Pascal's Treatise On The Arithmetical Triangle: Mathematical Induction, Combinations, The Binomial Theorem and Fermat's Theorem

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

Pascals Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle: Mathematical

Induction, Combinations, the Binomial Theorem and Fermats


Theorem
David Pengelley

Introduction
Blaise Pascal (16231662) was born in Clermont-Ferrand in central France. Even as a teenager his
father introduced him to meetings for mathematical discussion in Paris run by Marin Mersenne,
who served as a primary conduit for transmitting mathematical ideas widely at that time, before
the existence of any research journals. He quickly became involved in the development of projective
geometry, the first in a sequence of highly creative mathematical and scientific episodes in his life,
punctuated by periods of religious fervor. Around age twenty-one he spent several years developing
a mechanical addition and subtraction machine, in part to help his father in tax computations as
a local administrator. It was the first of its kind ever to be marketed. Then for several years he
was at the center of efforts to understand vacuum, which led to an understanding of barometric
pressure. In fact the scientific unit of pressure is named the pascal. He is also known for Pascals
Law on the behavior of fluid pressure.
Around 1654 Pascal conducted his studies on the Arithmetical Triangle (Pascals Triangle)
and its relationship to probabilities. His correspondence with Pierre de Fermat (16011665) in that
year marks the beginning of probability theory. Several years later, Pascal refined his ideas on
area problems via the method of indivisibles already being developed by others, and solved various
problems of areas, volumes, centers of gravity, and lengths of curves. Later in the seventeenth
century, Gottfried Leibniz, one of the two inventors of the infinitesimal calculus which supplanted
the method of indivisibles, explicitly credited Pascals approach as stimulating his own ideas on
the so-called characteristic triangle of infinitesimals in his fundamental theorem of calculus. After
only two years of work on the calculus of indivisibles, Pascal fell gravely ill, abandoned almost all
intellectual work to devote himself to prayer and charitable work, and died three years later at
age thirty-nine. In addition to his work in mathematics and physics, Pascal is prominent for his
Provincial Letters defending Christianity, which gave rise to his posthumously published Pensees
(Thoughts) on religious philosophy [1, 2]. Pascal was an extremely complex person, and one of the
outstanding scientists of the mid-seventeenth century, but we will never know how much more he
might have accomplished with more sustained efforts and a longer life.
Pascals Traite du Triangle Arithmetique (in English translation in [5, vol. 30]) makes a systematic study of the numbers in his triangle. They have simultaneous roles in mathematics as figurate
numbers1 , combination numbers, and binomial coefficients, and he elaborates on all these. Given

With thanks to Joel Lucero-Bryan and Jerry Lodder.


Mathematical Sciences; Dept. 3MB, Box 30001; New Mexico State University; Las Cruces, NM 88003;
[email protected].
1
Figurate numbers count the number of equally spaced dots in geometric figures. Especially important to Pascal
were the numbers of dots in equilateral triangles, triangular pyramids, and so forth in higher dimensions.

