The Imputation of Adams Sin by JM (Part1of3) PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 21
At a glance
Powered by AI
The passage discusses the principle of solidarity and its application to the relationship between Adam and posterity.

The principle of solidarity refers to corporate or group relationships that exist between individuals, such as between family members or citizens of a state. God deals with both individuals and groups based on these relationships.

The passage discusses views of the union as merely biological/genealogical or requiring an additional solidaric relationship. Realism posits a 'specific unity'.

THE IMPUTATION OF ADAM'S SIN

SECOND ARTICLE

JOHN MURRAY
III.

T H E UNION INVOLVED

HE principle of solidarity is embedded in the Scripture


and is exemplified in numerous ways. It is not necessary
to enumerate the instances in which the principle comes to
expression. It is a patent fact that in God's government of
men there are the institutions of the family, of the state, and
of the church in which solidaric or corporate relationships
obtain and are operative. This is simply to say that God's
relations to men and the relations of men to one another are
not exclusively individualistic; God deals with men in terms
of these corporate relationships and men must reckon with
their corporate relations and responsibilities.
There is also the institution of the individual, and to discount our individuality is to desecrate our responsible relations
to God and to men. The principle of solidarity can be exaggerated; it can become an obsession and lead to fatalistic
abuse (c/. Ezek. 18:2). All such exaggeration is evil. But it is
also evil to conceive of our relations to God and to men
atomistically so that we fail to appreciate the corporate
entities which to such a large extent condition our life and
responsibility. Solidarity works for good and for evil. It is
scarcely necessary to be reminded of the beneficent influences
which have emanated from its application in the realm of
grace. Redemption in its design, accomplishment, application, and consummation is fashioned in terms of this principle.
And in the realm of evil it is a fact of revelation and of observation that God visits "the iniquity of the fathers upon the
children unto the third and fourth generation of them that
hate" him(Exod. 20:5).
It is consonant with these facts of the biblical revelation and of our human experience that the principle of sol25

26

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

idarity should come to its broadest and most inclusive


expression in racial solidarity and we should not be surprised
to find in this case the prototypal solidarity. Racial solidarity
is the only possible construction of the various data which the
Scripture brings to our attention. Paul bears pointed witness
to this fact when he says that "in Adam all die" ( I Cor. IS :22).
And it is this same solidaric relationship that forms the background of his thought when he says, "The first man Adam
was made a living soul ; the last Adam was made a life-giving
Spirit" (I Cor. 15:45).
If we appreciate this fact of racial solidarity and therefore
the solidaric relationship which Adam sustains to posterity
and posterity to him, we shall be less reluctant, to say the
least, to entertain the proposition that the one trespass of
Adam can properly be construed as the sin of all.
The fact of solidarity does not, however, determine for us
the question of its nature. What is the nature of the union
that existed between Adam and posterity? On any biblically
oriented view of Adam, it will be granted that from Adam
proceeded by way of natural generation all the other members
of the human race, that Adam was the natural father of all
mankind. It might appear to be an adequate answer to our
question to say that the union between Adam and posterity
is biological and genealogical and that no more is required to
explain the facts. This is to say that Adam was the "natural
root" of all mankind. Levi was in the loins of his father
Abraham when the latter paid tithes to Melchizedek, and thus
it can be said that Levi paid tithes to Melchizedek (Heb. 7:9,
10). In like manner all were in the loins of Adam when he
sinned, and so it can be said that they sinned in him and fell
with him in his first transgression. It may not be alleged that
the fact of seminal relationship is irrelevant in this connection.
We may not presume to say that the solidarity of the race with
Adam, by reason of which all are involved in his sin, could
have been true if he had not been the father of all mankind.
Whatever additional principle of solidarity may be posited or
established it cannot be abstracted from the fact of biological
ancestry.
Exegetes and theologians have not been content to explain
the solidarity with Adam in terms simply of our lineage from

IMPUTATION

27

him. They have been constrained to posit some solidaric


relationship other than the genealogical as necessary to a
proper grounding of the involvement in Adam's sin, whether
this additional relationship is conceived of as coordinate with
the genealogical or as in itself the specific ground of the
imputation of Adam's first sin. There are two views of this
relationship that are worthy of serious consideration. And
perhaps they are the only views that can worthily claim
consideration. The one is that human nature was numerically
and specifically one in Adam and the other that Adam was
the appointed head and representative of the whole race.
1. The Realistic View
Perhaps the ablest exponent and defender of the view that
human nature was both numerically and specifically one in
Adam is William G. T. Shedd. "The doctrine of the specific
unity of Adam and his posterity", he says, "removes the great
difficulties connected with the imputation of Adam's sin to
his posterity, that arise from the injustice of punishing a
person for a sin in which he had no kind of participation."24
And in controverting the representative view he says: "To
impute Adam's first sin to his posterity merely, and only,
because Adam sinned as a representative in their room and
place, makes the imputation an arbitrary act of sovereignty,
not a righteous judicial act which carries in it an intrinsic
morality and justice".25
In brief, the position is that human nature in its unindividualized unity existed in its entirety in Adam, that, when
Adam sinned, not only did he sin but also the common nature
which existed in its unity in him, and that, since each person
who comes into the world is an individualization of this one
human nature, each person as an "individualized portion" of
that common nature is both culpable and punishable for the
sin committed by that unity.26 "This unity commits the first
*4 William G. T. Shedd: Dogmatic Theology (New York, 1889), Vol. II,
p. 30.
2
* Ibid., p. 36.
26
Cf. ibid., pp. 43 f.

