Pascal's Treatise On The Arithmetical Triangle: Mathematical Induction, Combinations, The Binomial Theorem and Fermat's Theorem
Pascal's Treatise On The Arithmetical Triangle: Mathematical Induction, Combinations, The Binomial Theorem and Fermat's Theorem
Pascal's Treatise On The Arithmetical Triangle: Mathematical Induction, Combinations, The Binomial Theorem and Fermat's Theorem
Introduction
Blaise Pascal (16231662) was born in Clermont-Ferrand in central France. Even as a teenager his
father introduced him to meetings for mathematical discussion in Paris run by Marin Mersenne,
who served as a primary conduit for transmitting mathematical ideas widely at that time, before
the existence of any research journals. He quickly became involved in the development of projective
geometry, the first in a sequence of highly creative mathematical and scientific episodes in his life,
punctuated by periods of religious fervor. Around age twenty-one he spent several years developing
a mechanical addition and subtraction machine, in part to help his father in tax computations as
a local administrator. It was the first of its kind ever to be marketed. Then for several years he
was at the center of efforts to understand vacuum, which led to an understanding of barometric
pressure. In fact the scientific unit of pressure is named the pascal. He is also known for Pascals
Law on the behavior of fluid pressure.
Around 1654 Pascal conducted his studies on the Arithmetical Triangle (Pascals Triangle)
and its relationship to probabilities. His correspondence with Pierre de Fermat (16011665) in that
year marks the beginning of probability theory. Several years later, Pascal refined his ideas on
area problems via the method of indivisibles already being developed by others, and solved various
problems of areas, volumes, centers of gravity, and lengths of curves. Later in the seventeenth
century, Gottfried Leibniz, one of the two inventors of the infinitesimal calculus which supplanted
the method of indivisibles, explicitly credited Pascals approach as stimulating his own ideas on
the so-called characteristic triangle of infinitesimals in his fundamental theorem of calculus. After
only two years of work on the calculus of indivisibles, Pascal fell gravely ill, abandoned almost all
intellectual work to devote himself to prayer and charitable work, and died three years later at
age thirty-nine. In addition to his work in mathematics and physics, Pascal is prominent for his
Provincial Letters defending Christianity, which gave rise to his posthumously published Pensees
(Thoughts) on religious philosophy [1, 2]. Pascal was an extremely complex person, and one of the
outstanding scientists of the mid-seventeenth century, but we will never know how much more he
might have accomplished with more sustained efforts and a longer life.
Pascals Traite du Triangle Arithmetique (in English translation in [5, vol. 30]) makes a systematic study of the numbers in his triangle. They have simultaneous roles in mathematics as figurate
numbers1 , combination numbers, and binomial coefficients, and he elaborates on all these. Given
their multifaceted nature, it is no wonder that these ubiquitous numbers had already been in use
for over 500 years, in places ranging from China to the Islamic world [3]. Pascal, however, was the
first to connect binomial coefficients with combinatorial coefficients in probability. In fact, a major
motivation for Pascal was a question from the beginnings of probability theory, about the equitable division of stakes in an interrupted game of chance. The question had been posed to Pascal
around 1652 by Antoine Gombaud, the Chevalier de Mere, who wanted to improve his chances at
gambling: Suppose two players are playing a fair game, to continue until one player wins a certain
number of rounds, but the game is interrupted before either player reaches the winning number.
How should the stakes be divided equitably, based on the number of rounds each player has won [3,
p. 431, 451ff]? The solution requires the combinatorial properties inherent in the numbers in the
Arithmetical Triangle, as Pascal demonstrated in his treatise, since they count the number of ways
various occurrences can combine to produce a given result. The Arithmetical Triangle overflows
with fascinating patterns and applications, and we will see several of these in reading his treatise.
We will study parts of Pascals explanation of the connections between the numbers in his triangle
and combination numbers. The reader is encouraged to read his entire treatise to see its many
other aspects and connections.
From Pascals treatise we will also learn the principle of mathematical induction. Pascal explains this in the specific context of proofs about the numbers in the triangle. The basic idea of
mathematical induction had occurred in the mathematics of the Islamic world during the Middle
Ages, and in southern Europe in the fourteenth century [3], but Pascals was perhaps the first text
to make a complete explicit statement and justification of this extremely powerful method of proof
in modern mathematics. Mathematical induction is an astonishingly clever technique that allows
us to prove claims about infinitely many interlinked phenomena all at once, even when proving
just a single one of them in isolation would be very difficult! It will be a challenging technique to
master, but will provide tremendous power for future mathematical work.
