FAO, 2004. Ethics Agricultural Intensification
FAO, 2004. Ethics Agricultural Intensification
FAO, 2004. Ethics Agricultural Intensification
Rome, 2004
Produced by the
Editorial Production and Design Group
Publishing Management Service
FAO
ISBN 92-5-105067-8
FAO 2004
Contents
iv
Foreword
1
Introduction
3
Agricultural intensification
6
An ethics framework
9
Conclusion
iv
Foreword
Jacques Diouf
FAO Director-General
FAO /19632/G.BIZZARRI
FAO/21028/R. FAIDUTTI
Introduction
concerning relationships among data has tended to push aside explicit attention to
underlying normative concerns or assumptions. The ethical dimension of such
questions can be obscured by implicit and unquestioned assumptions. Each of these
factors complicates the articulation, defence and critique of ethical issues.
It is therefore useful to undertake planning and analytical exercises in which ethical
questions are the primary focus. The goal here is to provide a basic conceptual
framework in ethics that will aid in the articulation and justification of norms for
intensification, although this framework will also be applicable in other areas. As
already stated, this paper does not endorse a particular set of answers to the ethical
questions that arise from intensification. Instead, conceptual tools that allow these
questions to be articulated and discussed are presented and examples are given for
illustrative purposes. A short discussion on intensification is followed by the
presentation of a general framework for organizing and considering ethical issues.
This framework is then used and developed in a series of discussions about the ethical
issues associated with agricultural intensification.
Applying fertilizer
to a maize crop
FAO/14519/ D. DEBERT
Agricultural
intensification
AGRICULTURAL INTENSIFICATION
commons and gleaning. Yet the growing surpluses allowed greater specialization,
provided capital and cheap labour for industrialization in Europe and drove the long,
violent European nineteenth century. They also resulted in much larger markets in
food to supply a burgeoning population, which produced many more goods and
services than at any time in previous history. However, the costs paid in human
suffering by three or four generations of impoverished families were considerable.
An understanding of the ethical issues involved in intensification can take both a
prospective and a retrospective outlook, and ethical standards for evaluating
intensification can take either a broad outlook on the general trend of events or a
specific focus on the particular responsibilities of key actors. There are three general
ethical questions to be posed. First, it is possible to ask whether intensification in a
given situation is good or bad, all things considered, without pointing to specific
decisions or activities undertaken by particular people or organizations. Second,
assuming that intensification is a good thing, how should the burdens and benefits of
intensification be distributed? Third, who is responsible for seeing that intensification
occurs and that it follows an ethically acceptable path? Beyond these questions, it will
be critical to deploy the resources of the natural and social sciences to identify the
impediments to intensification, as well as to identify factors that would make an
ethically justified form of intensification become ethically problematic, but that task will
not be attempted in the present paper.
An ethics
framework
FIGURE 1
Technology
Law and policy
Customs and norms
Conduct
Consequences
AN ETHICS FRAMEWORK
make up the opportunity set, the class of actions or behaviours that are effectively available
to any potential actor.
Eventually, the actor will select one possible course of action from the opportunity
set and will engage in conduct. Conduct indicates the behaviour performed, including
both physical motions and symbolic or meaningful behaviour. Conduct may be quite
complex, and it is not unusual to characterize a long series of acts or behaviours
performed over time as a single action. Because conduct is an active response to an
actors opportunity set, it is indicated by an arrow in Figure 1. Clearly, the significance
of behaviour and the interpretation of the relatedness of multiple acts depend heavily
on the broader social context. There may be room for differences of opinion about
what, exactly, constitutes conduct in a given instance. For the present purposes, conduct
is inclusive of all acts understood as components in an actors performance of an action.
One primary goal in offering this definition of conduct is to distinguish conduct from
the consequences of the agents behaviour, which can be understood to be the effects
of the action on the natural world, particularly on other people and associations,
represented by the oval in Figure 1. The term consequences here designates
especially changes in the health, wealth and well-being of affected parties (including
the person who acts) that are caused by the initial action. As with conduct, there may
be differences of opinion about what these consequences are, especially when
consequences are indirect or are remote in space and time. Notwithstanding these
possibilities for difference in interpretation, Figure 1 represents a very simple picture
of human action as conduct performed under constraints and producing consequences
or outcomes.