28

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

sin. . . . This sin is imputed to the unity that committed it,


inheres in the unity, and is propagated out of the unity.
Consequently, all the particulars regarding sin that apply to
the unity or common nature apply equally and strictly to each
individualized portion of it. The individual Socrates was a
fractional part of the human nature that 'sinned in, and fell
with Adam in his first transgression'. . . . Consequently, the
commission, imputation, inherence, and propagation of original sin cleave indissolubly to the individualized part of the
common nature, as they did to the unindividualized whole
of it. The distribution and propagation of the nature make no
alteration in it, except in respect to forni."27
To much the same effect is the view of A. H. Strong. Calling
it the Augustinian theory, he says: "It holds that God imputes
the sin of Adam immediately to all his posterity, in virtue of
that organic unity of mankind by which the whole race at the
time of Adam's transgression existed, not individually, but
seminally, in him as its head. The total life of humanity was
then in Adam; the race as yet had its being only in him. Its
essence was not yet individualized; its forces were not yet
distributed ; the powers which now exist in separate men were
then unified and localized in Adam; Adam's will was yet the
will of the species. In Adam's free act, the will of the race
revolted from God and the nature of the race corrupted
itself. . . . Adam's sin is imputed to us immediately, therefore,
not as something foreign to us, but because it is ours we
and all other men having existed as one moral person or one
moral whole, in him, and, as the result of that transgression,
possessing a nature destitute of love to God and prone to
evil."28 "Adam was once the race; and when he fell, the race
fell. Shedd : 'We all existed in Adam in our elementary invisible substance. The Seyn of all was there, though the Daseyn
was not; the noumenon, though not the phenomenon was in
existence.' "29
3

? Ibid., pp. 43 f.
Augustus Hopkins Strong: Systematic Theology (Philadelphia, 1907),
Vol. II, pp. 619 f.
a
' Ibid., p. 621; cf. Samuel J. Baird: The Elohim Revealed in the Creation
and Redemption of Man (Philadelphia, 1860), pp. 305-334; Philip Schaff
in John Peter Lange: A Commentary on the Holy Scriptures (New York,
a8

IMPUTATION

29

It must be acknowledged that if this view were proven to be


correct it would adequately explain the two aspects from which
the one fact or event may be viewed, namely, that "one
sinned" and "all sinned". The question is whether the relevant
evidence supports this construction of the Adamic relation.
In dealing with this realistic position and the debate between
its proponents and the proponents of the representative view
of the relation between Adam and his posterity, it is necessary
to place in proper perspective what the crux of the debate is.
Sometimes the question is confused by failure to recognize
that the proponents of representation as over against realism
do not deny but rather maintain that Adam is the natural
head as well as the representative head of the race. That is
to say, they maintain that the race is seminally one in Adam
and that representative union is not to be abstracted from
seminal union. Francis Turretine, for example, is quite explicit
to this effect. For while holding that the foundation of the
imputation of Adam's sin is principally "moral and federal"
nevertheless he does not leave out of account the natural
headship arising from the unity of origin and the fact that all
are of one blood. God willed that Adam should be "the stock
and Head of the whole human race" and it is for that reason
that "all are said to be one man".30 What the proponents of
the representative headship of Adam insist upon is that the
natural or seminal union alone is not sufficient to explain the
imputation of Adam's sin to posterity. In this particular
respect they are at one with the proponents of realistic union,
for the latter also insist on the necessity of more than unity
of origin.
Furthermore, not only do the proponents of representation
hold to seminal union; they also insist on community of
nature. In other words, natural union is involved in natural
headship and hence they will say that human nature became
1915), The Epistle of Paul to the Romans, pp. 178 f. A. H. Strong's citation
of authorities (op. cit., p. 622) is quite unreliable. His appeal to various
theologians in support of the realist position is marked by the lack of
discrimination which will be shown later on. For example, an examination
of H. Martensen: Christian Dogmatics, pp. 173-183 or of C. A. Auberlen:
The Divine Revelation, pp. 175-180 will not disclose the realist position.
30
Institutio Theologiae Elencticae, Locus IX, Quaestio IX, XI, XII.