their multifaceted nature, it is no wonder that these ubiquitous numbers had already been in use
for over 500 years, in places ranging from China to the Islamic world [3]. Pascal, however, was the
first to connect binomial coefficients with combinatorial coefficients in probability. In fact, a major
motivation for Pascal was a question from the beginnings of probability theory, about the equitable division of stakes in an interrupted game of chance. The question had been posed to Pascal
around 1652 by Antoine Gombaud, the Chevalier de Mere, who wanted to improve his chances at
gambling: Suppose two players are playing a fair game, to continue until one player wins a certain
number of rounds, but the game is interrupted before either player reaches the winning number.
How should the stakes be divided equitably, based on the number of rounds each player has won [3,
p. 431, 451ff]? The solution requires the combinatorial properties inherent in the numbers in the
Arithmetical Triangle, as Pascal demonstrated in his treatise, since they count the number of ways
various occurrences can combine to produce a given result. The Arithmetical Triangle overflows
with fascinating patterns and applications, and we will see several of these in reading his treatise.
We will study parts of Pascals explanation of the connections between the numbers in his triangle
and combination numbers. The reader is encouraged to read his entire treatise to see its many
other aspects and connections.
From Pascals treatise we will also learn the principle of mathematical induction. Pascal explains this in the specific context of proofs about the numbers in the triangle. The basic idea of
mathematical induction had occurred in the mathematics of the Islamic world during the Middle
Ages, and in southern Europe in the fourteenth century [3], but Pascals was perhaps the first text
to make a complete explicit statement and justification of this extremely powerful method of proof
in modern mathematics. Mathematical induction is an astonishingly clever technique that allows
us to prove claims about infinitely many interlinked phenomena all at once, even when proving
just a single one of them in isolation would be very difficult! It will be a challenging technique to
master, but will provide tremendous power for future mathematical work.
Learning about the connections of the Arithmetical Triangle to the binomial theorem in algebra will also allow an application to proving a famous and extremely important theorem on prime
numbers discovered by Pascals correspondent Pierre de Fermat (16011665) of Toulouse, on congruence remainders and prime numbers. This prepares one to understand the RSA cryptosystem,
which today is at the heart of securing electronic transactions. Well see how all these things are
interconnected, and along the way well also acquire important mathematical tools, like notations
for general indexing, summations, and products, and learn how to work with recurrence relations.

Part One: The Arithmetical Triangle and Mathematical Induction


Let us begin reading Blaise Pascals

TREATISE ON THE ARITHMETICAL TRIANGLE


Definitions
I call arithmetical triangle a figure constructed as follows:
From any point, G, I draw two lines perpendicular to each other, GV, G in each of which I
take as many equal and contiguous parts as I please, beginning with G, which I number 1,
2, 3, 4, etc., and these numbers are the exponents of the sections of the lines.
Next I connect the points of the first section in each of the two lines by another line, which
is the base of the resulting triangle.

In the same way I connect the two points of the second section by another line, making a
second triangle of which it is the base.

@G
1
1
1
1
1
1
@
1
@
@

S
N
R
1
2
3
4
5
6
@
2
@

A
B @C
1
3
6
10
15
21
@
3
@
Y
D
E
F @
1
4
10
20
35
56
@
4
@
H
M
K
@
1
5
15
35
70
126
@
5
@
P

21

56

28

84

36

7
T
8
9
10

7 L

10

28

36

84

126

And in this way connecting all the points of section with the same exponent, I construct as
many triangles and bases as there are exponents.
Through each of the points of section and parallel to the sides I draw lines whose intersections
make little squares which I call cells.
Cells between two parallels drawn from left to right are called cells of the same parallel row,
as, for example, cells G, , , etc., or , , , etc.
Those between two lines are drawn from top to bottom are called cells of the same perpendicular row, as, for example, cells G, , A, D, etc., or , , B, etc.
Those cut diagonally by the same base are called cells of the same base, as, for example,
D, B, , , or A, , .
Cells of the same base equidistant from its extremities are called reciprocals, as, for example,
E, R and B, , because the parallel exponent of one is the same as the perpendicular
exponent of the other, as is apparent in the above example, where E is in the second
perpendicular row and in the fourth parallel row and its reciprocal, R, is in the second
parallel row and in the fourth perpendicular row, reciprocally. It is very easy to demonstrate
that cells with exponents reciprocally the same are in the same base and are equidistant
from its extremities.
3

It is also very easy to demonstrate that the perpendicular exponent of any cell when added
to is parallel exponent exceeds by unity the exponent of its base.
For example, cell F is in the third perpendicular row and in the fourth parallel row and in
the sixth base, and the exponents of rows 3 and 4, added together, exceed by unity the
exponent of base 6, a property which follows from the fact that the two sides of the triangle
have the same number of parts; but this is understood rather than demonstrated.
Of the same kind is the observation that each base has one more cell than the preceding
base, and that each has as many cells as its exponent has units; thus the second base, ,
has two cells, the third, A, has three, etc.
Now the numbers assigned to each cell are found by the following method:
The number of the first cell, which is at the right angle, is arbitrary; but that number having
been assigned, all the rest are determined, and for this reason it is called the generator of
the triangle. Each of the others is specified by a single rule as follows:
The number of each cell is equal to the sum of the numbers of the perpendicular and parallel
cells immediately preceding. Thus cell F, that is, the number of cell F, equals the sum of
cell C and cell E, and similarly with the rest.
Whence several consequences are drawn. The most important follow, wherein I consider
triangles generated by unity, but what is said of them will hold for all others.

First Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle all the cells of the first parallel row and of the first perpendicular
row are the same as the generating cell.
For by definition each cell of the triangle is equal to the sum of the immediately preceding
perpendicular and parallel cells. But the cells of the first parallel row have no preceding
perpendicular cells, and those of the first perpendicular row have no preceding parallel cells;
therefore they are all equal to each other and consequently to the generating number.
Thus = G + 0,
A = + 0,
= G + 0,

that is, = G,
that is, ,
= + 0,

And similarly of the rest.

Second Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell is equal to the sum of all the cells of the preceding
parallel row from its own perpendicular row to the first, inclusive.
Let any cell, , be taken. I say that it is equal to R + + + , which are the cells of the
next higher parallel row from the perpendicular row of to the first perpendicular row.
This is evident if we simply consider a cell as the sum of its component cells.

For equals R + C
| {z }
+B
| {z }
+A
| {z }
,
for A and are equal to each other by the preceding consequence.
Therefore = R + + + .
Third Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell is equal to the sum of all the cells of the preceding
perpendicular row from its own parallel row to the first, inclusive.
Let any cell, C, be taken. I say that it is equal to B + + , which are the cells of the
preceding perpendicular row from the parallel row of cell C to the first parallel row.
This is also apparent, as above, simply by the interpretation of cells.
For C = B +
| {z }
+
|{z}
,
for = by the first consequence.
Therefore C = B + + .

Fourth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell exceeds by unity the sum of all the cells within its
parallel and perpendicular rows, exclusive.
Let any cell, , be taken. I say that G = R + + + + + + + G, which are all
the numbers between row CBA and row S exclusive.
This is also apparent by interpretation.
For = + R +
| {z }
++C
| {z }
++B
| {z }
G++A
| {z }
G.
Therefore = + R + + + + + G + + G.
N.B. I have written in the enunciation each cell exceeds by unity because the generator is
unity. If it were some other number, the enunciation should read: each cell exceeds by the
generating number.

1. Pascals Triangle and its numbers

(a) Let us use the notation Ti,j to denote what Pascal calls the number assigned to the cell
in parallel row i (which we today call just row i) and perpendicular row j (which we
today call column j). We call the i and j by the name indices (plural of index ) in our
notation. Using this notation, explain exactly what Pascals rule is for determining all
the numbers in all the cells. Be sure to give full details. This should include explaining
for exactly which values of the indices he defines the numbers.
(b) In terms of our notation Ti,j , explain his terms exponent, base, reciprocal, parallel row,
perpendicular row, and generator.
(c) Rewrite Pascals first two Consequences entirely in the Ti,j notation.
(d) Rewrite his proofs of these word for word in our notation also.
(e) Do you find his proofs entirely satisfactory? Explain why or why not.
(f) Improve on his proofs using our notation. In other words, make them apply for arbitrary
prescribed situations, not just the particular examples he lays out.
2. Modern mathematical notation
Read in a modern textbook about index, summation, and product notations, and recurrence
relations. Do some exercises.

Fifth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell is equal to its reciprocal.
For in the second base, , it is evident that the two reciprocal cells, , , are equal to each
other and to G.
In the third base, A, , , it is also obvious that the reciprocals, , A, are equal to each
other and to G.
In the fourth base it is obvious that the extremes, D, , are again equal to each other and
to G.
And those between, B, , are obviously equal since B = A + and = + . But
+ = A + by what has just been shown. Therefore, etc.
Similarly it can be shown for all the other bases that reciprocals are equal, because the
extremes are always equal to G and the rest can always be considered as the sum of cells
in the preceding base which are themselves reciprocals.