Three distinct ways in ethical principles can be developed to determine whether an
action is right, good and proper. First, it is possible to see the ethical validity or
correctness of an action as a function of its consequences. Increases in the health, wealth
and well-being of people are generally characterized as benefits, whereas adverse effects
on health, wealth and well-being are characterized as harms or costs. Right, good or
proper actions will tend to be seen as those that have achieved the best balance of benefit
and harm relative to other possibilities in the actors opportunity set. Second, it is
possible to see the ethical validity or correctness of an action in terms of its consistency
with an ideal set of constraints. These constraints may be articulated either as duties
that the actor must discharge, or as rights held by others, which the agent must respect.
Rights and duties are generally correlated, however, so that if one person has a right,
others have a duty to respect it, while having a duty means that others have a right to
expect that the duty will be discharged. Finally, it is possible to see the ethical validity
or correctness of an action in terms of conformity to certain types of conduct. Instances
or patterns of conduct that are ethically right, good and proper are virtues, while those
that are wrong, bad or improper are vices. This third pattern of ethical evaluation lends
itself particularly to expressions of ethical judgement that emphasize the character of
the actor, so that not only is the act virtuous, but also the person who reliably acts in
virtuous ways.
In summary, a simple analysis of human action indicates three patterns of argument
or discourse for articulating, stipulating or defining actions as right, good and proper.
Each pattern tends to place the focus or emphasis of ethical inquiry in a different place
and many philosophers have developed entire moral systems based entirely on one of
these three approaches. In many instances ethical disagreements arise from one partys
tendency to formulate a rationale for the evaluation of an action in language and concepts
that emphasizes one of the three patterns, while another party emphasizes one or both
of the other two. Nevertheless, it is possible for there to be significant differences in
approach even within each of the three broad patterns, and many of historys most
notable moralists have tended to develop accounts of ethical evaluation that involve
considerably detailed discussion of one framework. For simplicity, arguments that
interpret the ethics of an action as a function of benefits and harms (or costs) will be
called consequentialist. Arguments or claims that understand what is right, good and
proper as determined by rights or duties will be called rights-based and statements that
stress the conduct and character of the agent will be called virtue-based. It will prove
useful to discuss each general approach in slightly more detail while discussing the
main topic of intensification.
FIGURE 2
Technology
Law and policy
Rights and duties
Customs and norms
Virtues and vices
Conduct
Consequences
Intensification is
associated with
periods of human
population growth
FAO/19698/G. BIZZARRI
When is
intensification
ethically good?
A utilitarian
model
10
supplies, food scarcity causes hunger, disease and starvation. Using the framework
previously described, many individuals and groups consider options and undertake
conduct that has the outcome (consequence) of increased food supply. The benefits
associated with increased food availability provide the elemental argument for
intensification, and this argument is consequentialist in its moral logic. In the simple
case where new technology or farming methods allow a farmer or landowner to
produce more food, consequential reasoning shows why this is ethically a good thing.
As already stated, European agricultural intensification immediately prior to the
Industrial Revolution was accomplished not only by applying a package of new
production technologies to farming, but also by the Enclosure Acts, which
disestablished a system of rights and duties that permitted commoners to live on and
farm lands as long as their crops were shared according to an ancient formula. The
framework applies not only to the conduct of individual farmers and landowners, but
also to the political activity that led to this policy change. Was enclosure ethically
justifiable? The British philosopher John Locke (1632-1704) posited the following
argument to show that it was:
He that encloses land, and has a greater plenty of the conveniences of life from
ten acres, than he could have from an hundred left to nature, may truly be said to
give ninety acres to mankind; for his labour now supplies him with provisions out
of ten acres, which were but the product of an hundred lying in common.1
Here the disestablishment of the old system of commoner rights and duties is
portrayed as justified in light of the increased benefits (conveniences) accruing from
enclosure. Although this style of thinking is not typical of Locke, the passage implies
that any system of rights and privileges is justified, given the efficiency with which it
supplies human beings with provisions.