30

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

corrupt in Adam and that this human nature which became


corrupt in Adam is transmitted to posterity by natural generation. In respect of the term "human nature", then, the difference is not that the proponents of representation deny
community of nature nor do they deny that the human nature
which became corrupt in Adam is propagated to the members
of the race. The difference is simply that realism maintains
the existence in Adam of human nature as an entity that is
specifically and numerically one and at this the exponents of
representation demur.
Hence the crux of the question is not whether the representative view discounts seminal union or natural headship
or community of nature in that unity which exists between
Adam and posterity but simply and solely whether the necessary plus which both views posit is to be interpreted in terms
of an entity which existed in its totality in Adam and is
individualized in the members of the race or in terms of a
representation which was established by divine ordinationIt is on that restricted question that the debate must turn.
Other questions undoubtedly emerge in connection with this
restricted question but, relatively, they are subordinate and
peripheral. Confusion can be avoided only if the real crux is
appreciated and debated on the basis of the pertinent data.
When the distinguishing feature of realism is perceived to be
this concept of human nature as specifically and numerically
one in Adam, the appeal on the part of realists to theologians
of the past in support of this position is not by any means as
valid as it might appear to be. For example, A. H. Strong
says that "Calvin was essentially Augustinian and realistic"
and appeals, in support of this claim, to the Institutes, II,
i-iii.31 Calvin indeed says that all of Adam's posterity became
guilty on account of the fault (culpa) of one. He speaks of the
sin of the one as common.32 All are dead in Adam, he says,
and are therefore implicated in the ruin of his sin. And, if so,
he likewise maintains, all must be charged with the blame
31 Op. cit., p. 621; cf. also Shedd: op. cit., p. 44.
3a Institutio Christianae Religionis, II, i, 5: "Qua de re multa fuit illis
concertatio, quum a communi sensu nihil magis sit remotum quam ob
unius culpam fieri omnes reos, et ita pecca tum fieri commune."

IMPUTATION

31

(culpa) of iniquity, for there is no condemnation when there


is no blame (culpa).33 Adam plunged all his progeny into the
same miseries to which he himself became heir. If we give to
such expressions the fullest scope and interpret them as implying that the one sin of Adam is the sin of all, there is no proof
that Calvin conceived of the union existing between Adam and
posterity in realistic terms. Calvin, however, does not leave
us in doubt as to his understanding of the involvement of
posterity in the sin of Adam, or, in other words, how the sin of
Adam becomes the sin of all. Calvin was not unaware of the
objection urged against the doctrine that the sin of Adam
involved the race in ruin, namely, that posterity is charged
with the guilt of a sin which is the sin of another and not
their own personal transgression.34 But he did not meet this
objection by saying that the sin in question was not only the
sin of Adam but also of that human nature, specifically and
numerically one, which existed in its undivided totality in
Adam and belonged to each member of the race as well as to
Adam himself. He did not appeal to the participation of such
an entity in the first sin of Adam. And there need not be
doubt as to his positive answer to the question how we become
involved in the sin of Adam ; he does not weary of reiteration.
It is to the effect that we derive from Adam by natural generation and propagation a corrupt nature. The key concept is
that of hereditary depravity. Adam by his sin corrupted his
nature and we all from our birth are infected with that contagion.35 "We hear that the uncleanness of the parents is
transmitted to the children so that all without any exception
are defiled from their beginning. But we shall not find the
origin of this pollution unless we ascend to the first parent of
all, as to the fountain. Thus it is certain that Adam was not
only the progenitor of human nature but as it were the root,
33 Inst. II, i, 6: "Qui nos omnes in Adam mortuos esse pronuntiat, jam
simul aperte quoque testatur, peccati labe esse implcitos. eque enim ad
eos perveniret damnatio qui nulla iniquittis culpa attingerentur."
34 Idem: "Neque id suo unius vitio, quod nihil ad nos pertineat; sed
quoniam universum suum semen ea, in quam lapsus erat, vitiositate
infecit."
35 Ibid., II, i, 5: 'Omnes ergo qui ab impuro semine descendimus peccati
contagione nascimur infecti."