3. Symmetry in the triangle: first contact with mathematical induction


Write the Fifth Consequence using our index notation. Use index notation and the ideas in
Pascals proof to prove the Consequence in full generality, not just for the example he gives.
Explain the conceptual ideas behind the general proof.
4. Mathematical induction: gaining more familiarity
(a) Read in a modern textbook about mathematical induction.

(b) Prove Pascals First Consequence by mathematical induction. (Hint: for a proof by
mathematical induction, always first state very clearly exactly what the n-th mathematical statement P (n) says. Then state and prove the base step. Then state the inductive
step very clearly before you prove it.)
(c) Write the general form of Pascals Second Consequence, and give a general proof using
summation notation, but following his approach.
(d) Now prove the Second Consequence by mathematical induction, i.e., a different proof.
(e) Optional: More patterns.
i. Write the Fourth Consequence using summation notation. Hint: You can write it
using a sum of sums. Try writing Pascals proof in full generality, using summation
notation to help. If you dont complete it his way, explain why it is difficult.
ii. Prove the Fourth Consequence by mathematical induction.

Seventh Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle the sum of the cells of each base is double that of the preceding
base.
Let any base, DB, be taken. I say that the sum of its cells is double the sum of the cells
of the preceding base, A.
For the extremes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

D,
|{z}
are equal to the extremes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . A,
and each of the rest . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . B,
|{z}
is equal to two cells of the other base . . . A + ,

,
|{z}
,
,
|{z}
+ .

Therefore D + + B + = 2A + 2 + 2.
The same thing is demonstrated in the same way of all other bases.

Eighth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle the sum of the cells of each base is a number of the double
progression beginning with unity whose exponent is the same as that of the base.
For the first base is unity.
The second is double the first; therefore it is 2.
The third is double the second; therefore it is 4.
And so on to infinity.
N.B. If the generator were not unity but some other number, such as 3, the same thing would
be true. But we should have to take not the numbers of the double progression beginning
with unity, that is, 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, etc., but those of the double progression beginning with
the generator 3, that is, 3, 6, 12, 24, 48, etc.

5. Sums of bases in the triangle: a geometric progression


(a) Use our index notation Ti,j to explain exactly which are the numbers in the n-th base.
(b) In full generality, write the Seventh Consequence and its proof, using our Ti,j notation.
(c) Write the statement of the Eighth Consequence in our notation, using modern exponential notation to describe his double progression. Use summation notation as needed,
and introduce additional new notation if helpful. Then prove the Eighth Consequence
by mathematical induction.
The next consequence is the most important and famous in the whole treatise. Pascal derives
a formula for the ratio of consecutive numbers in a base. From this he will obtain an elegant and
efficient formula for all the numbers in the triangle.
Twelfth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle, of two contiguous cells in the same base the upper is to the
lower as the number of cells from the upper to the top of the base is to the number of cells
from the lower to the bottom of the base, inclusive.
Let any two contiguous cells of the same base, E, C, be taken. I say that
E : C ::
2
the
the
because there are two
lower upper cells from E to the
bottom, namely E, H,

3
because there are three
cells from C to the top,
namely C, R, .

Although this proposition has an infinity of cases, I shall demonstrate it very briefly by
supposing two lemmas:
The first, which is self-evident, that this proportion is found in the second base, for it is
perfectly obvious that : :: 1 : 1;
The second, that if this proportion is found in any base, it will necessarily be found in the
following base.
Whence it is apparent that it is necessarily in all the bases. For it is in the second base
by the first lemma; therefore by the second lemma it is in the third base, therefore in the
fourth, and to infinity.
It is only necessary therefore to demonstrate the second lemma as follows: If this proportion
is found in any base, as, for example, in the fourth, D, that is, if D : B :: 1 : 3, and
B : :: 2 : 2, and : :: 3 : 1, etc., I say the same proportion will be found in the following
base, H, and that, for example, E : C :: 2 : 3.
For D : B :: 1 : 3, by hypothesis.
+ 3} : 3
Therefore D
+ B} : B :: |1 {z
| {z
E : B :: 4 : 3
Similarly B : :: 2 : 2, by hypothesis
Therefore B
+ } : B :: |2 {z
+ 2} : 2
| {z
C : B :: 4 : 2
But
B : E :: 3 : 4
Therefore, by compounding the ratios, C : E :: 3 : 2.
8

q.e.d.

