COMMON DISSENT: LANGUAGE AND IDEOLOGY OF A SOCIAL MOVEMENT - A CASE STUDY OF THE EVOLUTIONARY STUDIES (EVOS) PROGRAM (David Gerstle)
COMMON DISSENT: LANGUAGE AND IDEOLOGY OF A SOCIAL MOVEMENT - A CASE STUDY OF THE EVOLUTIONARY STUDIES (EVOS) PROGRAM (David Gerstle)
COMMON DISSENT: LANGUAGE AND IDEOLOGY OF A SOCIAL MOVEMENT - A CASE STUDY OF THE EVOLUTIONARY STUDIES (EVOS) PROGRAM (David Gerstle)
Accepted
in
partial
fulfillment
of
the
requirements
for
the
degree
of
Doctor
of
Philosophy
in
Anthropology
in
the
Graduate
School
of
Binghamton
University
State
University
of
New
York
2015
December
4,
2015
Dr.
Douglas
J
Glick,
Chair
Department
of
Anthropology,
Binghamton
University
Dr.
Thomas
M
Wilson,
Member
Department
of
Anthropology,
Binghamton
University
Dr.
Deborah
A
Elliston,
Reader,
Member
Department
of
Anthropology,
Binghamton
University
Dr.
Bat-Ami
Bar
On,
Outside
Reader
Department
of
Philosophy,
Binghamton
University
iii
iv
Abstract
In
challenging
particular
ideologies
and
institutions,
social
movements
offer
more
general
examples
of
how
people
introduce
and
circulate
new,
often
controversial
meanings.
The
Evolutionary
Studies
(EvoS)
Program
at
Binghamton
University
challenges
the
structure
and
epistemic
grounds
of
higher
education,
arguing
that
evolutionary
reasoning
should
become
a
foundational
perspective
for
the
study
of
human
experience.
Doing
so,
the
Humanities
and
Social
Sciences
would
be
reoriented
to
seek
the
evolutionary
origins
and
functions
of
(among
other
subjects)
religion,
government,
law,
art,
and
literature.
Yet,
this
ambitious
challenge
must
first
and
foremost
be
persuasively
communicated
to
a
variety
of
academic
audiences,
and
some
will
find
it
objectionable.
My
research
shows
that
the
EvoS
Program
introduces
and
spreads
its
arguments
by:
reaffirming
the
movements
principles
and
goals
as
the
messages
across
increasingly
novel
(sometimes
hostile)
settings,
establishing
critical
representations
of
critics,
and
socializing
newcomers
to
practice
their
own
expressions
of
this
message.
The
introduction
and
spread
of
new
meanings
can
thus
be
seen
as
a
sociolinguistic
process
involving
contextualization
across
novel
contexts,
public
confrontations
between
advocates
and
critics,
and
socialization
of
the
newly
persuaded
into
agents
of
the
meanings
spread
and
endurance.
To
Sarah
Seeley.
You
own
my
life
and
my
heart.
And
to
Lucy,
my
kitty
and
my
friend.
See
you
on
the
other
side,
fuzzy
face.
vi
Acknowledgements
My
parents,
Louise,
Frank,
and
Polli,
for
their
open
minds,
incredible
brains,
and
loving
hearts.
My
grandparents,
who
I
think
would
be
proud
of
me.
My
dear
friends
Kelly
Buman,
Clara
Marx,
Diego
Santos,
Jim
Devona,
and
Dene
Farrell.
My
committee,
Douglas
Glick,
Thomas
Wilson,
Deborah
Elliston,
and
Bat-Ami
Bar
On.
I
could
not
have
hoped
for
better
mentors
and
colleagues.
Heidi
Kenyon,
Robin
Barron,
Erin
Stanley,
Aneesa
Thomas,
and
Laura
Potter,
for
their
continuous
kindness,
knowledge,
and
commitment
to
my
success.
Archana
Mohan,
Surey
Gonzalez,
Layoung
Shin,
Marina
Weinberg,
Darwin
Tsen,
Charlie
Wesley,
Jarret
and
Shelie
Rose,
and
Jason
Allen,
for
making
grad
school
a
mistake
that
I
dont
regret.