Efficiency is particularly important in the most common form of consequentialism,
utilitarianism. Utilitarians assume that the values associated with consequences can be
quantified to produce a ranking system for all possible courses of action (or options)
available to an agent. They also assume that the value of benefits and harms can be
added and subtracted. Such a ranking system produces a class of optima such that no
option in the opportunity set yields greater total value (although there may be more
J. Locke. 1690. Second treatise of Government. In C.B. McPherson, ed. 1980. Indianapolis, USA, Hackett Publishing.
Lockes philosophy is not consequentialist, but contractarian. He believed that people had a natural right to appropriate
goods (including land) found in nature, and that others had a duty to respect this property right, which was grounded both
in the nature of things and in the social contract forming the basis of civil society. It is thus likely that he understood the
phrase give ninety acres to mankind in an almost literal sense, and saw the justification of enclosure in terms of a kind
of expansion of the commons, rather than in starkly utilitarian terms. Nevertheless, it is difficult to interpret this particular
passage as anything more than a consequentialist moral argument.
than one option that is optimal). According to the utilitarian standard (e.g. the utilitarian
maxim), the right, best and proper action or policy must be a member of this class of
optima. This is popularly stated as: Act so as to produce the greatest good for the greatest
number of people. Thus, the most efficient approach to producing benefits or avoiding
harms is the course of action most thoroughly justified by ethics. Utilitarianism has been
an implicit ethical philosophy for agricultural science, which has sought to make two
blades of grass grow where one grew before.
One critical and often overlooked aspect of the utilitarian approach is the need for
a complete accounting of costs and benefits. The green revolution involved new seed
varieties that were more responsive to nitrogen fertilizers, which are, in most settings,
a purchased input. Hence, a simple utilitarian approach weighs the benefits of increased
yields against the costs of seeds and fertilizer. If benefits outweigh costs, the green
revolution is justified. Yet other shifts accompanied the new technology, and many
critiques of the green revolution can be articulated entirely within the framework of
a utilitarian/consequentialist ethic. Within the first decade of the green revolution of
the 1970s, which led to aggregate increases in rice production across Asia, large-scale
insect pest outbreaks and plant disease epidemics destabilized food production,
supplies and prices.
Only after three boom and bust cycles and pest outbreaks did governments begin
to move away from simplified, centralized pest control policies that relied on
insecticides and vertical host plant resistance towards decentralized integrated pest
management that built on local ecological processes to realize production potential.
With the concentration of farm animal processing facilities, the chances of large-scale
epizootics occurring (such as foot-and-mouth disease) increase exponentially because
of the more extensive movements of animals between pasturage, feedlots and abattoirs,
and contacts with animal offal and excrement. Feeding livestock with products derived
from their own species creates routes for infection by diseases associated with prions.2
Short-rotation forest plantations increase wood (especially pulpwood) production but
at the same time increase vulnerability to specialized pests and diseases. Fast-growing
dwarf coconut varieties increase short-term yields but are more frequently at risk from
diseases previously found in limited geographic areas. In fisheries and aquatic
production systems, exotic species are commonly introduced. These often initially
increase total production, but can unexpectedly change trophic relationships and
disrupt ecosystems, as did the Nile perch in Lake Victoria. Intensive salmon hatcheries
have been criticized for reducing the genetic adaptability of natural populations. These
problems testify to the need for completeness in thinking through the costs and benefits
of intensification.
2 Prion-associated
diseases include kuru, scrapie and bovine spongiform encephalopathy (BSE). The infection route and
aetiology of BSE and the variant of Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease that has been linked to BSE are still a matter of investigation.
11
12
When is
intensification
ethically good?
A rights-based
model
characterized as contractualist in light of the way that rights and duties are described
as being grounded in an implicit agreement (or social contract) among all members
of society. 3
While a Kantian might argue that enclosure treated commoners as a mere means
to a larger social goal, a contractualist might say that enclosure violated the social
contract. In either case, the problem with enclosure from a rights-based perspective
was that commoners had a right to use these lands. As such, any plan to exclude them
from the land could not be justified unless it included some provision for obtaining
their agreement. This would require involvement of the commoners at some stage of
the enclosure process, and their involvement would need to be such that each rights
holder had the opportunity to give or withhold their agreement voluntarily to the
plan. Perhaps they could be convinced that they would be better off, or perhaps they
would be enticed to accede to such use of the land in exchange for compensation.
