Understanding Existentialism
Understanding Existentialism
Understanding Existentialism
Source: The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Vol. 26, No. 2, SPECIAL ISSUE WITH THE
SOCIETY FOR PHENOMENOLOGY AND EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY (2012), pp. 247-267
Published by: Penn State University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/jspecphil.26.2.0247
Accessed: 02-05-2016 11:40 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
Journal of Speculative Philosophy
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
jsp
50
th
Existentialism
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
248
anniversary sessions
of Contemporary Philosophy (1932).4 Not only did it impress both Sartre and
Beauvoir, who referred to it several times in their writings, but it seemed
to have focused their attention and that of others seeking a new philosophy
to address the contingency of our concrete existence as opposed to what
Sartre called the digestive neo-Kantian idealism of their Sorbonne
professors. Not coincidentally, Wahls study discussed the philosophies
of Alfred North Whitehead, William James, and Gabriel Marcel. Of the
many candidates for the distinguishing feature of existentialist philosophy,
I would propose this pursuit of the concrete. Certainly, Sartres attraction
to Husserlian phenomenology was motivated by this concern. Recall
Beauvoirs story of his discovering Husserlian phenomenology upon
Raymond Arons assurance that it would enable him to make philosophy
out of his perception of the apricot cocktail glass before them. Whatever
one thinks of this tale, it is clear that the organization and exposition of
Being and Nothingness, as Joseph Catalano has pointed out, was geared to
rendering ontologically possible an existential psychoanalysis that in turn
would issue in the existential biographies of Baudelaire, Malarm, Genet,
and, above all, his multivolume study of Gustave Flaubert, The Family
Idiot. These are all attempts to grasp what Sartre would subsequently call
the singular universal, in effect, the concrete. In the same vein, Marcel
entitled one of the essays in his Creative Fidelity An Outline of a Concrete
Philosophy(1940).
Mention of Whitehead, James, and Marcel is not coincidental. The
migration of French and more broadly European existentialism to our
shores was eased by a Pragmatism that softened the Yankee suspicion of
abstractions and also fostered by process philosophy, with its critique of
the fallacy of misplaced concreteness and its openness to a more fluid
metaphysics. Im not saying that there was an easy exchange among pragmatists, process philosophers, and existentialists. Some of the problems
are exhibited in the fallout of John Wildes move from the Metaphysical
Society of America (MSA), which was not only neo-Aristotelian but processive under the direction of its founder and Wilds Yale colleague, Paul
Weiss. It would be interesting to know what their conversations, if any,
might have been while on the same campus. As someone who straddles
membership in both the MSA and the Society for Phenomenology and
Existential Philosophy (SPEP) to this day, I recall hearing that Wild, whose
work I respected under both descriptions, was especially harsh on his
former friends at the MSA once he left their company.
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
249
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
250
anniversary sessions
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
251
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
252
anniversary sessions
But one could survey the material in terms of the issues that
e xistentialist considerations brought to the table in its conversations with
other major philosophies of the day, especially Marxism in its various
guises. To be sure, there were closer fields for internecine warfare, with
personalists, pragmatists, and Thomists, for example, but the exchange
that received the most attention was the ongoing struggle with Marxism,
especially hard-line Soviet-style Communism that began in the streets and
cafs of Left Bank Paris in the mid-1940s and ended in the same locales in
1968. Irecall two graffiti from the events of 1968 that caught my attention
in this respect: All power to the imagination (a critique of the French
Communist Party, which, Sartre insisted to his Maoist friends, lacked imagination) and Structures dont take to the streets (a thinly veiled attack
on Althusserian Marxism). The issue was existential humanism. Curiously,
this is a matter that has returned in post-poststructuralist critiques of a
sclerotic existentialism on the part of many critics today, including
some members of SPEP. Let me focus on the Parisian frame of the debate
because much of it reverberated in American locales, especially during the
late 1960s and early 1970s.
In the immediate postwar years, the question was theoretical but
particularly strategic: how to win the minds of the youth coming of age in
the immediate postwar era. The French Communist Party survived the war
with a chiefly positive image thanks to the courage of many of its members
in the Resistance. The party saw existentialist philosophy as a warmed-over
bourgeois individualism that had little new or relevant to offer the next
generation. The existentialist response was stated in the Presentation
of Les temps modernes and broadcast, somewhat regrettably, in the lecture
advertised as Is Existentialism a Humanism? (1946). It was elaborated in
subsequent publications like What Is Literature? (1947) and given impressive ontological grounding in the Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960).
Raymond Aron said of this project, from which he distanced himself,
that it undertook the impossible task of uniting Kierkegaard and Marx. In a
sense, he was right. This was the enterprise to which Sartre was committed.