Learning about the connections of the Arithmetical Triangle to the binomial theorem in algebra will also allow an application to proving a famous and extremely important theorem on prime
numbers discovered by Pascals correspondent Pierre de Fermat (16011665) of Toulouse, on congruence remainders and prime numbers. This prepares one to understand the RSA cryptosystem,
which today is at the heart of securing electronic transactions. Well see how all these things are
interconnected, and along the way well also acquire important mathematical tools, like notations
for general indexing, summations, and products, and learn how to work with recurrence relations.
In the same way I connect the two points of the second section by another line, making a
second triangle of which it is the base.
@G
1
1
1
1
1
1
@
1
@
@
S
N
R
1
2
3
4
5
6
@
2
@
A
B @C
1
3
6
10
15
21
@
3
@
Y
D
E
F @
1
4
10
20
35
56
@
4
@
H
M
K
@
1
5
15
35
70
126
@
5
@
P
21
56
28
84
36
7
T
8
9
10
7 L
10
28
36
84
126
And in this way connecting all the points of section with the same exponent, I construct as
many triangles and bases as there are exponents.
Through each of the points of section and parallel to the sides I draw lines whose intersections
make little squares which I call cells.
Cells between two parallels drawn from left to right are called cells of the same parallel row,
as, for example, cells G, , , etc., or , , , etc.
Those between two lines are drawn from top to bottom are called cells of the same perpendicular row, as, for example, cells G, , A, D, etc., or , , B, etc.
Those cut diagonally by the same base are called cells of the same base, as, for example,
D, B, , , or A, , .
Cells of the same base equidistant from its extremities are called reciprocals, as, for example,
E, R and B, , because the parallel exponent of one is the same as the perpendicular
exponent of the other, as is apparent in the above example, where E is in the second
perpendicular row and in the fourth parallel row and its reciprocal, R, is in the second
parallel row and in the fourth perpendicular row, reciprocally. It is very easy to demonstrate
that cells with exponents reciprocally the same are in the same base and are equidistant
from its extremities.
3
It is also very easy to demonstrate that the perpendicular exponent of any cell when added
to is parallel exponent exceeds by unity the exponent of its base.
For example, cell F is in the third perpendicular row and in the fourth parallel row and in
the sixth base, and the exponents of rows 3 and 4, added together, exceed by unity the
exponent of base 6, a property which follows from the fact that the two sides of the triangle
have the same number of parts; but this is understood rather than demonstrated.
Of the same kind is the observation that each base has one more cell than the preceding
base, and that each has as many cells as its exponent has units; thus the second base, ,
has two cells, the third, A, has three, etc.
Now the numbers assigned to each cell are found by the following method:
The number of the first cell, which is at the right angle, is arbitrary; but that number having
been assigned, all the rest are determined, and for this reason it is called the generator of
the triangle. Each of the others is specified by a single rule as follows:
The number of each cell is equal to the sum of the numbers of the perpendicular and parallel
cells immediately preceding. Thus cell F, that is, the number of cell F, equals the sum of
cell C and cell E, and similarly with the rest.
Whence several consequences are drawn. The most important follow, wherein I consider
triangles generated by unity, but what is said of them will hold for all others.
First Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle all the cells of the first parallel row and of the first perpendicular
row are the same as the generating cell.
For by definition each cell of the triangle is equal to the sum of the immediately preceding
perpendicular and parallel cells. But the cells of the first parallel row have no preceding
perpendicular cells, and those of the first perpendicular row have no preceding parallel cells;
therefore they are all equal to each other and consequently to the generating number.
Thus = G + 0,
A = + 0,
= G + 0,
that is, = G,
that is, ,
= + 0,
Second Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell is equal to the sum of all the cells of the preceding
parallel row from its own perpendicular row to the first, inclusive.
Let any cell, , be taken. I say that it is equal to R + + + , which are the cells of the
next higher parallel row from the perpendicular row of to the first perpendicular row.
This is evident if we simply consider a cell as the sum of its component cells.
For equals R + C
| {z }
+B
| {z }
+A
| {z }
,
for A and are equal to each other by the preceding consequence.
Therefore = R + + + .
Third Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell is equal to the sum of all the cells of the preceding
perpendicular row from its own parallel row to the first, inclusive.
Let any cell, C, be taken. I say that it is equal to B + + , which are the cells of the
preceding perpendicular row from the parallel row of cell C to the first parallel row.
This is also apparent, as above, simply by the interpretation of cells.
For C = B +
| {z }
+
|{z}
,
for = by the first consequence.
Therefore C = B + + .
Fourth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell exceeds by unity the sum of all the cells within its
parallel and perpendicular rows, exclusive.
Let any cell, , be taken. I say that G = R + + + + + + + G, which are all
the numbers between row CBA and row S exclusive.
This is also apparent by interpretation.