These details might vary considerably on a case-by-case basis, but what is critical from
a rights-based perspective is that respect for the individuals affected by enclosure
requires that they be accorded a role in the intensification process that is fully consistent
with their rights. Either version of rights theory provides a starting-point for
questioning whether intensification is good simply because it produces more benefits
(in the form of greater food production) than costs (in the form of losses for the
minority).
Either approach to rights implies that the exclusion of commoners from decisionmaking is unacceptable, but a Kantian might in addition note that the effect of
enclosure was radically to impoverish commoners and their descendants. For a
Kantian, such conditions of poverty make it impossible for a person to exercise rational
free will; the circumstances of need are so great that people in dire poverty are
effectively coerced into enduring humiliation and deprivation. As such, key subsistence
rights, including the right to food, become minimal conditions that must be met if all
people are to be treated with the moral respect to which they are due. Thus, any
situation in which people are so poor that they cannot freely exercise their innately
human capacity to choose a life plan involves an ethical wrong. Methods of
intensification that place people in such circumstances cannot be endorsed from a
rights-based perspective.
3 Although similar in important respects, Kantian deontology and Hobbesian contractualism provide important different
rationales for justifying rights. In both versions of rights theory, the ethical significance of a right resides in the way that it
protects human freedom. For Kantians, an individuals freedom is an expression of the ability to plan and order ones own
thoughts and actions rationally, while for contractarians freedom means simply that others do not control or limit ones
action. In Kantian philosophies, preserving the entitlements owed under the system of rights is a form of showing respect
for anothers need to plan and order his or her own life, but rights can also be seen as being based on the social contract.
13
14
FAO/17259/L. WITHERS
Utilitarianism
and rights-based
ethics: further
issues
he basic tension between
utilitarian consequentialism,
on the one hand, and rightsbased ethics, on the other, underlies
Local scientists at a
many issues associated with agricultural intensification. For
training session on the
collection of
decades, researchers from developed countries have
germplasm in vitro
harvested germplasm from farmers and local markets in the
developing world. These researchers have used the
germplasm in breeding programmes to develop higher-yielding varieties as well as
searching for other valuable genetic traits. Many of those who collected seeds were
shocked when critics suggested that their work failed to respect the rights of people
from the developing world. From a utilitarian viewpoint, the increased yields of new
varieties more than justified the collection of germplasm, and researchers saw no
ethical issue in using seeds they had collected this way. However, critics asserted that
researchers had failed to show proper respect for the rights of indigenous farmers
whose forebears had saved seed for centuries. Purchasing seed in village markets,
critics affirm, gives the buyer an implied right to use the commodity good for food,
or possibly for replanting, but farmers could not be interpreted to have given up rights
to further development of their germplasm without a careful and explicit process to
inform them of its true value and to ensure that they had given consent. Some critics
argue that because of the collective and collaborative nature of seed development in
traditional agriculture, only someone who represents the collective interests of all
growers would be in a position to undertake such a negotiation.
Today, some opponents of genetically engineered crops argue that individual
consumers should not be forced to eat these crops against their will. Advocates of
genetically engineered crops see them as a safe and effective tool for increasing the
efficiency of farm production and believe that their opponents claims are an unjustified
barrier to adopting them. While this debate often involves factual disputes about the
safety of these crops, the underlying ethical structure of the debate pits the rightsbased claims of the opponents against the utilitarian reasoning of the advocates. Why?
Irrespective of the safety or risks associated with genetically modified (GM) crops,
opponents are claiming that the companies promoting these technologies have placed
food consumers in a position where they have no opportunity to reject them. Rather
than rebut the claim that consumer rights are at stake on its merits, advocates have
often argued that if the crops are safe (as they claim), then consumers have no basis
for rejecting them, since rejecting GM crops is an action with real costs but no real
benefit. Thus, opponents try to meet a rights claim with a utilitarian argument, and
the ethical issues fail to be enjoined.