32

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

and therefore the human race was vitiated in his corruption."36


Adam "infected all his seed with that vitiosity into which he
had fallen".37 "Hence from a rotten root spring rotten branches
which transmit their rottenness to other twigs which spring
from them."38 The figure is obviously that of contagion
spreading from a corrupted source. And Calvin is even careful
to say that Adam's own personal corruption does not pertain
to us; it is simply that he infects us with the depravity into
which he had lapsed.39 Indubitably, therefore, according to
Calvin, the sin by which posterity is ruined is the depravity
which stems from the sin of Adam, the corrupted human
nature which is the consequence of Adam's apostasy and which
is communicated to and transfused into us by propagation.
And it is not without some significance that he appeals to
Augustine in support of his contention. "Therefore good men,
and above all others Augustine, have laboured on this point
to show that we are corrupted not by acquired wickedness but
that we bring innate depravity from our mother's womb."40
It is not our purpose now to maintain that Calvin has given
an adequate account of the relation of the race to the one sin
of Adam. Our interest now is merely to show that his emphasis
upon hereditary depravity, and the corruption of our nature
which emanates from the sin of Adam, is no proof that Calvin
held the realist conception of the Adamic union. The representative view of our relation to Adam maintains insistently all that Calvin propounds respecting the propagation of
hereditary depravity and does so in Calvinian terms.
Realists also appeal with confidence to Augustine as a
proponent of the realist position. It is not our interest or
intent to demonstrate that Augustine did not entertain realist
conceptions. It is necessary, however, to point out that the
statements of Augustine on this subject, quoted or cited by
the proponents of realism, are not conclusive in this connec3 Ibid., II, i, 6.
37 Idem.
3 8 Ibid., II, i, 7: "Proinde a radice putrefacta rami putridi prodierunt,
qui suam putredinem transmiserunt ad alios ex se nascentes surculos. , ,
39 Ibid., II, i, 6.
* Ibid., II, i, 5: " N o s non ascita nequitia corrumpi, sed ingenitam
vitiositatem ab utero matris afferre."

IMPUTATION

33

tion. Augustine does say that "all sinned, since all were that
one man". 4 1 And perhaps the following offers more apparent
support than any other to a realist interpretation of Augustine's
position. "For God, the author of natures, not of vices, created
man upright; but man, being of his own will corrupted, and
justly condemned, begat corrupted and condemned children.
For we all were in that one man, since we all were that one
man, who fell into sin by the woman who was made from him
before the sin. For not yet was the particular form created
and distributed to us, in which we as individuals were to live,
but already the seminal nature was there from which we were
to be propagated ; and this being vitiated by sin, and bound by
the chain of death, and justly condemned, man could not be
born of man in another condition. And thus, from the bad
use of free will, there arose the train of this calamity which
leads the human race by a combination of miseries from its
depraved origin, as from a corrupt root, to the destruction of
the second death, which has no end, those only being excepted
who are freed by the grace of God." 42 When, however, the
contexts of such quotations as these are examined it will be
observed that the paramount interest of Augustine, as of
Calvin, is to deny that it is by imitation that the one offence of
Adam is unto the condemnation of all and to prove that it is
by propagation that sin was transmitted from the first man to
other men.43 Referring to Paul he writes: " 'By one man', he
says, 'sin entered into the world, and death by sin.' This
speaks of propagation, not of imitation: for if it were by
44
imitation, he would have said, 'by the devil'." "As there
fore, He, in whom all are made alive, besides offering himself
as an example of righteousness to those who imitate Him,
gives also to those who believe on Him the hidden grace of
His Spirit, which He secretly infuses even into infants; so
likewise he, in whom all die, besides being an example for
De Peccatorum Mentis et Remissione, I, , 11: "in quo omnes peccaverunt; quando omnes ille unus homo fuerunt"; cf. ibid., Ill, vii, 14.
4 2 De Civitate Dei, XIII, xiv; cf. ibid., XIII, iii. With slight variation
the translation is that of Marcus Dods in A Select Library of the Nicene
and Post-Nicene Fathers (Buffalo, 1887).
43 Cf. De Pec. Mer. et Rem., I, ix, 9.
44 Ibid., I, ix, 10.

34

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

imitation to those who wilfully transgress the commandment


of the Lord, depraved also in his own person all who come of
his stock by the hidden corruption of his own carnal concupiscence. It is entirely on this account, and for no other
reason, that the apostle says: 'By one man sin entered into
the world, and death by sin, and so passed upon all men; in
which all have sinned.' "45
Consequently, although Augustine says that all of Adam's
posterity were that one man, that the whole human race was
in the first man,46 and that all sinned in Adam when as yet
they were that one man,47 nevertheless when he defines more
specifically the sin by which all sinned in Adam and through
which death passed to all he does so in terms of original sin
or hereditary depravity passed on from Adam to his seed by
propagation. The reason why posterity is said to have sinned
in Adam is that the "seminal nature",48 from which all were
to be propagated, had been defiled in Adam when as yet it
existed only in him. And so, when Augustine exegetes Romans
5:12 and particularly "in whom all sinned", his most defining
concept is that Adam "depraved . . . in himself by the hidden
corruption of his carnal concupiscence all who come of his
stock"49 and that this defilement is propagated by natural
generation.
When this is recognized it is not so apparent that Augustine's thought follows the realist pattern. In the last
analysis he falls back on the notion of original sin as prop4s Idem, a s translated in A Select Library of the Nicene and Post-Nicene
Fathers ( N e w York, 1887).
4 6 De Civ. Dei, X I I I , iii: "In primo igitur homine per feminam in progeniem transiturum universum genus humanum fuit, quando illa conjugum
copula divinam sententiam suae damnationis excepit."
47 De Pec. Mer. et Rem., I l l , vii, 14: "Unde nee illud liquide dici potest,
quod peccatum Adae etiam non peccantibus nocuit, cum Scriptura dicat,
in quo omnes peccaverunt. N e e sic dicuntur ista aliena peccata, tanquam
omnino a d prvulos non pertineant: siquidem in A d a m omnes tunc peccaverunt, quando in ejus natura illa insita v i q u a eos gignere poterat,
adhuc omnes ille unus fuerunt: sed dicuntur aliena, quia nondum ipsi
agebant vitas proprias, sed quidquid erat in futura propagine, vita unius
hominis continebat."
48 Cf. De Civ. Dei, X I I I , xiv.
49 De Pec. Mer. e t Rem., I, ix, 10.

