100% found this document useful (1 vote)
184 views

Time Machines: 1. Introduction: Time Travel vs. Time Machine

This document discusses the topic of time machines as presented in physics literature. It begins by distinguishing between two concepts of time machines - Wellsian and Thornian. Thornian time machines are devices that manipulate spacetime structure to produce closed timelike curves and enable time travel, without violating laws of physics. The document reviews arguments that the notion of a Thornian time machine is not well-defined, as it is unclear what conditions must be met for such a device to be responsible for producing closed timelike curves. It then summarizes various "no-go" theorems from classical and quantum gravity that aim to establish the physical impossibility of operating a time machine under certain assumptions.

Uploaded by

sonirocks
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOC, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
184 views

Time Machines: 1. Introduction: Time Travel vs. Time Machine

This document discusses the topic of time machines as presented in physics literature. It begins by distinguishing between two concepts of time machines - Wellsian and Thornian. Thornian time machines are devices that manipulate spacetime structure to produce closed timelike curves and enable time travel, without violating laws of physics. The document reviews arguments that the notion of a Thornian time machine is not well-defined, as it is unclear what conditions must be met for such a device to be responsible for producing closed timelike curves. It then summarizes various "no-go" theorems from classical and quantum gravity that aim to establish the physical impossibility of operating a time machine under certain assumptions.

Uploaded by

sonirocks
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOC, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 16

Time Machines

First published Thu 25 Nov, 2004

Recent years have seen a growing consensus in the philosophical community that the
grandfather paradox and similar logical puzzles do not preclude the possibility of time
travel scenarios that utilize spacetimes containing closed timelike curves. At the same
time, physicists, who for half a century acknowledged that the general theory of relativity
is compatible with such spacetimes, have intensely studied the question whether the
operation of a time machine would be admissible in the context of general relativity
theory or theories that attempt to combine general relativity and quantum mechanics. A
time machine is a device which brings about closed timelike curves—and thus enables
time travel—where none would have existed otherwise. The physics literature contains
various no-go theorems for time machines, i.e., theorems which purport to establish that,
under physically plausible assumptions, the operation of a time machine is impossible.
We conclude that for the time being there exists no conclusive no-go theorem against
time machines. The character of the material covered in this article makes it inevitable
that its content is of a rather technical nature. We contend, however, that philosophers
should nevertheless be interested in this literature for at least two reasons. First, the topic
of time machines leads to a number of interesting foundations issues in classical and
quantum theories of gravity; and second, philosophers can contribute to the topic by
clarifying what it means for a device to count as a time machine, by relating the debate to
other concerns such as Penrose's cosmic censorship conjecture and the fate of
determinism in general relativity theory, and by eliminating a number of confusions
regarding the status of the paradoxes of time travel. The present article addresses these
ambitions in as non-technical a manner as possible, and the reader is referred to the
relevant physics literature for details.

• 1. Introduction: time travel vs. time machines


• 2. What is a (Thornian) time machine? Preliminaries
• 3. When can a would-be time machine be held responsible for the emergence of
CTCs?
• 4. No-go results for (Thornian) time machines in classical general relativity theory
• 5. No-go results in quantum gravity
• 6. Conclusion
• Bibliography
• Other Internet Resources
• Related Entries

1. Introduction: time travel vs. time machine


The topic of time machines is the subject of a sizable and growing physics literature,
some of which has filtered down to popular and semi-popular presentations.[1] The issues
raised by this topic are largely oblique, if not orthogonal, to those treated in the
philosophical literature on time travel.[2] Most significantly, the so-called paradoxes of
time travel do not play a substantial role in the physics literature on time machines. This
literature equates the possibility of time travel with the existence of closed timelike
curves (CTCs) or worldlines for material particles that are smooth, future-directed
timelike curves with self-intersections.[3] Since time machines designate devices which
bring about the existence of CTCs and thus enable time travel, the paradoxes of time
travel are irrelevant for attempted “no-go” results for time machines because these results
concern what happens before the emergence of CTCs.[4] This, in our opinion, is fortunate
since the paradoxes of time travel are nothing more than a crude way of bringing out the
fact that the application of familiar local laws of relativistic physics to a spacetime
background which contains CTCs typically requires that consistency constraints on initial
data must be met in order for a local solution of the laws to be extendable to a global
solution. The nature and status of these constraints is the subject of ongoing discussion.
We will not try to advance the discussion of this issue here;[5] rather, our aim is to
acquaint the reader with the issues addressed in the physics literature on time machines
and to connect them with issues in the philosophy of space and time and, more generally,
with issues in the foundations of physics.

Paradox mongers can be reassured in that if a paradox is lost in shifting the focus from
time travel itself to time machines, then a paradox is also gained: if it is possible to
operate a time machine device that produces CTCs, then it is possible to alter the
structure of spacetime such that determinism fails; but by undercutting determinism, the
time machine undercuts the claim that it is responsible for producing CTCs. But just as
the grandfather paradox is a crude way of making a point, so this new paradox is a crude
way of indicating that it is going to be difficult to specify what it means to be a time
machine. This is a task that calls not for paradox mongering but for scientifically
informed philosophizing. The present article will provide the initial steps of this task and
will indicate what remains to be done. But aside from paradoxes, the main payoff of the
topic of time machines is that it provides a quick route to the heart of a number of
foundations problems in classical general relativity theory and in attempts to produce a
quantum theory of gravity by combining general relativity and quantum mechanics. We
will indicate the shape of some of these problems here, but will refer the interested reader
elsewhere for technical details.