My
friends
and
colleagues,
Suronda
Gonzalez,
Kerry
Cook
Stamp,
Natalia
Andrievskikh,
Hwa
Yeong
Wang,
Shannon
Hilliker,
Laura
Kipfer,
Mike
Miller,
and
Colleen
Parks.
Michael
Van
Auken,
a
very
smart
man
who
talked
with
me
about
something
like
this,
a
long
time
ago.
That
was
the
start.
William
Russell,
my
counselor
and
friend.
The
results
of
our
discussions
are
in
every
page
here.
Thank
you
so
much.
Taylor
Sisson,
John
Ewing,
Leah
Gottlieb,
Tracy
Allison,
Allie
Hall,
Geena
Vabulus,
Renata
Kuperman,
,
Alyssa
Kassner,
and
Diddy
Herskovics
amazing
students
that
I
am
lucky
to
know.
Judy
Koskovich,
the
best
teacher
I
ever
had.
Dr.
Ann
Stahl
and
Dr.
Surinder
Bhardwaj,
two
professors
who
were
endlessly
patient
and
interested
in
my
ideas.
Dr.
Jonathan
Marks,
Dr.
Martha
McCaughey,
and
Emma
Marris,
who
talked
with
me
about
this
research
and
read
my
early
drafts.
vii
Table
of
Contents
List
of
Tablesix
List
of
Figures...x
Introduction...1
Chapter
One:
Relevant
Fields,
Terms,
and
Data
Collection....11
1. Social
Movement
Theory.12
2. Indexicality
and
Ideology22
3. Foregrounding
and
Contextualization36
4. Language
and
Ideology
in
the
Maintenance
and
Spread
of
a
Social
Movement.48
5. Research
Site
and
Data
Collection.50
Chapter
Two:
The
EvoS
Programs
Presupposed
Ideologies,
First
Principle,
and
Resources...53
1. Evolutionary
Reasoning:
Four
Presupposed
Ideologies
on
Human
Evolution
and
its
Implications....53
2. The
EvoS
Programs
First
Principle.70
3. The
EvoS
Programs
Resources:
Incentives,
Coursework,
Membership,
Promotional
Media,
and
Funding..73
Chapter
Three:
The
EvoS
Programs
In-House
Ideologies101
Chapter
Four:
Foregrounding
and
Contextualization
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures............137
1. Attacks
on
the
Structure
of
Academics....142
2. Gratuitous
Displays
or
Mentioning
Taboo
Subjects.152
3. Introducing
Personal
Testimonies.167
4. Marked
Modes
of
Speaker
Performance/Audience
Participation..185
Chapter
Five:
Criticism
and
Modes
of
Defense
in
the
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer
Sessions...207
1. Time
Limits
and
Moderation.208
2. Critics
in
the
EvoS
Audience..210
3. Modes
of
Defense
Against
Audience
Critiques...214
4. Critics
of
EvoS
as
Resources
for
the
Movement.235
5. EvoS
New
Paltz
and
The
Tiger
Incident237
viii
Chapter
Six:
Practice,
Demonstration,
and
Criticism
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Social
Events..251
1. Encouraging
(and
Requiring)
Student
Engagement..............254
2. Student
Practice
and
Lecturer
Guidance....260
3. Further
Lecturer
Foregrounding-Contextualizations270
4. Criticisms
and
their
Consequences
in
the
Social
Event.280
5. EvoS
at
the
University
of
Lisbon
and
The
Inquisition
against
Evolution..288
6. EvoS
Social
Events
and
the
Recruitment
of
New
Participants..293
Chapter
Seven:
Contextualization,
Socialization
and
the
fate
of
EvoS.299
1. Abstraction...302
2. Analogical
Extension..305
3. Reflexive
Recursion.310
4. The
Fate
of
the
EvoS
Program
at
Binghamton
University...314
Works
Cited..318
ix
List
of
Tables
Data
Summary
1.
Attacks
on
Academic
Structure
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
149
Data
Summary
2.
Gratuitous
Displays/Mentioning
Taboo
Topics
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
163
Data
Summary
3.
Personal
Testimonies
Introduced
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
180
Data
Summary
4.
Marked
Modes
of
Speaker
Performance/Audience
Participation
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures.199
List
of
Figures
Figure
1.