The proof is the same for all other bases, since it requires only that the proportion be found
in the preceding base,and that each cell be equal to the cell before it together with the cell
above it, which is everywhere the case.

6. Pascals Twelfth Consequence: the key to our modern factorial formula


(a) Rewrite Pascals Twelfth Consequence as a generalized modern formula, entirely in our
Ti,j terminology. Also verify its correctness in a couple of examples taken from his table
in the initial definitions section.
(b) Adapt Pascals proof by example of his Twelfth Consequence into modern generalized
form to prove the formula you obtained above. Use the principle of mathematical induction to create your proof.

Now Pascal is ready to describe a formula for an arbitrary number in the triangle.
Problem
Given the perpendicular and parallel exponents of a cell, to find its number without making
use of the arithmetical triangle.
Let it be proposed, for example, to find the number of cell of the fifth perpendicular and
of the third parallel row.
All the numbers which precede the perpendicular exponent, 5, having been taken, namely 1,
2, 3, 4, let there be taken the same number of natural numbers, beginning with the parallel
exponent, 3, namely 3, 4, 5, 6.
Let the first numbers be multiplied together and let the product be 24. Let the second
numbers be multiplied together and let the product be 360, which, divided by the first
product, 24, gives as quotient 15, which is the number sought.
For is to the first cell of its base, V, in the ratio compounded of all the ratios of the cells
between, that is to say, : V
in the ratio compounded of
or by the twelfth consequence

: ,
3:4

: K,
4:3

K : Q,
5:2

Q:V
6:1

Therefore : V :: 3 4 5 6 : 4 3 2 1.
But V is unity; therefore is the quotient of the division of the product of 3 4 5 6 by
the product of 4 3 2 1.
N.B. If the generator were not unity, we should have had to multiply the quotient by the
generator.

7. Pascals formula for the numbers in the Arithmetical Triangle


(a) Write down the general formula Pascal claims in solving his Problem. Your formula
should read Ti,j = some formula in terms of i and j. Also write your formula entirely
in terms of factorials.
9

(b) Look at the reason Pascal indicates for his formula for a cell, and use it to make a general
proof for your formula above for an arbitrary Ti,j . You may try to make your proof just
like Pascal is indicating, or you may prove it by mathematical induction.

VARIOUS USES OF THE ARITHMETICAL TRIANGLE


WHOSE GENERATOR IS UNITY
Having given the proportions obtaining between the cells and the rows of arithmetical
triangles, I turn in the following treatises to various uses of those triangles whose generator
is unity. But I leave out many more than I include; it is extraordinary how fertile in properties
this triangle is. Everyone can try his hand. I only call your attention here to the fact that in
everything that follows I am speaking exclusively of arithmetical triangles whose generator
is unity.

Part Two: Combinations and the Arithmetical Triangle


We continue reading Pascals Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle:

USE OF THE ARITHMETICAL TRIANGLE FOR COMBINATIONS


The word combination has been used in several different senses, so that to avoid ambiguity
I am obliged to say how I understand it.
When of many things we may choose a certain number, all the ways of taking as many as we
are allowed out of all those offered to our choice are here called the different combinations.
For example, if of four things expressed by the four letters, A, B, C, D, we are permitted
to take, say any two, all the different ways of taking two out of the four put before us are
called combinations.
Thus we shall find by experience that there are six different ways of choosing two out of
four; for we can take A and B, or A and C, or A and D, or B and C, or B and D, or C
and D.
I do not count A and A as one of the ways of taking two; for they are not different things,
they are only one thing repeated.
Nor do I count A and B and B and A as two different ways; for in both ways we take only
the same two things but in a different order, and I am not concerned with the order; so that
I could make myself understood at once by those who are used to considering combinations,
simply by saying that I speak only of combinations made without changing the order.
We shall also find by experience that there are four ways of taking three things out of four;
for we can take ABC or ABD or ACD or BCD.
Finally we shall find that we can take four out of four in one way only, ABCD.
I shall speak therefore in the following terms:
1
2
3
4