There are at least two distinct general notions of time machines, which we will call
Wellsian and Thornian for short. In The Time Machine, H. G. Wells (1931) described
what has become science fiction's paradigmatic conception of a time machine: the
intrepid operator fastens her seat belt, dials the target date—past or future—into the
counter, throws a lever, and sits back while time rewinds or fast forwards until the target
date is reached. We will not broach the issue of whether or not a Wellsian time machine
can be implemented within a relativistic spacetime framework. For, as will soon become
clear, the time machines which have recently come into prominence in the physics
literature are of an utterly different kind. This second kind of time machine was originally
proposed by Kip Thorne and his collaborators (see Morris and Thorne 1988; Morris,
Thorne, and Yurtsever 1988). These articles considered the possibility that, without
violating the laws of general relativistic physics, an advanced civilization might
manipulate concentrations of matter-energy so as to produce CTCs where none would
have existed otherwise. In their example, the production of “wormholes” was used to
generate the required spacetime structure. But this is only one of the ways in which a
time machine might operate, and in what follows any device which affects the spacetime
structure in such a way that CTCs result will be dubbed a Thornian time machine. We
will only be concerned with this variety of time machine, leaving the Wellsian variety to
science fiction writers. This will disappoint the aficionados of science fiction since
Thornian time machines do not have the magical ability to transport the would-be time
traveler to the past of the events that constitute the operation of the time machine. For
those more interested in science than in science fiction, this loss is balanced by the gain
in realism and the connection to contemporary research in physics.

In Sections 2 and 3 we investigate the circumstances under which it is plausible to see a


Thornian time machine at work. The main difficulty lies in specifying the conditions
needed to make sense of the notion that the time machine “produces” or is “responsible
for” the appearances of CTCs. We argue that at present there is no satisfactory resolution
of this difficulty and, thus, that the topic of time machines in a general relativistic setting
is somewhat ill-defined. This fact does not prevent progress from being made on the
topic; for if one's aim is to establish no-go results for time machines it suffices to identify
necessary conditions for the operation of a time machine and then to prove, under
suitable hypotheses about what is physically possible, that it is not physically possible to
satisfy said necessary conditions. In Section 4 we review various no-go results which
depend only on classical general relativity theory. Section 5 surveys results that appeal to
quantum effects. Conclusions are presented in Section 6.

2. What is a (Thornian) time machine? Preliminiaries


The setting for the discussion is a general relativistic spacetime (M, gab) where M is a
differentiable manifold and gab is a Lorentz signature metric defined on all of M. The
central issue addressed in the physics literature on time machines is whether in this
general setting it is physically possible to operate a Thornian time machine. This issue is
to be settled by proving theorems about the solutions to the equations that represent what
are taken to be physical laws operating in the general relativistic setting—or at least this
is so once the notion of a Thornian time machine has been explicated. Unfortunately, no
adequate and generally accepted explication that lends itself to the required mathematical
proofs is to be found in the literature. This is neither surprising nor deplorable.
Mathematical physicists do no wait until some concept has received its final explication
before trying to prove theorems about it; indeed, the process of theorem proving is often
an essential part of conceptual clarification. The moral is well illustrated by the history of
the concept of a spacetime singularity in general relativity where this concept received its
now canonical definition only in the process of proving the Penrose-Hawking-Geroch
singularity theorems, which came at the end of a decades long dispute over the issue of
whether spacetime singularities are a generic feature of solutions to Einstein's
gravitational field equations.[6] However, this is not to say that philosophers interested in
time machines should simply wait until the dust has settled in the physics literature;
indeed, the physics literature could benefit from deployment of the analytical skills that
are the stock in trade of philosophy. For example, the paradoxes of time travel and the
fate of time machines are not infrequently confused in the physics literature, and as will
become evident below, subtler confusions abound as well.

The question of whether a Thornian time machine—a device that produces CTCs—can
be seen to be at work only makes sense if the spacetime has at least three features:
temporal orientability, a definite time orientation, and a causally innocuous past. In order
to make the notion of a CTC meaningful, the spacetime must be temporally orientable
(i.e., must admit a consistent time directionality), and one of the two possible time
orientations has to be singled out as giving the direction of time.[7] Non-temporal
orientability is not really an obstacle since if a given general relativistic spacetime is not
temporally orientable, a spacetime that is everywhere locally the same as the given
spacetime and is itself temporally orientable can be obtained by passing to a covering
spacetime.[8] How to justify the singling out of one of the two possible orientations as
future pointing requires a solution to the problem of the direction of time, a problem
which is still subject to lively debate (see Callender 2001). But for present purposes we
simply assume that a temporal orientation has been provided. A CTC is then (by
definition) a parameterized closed spacetime curve whose tangent is everywhere a future-
pointing timelike vector. A CTC can be thought of as the world line of some possible
observer whose life history is linearly ordered in the small but not in the large: the
observer has a consistent experience of the “next moment,” and the “next,” etc., but
eventually the “next moment” brings her back to whatever event she regards as the
starting point.

As for the third condition—a causally innocuous past—the question of the possibility of
operating a device that produces CTCs presupposes that there is a time before which no
CTCs existed. Thus, Gödel spacetime, so beloved of the time travel literature, is not a
candidate for hosting a Thornian time machine since through every point in this
spacetime there is a CTC. We make this third condition precise by requiring that the
spacetime admits a global time slice Σ (i.e., a spacelike hypersurface without edges);[9]
that Σ is two-sided and partitions M into three parts—Σ itself, the part of M on the past
side of Σ and the part of M on the future side of Σ—and that there are no CTCs that lie on
the past side of Σ. The first two clauses of this requirement together entail that the time
slice Σ is a partial Cauchy surface, i.e., Σ is a time slice that is not intersected more than
once by any future-directed timelike curve.[10]

Now suppose that the state on a partial Cauchy surface Σ0 with no CTCs to its past is to
be thought of as giving a snapshot of the universe at a moment before the machine is
turned on. The subsequent realization of a Thornian time machine scenario requires that
the chronology violating region V ⊆ M, the region of spacetime traced out by CTCs,[11] is
non-null and lies to the future of Σ0. The fact that V ≠ Ø does not lead to any consistency
constraints on initial data on Σ0 since, by hypothesis, Σ0 is not intersected more than once
by any timelike curve, and thus, insofar as the so-called paradoxes of time travel are
concerned with such constraints, the paradoxes do not arise with respect to Σ0. But by the
same token, the option of traveling back into the past of Σ0 is ruled out by the set up as it
has been sketched so far, since otherwise Σ0 would not be a partial Cauchy surface. This
just goes to underscore the point made above that the fans of science fiction stories of
time machines will not find the present context of discussion broad enough to encompass
their vision of how time machines should operate; they may now stop reading this article
and return to their novels.