IMPUTATION

35

agated. And we must bear in mind that the concept of human


nature as defiled in Adam and transmitted to posterity by
propagation is not the monopoly of the realist. The proponent
of representation holds as tenaciously to that doctrine as does
the realist. While it is granted that some of Augustine's
expressions could readily fall into the realist construction of
the Adamic union, there is no clear-cut or conclusive evidence
in these quotations that he conceived of the rationale of our
involvement in Adam's sin as consisting in the participation
of human nature, as specifically and numerically one, in the
sin of Adam. He conceived indeed of human nature as having
become depraved in Adam and as communicated to us. But
these two are not identical and to fail to distinguish them
leads only to confusion and to misapprehension of the status
quaestionis.
If the distinguishing feature of realism has been brought
into focus and if the question at issue has been placed in
proper perspective, we may now address ourselves to the
examination of realism as it applies to our topic. It may be
repeated that if realism were shown to be correct it would
provide an adequate explanation of the two ways in which
the one event may be viewed, namely, that uone sinned" and
yet "all sinned". However, is there evidence to support this
construction of the relationship of the one to the many?
(i) W. G. T. Shedd maintains that it is unreasonable to
regard representative union of Adam and posterity as a proper
basis for the imputation of Adam's sin, because such imputation would be "an arbitrary act of sovereignty". But, we are
compelled to ask, does the notion of human nature, specifically and numerically one, human nature as an "elementary
invisible substance", in any way relieve the difficulty entailed?
For the real question is how the individual members of the
race can bear the guilt of a sin in which they did not, as
individuals, personally and voluntarily participate. And the
realist has to admit that the individual members of the race
did not personally and individually participate in the sin of
this human nature as it existed in its unity in Adam. The
sin of generic humanity is just as far removed from the
individual sin of the members of posterity as is the sin of a
representative head and that for the simple reason that as

36

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

individuals posterity did not yet exist. In other words, it is as


difficult to establish the nexus between the sin of generic
humanity and the members of the race as it is to establish the
nexus between the sin of Adam as representative head and
the members of the race. After all, generic humanity as it
existed in Adam is impersonal unindividualized human nature,
(ii) The analogy instituted in Romans 5:12-19 (cf. I Cor.
15:22) presents a formidable objection to the realist construction. It is admitted by the realist that there is no "realistic"
union between Christ and the justified. That is to say, there
is no human nature, specifically and numerically one, existing
in its unity in Christ, which is individualized in those who are
the beneficiaries of Christ's righteousness. On realist premises,
therefore, a radical disparity must be posited between the
character of the union that exists between Adam and his
posterity, on the one hand, and the union that exists between
Christ and those who are his, on the other. In Romans 5:15-19
the differences between the reign of sin, condemnation, and
death and the reign of righteousness, justification, and life
are in the forefront; they are evident from the negations of
verses 15-17 and from the emphasis placed upon the superabundance that prevails in the provisions of grace. But there
is no hint of the kind of discrepancy that would obtain if the
distinction between the nature of the union in the two cases
were as radical as realism must suppose. This argument from
silence might carry little weight of itself. But the case is not
merely that there is no hint of this kind of difference; the
sustained parallelism militates against any such supposition.
Adam is the type of the one to come (vs. 14). Adam as the
one is parallel to Jesus Christ as the one (vs. 17). The one
trespass unto condemnation is parallel to the one righteousness
unto justification (vs. 18). The disobedience of the one is
parallel to the obedience of the one (vs. 19). This sustained
emphasis not only upon the one man Adam and the one man
Christ but also upon the one trespass and the one righteous
act points to a basic identity in respect of modus operandi.
But if, in the one case, we have a oneness that is focused in the
unity of the human nature, which realism posits, and, in the
other case, a oneness that is focused in the one man Jesus
Christ, where no such unity exists, it is difficult not to believe