Detail
from
About
EvoS
informational
flyer,
distributed
at
Binghamton
University
between
2012-2013
90
Figures
2
and
3.
Promotional
EvoS
flyers
from
the
2013-14
school
year.92
1
Introduction
In
my
final
days
collecting
data
on
Binghamton
Universitys
Evolutionary
Studies
(EvoS)
Program,
I
needed
to
access
the
programs
website
to
double-check
the
date
of
a
publication.
Along
the
right-hand
side
of
the
websites
title
page,
as
always,
were
Twitter
submissions
by
the
programs
participants.
These
tended
to
be
notes
about
upcoming
events
or
Tweeters
spreading
happy
news
about
an
EvoS
members
new
publication,
award,
or
employment.
This
day,
however,
the
most
recent
tweet
was
something
more
attention
grabbing:
Education
anecdotes:
Im
not
saying
youre
related
to
monkeys;
Im
saying
youre
related
to
yeast.
No
author
for
this
anecdote
was
given.
Was
it
quoting
a
professor
speaking
to
students,
some
retort
heard
during
an
in-class
dispute,
or
perhaps
invented
solely
for
this
online
posting?
Regardless
of
the
source,
I
recognized
the
comment
as
similar
to
many
others
I
encountered
during
my
fieldwork
on
the
EvoS
Program.
It
was
an
unabashedly
sweeping,
intentionally
provocative,
but
somewhat
clever
bit
of
evolutionary
reasoning
about
social
life
and
human
existence.
It
was
a
bit
of
quirky
knowledge
that
taken
seriously
could
be
interpreted
as
a
challenge
to
just
about
any
spiritual
or
philosophical
argument
about
humanitys
uniqueness
in
the
living
world.
In
this
research,
I
investigate
the
functions
of
language
and
ideology
within
the
EvoS
Program,
approaching
it
as
a
case
study
in
endurance
and
spread
of
a
2
social
movement.
I
am
asking
a
simply
phrased,
but
complexly
answered
question:
How
do
people
introduce
and
spread
new
meanings
to
the
activities
and
relationships
of
others,
particularly
when
such
interpretations
are
either
unknown
or
unpopular?
Anyone
familiar
with
EvoS
will
attest
that
this
program
is
an
ideal
place
to
make
this
inquiry.
It
is
initiative
to
transform
U.S.
higher
education,
arguing
that
evolutionary
reasoning
(grounded
in
Darwinian
theories
of
natural
selection
and
adaptation)
should
be
embraced
by
every
university
discipline
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
human
behaviors.
The
program
seeks
a
similar
goal
outside
U.S.
universities,
promoting
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
means
reshape
public
policies
and
even
guide
international
regulation.
EvoS
poses
a
radical
challenge
to
the
ways
that
social
life
is
researched.
It
further
seeks
an
existential
and
socio-political
shift
in
peoples
understandings
of
themselves
as
the
products
of
this
species
evolutionary
past
and
the
potential
shapers
of
future
evolution.
In
this
way,
participants
in
EvoS
regularly
ascribe
new
and
contested
meanings
to
social
life,
work
to
spread
these
meanings
to
new
participants
and
novel
settings,
and
ultimately
hope
that
these
meanings
will
result
in
far-reaching
transformations.
As
the
programs
founder
proposes,
when
you
take
an
evolutionary
perspective,
you
see
things
differently
and
a
new
common
sense
emerges
(Marris
2010).
My
investigation
documents
how
such
a
transformative
vision
is
created,
spread,
embraced,
and
challenged
through
the
interpersonal
activities
and
relationships
of
this
movement.
I
first
learned
of
EvoS
in
2005,
when
I
came
to
Binghamton
as
a
graduate
student
in
Anthropology.
During
my
undergraduate
years
at
Kent
State
University,
I
3
majored
in
Biological
Anthropology,
studying
human
genetics,
paleoanthropology,
human
behavioral
ecology,
and
evolutionary
psychology.
During
that
time,
I
became
persuaded
that
Darwinism
had
the
potential
to
explain
the
most
confounding
areas
of
life
romance,
crime,
violence,
insanity,
and
death.