As a concrete example of these concepts, consider the (1 + 1)-dimensional Misner


spacetime (see Figure 1) which exhibits some of the causal features of Taub-NUT
spacetime, a vacuum solution to Einstein's gravitational field equations. It satisfies all
three of the conditions discussed above. It is temporally orientable, and a time orientation
has been singled out—the shading in the figure indicates the future lobes of the light
cones. To the past of the partial Cauchy surface Σ0 lies the Taub region where the causal
structure of spacetime is as bland as can be desired. But to the future of Σ0 the light cones
begin to “tip over,” and eventually the tipping results in CTCs in the NUT region.

The issue that must be faced now is what further conditions must be imposed in order that
the appearance of CTCs to the future of Σ0 can be attributed to the operation of a time
machine. Not surprisingly, the answer depends not just on the structure of the spacetime
at issue but also on the physical laws that govern the evolution of the spacetime structure.
If one adopts the attitude that the label “time machine” is to be reserved for devices that
operate within a finite spatial range for a finite stretch of time, then one will want to
impose requirements to assure that what happens in a compact region of spacetime lying
on or to the future of Σ0 is responsible for the CTCs. Or one could be more liberal and
allow the would-be time machine to be spread over an infinite space. We will adopt the
more liberal stance since it avoids various complications while still sufficing to elicit key
points. Again, one could reserve the label “time machine” for devices that manipulate
concentrations of mass-energy in some specified ways. For example, based on Gödel
spacetime—where matter is everywhere rotating and a CTC passes through every
spacetime point—one might conjecture that setting into sufficiently rapid rotation a finite
mass concentration of appropriate shape will eventuate in CTCs. But with the goal in
mind of proving negative general results, it is better to proceed in a more abstract fashion.
Think of the conditions on the partial Cauchy surface Σ0 as encoding the instructions for
the operation of the time machine. The details of the operation of the device—whether it
operates in a finite region of spacetime, whether it operates by setting matter into
rotation, etc.—can be left to the side. What must be addressed, however, is whether the
processes that evolve from the state on Σ0 can be deemed to be responsible for the
subsequent appearance of CTCs.

3. When can a would-be time machine be held


responsible for the emergence of CTCs?
The most obvious move is to construe “responsible for” in the sense of causal
determinism. But in the present setting this move quickly runs into a dead end. For if
CTCs exist to the future of Σ0 they are not causally determined by the state on Σ0 since
the time travel region V, if it is non-null, lies outside the future domain of dependence D+
(Σ0) of Σ0, the portion of spacetime where the field equations of relativistic physics
uniquely determine the state of things from the state on Σ0.[12] The point is illustrated by
the toy model of Figure 1. The surface labeled H+(Σ0) is called the future Cauchy horizon
of Σ0. It is the future boundary of D+(Σ0),[13] and it separates the portion of spacetime
where conditions are causally determined by the state on Σ0 from the portion where
conditions are not so determined. And, as advertised, the CTCs in the model of Figure 1
lie beyond H+(Σ0).

Thus, if the operation of a Thornian time machine is to be a live possibility, some


condition weaker than causal determinism must be used to capture the sense in which the
state on Σ0 can be deemed to be responsible for the subsequent development of CTCs.
Given the failure of causal determinism, it seems the next best thing to demand that the
region V is “adjacent” to the future domain of dependence D+(Σ0). Here is an initial stab
at such an adjacency condition. Consider causal curves which have a future endpoint in
the time travel region V and no past endpoint. Such a curve may never leave V; but if it
does, require that it intersects Σ0. But this requirement is too strong because it rules out
Thornian time machines altogether. For a curve of the type in question to reach Σ0 it must
intersect H+(Σ0), but once it reaches H+(Σ0) it can be continued endlessly into the past
without meeting Σ0 because the generators of H+(Σ0) are past endless null geodesics that
never meet Σ0.[14] This difficulty can be overcome by weakening the requirement at issue
by rephrasing it in terms of timelike curves rather than causal curves. Now the set of
candidate time machine spacetimes satisfying the weakened requirement is non-empty—
as illustrated, once again, by the spacetime of Figure 1. But the weakened requirement is
too weak, as illustrated by the (1 + 1)-dimensional version of Deutsch-Politzer
spacetime[15] (see Figure 2), which is constructed from two-dimensional Minkowski
spacetime by deleting the points p1–p4 and then gluing together the strips as shown. Every
past endless timelike curve that emerges from the time travel region V of Deutsch-
Politzer spacetime does meet Σ0. But this spacetime is not a plausible candidate for a time
machine spacetime. Up to and including the time Σ0 (which can be placed as close to V as
desired) this spacetime is identical with empty Minkowski spacetime. If the state of the
corresponding portion of Minkowski spacetime is not responsible for the development of
CTCs—and it certainly is not since there are no CTCs in Minkowski spacetime—how
can the state on the portion of Deutsch-Politzer spacetime up to and including the time Σ0
be held responsible for the CTCs that appear in the future?

The deletion of the points p1-p4 means that the Deutsch-Politzer spacetime is singular in
the sense that it is geodesically incomplete.[16] It would be too drastic to require of a time-
machine hosting spacetime that it be geodesically complete. And in any case the
offending feature of Deutsch-Politzer can be gotten rid of by the following trick.
Multiplying the flat Lorentzian metric ηab of Deutsch-Politzer spacetime by a scalar
function f(x, t) > 0 produces a new metric η′ab := f ηab which is conformal to the original
metric and, thus, has exactly the same causal features as the original metric. But if the
conformal factor f is chosen to “blow up” as the missing points p1–p4 are approached, the
resulting spacetime is geodesically complete—intuitively, the singularities have been
pushed off to infinity.

A more subtle way to exclude Deutsch-Politzer spacetime focuses on the generators of H+


(Σ0). The stipulations laid down so far for Thornian time machines imply that the
generators of H+(Σ0) cannot intersect Σ0. But in addition it can be required that these
generators do not “emerge from a singularity” and do not “come from infinity,” and this
would suffice to rule out Deutsch-Politzer spacetime and its conformal cousins as
legitimate candidates for time machine spacetimes. More precisely, we can impose what
Stephen Hawking (1992a,b) calls the requirement that H+(Σ0) be compactly generated;
namely, the past endless null geodesics that generate H+(Σ0) must, if extended far enough
into past, fall into and remain in a compact subset of spacetime. Obviously the spacetime
of Figure 1 fulfills Hawking's requirement—since in this case H+(Σ0) is itself compact—
but just as obviously the spacetime of Figure 2 (conformally doctored or not) does not.

