCHALK
232
H. B. GOTTSCHALK
233
234
H. B. GOTTSCHALK
fundamental principle which, until the advent of quantum mechanics, was regarded as the basis of all science and philosophy.
Epicurus states it without embellishment and tries to establish its
truth by induction-if it were not true, anything could spring from
anything. He then goes on to establish that the only things which
exist in their own right are matter and void, and all other existing
things are derivatives or accidents of them. Lucretius clearly
means to reproduce Epicurus' argument, but vitiates it by adding
one word to his premiss: nullam rem e nilo gigni divinitus umquam. In
this form, his premiss loses its universality and can no longer be
inferred from the inductive evidence he adduces; for God is not
'nothing', and the fact that particular things are always seen to
come from other particular things, does not prove that there is not a
deity (instead of another particular thing) at the beginning of the
chain. Moreover, since his avowed purpose is to disprove divine
creation ( 1.159), the presence of this word in his premiss makes
the argument circular. Lucretius' eagerness to give his demonstration an extra anti-religious twist has betrayed him into formulating
his initial postulate in a way that renders it invalid.
Lucretius' view of Roman religion could be regarded as an
intensification of Epicurus' attitude. In other ways, the psychological differences between them are more marked, and some of
them touch the very roots of their philosophy. For example,
Lucretius describes the contemplation of nature as thrilling and a
source of god-like pleasure:5
His ibi me rebus quaedam divina voluptas
percipit atque horror, quod sic natura tua vi
tam manifesta patens ex omni parte retecta est.
235
But this is far from the impression we get from Epicurus' own
writings. He holds that the study of nature would be superfluous if
we could banish our fears without it (KD 11); in the Letter to
Herodotus he insists that its only purpose is to obtain a calm life
(EyyaJ.:rtvf~etV, 37) and warns his readers to confine themselves to
the study of general principles and not to delve too deeply into
details, as this might cause them amazement (8aJ.tBo~) if they met
problems they cold not solve (79). For Epicurus, it seems, horror
was not compatible with pleasure. Thus we are faced with two
opposed attitudes to the purpose of natural philosophy: on one side,
a zestful pursuit of a vision which will reveal the truth about the
universe and free men from the terrors of superstition, on the
other, a purely defensive search for 'scientific' support for a rather
timid ideology. One reason, perhaps, why Lucretius' poem is great
literature and Epicurus' works are not. Some of Lucretius' most
memorable lines are those which state the terrifying aspects of his
vision in the most dramatic terms:
Principio mare ac tnras caelumque tune:
quorum naturam triplicem, tria corpora, Memmi,
una dies dabit exitio multosque per annos
sustentata ruet moles et machina mundi. (5.91 ff.)
236
H. B. GOTTSCHALK
237
[natura]. But these do not lead him to depart from a strictly mechanistic account of causation; they do not signify a modification of
Epicurus' doctrine but are part of the poetical form Lucretius has
given to his exposition. However, this brings us to the greatest
departure from his master's teaching. In the 'ancient quarrel
between poetry and philosophy' Epicurus was as uncompromising
as Plato. He warns his followers against the snares of poetry, with
its tales of a world controlled by jealous deities and of a dire
existence after death, and tells them to avoid all 'culture' . 11 But
Lucretius, author of the fullest exposition of Epicurean philosophy
that has come down to us, made a poem of it, a poem, moreover,
which is no dry piece of versified argument like the poem of
Parmenides, but used all the devices of high poetry and openly
acknowledged its debt to Empedocles, a myth-maker if ever there
was one. The paradox is pointed up by a passage where Lucretius
warns Memmius not to be put off by vatum terriloquis dictis (1.102 f.).
It has become customary to translate vatum here by 'bards' or even
'priests', 12 but this is mistaken. There are several passages where
Epicurus advises his followers not to be put off by fears arising from
11u8ot; 13 the writers of 'myths' were poets, and when Lucretius goes
on to give examples of the 'terrifying sayings' against which he
wants to warn Memmius, he refers to accounts of the underworld
given by Ennius (1.115 ff.). The term vates is ambiguous, and
Lucretius may have chosen it in order to give an anti-religious
twist to Epicurus' warning; it would then be a parallel to the insertion of divinitus in line 150, with less disastrous consequences. 14 But
the immediate reference is to the stories of poetry, and the paradox
of a poet warning his readers against poetry is something we
should embrace, not fudge. Lucretius did not regard himself as a
11 Ap. Diog. Laert. 10.6 = fr. 163 Usener. natoda includes all kinds of nonphilosophical literary activity.
12 'Bards': Bailey; 'seers': Munro; 'priests': Diels, M.F. Smith. But Knebel
(18312) and Binder (1868) have Dichter.
13 Ep. Her. 81, KD 12. Note that the Greeks mostly speak of J.I.U8ot in the
plural and never use the singular as a collective noun to denote a privileged
group of fictions endowed with some kind of mystical collective significance.
To speak of Lucretius', or any other ancient writer's, use of or attitude to
'myth' (or der Mythos) in this sense, is at best anachronistic and could be
seriously misleading.
14 Another reason for his choice may have been that vates could have a
contemptuous meaning in Lucretius' time (see Munro and Bailey ad loc.). But
this would not fit well with his immediately citing Ennius, in most honorific terms.
238
H. B. GOTTSCHALK
poet of quite the same kind as the rest: when staking his claim to
poetic fame, his first boast was that he 'taught about great issues and
freed minds from the bonds of religion', his second that he 'wrote
clear poetry about an obscure subject'. The poetic quality of his
work, musaeo contingens cuncta lepore, comes last and is justified by
the famous image of the honey on the cup of bitter medicirte. 15
This raises the question of the relationship between the form
and content of his work. There was a time when it was thought
that he began by wanting to write a poem, looked for a subject and
chose Epicurus' philosophy; some nineteenth-century writers,
including Macaulay and Mommsen, even suggested that his
choice was a mistake and complain that he wasted so much poetic
talent on an inherently dull subject, while Munro devotes a whole
page of rhetoric to demonstrating that Epicureanism is a better
subject for poetry than any of the alternative systems available to
Lucretius. 16 Of course this is arrant nonsense. If one thing is clear
from his poem, it is that Lucretius decided to write about Epicureanism because he saw it as the key to the salvation of mankind. His
choice of poetry as his vehicle, in an age when prose had long
been the normal medium for serious philosophical writing, must
mean that, in his own situation, it seemed to offer some palpable
advantage over prose. Our task is to determine what this advantage
may have been.
Lucretius' purpose was to write in a way that would attract the
audience he was aiming at, the narrow, highly sophisticated
circle of the Roman upper class in which he and Memmius, the
dedicatee of his poem, moved. Now prose treatises on philosophy
or other instructional subjects seem to have had a low literary
status, rather like textbooks or what the trade calls 'academic books'
to-day, and according to Cicero, the only Latin prose works on
philosophy produced up to that time, by the Epicureans Catius and
Amafinius, were too shoddily written to appeal to sophisticated
readers, although he admits that they had a wide popular following.17 Those philosophers who aspired to be men of letters wrote
dialogues or open addresses to named individuals, which could be
15 1.93 ff, = 4.6 ff. Clarity (cr!X<JlllVElll) was the one quality on which Epicurus
insisted in his Rhetoric (ap. Diog. Laert. 1013).
16 Th. Mommsen, Romische Geschichte (Berlin 18827) 3.595 f. H.AJ. Munro,
in the introduction to vol. II of his edition (London 19004 ) 5 ff.
1 7 Cic. Ad Jam. 15.16, 19; Tusc. 4.3.6, Acad. 1.3.6. But Quintilian (Inst.
10.1.124) describes Catius as levis quidem sed non iniucundus auctar.
239
240
H. B. GOTTSCHALK
PART FIVE
IMPERIAL PHILOSOPHY
Il y a peu de philologues qui ont fait autant que Jaap Mansfeld pour
traverser les frontieres nationales et linguistiques du monde savant. En
hommage a cet esprit d 'internationalisme, j 'ose offrir la petite discussion qui
suit, convenable (je l'espere) cette occasion et par son theme et par le fait
que celle-ci represente la premiere fois que j'ai pu offrir une communication
dans une langue itrangere. I
244
BRAD INWOOD
245
246
BRAD INWOOD
247
248
BRAD INWOOD
249
les vies sont les plus rapprochees de Ia notre, alors nous courtisons
Ia misere. 6 D'autre part, nos relations humaines constituent une
partie vitale de ce que nous sommes en tant qu' etres humains.
C' est difficile, sin on impossible, de decouvrir ce que no us sommes
et ce que nous devons faire si nous n'avons pas une conception
adequate de nos liens naturels et indissolubles avec les autres. Les
autres etres humains ne sont pas seulement les objets de nos
affections; ils sont aussi des elements constitutifs et indispensables
de notre vie morale. II est difficile d'imaginer une vie caracterisee
par Ia sorte d'indifference aux autres preconisee par Epictete.
Je ne veux pas suggerer que Epictete n'offre aucune resolution a
Ia tension dans ses travaux que je vi ens d' esquisser si brievement. II
n'en est pas ainsi, et je veux me pencher sur une tentative de
reconcilier ces tendances opposees de Ia pensee d'Epictete.7 Mais il
est important, je crois, de partir de !'idee qu' il y a bel et bien une
tension ici, notamment parce que nous devrons eviter d'etre seduits
trop facilement par l'attrait de l'optimisme stoicien. II serait facile
de s'endormir dans une fausse securite, et de presumer qu' il est
tout simplement raisonnable d'avoir beaucoup d'interet et meme
d'inquietude pour les autres. Epictete montre que tel n'est pas le cas.
II soutient qu' un trop grand souci pour les autres est une source de
misere, et que notre interet rationnel pour notre propre bonheur
peut parfois prescrire une cruelle indifference aux autres etres
humains. ('Quel mal y a-ti'l a dire tout bas, en embrassant ton
enfant 'demain tu mourras" 3.24.88). Dans sa theorie quelque
chose d'aussi simple que !'affection d'un pere envers son fils peut
presenter un probleme theorique profond, une theorie qui montre
que nous devons souvent choisir entre nos engagements envers les
autres et notre tendance vers le bonheur.
Les moyens disponibles a Epictete pour reconcilier ces deux tendances ne lui appartiennent pas tout seul. En effet, plus nous regardons les choses de pres, plus nous verrons une continuite avec le
stoicisme ancien. Considerons d'abord Ia contribution apportee par
Ia theorie stoicienne de Ia valeur. Cette theorie est basee sur Ia distinction cardinale entre deux sortes de valeur qui sont considerees
6 Cf. B. Inwood, 'Why do fools fall in love?' Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies (London) 1996, et M. Nussbaum The Therapy of Desire (Princeton
1994) ch. 10.
7 Cf. A. Bonhoffer, Die Ethik des Stoikers Epiktet (Stuttgart 1894) 4-5, 158-9.
j'ose offrir dans cette discussion-ci une solution complementaire aux remarques de BonhOffer, qui son tres a propos mais trop breves.
250
BRAD INWOOD
251
Voir 3.24.88.
252
BRAD INWOOD
253
254
BRAD INWOOD
255
256
BRAD INWOOD
257
258
BRAD INWOOD
259
260
BRAD INWOOD
261
ville est basee sur nos liens de parente avec nos semblables, et notre
citoyennete dans Ia cosmopolis est basee de Ia meme fa~,;on sur
notre parente avec dieu. Le divin est le paradigme pour Ia vie
terrestre; nos relations cosmiques soot a Ia fois le modele et Ia cause
de nos relations humaines-et ce qui est plus important, le divin
nous aide a comprendre que !'experience humaine est un systeme
rationnel et coherent.
En soulignant que Zeus remplit le role du pere commun de tous
les hommes, Epictete augmente et renforce les fondements de Ia
theorie stoicienne des relations humaines. Nos liens avec les
autres hommes ne soot pas, comme les autres stoiciens le pensaient, seulement une extension de }'affection parentale aux autres
etres humains par le biais d'une analogie faible et diluee (comme
le suggere les cercles en expansion de Hierocle); cette fa~,;on de
promouvoir Ia fraternite des hommes fut attaquee par le commentateur anonyme du Theetete, et cette critique nous fait penser aux
commentaires d'Aristote sur les relations familiales artificielles
dans Ia Ripublique de Platon. Plutot, cette relation est ancree dans
une application nouvelle de Ia metaphore des relations familiales,
dans laquelle Ia figure principale est Zeus dans le role du pere. Ce
modele aide aussi a expliquer nos relations sociales aux autres
hommes, et rend compte et de leur caractere naturel et de leur
place secondaire. Le lien le plus fort dans n'importe quelle famille
ancienne (d'un point de vue ideologique) est le lien entre pere et
fils; les relations entre freres (et soeurs) doivent leur existence
meme a Ia primaute de Ia relation paternelle. La primaute de notre
relation avec Zeus le pere est un symbole, pour ainsi dire, de Ia primaute de Ia coherence rationnelle dans nos vies. Et tout comme Ia
primaute de Ia relation parent-enfant met les liens entre freres (et
soeurs) en perspective, Ia primaute de Ia coherence rationnelle
dans nos vies determine que toutes les autres relations-crxaet~
sont secondaires. Ces themes sont tres importants dans le discours
que je vais explorer en guise de conclusion, I' Entretien 2.22 intitutle
De l'amitie.
Epictete prend comme point de depart un argument raisonnable
(eiK6-rco~) modele sur celui que Chrysippe a employe pour fonder Ia
rationalite de notre inclination a Ia preservation de soi dans D.L.
7.85 ss. Nous aimons (cptAe\v) ce que nous prenons au serieux; ceci
est raisonnable, puisqu' il serait absurde de prendre au serieux ce
qui est mauvais pour nous ou ce qui ne presente aucun interet pour
262
BRAD INWOOD
263
264
BRAD INWOOD
266
TEUN TIELEMAN
brain. A few decades earlier, 6 Galen had devoted no less than four
books (viz. 1-111 and VI) of his On the doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato
(hereafter PHP) 7 to the same issue. Drawing on his dialectical
skills and extensive anatomical knowledge, he delivered a
thundering vindication of the Platonic tripartition and trilocation.
That is to say, he established the brain as the seat of Plato's rational
part (commonly identified with the regent part8 ), refuting in the
process the main Stoic and Peripatetic arguments in favour of the
cardiocentric theory.
Naturally enough, it has been suggested that Alexander wrote
the last section of De an. in conscious opposition to Galen.9 Some
scholars have even commented unfavourably on the strength of
what is considered Alexander's response to Galen's challenge. 10 In
view of what is otherwise known of Alexander's reactions to
Galen's workll and of the impact of PHP,12 it is quite plausible that
Alexander had the argument of PHP forced upon his attention.
6 PHP books I-VI were written during Galen's first stay in Rome, i.e.
between 162 and 166 CE, see De Lacy (1978) 46-48. Alexander's De anima is
usually dated to the final period of his career; see Moraux (1978) 304-5;
Donini (1982) 231; cf. supra, n. 2.
7 References give book-, chapter- and paragraph-numbers in Ph. De Lacy's
edition (CMG V 4,1,2, 3 vols. Berlin 1978-82)
8 Cf. Alex. De an. 98.24., Gal., PHP II 5.81.
9 Todd (1977); Moraux (1978) 293; Donini (1982) 232; Mansfeld (1990) 3109
n. 223.
10 Moraux (1978) 293; Donini (1982) 231.
11 Alexander, In Top. 549.24 Wallies mentions Galen alongside Plato and
Aristotle as an authority whose views count as voo~a suitable for dialectical
discussion. He composed two tracts against Galen's (lost) On the First Mover
and On Possibility respectively. The former has been preserved in an Arabic
abstract; see Rescher-Marm urra ( 1965). One of the Arabic mss. contains a
notice saying that Galen wrote to Herminus a letter in which he criticized
Aristotle's theory of motion; see Pines (1961) 23, Rescher and Marmurra
(1965) 57f. Herminus was Alexander's teacher, see Simp!. De caelo 430.32ff.
Heioerg. He may be identical to the Peripatetic philosopher and pupil of
Aspasius, whom the young Galen heard lecture in Pergamum, Aff. Dig. 8.4,
p.28.15f. De Boer. See further Moraux (1984) 361ff. On Alexander's affiliations
with (proximate) contemporaries cf. also Sharples (1990). The identification
of Alexander with Alexander of Damascus (De praecogn. 5.9-15 Nutton; De A nat.
Admin. 2.216.6-8 K.)-first made in Arabic sources-is today generally rejected; see Todd (1976) 4ff. esp. 6 n.29, Sharples (1987) 1179 with nn. 18-21.
l2 See esp. PHP VII 1.1-4: books I-VI circulated among Peripatetics, Stoics
and physicians and, if we may believe Galen, had already convinced some of
these opponents. On the Peripatetic section of his audience see also II 3.23. In
fact, books I-VI were written at the request of a Peripatetic, viz. Flavius
Boethus, see Lib. Prop. 1, SM II p.96.19ff. Muller; cf. also De praecogn. 2.24, 5.9,
5.19 with Nutton ad loc.
267
This claim is not invalidated by the fact that Alexander does not
refer explicitly to Galen in the De an. Both Alexander and Galen
follow the common practice of avoiding names of contemporary
opponents when dealing with their arguments.l 3 For example
Alexander directed his tract on the theory of motion against Galen
without mentioning him by name.14
But it is one thing to assume that Galen looms in the background of Alexander's argument; it is quite another to substantiate
and illustrate this assumption on the basis of textual evidence. In
fact, a negative conclusion has been reached by Accattino in the
most recent and fullest available discussion on the matter. 15 This
discussion takes the form of an extensive critique of three parallels
adduced by Todd.I6 These parallels, Accattino argues, fail to establish the thesis that Alexander uses arguments or ideas of Galen. 17
However, the removal of Todd's trio of parallels does not settle the
issue satisfactorily. What we need is a systematic treatment involving more material from Galen. Oddly enough, neither Todd nor
Accattino pays much attention to what might be called Galen's
formal contribution to the controversy over the seat of the regent
part-the PHP.
In the following pages, I will reconsider the relation between
the closing section of the De an. and what is to be found in Galen's
writings, most notably the PHP. I shall argue that Alexander does
respond to specific arguments he had read in Galen. Meanwhile
Accattino's critique may stand as a reminder of the strict criteria
needed for assessing 'parallels' in terms of historical relations.
Mere resemblances are not good enough. Many current arguments and ideas used in the controversy over the regent part
were traditional and hence not confined to Galen and Alexander.
13 Tieleman (1996) 67ff., Sharples (1987) 1178f. The exegetical style of later
ancient philosophy entailed a heavy concentration on the ipsissima verba of
the past masters, notably Plato, Aristotle and Chrysippus. PHP books I-VI,
with their extensive quotations, are a case in point. Likewise Alexander
presents his De an. as an explication of Aristotle's doctrine (2.4-9). In much
philosophical polemicizing of the period, contemporary opponents are thus
involved without being explicitly or separately refuted.
14 See Rescher and Marmurra (1965), esp. 59.
15 Accattino ( 1987).
16 Todd (1977), esp. 117f., 121-3. See infra, nn. 33, 55.
17 In fact Todd (1977) 123 does not even claim that Alexander had read
Galen but merely propounds an indirect kind of relation, i.e. one mediated
by other authors.
268
TEUN TIELEMAN
269
heart is the source of taste and touch, the other senses must reside
there too (96.25-8) .2 The series culminates in the theoretical
intellect (o 8ecop11'tuco~ vou~). being the perfection of the soul (99.6).
This scheme constitutes so to speak the skeleton of the demonstration as a whole. It is fleshed out by additional arguments establishing the location of each of the main functions independently
of the others. This concatenation of functions corresponds to the
order in which the individual powers are treated in the main body
of the work (27.1-92.11, recapitulated at 92.12-94.6): Alexander
successively deals with the nutritive (94.17-96.1 0), the perceptive
(96.10-97.15), the appetitive-cum-motive (97.15-99.1) and cognitive
(99.1-10) powers. Each of these main powers is further subdivided,
and the resulting sub-species are linked by inferences as well. We
must note in particular his ploy of proceeding by small transitions,
including those from one main function to another. Thus at 98.2999.2 we have the following sequence: where is the appetitive
(opEK'ttKOv), there is also the volitional (~ouA.rtnK6v); and where is
the volitional, there is the deliberative and rational (~oUAEU'ttlCOV 'tE
K<Xt A.oytcr't11COV) faculty.
The ordering of the main functions is loosely modelled on
Aristotle's De an. Books II and III. As to the steps made from one
function to another it is also worth comparing individual passages
such as Arist. De an. B 2, 413b21-421 and the hierarchy of five functions, ibid. 3, 414a31-33. But the prominence given by Alexander to
this inferential sequence is no doubt due to the influence of the
(originally Sceptical) little-by-little argument or s6rites.22
Here Alexander was anticipated by Chrysippus' demonstration
of the cardiocentric view in his De an., from which Galen has preserved extensive quotations in PHP books II and III. In his account
of what he regards as common opinion, Chrysippus started from
the perception of certain passions, notably inflamed anger (6pYJ1),
arising in the heart. But then:
20
21 'In insects which have been cut in two each of the segments possesses
both sensation and local movement; and if sensation, necessarily also imagination and appetition; for where there is sensation, there is also pleasure
and pain; and where these, necessarily also desire' (Oxford transl.).
22 On the sorites in general see Barnes (1982); Burnyeat (1982). For Chrysippus' use of it see SW 2.665; cf. 1003, 1005, Cic. ND 2.164-166. Cf. Burnyeat
(1982) 337f.
270
TEUN TIELEMAN
given the fact that inflamed anger arises there, it is also reasonable
that the other desires are there, and indeed the rest of the passions
and the deliberations and whatever resembles these (PHP III 2.5 =
SW2.890; cf. Alex. De an. 97.1-3).23
Galen tells us (III 2.4) that Chrysippus used this mode of reasoning
throughout his demonstration, thus indicating, ones presumes, that
the Stoic developed this common pattern of thought further in the
light of considerations of a more philosophical and scientific
kind.2 4 The argument exemplifies Chrysippus' use of the sorites for
constructive purposes, just as he appropriated the Sceptical technique of diaphonia.2 5 The use made of sorites by Chrysippus and
Alexander in this particular context is an effective means of
countering the Platonic tripartition.26
3. Let us now take a closer look at those of Alexander's arguments
which invite comparison with the relevant parts of PHP. Given the
relation posited between things of greater or lesser perfection (see
above) it is of prime importance for Alexander to establish the
presence in the heart of the lowest or nutritive faculty: 'where the
nutritive power is, there are also the more perfect ones' (94.17).
Obviously, the nutritive faculty, being at the bottom of the scale,
cannot be inferred from the presence of another one. Thus he
devotes considerably more space to the principle of nourishment
than to any of the otherfaculties (94.11-96.10).