IMPUTATION

37

that discrepancy enters at the very point where similitude


must be maintained. For, after all, on realist assumptions, it is
not our union with Adam that is the crucial consideration in
our involvement in his sin but our involvement in the sin of
that human nature which existed in Adam. And what the
parallelism of Romans 5:12-19 would indicate is that the one
sin of the one man Adam is analogous on the side of condemnation to the one righteousness of the one man Jesus
Christ on the side of justification. The kind of relationship
that obtains in the one case obtains in the other. And how
can this be if the kind of relationship is so different in respect
of the nature of the union subsisting?
It is not a valid objection to the foregoing argument drawn
from the parallelism in Romans 5:12-19 to say that, since
there is an incontestable distinction between the relation of
Adam to the race and the relation of Christ to his own, there
is no reason why the further distinction which realism posits
should be inconsistent with the parallelism of the passage
concerned. The distinction which cannot be questioned is
that Adam sustains a genetic relation to the whole race and
that all are seminally united with and derived from him.
This does not hold in the relation of Christ to his people.
But the reason why this consideration does not affect the
argument is that, in terms of the debate between the realist
and the representationist, it is not the fact of seminal, genetic
relationship that constitutes the specific ground of our involvement in the one sin of the one man Adam either for the realist
or for the exponent of representation. For the realist it is
realistic union; for the represen tationist it is representative
union. And in the matter of Romans 5:12-19 it is the question
of the ground upon which the one sin of Adam is unto the
condemnation of all and the one righteousness of Christ unto
the justification of all who are Christ's. Neither the realist
nor the representationist holds that the ground in the case
of Adam's sin is the fact that Adam is the natural progenitor
of the race. Both are concerned with the specific ground of the
imputation of Adam's sin, and, in respect of the parallel
drawn in Romans 5:12-19, the question is whether the specific
ground posited by the realist for this imputation is compatible
with the analogy which is instituted by the apostle between

38

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

the one sin of the one man unto condemnation and the one
righteousness of the one man Jesus Christ unto justification.
The specific character of the union which is the specific ground
of condemnation and justification is the question at issue.
(iii) When we ask the question as to the evidence provided
by Scripture for the existence in Adam of this "elementary
invisible substance" called human nature construed as specifically and numerically one, we are at a loss to find it. We are
truly one in Adam, in terms of Hebrews 7:9, 10 we were all in
the loins of Adam, he is the first parent of all mankind, and
seminally there is the unity of Adam and his posterity. Adam
was the first endowed with human nature and to all his offspring he has transmitted that human nature by natural
procreation. All of this is maintained by representationists as
well as by realists and finds support in Scripture. But the
additional postulate on the part of the realist, the postulate
indispensable to his distinctive position, is not one that can
plead the support of biblical evidence. And it is not a postulate
that is necessary to explain the facts brought to our attention
in the biblical revelation. The union that exists between
Adam and posterity is one that can be interpreted in terms
for which there is sufficient evidence in the data of revelation
available to us.
(iv) The argument of the realist to the effect that only the
doctrine of the specific unity of the race in Adam lays a proper
basis in justice for the imputation to posterity of the sin of
Adam and his contention that the imputation to posterity
of the sin of a vicarious representative violates the order of
justice50 do not take sufficient account of what is involved 4n
our solidaric or corporate relationships. Realists admit that
only in the case of Adam and posterity does their postulate of
specific unity hold true. And solidaric relationship, they must
likewise admit, exists in other institutions where the specific
unity exemplified in Adam is not present at all. But, if we
analyse the responsibilities entailed in these other solidaric
relationships and assess the same in scriptural terms, we shall
find that moral responsibility devolves upon the members of a
corporate entity by virtue of the actions of the representatives
* Cf. Shedd: op. cit., p. 36.

IMPUTATION

39

or the representative of that entity.51 Consequently the denial


of the imputation of vicarious sin runs counter to the way in
which the principle of solidarity operates in other spheres.
And it is not valid to insist that vicarious sin can be imputed
only when there is the voluntary engagement to undertake
such imputation.52 Corporate relationship exists by divine
institution and the corporate responsibilities exist and come to
effect apart altogether from voluntary engagement on the
part of the persons concerned to assume these responsibilities.
It is only because we fail to take account of the pervasiveness
of corporate responsibility and think too lightly of the implications of this responsibility that we might be ready to accede to
the argument that there cannot be the imputation to us of the
sin of a vicarious representative. As the principle applies to
Adam it is not difficult to see that imputation of sin on the
basis of Adam's representative capacity could operate with
unique and universal application. For this would be but the
extension to the whole race, in terms of its solidarity in Adam,
of a principle which is exemplified constantly in more restricted
corporate relationships.
2. The Representative View
In presenting and defending the representative view it is
necessary to relieve it of some misrepresentation on the part of
opponents and of certain extravagances on the part of proponents. With reference to the latter, as will be shown later in
this series of studies, the representative view is not bound up
with the assumption that posterity is involved only in the
poena of Adam's sin and not in the culpa. It is not to be
supposed that only realism can hold to the imputation of the
s1 It is purely gratuitous to say, as Shedd does, that "representative
union requires and supposes the consent of the individuals who are to be
represented" {ibid., p. 39). This is not the case in some of the solidaric
relationships which exist among men by divine constitution. In the state,
for example, it is a fallacy to suppose that the solidarity arises simply and
solely from the consent of the citizens or subjects. The state is a divine
ordinance and its sanctions and responsibilities do not emanate from
voluntary contract on the part of the members.
s* Cf. Shedd: ibid., p. 57.