One
of
my
undergraduate
textbooks
framed
my
thinking
quite
accurately:
Is
there
a
point
to
all
this?
Yes.
There
is
a
reason
why
dungflies
copulate
for
35.5
minutes;
why
big
male
reef
fish
turn
into
females
but
little
male
reef
fish
dont;
why
female
swallows
like
males
with
elongated
tails;
why
more
promiscuous
primates
have
bigger
testes.
The
reason
is
simple.
Dungflies,
reef
fish,
swallows,
and
promiscuous
primates
who
do
otherwise
leave
less
DNA.
The
chemically
encoded
messages
copulate
for
just
28
minutes
and
if
promiscuous,
grow
a
small
scrotum
all
get
passed
on
to
fewer
bodies,
and
so
all
tend
to
die
out.
Messages,
on
the
other
hand,
that
make
it
easier
for
animals
to
grow,
mate,
and
this
is
the
bottom
line
breed,
all
tend
to
spread.
The
point
of
life
is
the
proliferation
of
life.
[Betzig
1997:1]
After
going
on
to
graduate
school,
it
seemed
fortuitous
that
this
program
at
Binghamton
could
satisfy
my
long
fascination
with
evolutionary
science.
I
looked
forward
to
meeting
others
who
hoped
that
Darwinian
theory
could
explain
troubling
social
questions,
perhaps
even
show
us
how
to
rectify
injustice
and
inequality.
Binghamtons
Biological
Sciences.
In
the
late
1990s
and
early
2000s,
Wilson
became
widely
known
for
applying
evolutionary
assessments
to
areas
previously
untouched
by
Darwinian
theory,
particularly
studies
of
religion
and
spirituality.
Doing
so,
he
was
expanding
on
positions
established
by
writers
such
as
Daniel
Dennett
and
Edward
O.
Wilson,
who
outlined
evolutionary
angles
on
morality,
politics,
and
philosophy.
Yet,
the
EvoS
founder
differed
from
these
theorists
in
an
important
way
4
he
ardently
believed
that
evolutionary
science
could
make
human
existence
more
egalitarian,
just,
and
self-aware.
From
my
first
experiences
in
EvoS,
I
saw
that
its
organizers
and
students
(like
the
programs
founder)
wanted
to
explain
even
the
most
problematic
issues
of
human
life
through
evolution.
Visiting
lecturers
pursued
arguments
that
I
previously
thought
only
dim
possibilities.
They
posed
evolutionary
hypotheses
about
warfare,
totalitarianism,
creativity,
and
the
nature
of
human
consciousness.
The
programs
events
were
charged
with
enthusiasm,
humor,
and
passion.
In
one
instance,
a
guest
speaker
argued
that
psychologists
should
treat
attempted
suicide
as
an
adaptation
(individuals
trying
to
alert
others
to
threats
to
their
long-term
survival).
Several
times,
I
heard
students
say
that
their
troubles
with
friends,
siblings,
parents,
or
romantic
partners
were
more
understandable
when
they
considered
themselves
(and
others)
to
be
social
animals,
competing
for
resources.
A
growing
community
saw
evolution
in
social
and
personal
problems,
and
their
potential
solutions.
David
Sloan
Wilson
nurtured
these
perspectives,
and
his
enthusiasm
about
evolutions
new
possibilities
colored
every
EvoS
event.
At
the
same
time,
these
broad
applications
of
evolutionary
theory
were
clearly
not
favored
in
other
spheres
of
academic
life.
Many
of
my
professors
were
deeply
skeptical
toward
Darwinian
studies
of
language,
politics,
religion,
and
family.
Some
of
my
fellow
graduate
students
would
debate
with
me
when
I
started
talking
evolution,
in
class
or
over
drinks.
I
found
books
and
essays
echoing
these
doubts,
and
I
read
extensively
about
the
controversies
over
human
evolution
in
higher
education.
Darwinian
perspectives
on
gender
norms,
social
dominance,
and
violence
5
(among
other
subjects)
were
at
odds
with
much
of
what
I
was
learning
in
graduate
school.
Indeed,
it
was
hard
not
to
agree
that
Darwinian
theorists,
when
they
looked
at
social
life,
often
glossed
over
some
well-established
knowledge
of
history,
politics,
and
language.