Alexander begins by pointing to the need for a large supply of
hot and wet material as indispensable for life and hence for the
nutritive soul, affirming that the heart meets this requirement
(94.17-20; cf. 96.5-8) .27 This passage (as well as 39.21-40.3, to which
he refers) is closely similar to an argument paraphrased and
criticized by Galen at PHP II 8.30ff.2 8 For chronological reasons
Galen cannot be attacking Alexander.29 We are dealing with a
traditional Peripatetic (and Stoic) argument reiterated by Alexander, who gives no sign of taking note of Galen's objections.
23 Also quoted at ibid. III 5.2 (SW2.89), II 7.11 (SW 2.887).
24 PHP III 5.43-44 (= SW 2.899); cf. III 3.7 with Tieleman (1996) 249 ff.
25 For the diaphtSnia see esp. Chrys. ap. Gal, PHP III 1.10-15 (SW 2.885)
with Mansfeld (1990) 3167ff. See also, infra, n. 61.
2 6 On Plato as Chrysippus' main butt see Tieleman (1996) 140f.
27 PA f 4,665b, Iuv. 4, 469b7ff.
28 See Tieleman (1996) 67ff.
29 Supra, nn. 2, 6.
271
Top. A 13,
105a20ff.
But Galen may owe something to the analogy between animals and
plants drawn by Aristotle at Iuv. 2, 468a13ff., where the nutritive part is associated with the middle part of the body; cf. also ibid. 3, 468b17ff.
32 Cf. the phrase ai <pAEPE~ ... El<: . 'tft~ Kapoia~ ... cb~ EK 't!XU'tll<; 'tTJV apxiJv
exouam 1:ft~ PA.aa1:~aeroc;. Alexander, like Aristotle, does not differentiate
between arteries and veins, speaking of <pA.ePe~ ('vessels') only.
33 On this parallel cf. Todd (1977) 118, Accattino (1987) 455fT.
34 Cf. also Arist. PA f 5, 668b36ff.
30
31
272
TEUN TIELEMAN
273
of nourishment is not yet exhausted. He continues with a few arguments (95.12-96.15) which are used by other authors to establish the
location of the regent part. As far as Galenic parallels are concerned, we now have to switch from PHP VI to II. At II 4 Galen
takes issue with a set of Stoic and Peripatetic arguments 'from position' (II 4.6ff., cf. Arist. PAr 4). According to Alexander, the heart
must contain the principle of life since it occupies the midmost
position in the body, which is safest and least vulnerable to ailments (95.12-16; cf. Arist. PAr 4, 665b25ff.). 3 8 Galen does not discuss this particular train of thought, though he speaks broadly of
various possible arguments from position (II 4.12ff.). Alexander
points to the chest (8ropa~) as the proper body of animal on which
the organs have, as it were, grown; the common psychic faculty
must be in the common bodily part.39 Galen, for his part, refers to
an (otherwise unknown) argument which appeals to the middle
position of the heart in the chest (II 4.14). 40 Galen refers to the
originally Aristotelian 41 argument that the heart lies in the middle
of the body for the sake of an even distribution of the powers ( ouvaJlEOOV) sent out from the heart (II 4.12). Alexander uses this argument at 95.19-24, but restricts its scope to the distribution of nutriment and the nutritive principle for the reasons indicated above. 42
At 96.10ff. Alexander proceeds to the second faculty of the series,
viz. the perceptive (aicr8T)nlCTJ) faculty. He argues that the nutritive
and the perceptive powers must necessarily be located in one and
the same place, or else animals would have two souls instead of
one (and by the same token lose their individuality). 4 " For Galen
38
This point is also made with regard to the perceptive faculty, 98.20ff.
39 This could reflect Arist. Iuv. 2, 468al3ff., where Aristotle says that the
nutritive principle resides in the middle part of the body: some animals
(wasps, bees) can be seen to survive for some time without heads or food
receptacle (viz. the upper and lower parts of their structure). Cf. Alex. De an.
100.8ff. on which see infra p. 13f.
40 This may however reflect Aristotle's observation that in animals the
place of the heart is in the middle of the breast (whereas in man it inclines
slightly to the left), PAr 4, 666b7-9.
4 1 Arist. PAr 4, 666bl8-20, 666al4-15; MA 9, 702bl2-703a3; cf. Simp!. In
Arist. De caelo p. 514.11-3 Heiberg.
42 But cf. Arist. Iuv. 4, 469a24ff. where the same argument is also used
with regard to the nutritive-cum-perceptive function only.
43 Cf. 99.5 ff. where Alexander says that this implication is not
inescapable in the case of the theoretical intellect: we may accept that it exists
separately from the other functions without having to assume two soulswhich is impossible. The fact that he takes into account a counter-argument is
typical of his method, see infra, p. 278.
274
TEUN TIELEMAN
the doctrine that the psychic powers determine the shape of the
bodily organs is related to-and justified by-a scala naturae
expressed in terms of the three Platonic parts of the soul: plants
possess only the desiderative part, 44 non-rational animals have the
desiderative and the spirited part, human have the rational on top
of the other two. 45 Here the non-rational parts of the soul coincide
with the kind of soul possessed by non-rational animals. This scala
naturae thus brings out the status of the non-rational (i.e. the
desiderative-cum-spirited) as a distinct part of the soul. 46 This
emphasis is typical of Galen, who, in PHP and elsewhere,
describes the parts or forms ( etOT)) of the soul as distinct in kind
(yevn) and being (ouaia). On occasion he even speaks-in a way
which is unwarranted by the Platonic text-of a plurality of souls. 47
So here too Galen would seem to be the most likely target of
Alexander's critique.4B
44 Cf. Pl. Tim. 77b with Gal., In Tim. 11.24-27 Schroder. In the context
Galen connects this point to his view that the desiderative part is different in
essence (oucria) from the rational part; pace those who posit one essence with
three powers ( OUVclJ.1Et<;) Plato speaks of forms or parts. This may be directed
against Platonists like Severus who were swayed by Peripatetic criticism to
abandon soul-partition in order to save the unity (and immortality) of the
soul; cf. Deuse (1983) 104ff.
45 PHP V 6.37-9, where Galen ascribes this Platonizing chain of being to
Posidonius (F144 E-K). Posidonius, for his part, conceived of the soul in terms
of powers (OUVclJ.1Et<;) not parts, let alone separate souls; like Aristotle and most
Stoics he assigned the powers (i.e. the regent part) to the heart. See PHP V
4.3; 7.9-10; 7.50; VI 2.5 (Posid. Frs. 142, 144, 145, 146 E-K).
46 See supra, n. 18 with text thereto. Similarly, Alex. De an. 27.8ff. (who of
course speaks of OUVclJ.1Et<;), Nemes. Nat. hom. 16, 73.3-6 Morani.
4 7 PHPV 4.3, 7.9-10; 7.50; VI 2.5, In Hipp. Epid. p. 272.22-273.1 WenkebachPfaff. For a plurality of souls distinct in essence see esp. De meth. med. X,
635.6ff. K., In Plat. Tim. Fr. II 1.87 Schroeder. Cf. also De moribus, p. xvi
Walzer, where Galen presents it as one of the options available in the debate
concerned with the structure of the soul. On his conception of the soul against
the backdrop of contemporary Platonism cf. the concise discussion of Deuse
( 1983) lOOff.
48 It might be supposed that Alexander's target was the Pythagoreanizing
Platonist Numenius of Apamea, who is known to have distinguished between
a rational and a non-rational soul: Numen. ap. Porph. ap. Stob. Eel. I 49.25a
(350.25-351.1 Wachsmuth) = Numen. fr. 44 Des Places, Porph. fr. 253 Smith
(272.18 ff.). Here Numenius is mentioned as one among a plurality of authorities, who remain anonymous but may include Galen; cf. Nemesius referred
to supra, n. 46. Numenius' floruit is generally dated to around 150 CE or the
later 2nd century CE; Frede (1987) 1038 f. So as far as chronology is concerned
he might have been Alexander's butt. But on closer thought this seems far
less likely. The cosmic perspective motivating Numenius' doctrine is something quite different from the anatomical and physiological aspects highlighted by both Galen and Alexander. On Numenius's conception of the soul
275
see Deuse (1983) 62ff., esp. 79ff., Frede (1987) 1070 ff. At this stage, moreover,
he was not yet a factor on the philosophical stage; see the evidence surveyed by
Frede (1987) 1034 ff. Alexander, at any rate, nowhere refers to him explicitly.
49 Cf. Mansfeld (1991) 138ff.
50 I do not of course wish to imply that this dictum is confined to Galen,
cf. e.g. Arist. De an. 9, 432b21, 12 434a31, PA B 13, 658a5, f 1, 661b24; Alex. Fat.
178.12, De an. 27.9, 13, 28.5. The theme of Nature's design in shaping the
or~ans of the body is also prominent in Alexander's preface, 2.10-25.
1 Cf. also De usu parlium X 5.6, vol. 2, p. 75 Helmreich, Nat. fac. III 8,
p. 227.19ff., Helmreich. Similarly, Alex. De an. 2.19-20, in a context strongly
reminiscent of Galen's De usu partium, a work which, if we may believe
Galen, was popular among Aristotelians, see Lib. Prop. 2, p.100.18-23 Miiller.
276
TEUN TIELEMAN
55 Cf. also Loc. aff. III 5, 8.158.1ff. K., Meth. med. XIII 21, 10.928.2-932.17 K.
with Mansfeld (1990) 3141ff., 3110 n. 225. Todd (1977) 122f. suggests that Alexander's argument is based on his misunderstanding of Caus. Symp. 7, 1.137
K., but this seems less likely; cf. Accattino (1987) 467f. Likewise Todd (1977)
277
278
TEUN TIELEMAN
activity of the brain that the same holds good of the heart. If
intended as a rebuttal of Galen, this is beside the point, for the
latter-in accordance with the Platonic trilocation-assigns to
either organ its own distinctive motion. So the issue is not that of
function vs. loss of function. But if Alexander fails to meet Galen's
argument, that does not mean that he did not respond to it. It is
noteworthy that Alexander says that each organ, when removed
from the body, retains its 'proper activities (oiled a<; evepyda<;,
100.12f.)'. This very point is stressed by Galen in the context of the
same kind of observations, where it supports his anatomically
based Platonic tripartition (PHPII 4.49; II 6.10).59
Alexander's claim that arguments of this type tell in favour of
neither alternative recalls his view of the purpose of a dialectical
investigation in search of the truth in an Aristotelian manner. The
ability to discern the strong points-and argue oneself-in favour
of one of two opposed positions is integral to his concept of
dialectic.6 This made him hospitable to the Sceptical technique of
diaphonia. But the Aristotelian dialectician cannot of course rest
content with a stalemate of conflicting views and arguments, i.e.
he tries to balance the arguments pro and con in order to determine which of two tenets is to be accepted, or at least preferred. Jaap
Mansfeld has established and analysed Alexander's use of this
technique on the basis of his De fato. 61 For our purposes it is
interesting to note that it is part of this procedure that Alexander is
interested not only in arguments or facts supporting either of the
views at issue, but also in points to be scored against both of them.
Those of the two positions which appears more vulnerable to these
objections, and hence more complicated or muddled, is the one to
be discarded in favour of the other. Indeed, the thesis to be accepted
becomes clearer insofar as the alternative can be shown to be
muddled. 62 Hence the exposure of the invalidity of both the
encephalocentric and cardiocentric arguments from sympathy at
59 Cf. also PHP I 6.10, III 6.5, V 3.5, VI 6.44.
279
5. What are we to conclude from the preceding survey of resemblances and differences ? Many of the arguments used by Alexander had started their career in Aristotle's PAr 3-4 and Iuv. 2-4 and
found their way into the traditional debate concerned with the seat
of the soul, where they served, often in a somewhat modernized
form, on the Peripatetic side. Alexander uses some of these without
adapting them to meet Galen's objections. It would however be
rash to assume that he did not know, or chose to ignore, Galen's
critique and simply drew on a repertoire of traditional Peripatetic
arguments. Not only would such a dialogue des sourds be implausible in the light of his knowledge of Galen's work. 63 Alexander has
been shown to use specifically Galenic notions and arguments
and to do so in a way which can best be explained on the
assumption that he had indeed read the Galenic passages I have
been referring to.64
Large parts of Alexander's argument read like an inverted mirror image of Galen's demonstration in PHP books II and VI. The
reason is that Alexander applies the technique of turning Galen's
arguments and concepts against him, just as he elsewhere appropriated Stoic concepts and arguments to anti-Stoic ends. 65 This is
the familiar technique of reversal (1tepnp01t1l) in its wider sense of
taking a statement of one's opponent and turning it against him. 66
The opposition of two alternative views (or arguments) is also at
issue in the so-called Placita tradition as reconstructed by Diels in
his Doxographi Graeci. 67 Jaap Mansfeld has demonstrated Galen's
knowledge of this tradition on the basis of De locis affectis III 5. 68
63 See supra, n. 11.
64 See supra, p. 3.
65 Cf. Todd (1976) 27f., Moraux (1984) 335-6, 359, Sharples (1987) 1178 with
further references.
66 The wider sense gained currency under the influence of the rhetorical
tradition; cf. e.g. Arist. Rh. B 23, 1398a3-4. The technical term 7tEpttpo7t~ stems
from dialectic, where it designates self-refutation in the narrower sense of
refuting a thesis from its own contents. One of the most famous instances in
ancient philosophical literature occurs in Pl. Th. 17la-b, where Protagoras'
Man is the Measure-thesis is turned against itself. See further Burnyeat
(1976), esp. 65.
67 Berlin 1879; several reprints. A new study devoted to the so-called doxographic tradition is being prepared by Jaap Mansfeld and David T. Runia.
6'!! Mansfeld (1990) 3141ff.
280
TEUN TIELEMAN
ou
70
281
an. 94.25ff. 74 No. 48 dealt with the question whether or not the heart
is the source of the nerves (cf. PHP I 8, 10; De an. 98.15).75 The
formulation in terms of polarities recalls the theses in the doxographic texts. The phrase Kat on ava1taA.w ('and in reverse', 'and contrariwise') may indicate the reversal of argumentation exemplified
by the (lost) pairs of arguments.
According to Photius, Dionysius' booklet was 'quite useful for
dialectical exercise and the knowledge of some doctrines belonging to medical theory' (Cod. 185). It has been assumed that the pairs
of arguments were designed to induce suspension of judgement. 76
But we have to be cautious in drawing precise conclusions about
historical affiliations. The exact dates and identity of the author of
the ~uctua.Ka must remain uncertain (though the issues listed seem
to presuppose Galen's work).77 But it is tempting to assume that the
lost arguments reflected the same kind of method as is followed by
Alexander in the closing section of his De an.
To conclude. We have found a number of parallels which relate
Alexander's argument to Galen's in the various ways I have been
arguing. In the light of this evidence we may, in Alexander's own
fashion, tip the scales in favour of the thesis that De an. 94.7-100.17
is primarily designed as a response to Galen. Particularly striking
are Alexander's use of the sorites and his technique of inverting
Galen's arguments. Thus Alexander succeeds in exposing a few
weak (and blind) spots of Galen's position, especially those relating
to the spatial separation between the 'parts' of the soul. The
cardiocentric view still had a future lying ahead.*
Utrecht University
74
7 6 For this reason the author has been identified with a Dionysius who
was a Methodist physician of the 1st cent. CE. Alternatively, he has been
described as an Empiricist and Sceptical doctor. But his identity must remain
uncertain. Eustathius, In ll. 1192 (= vol. 4, p. 355.10-13 Van der Valk) aligns
the author of the AtJC't\HXJCa with the dialecticians and the Sceptics; cf.
Deichgriiber (1930) 336.
77 E.g. No. 15 at Cod. 185 'that heat does not vary in quality' clearly states
the view of Lycus of Macedonia as discussed by Galen, Adv. Lye. c. 3, pp. 8.1514.4 Wenkebach. Lycus belonged to the generation of Galen's teachers; cf. De
anat. admin. 2.449f., 470 K
I should like to thank Keimpe Algra, Han Baltussen and David Runia
for their comments on an earlier version. Research for this article was made
possible by a fellowship of the Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences.
282
TEUN TIELEMAN
BIBLIOGRAPHY
283
285
286
PIERLUIGI DONINI
287
288
PIERLUIGI DONINI
L'accordo con il cap. 6 e qui davvero notevole: prevalenza statistica dei caratteri deteriori; rarita estrema delle persone virtuose; la
virtu raggiunta mediante 1' esercizio e 1' educazione; l'incapacita
della physis a conferire da sola la virtu-su tutti questi punti i due
testi implicano o sostengono le stesse posizioni, per di piu sempre
all'interno della generale nozione aristotelica della natura come
agente che opera 'sempre o per lo piu' . C' e tuttavia un aspetto della
questione per il quale la coincidenza delle tesi espresse da Alessandro nei due passi non e totale. Nel cap. 6 la possibilita di migliorarsi
rispetto a quanto comporterebbe la natura appare si fuori della
normalita statistica (e infatti quanto rimane al di fuori del 'per lo
piu', che opera nel senso di vincolare la maggior parte dell'umanita al suo carattere naturale); rna non e cosi drasticamente
limitata come nel cap. 27 a un solo individuo: Socrate e certamente
un caso eccezionale, rna nel cap. 6 non e detto che sia anche
l'unico. Come spiegare questa difformita di posizioni?
Ora la tesi dell'estrema rarita degli uomini virtuosi puo essere
fatta derivare anche da Aristotele, e vero;I6 rna la formulazione di
Alessandro in De jato 27, p. 198,20 sembra davvero eccessiva per un
aristotelico e di fatto viene a coincidere con la tesi stoica. 11 risultato
e paradossale: il medesimo autore che si sforza lungo tutto il trattato
di distinguere la filosofia aristotelica da ogni possibile versione del
determinismo enuncia in quel passo una proposizione che altrove
rimprovera aspramente agli avversari stoici di aver sostenuto;I7 e la
enuncia senza che nemmeno ve ne sia la stretta necessita: non gli
bastava forse dire che gli uomini per bene non essendo tali per
natura-perche allora sarebbero buoni tutti quanti gli uomini, o
almeno la loro maggioranza-il loro numero si restringe a un
piccolo gruppo? Perche mai dire, invece, 'a uno solo'? Puo ben
darsi, dunque, che sugli avversari di quella filosofia la pressione
(seguito poi da Zierl) accetta invece l'avverbio O.vayKairo~ di tradizione indiretta. Si introdurrebbe cosi una nozione di necessita assoluta che mi sembra
quanto di piil sgradito ed estraneo all'aristotelism9 ci possa essere per Alessandro. 'AvayKaiov si intende invece facilmente nel senso di Metaph. b. 5,
1015a 22-26: e 'que! che e necessario perche il bene si realizzi'.
l6 Come osserva Sharples, op.cit. (n. 14) 162.
17 Cfr. De Jato 28, p. 199,16 sg.
289
delle tesi stoiche fosse ancora fra il secondo e il terzo secolo tale, da
imporre come ovvie persino tesi che a una riflessione critica attenta
avrebbero dovuto essere rifiutate; rna e anche vero che nel complesso del De Jato Ia concezione di Alessandro non e comunque
pienamente identificabile con quella stoica. Puo essere assimilata
alia posizione stoica Ia tesi che ci siano, o che siano esistiti, soltanto
uno o due uomini per bene; rna certamente Alessandro non accetta
mai il corollario stoico che ne consegue a proposito della rimanente umanita-che si tratterebbe cioe di una massa di stolti, folli e
malvagi tutti ugualmente immersi nell'errore e nel vizio. Ben lontano da queste convinzioni, Alessandro le censura anzi esplicitamente in una pagina del De fato. 18 La sua convinzione 19 sembra
dunque piuttosto essere che l'umanita comune si trovi in una
condizione che e certamente ancora lontana dalla virtu, rna si
colloca tuttavia in una posizione in qualche modo mediana fra la
virtu e il vizio completo. Quel che allora occorre ammettere e che,
almeno in vista dell'argomento del cap.6, Alessandro ha deciso di
non tenere conto di alcuna differenza fra i caratteri che risultano
comunque inferiori alia virtu: tutti risultano assimilati dal fatto di
essere legati al carattere naturalmente costituitosi nell'anima.
Prima di proseguire nell'analisi del nostro problema vorrei
segnalare un aspetto interessante dell'esemplificazione di Alessandro a p. 171, perche esso puo avere qualche importanza in relazione
alia (ancora irrisolta) questione del rapporto fra il trattato maggiore
e l'opuscolo sui fato incluso nella Mantissa. Nel suo articolo Mansfeld segnalo20 come 'a flagrant contradiction of major importance'
il fatto che nella pagina del trattato l'esempio di Socrate serve a
illustrare Ia rilevante eccezione che si puo introdurre al dominio
del fato sulle vite umane, mentre nell'opuscolo (p. 185,14 sg.) lo
stesso Socrate (in compagnia di Callia) e presentato come esempio
della regola generale che il fato governa gli individui. E apparentemente questa contraddizione dovrebbe allora corroborare il sospetto21 che l'opuscolo non sia opera di Alessandro, rna di un suo
scolaro. Dopo aver accettato per qualche tempo l'osservazione di
Mansfeld sono ora giunto alia conclusione che essa e infondata e
18
19 Come si potrebbe anche indurre da altre pagine della sua opera. Si veda
in frroposito il mio saggio citato sopra (n. 8) 1254-1256.
0 182 nota 4, sub fin.
21 Espresso da Mansfeld nella stessa pagina gia citata qui sopra, n. 20.
290
PIERLUIGI DONINI
che 1' uso del nome di Socrate nei due esempi non puo servire a
discriminare in nulla le due diverse opere in cui lo leggiamo.
Questo perche, come mostra precisamente il fatto che esso compaia
abbinato con il nome di Callia, nell'opuscolo il nome di Socrate
deve essere letto, secondo l'uso aristotelico ben noto,22 senza alcun
preciso riferimento al personaggio storico: e soltanto un modo di
riferirsi a persone reali, rna la cui individuazione precisa e irrilevante: e l' equivalente, insomma, dei nostri Tizio, Caio o Sempronio.
Diversa sarebbe stata l'importanza del caso se l'opuscolo avesse
citato Socrate in riferimento o alla stessa situazione in cui compare
nel trattato (il giudizio espresso su lui da Zopiro), o comunque a un
episodio preciso della vita del personaggio storico di quel nome.
