How Euler Did It: by Ed Sandifer
How Euler Did It: by Ed Sandifer
by Ed Sandifer
Foundations of Calculus
September 2006
As we begin a new academic year, many of us are introducing another generation of
students to the magic of calculus. As always, those of us who teach calculus are asking ourselves
again, What is the best way to begin calculus? More specifically, How do we start to teach
students what a derivative is? Some of us will start with slopes and others choose limits.
Among those who begin with limits, some will use epsilons and deltas and others will use a more
intuitive approach to the algebra of limits. A few might use non-standard analysis, as rigorously
presented in the wonderful book [K] by Jerome Kiesler. Newton began with fluxions, while
Leibniz used differentials and a differential triangle. Regular readers of this column, though,
know to ask How did Euler do it?
Almost as soon as it was invented (or, if you prefer, discovered) people began arguing
about its foundations. Leibniz looked for an algebraic basis for calculus, while Newton argued
in favor of geometric foundations. The controversy continued for more than a hundred years,
with key contributions from Berkeley and Lagrange, until most of the issues were finally
resolved in the time of Cauchy, Riemann and Weierstrass.
Euler published his differential calculus book, Institutiones calculi differentialis, [E212],
in 1755. The book has two parts. Euler describes the first part, nine chapters, 278 pages in the
original, as containing a complete explanation of this calculus. John Blanton translated this
part of the book into English in 2000, and most of the quotations used in this column are from
John Blantons edition. The second part of the book, 18 chapters, 602 pages, contains the use
of this calculus in finite analysis and in the doctrine of series. A translation of this part of the
book has not yet been published, though there are rumors that people are working on it.
When Euler sat down to write the Calculus differentialis, as it is commonly called, he had
to decide how to explain the foundations of calculus and the reasons calculus works. In his
preface he writes (in John Blantons translation, p. vii.):
With this notation in place, he is ready to describe the first, and higher differences of the
function. This is apparently the first time the symbol for this purpose. The image below, from
The Euler Archive, shows Eulers definition of the higher differences:
Next we get some of the elementary properties of higher differences, starting with their
values in terms of the values of y.
y = y II 2 y I + y
y I = y III 2 y II + y I
3 y = y III 3y II + 3 y I y.
and so on up to 5th differences. He follows these with rules for sums and products:
If y = p + q then y = p + q , and
If y = pq then y = p q + q p.
By the end of this 24-page chapter, Euler has taught us to find differences of sums,
products and radicals involving polynomials, sines, cosines, logarithms and radicals, as well as
inverse differences, finding a function that has a given first difference.
In Chapter 2 Euler uses differences to study what he calls series. We would call them
sequences. Probably his most interesting result in the chapter is the discrete Taylor series.
Consider a sequence a , a I ,a II , etc., with indices 1, 2, 3, 4, etc. Let the first, second, third, etc.
differences be b, c, d, etc. Then the general term of index x is given by
a+
1 2
1 2 3
Eulers chapter 3, On the Infinite and the Infinitely Small, he returns to the
philosophical underpinnings of calculus. The chapter is 30 pages long, and is mostly a
fascinating philosophy-laced essay on the nature of infinites and infinitesimals in the real world.
In the 18th century, real numbers were not the free-standing axiomatized objects they became late
in the 19th century (thanks to Dedekind and his cuts). The properties of the real numbers were
expected to reflect the properties of the real world they describe. Hence, the debate between
Newton and Leibniz about whether real world objects are infinitely and continuously divisible
(Newton), or composed of indivisible ultimate particles (that Leibniz called monads) was also a
dispute over the nature of the real numbers. That, in turn, became a dispute about the nature and
foundations of calculus. Though their public argument was mostly about who first discovered
calculus, each also believed that the others version of calculus was based on false foundations.
After careful consideration, Euler eventually sides mostly with Newton and accepts the
reality of the infinite and infinitely small. The difficult part of this is that, if dx is an infinitely
small quantity, then
Since the symbol stands for an infinitely large quantity, we
have the equation
a
= .
dx
The truth of this is clear also when we invert:
a
= dx = 0 .
So, Euler is stuck with the paradox that the quantity dx is, in some sense, both zero and
not zero. He cannot resolve this paradox, so he has to figure out a way to avoid it.
To do this, he begins to use his results on differences from the first two chapters. When
he takes a sequence with an infinitely small quantity dx as its difference, then considers second
differences, he is forced to conclude that a / dx 2 is a quantity infinitely greater than a / dx , and
similarly for higher differences. We have, therefore, an infinity of grades of infinity, of which
each is infinitely greater than its predecessor.
Essentially, he introduces some rules for the use of infinite and infinitesimal quantities,
roughly equivalent to our techniques for manipulating limits. A quantity like a / dx : A / dx ,
where a and A are finite quantities (i.e., neither infinite nor infinitesimal) should not be resolved
by first dividing by dx, for that leads to / . This cannot be evaluated because, as he noted
above, there are many different sizes of infinity, and this expression doesnt tell us which size we
have. Instead, the quantity a / dx : A / dx should first be reduced to a/A, a ratio of finite
quantities.
Euler tells us that also it is possible not only for the product of an infinitely large
quantity and an infinitely small quantity to produce a finite quantity, but also that a product of
this kind can also be either infinitely large or infinitely small.
The last part of chapter 3 deals with issues of convergence. It could be the basis of some
future column.
Now that Euler believes he has convinced us of the logical integrity of his foundations, he
returns to his calculations with series and differences. He reminds us that, given a variable x, a
quantity y that depends on x, and an increment x = , then y has a difference of the form
y = y I y = P + Q 2 + R 3 + S 4 + etc.
dy
= P . Note that
dx
Euler and his contemporaries did calculus with differentials, dy and dx, and not with derivatives,
dy
. Euler explains how the higher coefficients, Q, R, S, etc., are related to higher differences,
dx
and hes ready to go with the rules of calculus.
If y = ee , then
ex
dy = e e ee e x dx.
x
It is visually striking if you write it on a blackboard and use a longer string of es.
Euler is sometimes criticized by modern mathematicians for what seems like a reckless
use of infinite and infinitesimal numbers in his calculations, and for ignoring the foundations of
calculus. What he writes in the Calculus differentialis, though, makes it clear that he was very
aware of the issues involved, and that he tried hard to resolve them. In fact, he himself believed
that he had indeed put calculus on a solid philosophical foundation.
Two generations after Euler, though, the way we build the foundations of mathematics
changed, and a philosophical basis was no longer accepted. The age of Cauchy and Weierstrass
sought less geometric and more axiomatic foundations, and Eulers approach was discarded as
insufficiently rigorous.
In the 20th century, though, Abraham Robinson developed non-standard analysis, and
showed how Eulers techniques could be made rigorous. Jerome Keisler, [K] in turn, used
Robinsons constructions to write a modern calculus text. It took 220 years, but Eulers Calculus
differentialis was eventually shown to have rigorous foundations. Now, if we want to, we can do
the way Euler did it.
References:
[E212]
[K]
Euler, Leonhard, Insitutiones calculi differentialis cum ejus usu in analysi finitorum ac doctrina serierum,
St. Petersburg, 1755. Reprinted in Opera Omnia, Series I vol 10. English translation of chapters 1 to 9 by
John Blanton, Springer, New York, 2000. Original is available online through The Euler Archive at
EulerArchive.org.
Keisler, H. Jerome, Elementary Calculus, Prindle, Weber & Schmidt, Boston, 1976. The entire book is
available (Free! under a Creative Commons License) at www.math.wisc.edu/~keisler/calc.html.