Imposing the requirement of a compactly generated future Cauchy horizon has not only
the negative virtue of excluding some unsuited candidate time machine spacetimes but a
positive virtue as well. It is easily proved that if H+(Σ0) is compactly generated then the
condition of strong causality is violated on H+(Σ0), which means, intuitively, there are
almost closed causal curves near H+(Σ0).[17] This violation can be taken as an indication
that the seeds of CTCs have been planted on Σ0 and that by the time H+(Σ0) is reached
they are ready to bloom.

However, we still have no guarantee that if CTCs do bloom to the future of Σ0, then the
state on Σ0 is responsible for the blooming. Of course, we have already learned that we
cannot have the iron clad guarantee of causal determinism that the state on Σ0 is
responsible for the actual blooming in all of its particularity. But we might hope for a
guarantee that the state on Σ0 is responsible for the blooming of some CTCs—the actual
ones or others. The difference takes a bit of explaining. The failure of causal determinism
is aptly pictured by the image of a future “branching” of world histories, with the
different branches representing different alternative possible futures of (the domain of
dependence of) Σ0 that are compatible with the actual past and the laws of physics. And
so it is in the present setting: if H+(Σ0) ≠ Ø, then there will generally be different ways to
extend the spacetime model beyond H+(Σ0), all compatible with the laws of general
relativistic physics. But if CTCs are present in all of these extensions, even through the
details of the CTCs may vary from one extension to another, then the state on Σ0 can
rightly be deemed to be responsible for the fact that subsequently CTCs did develop.

Not surprisingly, the would-be time machine operator cannot hope to set conditions on Σ0
such that every mathematically possible extension of D+(Σ0) contains CTCs. Reverting to
the example of Figure 1, a CTC-free extension of D+(Σ0) is obtained by having the light
cones “tip back up” starting on H+(Σ0) so that although a closed null curve develops, no
CTCs appear in the extension. Here the would-be time machine operator might hope to
save the day by showing that the extension in question is not physically possible because
the laws of physics dictate that once the light cones start to tip over in the way shown in
Figure 1, they keep tipping until CTCs form. That such an appeal to the laws of physics
(which in the end may rule out the operation of a time machine) cannot be avoided is also
shown by a second way of creating CTC-free extensions of D+(Σ0) in Figure 1; namely,
allow the light cones to continue to tip but delete a vertical strip of spacetime extending
from H+(Σ0) into the future, thus preventing a timelike curve from circling around the
cylinder and closing on itself. This and similar examples can be bypassed by the
additional reasonable requirement that the relevant extensions to consider are maximal,
i.e., cannot be further extended in the sense of being isometrically embeddable as a
proper subset of a larger spacetime. But (as the alert reader will have perceived) this
additional requirement can be finessed by means of the stratagem used above; namely,
multiplying the metric by a conformal factor does not change the causal features of the
model, but by choosing this factor to approach 0 or ∞ as the deleted strip is approached
the maximality of the extension can be secured.

At this juncture the natural move for the would-be time machine operator is to try to
show that the maximal CTC-free extensions created by the conformal doctoring exceed
the bounds of physical possibility. In general relativity theory these bounds are set using
the stress-energy tensor Tab, which specifies the distribution of matter-energy in the
spacetime (M, gab). The basic requirement is that together Tab and gab satisfy the Einstein
gravitational field equations for all of M. But without further specificity this requirement
does little to limit the possible metrics of spacetime. For given an arbitrary metric gab
defined on M, the Einstein tensor Gab[gab]—a functional constructed from the metric gab
and its derivatives—can be computed and the result taken to define a stress-energy tensor
Tab; the resulting pair Tab and gab automatically satisfies the Einstein gravitational field
equations, which have the form Gab[gab] ∝ Tab. The requirement that the Einstein
equations be satisfied gains bite in one of two ways: either by imposing energy conditions
on Tab, such as the weak energy condition that says that the energy density is non-
negative and/or the dominant energy condition which says that the flow of energy-
momentum is not spacelike;[18] or by requiring that Tab arises from known matter fields
and that together Tab and gab satisfy the coupled Einstein-matter field equations.

Alas, it seems that the would-be time machine operator is not saved by appeal to these or
other requirements that can be stated in terms of local conditions on Tab and gab. A
theorem by Krasnikov (2002, 2003) establishes that for every time-oriented spacetime
(M, gab), there exists a maximal extension that does not contain any CTCs, except,
perhaps, in the chronological past of the image of M in the extension. Furthermore,
Krasnikov shows how these extensions can be constructed such that local conditions,
such as satisfying the Einstein field equations or energy conditions, can be carried over
from the initial spacetime to the maximal CTC-free extension. Thus, if a time machine
were defined as a device which leads to CTCs in all possible extensions of H+(Σ0)
satisfying the conditions laid down thus far, it appears as if Krasnikov's theorem
effectively prohibits time machines.