Siamo forse ora in grado di capire il ragionamento di Alessandro benche esso rimanga largamente implicito e possiamo finalmente rendere conto in modo coerente tanto delle affermazioni del
cap. 6, quanto di quelle dei capitoli 27-29. E' verissimo, infatti, che
in questa serie di capitoli, apparentemente contraddicendo il 6, si
riconduce la formazione del carattere all'educazione, all'esercizio,
alle abitudini e non pili alla natura; rna si doveva aggiungere (cosa
che finora nessuno ha fatto) che in quei capitoli Alessandro intende parlare soprattutto e, anzi, quasi esclusivamente della formazione dei caratteri virtuosi, cioe del modo in cui si diventa cpp6vtJlot :
solo pochissimi e brevissimi sono gli accenni alia formazione dei
caratteri viziosi (e di questi ci occuperemo in un secondo tempo). Se
dunque il cap. 6--quando sia stato debitamente interpretato l'esempio di Socrate-concorda con 27-29 quanto all'ammissione che una
personalita virtuosa, formata come tale dalle abitudini contratte con
l'esercizio e l'educazione, e realmente un'occorrenza molto rara e
rappresenta un'eccezione alla regola che dice che Ia maggioranza
degli uomini e inferiore alla misura della virtu, tutto il discorso di
Alessandro puo assumere una sua coerenza anche se lascia
implicite troppe cose e sorvola inoltre su difficolta tutt'altro che
marginali. II significato complessivo potrebbe essere questo.
II fato e davvero identico alla natura, come vuole il cap. 6, e cioe
e identico negli uomini al destino gia iscritto nella costituzione
naturale della loro anima. Ma questo dominio del fato non si estende alla totalita degli uomini: come prevede Ia dottrina di Aristotele,
la natura puo funzionare come agente decisivo soltanto per una
22 Cfr. Bonitz, Index aristotelicus, 359b 56 e 74lb 45.
291
292
PIERLUIGI DONINI
293
25 EN X 9, 1180a 24-30.
294
PIERLUIGI DONINI
2B Si confronti con quello del De Jato il caso del trattato De anima che puo
essere messo in relazione al precedente commentario allo scritto di Aristotele dallo stesso titolo (in proposito, si veda l'introduzione di AccattinoDonini al De anima nell'edizione ricordata sopra - n. 23 ) . Anche senza
arrivare a parlare di carattere 'semipopolare' del De Jato (per il quale cfr.
Thillet, op. cit., - in n. 7 - CXXV) e pur ammettendo con Sharples, op. cit.,
(n. 14) 18 che il libro contiene anche parti di elevata tecnicita, rimane il
fatto che in esso Alessandro non si impegna direttamente mai nell'esegesi
di testi aristotelici che siano richiamati esplicitamente e analizzati parola per
parola, come invece accade nei commentari.
29 II commento di Sharples basta a suggerirlo. Sui metodo di lavoro di
Alessandro mi sia consentito di rinviare ancora una volta al commento di
Accattino-Donini al De anima di prossima pubblicazione.
30 Art.cit. (n. 1) 182 n. 4, cfr. anche R.W. Sharples, 'Alexander of Aphro-
295
del suo trattato sul destino dovrebbe bastare a suggerirci che egli
doveva aver lungamente e seriamente meditato sulle pagine di
almeno quella fra le tre etiche del Corpus (certamente, inoltre, su
un'EN che includeva gia i libri comuni).3I
Ma e infine doveroso che aggiungiamo a questa difesa della
coerenza di Alessandro anche l'ammissione che l'interpretazione
ora proposta non in grado di eliminare tutte le difficolta. Sull'origine del vizio i capitoli 27-29 del De Jato hanno, come si e detto,
qualche raro accenno che non
sempre possibile far concordare
con la tesi generale che ho creduto di attribuire ad Alessandro.
Una spiegazione e possibile trovare per l'implicito accenno di
p. 198,29;32 rna l'esordio del capitolo 27 rimane sotto molti aspetti
problematico:
296
PIERLUIGI DONINI
297
197,8.
Notevole sembra un altro passaggio del ragionamento di
Alessandro nel cap. 27, in cui c'e un'allusione inequivocabile, rna
anche alquanto problematica, alia teoria del cap. 6. Nel corso di un
argomento inteso a mostrare che le virtu non nascono in nessun
senso per natura, Alessandro osserva (a 197,30-198,3) che
niente di impossibile bisogna richiedere alia natura (essa e infatti Ia
misura del possibile e dell'impossibile; infatti Ia virtu e perfezione e
compimento sommo della natura propria di ciascuno ed e
impossibile che qualcosa che e imperfetto sia nella perfezione, rna
quel che e stato genera to e imperfetto non appena generato).
11 concetto di oh:Eia <pUcrt<;, natura propria, e precisamente quello
che appare centrale nella teoria del fato esposta nel cap. 6;
sennonche, Ia Ia natura propria e unicamente collegata al carattere
deteriore e al destino delle persone non virtuose, tanto da indurci a
pensare che quel che si ha alia nascita come costituzione naturale
dell'anima sia destinato a tradursi in un carattere vizioso ogni volta
che non intervenga l'educazione (o l'autoeducazione) mediante le
buone abitudini. Nei casi eccezionali in cui questo intervento ci sia,
l'opera dell'educazione consisterebbe allora essenzialmente nel
cancellare o radicalmente emendare il carattere naturale (cosi
appunto ci dice anche l'esempio di Socrate) e nessun positivo contributo questo carattere dovrebbe poter dare alla costituzione della
personalita virtuosa. Infatti, coerentemente con queste assunzioni,
implicite o esplicite che siano, lo stesso cap. 27 insiste a presentare
il contributo che Ia natura darebbe alla virtu soltanto nei termini di
Sharples (similarly). Non
298
PIERLUIGI DONINI
e detto
n. 26), di EN II 1.
Nel senso, dunque, in cui parla delle doti naturali Ia Politica VII 13,
1332b 1-3. Sono pen) evidenti le ragioni per cui Alessandro non poteva
adottare in modo esplicito questa soluzione: a parte il fatto che Ia Politica parla
della presenza innata solo di 'alcune' doti e non di tutte, se Alessandro avesse
ammesso che tali doti erano fondamentalmente ambigue e potevano essere
risolte in meglio o in peggio soltanto dai processi di assuefazione, avrebbe
anche dovuto rinunciare a identificare il fato con una natura a cui non poteva
piu attribuire Ia forza di determinare il corso successivo degli eventi quanto
meno nella maggior parte dei casi. L'intera sua teoria dell'identita tra fato e
natura avrebbe cosi dovuto limitarsi alia sola considerazione del livello della
generazione nelle specie biologiche senza poter discendere aile qualita degli
individui umani (o, tutt'al piu, dei tipi). Per qualche ragione (cfr.anche qui
sotto, nota 41) egli credette di non potersi limitare a questo livello, dove
certamente Ia sua teoria sarebbe potuta risultare piu aristotelica e piu coerente.
40 Cfr. il mio libro del 1974 cit. sopra (n. 3) 165-170.
38
(so~ra,
299
c'e
Universita di Milano
41 Cfr. Ia mia messa a punto del problema nel saggio citato sopra (n. 8)
soprattutto 1249-1258; e da ultimo le chiare osservazioni di D. Frede, art. cit.
(n. 34) 203 a proposito del carattere deterministico che si puo riconoscere
all'etica di Aristotele-Vorrei ancora aggiungere una precisazione. Nei miei
precedenti interventi, soprattutto nel libro citato sopra (n. 2), avevo ricondotto
all'influenza di Galeno Ia teoria esposta net De Jato che assume un'identiti fra
il carattere naturale e il destino. Non vedo contraddizione fra quell'ipotesi e
il suggerimento che do oggi e che mira a ricondurre all'interpretazione
sistematica dei passi aristotelici sulle doti naturali l'origine della concezione
alessandrista. E' infatti perfettamente concepibile che Alessandro, influenzato
da Galeno (di cui comunque conosceva qualcosa), o da una precedente tradizione peripatetica (per cui cfr. Mant. 186,28-31), si fosse convinto dell'importanza del carattere naturale legato alia costituzione dell'anima e che credesse
in buona fede di poter ricostruire Ia medesima concezione anche muovendo
dalle opere di Aristotele, di cui si sentiva comunque tenuto a offrire una
spiegazione che appianasse ogni incoerenza e oscurita. Del resto Galeno
stesso, nello scritto quod animi mores etc. (p. 51,12 sgg. Muller), si appella ad
Aristotele e cerca di includere Ia teoria aristotelica fra i garanti della sua tesi
deterministica. Un caso perfettamente analogo a quello del De Jato e fornito
dalla teoria alessandrista dell'origine dell'anima dalla mescolanza degli
elementi corporei: Alessandro Ia trovava gia presente nella tradizione
peripatetica e in Galeno, rna, d'altra parte, credeva anche di poterla ricavare
da un preciso testo di Aristotele. Riferimenti ai testi e alia letteratura in
Sharples, art. cit. (n. 30) 1203.
ALCINOUS' EPISTEMOLOGY
DAVID SEDLEY
ALCINOUS' EPISTEMOLOGY
301
develop a fuller account of how this last party handled the task, I
shall be analysing the Platonic exegesis propounded in Didaskalikos chapter 4.
Their outline position seems to have been as follows. Platonic
episteme, as explained in the Republic and Timaeus, has Ideas as its
objects, while the sensible world is the object of mere doxa. These
two faculties of episteme and doxa were jointly taken to map onto
what in the Hellenistic age had come to be known as the topic 'on
the criterion'-that is, the principles and means of cognition in
general. The Theaetetus was held to deal with only one half of this
topic, albeit the half which had become the central focus of
Hellenistic debates on the criterion: that is, the part which deals
with sensory cognition.3
The Theaetetus fails to find a definition of knowledge, but the
failure is interpreted as a calculated one. The search fails precisely
because what it in fact addresses itself to is the epistemology of the
sensible world, whereas knowledge has the Ideas as its proper
objects. Consequently, while it fails as an account of knowledge,
the Theaetetus succeeds as an investigation of the sensible world's
epistemological structure and of the cognitive faculties which bear
on it. It is to be plundered, not as a radical (and aporetic) reinvestigation of episteme, but as Plato's most fully elaborated account
of sensory cognition.
As for real episteme of the Ideas, it is held by this group of
Platonists that that topic is not tackled in the Theaetetus but in the
immediately succeeding dialogue, the Sophist. Their critic, the
anonymous commentator on the Theaetetus, sums up their view at
the beginning and end of the following passage (2.11-39):
Some of the Platonists have thought that the dialogue was on the
topic of the criterion, in view of the considerable space it also
of Dillon (op. cit.) xii-xiii and P.-L. Donini, 'Testi e commenti, manuali e
insegnamento: Ia forma sistematica e i metodi della filosofia in eta
postellenistica', ANRW II 36.7 (1994) 5027-5100, pp. 5057-8, who plead for a
date in the second century AD on the basis of comparisons with known
Platonists from Plutarch to Numenius. Nevertheless, it seems to me that we
still know far too little about first-century AD Platonism to exclude even so
early a dating. One thing, at least, has ceased to be controversial, and that is
the restoration of the author's name to the transmitted 'Alcinous', in place of
Freudenthal's century-old conjecture 'Albinus'.
3 I leave aside here the question how they managed to accommodate, or
discount, the Meno's definition of knowledge as a species of correct doxa. On
this, see my art. cit. (n. 1).
302
DAVID SEDLEY
LOGOS
divine
human
154.2!1-5
DOXASTIC LOGOS
ible, 154.21-!l)
tJrrou.gh which we judge,
154.10-21; 'natural',
155.!14-6
4 components of logos?
EPISTEMONIC LOGOS
154.25-!12
154.25-!12
doxai
epistimai haplai
154.40-155.1!1
155.!12-6
5 dispositional remnants
of cognitive activities
in 6.
6
.001.1Cft evvota
(etc.)/'memory'
(incarnate, dispositional)
memory
~ {
154.!16-155.1!1
155.20-!14
aisthesis
cognitive activities
(=)
noesis
= archai
(discarnate, active)
154.!12-4
155.20-!12
species of cognitive
activities
primary
secondary
objects of cognition
10 the species of 9
aiding doxastic
logos 156.9-10
aistheta
secondary
e.g. whiteness
155.42-156.1
primary
sensible world
156.1!1-14
athroismata
primary
secondary
Ideas
immanent forms
155.!19, 164.4-5 155.40-1
intelligible world
156.11-1!1
304
DAVID SEDLEY
ALCINOUS' EPISTEMOLOGY
305
Start on the right-hand side of the chart in line 6 with the cognitive
activity of v611crt<;. This is the discarnate soul's direct apprehension
of the Ideas, as described in the Phaedrus. When the soul is
incarnated, this same apprehension becomes (line 5) a set of
buried memories or innate conceptions. Severally, they are (line
4) simple pieces of knowledge ( bttcr'tfh.t.at a1tA.a'i), but jointly (line
3) they constitute epistemonic reason. This last identification
draws on the common Hellenistic notion of human reason as
constituted by a comprehensive set of ennoiai or conceptions. Thus
our epistemonic or scientific reason is, roughly speaking, an
innate capacity to handle a priori concepts, thanks to our souls' prenatal acquaintance with the Ideas.
An apparent anomaly must be tackled. In the lines just quoted,
Alcinous seems at pains to emphasize that 'intellection' (noesis) is a
term reserved for pre-natal direct acquaintance with the Ideas. Yet
he starts this very same passage by allowing, on the contrary, that
there are two species of noesis, of which one is prenatal contemplation of Ideas while the other in the incarnate soul's latent
memory of those same Ideas. Moreover, later in the chapter he is
ready to use noesis in yet another sense, namely the incarnate
soul's active contemplation of Ideas (156.5-8)-a usage, of course,
with excellent Platonic credentials. It is only within the confines
of the present context, the transition from pre-natal contemplation
to post-natal epistemonic logos, that the restricted usage is imposed.
Why so? The answer will, I think, become clear from the parallel
process by which doxastic logos is formed. Logos serves as a
criterion of truth because it is a stock of fundamental conceptsempirical concepts in the case of doxastic reason, a priori concepts
in the case of epistemonic reason-which furnish a standard
against which reasoning may be judged. In both cases this relies
on the presumption that the criterion in question is not itself the
outcome of any process of reasoning. Only thus are the dangers of
circularity or infinite regress averted-just the same requirement
that had underlain Hellenistic notions of the criterion from
Epicurus (Letter to Herodotus 37-8) onwards. 6 It is for this reason that
6 On the Hellenistic notion of a criterion, see esp. Gisela Striker,
Kpttt\ptov tfjc; aA.f19Eiac;, Nachrichten der Akademie der Wissenschaften in
Gottingen, Phil.-hist. Kl., (Gottingen 1974) 2, 47-110; and 'The problem of
the criterion', in Epistemology, ed. S. Everson, Companions to Ancient
Thought (Cambridge 1990) 143-60.
306
DAVID SEDLEY
ALCINOUS' EPISTEMOLOGY
307
308
DAVID SEDLEY
ALCINOUS' EPISTEMOLOGY
309
Regardless of these and other details, it seems clear that Alcinous is presenting us with an elaborated cognitive analysis of the
two modes of thought, that of doxa and that of episteme, which the
Republic graphically introduces to us with its parallelisms between
the lower and upper parts of the divided Line and between the
worlds inside and outside the Cave. The next question is where the
epistemology of the Theaetetus fits into this picture.
We have already seen how Part II of the Theaetetus-in particular the Wax Block analogy-is treated by Alcinous as Plato's
canonical account of doxa in the sense specified in the Republic,
fallible empirical cognition. We can now add that Theaetetus Part I
is used as Plato's guide to the epistemological structure of the
sensible world. A distinction is first made (I.e. diagram lines 6-7,
right-hand side) between primary and secondary noesis, distinguished (lines 9-10) by their objects, these being transcendent
Ideas in the case of primary noesis and immanent forms in the
case of secondary noesis:
Therefore, there being both epistemonic and doxastic reason, and
both intellection and perception, there are also the objects of these,
namely intelligibles and perceptibles. And since of intelligibles
some are primary, namely the Ideas, and others secondary, namely enmattered forms which are inseparable from the matter, intellection will also be of two kinds, namely that of primary and that of
secondary intelligibles. (155.36-42)
An analogous set of distinctions is then made for aisthisis (lines 67 and 9-10):
And again, since of perceptibles some are primary, namely
qualities like the colour whiteness, others accidental, like the object
coloured white, and, posterior to these, the aggregate ( &9potcrJ.ta ),
e.g. fire, honey, so too of perception one kind, called 'primary', will
be of primary perceptibles, and the other, called 'secondary', of
secondary perceptibles. (155.42-156.5)
For once Whittaker's excellent apparatus on the Platonic and Aristotelian antecedents is incomplete. He cites Aristotle De anima II 6,
which is certainly the correct antecedent for the terminology of
'accidental' perceptibles, but overlooks the passage's far more
profound dependence on Theaetetus 156d-157c. 12 There Socrates can
12 Whittaker (op. cit. [n. 2] 86 n. 65) does note the occurrence of athroisma
at Tht. 157b9, but does not appear to regard the present passage as alluding to
it. Dillon (op. cit. [n. 2] 70-1) is more attuned to the Theaetetan echoes,
including 157b9. However, he emphasizes 182a-rightly, but at the expense of
the more important 156d-157c.
310
DAVID SEDLEY
ALCINOUS' EPISTEMOLOGY
311
312
DAVID SEDLEY
soon after (29b) that the intelligible and sensible worlds each have
their own appropriate kind of logos, Alcinous is confident that doxa
at 28a is simply a shorthand for 'doxastic logos'. He has already
carefully prepared the ground for this equivalence by telling us
earlier (154.28-9, p. 304 above) that doxastic logos is sometimes
simply called doxa.
(This realization that doxa, and not bare sense-perception, is
required if we are to have cognitive access to athroismata, can now
be fed back into our earlier inquiry as to whether the passage from
aisthesis (line 6) to doxastic logos (line 3) need be mediated by doxa.
Since doxastic logos deals with complex perceptual items like fire
and man, there should now be no doubt that mere sense-perception
can never be a sufficient foundation for it, and that doxa must be
indispensable to the process of its formation.)
Alcinous' exegetical strategy is hideously complicated. But if we
persevere in tracing it, we can begin to see how thoroughly he and
his fellow-proponents of the interpretation have integrated the
epistemology of Theaetetus Parts I and II into a global reconstruction
of Plato's two-world system. On his view, the Theaetetus may
profess to be an inquiry into knowledge, but in reality it is Plato's
fullest account of perceptual cognition and its objects, demonstrating the parallel structures of the intelligible and sensible worlds.
In this way it analyses the type of reason to which we may appeal
in a cosmological investigation like that conducted in Alcinous'
own favourite dialogue, the Timaeus. Matters of no small importance are at stake:
The aim of physics is to learn what is the nature of the universe;
what sort of animal man is and what place he has in the world;
whether god exercises providence over things in their entirety;
whether this god has others subordinate to him; and what the
relation of human beings is to the gods. (161.3-7)
To reconstruct what cognitive capacity, in Plato's view, entitles us
to reason about such questions is no mean achievement.I5
Cambridge
15 I have benefited from discussion of this material in the Didaskalikos
seminar held at Cambridge in May 1995, and in the Seminaire Leon Robin
at the Sorbonne in December 1995. My thanks to participants in both seminars-including, at the former, the honorand of this volume Jaap Mansfeld,
whose expertise and good will contributed so much to the entire occasion.
W.
VANDER HORST
314
315
316
317
318
with an unadulterated gospel. A good example is found in Alexander's earlier compatriot and fellow Platonist, Clement of Alexandria, who says in his Strom. VII xvii 106-7 that the Lord founded the
Catholic Church in the times of Tiberius and that it is evident from
the high antiquity and perfect truth of this church that the later
heresies, from the times of Hadrian and Antoninus onwards, were
new inventions and therefore falsifications of the original truth.24
This myth of Christian origins became immensely influential. In
fact it remained the standard Christian view for some 1500 years
until it was subverted at the end of the 17th century when Gottfried
Arnold published his important Unparteiische Kirchen- und Ketzerhistorie ( 1699-1 700) .
Now one could of course argue that Alexander's observation of
the splitting up of the Christian philosophy into numerous factions
can simply be explained by the fact that in his days Egyptian
Christianity was indeed split up into numerous sects, as the Nag
Hammadi Codices, the Kellis papyri, the Coptic Manichaica, the
other early Coptic literature, and the writings of the Graeco-Egyptian Churchfathers bear witness. All of these testifY to such a great
variety and wide divergence of opinion in Christian Egypt that
any observer could have come to the same conclusion as Alexander.25 This view does not hold, however, for the simple reason that
a wide variety of viewpoints, and even the fact that the various
Christian parties themselves argued that they and only they were
continuing the original unity of doctrine, would not automatically
lead to a conclusion by an outsider to the effect that an original
'simple philosophy' was adulterated only by later (emyEVOjlEVOt is
Alexander's term) depraved adherents. So it would seem that Alexander's view derives from Christian authors or theorists, the more
so since he joins them in accusing the 'dissenters' of 'theoretical
imprecision' (1, p. 4 Br.) which formed the basis of the decline of
24 See also the fragment of Hegesippus (jloruit 3rd quarter of the 2nd cent.)
in Eusebius, Hist. Eccl. IV 22, 4-5, where this author says that the earliest
Church leaders 'used to call the Church a virgin for this reason that she had
not yet been seduced by listening to nonsense,' but soon afterwards this
process of corruption and heresy started. Cf. also the similar statements in
the slightly later Irenaeus, Adv. Hacreses III 4. See S. J. D. Cohen, 'A Virgin
Defiled. Some Rabbinic and Christian Views on the Origin of Heresies',
Union Seminary QJlarterly Review 35 (1980) 1-11, and esp. A. Le Boulluec, La notion
d 'heresie dans la litterature grecque Ile-Ille siecles, vol. 2 (Paris 1985).
25 See W. Bauer, Orthodoxy and Heresy in Earliest Christianity (London 1972)
44-60 (though no longer up to date).
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
58 Villey, Alexandre 279. Cf. also Alexander's remark in ch. 24 (p. 36 Br.):
'To have Christ submit to passion to make something manifest is utter
foolishness, when words are sufficient for the teaching and the knowledge of
what is.'
59 Compare Porphyry's remark that Jesus was one of the wise men of the
Hebrews (from De philosophia ex oraculis haurienda, quoted by Augustine, Civ. Dei
XIX 23). Geffcken, Ausgang 77, reckons Alexander among those who 'Porphyrios' Gerechtigkeit gegen Christus selbst noch weiter entwickelt haben.' On
Por~hyry's praise of Jesus see also Wilken, Christians 148-56, 159-60.
6
It is notable that in the third-century Acts of Thomas 2 the apostle
Thomas is also presented as a carpenter. In the Gospels Jesus is himself the
son of a carpenter.
328
men, the most wicked tax-collectors and sailors, and with these he
fled hither and thither, collecting a means of livelihood in a
disgraceful and importunate way' (CCI 61); and, similarly, in CCII
46: 'When he was alive he won over ten sailors and tax-collectors
of the most abominable character.' 61 And especially in CCIII 59-69
Celsus mocks Jesus' and the Christians' love for 'sinners' and tries
to demonstrate that this leads to the church's being nothing but a
band of criminals. 62 Not so Alexander. Of course, his enumeration
of the professions of Jesus' followers implies that they were lower
class people, who for that very reason needed 'simple and easy
conversations' but, contrary to Celsus, he does believe that Jesus
was succesful in bringing these simple people to a higher level
and a genuine 'desire for the good.'63
Even though the subject under consideration deserves more of an
in depth treatment than was possible in this short paper, we may
briefly summarize our provisional findings. Alexander had some
knowledge of the Bible but it was not extensive (especially when
compared with that of his predecessor Celsus and his contemporary and fellow-Platonist Porphyry, not to speak of the later Julian).