But Aron sold him short when it came to the social ontology of the Critique
of Dialectical Reason. So, too, did his erstwhile friend and colleague at Les
temps modernes, Merleau-Ponty, in his uncharacteristically harsh book The
Adventures of the Dialectic (1955). Could existentialism formulate a social
theory in response to its Marxist critics without abandoning what was most
properly its ownits abiding sense of individual moral responsibility?
Ihave argued elsewhere that Sartre could indeed, as he put it, reintroduce
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
253
man into Marxism, that is, pace Aron, unite Kierkegaard and Marx. His
key was exchanging consciousness for praxis, static descriptions for dialectical relations, and turning the whole on the ontological theory of the
mediating third party.5
Concomitant with this discussion was the primacy of free organic
praxis, the nature and force of what Althusser called structural causality
and the very notion of a meaning/direction (sens) to history. Again my
point in mentioning this controversy is that it was played out by various
authors and in different media on this side of the Atlantic. Ron Aronson,
Bill McBride, James Marsch, Bill Martin, Doug Kellner, Betsy Bowman,
Bob Stone, and Fredrick Jameson as well as my own Doktorvater, Robert
Cumming, are names that immediately come to mind. And the New
Left Review in addition to the above-mentioned publications devoted a
considerable amount of space to the issue over the years.
So much for existentialism then. How does it fare today? The
E still stands proud, if somewhat chastened, in the heading of SPEP.
Does it deserve more than historical honorable mention before retiring
(along with its adherents/supporters) to the golden shores of lotus-eaters,
nut-gatherers, and extinct volcanoes? Many of its themes are perennial
even if their specific spin has changed. The basic issues of the individual
and the social, of citizen and government, of biography and history, despite
their respective vestures, are still recognizable in the antiWall Street
movement, for instance.
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
254
anniversary sessions
and concrete. I am not going to pursue this tack because it invites, even
demands, ramification into contemporary issues of feminism, racism, neocolonialism, environmental study, globalization, and others that exceed the
scope of my talk but not the interests of the audience. I would reserve these
corollaries to the basic question of humanism and its supposedly unsalvageable, harm-producing connotationsan implicit attack on coffee-table
existentialismfor another time.
Rather, I wish to raise another philosophical topic of ancient interest that
has returned to challenge us in our very notion of what philosophy is and
should be doing today. I have in mind what has come to be called by Pierre
Hadot, Michel Foucault, and others Philosophy as a Way of Life.7 In his last
lectures at the Collge de France, Foucault, with explicit reference to Hadot,
distinguished the Socratic ideal of care of the self from the Platonic-Delphic
model of Know thyself, insisting that such self-knowledge grew increasingly abstract and antiseptic as philosophy became more professionalized
and beholden to the model of the natural sciences in its concept of its goal
and how it should pursue it. The Socratic ideal of self-care, on the other
hand, became increasingly separated from the professional philosophical
model and instead was assumed by spiritual directors, confessors, political
commissars, psychologists, and psychoanalysts. Though Hadot took issue
with Foucaults sharp distinction and separation of this contrast, he agreed
that ancient philosophy up to and including the Stoics and Epicureans was
less about information and more about personal formation.
Foucault implicitly, as I recall, and Hadot explicitly cite Kierkegaard,
Nietzsche, and the existentialists as philosophers who have retained
that formative view of their teaching. Foucault granted that the German
Romantics and Hegel combined the formative and informative dimensions
as well. It is this role of existentialist thought in various guises that I
propose as a hopeful beacon for its revival in the twenty-first century after
suffering eclipse by structuralist, poststructuralist, and possibly even
post-poststructuralist philosophies over the last decades. That said, you
can imagine the surprise and the renewed hope I felt when I received the
first official announcement for the next World Congress of Philosophy
scheduled for Athens in 2013. The officers of the International Federation
of Philosophical Societies that sponsors these gatherings selected as the
theme for the entire meeting Philosophy as Inquiry and Way of Life.
Suffice it to say in virtue of the foregoing that existentialism has indeed
survived. After all that has occurred in the philosophical world over the last
half century, fifty/fifty is not a bad split!
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
255
notes
1. Lucien Goldmann, The Hidden God, trans. Philip Thody (1955; New York:
Humanities Press, 1964).
2. Gergy Lukcs, Soul and Form, trans. Anna Bostock (1910; New York:
Columbia University Press, 2010).
3. It was in that discussion that the movement of existentialism was started
(Erich Fank, Erich Franks Work: An Appreciation by Ludwig Edelstein, in
Wissen, Wollen, Glauben [Zurich: Artemis Verlag, 1955], 419).
4. Jean Wahl, Vers le Concret. tudes dhistoire de la philosophie contemporaine
(1932; Paris: Vrin, 2004).
5. Thomas R. Flynn, Sartre and Marxist Existentialism: The Problem of Collective
Responsibility (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984).
6. Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism Is a Humanism, trans. Carol Macomber
(NewHaven: Yale University Press, 2007), 33.
7. Pierre Hadot, Philosophy as a Way of Life, trans. Michael Chase (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1995); and Michel Foucault, The Courage of Truth: Government of
Self andOthers II, trans. Graham Burchell (Houndmilles, England: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2011).
50
th
Existentialism
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
256
anniversary sessions
us to reflect on the fact that when John Wild left Harvard for Northwestern,
for what were to be just a few years before his subsequent move to Yale, and
organized the first Society for Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy
(SPEP) meeting in 1961 with the assistance of his younger protg, James
Edie, the span of time that had passed since those modern beginnings,
years before Wild himself first entered Harvard, was only slightly greater
than the subsequent fifty-year period that we are commemorating here.
In other words, the wisdom of the ancients that we are here attempting to
invoke is not very ancient, after all.
Wilds interest in existentialism or, as he would not have minded my
calling it, existential phenomenology had been stimulated by a postwar trip
to Europe, where he had first encountered the thought especially of Husserl
and Heidegger during a research leave in the mid-1930s. How much had
transpired during the intervening decade or so! Such massive destruction,
for example, of the major German cities, such as Munich, which at that
time and for some years to come still bore some of the scars of war. So it
was fitting that I began to write this essay while seated in a tranquil park in
Munich, looking up from my paper from time to time to stare at a chestnut
tree with massive roots. But I digressor perhaps I am becoming a bit
confused. I myself did not attend the two earliest SPEP meetings, though
I began to participate in SPEP immediately thereafter, but I first saw John
Wild even before SPEP had come into existence, when he delivered the
Presidential Address of the American Philosophical Associations Eastern
Division in December 1960. That meeting, the last of its kind to be held
on a university campus, took place at Yale, where I was a first-year graduate
student, having myself just spent my immediate postcollege year in Europe,
in France, with my principal scholarly focus having been existentialism,
specifically Sartrean existentialism.
By the time of his American Philosophical Association presidency,
John Wild had become a missionary, a zealot, for existentialism to a
degree that took him far beyond what one finds in his book. In the latter,
it is true, he already indicated his strong belief that the analytic trend in
philosophy, the increasing dominance of which at Harvard was to be his
main announced reason for leaving there, was rendering our discipline
increasingly irrelevant, whereas existentialism dealt with real-world issues.
But in The Challenge of Existentialism Wild still suggests that certain aspects
of metaphysical realism, the modernized version of the Western philosophia
perennis to which Wild had subscribed in earlier times, continued to have
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
257
some correctives to offer in areas in which the existentialists had had too
little to say. By the time of SPEPs founding, Wild was no longer given to
offering such conciliatory remarks.
Now, I have begun by focusing on John Wild and his book not so much
for their own sakes, and not even primarily because of the historical link
between Wild and the fiftieth anniversary of SPEP, but because I think
that his enthusiasm for existentialism had a solid basis when he first gave
it expression,2 and it still does now. Of course, existentialism is far from
being a single doctrine. For Wild, it was Kierkegaard, it was Jaspers, it was
Heidegger, it was Marcel, and it was Sartrehardly a homogeneous group!
It included, obviously, religious believers, nonbelievers, and nonbelieving
believers like Heidegger. In fact, what is it, if anything, that these disparate
thinkers have in common? And if we can find it, is this it still viable
today?
One way of approaching an answer to the first of these questions is to
consider the title of a book that was especially influential in beginning to
identify existentialism as a single movement, Jean Wahls Vers le Concret.
(Ihave always found it amusing, by the way, that John Wild and Jean Wahl
had such similar names. I do not know whether they ever met.) So much
of what passed for mainstream contemporary philosophy in prewar France,
with the single noteworthy exception of Bergsons philosophy, was irremediably lost in a world of pure abstraction. In Germany it was not quite so
bad, thanks in part to the influence of Husserl and other tendencies, but
still Heideggers taking leave of Husserl can be seen as in part a rejection
of Husserlian abstractness. In any case, the challenge of existentialism for
all of those usually labeled existentialists certainly involved this quest
for concreteness. A second point in common follows, in a way, from this
first: the focus on our responsibility while at the same time putting into
question and radically rethinking the meaning of ethics. One American
philosopher who saw this very wellan individual who is, with few publications to his credit and having died some years ago already, I believe
largely forgotten todaywas George Schrader. George, who was very active
in SPEP in its early years and played a significant role in bringing John
Wild to Yale, thus reinforcing Yales position as a major center for graduate studies in Continental European philosophy, edited a hefty textbook,
Existential Philosophers: From Kierkegaard to Merleau-Ponty, that was at the
time one of comparatively few in this area. The chapter in it on Sartre was
one of my earliest publications, and the chapter on Merleau-Ponty was
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
258
anniversary sessions
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
259
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
260
anniversary sessions
tradition but in many traditions, are unjustifiable. We have probably all had
occasion to affirm, at some time, that existentialism is of great importance
for ethics, but when challenged, so to speak, to define existentialist ethics,
to say what it is, we are likely to find the task elusive. The reason for this
is precisely because existentialism questions usual assumptions about the
ethical domain. It is radically unconventional, and, as I have already noted,
it throws human actors back on their own responsibility. In a society such
as ours in which, for many, profit maximization is the supreme value, the
existentialist attitude is one of appropriate ridicule of this.