in
in
in
in

4
4
4
4

can
can
can
can

be
be
be
be

combined
combined
combined
combined
10

4
6
4
1

times.
times.
times.
time.

Or:
the
the
the
the

number
number
number
number

of
of
of
of

combinations
combinations
combinations
combinations

of
of
of
of

1
2
3
4

in
in
in
in

4
4
4
4

is
is
is
is

4.
6.
4.
1.

But the sum of all the combinations in general that can be made in 4 is 15, because the
number of combinations of 1 in 4, of 2 in 4, of 3 in 4, of 4 in 4, when joined together, is 15.
After this explanation I shall give the following consequences in the form of lemmas:

Lemma 1.
There are no combinations of a number in a smaller number; for example, 4 cannot be
combined in 2.
...

Proposition 2
The number of any cell is equal to the number of combinations of a number less by unity
than its parallel exponent in a number less by unity than the exponent of its base.
Let any cell be taken, say F in the fourth parallel row and in the sixth base. I say that is is
equal to the number of combinations of 3 in 5, less by unity than 4 and 6, for it is equal to
the cells A + B + C. Therefore by the preceding proposition, etc.

1. Combinations according to Pascal


(a) Explain in your own words what Pascal says about how many combinations there are
for choosing two things out of four things.
(b) Write Pascals Proposition 2 using our Ti,j notation for numbers in the triangle. In
other words, fill in a sentence saying Ti,j is the number of combinations of choosing
things from
things. Pascals justification for his Proposition 2 is based on
his Lemma 4 and Proposition 1, which are not included in this project. However, the
reader is encouraged to study and understand them, to wit:
(c) Optional: From Pascals treatise [5, vol. 30], rewrite his statements and explanations
of his Lemma 4 and Proposition 1 in your own words. State and prove Lemma 4 in the
general case; that is, show that the number of combinations of k in n is the sum of the
combinations of k 1 in n 1 and the combinations of k in n 1. Also explain why
Proposition 2 follows from Proposition 1.
2. Combinations and Pascals recursion formula

11


(a) The modern symbol nr means the number of ways (combinations) of choosing r things
from amongst n things. Explain how this is related to what we have been learning about
the Arithmetical Triangle from reading
Pascal. In particular, explain how the numbers
n
Ti,j are related to the numbers r . Do this by writingan equation expressing Ti,j in
n
n
r notation, and also writing an equation expressing r in Ti,j notation. Now use the
formula we learned earlier, from Pascals solution to his Problem,2 to write a formula
for the combination number nr , and manipulate it to express it entirely in terms of
factorials.
(b) Now read in a modern textbook about the multiplication rule for counting possibilities,
about permutations, and about combinations. Explain how a combination is different
from a permutation.
(c) Read in a modern textbook about the algebra of combinations, Pascals recursion formula, and how the text presents Pascals Triangle. How is it different from Pascals
presentation?