It cannot even be excluded that all the biblical references in his
work are based on hearsay, not on his own reading. The (only?)
biblical books he appears to have had some knowledge of were
Genesis and the Gospels (as usual among pagan authors with some
knowledge of the Bible), and perhaps also of 2 Timothy. But ~his
61 The Gospels mention four fishermen ('sailors') and one tax-collector as
Jesus' disciples. In CCI 62 Origen rejoins that a sailor is not the same as a
fisherman and, moreover, that, contrary to the suggestion by Celsus, of the
majority of the disciples we do not at all know what were the trades by
which they earned their living. Yet the designation 'fishermen' for the
apostles (and sometimes for Christians in general) is found more often; see
J. H. Waszink, Tertulliani De anima (Amsterdam 1947) 119. On Celsus' (and
others') uncertainty about the: number of disciples see W. Bauer, 'Das Apostelbild in der altchristlichen Uberlieferung', in E. Hennecke & W. Schneemelcher (edd.), Neutestamentliche Apokryphen, vol. 2 (Tubingen 1971, 3. Au1.)
11-12.
62 CC III 55 makes clear that it is probably also Celsus' own experiences
with Christians in his environment that colours his depiction of Jesus'
followers. Cf. also Lucian, De morte Peregrini 13. See on this topic further W.
Bauer, Das Leben Jesu im Zeitalter der neutestamentlichen Apokryphen (Tubingen
1909, repr. Darmstadt 1967) 426-7.
63 Unlike Alexander, Celsus heaps scorn upon the person of Jesus; for a
list of references see S. Benko, 'Pagan Criticism of Christianity During the
First Two Centuries A.D.', ANRWII 23, 2 (Berlin 1980) 1102.
329
PART SIX
1. Introduction
Aristotle's introductory discussions of earlier views on specific
philosophical issues have been studied from different angles. One
fairly recent line of investigation makes use of his handbook on
dialectic, the Topika.I This has proven profitable in many ways, but
has also created a (minor) problem af terminology. Whenever the
introductions are labelled 'dialectical', the meaning of this term is
usually considered as sufficiently clear. However, it hardly ever
receives an explicit definition.2 It seems to take on at least two basic
meanings: 1. Aristotle engages in a critical debate (ou:xA.eyecr8cxt)
and aims at scrutinizing the views; 3 2. Aristotle makes use of
certain techniques (diairesis, aporia, diaphOnia) indicated as useful in
the Topics, which provide the structure for the selection and
presentation of earlier doxai. These are very general ways of
clarifying his approach and are for the most part based on a few
passages in the Topics (mainly the programmatic books A and 8). 4
My objective in this paper is a modest one: (1) I will explore the
possibility of defining the label 'dialectical' more accurately than
has been customary hitherto, 5 and (2) I will argue that the actual
topoi of the central books of the Topics deserve more attention as an
aid for analysing the doxai-discussions. 6 Among several illustrative
vero magistro.
Fundamental paper by Wei! (1951). See Baltussen (1993) ch. 2 for further
literature.
2 His approach in these passages has also been labelled 'doxographical' or
even 'historical'. For some remarks on these (problematic) terms see section 2.
3 For this function of dialectic see Top. 101b4 E~Eta<rnKit and Rhet. 1354a5
1
phiinia (not an Aristotelian term!) see esp. Mansfeld (1990) 3060, 3063, 3092 ff.
5 Mansion (1961) 41 calls his method in Phys. A 'preparation dialectique'
without further clarification; not so Mansfeld ( 1990) 3063 who speaks of
overviews 'for dialectical purposes' or of 'a dialectical discussion (which may
even be purely didactic) .. .' (ibid. 3064) (cf. n. 4).
6 I prefer the expression 'doxaHliscussion' instead of 'doxography' because
334
HAN BALTUSSEN
2. A note on terminology
Since it may not be apparent why Aristotle's approach towards
previous views may be labelled 'dialectical' (rather than 'historical'
or 'doxographical'), some introductory remarks on terminology
are called for. In our view the alternative terms bring in connotations (and analyses) which are either anachronistic or inappropriate, and may actually be misleading in our understanding of
Aristotle's (and Theophrastus') actual procedure.
In modern studies the term 'doxography' appears to mean 'a
description or summary of what philosophers have said', where
it highlights the role of doxa and at the same time draws a distinction
between doxaHiiscussions and doxaH:ollections (cf. below n. 8).
7 Modern studies using the technical elements are e.g. Schickert (1977) 48
ff. (on the Eudemus/ De an. A), Morsink (1982), Beriger (1989) 81 ff. (on
Metaph. M 1-3).
8 The use of endoxa -the mark of applied dialectic- as views endorsed by
'reputable men' (Top. 100b21-23) is more than apparent: apart from adducing
qualified opinions (see esp. 407b4-5, 13, 27) Aristotle adds a positive formulation of a better perspective which itself is backed up by endoxic views ( 408a34b20). Compare 408a10 where he characterizes the discussion as the testing of
views (E'i>E~Etam:o~).
9 Despite many remarks on dialectical aspects Hicks ( 1907) does not
mention it.
10 Irwin's distinction (1988) 19 ff., 116 between 'strong dialectic' and 'pure
dialectic' seems less appropriate, because it does not take its cue from
Aristotle. It has met with strong criticism, see e.g. D.W. Hamlyn, Philosophy
65 (1990) 465-476, R. Wardy, Phronesis 26 (1991) 86-106.
335
336
HAN BALTUSSEN
and methodology (justification of sources and the aim of being objective) show that he did not self-consciously aim at such an approach.
It could be argued that Aristotle's investigations into the political
constitutions bring him closer to the historian than anything
else.16 Here as in biology his 'investigations' (ia-ropi<X1.) are of a
descriptive character, providing a first collection of the facts.l7 His
conviction that not knowledge of the particular, but of the universal, was essential must have guided him: by supplying himself
with the necessary material he would then be in a position to
perform the inductive reasoning towards the universal. 1B Clearly,
then, ia-rop{a is a term of wide application. 19 It can hardly support
the view that Aristotle was a historian sensu stricto. 2o Considerations
such as these must (and did) lead to the view that Aristotle did not
write (and did not intend to write) history of philosophy.2 1 The
main reason is that Aristotle is very selective in what he thinks is
useful for his own purposes.22
Since it is clear that the terms just discussed are problematic, I
propose to concentrate on the term 'dialectical' as the one which
offers the least problems. For this we may take a look at the Topics,
where we find a connection between arguments and doxai (e.g.
Top. A 14)23 and a statement which presents Aristotle's different
It is said of the works on politics and laws. See the references in n. 22.
Of course they are more concerned with facts than his doxai-discussions.
On historia see the thorough study by Zoepffel (1975) from which I take over
some conclusions.
18 In this respect there is a parallel with the basic principles of dialectic,
see e.g. Top. 105a12-20; 108b10-12. For a more elaborate exposition on the role
of the universal in linking history and Aristotle's general theory of knowled~e see Zoepffel (1975) 17 ff.
9 Zoepffel (1975) 33.
20 Even the famous passage in Poetics A 9, which brings the term historikos
close to what we would interpret as 'historical', cannot alter this conclusion.
Zoepffel (1975: 14f.) argues persuasively that in this passage, where Aristotle
calls poetry 'more philosophical than history, because it says more on the
universal, whereas history deals with the particular', the emphasis of the
comparative form is on poetry; hence it does not follow that (1) it also goes
with the particular thereby 'saving' a bit of the universal for history nor that
(2) poetry is philosophical in an absolute sense.
21 As Barnes has put it (1987, 25): 'These accounts have a historical purpose
and they are written with a philosophical intention; but they are not, properly sfeaking, 'histories of philosophy".
2
Meier (1930), von Fritz (1958), Weil (1965), Huxley (1973) 282 all use
the term 'historical'. More careful views are found in Reinhardt (1954) 82 ff.,
Braun (1973) 16, 20f.
23 Note that even the Greek commentators made a connection between
certain 'doxographic' discussions in Aristotle and the mandate of Top. A 2
!6
17
337
options for the use of dialectic, viz. ( 1) training, (2) everyday discussions, (3a) philosophy (where it may have several functions),
one of which is (3b) the search for archai in all fields of investigation (Top. A 2.10la25-b4).
Admittedly these are very general descriptions, but the inference seems warranted that modes (2), (3a) and (3b), which represent several stages of increasing technical complexity, build onand therefore reflect-the features of (1). And while (2) may have
left its traces mainly in rhetoric, (3a) and (3b) are very likely to be
found in Aristotle's philosophical research. They are different
modes of the same techne and may be regarded as offshoots of the
same stem.2 4 I would prefer to use the term 'dialectical' with reference to these, i.e. Aristotle's own, options. In my view it is against
this general background that we should try to establish to what
extent certain features of his treatment in the doxai-discussions
warrant use of the term 'dialectical'. I will now proceed to deal
briefly with some examples of how such technical features are
applied in a systematic context.
338
HAN BALTUSSEN
points to some parallels with the Physica: 2.1, 192b13-15, 22; 8.4,
254bl4.
31 Similar terminological distinctions are at the basis of the discussion of
soul as 'harmonia' at 407b27 ff., 'a further theory which has come down to us,
commending itself to many minds as readily as any that is put forward' (esp.
b31 and 408a5). See also section (III).
339
the line of reasoning behind this view-the body consists of opposites, a harmonia is a blending (Kpiic:nc;) or combining (cruv9Ecrtc;) of
opposites, the soul is a harmonia. In his view (407b32 ff.) harmonia
must either mean a ratio (A.oyoc;) between or a combination (cruv9Ecrtc;) of components, but the soul is (a) neither of these (b33) and
((3) this theory cannot explain the cause of motion.
The emphasis on terminology is important, as Aristotle thinks it
is preferable to apply the term harmonia to health or in general to
bodily excellence ( 408al). In the ensuing paragraph ( 408a5 ff.) he
goes even further and distinguishes two senses of harmonia. Much
is now made of the meaning of 'combination' (cruv9Ecrtc;), positing
that 'there are many combinations of the parts, and they combine
in many ways' (allf.). Aristotle asks for clarification as to how the
intellect combines with a part of the body, what the relation is with
the appetites, and denies that the mixture in flesh is identical to that
in bone. 32
The argument(s) concerning part and whole and concerning
'combination' (cruv9Ecrtc;) in Top. Z (which deals specifically with
definition) contain the 'blue-print' so to speak for the tactics in our
passage in the De an.: regarding composition one should state its
method (150b22-26) and what kind is meant (15la22-25). We may
compare:
De an. 408all-1233
~toUai te yap ai c:ruv6roet~ t&v llEpii'>v
en
340
HAN BALTUSSEN
The whole passage constitutes a kind of diairesis in which disjunctive options are followed through (thus (iii) follows (ii), (a) is
connected to (iii) and (b) to (i)). The question dealing with the
scheme parts-and-whole takes up one of the initial questions of De
an. A 1 and illustrates how the earlier views sometimes fail to
comply to Aristotelian standards. The most interesting point in
mixture of the elements which makes flesh has a different ratio from that
which makes bone.' (tr. Hicks, modified; italics mine).
35 'see if he has failed to state the manner of combination ... First, see
whether he has omitted to state the kind of composition, as (e.g.) in the
definition of flesh or bone as the combination of fire, earth, and air. For it is
not enough to say it is a composition, but you should also go on to define the
kind of combination'.
341
37
Otll7t0poUV't~ ... 'tac; 'tOOV 1tpo'tEprov oo~ac; ... Ei OE 'tl uiJ lCllA.i.ik [sc. tipll~ll], 'tOU't'
342
HAN BALTUSSEN
343
I am grateful to K.A. Algra, D.T. Runia and T.L. Tieleman for some
very useful remarks on an earlier version of this paper.
344
HAN BALTUSSEN
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Theophrastus' De sensibus is a unique source of information concerning earlier Greek philosophers' opinions on sense perception
and perceptible properties.2 If his work had not survived, we would
lack details pertinent to understanding Parmenides' obscure lines
on human thought (fr. 16 DK), and we would know very little
I offer this paper as a sixtieth birthday present to my friend Jaap Mansfeld. As the world's greatest expert on the doxography of Greek philosophy,
he will be the first to spot its shortcomings and the first to build on anything
of value it contains.
Much of my material was presented to the Theophrastus conference, which
took place on Lesbos in August 1989. I am grateful for the comments from participants that I received on this occasion, and also to Tom Rosenmeyer, who
helped me to improve this final version. Mter I had submitted it, the editors
recalled my attention to H. Baltussen's chapter, 'Theophrastus' De sensibus and
Plato's Timaeus', which forms part of his doctoral dissertation, Theophrastus on
Theories of Perception. Argument and Purpose in the De sensibus, written under the
direction of Jaap Mansfeld and Hans Gottschalk, and published as vol. VI of
Quaestiones injinitae. Publications of the Department of Philosophy, Utrecht University
(Utrecht 1993). Although there is some overlap in the material we discuss
and in our respective findings, our approaches are so different that I find it
best to let my original text stand for the most part. My purpose is largely
limited to comparing Theophrastus' reports on Plato, as clearly as possible,
with the relevant passages of the Timaeus. Baltussen's study offers much more
in the way of attempts to explain and partly justify Theophrastus' procedures.
2 Assessments of Theophrastus' accuracy in the De sensibus vary considerably. Citing Stratton (n. 3 below), Charles Kahn wrote: 'The performance of
Theophrastus here [i.e. his treatment of Plato], in the sole case where we can
fully control his use of source material, is fine enough to justify a modern
editor's praise of the "high accuracy" of his "dispassionate and marvellously
impartial report", Anaximanderand the Origins of Greek Cosmology (New York 1960)
21. Yet, Statton himself also admitted that Theophrastus, in his criticism of
Plato, 'seems oftener to miss the point' (p. 53). For a very different assessment,
cf. J. McDiarmid, who, in his article 'Theophrastus on the Presocratic Causes',
HSCPh 61 (1953) 133, wrote: 'The fragments considered disclose no evidence
that Theophrastus employed his knowledge of the Presocratics in such a way
as to exercise independent judgment about them ... He has frequently misrepresented his source and has exaggerated the faults present in it. It must be
concluded that, with regard to the Presocratic causes at least, he is a thoroughly biased witness and is even less trustworthy than Aristotle'. To place this
comment in perspective, note J. Mansfeld's comment in his Studies in the Historiography of Greek Philosophy (Assen-Maastricht 1990) 24: 'There is no doxography in the proper sense of the word in Aristotle or Plato, or even in Theophrastus, because the doxai at issue are presented from a systematical point of
view in order to further the discussion of problems of a systematical nature'.
346
A.A. LONG
about the relevant doctrines of Alcmaeon, Anaxagoras and Democritus. Theophrastus' lengthy treatment of Empedocles includes
many points that could not be inferred from the surviving fragments or from other secondary sources. In one instance only,
Plato, we are able to compare Theophrastus' reports with his own
source. Although he does not name the Timaeus, all his information about Plato in the De sensibus, as G.M. Stratton observed, seems
'to be drawn exclusively from' that dialogue.3 Indeed, according to
the same scholar, when he deals in the last part of the work (Sens.
83-91) with Plato's treatment ofperceptibles (aicrOrrra), Theophrastus preserves Plato's order of exposition 'without a single change'.
'This', he continues, 'with the various verbal similarities, makes
one almost see Theophrastus at work with the Timaeus spread
before him'. 4 My purpose in this paper is very simple-to exhibit
what happens when we study Theophrastus' treatment of Plato in
the De sensibus on the basis of Stratton's observation. 5
At the beginning of the work Theophrastus divides the majority
of opinions concerning ai"cr~crt~ into two groups: those that explain
it 'by likeness', and those that explain it 'by the opposite'. As proponents of the first explanation he cites Parmenides, Empedocles and
Plato. In aligning Plato with Empedocles, Theophrastus follows
Aristotle (De an. I 2, 404bl6) whose justification for the claim is
tendentious if not impenetrable. 6 After elaborating on the two types
of explanation, Theophrastus makes the following observation:
As for each particular sense, practically all of them are neglectful,
but Empedocles does try to refer them too to likeness (Sens. 3).
Theophrastus returns to Plato, after a page on Parmenides, with
these words:
3 G.M. Stratton, Theophrastus and the Greek physiological psychology before
Aristotle (London-New York 1917) 159. Stratton's text, which I draw on here,
is substantially that of Diels in his Doxographi Graeci. A new Bude text is bring
prepared by Andre Laks and Glenn Most.
4 Ibid. 203.
5 Baltussen (n. 1 above), p. 129, says: 'We should certainly not imagine
Theophrastus at work' in the way Stratton intimated. I demur. For even if, as
is probable, Theophrastus is writing on the basis of excerpts of the Timaeus,
Baltussen himself assumes (p. 127) that 'Theophrastus has consulted the (complete) Tim. text', and acknowledges the verbatim character of some of his
reports.
6 Aristotle ad Zoe. refers to 'Plato in the Timaeus'. R.D. Hicks, in his great
commentary on the De anima, comments: 'The reference is to the 'lfUXoyovia
in Timaeus 34C sqq.', and 'that like is known by like is the assumption underlying the language of Tim. 47A-C'. I confess to doubt about both proposals.
347
7 Cf. Stratton op. cit. (n. 3) 220: 'Theophrastus here does great violence to
Plato's doctrine'. See also D.N. Sedley, 'Empedocles' theory of vision', in
W.W. Fortenbaugh & D. Gutas, Theophrastus. His Psychological, Doxographical and
Scientific Writings (New Brunswick-London 1992) 26-31.
348
A.A. LONG
64a-65b
65b-66c
66d-67a
67a-c
67c-68d
8 Cf. H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci (Berlin 1879) 4.13.11, Aetius = Ps. Plut. 4.13
901C, Stob. Eel. 1.52.7. Both texts use the expression nA.a.trovtK'iJ auva.uyna. in
summarising Plato's theory of sight.
9 Cf. Alcinous, The Handbook of Platonism, ed. J. Dillon (Oxford 1993), chs.
18-19. Alcinous' reports of the Timaeus are much clearer and more accurate
than those of Theophrastus, especially in the case of sight, though he too
omits Plato's description of transmission back to the eye and the soul. Yet, as
Dillon notes ( 144-5), Alcinous seems to have been influenced directly or
indirectly by the De sensibus. This appears in his treatment of flavours, and
also in the Aristotelianism of his allusion to 'natural place' in his account of
Plato's theory of weight.
349
350
A.A. LONG
7) 30.
351
each other.) It passes out of the eye for a distance and coalesces with
the effluence, and that is how we see (Sens. 5).
Theophrastus draws this extremely condensed report from both
contexts of the Timaeus. He begins by alluding to Plato's first point
in (3), but he omits the fact that the eye's fire is light and also that
what it coalesces with is day-light. 11 Plato adduces the principle of
'like by like' to explain this coalescence. Theophrastus, however,
implies that Plato uses the principle for a different purpose-to
explain the relation of sight to colour. He takes Plato's reference to
the commensurability of colour and visual ray particles to involve
an explanation of sight by 'likeness', conflating symmetry of
particles to likeness of substance.
If this is regarded as a relatively minor distortion of Plato's
theory, such charity cannot extend to the rest of Theophrastus'
account. Without Plato's text we would have the impression that he
regarded sight as simply the effect of external interaction between
the visual ray and a colour effluence, without reference to transmission back to the eye and the soul. That impression is hardly
corrected when Theophrastus adds:
One could classify Plato's opinion as intermediate between those
who claim that sight falls upon its object and those who say it is a
case of transmission from visual objects to sight (Sens. 5).
For Plato the coalescence of colour and visual ray particles begins
outside the eye, but seeing occurs as a result of the way that
coalescence changes the visual ray and so affects the eye and
eventually the soul. By omitting all reference to Plato's points ( 4)
and (8), Theophrastus credits him with a misleadingly crude
theory of seeing as the contact between two fires outside the eye.
Plato on sound and hearing
352
A.A. LONG
Plato
0~ IJ.EV o.Ov <pCOVTJV ero!J.EV 'tlJV Ot, cittrov
im' aepo~ EYKE<paA.ou 'tE Klli lltiJ.Il'tO~
IJ.EXPt wuxfi~ 7tAt]'Y'lV OtllOtOOIJ.EVllV, 'tlJV
OE im' ll'lhfi~ KlVllOtV, a7to 'tfi~ KE<paA.fi~
~v apx;OIJ.EvllV, 'tEAE'Il'tiDallV OE 7tEpi 'tlJV
'tOU ll1tll't0~ eOpllV, aKO~V.
Theophrastus (Sens. 6)
aKolJV OE ou'x 'tfj~ <provfi~ opt~E'tllt . <pCOVTJV
yap etvat 7tA11YlJV im' aepo~ EyKE<paAo'll
Klli lltiJ.Il'tO~ Ot' cO'tCOV IJ.EXPt wuxfi~. 'tlJV
0' ll1t0 'tllU'tll~ KlVllOtV a1t0 KE<pllAfj~
~x;pt ll1tll't0~ aK~V.
By starting his account with the statement, 'Plato defines hearing through sound', Theophrastus gives the erroneous impression
that Plato takes hearing (the effect of the motion caused by sound
on the percipient's organs and soul) to be itself a sound. Thus the
unwary reader will take Plato's account of hearing to be an
instance of Theophrastus' general characterization of those who
explain sense perception 'by effluence and the transmission of like
to like' (Sens. 1). Apart from this, his report is impeccable and
almost verbatim. Here, in contrast with what he says about Plato's
treatment of sight, Theophrastus makes it clear that the sensory
stimulus has to reach the soul in order to be registered as such.
Why his treatment of the Timaeus should be so tendentious in the
one case and so accurate in the other is a question that is easier to
ask than to answer. For the present, I put it on one side, and
continue the comparison.
Plato's treatment of sound and hearing continues (Tim. 67b) with
a brief statement about how sounds vary in pitch, smoothness and
volume respectively according to the speed, regularity and size of
the motions that produce them. Much later (Tim. 80a-b) he gives a
fuller explanation of harmony and dissonance. Theophrastus
draws briefly on both contexts at Sens. 85, where he is dealing with
perceptibles. First, substituting o for yap, he repeats word for word
the sentence q>rovitv ... J.lEXPt 'lfUXll~ from Sens. 6. Next, he reports
Plato's explanation of differences of pitch, but omits Plato's further
reference to smooth, harsh, loud and soft sounds. Thus he says
nothing about regularity and size as further differentiae of soundproducing movements. He concludes by saying:
Sounds are in concord when the beginning of the slow sound is like
the end of the swift one.