The would-be time machine operator need not capitulate in the face of Krasnikov's
theorem. Recall that the main difficulty in specifying the conditions for the successful
operation of Thornian time machines traces to the fact that the standard form of causal
determinism does not apply to the production of CTCs. But causal determinism can fail
for reasons that have nothing to do with CTCs or other acausal features of relativistic
spacetimes, and it seems only fair to assure that these modes of failure have been
removed before proceeding to discuss the prospects for time machines. To zero in on the
modes of failure at issue, consider vacuum solutions (Tab ≡ 0) to Einstein's field
equations. Let (M, gab) and (M′, g′ab) be two such solutions, and let Σ ⊂ M and Σ′ ⊂ M′ be
spacelike hypersurfaces of their respective spacetimes. Suppose that there is an isometry
Ψ from some neighborhood N(Σ) of Σ onto a neighborhood N′(Σ′) of Σ′. Does it follow, as
we would want determinism to guarantee, that Ψ is extendible to an isometry from D+(Σ)
onto D+(Σ′)? To see why the answer is negative, start with any solution (M, gab) of the
vacuum Einstein equations, and cut out a closed set of points lying to the future of N(Σ)
and in D+(Σ). Denote the surgically altered manifold by M* and the restriction of gab to
M* by g*ab. Then (M*, g*ab) is also a solution of the vacuum Einstein equations. But
obviously the pair of solutions (M, gab) and (M*, g*ab) violates the condition that
determinism was supposed to guarantee as Ψ is not extendible to an isometry from D+(Σ)
onto D+(Σ*). It might seem that the requirement, contemplated above, that the spacetimes
under consideration be maximal, already rules out spacetimes that have “holes” in them.
But while maximality does rule out the surgically mutilated spacetime just constructed, it
does not guarantee hole freeness in the sense needed to make sure that determinism does
not stumble before it gets to the starting gate. That (M, gab) is hole free in the relevant
sense requires that if Σ ⊂ M is a spacelike hypersurface, there does not exist a spacetime
(M′, g′ab) and an isometric embedding Φ of D+(Σ) into M′ such that Φ(D+(Σ)) is a proper
subset of D+(Φ(Σ)). A theorem due to Robert Geroch (1977, 87), who is responsible for
this definition, asserts that if Σ ⊂ M and Σ′ ⊂ M′ are spacelike hypersurfaces in hole-free
spacetimes (M, gab) and (M′, g′ab), respectively, and if there exists an isometry Ψ: M → M
′, then Ψ is indeed extendible to an isometry between D+(Σ) and D+(Σ′). Thus, hole
freeness precludes an important mode of failure of determinism which we wish to
exclude in our discussion of time machines. It can be shown that hole freeness entails, but
is not entailed by, maximality.[19] And it is just this gap that gives the would-be time
machine operator some hope, for it is not obvious that Krasnikov's construction, which
produces maximal CTC-free extensions, also produces hole-free extensions.

Thus, we propose that one clear sense of what it would mean for a Thornian time
machine to operate in the setting of general relativity theory is given by the following
assertion: the laws of general relativistic physics allow solutions containing a partial
Cauchy surface Σ0 such that no CTCs lie to the past of Σ0 but every extension of D+(Σ0) as
a hole free solution of the laws contains CTCs. Correspondingly, a proof of the physical
impossibility of time machines would take the form of showing that this assertion is false
for the actual laws of physics, consisting, presumably, of Einstein's field equations plus
energy conditions and, perhaps, some additional restrictions as well. And a proof of the
emptiness of the associated concept of a Thornian time machine would take the form of
showing that the assertion is false independently of the details of the laws of physics, as
long as they take the form of local conditions on Tab and gab.

If such an emptiness proof should be forthcoming, the fan of time machines can retreat to
a weaker concept of Thornian time machine by taking a page from probabilistic accounts
of causation, the idea being that a time machine can be seen to be at work if its operation
increases the probability of the appearance of CTCs. Since general relativity theory itself
is innocent of probabilities, they have to be introduced by hand, either by inserting them
into the models of the theory, i.e., by modifying the theory at the level of the object-
language, or by defining measures on sets of models, i.e., by modifying the theory at the
level of the meta-language. Since the former would change the character of the theory,
only the latter will be considered. The project for making sense of the notion that a time
machine as a probabilistic cause of the appearance of CTCs would then take the
following form. First define a normalized measure on the set of models having a partial
Cauchy surface to the past of which there are no CTCs. Then show that the subset of
models that have CTCs to the future of the partial Cauchy surface has non-zero measure.
Next, identify a range of conditions on or near the partial Cauchy surface that are
naturally construed as settings of a device that is a would-be probabilistic cause of CTCs,
and show that the subset of models satisfying these conditions has non-zero measure.
Finally, show that conditionalizing on the latter subset increases the measure of the
former subset. Assuming that this formal exercise can be successfully carried out, there
remains the task of justifying the measure constructed as a measure of objective chance.
This task is especially daunting in the cosmological setting since neither of the leading
interpretations of objective chance seems applicable. The frequency interpretation is
strained since the development of CTCs may be a non-repeated phenomenon; and the
propensity interpretation is equally strained since, barring just-so stories about the
Creator throwing darts at the Cosmic Dart Board, there is no chance mechanism for
producing cosmological models.

We conclude that, even apart from general doubts about a probabilistic account of
causation, the resort to a probabilistic conception of time machines is a desperate stretch,
at least in the context of classical general relativity theory. In a quantum theory of
gravity, a probabilistic conception of time machines may be appropriate if the theory
itself provides the transition probabilities between the relevant states. But an evaluation
of this prospect must wait until the theory of quantum gravity is available.
4. No-go results for (Thornian) time machines in
classical general relativity theory
In order to appreciate the physics literature aimed at proving no-go results for time
machines it is helpful to view these efforts as part of the broader project of proving
chronology protections theorems, which in turn is part of a still larger project of proving
cosmic censorship theorems. To explain, we start with cosmic censorship and work
backwards.

For sake of simplicity, concentrate on the initial value problem for vacuum solutions (Tab
≡ 0) to Einstein's field equations. Start with a three-manifold Σ equipped with quantities
which, when Σ is embedded as a spacelike submanifold of spacetime, become initial data
for the vacuum field equations. Corresponding to the initial data there exists a unique[20]
maximal development (M, gab) for which (the image of the embedded) Σ is a Cauchy
surface.[21] This solution, however, may not be maximal simpliciter, i.e., it may be
possible to isometrically embed it as a proper part of a larger spacetime, which itself may
be a vacuum solution to the field equations; if so Σ will not be a Cauchy surface for the
extended spacetime, which fails to be a globally hyperbolic spacetime.[22] This situation
can arise because of a poor choice of initial value hypersurface, as illustrated in Figure 3
by taking Σ to be the indicated spacelike hyperboloid of (1 + 1)-dimensional Minkowski
spacetime. But, more interestingly, the situation can arise because the Einstein equations
allow various pathologies, collectively referred to as “naked singularities,” to develop
from regular initial data. The strong form of Penrose's celebrated cosmic censorship
conjecture proposes that, consistent with Einstein's field equations, such pathologies do
not arise under physically reasonable conditions or else that the conditions leading to the
pathologies are highly non-generic within the space of all solutions to the field equations.
A small amount of progress has been made on stating and proving precise versions of this
conjecture.[23]