Their
reaction
to
these
criticisms
was
often
an
indignant
rebuttal
that
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities
were
anti-science
and
anti-evolution.
It
was
fascinating
and
alarming
to
find
that
this
was
one
of
the
most
troublesome
issues
in
higher
education.
These
controversies
helped
to
shape
the
EvoS
Program
and
the
arguments
that
its
participants
made.
Many
of
the
EvoS
organizers,
speakers,
and
audience
enjoyed
the
controversy,
being
excitedly
politically
incorrect
in
their
contributions,
and
unabashedly
talking
about
topics
like
menstruation,
sexual
violence,
and
murder
in
evolutionary
terms.
Some
participants
described
non-industrialized
societies
as
primitive
or
un-evolved.
One
student
proposed
that
U.S.
inner
cities
operated
by
the
laws
of
the
jungle.
Lecturers
could
be
surprisingly
honest,
some
offering
details
about
their
failed
marriages,
sexual
orientation,
or
traumas
of
their
childhood.
EvoS
lectures
were
more
like
staged
performances,
replete
with
ribald
jokes,
graphic
depictions
of
sex
and
violence,
and
extensive
audience
participation.
One
lecture
used
call-and-response
techniques,
similar
to
a
revivalist
sermon.
Another
speaker
showed
slides
featuring
wartime
photos
of
mutilated
bodies,
thus
demonstrating
his
audiences
own
evolved
disgust-response
to
bloodshed
and
decay.
The
radical
goals
of
the
program
seemed
to
inhabit
the
events
themselves,
as
if
EvoS
were
actively
courting
the
controversy
surrounding
evolution
in
higher
education.
6
The
programs
unconventional
perspectives
inspired
student
participation
I
had
rarely
witnessed,
in
either
in
undergraduate
or
graduate
school.
Some
organized
research
projects
on
previously
unaddressed
issues
in
evolutionary
studies,
such
as
college
dating,
childhood
bullying,
and
public
education.
They
had
powerful,
personal
commitments
to
resolving
these
issues.
Their
strong
convictions
also
extended
to
the
program
itself,
which
they
described
as
an
intellectual
community
unlike
any
other
they
had
encountered
in
the
university.
The
programs
lectures,
discussions,
lunches,
and
parties
were
marked
by
this
sense
of
a
community.
Organizers
provided
free
pizza
and
beer
to
everyone
attending,
and
praised
participants
(particularly
undergraduates)
for
participating.
Students
helped
to
promote
EvoS
and
its
events
across
the
campus.
They
even
organized
outside
discussion
groups
and
clubs
that
focused
on
evolutionary
themes
in
popular
films
or
addressing
conflicts
between
religion
and
science.
I
saw
that
the
spread
of
this
programs
goals
were
due
in
part
to
the
rewards,
encouragement,
and
inclusivity
that
it
offered
its
members.
As
I
talked
with
more
people,
some
told
me
that
EvoS
(in
their
opinion)
over-
extended
evolutionary
science
into
untenable
disciplines,
such
as
Art
History
or
English.
They
commented
that
the
program
misunderstood
both
evolutionary
science
and
the
disciplines
that
it
wanted
to
transform.
Some
described
EvoS
as
a
kind
of
religion
or
cult,
its
participants
going
to
worship
at
the
feet
of
Darwin.
Yet,
these
same
people
felt
obliged
to
show
their
support
for
the
program,
despite
their
misgivings
about
its
arguments.
They
were
intrigued
(if
sometimes
frustrated)
by
its
ambitious
claims.
They
worried
that
the
program
would
disappear
if
they
stopped
7
attending.
Certainly,
they
were
attracted
by
the
offer
of
free
pizza,
beer,
and
discussion.
But
they
often
left
EvoS
events
complaining
about
a
lack
of
scholarship
or
meaningful
criticism.
They
had
been
invited
to
give
critical
feedback,
but
that
the
programs
lecturers
and
organizers
had
dismissed
it.
It
seemed
that
their
presence
was
important
to
EvoS,
but
its
goals
dictated
the
outcome
of
each
event.
creature,
but
in
other
ways
its
events
were
no
different
from
any
other
university
class
or
seminar.