This is a cryptic paraphrase of part of Plato's very difficult account,
which runs:
353
As to the swift and slow sounds that appear high and low, they are
dissonant when the motion they produce in us is dissimilar, and
concordant when that motion is similar. For the slower sounds catch up
with the motions of the earlier and swifter ones, which are already
fading and have reached a similar state to the motion that the
slower sounds, as they approach later, generate in them; when
these slower sounds encounter the others, they do not cause discord
by introducing a different movement but the beginning of a slower
movement which accords with the faster one that is ending, and by contributing similarity they cause a unitary experience in which high and
low are blended.
If Theophrastus had to restrict his paraphrase of this to thirteen
words, he could scarcely have done better. Even so, his words are
so condensed that they do little more than record his favourite
preoccupation in De sensibus--'likeness' as an explanatory factor in
sense perception. In particular, we are left without any understanding of how the two movements come to be 'like' one another,
which is Plato's main point.
Plato on tactile properties (Tim. 61e-64a)
12 Stratton op. cit. (n.3) 204 mistakenly refers to 'the three factors to which
Plato attributes the cutting power of heat', omitting the 'thinness' of the
particles' edges.
354
A.A. LONG
Plato
In his subsequent criticism of Plato's doctrine (Sens. 88-9), Theophrastus acknowledges Plato's refusal to define heavy and light
355
a1tAro~, but he adds, very misleadingly, that 'he defines them 'with
respect to what is made of earth'. In fact, Plato no more defines
terrestrial weight than weight in any other region. He takes the
earth as a region by means of which he can explain the principle
of relative weight (Tim. 63c-d). Theophrastus' critique of Plato,
which 'is only repeating Aristotle', as A.E. Taylor says in his commentary on the Timaeus ad loc., gives his readers no opportunity to
grasp the radical divergence between Plato's theory of relative
weight and the Aristotelian theory of objective weight or lightness
as a function of the elements' movement to their natural places.
Rough and smooth: Of these tactile properties Theophrastus says
(Sens. 83):
He passes over them, on the ground that they are sufficiently clear,
and says nothing.
The first part of this sentence is broadly true, the second totally
false. Plato writes (Tim. 63e):
Everyone, I think, who has seen the cause of the sensation of
smooth and rough could explain it to someone else; for the latter is a
combination of hardness and unevenness, and the former is
brought about by a combination of evenness and density.
356
A.A. LONG
357
Plato
... y{]tv<X ~p111C<X't<Xt111COJ.1EV<X {fi)Vcl'YEt ta q>Af3ta
Kat ci1to~1Jpa\vet, tpax{mpa ~ ovta atpu<pva,
~nov o tpaxuvovta au<rtTJpa <paivemt
ta o tout(l)v te pu1tnKa !Cal. 1t&v to 1tepl.
tlJV yA.&tt<XV cX1t01tAUvovta, 1tEp<X flEV tou
f.I.Etp{ou tOlltO Oprovt<X K<Xt 1tpO<JE1ttA<XJlf3avOflEV<X ro<JtE cXltOtTtKEtv autil~ til~ q>U<JE(l)~
otov fJ t&v A.hpffiv MvaJlt~. lttKpa 1tciv6' out(!)~
wvoJlaatat, ta o imooeeatepa til~ A.ttpwoou~ E~E(l)~ Eltt to f.I.Etpt6v tE tfl pu1j1Et
XPIDflEV<X W..uJCa iiveu lttK~to~ tpaxda~ ...
As this comparison shows, Theophrastus gives an accurate paraphrase of Plato's treatment of astringent, harsh, bitter, and salty, but
he reverses Plato's order of presenting the latter pair of flavours and
omits soda, Plato's illustrative example for explaining the difference between them.
Next he reduces Plato's six-line explanation of 'pungent' (Optj.!Ea)
to a single line (ibid.):
Things that are warm and move upward and have a cutting effect
are pungent ( tn 8epJ.latVOJ.l.EV!l K!lt &vw cpepOJ.l.EV!l K!lt Ot!lKptVOVt!l
optJJ.ia).
oe
This is a brilliant description of the sensations concomitant on eating spicy food. Theophrastus, having falsely declared that Plato has
nothing to say on taste, makes Plato's report virtually unintelligible.
Next, Theophrastus writes (ibid.):
Things that have a seething effect are sharp (tn
oe K\)K&vta o~w).
In his lengthy account (Tim. 66a-b) Plato uses the word 'seething' to
describe the general effect that (probably) acidic substances have
on the blood vessels of the tongue, an effect he actually calls
'bubbles, boiling and fermentation'. He does not characterise the
gustatory sensation itself as 'sharp', but says 'the cause of these
sensations is called sharp' .13
13
358
A.A. LONG
Plato
Eiaiv tE o<rJlal aUJllta<rat JCaJtvoc; ft OJlll(All,
to{mov o to JlEV ~ ciEpoc; de; uorop iov
OJlll(All, too ~ UOatoc; de; &epa JCaJtv6c;
o8Ev AElttOtEpat JlEV uOatoc;, Jtal(UtEpat
of: O<rJlal <rUJllta<ral yEyovacnv &poe;.
~l..ouvtat of: oJt6tav nvoc; avtuppax8vtoc;
ltEpt tTtV avaltVOTJV UYI1 nc; ~i~ tO ltVEUJla
de; aut6v. tOtE yap OO"Jllt JlEV OUOEJlla auvOt118Ettat, to o JtvEuJla t&v oaJl&v EP1lllro8f:v auto JlOVOV EltEtal. ou' o;)v taUta
avroVUJla ta tOUt<oV ltOl!ClAJlata yeyovEV,
OUJC EJC Jtol..l..&v OUOE b.Jtl..&v do&v ovta,
&I..J..Cx oxn t6
iJou JCal. to l..u1t11Pov
aut68t JlOV<o Ota<pavft 1..yEa8ov ...
exactly to Plato's terms: yl..u!CU, ai..Jlup6v, 1tl1Cp6v, aU<rtllPOV, OplflU, <rtpu<pv6v, o~u.
359
op.
360
A.A. LONG
This is a curiously synthetic report of two independent observations by Plato. 15 At Tim. 68b6-8, Plato writes:
Bright mixed with red and white becomes orange. It would make
no sense to state the proportions, even if one knew them, given that
no one could be even moderately capable of stating either their
necessity or the likely account.
Plato then (ibid. 68b8-d2) gives an account of many other colours
that are generated by mixtures, and concludes:
These examples make it more or less clear to what mixtures the
other colours must be assimilated in order to preserve the likely
account. But if anyone investigating should apply a test to the facts,
he would prove his ignorance of the difference between divine and
human nature; for god has the knowledge and the power to blend
the one into many and to resolve the many into one, but no human
being exists now or ever will exist who can do either of these things
(Tim. 68d2-7).
Theophrastus in his second sentence (cited above) alludes to Plato's
warning against experimentation and to the superiority of divine
power, but his brevity leaves his readers guessing as to what 'this'
is that god can do by way of frustrating the temerarious experimenter.
Conclusions
I now summarise the results of this survey. Theophrastus' reports
on Plato's sensory doctrines in the Timaeus range from being
almost verbatim and entirely clear at one extreme to misrepresentation and opacity at the other.
Accurate and clear. hearing, smell, the tactile properties hard and
soft, pleasure and pain, the gustatory properties astringent,
harsh, bitter, salty, the colours black and white
Venial omissions: explanations of four of the types of sound and of
rough and smooth
Damaging omissions: sight
Extreme condensation: sight, concord in sound, no pleasure or pain
in seeing, the gustatory properties pungent, sweet and sharp, his
concluding remarks about Plato on colours
15 Cf. Baltussen (n. 1), pp. 118-19, who comments cogently on other aspects
of Theophrastus' method of excerpting here.
361
Serious misrepresentation:
1. (general) the attribution to Plato of 'likeness' as the explanatory principle, the denial that Plato explains the operations of
touch, taste and smell;
2. (particular) the explanations of sight, hot and cold, heavy and
light, the first part of flavours
362
A.A. LONG
reports as 'brief, yet very informative' (9) and characterizes his criticism of
Democritus and Plato as 'precise and thorough' (11). This apologetic tendency
is my only objection to his excellent study of Theophrastus' treatment of the
Timaeus in his dissertation (n. I above.)
ADDITIONAL FRAGMENTS
OF ARIUS DIDYMUS ON PHYSICS
DAVID
T.
RUNIA
364
DAVID T. RUNIA
~pouc; -rile;
8.
9.
Flor. 4.39.28
365
that has been the point of reference ever since.B Paul Moraux, to
take a prominent example, presents a lengthy analysis of the
Aristotelian physical fragments purely on the basis of Diels'
identifications, the methodology of which is not even discussed. 9
Goransson states somewhat apodictically that the criteria used by
Diels to sift out the Didymean material 'are perhaps not as indisputable as they have been regarded every since',l 0 but makes no
attempt to embark on this investigation himself.
My intention is to reexamine the question of the separation of
the Didymean material on physics in Stobaeus' Eclogai afresh. I
will argue that Diels' criteria need to be refined and more consistently applied. This will lead to the identification of a number of
additional fragments, but also to the removal of a few snippets from
Diels' collection. The investigation may be regarded as a preliminary study for a new edition of these physical fragments, which remains a real desideratum. It is a joy to be able to dedicate this contribution to my mentor, colleague and friend Jaap Mansfeld on his
sixtieth birthday. We have discussed these and related issues on
numerous occasions during our joint research on ancient doxography, and have not always been able to reach complete unanimity. So I am sure that he will scrutinize these pages with an
even sharper eye than usual.
The disputed fragments we are concerned with are all located
in Book I of Stobaeus' Eclogae. This book, which unfortunately only
survives in a truncated version,ll contains a vast amount of doxographical material in the area of physics, but gives no indication
whatsoever as to where it was drawn from. As we all know, Diels,
basing his theory on earlier research but also adding new elements of his own, argued that most of this material was derived
from a compendium entitled Tiept apE<H.:OV't(I)V (De placitis) also
8 DG 449-472. As far as I know, apart from Wachsmuth, on whom more
below, no attention has been given to the question of the identification of
physical fragments of Arius Didymus in Stobaeus, except incidentally, for
example in my own articles cited below in n. 35 & 39.
9 P. Moraux, Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen von Andronikos von Rhodos his
Alexander von Aphrodisias, Band I: Die Renaissance des Aristotelismus im I. ]h. v.
Chr. (Berlin-New York 1973) 276-305.
10 op. cit. 220. No doubt he is especially thinking of Diels' criterion of a
certain Stoicizing flavour (DG 75); see further below n. 19.
II The prologue is missing; chapters 1-31 are fairly complete, but chapters
32-60 have been considerably abridged by an epitomator, who wrote out only
the Platonic and Aristotelian material.
366
DAVID T. RUNIA
367
Eusebius cites verbatim, as is his wont, and cites his source (at
15.20.8), whereas Stobaeus leaves his source unnamed and takes
the kind of liberties that one might expect from an anthologist. The
names of the three Stoics are brought to the fore in order to make
the contrast with the other doxai clearer. Only the change from
au-ri'tv to 'totaU'tllV might be thought worrying. It could easily be
interpreted as a Verschlimmbesserung, i.e. Stobaeus cannot imagine
the Stoics maintaining a cycle of identical worlds. But we must be
wary of hyperinterpretation (and how can we be sure that -rotaU'tllV
is not a textual corruption?).
We know, therefore, that Stobaeus (henceforth S) made use of
the compendia of both Aetius (henceforth A) and Arius Didymus
(henceforth AD) in his compilation. Most, though not all, of his
doxographical information on physics can be reduced to these two
sources. 16 Decisive criteria here are comparison with other sources
(notably Ps.Plutarch's abridgement of A, henceforth P 17 ) and considerations of style and content. The macro-structure of the book is
loosely based on A, but the anthologist has seen fit to introduce all
manner of structural changes in his material, involving the
opposed techniques of coalescence and separation, so that the
process of disentangling his original sources has become an immensely complex and often wearisome task. It is thus of vital
importance to determine various criteria that allow the two chief
sources to be separated. In our view the most significant of these are
eight in number. Obviously our list takes as its point of departure
the list of ten criteria which Diels outlined in his rigorous and admirably succint analysis. 18 It would seem better, however, to draw
up a new and revised list, in which his results are incorporated
rather than repeat his list more scholastico and comment on each of
his criteria individually. Unlike Diels we shall exclude any
considerations that are based wholly on content. 19 It needs to be
emphasized that these criteria are generalizations, and that for
16 These matters can in the present context not be discussed in detail. The
reader is referred to the study announced in n. 12.
17 In what follows references are to the Teubner edition of J. Mau, Plutarchi Maralia vol. V fasc. 2 pars 1 (Leipzig 1971).
18
19
DG73-75.
I.e. Diels' last three criteria. Diels argues that AD uses Stoic terminology in describing Aristotelian doctrine, but he may well be influenced by
his conviction that AD is the Stoic Arius. The criterion of a direct use of
Aristotle's Metearologica can only be verified as part of a thorough examination
of the meteorology of A's book III.
368
DAVID T. RUNIA
each one there are exceptions possible. Ideally every lemma found
in our sources should be individually analysed, a tedious and
time-consuming task. In his DC Diels did little more than present
the results of his analyses, so often the reasons for his decisions
need to be divined.
Here, then, is the list of eight criteria for separating A and AD.
1. The lemmata of AD are often longer than those of A, not only
because they enter into more detail, but also because they often
combine more than one topic. For example some of the longest
lemmata in A are found on the subject 11Ept 'tU~Eroc; 'tOU KOCJIJ.O'l> (cf.
P 2.7), e.g. Parmenides at S 1.22.la, Philolaus at ld. But they are not
even half the length of Chrysippus' long expose at S 1.21.5 (=AD fr.
31 Diels) on the nature and structure of the cosmos. Because AD
treats a number of topics together in a continuous expose, his
fragments often have a more fluent and discursive style than the
compact and sometimes crabbed style of A. There are, however,
two further complicating factors. Some of the fragments attributed
by Diels to AD are so short that the above remarks can hardly be
applied. Moreover we have to take into account that S in his
coalescing of various chapters in A also groups together subjects
that A kept apart. This means that the combinations of AD have to
be distinguished from the coalescences of S. As we shall see, this
proves to be a highly tricky business.
2. The standard formula of A's placita is to have the doxa immediately follow the name-label, whereby the verb of assertion is generally understood (occasionally cpTJcr{, EcpTJ or <htEcpf)va'tO is included).
The topic, which is always given in the chapter-title, is sometimes
repeated in the first lemma and thereafter it too is generally understood. Sometimes, however, it is even omitted in the opening
lemma. Such procedures come much less naturally to AD because
he, as far as we can tell, did not have chapter titles2 and also
makes less use of name-labels. Among the fragments of AD in S
four different types of lemmata can be observed: (a) those which
follow the usual style of the Placita, i.e. have the name-label in the
nominative at the beginning; (b) those which have the name-label
only in the genitive, without a direct grammatical relation to the
contents of the lemmata; (c) those which have the name of the
20 The title llEp\. 'tEAoU<; at 2.45.11 may not be original, but added either by S
or a scribe. See also above n. 7 on doubts as to whether Ethical doxography A
in Scan be ascribed to AD.
369
370
DAVID T. RUNIA
tendencies. AD uses indirect speech almost incessantly. His compendium must surely have been a pain to read. Of the forty fragments in Diels' collection only a handful contain material cast in
direct speech. 25 A in contrast often prefers not to linger too long in
indirect speech. Exx. of lemmata in A where he reverts to direct
speech are: P 1.3 at 876F2 and 877F3, P 1.5 at 879B9, P 2.12 at 888C5
(= S 1.23.3), P 2.20 (= S 1.25.3d), etc. The entire (exceptionally) long
passage in P 3.5 at 894B-E is cast in oratio recta until for the briefer
doxai of the Presocratics at the end he returns to oratio obliqua. This
criterion, we note, was not made explicit by Diels.
6. Detailed comparison of the adaptation of A by P and S respectively is often revealing. P tends to abridge by simply deleting whole
lemmata or (less often) by abbreviating longer lemmata. This
means he most often retains the original order in A. Comparison
of S with P can reveal that S has replaced A with material drawn
from AD. For example in S's chapter TIEpt ioErov, parallel toP 1.10,
he changes the order from Plato Aristotle Stoics to Aristotle Plato
Stoics.2 6 This, together with the fact that the contents of the lemmata are quite different, makes clear that he has inserted the fuller
reports of AD (including the passage also found in Eusebius).
7. S tends to begin his chapters with material from A, and group
the excerpts from AD towards the end. This characteristic is hardly surprising in light of the fact that he (and the Placita in general)
rather often begins with Presocratic philosophers, who of course
hardly occur in AD's physical fragments.27 There are also cases,
however, where Diels has postulated fragments from AD right in
the middle of a series of doxai from A (e.g. 1.14.1c, 25.1i). For the
brief Chrysippean lemma at 1.8.40b this must be the case, since, as
Diels acutely saw, the sentence is repeated at 1.8.42 (at 106.6). In
other cases, however, one should be suspicious, as we shall see.
8. Since, to the best of our knowledge, the physical fragments of
AD are confined to material on Aristotle and the Stoics (apart from
the solitary fragment on Plato just referred to above2 8 ), it is these
2 5 E.g. fr. 2, 3, 39.
2 6 The reason for the change is rather obscure. A not very flattering suggestion is that he saw the phrase
AEYOI!EV<X etOl] Kat ta~ ioa~ in the Pythago-
ta
371
29 See the quote cited above at n. 15. Note that I am not basing my argument on any assumption that AD himself was a Stoic.
30 DG 447-472; the fragment appended at 854 may be considered fr. 41.
31 DG 75: neque tantum vereor ne quid falso in syllogen receperim
quantum ne omnia.
32 Ibid. n. 2: frustula ex Didymo admixta credo I 7 31 18 6 23 2 III 1 7 2 3 7 4.
33 I owe this observation to Jaap Mansfeld.
34 It will be understood that for reasons of space an exhaustive interpretation of these texts cannot be presented. The analysis concentrates on aspects
relevant to the question of identification. For example in the case of the first
text I ignore the fact that in P the lemma is attributed to Socrates and Plato.
The reader is encouraged to have the relevant texts at hand.
372
DAVID T. RUNIA
373
374
DAVID T. RUNIA
cosmic void, whereas (iii) discusses place and void in quite general
terms, without any cosmological reference. Moreover between (ii) and
(iii) the account clearly passes from the views of Aristotle on the
Pythagoreans to those of Aristotle himself (although this is not explicitly
stated). It is thus logical to conclude that there is break between (ii) and
(iii). The style of the third part of the lemma points to AD (note the use of
indirect speech). A further hint is supplied by the fact that S has deleted a
lemma on Aristotle's views on space in P 1.19. Do the first two parts of the
lemma come from A or AD? It is certainly unusual for A to have a
lemma containing two complete references, but there are about 15 texts
in which he does refer to writings with greater or lesser accuracy. 35 The
possibility that S added the learned references is also not so likely
because elsewhere he does not cite the Aristotelian corpus or lost works
(preferring to use the De mundo). The references also do not fit easily into
AD's work, which-as far as we know-did not deal with Pythagorean
philosophy directly. These considerations point to the conclusion that the
first two parts of the lemma come from A and the third part from AD. On
the other hand it should be recognized that the differences between P
and S in the first part cannot be readily explained on this hypothesis. 36
6.119.1, 162.19-163.14: Aristotle. Once again Diels thought there might
be Arian material in this lemma, but nevertheless printed it as part of his
reconstruction of A 1.23. Wachsmuth shows the same vacillation, printing it as A but adding in the apparatus haec fort. rectius Ario tribuas. There
can be no doubt, however, that, had Diels followed his own criteria, he
would have concluded that the entire lemma was from AD. Not only is it
very long, but it replaces a very short lemma in P and occurs at the end
of the sequence. It is most perplexing that Diels should have printed this
piece as part of A. Perhaps he was swayed by the fact that it starts with the
name in the nominative, as is usual in A, and is not preceded by the
name in the genitive. But the ms. P does add 'AptcrtotO. (sic) in the
margin. These genitives, as argued above, are not a reliable criterion.
7. 127.7, 226.21-26: Aristotle. Diels in his reconstruction of A 3.1 (IX; 365)
states that he thinks the second part of the lemma in S is Arian since it
disagrees with P and is clearly excerpted from Meteor. 1.8 346a19ff. He
did not, however, include this section in his collection. This passage is
the only place in the whole chapter where P and S disagree. We note the
use of oratio obliqua, even though the second word of the additional
section is yap. It is to be concluded that S has added an excerpt from his
reading of AD to A.
8. 128.1a, 227.17-21: Aristotle. Again the text for A 3.2 in P and Sis identical except for the additional Aristotelian material. Diels suspected that it
came from AD. Wachsmuth ad loc. disagreed, arguing that, since the
35 I have listed these in my article 'Xenophanes or Theophrastus? an
Aetian Doxographicum on the Sun', in W. W. Fortenbaugh and D. Gutas (edd.),
Theophrastus: his Psychological, Doxographical and Scientific Writings (New Brunswick 1992) 112-140, on p. 122-123.
36 K. A. Algra, 'Posidonius' Conception of the Extra-cosmic Void: the Evidence and the Arguments', Mnemosyne 46 ( 1993) 484-485 tentatively suggests
that it may have been contaminated with material from the Posidonian
lemma in the parallel chapter at P 2.9.
375
37 Diels recognized this in a number of texts on Aristotle, though the presentation in Wachsmuth tends to conceal it: cf. 14.lc, 22.lc, 24.lm, 27.7.
376
DAVID T. RUNIA
mm
377
2. '125.5, 213.13-27: Zeno. I think there can be no doubt that this text is
from AD. In the first place it combines information about on the
substance of sun and moon and other stars which A keeps well separate
(and S does not coalesce together). Secondly it adds information about
kinds of fire that would be difficult to place in A. Thirdly it combines
information about the movement and eclipses of sun and moon, whereas
in A these are dealt with in separate groups of chapters (which S coalesces in his chapters 1.25 and 1.26 respectively).
3. '125.5, 214.1-3: Chrysippus. This lemma is much more difficult precisely because it is so short. It is possible that it represents two lemmata
39 In art. cit. (n. 35); see also 'Xenophanes on the Moon: a Doxographicum
in Aetius', Phronesis 34 ( 1989) 245-269. I hope to return to this problem in a
full reconstruction of Book II of Aetius.
378
DAVID T. RUNIA
Conclusions
On the basis of our investigation the following results have been
reached.
(1) The criteria that Diels and Wachsmuth used to separate out the
physical fragments of Arius Didymus in Stobaeus Eclogae book I
can be slightly improved. If intelligently and carefully applied,
they are equal to their task.
(2) Particular attention should be given to the fact that the anthologist Stobaeus sometimes joins together material from his two
sources in one and the same lemma.