The last of existentialisms contemporary challenges that I would
like to note here is the challenge to reconsider the relationship between
philosophy and the arts, particularly literature. Sartre and Beauvoir tended
to uphold a division between the two in theory while overcoming that same
division in practice. Heidegger, in his later work, increasingly valorized
poetry. At its best, existentialism deprofessionalizes, and it invites openness
and tolerance toward different visions of the world.
So there! To me, although the works that defined existentialism as a
movement must at this point be regarded as classicsas must SPEP and
some of us ourselvesexistentialism remains a living approach to the
world, the radical alternative to the values that they are trying, though
against considerable opposition right now, to impose on us; in fact, existentialism is a way of life. (I take this occasion to note that the theme of the next
World Congress of Philosophy, to be held in Athens in early August 2013,
is Philosophy as Inquiry and Way of Life.) And although I began writing
these brief remarks in Munich, I would have rather been in Philadelphia to
share them with a SPEP audienceas indeed, happily, I was.
notes
1. John Wild, The Challenge of Existentialism (1955; Westport, Conn.: Greenwood
Press, 1979).
2. I would like to call attention to Remembering John Wild, edited by Hwa
Yol Jung, special issue of the Continental Philosophy Review 44, no. 3 (August
2011), based on a panel held at the 2007 SPEP meetings in connection with the
publication of Wilds posthumous papers, which was made available in time for
the fiftieth anniversary meeting.
3. George Alfred Schrader Jr., Existential Philosophy: Resurgent H
umanism,
in Existential Philosophers: Kierkegaard to Merleau-Ponty, ed. George Alfred
Schrader Jr. (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), 144.
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
50
th
261
Existentialism
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
262
anniversary sessions
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
263
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
264
anniversary sessions
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
265
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
266
anniversary sessions
notes
I would like to express my appreciation to the Society for Phenomenology and
Existential Philosophy Executive Committee for inviting me to join the session
Existentialism: Then and Now, to Bryan Lueck for suggesting the theme of
existentialisms lineages, and to Sheryl Lauth at Southern Illinois University
Edwardsvilles Instructional Technology Services for converting the audiocassette
of the 1979 interview with Simone de Beauvoir to a digital format and showing
me how to prepare the PowerPoint slides that accompanied my presentation.
1. Quoted in Margaret A. Simons, Beauvoir and The Second Sex: Feminism,
Race, and the Origins of Existentialism (Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield,
1999), x.
2. See Edward Fullbrook, She Came to Stay and Being and Nothingness, Hypatia
14, no. 4 (Fall 1999): 5069; reprinted in The Philosophy of Simone de Beauvoir:
Critical Essays, ed. Margaret A. Simons (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
2006), 4264.
3. Simone de Beauvoir, Diary of a Philosophy Student, vol. 1: 192627, ed. B. Klaw,
S. Le Bon de Beauvoir, M. Simons, and M. Timmermann; trans. Barbara Klaw
(Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2006), 279.
4. For more on Baruzi and Husserl, see my Beauvoirs Early Philosophy:
192627, in Beauvoir, Diary of a Philosophy Student, 3940; and for Beauvoirs
wartime philosophy and her readings of Hegel, Heidegger, and Kierkegaard,
see my Introduction, in Simone de Beauvoir, Wartime Diary, ed. Margaret A.
Simons and Sylvie Le Bon de Beauvoir; trans. Anne Deing Cordero (Urbana:
University of Illinois Press, 2009), 135.
5. Beauvoir, Diary of a Philosophy Student, 5455, 66, 5860.
6. Simone de Beauvoir, When Things of the Spirit Come First. Five Early Tales,
trans. Patrick OBrian (New York: Pantheon, 1982), 55, 212.
7. Simone de Beauvoir, She Came to Stay, trans. Yvonne Moyse and Roger
Senhouse (New York: Norton, 1954), 1617, 26; my revised translation.
8. Ibid., 291, 295, 301.
9. Ibid., 4012.
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM
existentialism
267
This content downloaded from 210.212.199.162 on Mon, 02 May 2016 11:40:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
18/06/12 4:40 PM