A similar point of tension arises in debates over the green revolution technologies.
When higher yields are associated with purchased inputs, those with access to capital
will have an advantage over those without. One can interpret losses experienced by
poorer farmers as additional costs and weigh these, too, against benefits from higher
yields. The study New seeds for poor people by Michael Lipton and Richard Longhurst
(1989) is a particularly exhaustive and theoretically sophisticated attempt to assess
the green revolution varieties from a utilitarian standpoint. The authors conclude that,
over time, these technologies have been, on balance, beneficial to poor people.
However, these arguments do not necessarily address concerns that rights may have
been violated, or that cultural traditions may have been lost as a result of green
revolution strategies. How might rights be affected? It is possible to see any transition
from a situation in which people can feed themselves and meet their needs to one in
which they cannot as a violation of their rights. Even if such transitions have benefits
that outweigh the cost, they would not be seen as justified if there are even a few
individuals whose rights to subsistence are jeopardized as a result of the changes.
This is only a cursory introduction to the way that rights arguments should figure
in an overall evaluation of the green revolution. Yet one of the problems that has arisen
in debates over the retrospective impact of green revolution varieties is that those who
draw their ethical norms from utilitarian thinking seem to be ignoring ethical claims
that draw upon the language of rights. In doing this, people create an impression of,
at best, insensitivity to the full range of ethical concerns relevant to intensification
(which should also include virtues, discussed later) and, at worst, arrogant dismissal
of arguments that are inconvenient for the case they wish to present. When people
who hold influential positions for future attempts to meet food needs dismiss
alternative arguments in this way, they engage in a use of power that is itself ethically
questionable. As such, it would be valuable to launch retrospective studies that make
an explicit attempt to acknowledge the full range of concerns that have been or might
be brought to bear on evaluating green revolution intensification, in part as preparation
for more open and informed debates on the questions that must be addressed if world
food needs are to be met in the twenty-first century.
15
16
These cases are complex and deserve a more careful analysis than these summary
statements can provide. The point here is simply to note that, in both cases, a
utilitarian/consequentialist rationale is met with counterclaims that assert rights.
Someone assuming that utilitarian models are appropriate will respond to these
assertions with further arguments reciting the costs and benefits of alternative
arrangements, but to the extent that these rights are thought to be moral rights, rights
protecting the dignity of involved parties, recitation of further costs and benefits will
simply miss the point. What is being claimed is that there is a need to respect affected
parties by involving them fully and non-coercively in the process of intensification.
From the perspective of rights-based ethics no recitation of costs and benefits will
justify a failure to do this; what is needed is a justification that addresses how the
process of intensification influences the freedom of all persons affected by it. If freedom
is being constrained, it must be shown that this constraint is justified, perhaps because
it is required in order to show proper respect for the rights of less fortunate people,
or perhaps because the people agree to the constraint of their own free will.
17
When is
intensification
ethically good?
A virtue-based
model
18
to call attention to the norms, practices, traditions and institutions that are particularly
characteristic of and valued by a particular community, rather than particular virtues
and vices. Like Aristotle, contemporary communitarians emphasize the need to have
a social environment, a form of community life, that will give rise to exemplary conduct
and that will allow people to appreciate the ways of life that such forms exemplify.
Agricultural ways of life have figured prominently in some of the most influential
articulations of virtue and vice. The ancient Greeks themselves developed a form of
agriculture based upon rough terrain, varying soil types and a Mediterranean climate.
Their farms were a diverse mixture of grain production and pastoral livestock, but
with heavy reliance on tree and vine crops. The mix of crops and long growing season
provided steady work for fairly small households all year round, while the trees and
vines involved lifetime investments for smallholders. Military historian Victor Davis
Hanson argues that this pattern of agriculture gave rise to unique forms of military
organization and tactics as well as the political culture of the city-state. The relatively
large proportion of the population controlling property and the nature of their stake
in the land made them both fierce defenders of egalitarian political forms and equally
fierce warriors who could be relied upon for phalanx manoeuvres requiring discipline
and loyalty. These character traits, so critical to the success of Greek city-states as
political and military entities, were thought to emerge naturally in a farming
population of smallholders. In contrast, the large-scale plantation-style irrigated
agriculture common among the Greeks military rivals relied on stratified societies of
slaves and masters who did not develop the requisite virtues.