Part Three: The Binomial Theorem and Fermats Theorem


Now we can put together all of what we have learned from Pascal to prove an extremely important
result in number theory, called Fermats Little Theorem, which is at the heart of todays encryption methods in digital communications. The ingredients will be the binomial theorem, proof by
mathematical induction as learned from Pascal, Pascals formula for the numbers in his triangle
(solved in his Problem), and uniqueness of prime factorization.
1. The binomial theorem and combinations
Read in a modern textbook about the binomial theorem. Write an explanation of the proof
of the binomial theorem using the idea of counting combinations.
2. Discovering Fermats Little Theorem: prime numbers and congruence remainders
(a) Make a table of the remainders of an upon division by n for positive integer values of
both a and n ranging up to 14. To do this you should learn about congruence arithmetic,
and figure out how to do these calculations quickly and easily without a calculator.
(b) Based on your table, make a conjecture of the form ap ? (mod p) for p a prime number
and a any integer. This is called Fermats Little Theorem; it is one of the most
important phenomena in number theory. Also make some other interesting conjectures
from patterns in your table, and try to prove them, perhaps using the binomial theorem.
(c) Write up the details of proving Fermats Theorem by mathematical induction on a, with
p held fixed. Use the binomial theorem, our knowledge of Pascals factorial formula
for binomial coefficients, and the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic (uniqueness of
prime factorization) to analyze divisibility of the binomial coefficients by a prime p.
(d) Optional: Read about what Fermat was trying to do when he discovered his Theorem
[4, p. 159ff]. Describe what you find in your own words.
3. Optional: The RSA cryptosystem
2

Given the perpendicular and parallel exponents of a cell, to find its number without making use of the arithmetical
triangle.

12

Read and study the RSA cryptosystem and its applications to digital security, including how
it works, which follows from Fermats Theorem. Write up the details in your own words, with
some example calculations.

Notes to the Instructor


The projects primary aim is for students of introductory discrete mathematics to learn the concept
of mathematical induction and its application directly from reading the pioneering work Treatise
on the Arithmetical Triangle of Blaise Pascal in the 1650s. There are three project parts, covering
several standard topics: mathematical induction, combinations, and the binomial theorem and
Fermats Theorem. The project even ends with optional application to the RSA cryptosystem.
With the entirety of its applications the project can constitute as much as 20% of a semester
course. It works well to have students complete and submit small pieces of the project as one goes
along.
In some places the instructor should give students guidance on reading and excercises from
their textbook recommended by the project. There are also some places, especially in the third
part, where the project expects either substantial independent learning from the student or more
substantial instructor guidance.
In his treatise, Pascal, after arranging the figurate numbers in a defining triangular table, notices several patterns in the table, which he would like to claim continue indefinitely. Exhibiting
unusual rigor for his day, Pascal offers a condition for the persistence of a pattern, stated verbally
in his Twelfth Consequence, a condition known today as mathematical induction. This is perhaps
the first complete enunciation and justification in the literature of the logical principle of mathematical induction, all provided in the context of a particular application. Moreover, this Twelfth
Consequence immediately results in the modern formula for the combination numbers or binomial
coefficients.
When Pascals original writing becomes a students initial contact for learning the idea of
mathematical induction, a textbook is then merely a supplement. We have found that students
come to grips with mathematical induction better by first seeing how Pascal eases into the idea
through the proof of several patterns in the triangle, and then formalizes the principle and applies
it further. Have students first read and work quite a bit with Pascals verbal description, and
then hold an instructor-moderated class discussion comparing this to the axiomatic formulation
of induction students can read in the textbook. We intentionally wait on having students read
the textbook approach until they have become comfortable with Pascals. In fact, many students
become and remain more comfortable with Pascals more verbal way of handling mathematical
induction than with their textbooks. Students can become so comfortable with Pascals treatise
that, on a final exam, many will voluntarily choose a question requiring new analysis of a part
of Pascals treatise using mathematical induction that they have never seen, over an analogous
exercise from their modern textbook.

References
[1] Encyclopdia Britannica, Chicago, 1986.
[2] Gillispie, C. C., Holmes, F. L., (editors) Dictionary of Scientific Biography, Scribner, New
York, 1970.

13

[3] Katz, V., A History of Mathematics: An Introduction, Second Edition, Addison-Wesley, New
York, 1998.
[4] Laubenbacher, R., Pengelley, D., Mathematical Expeditions: Chronicles by the Explorers,
Springer Verlag, New York, 1999.
[5] Pascal, B., Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle, in Great Books of the Western World,
Mortimer Adler (editor), Encyclopdia Britannica, Inc., Chicago, 1991.

14

You might also like