Students
were
obliged
to
sign
attendance
sheets.
They
wrote
response
papers
on
articles
by
the
visiting
lecturers.
They
received
weekly
grades
for
these
responses,
and
earned
a
letter
grade
at
the
semesters
end.
Like
other
university
classes,
graduate
assistants
performed
the
lions
share
of
grading,
event
preparation,
and
student
consultations.
The
general
decorum
was
also
typical
of
any
college
seminar:
faculty
members
introduced
visiting
speakers,
audiences
applauded
and
saved
their
questions
for
the
lectures
end,
and
discussants
raised
their
hands
and
waited
to
be
acknowledged
before
speaking.
Some
students
fell
asleep
during
lectures,
talked
among
themselves,
or
texted
beneath
their
desks.
Others
left
lectures
early,
hoarded
pizza
and
beer
during
dinner,
or
conspired
with
their
friends
to
sign
their
names
on
attendance
sheets
while
they
skipped
an
event.
For
a
movement
so
intent
on
transforming
higher
education
and
courting
controversy,
EvoS
could
resemble
the
mundane
things
happening
everywhere
else
on
campus.
I
chose
to
examine
EvoS
because
I
found
its
message
provocative
and
its
activities
unusual.
This
movement
intrigues
me
in
part
because
I
am
quite
8
conversant
with
the
science
underlying
its
arguments.
But
I
am
more
interested
in
the
controversy
how
it
is
created,
spread,
utilized,
and
challenged.
As
I
see
it,
the
study
of
controversy
is
important
to
socio-cultural
research
for
two
reasons:
First,
in
the
face
of
ideas
or
practices
that
contradict
their
core
values,
people
tend
to
start
saying
what
those
values
are
(sometimes
loudly).
Unconventional
or
heretical
ways
of
thinking
can
unearth
the
more
elusive
norms
of
a
community.
Second,
controversies
hint
at
the
motion
of
a
socio-cultural
process,
wherein
these
norms
are
challenged,
defended,
reinforced,
or
changed.
To
this
end,
they
mark
dynamic
restructurings
of
the
web
of
relationships,
activities,
values,
and
symbols
constituting
what
many
would
call
culture.
Social
movements
such
as
EvoS
offer
useful
answers
to
the
central
question
of
this
research.
I
approach
this
movement
as
a
case
study
of
a
social
movements
spread
and
endurance,
showing
more
broadly
how
people
introduce
and
circulate
controversial
meanings.
The
EvoS
Program
suggests
that
this
may
take
place
by:
violating
certain
communicational
norms,
establishing
critical
representations
of
opponents,
reaffirming
the
movements
principles
and
goals
as
the
messages
of
all
activities,
and
socializing
newcomers
to
practice
their
own
expressions
of
this
message.
I
should
note
that
EvoS
grapples
with
one
of
the
most
contentious
matters
of
U.S.
society.
The
dispute
over
evolution
and
religion
in
the
U.S.
is
widely
known.
As
many
popular
science
writers
are
quick
to
remind,
this
country
is
unique
among
industrialized
nations
for
its
enduring
argument
over
the
factuality
of
evolutionary
science.
Darwinism
has
additionally
come
under
fire
for
its
assumptions
about
9
gender,
race,
reproduction,
aggression,
and
inequality.
Its
theories
were
employed
as
the
scientific
justification
for
a
variety
of
inhumane
practices
and
policies
during
the
20th
century.
More
broadly,
evolution
is
at
the
center
of
one
of
the
most
long-
standing
uncertainties
in
the
Western
world:
How
much
of
our
social
values
can
be
ascribed
to
(and
possibly
guided
by)
the
natural
order?
No
matter
how
unconventional
or
unusual
I
found
EvoS,
I
was
consistently
reminded
that
its
organizers
and
participants
saw
the
stakes
of
their
struggle
as
very
high.
This
struggle
was
ultimately
over
conflicting
representations
of
human
life
and
the
ultimate
meanings
underlying
its
existence.
Chapter
One
of
this
dissertation
addresses
my
methods
of
analysis,
which
draw
primarily
from
research
and
critiques
in
Social
Movement
Theory,
Linguistic
Anthropology,
Sociolinguistics,
and
Discourse
Analysis.