The idea that forms of agriculture were seminal sources for community practice
and national culture reached its culmination in the intellectual cultures of seventeenth
and eighteenth century Europe. These ideas were especially influential for those who
framed the United States Declaration of Independence and Constitution. In his Notes
on the State of Virginia (178184), Thomas Jefferson, third President of the United States
famously wrote:
Those who labor in the earth are the chosen people of God, if ever he had a
chosen people, whose breasts he has made his peculiar deposit for substantial
and genuine virtue. The mobs of great cities add just so much to the support
of pure government, as sores do to the strength of the human body.
Jeffersons key idea was that smallholding farmers would have a greater stake in
the stability and success of the new nation than either manufacturers or their labourers,
since both of the latter could pull up stakes and leave when difficulties arose. As
President, Jefferson went on to set a course for the development of the United States
as an agrarian nation, negotiating the Louisiana Purchase to ensure ample lands for
future generations of American farmers and authorizing the (Meriwether) Lewis and
(William) Clark expedition to determine the suitability of these lands for cultivation
and transport.
Jeffersons plan was not, of course, an episode of intensification, as his strategy
called for extensive expansion of American farming rather than a transformation
designed to increase yields or use resource inputs more efficiently. Nevertheless, his
view is important because it shows that ideas about how farming systems and methods
produce virtues such as citizenship and community solidarity have had a profound
influence on political developments in the past. Plans for intensification that
substantially alter the pattern of land tenure, or that change the basic practices of
farming thought to be critical to the formation of exemplary patterns of conduct or
community identity are almost certain to provoke moral protest. Indeed, the most
memorable protests against British attempts at enclosure are not tracts arguing that
rights have been violated, but literary efforts such as Oliver Goldsmiths poem, The
deserted village, lamenting the loss of small village cultures thought to be particularly
characteristic of the British national character:
Ill fares the land, to hast'ning ills a prey,
Where wealth accumulates, and men decay:
Princes and lords may flourish, or may fade;
A breath can make them, as a breath has made:
But a bold peasantry, their country's pride,
When once destroy'd, can never be supplied.4
The Old Order Amish communities established throughout Europe and now
dispersed around the globe provide another example of a philosophy of agriculture
that relies heavily on virtue ethics. The Amish emphasize a very high degree of family
and community integration together with independence from the outside world. They
derive meaning from their ability to live together at a particular place with a great
stability of practice over generations. Agriculture is important because Amish
communities see dependence on outsiders as a potential threat to their ties to one
another. The Amish are notoriously suspicious of modern technologies, largely because
they see their effects as weakening social relations among members of the local
community. Nevertheless, Amish farmers are known for both high yields and
ecologically sustainable farming methods. From an Amish perspective, intensification
would not emerge as an ethically important goal, and intensifying practices that
weakened community bonds either by tempting members away from the household
or by increasing dependence on the outside world would be resisted. However,
Oliver Goldsmith. 1770. The deserted village. Accessed online at: www.ucc.ie/celt/online/E750001-001/.
19
20
intensification would not be seen as an evil in itself, and increases in yields that could
be attained by more effective use of household labour might be deemed entirely
acceptable.
These few examples illustrate how thinking in terms of virtues provides an entirely
different point of view from which to evaluate intensification. From the perspective
of a virtue theorist, agricultures role in forming both personal and national character
provides the basis for evaluating policies and technologies that transform the food
system. Periods of intensification would be justified only if they reinforce this role and
would be opposed if they tended to weaken it. The actual forms that a virtue
perspective might take will be highly variable and will depend upon cultural traditions
and history. Thus, while utilitarian/consequentialist and rights-based approaches in
ethics point towards ethical standards that might be applied to virtually any
agricultural system, the specific content of a virtue approach is likely to be highly
dependent on local culture and may vary from one cultural setting to another.