For = + R +
| {z }
++C
| {z }
++B
| {z }
G++A
| {z }
G.
Therefore = + R + + + + + G + + G.
N.B. I have written in the enunciation each cell exceeds by unity because the generator is
unity. If it were some other number, the enunciation should read: each cell exceeds by the
generating number.
(a) Let us use the notation Ti,j to denote what Pascal calls the number assigned to the cell
in parallel row i (which we today call just row i) and perpendicular row j (which we
today call column j). We call the i and j by the name indices (plural of index ) in our
notation. Using this notation, explain exactly what Pascals rule is for determining all
the numbers in all the cells. Be sure to give full details. This should include explaining
for exactly which values of the indices he defines the numbers.
(b) In terms of our notation Ti,j , explain his terms exponent, base, reciprocal, parallel row,
perpendicular row, and generator.
(c) Rewrite Pascals first two Consequences entirely in the Ti,j notation.
(d) Rewrite his proofs of these word for word in our notation also.
(e) Do you find his proofs entirely satisfactory? Explain why or why not.
(f) Improve on his proofs using our notation. In other words, make them apply for arbitrary
prescribed situations, not just the particular examples he lays out.
2. Modern mathematical notation
Read in a modern textbook about index, summation, and product notations, and recurrence
relations. Do some exercises.
Fifth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle each cell is equal to its reciprocal.
For in the second base, , it is evident that the two reciprocal cells, , , are equal to each
other and to G.
In the third base, A, , , it is also obvious that the reciprocals, , A, are equal to each
other and to G.
In the fourth base it is obvious that the extremes, D, , are again equal to each other and
to G.
And those between, B, , are obviously equal since B = A + and = + . But
+ = A + by what has just been shown. Therefore, etc.
Similarly it can be shown for all the other bases that reciprocals are equal, because the
extremes are always equal to G and the rest can always be considered as the sum of cells
in the preceding base which are themselves reciprocals.
(b) Prove Pascals First Consequence by mathematical induction. (Hint: for a proof by
mathematical induction, always first state very clearly exactly what the n-th mathematical statement P (n) says. Then state and prove the base step. Then state the inductive
step very clearly before you prove it.)
(c) Write the general form of Pascals Second Consequence, and give a general proof using
summation notation, but following his approach.
(d) Now prove the Second Consequence by mathematical induction, i.e., a different proof.
(e) Optional: More patterns.
i. Write the Fourth Consequence using summation notation. Hint: You can write it
using a sum of sums. Try writing Pascals proof in full generality, using summation
notation to help. If you dont complete it his way, explain why it is difficult.
ii. Prove the Fourth Consequence by mathematical induction.
Seventh Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle the sum of the cells of each base is double that of the preceding
base.
Let any base, DB, be taken. I say that the sum of its cells is double the sum of the cells
of the preceding base, A.
For the extremes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
D,
|{z}
are equal to the extremes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . A,
and each of the rest . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . B,
|{z}
is equal to two cells of the other base . . . A + ,
,
|{z}
,
,
|{z}
+ .
Therefore D + + B + = 2A + 2 + 2.
The same thing is demonstrated in the same way of all other bases.
Eighth Consequence
In every arithmetical triangle the sum of the cells of each base is a number of the double
progression beginning with unity whose exponent is the same as that of the base.
For the first base is unity.
The second is double the first; therefore it is 2.
The third is double the second; therefore it is 4.
And so on to infinity.
N.B. If the generator were not unity but some other number, such as 3, the same thing would
be true. But we should have to take not the numbers of the double progression beginning
with unity, that is, 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, etc., but those of the double progression beginning with
the generator 3, that is, 3, 6, 12, 24, 48, etc.
3
because there are three
cells from C to the top,
namely C, R, .
Although this proposition has an infinity of cases, I shall demonstrate it very briefly by
supposing two lemmas:
The first, which is self-evident, that this proportion is found in the second base, for it is
perfectly obvious that : :: 1 : 1;
The second, that if this proportion is found in any base, it will necessarily be found in the
following base.
Whence it is apparent that it is necessarily in all the bases. For it is in the second base
by the first lemma; therefore by the second lemma it is in the third base, therefore in the
fourth, and to infinity.
It is only necessary therefore to demonstrate the second lemma as follows: If this proportion
is found in any base, as, for example, in the fourth, D, that is, if D : B :: 1 : 3, and
B : :: 2 : 2, and : :: 3 : 1, etc., I say the same proportion will be found in the following
base, H, and that, for example, E : C :: 2 : 3.
For D : B :: 1 : 3, by hypothesis.