(3) In the case of very short fragments formal and stylistic criteria
are ineffective. It in fact becomes almost impossible to determine
with any degree of certainty whether the texts should be assigned
to the one doxographical source rather than the other.
( 4) On the basis of the examination carried out above the following
ten fragments should be added to Diels' collection.
40
Ibid. 258.
379
a.
b.
c.
d.
e.
f.
g.
h.
i.
5.15, 79.12-20
Chrysippus on the Moipat
6.17a, 87.23-88.6
Aristotle on eiJ.l.CXPJ.l.Evll
6.17c, 89.2-5
Theophrastus on eiJ.l.CXPJ.l.Evn
13.1b, 138.9-12
Aristotle on the four causes
14.1e, 142.1-7
Chrysippus on the divisibility of bodies
18.1c, 156.15-25
Aristotle on place
19.1, 162.19-163.14 Aristotle on motion
27.7, 226.21-26
Aristotle on the milky way
28.1a, 227.17-21
Aristotle on comets
j. 32,248.7-11
Aristotle on winds
Of great interest is the fact that in one of these texts Theophrastus
was mentioned. This confirms that the physical doxography dealt
with the thought not only of Aristotle, but also of his Peripatetic
successors. 4 1
(5) Conversely the following two fragments should be subtracted
from Diels' edition.
a. 1.26, 31.12-14
Chrysippus on the name of Zeus
b. 26.1i, 219.14-15
Cleanthes on the moon.
(6) For the assistance of scholars who wish to make use of this important doxographical source, I append below a full list of the physical fragments of Arius Didymus, taking into account the results
of this article. The sequence is determined by the following criteria: (i) the philosophers or philosophical school dealt with (PlatoPeripatos-Stoa); (ii) the source (Eusebius, abbreviated as E; Stobaeus,
abbreviated asS); (iii) the location in the source (in the editions of
Mras and Wachsmuth respectively). In the list I try to separate individual Stoic philosophers as much as I can, splitting up the fragments in Diels' collection in the process. 4 2 This leads to complications in the case offr. 36, parts ofwhich are found in both sources.
(7) Finally, I remind the reader of the remark, made at the outset
of the article, that a new edition of these fragments is highly desirable.
Leiden
4 1 Cf. the heading given to the lemma at Stob. EeL 1.17.2, 'AptcrtoteA.ouc; Kai
t&v an' auto\i, and the name-label 'AptcrtotEAtKOl at 8.40d (but these may have
been the work of Stobaeus). The title of Ethical doxography Cat 2.116.19-20 is
'AptcrtotEAouc; Kai tiDv Aol!tiDV llEptltatTittKIDV ltEpi tiDV lj9tKIDV.
4 2 There is no need to try to retain Diels' sequence of fragments, since his
ordering is by no means always logical (e.g. why place fr. 16 between 15 and
17?).
380
DAVID T. RUNIA
APPENDIX
THE PHYSICAL FRAGMENTS OF ARIUS DIDYMUS
source
subject
Academy
1
Plato
E 11.23.3-6, 51.18-52.11
& S 12.2a, 135.20-136.13
Aristotle
Theophrastus
Aristotle
Aristotelians
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
& successors
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
Aristotle
S 6.17a, 87.23-88.6
S 6.17c, 89.2-5
S 8.40c, 103.10-16
s 8.40d, 103.18-104.5
s 11.4, 132.10-25
s 12.1b, 134.18-135.18
s 13.1b, 138.9-12
S 14.1c, 141.7-22
s 17.2, 152.14-17
unnamed
Cleanthes
Chrysippus
unnamed
Chrysippus
Zeno of Tarsus
E
E
E
E
E
E
Peripatos
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
6
7
2
3
5
4
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
9
8
10
12
14a
11
13
14b
15
17a
17b
17c
17d
16
S 18.1c, 156.15-25
s 19.1, 162.19-163.14
S 22.1c, 196.5-15
S 24.1m, 204.8-12
s 25.4, 212.13-213.13
s 27.7, 226.21-26
S 28.1a, 227.17-21
s 29.1, 234.5-235.8
s 30.2, 240.13-242.17
s 31.6, 243.23-245.21
s 32, 248.7-11
s 36.2, 249.12-251.27
s 39, 253.25-255.7
s 51.5, 482.11-19
s 52.19, 484.15-21
s 54.3, 492.21-22
s 55.1, 494.6-7
s 56.1, 496.15-23
s 58, 497.15-25
ideas
heimarmene
heimarmene
time
time
archai: matter
archai: form
Stoa
30
31
32
33
34
35
29a
29b
29c
36a
36b
36d
36c
37
38
39
37
39a
39b
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
39c
39d
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
26a
26b
26c
26d
21
20a
20b
20c
40
18a
18b
1&
19
38a
38b
28
25
22
23
24
36e
27a
27b
31
33a
33b
34a
34c
35
Zeno
-Cleanthes
-Chrysippus
unnamed
Zeno
Zeno
-Cleanthes
unnamed
unnamed
Chrysippus
Zeno
Apollodorus
Posidonius
Chrysippus
Chrysippus
Zeno
Chrysippus
Posidonius
Zen<r8toics43
Zeno
Chrysippus
Posidonius
Chrysippus
unnamed
Zeno
Cleanthes
Chrysippus
Chrysippus
Chrysippus
Zeno
Apollodorus
Panaetius
Posidonius
Mnesarchus
Chrysippus
Zeno
Chrysippus
Zeno
Chrysippus
Chrysippus
381
E 15.18.3, 383.7-12
& S 20.le, 171.2-7
cosmic ekpyrosis
E 15.19, 383.15-384.5
E 15.20.1, 384.7-13
E 15.20.2-3, 384.15-24
cosmic regeneration
seed and birth
nature of soul
E 15.20.4-5, 385.2-7
E 15.20.6-7, 385.9-15
s 5.15, 79.12-20
S 8.40e, 104.7-11
s 8.42, 105.8-16
s 8.42, 105.17-106.4
s 8.42, 106.5-107.7
s 10.16c, 129.2-130.20
S 11.5a, 132.27-133.5
S 11.5a, 133.6-11
S 11.5c, 133.18-23
s 12.3, 136.21-137.6
S 13.lc, 138.14-22
S 13.lc, 138.23-139.4
S 13.lc, 139.5-8
S 14.le, 142.1-7
s 14.11, 143.24-144.10
s 17.3, 152.19-153.6
s 17.3, 153.7-22
s 17.4, 153.24-155.14
s 18.4d, 161.8-26
s 19.3, 165.15-166.2
s 19.4, 166.4-22
s 19.5, 166.24-167.14
S 20.le, 171.5-7
s 20.7, 177.21-179.5
s 20.7, 179.6-17
s 21.5, 184.8-185.24
s 25.5, 213.15-27
s 25.5, 214.1-2
s 26.li, 219.12-13
s 26.11, 219.24-220.2
s 31.7, 245.23-30
cosmic soul
soul and body
Moirai
time
time
time
time
elements
ousia as matter
first matter
ousia and matter
concepts
cause
cause
cause
divisibility of bodies
three-dimensional body
cosmic cycle
cosmic cycle
kinds of mixture
place
motion
cosmic motion
motion
ekpyrosis rejected
generation-destruction
generation-destruction
description of cosmos
sun-moon-stars
sun
moon
moon
mist etc.
43 Diels' emendation Zi!vrovor; (Kai trov alt'ai>tou) is taken over by Wachsmuth. It is far from certain, but later in the lemma S uses the label oi I:trotKoi
<ptA.60'Q(pOl.
PART SEVEN
HISTORY OF SCHOLARSHIP
386
JOHN GLUCKER
387
388
JOHN GLUCKER
The negative procedure is so conspicuous, and even so preponderant, in the Platonic dialogues, that no historian of philosophy can
omit to notice it. But many of them (like Xenophon in describing
Sokrates) assign to it only a subordinate place and a qualified application: while some (and Schleiermacher especially) represent all
the doubts and difficulties in the negative dialogues as exercises to
call forth the intellectual effort of the reader, preparatory to full and
satisfactory solutions which Plato has given in the dogmatic dialogues at the end. The first half of this hypothesis I accept: the last
half I believe to be unfounded. The doubts and difficulties were
certainly exercises to the mind of Plato himself, and were intended
as exercises to his readers; but he has nowhere provided a key to the
solution of them. Where he propounds positive dogmas, he does not
bring them face to face with objections, nor verify their authority
by showing that they afford satisfactory solutions to the negative
procedure. The two currents of his speculation, the affirmative and
the negative, are distinct and independent of each other. Where the
affirmative is especially present (as in Timaeus), the negative altogether disappears. Timaeus is made to proclaim the most sweeping
theories, not one of which the real Sokrates would have suffered to
pass without abundant cross-examination; but the Platonic Sokrates
hears them with respectful silence and commends afterwards. The
declaration so often made by Sokrates that he is a searcher, not a
teacher-that he feels doubts keenly himself, and can impress
them upon others, but cannot discover any good solutions of
them-this declaration, which is usually considered as irony, is
literally true. The Platonic theory of Objective Ideas separate and
absolute, which the commentators often announce as if it cleared
up all the difficulties-not only clears up none, but introduces fresh
ones belonging to itself. When Plato comes forward to affirm, his
dogmas are altogether a priori: they enunciate preconceptions or
hypotheses, which derive their hold upon his belief, not from any
aptitude for solving the objections which he has raised, but from
deep and solemn sentiment of some kind or other-religious, ethical, aesthetical, poetical, &c.-the worship of numerical symmetry
or exactness, &c. The dogmas are enunciations of some grand
sentiment of the divine, good, just, beautiful, symmetrical, &c.,
which Plato follows out into corollaries. But this is a process in
itself; and while he is performing it, the doubts previously raised
are not called up to be solved, but are forgotten or kept out of sight. It
is therefore a mistake to suppose that Plato ties knots in one dialogue
only with a view to untie them in another; and that the doubts
which he propounded are already solved in his own mind, only
that he defers the announcement of the solution until the embarrassed hearer [sic] has struggled to find it for himself. (270-273)
With persons who complain of prolixity in the dialogue-of
threads which are taken up only to be broken off, devious turns and
"passages which lead to nothing"-of much talk "about it and about
it," without any peremptory decisions from an authorized judgewith such complainants Plato has no sympathy. He feels a strong
389
390
JOHN GLUCKER
391
quote most of them, omitting Jowett's disagreement about the Platonic canon, which is beside our main argument:I2
I have derived much assistance from the great work of Mr. Grote,
which contains excellent analyses of the dialogues, and is rich in
original thoughts and observations. I agree with him in rejecting as
futile the attempts of Schleiermacher and others to arrange the
dialogues of Plato into a harmonious whole ...
If Mr. Grote should do me the honour to read any portion of this
work he will probably remark that I have endeavoured to approach
Plato from a point of view which is opposed to his own. The aim of
the Introductions in these volumes has been to represent Plato as the
father of Idealism, who is not to be measured by the standards of
utilitarianism or of any other modern philosophical system. He is
the poet or maker of ideas, satisfying the wants of his own age,
providing the instruments of thought for future generations. He is
no dreamer, but a great philosophical genius struggling with the
unequal conditions of light and knowledge under which he is
living. He may be illustrated by the writings of moderns, but he
must be interpreted by his own, and by his place in the history of
philosophy. We are not concerned to determine what is the
residuum of truth which remains for ourselves. His truth may not
be our truth, and nevertheless may have an extraordinary value
and interest for us ...
It will be seen also that I do not agree with Mr. Grote's view about
the sophists; nor with the low estimate which he has formed of
Plato's Laws; nor with his opinion respecting Plato's doctrine of the
rotation of the earth. But I am not going to lay hands on my father
Parmenides (Soph. 24ld), who will, I hope, forgive me for differing
from him on these points. I cannot close this preface without
expressing my deep respect for his noble and gentle character, and
the great services which he has rendered to Greek literature. 13
So much in public. Mter all, Grote did have an international reputation; he had been made an honorary Doctor of Oxford University
in 1853, and had been Vice-Chancellor of the University of
London since 1862. Uowett was to become Vice-Chancellor of the
University of Oxford only in 1882). In private, Jowett could be far
more explicit. In a letter to Sir Alexander Grant, written on August
21, 1865, he says:
I have been reading Grote with very great interest, but with a good
deal of disagreement ... I think without fancy that there is more to
!2 The Dialogues of Plato, translated into English with Analyses and
Introductions by B. Jowett, Fourth Edition (Oxford 1953) vol.l, xxvii-xxix. This
part of the Preface is .reprinted unchanged from the First Edition.
13 I think it was Heine who said of Victor Cousin: 'M. Cousin is doing
his best to understand German philosophy and interpret it to his countrymen; and I must admit that M. Cousin is a very nice man.'
392
JOHN GLUCKER
393
394
JOHN GLUCKER
395
op.
cit., 151-5.
27 On the whole of this issue, the best general survey is still E.N.
Tigerstedt, The Decline and Fall of the Neoplatonic Interpretation of Plato (Helsinki
1974). It is too brief, and there are gaps. The same author's Interpreting Plato
(Stockholm 1977) is also too brief, and devotes only two pages to Grote and
none to the Mills or Jowett. The proper and extensive history of the modem
study of Plato is yet to be written. On Mosheim and Brucker, see The Decline
and Fall ... 55-61; 62-3, and notes.
2S Tigerstedt, Decline and Fall ... (n. 27) failed to notice that in his Historia
Critica Philosophiae ... , 2 vols. (Leipzig 1742) 1.669, Brucker says that in his
survey of Plato's system, he will follow Cicero's Academicus Primus (that is,
Varro's account, 19-33), Apuleius, and Alcinous, 'qui, ut omnium optime ad
ordinem nexumque philosophiae Platonicae attendit, ita dux erit nobis in
itinere ... '
2 9 A shortened version of Brucker appeared in English in 1791, in a
translation by William Enfield. The account of Plato appears in vol.l, 199125, and it contains all the main ingredients of the Latin version. James
Mill, in his review of Thomas Taylor of 1804 (see n. 33 and context), is still
apparently unaware of Brucker; but in the 1809 review in The Edinburgh
Review, he already quotes Brucker. See further nn. 45-46 and context.
30 According to the two biographical accounts reprinted in Kathleen
Raine and George Mills Harper (eds.), Thomas Taylor the Platonist (Princeton
1969) 105-132, Taylor came to Plato through reading Aristotle and his commentators, and what made him opt for the Neo-Platonic view was his reading ofProclus' Platonic Theology (112-3 and 125, probably derived from it). The
first of these accounts is almost certainly Taylor's own story (see ibid. 105,
396
JOHN GLUCKER
among the few scholars interested in Plato, this view was already
out of date.
Nor was the climate of philosophical opinion in Britain in 1804
favourable to 'the perennial philosophy' or to metaphysics in
general. Readers of that neglected genius, Thomas Love Peacock,
will remember his many digs at German philosophy, and
especially at 'the profound Kant'. On 27 September 1804, Francis
Horner, lawyer, scholar, one of the founders of The Edinburgh
Review, and a future influential politician, wrote to a Scottish friend
who proposed to translate Kant into English, and attempted to
dissuade him from carrying out his project, since metaphysics
had never been a favourite of the British philosophical reader, and
its present status-at least in the literary circles in London-was
worse than ever before.3I 1804 was obviously a good year for taking
a 'tough-minded', empirical, or even sceptical look at the dialogues
of Plato. Even in 1834-5, Mill's translations/paraphrases of some
dialogues still had a wide appeal.32 Had Mill and Grote published
their work during those years, they may have created a very
different image of the Platonic writings than that which was created by Jowett and others in the 1860's and the 1870's, and became
the most influential one for decades. But in 1804 Mill, however
precocious he was, had still two years to wait for his own birth, and
Grote was still a boy of ten. The only person, during those years,
who was capable of expressing a more empirical view of Plato was
the father of John Mill and the teacher of both, James Mill.
I have found no external evidence that the reviewer of Taylor's
Plato in vol. 14, 1809, of The Edinburgh Review [henceforth ER] was
James Mill. 33 But an earlier review, in The Literary Journal [henceforth Lj] 3 (1804) 449-61; 577-89, is signed, in both instalments,
"M. ", which stands for the founder and editor, Uames] M [ill]. The
style of both reviews is the clear and trenchant style of Mill's
n. *). But is this the whole story?
31 L. Horner, Memoirs and C01Tespondence of Francis Horner, M.P. (Boston and
London 1853) 1.282-3.
32 See n. 3 and context.
3 3 The only full biography of James Mill is still that of Alexander Bain,
James Mill: A Biography (London 1882). Although Bain deals in a number of
places with articles in ER which can be ascribed to Mill, this one is never
mentioned. Nor is it mentioned in two more recent studies of early ER
reviewers-! omit the details for lack of space. Kathleen Raine (n. 30) 535,
ascribes this review to Mill, but gives no reference to any source. Her words
were taken as evidence or near evidence by some more recent scholars.
397
398
JOHN GLUCKER
399
400
JOHN GLUCKER
L]577.
Dialogues of Plato, three volumes (London 1767, 1769, 1773.) No translator's name on the title-pages, but each dialogue has a dedication to some
public figure, signed by Sydenham. Vol. 1, 5-19, has 'A general View of the
Works of Plato,' where the translator's opinions are made clear. Sydenham's
translation is a rare book today; but the 'General View' was reprinted by the
learned Thomas James Mathhias in his-more accessible-edition of the
works of Thomas Gray, vol. 2 (London 1814) 289-296, as an introduction to
Grats own notes on the dialogues.
4
In 1805, James Mill published in London a translation of Charles
Villers, An Essay on the Spirit and Influence of the Reformation of Luther. On p. 315,
Brucker is mentioned-but in a note by the author.
47 See n. 28 and context.
48 Audomari Talaei, Academica (Paris 1550) 11-15. Talon also cites Quintilian 2.15.26, for the division of Socrates' sermones into O.. qKtucoi and
OOYJ.lllttKoi. On Talon, see Tigerstedt, Decline and Fall (n. 28) 36, and C. B.
Schmidt, Cicero Scepticus, a Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Renaissance
(The Hague 1972) 78-91. It is at least likely that the Calvinist Talon, friend
and apostle of the Calvinist Ramus, would continue to be popular in Calvinist
Scotland even after the decline of Ramism. This should be looked into by
someone more familiar with Scottish philosophy and theology than myself.
See also next note.
49 See nn. 38-39 and context. In his A Fragment on Mackintosh (London
1835) 25, James Mill regards Plato as the originator of Bentham's method of
classification. A similar view is expressed by John Mill in his essay on
Bentham (n. 38), 88; and in his review of Grote, Collected Works (n. 34) 11.405,
401
402
JOHN GLUCKER
and Schelling in the early years of the century, and Sir William
Hamilton's essays in the 1830's show close familiarity with
Continental philosophy in general. Coleridge's, and Carlyle's,
works of the 1820's and 1830's had already made a wide circle of
readers aware of the revolutionary nature of much of the new
German philosophy. About the same time when Jowett began to
acquaint Oxford with Hegel, a group of philosophers in Trinity
College, Dublin, began to turn philosophy in their university in
the new, 'idealistic', direction. In 1837, William Archer Butler was
made the first incumbent of the new chair of Moral Philosophy.
His lectures on ancient philosophy, published many years after
his death,56 must date from the 1830's or the early 1840's: they
could not have been delivered later than 1847, when he was
'engaged in the preparation of some work on faith' .57 In them, he
shows familiarity with Kant, Fichte and Schelling, who are
mentioned by name, and uses some ideas and expressions which
may come from Hegel. Butler attempts to reach a compromise
between 'the Science of Real Experience' and 'the Philosophy of
Induction.' But when he comes to Plato, he sees the Idea of the
Good as the main object of Plato's philosophy. 'The predominant
quality of Platonic philosophy' is for him 'the perfect union of
Absolute Goodness with Absolute Reality. '58
One of Butler's successors in Trinity, Thomas Maguire, Professor of Moral Philosophy from 1880 to his death in 1889, was described by his biographer as 'a thorough idealist in philosophy.'59
In his Essay on the Platonic Idea of 1866, and Lectures on Philosophy of
1885, he fights the battles of idealism against many an 'empiricist'
of the time, and regards Plato and Hegel as the two great
champions of idealism. To go back in time, and to return to
England: in 1841, Professor William Sewell of Oxford published a
book called An Introduction to the Dialogues of Plato. Although Sewell
has some interesting things to say about the dialogues as works of
art, he is sure that Plato expected the intelligent reader to arrive at
the 'grand formularies of his doctrine:' a philosophical system,
with the Idea at its centre and the education and improvement of
5 6 William Archer Butler, Lectures on the History of Ancient Philosophy, ed.
W. H. Thompson, 2 vols. (Cambridge 1856).
57 DNB, 'Butler, William Archer' (by John Dowden).
58 Lectures ... , 1.63.
59 DNB 'Maguire, Thomas' (by E.S. Robertson.)
403
man as its goal. In 1845, George Henry Lewes published the first
edition of what was to become a very popular book, A Biographical
History of Philosophy. Lewes was a professed positivist, but he treats
Plato clearly as an idealist, with the Idea of the Good at the centre
of his thought, and with his own psychology, dialectic, theology,
cosmology and ethics.
Against this background, we should be surprised, not at the
failure of Grote's work to exercise any significant influence on the
study of Plato in Britain for the next few generations, but at the fact
that some of the reviews of it were positive and laudatory. But
everyone must have known or guessed that the review in ER 6o
was written by a close associate, and it was soon revealed that the
author was John Mill. As for the favourable review in The Westminster Review 61-what could one expect of the 'Benthamites"
periodical, edited for many years by James Mill? The short and
cursory review in The Gentleman's Magazine and the long and
learned review in The Qy,arterly Review, 62 while full of respect for
Grote's learning, were entirely opposed to his views of Plato. The
QR reviewer is clearly an idealist, and he takes Plato's idealism for
granted. He ascribes to Plato's 'most exact writings ... the necessity
of reconciling the abstract with the concrete, the Ideal with the
Actual,' and 'an approach ... to a new and larger idea of knowledge, not merely as the Universal, in which subjective peculiarities are done away [Schelling?], but as the union of all permanent
relations in the contemplation of the mind [Hegel?].' Jowett
himself could not put it better: indeed, I would not be surprised if it
were revealed that Jowett himself was the reviewer. Needless to
say, the reviewer dismisses Grote's whole conception of Plato's
dialogues as inadequate, and adds: ' ... it remains for those whose
point of view is nearer to Plato's own to vindicate him.' This, of
course, is insidious: 'Plato's own point of view' can only be a
construct, based on someone's reading of the dialogues. But such
expressions show that by 1866, Grote's idealist critics were fighting
from a dominant position. Needless to say, Grote is accused again
404
JOHN GLUCKER
and again-sometimes explicitly, often by insinuation-of intruding his Radical or Utilitarian views into the dialogues (a thing
which he does from time to time,63 but not as often as one could
guess from his reviewers.) And, as if it was not bad enough, in the
1860's, to be a Radical-Grote even served as a Radical Member of
Parliament between 1832 and 1841-he was also labelled 'Positivist'
by the Gentleman s Magazine reviewer. Grote was not a Positivist, but
his personal friendship with Comte was well-known, and in the
same year as his Plato-1865-his good friend and fellowUtilitarian John Mill published his Auguste Comte and Positivism.