One way in which strong cosmic censorship can be violated is through the emergence of
acausal features. Returning to the example of Misner spacetime (Figure 1), the spacetime
up to H+(Σ0) is the unique maximal development of the vacuum Einstein equations for
which Σ0 is a Cauchy surface. But this development is extendible, and in the extension
illustrated in Figure 1 global hyperbolicity of the development is lost because of the
presence of CTCs. The chronology protection conjecture then can be construed as a
subconjecture of the cosmic censorship conjecture, saying, roughly, that consistent with
Einstein field equations, CTCs do not arise under physically reasonable conditions or else
that the conditions are highly non-generic within the space of all solutions to the field
equations. No-go results for time machines are then special forms of chronology
protection theorems that deal with cases where the CTCs are manufactured by time
machines. In the other direction, a very general chronology protection theorem will
automatically provide a no-go result for time machines, however that notion is
understood, and a theorem establishing strong cosmic censorship will automatically
impose chronology protection.

The most widely discussed chronology protection theorem/no-go result for time machines
in the context of classical general relativity theory is due to Hawking (1992a). Before
stating the result, note first that, independently of the Einstein field equations and energy
conditions, a partial Cauchy surface Σ must be compact if its future Cauchy horizon H+
(Σ) is compact (see Hawking 1992a and Chrusciel and Isenberg 1993). However, it is
geometrically allowed that Σ is non-compact if H+(Σ) is required only to be compactly
generated rather than compact. But what Hawking showed is that this geometrical
possibility is ruled out by imposing Einstein's field equations and the weak energy
condition. Thus, if Σ0 is a partial Cauchy surface representing the situation just before or
just as the would-be Thornian time machine is switched on, and if a necessary condition
for seeing a Thornian time machine at work is that H+(Σ0) is compactly generated, then
consistently with Einstein's field equations and the weak energy condition, a Thornian
time machine cannot operate in a spatially open universe since Σ0 must be compact.

This no-go result does not touch the situation illustrated in Figure 1. Taub-NUT
spacetime is a vacuum solution to Einstein's field equations so the weak energy condition
is automatically satisfied, and H+(Σ0) is compact and, a fortiori, compactly generated.
Hawking's theorem is not contradicted since Σ0 is compact. By the same token the
theorem does not speak to the possibility of operating a Thornian time machine in a
spatially closed universe. To help fill the gap, Hawking proved that when Σ0 is compact
and H+(Σ0) is compactly generated, the Einstein field equations and the weak energy
condition together guarantee that both the convergence and shear of the null geodesic
generators of H+(Σ0) must vanish, which he interpreted to imply that no observers can
cross over H+(Σ0) to enter the chronology violating region V. But rather than showing that
it is physically impossible to operate a Thornian time machine in a closed universe, this
result shows only that, given the correctness of Hawking's interpretation, the observers
who operate the time machine cannot take advantage of the CTCs it produces.

There are two sources of doubt about the effectiveness of Hawking's no-go result even
for open universes. The first stems from possible violations of the weak energy condition
by stress-energy tensors arising from classical relativistic matter fields (see Vollick 1997
and Visser and Barcelo 2000).[24] The second stems from the fact that Hawking's theorem
functions as a chronology protection theorem only by way of serving as a potential no-go
result for Thornian time machines since the crucial condition that H+(Σ0) is compactly
generated is supposedly justified by being a necessary condition for the operation of such
machine. But in retrospect, the motivation for this condition seems frayed. As argued in
the previous section, if the Einstein field equations and energy conditions entail that all
hole free extensions of D+(Σ0) contain CTCs, then it is plausible to see a Thornian time
machine at work, quite regardless of whether or not H+(Σ0) is compactly generated or not.
Of course, it remains to establish the existence of cases where this entailment holds. If it
should turn out that there are no such cases, then the prospects of Thornian time machines
are dealt a severe blow, but the reasons are independent of Hawking's theorem. On the
other hand, if such cases do exist then our conjecture would be that they exist even when
some of the generators of H+(Σ0) come from singularities or infinity and, thus, H+(Σ0) is
not compactly generated.[25]

5. No-go results in quantum gravity


Three degrees of quantum involvement in gravity can be distinguished. The first degree,
referred to as quantum field theory on curved spacetimes, simply takes off the shelf a
spacetime provided by general relativity theory and then proceeds to study the behavior
of quantum fields on this background spacetime. The Unruh effect, which predicts the
thermalization of a free scalar quantum field near the horizon of a black hole, lies within
this ambit. The second degree of involvement, referred to as semi-classical quantum
gravity, attempts to calculate the backreaction of the quantum fields on spacetime metric
by computing the expectation value <Ψ|Tab|Ψ> of the stress-energy tensor in some
appropriate quantum state |Ψ> and then inserting the value into Einstein's field equations
in place of Tab .[26] Hawking's celebrated prediction of black hole radiation belongs to this
ambit.[27] The third degree of involvement attempts to produce a genuine quantum theory
of gravity in the sense that the gravitational degrees of freedom are quantized. Currently
loop quantum gravity and string theory are the main research programs aimed at this
goal.[28]

The first degree of quantum involvement, if not opening the door to Thornian time
machines, at least seemed to remove some obstacles since quantum fields are known to
lead to violations of the energy conditions used in the setting of classical general
relativity theory to prove chronology protection theorems and no-go results for time
machines. However, the second degree of quantum involvement seemed, at least initially,
to slam the door shut. The intuitive idea was this. Start with a general relativistic
spacetime where CTCs develop to the future of H+(Σ) (often referred to as the
“chronology horizon”) for some suitable partial Cauchy surface Σ. Find that the
propagation of a quantum field on this spacetime background is such that <Ψ|Tab|Ψ>
“blows up” as H+(Σ) is approached from the past. Conclude that the backreaction on the
spacetime metric creates unbounded curvature, which effectively cuts off the future
development that would otherwise eventuate in CTCs. These intuitions were partly
vindicated by detailed calculations in several models. But eventually a number of
exceptions were found in which the backreaction remains arbitrarily small near H+(Σ).[29]
This seemed to leave the door ajar for Thornian time machines.