+ 3} : 3
Therefore D
+ B} : B :: |1 {z
| {z
E : B :: 4 : 3
Similarly B : :: 2 : 2, by hypothesis
Therefore B
+ } : B :: |2 {z
+ 2} : 2
| {z
C : B :: 4 : 2
But
B : E :: 3 : 4
Therefore, by compounding the ratios, C : E :: 3 : 2.
8
q.e.d.
The proof is the same for all other bases, since it requires only that the proportion be found
in the preceding base,and that each cell be equal to the cell before it together with the cell
above it, which is everywhere the case.
Now Pascal is ready to describe a formula for an arbitrary number in the triangle.
Problem
Given the perpendicular and parallel exponents of a cell, to find its number without making
use of the arithmetical triangle.
Let it be proposed, for example, to find the number of cell of the fifth perpendicular and
of the third parallel row.
All the numbers which precede the perpendicular exponent, 5, having been taken, namely 1,
2, 3, 4, let there be taken the same number of natural numbers, beginning with the parallel
exponent, 3, namely 3, 4, 5, 6.
Let the first numbers be multiplied together and let the product be 24. Let the second
numbers be multiplied together and let the product be 360, which, divided by the first
product, 24, gives as quotient 15, which is the number sought.
For is to the first cell of its base, V, in the ratio compounded of all the ratios of the cells
between, that is to say, : V
in the ratio compounded of
or by the twelfth consequence
: ,
3:4
: K,
4:3
K : Q,
5:2
Q:V
6:1
Therefore : V :: 3 4 5 6 : 4 3 2 1.
But V is unity; therefore is the quotient of the division of the product of 3 4 5 6 by
the product of 4 3 2 1.
N.B. If the generator were not unity, we should have had to multiply the quotient by the
generator.
(b) Look at the reason Pascal indicates for his formula for a cell, and use it to make a general
proof for your formula above for an arbitrary Ti,j . You may try to make your proof just
like Pascal is indicating, or you may prove it by mathematical induction.
in
in
in
in
4
4
4
4
can
can
can
can
be
be
be
be
combined
combined
combined
combined
10
4
6
4
1
times.
times.
times.
time.
Or:
the
the
the
the
number
number
number
number
of
of
of
of
combinations
combinations
combinations
combinations
of
of
of
of
1
2
3
4
in
in
in
in
4
4
4
4
is
is
is
is
4.
6.
4.
1.
But the sum of all the combinations in general that can be made in 4 is 15, because the
number of combinations of 1 in 4, of 2 in 4, of 3 in 4, of 4 in 4, when joined together, is 15.
After this explanation I shall give the following consequences in the form of lemmas:
Lemma 1.
There are no combinations of a number in a smaller number; for example, 4 cannot be
combined in 2.
...
Proposition 2
The number of any cell is equal to the number of combinations of a number less by unity
than its parallel exponent in a number less by unity than the exponent of its base.
Let any cell be taken, say F in the fourth parallel row and in the sixth base. I say that is is
equal to the number of combinations of 3 in 5, less by unity than 4 and 6, for it is equal to
the cells A + B + C. Therefore by the preceding proposition, etc.
11
(a) The modern symbol nr means the number of ways (combinations) of choosing r things
from amongst n things. Explain how this is related to what we have been learning about
the Arithmetical Triangle from reading
Pascal. In particular, explain how the numbers
n
Ti,j are related to the numbers r . Do this by writingan equation expressing Ti,j in
n
n
r notation, and also writing an equation expressing r in Ti,j notation. Now use the
formula we learned earlier, from Pascals solution to his Problem,2 to write a formula
for the combination number nr , and manipulate it to express it entirely in terms of
factorials.
(b) Now read in a modern textbook about the multiplication rule for counting possibilities,
about permutations, and about combinations. Explain how a combination is different
from a permutation.
(c) Read in a modern textbook about the algebra of combinations, Pascals recursion formula, and how the text presents Pascals Triangle. How is it different from Pascals
presentation?
Given the perpendicular and parallel exponents of a cell, to find its number without making use of the arithmetical
triangle.
12
Read and study the RSA cryptosystem and its applications to digital security, including how
it works, which follows from Fermats Theorem. Write up the details in your own words, with
some example calculations.
References
[1] Encyclopdia Britannica, Chicago, 1986.
[2] Gillispie, C. C., Holmes, F. L., (editors) Dictionary of Scientific Biography, Scribner, New
York, 1970.
13
[3] Katz, V., A History of Mathematics: An Introduction, Second Edition, Addison-Wesley, New
York, 1998.
[4] Laubenbacher, R., Pengelley, D., Mathematical Expeditions: Chronicles by the Explorers,
Springer Verlag, New York, 1999.
[5] Pascal, B., Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle, in Great Books of the Western World,
Mortimer Adler (editor), Encyclopdia Britannica, Inc., Chicago, 1991.
14