The reviewer knew his master's crib when he wrote: 'The secularist [i.e. Grote] cannot sympathize with the great thinker who
clings with the tenacity of a drowning man . .. less to the arguments for the soul's immortality which unassisted reason supplies,
than to the belief itself, which so commended itself to his mind
and heart.' 64 This sounds almost like Augustine's 'Christian'
Plato-with his Christianity brought in by insinuation.
John Mill's laudatory review of Grote's Plato was not the only
place where he echoed the sceptical image of Plato which he
inherited from his father. It is now common knowledge that
many of the ideas of On Liberty of 1839 were conceived as part of his
rebellion against Bentham's proposals for a 'totalitarian democracy', in which the majority has full control of the expression of
thought.65 One may, perhaps, offer the suggestion that much of
Chapter II of that work was the result of Mill's reflections on
Socrates, Plato, and even the sceptical Academy. I refer not only to
the famous passage beginning with the words 'Mankind can
hardly be too often reminded that there was once a man called
Socrates. '66 I refer also to the passages beginning 'The beliefs
which we have most warrant for. . .';67 and 'He who knows only his
63 E.g., in his Plato (n. 5) 2.77-89, he takes Socrates' proposal of a 'beatific
calculus' in Protagoras as a central view of Plato himself. This is one of the
issues which his critics jump on, as a proof of Grote's parti pris in general.
6 4 Ibid. 390. Grote also assumed that Plato held such beliefs, often 'from
deep and solemn sentiments,' and even from religious sentiments. See, e.g.,
his Plato (n. 5) 1.271. What he was not prepared to do is to accept such beliefs
as if they were the essence of Plato's philosophy.
65 For two recent works, see Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford
1969) 172-206, esp. 175-185; Gertrude Himmelfarb, On Liberty and Liberalism, the
Case ofjohn Stuart Mill (New York 1974), esp. 3-22.
66 J.S. Mill, On Liberty in Collected Works (n. 34) vol. 18 (1977) 235.
67 Mill, op. cit. (n. 66) 232.
405
own side of the case .. .'68 Such passages are full of sceptical
Academic terms like 'assent' and 'suspension of judgement,' and
advocate the Academic practice in utramque partem disputandi.
But by the 1860's, as we have seen, the game was over. Plato was
studied once again in Oxford -and very soon, in the other
universities, and the idealists were now in control, both of the
academic study of philosophy and of much of public opinion. The
idealist image of Plato became canonical, and has been taken for
granted since, in various shapes and forms, by most students of
Plato and ancient philosophy. Even some analytic philosophers,
finding in some of the Platonic dialogues 'prefigurations' of their
own discussions, felt it necessary to point out that this is not the
way Plato himself regarded what he was doing.69 It was only
recently, in a book on Plato published in 1982, that an analytic
philosopher rediscovered the two sides of Plato with which the
reader of this article should by now be thoroughly familiar. He
calls them, for convenience's sake, Pato and Lato.70 Was Professor
Hare aware of the fact that Grote and Mill had already distinguished between these two sides of Plato more than a century
ago?
In the past, I expressed the view that, if I had to make a choice, I
would rather accept the sceptical Academy's image of the sceptical
Plato than any of the, far more influential, dogmatic images of
him, from those of Xenocrates and Aristotle to the present day.
Meanwhile, a new approach to the Platonic dialogue has made its
appearance: reading the dialogue as an organic unity in which
drama, narrative, characters and philosophical arguments work
together for the purpose of achieving a philosophical discourse in a
concrete, human (albeit larger than life) situation.71 I regard this
relatively new approach to Plato as an important and seminal new
method, which does justice to the Platonic texts on all their aspects.
What made it easy for me to understand this approach and adopt it
68 op. cit., 245.
69 See, e.g., G.E.L. Owen, 'Plato on not-being', in his Logic, Science and
Dialectic, ed. M. Nussbaum (Ithaca, N.Y. 1986), 104-137, The article was first
published in 1970.
70 R.M. Hare, Plato (Oxford 1982), esp. 26-7 and 69 ff.
7l Of a number of works, I shall mention two recent ones: Michael C.
Stokes, Plato's Socratic Conversations ... (London 1986); Ivor Ludlam, Hippias
Major: an Interpretation (Stuttgart 1991). I do not refer to the rather eccentric
use made of the dialogue form by the late Leo Strauss.
406
JOHN GLUCKER
was, among other things, my long preoccupation with the sceptical Academy's approach to Plato. I wonder if such a new and
fruitful way of reading Plato might not have been discovered
earlier, had the British philosophical community adopted Grote's
and Mill's image of the sceptical Plato rather than the dogmatic
image promoted by Jowett and other idealists.
Tel-Aviv University
M.
CALDER
III
Einleitung
Hochbetagt schrieb Wilhelm Dilthey (1833-1911) die nachfolgenden drei Briefe an Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff
(1848-1931).2 Sie weisen eine Reihe von Gemeinsamkeiten auf.
Zum einen handeln sie allesamt von Wissenschaftlern des
kaiserlichen Berlin, namlich von Eduard Zeller, Georg Misch,
Reinhard Kekule von Stradonitz und Friedrich Hiller von
Gaertringen, sowie von einem Projekt der Koniglich PreuBischen
Akademie der Wissenschaften. Zum anderen ist ihnen gemein,
daB die genannten Gelehrten iiberwiegend einerseits der Berliner
Universitat verbunden waren und andererseits der Koniglich
PreuBischen Akademie der Wissenschaften angehorten.
Zu den zu jener Zeit nach Ausweis der Mitgliederverzeichnisse
rund dreiBig ordentlichen Mitgliedern der philosophisch-historischen Klasse der Berliner Akademie zahlten sowohl der Verfasser
408
als auch der Adressat der drei Briefe. Dilthey3 war 1882 an die
Friedrich-Wilhelm-Universitat berufen und 1887 als ordentliches
Mitglied in die Akademie aufgenommen worden. Wilamowitz,
dessen Schwiegervater Theodor Mommsen der Akademie ein
halbes Jahrhundert lang angehort hatte, kam 1897 nach Berlin
und wurde nach einem gescheiterten Aufnahmeversuch 1899 4
ordentliches Akademiemitglied.5 Zeller hingegen war bereits
1872 aus Heidelberg einem Ruf nach Berlin gefolgt und noch im
gleichen Jahr als ordentliches Mitglied in die Akademie kooptiert
worden. Nach seiner Ubersiedlung nach Stuttgart im Jahre 1894
blieb er ihr als auswartiges Mitglied verbunden. Kekule, unter
dessen Bonner Studenten sich im Sommersemester 1881 der
einstige preuBische Thronanwarter und damalige Kaiser Wilhelm II. befand, 6 wurde von diesem 1889, d.h. ein Jahr nach der
Thronbesteigung, zum Direktor der Sammlung antiker Skulpturen
und Gipsabgiisse bei den Berliner koniglichen Museen sowie zum
Honorarprofessor und spater zum Ordinarius an der Berliner
Universitat ernannt. Im selben Jahr folgte seine Aufnahme in die
Akademie als ordentliches Mitglied7. deren 'unmittelbarer Protector' Wilhelm II. war.B Im dritten Brief wird ferner Friedrich Leo
(1851-1914) genannt, der Wilamowitz' Gottinger Kollege gewesen
war und seit 1906 als korrespondierendes Mitglied der preuBischen Akademie angehorte. In jenem Schreiben wird auBerdem
Wilamowitz' Schwiegersohn Friedrich Hiller von Gaertringen er3 Thomas Kornbichler, 'Wilhelm Dilthey', in: Michael Erbe (Hg.),
Berlinische Lebensbilder. Geisteswissenchaftler (Berlin 1989) 195-208, 201ff.
4 Vgl. Theodor Lorenz (Hg.), Friedrich Paulsen An Autobiography (New York
1938) 300-301.
5 Christa Kirsten (Hg.), Die Altertumswissenschaften an der Berliner Akademie.
Wahlvorschliige zur Aufnahme von Mitgliedern von F. A. Wolf bis zu G. Rodenwaldt
(1799-1932) (Berlin 1985) 117.
6 Hans Schrader, 'Reinhard Kekule von Stradonitz', Bursians Biographisches
Jahrbuch 35 (1913) 1-40, 20.
7 SB Akad.Wiss.Berlin (1912) 616; Schader, a.a.O., 22. Der Wahlvorschlag
wurde von Alexander Conze ( 1831-1917) eingebracht und ist lediglich von
Johannes Vahlen (1830-1911) mitunterzeichnet. Er beginnt mit folgenden
Worten: 'Nachdem es misghickt [sic] ist die gegenwartige vakante Fachstelle
fiir Kunstwissenschaft mit einem Vertreter der Wissenschaft moderner
Kunst zu besetzen, wird man zur Besetzung der Stelle einen Vertreter der
Wissenschaft antiker Kunst suchen wollen. DemgemaB schlagen die Unterzeichneten Herrn Reinhard Kekule yon Stradonitz, den Nachfolger unseres
heimgegangenen Curtius in dessen Amtern an Universitat und Museum, zu
dessen Nachfolger auch in der Akademie vor.' (Kirsten, a.a.O., 113).
8 Adolf von Harnack, Geschichte der Kiiniglich Preujlischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften zu Berlin 1 (Berlin 1900) 1044.
409
410
Als letzte Gemeinsamkeit sei erwiihnt, daB Dilthey und Wilamowitz nicht nur durch die Berliner Universitiit und Akademie,
sondern gleichfalls durch die zentrale Person des ersten Briefs
miteinander verbunden waren, niimlich durch Eduard Zeller
(1814-1908). Diltheys Verhiiltnis zu Zeller ist bekannt. 14 Als junger
Privatdozent lernte Wilamowitz ihn durch Theodor Mommsen
kennen und-wie bereits zuvor sein Studienfreund Hermann
Diels (1848-1922) 15-schiitzen. 16 Davon zeugt auch sein Brief, den
er am 7. Dezember 1881 an Zeller richtete:17
gewohnt daB meinen arbeiten nichts als hohn und rancune
gegeniiber laut wird, ist mir nachst dem eigenen gewissen die
einzige beruhigung daB die manner, auf deren urteil ich den
hochsten wert lege, das urteil der tageswelt nicht teilen. es verstand
sich bei dieser arbeit 1Bvon selbst, daB ich an Sie, hochverehrtester
herr geheimrat, an Bernays und Usener als Ieser eigentlich
immer dachte.
Angeregt wurde das erste der nachstehenden Schreiben des
Geheimen Regierungsrats Dilthey, der 1905 seine Lehrtiitigkeit
aufgegeben hatte, durch die Reaktion des Wirklichen Geheimen
Rates Wilamowitz auf den Nachruf, den Dilthey auf den kurz
zuvor verschiedenen Wirklichen Geheimen Rat Eduard Zeller
verOffentlicht hatte.l9 Das Thema war ihm wohlvertraut. Nach
mehreren Rezensionen und Aufsiitzen iiber das Schaffen Zellers
14 Siehe nur Eduard Zeller, Erinnerungen eines Neunzigjiihrigen (Stuttgart
1908). Vgl. Maximilian Braun, William M. Calder III, Dietrich Ehlers,
Philology and Philosophy: The Letters of Hermann Diels to Theodor and Heinrich
GomtJerz (1871-1922) (Hildesheim 1995) 67, 169.
l5' Zu Diets und Zeller siehe Otto Kern, Hermann Diels und Carl Robert. Ein
biographischer Versuch (Leipzig 1927) 60f., 65, 103-107. Ferner Dietrich Ehlers
(Hg.), Hermann Diels- Hermann Usener- Eduard Zeller. Briefwechsel (Berlin 1992)
mit Nachweisen in Bd. 2, 497 (sub nomine Dilthey, Wilhelm).
16 Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Erinnerungen 1848-1914 (Leipzig
21929) 175, 180.
1 7 Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, 'Selected Correspondence 18691931', hg. von William M. Calder III, Antiqua 23 (Neapel 1983) 301.
IS Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, 'Antigonos von Karystos', Philologische Untersuchungen 4 (Berlin 1881) (Nachdruck Berlin-Zurich 1965).
19 Wilhelm Dilthey, 'Eduard Zeller', Neue Freie Presse, 5. April 1908, 3135. Dieser Beitrag wurde urspriinglich nicht in Diltheys Gesammelte Schriften
aufgenommen, wei! er nach Meinung des Herausgebers des vierten Bandes,
Herman Noh!, gegeniiber Diltheys friiherem, in die Edition aufgenommenem Beitrag 'Aus Eduard Zellers Jugendjahren' inhaltlich nichts Neues
enthalte (578; vgl. Vorwort, VIII). Noh! irrt. 1970 schlieBiich wurde der
Nachruf in dem von Ulrich Herrmann edierten fiinfzehnten Band der
Gesammelten Schriften wiederabgedruckt (267-278).
411
muBte.
Der zweite Brief handelt iiber die Verlobung der 1877
geborenen Dilthey-Tochter Clara mit Georg Misch (1878-1965),
einem Schuler ihres Vaters, der zu jener Zeit sein Leben als
Privatdozent fiir Philosophie an der Berliner Universitat fristete,
jedoch 1911 in Marburg ein Extraordinariat erhalten und 1916
20 Diese Rede wurde unter dem Titel 'Aus Eduard Zellers Jugendjahren'
in der Deutschen Rundschau (1897, 294-309) veroffentlicht und ist in Diltheys
Gesammelten Schriften, Bd. 4 (Leipzig/Berlin 1921) 433-450 Ieicht greifbar.
2 I Wilhelm Dilthey, 'Emilie Zeller', Nationalzeitung, 17. Mai 1904;
wiederabgedruckt in: ders., Gesammelte Schriften, Bd. 15 (Gottingen 1970) 265f.,
265.
22 Uber Baur und seine Schule vergleiche Eduard Zeller, 'Ferdinand
Christian Baur', ADB 2, 172-179; ders., 'Die Tubinger historische Schule', in:
ders., Vortriige und Abhandlungen 1 (Leipzig 21875) 294-389; ders., 'Ferdinand
Christian Baur', in: ders, Vortriige und Abhandlungen, Bd. 1, 390-479; Ferdinand
Christian Baur, Kirchengeschichte des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts, hg. von Eduard
Zeller (Tubingen 1862) mit Diltheys Rezension in: ders., Gesammelte Schriften,
16 (Gottingen 1972) 449-456; Eduard Zeller, Geschichte der deutschen Philosophie
seit Leibniz (Munchen 21875) 721, 723, 729 mit der Rezension von Dilthey in:
ders., Gesammelte Schriften 17 (Gottingen 1974) 322f. Ferner seien Zellers
Strauss-Editionen erwahnt sowie sein Aufsatz 'StrauB und Renan', in: ders.,
Vortriige und Abhandlungen, 1. 480-555; s. besonders Eduard Zeller, Ausgewiihlte
Briefe von David Friedrich Strauft (Bonn 1895). Zur Tubinger Schule vgl. Horton
Harris, The Tii.bingen School (Oxford 1975).
412
413
[ 19 April1908]
414
415
einem festen Schema, und ich habe, so wie man das in diesem
Momente durfte, darauf hingewiesen, wie 'geniale Leistungen',
die aus einer hochentwickelten Philologie kamen, von ihm theils
verwerthet wurden, theils hat er in der ihm eigenen Continuitat
seiner Arbeit sich mit ihnen abzufinden gewuBt, ohne daB er
doch selbst Philologe in diesem groBen Sinne gewesen ware.3B
Das wird man bei aller Verehrung fiir seine groBe Leistung
zugestehen miissen.
Und nun verzeihen Sie diese Weitlaufigkeit iiber etwas das
wenn Sie meine Zeilen erhalten schon hinter Ihnen liegt. Aber
gerade bei Ihnen mochte ich doch nicht gern im Verdacht eines
solchen Schnitzers stehen.
lch hatte das miindlich gesagt-aber mein Gesundheitszustand
ist Ieider so erbarmlich daB ich an eine Riickkehr nach Berlin
noch lange nicht denken kann.
In herzlicher Verehrung
der Ihrige
[gez.] Wilhelm Dilthey
Meran SchloB Labers
Ostern
416
ich zu jeder Zeit fiir meinen kiinftigen Schwiegersohn 40 eingetreten bin. Und meine Uberzeugung von seinen hervorragenden
geistigen Gaben und einer seltenen Energie und verzichtenden
AusschlieBlichkeit in der wissenschaftlichen Arbeit war immer
verbunden mit der von seinem Charakter. Daher habe ich, als
seine Anfrage 41 kam, nach eingehendem Gespdi.ch mit meiner
Tochter meine Einwilligung gegeben, aber mir die Bedingung
vorbehalten, daB er ein Extraordinariat oder eine demselben aquivalente Stellung erst erwerbe; Und ich habe meine Uberzeugung,
daB diese Bedingung nach der Lage der Dinge erforderlich sei,
wie sie auf langem aufreibendem Nachdenken beruht, selbstverstandlich auch nicht aufgeben konnen. Meine sehr geliebte und
innigst mit mir verbundene Tochter hielt aus Grunden, die ich
zwar anerkenne, die mich jedoch durchaus nicht iiberzeugen
konnen, ein moglicher Weise langes Warten nicht fiir richtig.
Entstand nun hieraus zwischen uns Beiden eine Differenz, so ist
doch unsere Liebe zu einander unversehrt aus ihr hervorgegangen, meine Achtung fiir Misch ist unverandert, und mein
Herz und meine Fiirsorge sind ganz bei der Verlobung, Ausstattung, Verbindung meiner Tochter, wenn auch mein sehr
bedenklicher Gesundheitszustand mich von Berlin fernhalt. 42 Ich
bin schon seit Jahren sehr leidend, und in diesem Winter hat
mein Gesundheitszustand eine gefahrliche Form angenommen:
zu arbeiten werde ich natiirlich immer wieder versuchen, wie
sehr es mich auch schadigen mag: ich konnte sonst nicht Ieben:
das muB ich besser wissen als die Arzte. II Ich habe keinen Grund
von diesem ganzen Verlauf irgend etwas zu verhehlen, nachdem
gegen meinen Willen durch Unberufene ein thorichtes Gerede
entstanden ist.
Nehmen Sie nochmals fiir
Ihren Brief besten Dank.
40 Georg Misch. Dieser war nach dem Tod Diltheys einer der Herausgeber seiner Gesammelten Schriften, beschiiftigte sich aber auch monographisch
mit seinem Schwiegervater (Lebensphilosophie und Phiinomenologie. Eine Auseinandersetz.ung der Dilthey'schen Richtung mit Heidegger und Husser[ (Leipzig 1930);
Vom Lebens- und Gedankenkreis Wilhelm Diltheys (Frankfurt/Main 194 7). Vgl.
Josef Konig, 'Georg Misch als Philosoph,' Nachrichten der Akad. Wiss.Gott.
Philol.-hist. Klasse 7 (1967) 151-243.
41 Urspriinglich: sein Antrag.
42 Clara Dilthey setzt schlieBiich ihren Willen durch. Die EheschlieBung erfolgte noch 1908 (Wer ist wer? 1 [Berlin 1962] 1027).
417
Grunewald-Siemensstr. 37
[ 1] Die Offenbarung des Parmenides und die menschliche Welt, Philosophical texts and Studies 9 (Assen: Royal Van Gorcum &
Comp.), pp. 285 (simultanously published as Ph.D. Dissertation,
University of Utrecht, under the direction of C. J. de Vogel).
1965
419
1968
[12] review of J. Bollack, Empedocle I, Mnemosyne 21: 426-8.
[13] review of M. Giusta, I dossografi di etica I, Mnemosyne 21: 436-8.
[14] review of G. F. Parker, A Short Account of Greek Philosophy,
Bibliotheca Orientalis 25: 224-5.
[15] review of Th. Cole, Democritus and the Sources of Greek Anthropology, janus 55: 220-4.
[16] 'Positivistische Hermeneutiek bij Popper', in Handelingen dertigste nederlandse filologencongres (Groningen: Wolters-Noordhoff),
65-7 [Abstract].
1969
[17] review article G. E. R. Lloyd, Polarity and Analogy: Two Types
of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought, Lampas 2: 46-57.
[18] review of F. M. Cleve, The Giants of Pre-Sophistic Greek
Philosophy 1-11, Mnemosyne 22: 436-8.
[19] review of F. Dieterle, Platons Laches und Charmides, Gymnasium
76:93-5.
[20] review of D. J. Furley, Two Studies in the Greek Atomists,
Gymnasium 76: 100-3.
1970
[21] 'cr<pa.tpf\c; EV<X.AtyJCtOV oyKcp', in Akten des XIV. Internationalen
Kongresses fur Philosophie, Wien 2-9 Sept. 1968, Bd. V (Wien:
Herder), 414-9.
[22] review of E. de Strycker, Beknopte geschiedenis van de antieke
filosofie, Mnemosyne 23: 198-9.
[23] 'Nawoord', in Grondslagen van het wetenschappelijk denken,
Voordrachten Studium Generale Rotterdam (Rotterdam:
Universitaire Pers Rotterdam), 141-51.
[24] 'Naschrift' in Dutch translation with commentary of M.
Heidegger, Wat is dat -Filosofie? (Tiel-Utrecht: Lannoo), 60-1.
1971
[25] The Pseudo-Hippocratic Tract IIEPI 'EB.tWMA.J.QN Ch. 1-11 and
Greek Philosophy, Philosophical Texts and Studies 20 (Assen:
Royal Van Gorcum & Comp.), pp. 271.
420
1972
[26] 'Ambiguity in Empedocles B 17, 3-5: A Suggestion', Phronesis
17: 17-39.
[27] 'Three Notes on Albinus (1. Problems of Transcendence. 2.
Forms and Qualities. 3. The Descent of Soul)', Theta-Pi 1: 61-80;
repr. in [125].
[28] 'Man the Measure and Sense-Perception', Theta-Pi 1: 128-39.
[29] review of]. Moreau, Le sens du Platonisme, Gymnasium 79: 254-5.
[30] 'Literatuurbericht: Wijsbegeerte in de Oudheid, 1', Algemeen
Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 64: 140-58.
[31] 'Literatuurbericht: Wijsbegeerte in de Oudheid, II', Algemeen
Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 64: 216-33.
1973
[32] Theorie en Empirie. Filosofie en geneeskunst in de voorsokratische
periode. Assen: Van Gorcum, pp. 38 [inaugural lecture Utrecht
University].
[33] 'Notes on Some Passages in Plato's Theaetetus (l. The Objects
of Knowledge. 2. The Mathematical Passage)', in Zetesis. Liber
amicorum E. de Strycker (Antwerpen-Utrecht: De Nederlandse
Boekhandel), 108-14.