But fortunes were reversed once again by a result of Kay, Radzikowski, and Wald
(1997). The details of their theorem are too technical to review here, but the structure of
the argument is easy to grasp. The naïve calculation of <Ψ|Tab|Ψ> results in infinities
which have to be subtracted off to produce a renormalized expectation value <Ψ|Tab|Ψ>R
with a finite value. The standard renormalization procedure uses a limiting procedure that
is mathematically well-defined if, and only if, a certain condition obtains.[30] The KRW
theorem shows that this condition is violated for points on H+(Σ) and, thus, that the
expectation value of the stress-energy tensor is not well-defined at the chronology
horizon.

While the KRW theorem is undoubtedly of fundamental importance for semi-classical


quantum gravity, it does not serve as an effective no-go result for Thornian time
machines. In the first place, the theorem assumes, in concert with Hawking's chronology
protection theorem, that H+(Σ) is compactly generated, and we repeat that it is far from
clear that this assumption is necessary for seeing a Thornian time machine in operation.
A second, and more fundamental, reservation applies even if a compactly generated H+
(Σ) is accepted as a necessary condition for time machines. The KRW theorem functions
as a no-go result by providing a reductio ad absurdum with a dubious absurdity: roughly,
if you try to operate a Thornian time machine, you will end up invalidating semi-classical
quantum gravity. But semi-classical quantum gravity was never viewed as anything more
than a stepping stone to a genuine quantum theory of gravity, and its breakdown is
expected to be manifested when Planck-scale physics comes into play. This worry is
underscored by Visser's (1997, 2003) findings that in chronology violating models trans-
Planckian physics can be expected to come into play before H+(Σ) is reached.

It thus seems that if some quantum mechanism is to serve as the basis for chronology
protection, it must be found in the third degree of quantum involvement in gravity. Both
loop quantum gravity and string theory have demonstrated the ability to cure some of the
curvature singularities of classical general relativity theory. But as far as we are aware
there are no demonstrations that either of these approaches to quantum gravity can get rid
of the acausal features exhibited in various solutions to Einstein's field equations. An
alternative approach to formulate a fully-fledged quantum theory of gravity attempts to
capture the Planck-scale structure of spacetime by constructing it from causal sets.[31]
Since these sets must be acyclic, i.e., no element in a causal set can causally precede
itself, CTCs are ruled out a priori. Actually, a theorem due to Malament (1977) suggests
that any Planck-scale approach encoding only the causal structure of a spacetime cannot
permit CTCs either in the smooth classical spacetimes or a corresponding phenomenon in
their quantum counterparts.[32]

In sum, the existing no-go results that use the first two degrees of quantum involvement
are not very convincing, and the third degree of involvement is not mature enough to
allow useful pronouncements.

6. Conclusion
Hawking opined that “[i]t seems there is a chronology protection agency, which prevents
the appearance of closed timelike curves and so makes the universe safe for historians”
(1992a, 603). He may be right, but to date there are no convincing arguments that such an
Agency is housed in either classical general relativity theory or in semi-classical quantum
gravity. And it is too early to tell whether this Agency is housed in loop quantum gravity
or string theory. But even if it should turn out that Hawking is wrong in that the laws of
physics do not support a Chronology Protection Agency, it could still be the case that the
laws support an Anti-Time Machine Agency. For it could turn out that while the laws do
not prevent the development of CTCs, they also do not make it possible to attribute the
appearance of CTCs to the workings of any would-be time machine. We argued that a
strong presumption in favor of the latter would be created in classical general relativity
theory by the demonstration that for any model satisfying Einstein's field equations and
energy conditions as well as possessing a partial Cauchy surface Σ0 to the future of which
there are CTCs, there are hole free extensions of D+(Σ0) satisfying Einstein's field
equations and energy conditions but containing no CTCs to the future of Σ0. There are no
doubt alternative approaches to understanding what it means for a device to be
“responsible for” the development of CTCs. Exploring these alternatives is one place that
philosophers can hope to make a contribution to an ongoing discussion that, to date, has
been carried mainly by the physics community. Participating in this discussion means
that philosophers have to forsake the activity of logical gymnastics with the paradoxes of
time travel for the more arduous but (we believe) rewarding activity of digging into the
foundations of physics.

Time machines may never see daylight, and perhaps so for principled reasons that stem
from basic physical laws. But even if mathematical theorems in the various theories
concerned succeed in establishing the impossibility of time machines, understanding why
time machines cannot be constructed will shed light on central problems in the
foundations of physics. As we have argued in Section 4, for instance, the hunt for time
machines in general relativity theory should be interpreted as a core issue in studying the
fortunes of Penrose's cosmic censorship conjecture. This conjecture arguably constitutes
the most important open problem in general relativity theory. Similarly, as discussed in
Section 5, mathematical theorems related to various aspects of time machines offer
results relevant for the search of a quantum theory of gravity. In sum, studying the
possibilities for operating a time machine turns out to be not a scientifically peripheral or
frivolous weekend activity but a useful way of probing the foundations of classical and
quantum theories of gravity.