40

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

culpa of Adam's transgression. Furthermore, the representative view is not to be loaded with the distinction between
reatus culpae and reatus poenae which the older Reformed
theologians rejected and which they characterized and criticized as papistical. With reference to misrepresentation or
at least misconception on the part of opponents, it may not
be unnecessary to repeat that the representative view does
not deny but rather affirms the natural headship of Adam, the
seminal union of Adam and posterity, that all derive from
Adam by natural generation a corrupt nature, and that therefore original sin is passed on by propagation. W. G. T. Shedd
says: "Since the idea of representation by Adam is incompatible with that of specific existence in Adam, the choice must
be made between representative union and natural union.
A combination of the two views is illogical.,,S3 It is true that
in terms of Shedd's definition of natural union as that of
specific existence in Adam there cannot be a combination of
the two ideas in the explanation of the imputation of Adam's
sin to posterity; to say the least, one idea makes superfluous
the other. And it is also true that the representative idea finds
in representation rather than in natural headship the specific
ground of the imputation of Adam's sin. In this respect there
is similarity to the realist distinction, because realists find in
the specific unity rather than in Adam's parenthood the
specific ground of the imputation of Adam's sin. But it is
quite illogical to maintain that on the representationist view
of Adam's natural headship there is any incompatibility
between natural headship and representative union. On the
representative construction natural headship and represent Ibid., p. 39; cf. pp. 37 f. It should be noted, however, that realists do
not refrain from speaking of Adam as the representative head of the human
race. Philip Schaff says: "Adam fell, not as an individual simply, but as
the real representative head of the human race" {op. cit., p. 179). And
A. H. Strong: "Only on this supposition of Natural Headship could God
justly constitute Adam our representative, or hold us responsible for the
depraved nature we have received from him" {op. cit., p. 623). This use
of the word "representative", however, is in their esteem based upon the
conception of the specific unity of the race in Adam and does not have
associated with it the distinguishing connotation attached to it by those
maintaining the representative view in distinction from and opposition
to the realist.

IMPUTATION

41

ative headship are correlative, and each aspect has its own
proper and specific function in the explanation of the status
and condition in which the members of the race find themselves
in consequence of their relation to Adam. Hence it must be
appreciated that emphasis upon the natural headship of Adam
and upon the seminal union of Adam and his posterity in
Reformed theologians is not to be interpreted as vacillation
between two incompatible ideas,54 nor is appeal to natural
headship and seminal relationship on the part of such theologians to be regarded as the espousal of the realist construction.55
When we come to the question of the evidence in support of
the representative view it is necessary to adduce in more
positive fashion considerations mentioned already in the
criticism of realism.
(i) The natural or seminal union between Adam and posterity is not in question; it is assumed. It might be argued that
this is all that is necessary and that Scripture does not clearly
establish any additional kind of union, that as Levi paid
tithes when he was in the loins of Abraham, so posterity sinned
in the loins of Adam.56 Why postulate more? Some plus,
however, appears to be demanded. It may not be questioned
that there is something severely unique and distinct about our
involvement in the sin of Adam. The sin is the one sin of
Adam. If the relationship to Adam were simply that of
seminal union, that of being in his loins, this would not provide
any explanation why the sin imputed is the first sin alone.
54 Cf. Shedd: op. cit., p. 36.
ss Cf. Shedd's interpretation of Calvin in this regard {ibid., p. 44).
s6 The Westminster Confession of Faith may appear to ground the
imputation of Adam's sin upon the seminal relationship in Chapter VI,
iii, when, referring to our first parents, it says: "They being the root of all
mankind, the guilt of this sin was imputed; and the same death in sin, and
corrupted nature, conveyed to all their posterity descending from them by
ordinary generation". The Larger Catechism, however, grounds the imputation of Adam's sin upon the covenant institution. "The covenant being
made with Adam as a publick person, not for himself only, but for his
posterity, all mankind descending from him by ordinary generation, sinned
in him, and fell with him in that first transgression" (Q. 22; cf. The Shorter
Catechism, Q. 16). How the difference is to be explained is another question
into which it is not necessary to enter now.