[34] 'Moeite met Plato', Lampas 6: 255-66.
[35] review of Th. G. Sinnige, Matter and Infinity in the Presocratic
Schools and Plato, Mnemosyne 26: 64-70.
[36] review of M. Giusta, I Dossografi di Etica II, Mnemosyne 26: 75-6.
[37] review of K. Oehler, Antike Philosophie und byzantinisches
Mittelalter, Gymnasium 80: 324-5.
[38] 'Grieks-wijsgerig commentaar', philosophical comments in
Dutch translation with commentary of M. Heidegger, Brief over
het humanisme (Tiel-Utrecht: Lannoo), 125-9.
1975
[39] (with P. W. van der Horst) An Alexandrian Platonist Against
Dualism: Alexander of Lycopolis' Treatise 'Against the Doctrines of
Manichaeus', translated with an introduction, notes, and index
(Leiden: E. J. Brill), pp. 99; introduction repr. in [ 125]; simultaneously published at Theta-Pi 3: 1-97.
[ 40] 'Alcmaeon: Physikos or Physician?', in J. Mansfeld and L. M.
de Rijk (eds.), Kephalaion. Festschrift C. J de Vogel, Philosophical
421
Texts and Studies 23 (Assen: Royal Van Gorcum & Comp.), 2638.
[41] 'Voorsocratici', Lampas8: 318-26.
1976
[ 42] Review of H. Lloyd:Jones, Semonides on Women, Maatstaf 24:
71-3.
1977
[ 43] 106 articles on ancient philosophy, ranging from the very
brief to the quite extensive, in K. Kuypers (ed.), Encyclopedie van
de .filoso.fie (Amsterdam-Brussel: Argus Elsevier); revised and
bibliographically updated versions of contributions to the major
Dutch general encyclopedia, the Grote Winkler Prins, 7th edition
(Amsterdam-Brussel: Elsevier), 1966-1975; these have been
reprinted in the Grote Winkler Prins, 8th entirely revised edition
(Arnsterdam-Brussel: Elsevier), 1979-84.
[44] 'Aristoteles over waar en onwaar', Wijsgerig Perspectiefl8: 18-9.
1978
[45] 'Zeno ofCitium', Mnemosyne3I: 134-78.
[ 46] review of]. Bollack, Empedocle II-III, Mnemosyne 31: 207-9.
1979
[ 47] Heraclitus: Fragmenten, bezorgd, vertaald en toegelicht (Amsterdam: Polak en Van Gennep), pp. 79; 2nd rev. ed. 1987.
[ 48] 'The Chronology of Anaxagoras' Athenian Period and the
Date of his Trial. Pt. I, The Length and Dating of the Athenian
Period', Mnemosyne 32: 39-69; repr. in [134].
[49] 'Providence and the Destruction of the Universe in Early Stoic
Thought', in M. ]. Vermaseren (ed.), Studies in Hellenistic
Religions, EPRO 78 (Leiden: EJ. Brill), 129- 88; repr. in [125].
[50] review of H. A. K. Hunt, The Doctrines of Zeno the Stoic, Mnemosyne 32: 411-4.
1980
[51] 'The Chronology of Anaxagoras' Athenian Period and the
Date of his Trial. Pt. II, The Plot against Pericles and his
Associates', Mnemosyne 33: 17-95.
422
[56] 'Bad World and Demiurge: A 'Gnostic' Motif from Parmenides and Empedocles to Lucretius and Philo', in R. v. d. BroekM. J. Vermaseren (eds.), Studies in Gnosticism and Hellenistic
Religions. Festschrift G. Qyispel, EPRO 91 (Leiden: EJ.Brill), 261314; repr. in [125].
[57] 'Hesiod and Parmenides in Nag Hammadi', Vigiliae
Christianae 35: 174-82; repr. in [125].
[58] 'Protagoras on Epistemological Obstacles and Persons', in G. B.
Kerferd (ed.), The Sophists and their Legacy, Hermes Einzelschriften 44 (Wiesbaden: Steiner), 38-53.
[59] review of W. Kullman, lnterpretationen zur aristotelischen Theorie
der Natunvissenschaft, Bibliotheca Orientalis 38: 219-25.
[60] 'De metafysika van Aristoteles', in C. A. van Peursen -E. J.
Petersma (eds.), Metafysica (Meppel: Boom), 16-48.
[61] 'De maat en de mensen' (oration on the occasion of the dies
natalis of Utrecht University), Utrecht, The University, pp. 21.
[62] 'Pythagoras en het oude Pythagoreisme', Hermeneus 53: 80-93.
1982
423
424
[87] 'Wilamowitz' Ciceronian Philosophy', in W. M. Calder IIIH. Flashar- Th. Lindken (eds.), Wilamowitz nach funftig jahren
(Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft), 178-221.
[88] 'Some Stoics on the Soul', Mnemosyne 37: 443-5; repr. in [125].
[89] 'Versions of the Nobody', Mnemosyne 37: 445-7.
[90] . 'On Two Fragments of Heraclitus in Clement of Alexandria',
Mnemosyne37: 447-51; repr. in [125].
[91] 'Aristotle and Others on Thales, or the Beginnings of Natural
Philosophy. With Some Remarks on Xenophanes', Mnemosyne
38: 109-29; repr. in [134].
[92] 'Heraclitus, Empedocles, and Others in a Middle Platonist
Cento in Philo of Alexandria', Vigiliae Christianae 39: 131-56; repr.
in [125].
[93] 'Philosophy and Philosophies: A Reply to Leszl and Vegetti',
Qy,aderni di Storia 11: 177-83.
[94] 'Myth, Science, Philosophy: A Question of Origins', in
W. M. Calder III - U. K. Goldsmith - P. B. Kenevan (eds.),
Hypatia. Festschrift H. E. Barnes (Boulder Co.: Colorado Associated
University Press), 45-65; English version of [84]; repr. in [134].
[95] review of D. O'Brien, Pour interpretrrr Empedocle, Mnemosyne 38:
183-8; repr. in [125].
[96] review of H. B. Gottschalk, Heraclides of Pontus, Mnemosyne 38:
202-8.
[97] review of A. M. Ioppolo, Aristone di Chio e lo Stoicismo antico,
Mnemosyne 38: 209-15.
[98] review of S. Stiidele, Die Briefe des Pythagoras und der Pythagoreer, Mnemosyne 38: 215-7.
[99] review of G. Rocca-Serra, Censorinus. Le jour nata~ Mnemosyne
38:234-6.
[100] review of L. J. Alderink, Creation and Salvation in Ancient
Orphism, Mnemosyne 38: 436-8; repr. in [125].
[101] Absolutisme en relativisme, Haarlemse voordrachten XLV
425
426
427
428
1992
429
1994
[ 155] Prolegomena. Questions to be Settled before the Interpretation of an
Author, or a Text, Philosophia Antiqua Vol. LVIII (Leiden: EJ.
Brill), pp. vii + 252.
[156] 'A Lost Manuscript of Empedocles' Katharmoi', Mnemosyne 47:
79-82.
[157] 'Epicurus Peripateticus', in A. Alberti (ed.), Realta e ragione.
Studi di filosofia antica (Firenze), 29-4 7.
[158] 'The Rhetoric in the Proem of Parmenides', in L. BertelliP.-L. Donini (eds.), Filosofia, Politica, Retorica. Intersezioni possibili
(Milano: Francoangeli 1994) 1-11.
[159] review of M. Frede - G. Patzig, Aristoteles, Metaphysik Z,
Mnemosyne 47: 120-1.
[160] review of Dexippus, On Aristotle, Categories. Translated by John
Dillon, Mnemosyne 47: 287.
[161] review of Alexander of Aphrodisias, Quaestiones 1.1-2.15.
Translated by R. W. Sharples, Mnemosyne 4 7: 427-8.
1995
[162] 'Critical Note: Empedocles and his Interpreters', Phronesis 40:
109-15.
[163] 'Aenesidemus and the Academics', in L. Ayres (ed.), The
Passionate Intellect. Festschrift I. G. Kidd, Rutgers Studies in the
Classical Humanities, Vol. VII (New Brunswick/London:
Transaction Publishers), 235-47.
[164] 'Papias over traditie', Nederlands Theologisch Tijdschrift 49
(1995): 140-53.
[165] 'Insight by Hindsight. Intentional unclarity in Presocratic
Proems', Bulletin Institute Classical Studies 42: 225-32.
Major works In Progress
430
Editorial Work
Asdepius 337
Aspasius 266
Athenodorus of Tarsus 236
Atticus 82, 84
Augustine 194, 216, 404
Aulus Gellius 193, 198, 203-204, 216
Ausonius 216
Basil of Caesarea 86
Bion 169
Bion of Borysthenes 206
Boethus of Sidon 136
Callias 289-290
Callimachus 206
Calliphon 215
Carneades 169, 215
Catius 238
Celsus 315, 319-323, 327-328
Chamaeleon 206
Chrysippus 169-183, 191-193, 197200,203,253,257,261,267,269270,276-278,366,368,373,375,
377-381
Cicero 21, 23, 32-37, 191, 194, 196198,204,208-217,222,223,236,
238-239, 246, 254, 258, 262, 277,
308,386,395,397-398
Cleanthes 171, 258, 366, 378-381
Clement of Alexandria 100, 197198,280,318
Cleomedes 195
Clitomachus 169, 208
Corpus Hermeticum 326
Critolaus 192
Democritus 7, 8, 22, 24, 27, 32, 36,
37,140,169,239,337,346
Diagoras of Melus 211, 216
Dichaearchus 223-224, 230
Diodes 208
Diodes of Cnidus 208
Diodes of Magnesia 175, 178
Diodorus 169
Diodorus Siculus 140
Diogenes Laertius 22, 27-28, 101,
114, 145-165, 169-183, 207, 208,
212,254,386
Diogenes of Babylon 136, 181
432
Idomeneus 207
Irenaeus 318
!socrates 157-58
John Chrysostom 151
John Lydus 377
John Philoponus 86-87
Josephus 314, 325
Julian 319-320, 322-323, 326
Lactantius 216
Lacydes 169
Leucippus 7, 169
Lucian 328
Lucilius 208-209, 216
Lucretius 22, 139, 220-230, 231-240
Lycon 169
Lycus 281
Mani 314
Marcus Aurelius 258
Meleager 208
Meleager of Gadara 208
Melissus 24, 169
Menedemus of Eretria 169
Menedemus the Cynic 169
Metrodorus of Chios 21-37
Mnesarchus 381
Monimus 28
Musonius Rufus 246
Myson 169
Nemesius 192, 274
Nessas of Chios 27
New Testament 319, 321-322
Nikolaus 208
Nilus 163
Numenius of Apamea 274, 301, 317
Old Testament 322-326
Onesicritus 224
Origen 328
Ovid 141
Panaetius 136, 171-72, 208, 252,
366,381
Parmenides 24, 237, 345, 368
Pausanias 141
Phainias 206
Philip the Megarian 206, 207
Philo of Alexandria 135-144, 325
Philodemus 22, 25, 170, 224, 228,
229
Philolaus 142, 368
Photius 280-281, 323
433
Bonjour, L. 24
Bork, A. 414
Boudreaux, P. 148-150, 162-164
Bousquet, J. 66
Bowersock, G. W. 364
Braun, L. 336
Braun, M. 410
Brinkmann, A. 315
Brisson, L. 77, 172
Brochard, V. 31
Brucker,J.J. 395, 400
Bruns, I. 202, 265, 286
Brunschwig, J. 170, 177, 253
Burnet, J. 8, 104
Burnyeat, M. 22, 26, 29, 269, 279
Butler, W. A. 402
Calder III, W. M. 410-412, 417
Cambiano, G. 68
Campbell, L. 392, 401
Cappelletti, A. J. 31, 33
Carlyle, T. 402
Charlton, W. 188
Chenu, M.-D. 76
Cherniss, H. 77, 87, 89
Christ, G. 155
Classen, C. J. 206, 213
Cohen, S.J. D. 318
Cole, T. 221, 223
Coleridge, S. T. 402
Comte, A. 403
Conche, M. 34, 37
Conze, A. 408
Copleston, F. 401
Cornford, F. M. 6
Costa, C. D. N. 223, 228, 230
Courcelle, P. 316
Cousin, V. 391
Cozijnsen, B. 324
Cronert, W. 25, 170, 208
Cross, R. C. 41, 56
Daiber, H. 144
Dal Pra, M. 34
Dancy, R. M. 99
Deichgraber, K. 70, 280-281
DeLacy, P. 22, 266
Denyer, N. 5
Des Places, E. 31
Deuse, W. 274-275
Diels, H. 33, 35-36, 237, 279, 335,
348, 363-381, 410
Dies, A. 104, 107, 111
Diez Macho, A. 324
Dihle, A. 227
Dillon, J. M. 300, 302, 307-308,
325,348
Dilthey, W. 407-417
Dirlmeier, F. 295
Dodd, C. H. 327
Donini, P.-L. 265, 266, 284-285,
292,294-295,298,301
Dorandi, T. 169-70, 226, 228
Doring, K. 104, 206, 207, 212, 217
Dorrie, H. 76, 173
Dowden, J. 402
Dreyer, 0. 323
Dryoff, A. 170, 177
Dumont, J. P. 31, 34
During, I. 104
Easterling, H. J. 77
Ebert, T. 90
Eggers Lan, C. 84, 86
Egli, U. 173
Ehlers, D. 410
Enfield, W. 395
Englert, W. 262
Erler, M. 207
Ernout, A. 22, 36-37
Faber, G. 401
Fakhry, M. 76
Festugiere, A.-:J. 316
Fichte, J. G. 401
Ficino, M. 390, 395
Fortenbaugh, W. W. 144, 376
Fowler, D. P. 230
Frankel, H. 3, 7, 9-11, 13
Frede, D. 188, 295, 299
Frede, M. 194, 199, 265, 274-275
Freudenthal, J. 301
Friedlander, P. 33, 104
Friedrich, C. 70
Fritz, von, K. 336
Furley, D. 3, 5, 9, 11-13
Furth, M. 3, 14, 17
Gaiser, C. 156
Gale, M. R. 223, 226, 236
Gauthier, R. A. 104
Geffcken, J. 326-327
Giannantoni, G. 206
Giannattasio Andria, R. 170
435
436
Levy, c. 35
Lewes, G. H. 402
Lieu, S. N. C. 313-314, 319
Lloyd, G. E. R. 67
Long, A.A. 175,195,252,257
Long, H. S. 153
Lorenz, T. 408
Louis, P. 300
Ludlam, I. 53, 405
364
Irwin, T. H. 334
Isnardi Parente M. 22, 99
Jahn, K. 409
Jensen, C. 163
Jolif, J. Y. 104
Joly, R. 68, 71
Jori, A. 68
Jowett, B. 56, 385-406
Kaerst, J. 225
Kahn, C. H. 41-42, 48-49, 345, 364
Kant, I. 396, 401-402
Kardaun, M. 117, 123
Kekule von Stradonitz, R. 407-409,
417
Kerferd, G. B. 41, 56
Kern, 0. 410
Kidd, I. G. 143-144
Kindstrand, J. F. 207, 208
Kirchhoff, A. 409
Kirk, G. S. 3, 7
Kirsten, C. 408
Klaffenbach, G. 417
Knebel, K. L. von 237
Knoepfler, D. 146-148
Kornbichler, T. 408
Kosenina, A. 412
Kozik, I. S. 316
Kramer, H. J. 104, 156
Krenkel, W. 209
Labriolle, P. de 329
Laks, A. 346
Lambinus, D. 212
Landmann, M 77
Langerbeck, H. 22-23, 29, 33, 35-36
Lanza, D. 8
Lattermann, H. 413
Le Boulluec, A. 318
Lebeck, A. 48-49
Lebedev, A. 366
Leo,F. 408,413,417
Leon, P. 15, 18
Lesher, J. H. 25
Macaulay, T. 238
Mackie,]. L. 186, 190, 200
Mackintosh, J. 401
Maguire, J. P. 43-44, 56-57
Maguire, T. 402
Maher, M. 324
Maier, H. 412
Malherbe, A. J. 314
Malingrey, A. M. 314
Mannebach, E. 206
MansfeldJ. 3, 10, 13-19, 21, 25, 32,
34,36,50, 68, 71, 77,83,92, 135,
143-144, 146, 157-158, 169, 174,
178,181,265,266,270,275-280,
284-285,289,294,313,315,321322, 333, 337, 341, 345 366, 371,
387,412
Mansion, S. 333
Marmura, M. E. 266, 267
Mathhias, T. J. 400
Matthen, M. 131
Mau, J. 367
McDiarmid, J. B. 137, 345
Meier, M. 336
Meineke, A. 363, 373
Mejer, J. 170, 335
Meredith, A. 319
Merlan, P. 99, 102
Mill, James 396-406
Mill, J. S. 385-386, 396-406
Misch, G. 407, 409, 411, 415-416
Misch, geb. Dilthey, C. 409, 411,
415-416
Mohr, R. D. 77-78, 83-84, 89
Mommsen, T. 238, 408-412
Mondolfo, R. 22, 31
Montanari, E. 115, 126
Moraux, P. 148-164, 266, 279, 365
Morsink, J. 334
Mosheim, J. L. von 395
Most, G. 346
Mras, K. 379
Muller, G. 44
Munro, H. A. J. 237, 238
Mure, G. R. G. 186
Murray, 0. 225
Mutschmann, H. 146-164
Nachmanson, E. 177
Naddaf, G. 77, 84-85
Naldini, M. 316
Nestle, W. 320
Nettleship, R. C. 58
Nicholson, P. P. 53, 56-57
Nohl, H. 410, 414
Nussbaum, M. C. 249
Nutton, V. 66, 265
Oehler, K. 407
Orelli, G. 287
Orlandi, T. 316
Ostenfeld, E. 77
Owen, G. E. L. 405
Pasquali, G. 158
Passmore, J. 335
Peacock,T.L. 396
Pease, A. S. 321
Pembroke, S. G. 252
Pepin, J. 77
Philippson, R. 104
Pines, S. 266, 317
Plasberg, 0. 23
Pohlenz, M. 252
Rackham, H. 23, 34
Raine, K. 395
Ramus, P. 400-401
Raven, ]. E. 3, 6
Reeve, C. D. C. 43, 55, 58
Reeves, J. C. 320, 326
Regenbogen, 0. 239
Reid, ]. S. 23
Reimer, G. 409
Reinhardt, K. 336, 412
Renan, E. 411
Rescher, N. 266, 267
Rijk, L. M. de 119, 121-125, 130133
Rinaldi, G. 326
Roberts, C. H. 313
Robertson, E. S. 402
Robin, L. 22, 36-37, 78
Robinson, T. M. 77, 81, 88
Robson, ]. M. 397
Rohlfing, H. 407
Rorty, R. 335
Rose, V. 153-154, 158, 163-164
Ross, W. D. 115, 156, 190, 341
Rossitto, C. 148-164
437
Rubensen, S. 316
Rugullis, S. 407, 412
Ruijgh, C.]. 313
Runia, D. T. 49, 136-137, 141, 279280,366,374,376-378
Russell, B. 190
Russell, N. 316
Rutherford, R B. 41, 43, 53-54
Ryffel, H. 223
Salmon, W. 186, 204
Sandbach, F. H. 194
Scheffel, W. 76, 78, 80, 86
Schelling, F. W. ]. von 402-403
Schickert, K. 334
Schleiermacher, F. 388, 392
Schmidt, C. B. 400
Schofield, M. 3, 7, 9, 16, 104, 252
Schrader, H. 408-409
Schrijvers, P. H. 224, 226, 229
Schwyzer, E. 91
Scott, D. 307
Sedley, D. N. 31, 135, 141, 195, 252,
300-301, 347, 350
Sewell, W. 402
Sharples, R W. 144, 202, 266, 267,
279, 287-288, 294, 296-297, 299,
300,376
Shorey, P. 22
Shrenk, L. P. 300
Sider, D. 4
Sidgwick, H. 56
Simon, H. 76
Skemp,]. 83
Smith, M. F. 231, 237
Smith, R. 342
Smith, W. D. 71
Solmsen, F. 77
Sorabji, R 17, 76, 83, 186, 188, 295,
329
Souilhe,]. 158, 255
Spiegel, S. 324
Spinoza, B. 394
Spoerri, W. 229
Steenberghen, F. van 76
Stern, L. 409
Stevenson,]. G. 335
Stirling, A. H. 401
Stirling, ]. H. 401
Stokes, M. C. 44, 52, 405
Strang, C. 11, 15, 18
Stratton, G. M. 345-347, 351, 353,
359
Straume-Zimmermann, L. 22-23,
29,35
438
Strauss, D. F. 411
Strauss, L. 405
Striker, G. 253, 305
Stroumsa, G. 313, 320
Stuart, D. 399
Suchow, F. G. G. 155
Sudhaus, S. 163
Summers, K. 233
Susemihl, F. 155
Sydenham, F. 400
Szlezak, T. 94
Talon, 0. 400
Taran, L. 77-78, 83, 86-89, 99, 102,
104-105
Taylor, A. E. 104, 355
Taylor, T. 385, 386, 394-396, 400
Temkin, 0. 265
Thiilet, P. 285-287, 294, 296
Thompson, W. H. 402
Throm, H. 280
Tieleman, T. L. 178, 265, 270, 272,
276
Tigerstedt, E. N. 395, 400
Timpanaro, S. 225
Todd,R.B. 26~267,271, 276,279
Traina, A. 218
Usener, H. 195, 208
Vahlen, ]. 408
Van der Waerdt, P. 22, 31, 228
Vegetti, M. 71, 73
Venn,J. 185,204
Villers, C. 400
Viiley, A. 313, 314, 316, 320, 327
Vlastos, G. 6-7, 9-11, 19, 42, 77, 84
Vries, G. de 53
Wachsmuth, C. 366, 374-375, 379
Walbank, F. 221
Wallis, R. T. 320
Walzer, R. 317
Wansink, P. 324
Wardy, R. 334
Warnock, G.]. 401
Waszink, ]. H. 328
Weber, B. C. 217
Weber, H.-0. 221
Wehrli, F. 208, 230
Weidemann, H. 115-120, 124, 126130, 132-133
Weil, E. 333
Weil, R. 336
Welcker, F. C. 417
Wendland, P. 163
Westerink, L. G. 329
Wevers, ]. W. 325
White, N. P. 42
White, S. 201
Whittaker,]. 300, 307, 309
Wieland, W. 119
Wiersma, W. 137
Wiggins, D. 189
Wilamowitz-Mollendorf, U.
von 26, 42, 104, 407-417
Wilke, K. 163
Wilken, R. L. 314, 327
Wilpert, P. 155
Winston, D. 325
Woodruff, P. 52
Woozley, A. D. 41, 56
Yorck von Wartenburg, P. 413
Zeller, E. 22, 31, 77, 135, 155, 364,
407-411, 413-415
Zierl, A. 285, 288
Zoepffel, R. 336