Bibliography
• Arntzenius, F. and T. Maudlin, 2000, “Time Travel and Modern Physics,” in E.N.
Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2000 Edition),
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2000/entries/time-travel-phys/.
• Brightwell, G., H.F. Dowker, R.S. Garcia, J. Henson, and R.D. Sorkin, 2003,
“‘Observables’ in causal set cosmology,” Physical Review D, 67: 08403. [Preprint
available online.]
• Callender, C., 2001, “Thermodynamic Asymmetry in Time,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.),
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2001 Edition),
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2001/entries/time-thermo/.
• Chrusciel, P.T. and J. Isenberg, 1993, “Compact Cauchy Horizons and Cauchy
Surfaces,” in B.L. Hu and T.A. Jacobson (eds.), Papers in Honor of Dieter Brill:
Directions in General Relativity, Vol. 2, pp. 97-107. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
• Davies, P., 2002a, How to Build a Time Machine. London: Viking Penguin.
• Davies, P., 2002b, “How to Build a Time Machine,” Scientific American, 287 (no.
3): 50-55.
• Deutsch, D., 1991, “Quantum Mechanics Near Closed Timelike Lines,” Physical
Review D, 44: 3197-3217.
• Earman, J., 1995a, Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and
Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes. New York: Oxford University Press.
• Earman, J., 1995b, “Recent Work on Time Travel,” in S.F. Savitt (ed.), Time's
Arrow Today: Recent Physical and Philosophical Work on the Direction of Time,
pp. 268-310. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
• Earman, J., 1995c, “Outlawing Time Machines: Chronology Protection
Theorems,” Erkenntnis, 42: 125-139.
• Earman, J., 1999, “The Penrose-Hawking Singularity Theorems: History and
Implications,” in H. Goenner, J. Renn, and T. Sauer (eds.), The Expanding
Worlds of General Relativity, Einstein Studies, Vol. 7, pp. 235-267. Boston:
Birkhäuser.
• Earman, J., C. Smeenk, and C. Wüthrich, 2004, “Take a Ride on a Time
Machine,” to appear in R. Jones and P. Ehrlich (eds.), Reverberations of the
Shaky Game: Festschrift for Arthur Fine, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[Preprint available online]
• Geroch, R., 1977, “Prediction in General Relativity,” in J. Earman, C. Glymour,
and J. Stachel (eds.), Foundations of Spacetime Theories, Minnesota Studies in
the Philosophy of Science, Vol. VIII, pp. 81-93. Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press.
• Gott, R., 2001, Time Travel in Einstein's Universe. New York: Houghton Mifflin.
• Greene, B., 2003, The Elegant Universe. New York: W. W. Norton.
• Hawking, S.W., 1992a, “Chronology Protection Conjecture,” Physical Review D,
46: 603-611.
• Hawking, S.W., 1992b, “The Chronology Protection Conjecture,” in H. Sato and
T. Nakamura (eds.), Proceedings of the Sixth Marcel Grossmann Meeting on
General Relativity, pp. 3-13. Singapore: World Scientific.
• Hawking, S.W., 2001, “Chronology Protection: Making the World Safe for
Historians,” in S.W. Hawking et al. (eds.), The Future of Spacetime, pp. 87-108.
New York: W.W. Norton.
• Hawking, S.W. and G.F.R. Ellis, 1973, The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
• Hoefer, C., 2003, “Causal Determinism,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2003 Edition),
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/determinism-causal/.
• Kay, B.S., M.J. Radzikowski, and R.M. Wald, 1997, “Quantum Field Theory On
Spacetimes with Compactly Generated Cauchy Horizons.” Communications in
Mathematical Physics, 183: 533-556.
• Keller, S. and M. Nelson, 2001, “Presentists Should Believe in Time-Travel,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79: 333-345.
• Krasnikov, S., 1999, “Time Machines with Non-Compactly Generated Cauchy
Horizons and ‘Handy Singularities’,” in T. Piran and R. Ruffini (eds.),
Proceedings of the Eighth Marcel Grossmann Meeting on General Relativity, pp.
593-595. Singapore: World Scientific. [Preprint available online.]
• Krasnikov, S., 2002, “No Time Machines in Classical General Relativity,”
Classical and Quantum Gravity, 19: 4109-4129. [Preprint available online.]
• Krasnikov, S., 2003, “Time Machine (1988-2001),” talk given at 11th UK
Conference on the Foundations of Physics, Oxford, England, 9-13 Sept. 2002.
[Preprint available online.]
• Malament, D.B., 1977, “The class of continuous timelike curves determines the
topology of spacetime,” Journal of Mathematical Physics, 18: 1399-1404.
• Monton, B., 2003, “Presentists Can Believe in Closed Timelike Curves,”
Analysis, 63: 199-202.
• Morris, M.S. and K.S. Thorne, 1988, “Wormholes in Spacetime and Their Use for
Interstellar Travel: A Tool for Teaching General Relativity,” American Journal of
Physics, 56: 395-412.
• Morris, M.S., K.S. Thorne, and U. Yurtsever, 1988, “Wormholes, Time
Machines, and the Weak Energy Condition,” Physical Review Letters, 61: 1446-
1449.
• Nahin, P.J., 1999, Time Machines: Time Travel in Physics, Metaphysics, and
Science Fiction. New York: AIP Press, Springer.
• Norton, J., 2004, “The Hole Argument,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2004 Edition),
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/spacetime-holearg/.
• Ori, A., 1993, “Must Time-Machine Construction Violate the Weak Energy
Condition?” Physical Review Letters, 71: 2517-2520.
• Politzer, H.D., 1992, “Simple Quantum Systems in Spacetimes with Closed
Timelike Curves,” Physical Review D, 46: 4470-4476.
• Visser, M., 1997, “The Reliability Horizon for Semi-Classical Quantum Gravity:
Metric Fluctuations Are Often More Important than Back-Reaction,” Physics
Letters B, 115: 8-14.
• Visser, M., 2003, “The Quantum Physics of Chronology Protection,” in G.W.
Gibbons, E.P.S. Shellard, S.J. Rankin (eds.), The Future of Theoretical Physics
and Cosmology: Celebrating Stephen Hawking's 60th Birthday, pp. 161-176.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
• Visser, M. and C. Barcelo, 2000, “Energy conditions and their cosmological
implications,” Plenary talk presented at Cosmo99, Trieste Sept/Oct 1999.
[Preprint available online.]
• Vollick, D.N., 1997, “How to Produce Exotic Matter Using Classical Fields,”
Physical Review D, 56: 4720-4723.
• Wald, R.M., 1984, General Relativity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
• Wald, R.M., 1994, Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime and Black Hole
Thermodynamics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
• Wald, R.M., 1998, “Gravitational Collapse and Cosmic Censorship,” in B.R. Iyer,
and B. Bhawal (eds.), Black Holes, Gravitational Radiation and the Universe:
Essays in Honor of C. V. Vishveshwara, pp. 69-85. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
[Preprint available online.]
• Wells, H.G., 1931, The Time Machine. New York: Random House.
• Zwiebach, B., 2004, A First Course on String Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.

You might also like