21
22
Intensive livestock
farming provides food
for growing
populations but raises
food safety, equity and
animal welfare issues
How should
burdens and
benefits be
distributed?
distributive justice, difficulties also arise within the rights-based approach. In particular,
rights-based thinking is occasionally confronted with situations where rights seem to
conflict. For example, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights notes that all persons
have a right to food. If one encounters a situation in which the only way to secure this
right is to violate other rights, such as property rights, which rights have priority? As
23
24
in the case of establishing the validity of rights, resolving conflicts among rights will
require use of philosophical arguments that support rights-based views. Henry Shues
Basic rights argues that rights have an internal principle of order that can be used to
resolve conflict. Some rights (such as the right to education or to vote) would not be
meaningful unless more basic rights (such as the right to food and personal security)
were already secure. Shue argues that basic rights should be secured for all before less
basic rights are secured for a few. Shues approach does not rely on cost-benefit
thinking as a tie-breaker, yet few would resist combining principles from utilitarian/
consequentialist thinking with approaches from rights theory.6
Virtue-based approaches typically address distributive issues either through the
idea of community so that community solidarity comes into play when a few
individuals may be put in a position where unreasonable burdens are placed upon
them or as components of a specific virtue, such as charity. In some settings, culturally
sophisticated mechanisms for sharing burdens can be imbedded in social norms that
would be articulated in the standard terminology of cultural identity, community and
personal virtue. However, some articulations of virtue have been particularly
insensitive to social inequalities. Virtue-based thinking (often with religious backing)
can be used to rationalize enormous inequalities in defense of a given social order. It
is no accident that the word aristocracy derives from Aristotle.
6 Indeed, one of the most sophisticated versions of utilitarian thinking (R.M. Hares two-level utilitarianism), argues that the traditions
of rights provide important sources of moral insight; only when we are very sure that the consequences of our actions are fairly
narrow and can be predicted accurately should cost-benefit considerations be allowed to override a traditional rights-based claim.
(See Henry Shue. 1980. Basic rights. Princeton University Press. 2nd ed. 1996.)
25
Who is
responsible for
ensuring that
intensification
occurs?
26
Ethical ideas that stipulate particular responsibilities for people who have special
roles such as teachers, holders of public office, technical experts and parents have
more typically been articulated in the language of virtue and community solidarity.
Thus, community leaders are people who have assumed or been appointed to a
particular social station that entails special duties. A virtuous leader therefore assumes
duties that are not those of the ordinary person, and in traditional societies such leaders
would also have the authority to ensure that these duties are carried out. Consequently,
in a traditional society, leaders might be acting rightly even when they order people to
do things that might not be consistent with a modern conception of rights. Military
leaders, for example, can order citizens to sacrifice their lives for the greater good of the
community, and one can easily imagine situations in which changes in land use or
farming practice might be ordered as part of a leaders performance of special
responsibilities.
In modern societies, social roles are often highly rationalized so that particular
agencies are formed to take over roles that might have been understood as components
of a leaders virtue in traditional societies. Thus organizations such as the Food and
Agriculture Organization of the United Nations (FAO) have been assigned an explicit
social mission that entails a responsibility to ensure that food needs are met. The report
of the 1996 World Food Summit makes the case for a new round of intensification, and
places responsibilities on national governments, with organizations such as FAO
having major responsibilities for coordinating and facilitating that work. However,
officers within FAO have an ethical challenge in meeting this responsibility. On the
one hand, traditional models for interpreting the responsibilities these officers have
been delegated to carry out stipulate ethics of virtue, and many expect these people
to act as virtuous and authoritative leaders, especially when working in traditional
societies. These traditional ways of understanding ethical responsibilities provide an
implicit basis for acting ethically to discharge official responsibilities. On the other
hand, the rationale for forming organizations such as the United Nations has largely
been articulated in utilitarian or rights-based terms, and this language places significant
constraints on the authority of officers who occupy posts within these organizations.
Thus, the exercise of these role responsibilities requires ethical resources that may
exceed those on which the mandate of an organizations authority is based.
27
28
Conclusion
FAO/10995/J.VAN ACKER
FAO/17322/N.RUBERY
FAO/20722/A.PROTO