42

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

We were as much in his loins when he committed other sins


and these other sins would be just as applicable to us as his
first sin if the whole explanation of the imputation of his first
sin resides in the fact that we were in his loins. Hence some
additional factor is required to explain the restriction to the
one sin of Adam. In the light of the narrative in Genesis 2
and 3 we shall have to infer that the prohibition of the tree
of the knowledge of good and evil was associated with and
epitomised some special relationship that was constituted by
divine institution and by reason of which the trespass or
disobedience of Adam in this particular involved not only
Adam but all of his posterity by natural generation. In other
words, there was a special act of providence by which a special
relationship was constituted in terms of which we are to
interpret the implications for posterity of that one trespass of
Adam in partaking of the forbidden fruit.
(ii) In I Corinthians 15:22, 45-49 Paul provides us with
what is one of the most striking and significant rubrics in all
of Scripture. He comprehends God's dealings with men under
the twofold headship of the two Adams. There is none before
Adam; he is the first man. There is none between Adam and
Christ, for Christ is the second man. There is none after
Christ; he is the last Adam (vss. 45-47). Adam and Christ
sustain unique relations to men. And that history and destiny
are determined by these relationships is demonstrated by
verse 22: "As in Adam all die, even so in Christ all shall be
made alive". All who die die in Adam; all who are made alive
are made alive in Christ. In view of this comprehensive
philosophy of human history and destiny and in view of the
pivotal and determinative roles of the first and last Adam,
we must posit constitutive ordination on God's part to these
unique relationships. And since the analogy instituted between Adam and Christ is so conspicuous, it is surely necessary
to assume that the kind of relationship which Adam sustains
to men is after the pattern of the relationship which Christ
sustains to men. To put the case conversely, surely the kind
of relationship that Christ sustains to men is after the pattern
which Adam sustains to men (cf. Rom. 5:14). But if all that
we posit in the case of Adam is simply his natural headship or
parenthood, we do not have the kind of relationship that

IMPUTATION

43

would provide the pattern for the headship of Christ. Hence


the analogy would require some community of relationship
which the natural headship of Adam does not provide.
(iii) As noted already, Romans 5:12-19 furnishes more
evidence relevant to the question at issue than any other
passage. The fact that Adam is the type of the one to come
(vs. 14) and the sustained parallelism throughout the succeeding verses (vss. 15-19) imply some similarity of relationship.
And when we ask the question what this common principle is
there are three things to be said, (a) In the relation of Adam
to posterity we must posit more than natural headship, for
the simple reason that, as we found above, this kind of union
provides no analogy to the union that exists between Christ
and his people, (b) In the case of Christ and the justified we
know that the union is that of vicarious representation. In
the provisions of grace Christ has been ordained to act for
and in the place of those who are the beneficiaries of redemption. His righteousness becomes theirs unto their justification
and eternal life. This is a constitution that exists by divine
institution, and the whole process which negates the reign of
sin, condemnation, and death rests upon the union thereby
constituted, (c) The general thrust as well as the details of
the passage would indicate that a similar kind of relationship
exists in the reign of sin, condemnation, and death. The
passage is built upon the contrast between the reign of sin,
condemnation, and death, on the one hand, as proceeding
from the sin of Adam, and the reign of righteousness, justification, and life, on the other, as proceeding from the righteousness of Christ. We are compelled to recognize an identity of
modus operandi because Adam is the type of Christ. Why,
we may ask, should we seek for any other principle in terms of
which the reign of sin, condemnation, and death operates than
the principle which is exemplified in the reign of righteousness,
justification, and life? We cannot posit less. Why should we
posit more when there is no evidence to demand or support it?
We conclude, therefore, that more than natural headship is
necessary, that natural headship does not carry with it the
notion of "specific unity" in Adam, that the plus required to
explain the imputation of Adam's first sin and no other is
not shown by Scripture to be the kind of union which realism

44

WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

postulates, and that when we seek to discover the specific


character of the union which will ground the imputation of
Adam's first sin we find it to be that same kind of union as is
analogous to the union that exists between Christ and his
people and on the basis of which his righteousness is theirs
unto justification and eternal life. How we should denominate
this kind of union is a matter of terminology. If we call it
representative union or headship, this will suffice for identification purposes. Solidarity was constituted by divine institution
and the solidarity is of such a nature that the sin of Adam
devolves upon all naturally procreated posterity.
(to be continued)

^ s
Copyright and Use:
As an ATLAS user, you may print, download, or send articles for individual use
according to fair use as defined by U.S. and international copyright law and as
otherwise authorized under your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement.
No content may be copied or emailed to multiple sites or publicly posted without the
copyright holder(s)' express written permission. Any use, decompiling,
reproduction, or distribution of this journal in excess of fair use provisions may be a
violation of copyright law.
This journal is made available to you through the ATLAS collection with permission
from the copyright holder(s). The copyright holder for an entire issue of a journal
typically is the journal owner, who also may own the copyright in each article. However,
for certain articles, the author of the article may maintain the copyright in the article.
Please contact the copyright holder(s) to request permission to use an article or specific
work for any use not covered by the fair use provisions of the copyright laws or covered
by your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement. For information regarding the
copyright holder(s), please refer to the copyright information in the journal, if available,
or contact ATLA to request contact information for the copyright holder(s).
About ATLAS:
The ATLA Serials (ATLAS) collection contains electronic versions of previously
published religion and theology journals reproduced with permission. The ATLAS
collection is owned and managed by the American Theological Library Association
(ATLA) and received initial funding from Lilly Endowment Inc.
The design and final form of this electronic document is the property of the American
Theological Library Association.

You might also like