This
chapter
will
introduce
my
readers
to
the
terms
and
concepts
I
employ
in
this
inquiry.
Chapters
Two
and
Three
familiarize
my
readers
with
the
relevant
ethnographic
information
to
understand
the
EvoS
Program
as
a
social
movement,
including
its
ideologies,
resources,
and
the
movements
overarching
challenge
to
U.S.
higher
education.
Turning
to
my
fieldwork,
in
Chapters
Four,
Five,
and
Six,
I
document
how
these
ideologies,
resources,
and
challenges
are
deployed
in
a
variety
of
institutional
settings.
Lastly,
I
propose
that
the
repeated
invocation
of
new
meanings
across
settings
and
over
time
can
be
seen
as
a
process
of
socialization.
I
argue
that
new
ways
of
interpreting
social
life
must
not
only
be
thought,
but
thoroughly
experienced
by
growing
groups
of
individuals
as
parts
of
their
daily
lives.
10
Note
on
the
Presentation
of
Spoken
Interactions
exhaustive
(and
exhausting)
transcription.
What
our
subjects
say
is
the
evidence
we
use
to
answer
our
own
questions
about
meaning
and
social
organization.
But
how
to
communicate
such
evidence
to
a
broader
readership
is
a
challenge.
Language
is
fascinating,
but
people
usually
speak
in
bursts
and
breaks,
including
dozens
of
utterances
that
are
simply
unconscious
habits.
To
make
my
evidence
as
accessible
as
possible,
I
use
only
two
conventions
when
presenting
spoken
examples:
I
include
these
markers
mostly
for
the
sake
of
accurate
presentation,
but
also
make
clear
when
such
pauses
indicate
an
unfolding,
contextual
pattern.
Because
my
analysis
focuses
on
the
sociolinguistic
introduction
and
spread
of
meanings
over
a
variety
of
contexts,
I
forego
the
more
nuanced
conventions
of
linguistic
transcription.
11
Chapter
One:
Relevant
Fields,
Terms,
and
Data
Collection
This research deals with an important question for studies of the social
dimensions
of
language:
How
do
people
introduce
and
spread
new
meanings
to
the
activities
and
relationships
of
others,
particularly
when
such
interpretations
are
likely
to
be
disputed?
While
this
question
might
(rightly)
invoke
images
of
the
shouting
matches
and
political
punditry,
the
pursuits
of
the
people
I
document
here
are
not
especially
tumultuous.
Their
attempts
at
persuasion
are
often
rather
mundane,
though
directed
toward
unlikely
and
even
contentious
goals.
Certainly,
in
EvoS,
there
are
instances
of
shock,
humor,
criticism,
and
argument.
But,
these
moments
are
often
strategically
employed
toward
persuading
others
that
the
groups
new
interpretations
are
the
most
reasonable
and
undeniable
meanings
of
human
social
life.
12
and
media
spectacle.
Rather,
many
of
the
participant
activities
and
relationships
that
comprise
a
social
movement
are
not
so
dissimilar
from
other
practices
(for
example,
attending
church
or
having
coffee
with
friends).
But,
some
of
these
otherwise
mundane
activities
are
charged
with
the
movements
interpretive
force,
which
is
pointed
to
or
indexed
through
these
very
same
practices.
In
this
way,
the
movements
shared
representations
of
social
reality
its
ideologies
become
sewn
into
the
threads
of
peoples
daily
lives.
While
many
of
the
goings-on
of
a
social
movement
prove
similar
to
the
mundane
activities
of
its
participants
lives,
certainly
the
maintenance
and
spread
of
a
movement
are
not
unsubtle
processes.
Social
movements
strategically
violate
some
normative
practices,
creating
foregroundings
that
highlight
the
significance
of,
say,
having
coffee
with
friends
to
the
overall
goals
of
the
movement.
For
participants,
such
violations
are
grounded
or
contextualized
by
indexing
the
ideologies
of
the
movement.
How
such
patterns
develop
and
how
they
contribute
to
the
maintenance
and
spread
of
a
social
movement,
are
matters
of
the
sociolinguistic
activities
and
relationships
of
its
participants.
1.
Social
Movement
Theory
Since
the
mid-1900s,
the
study
of
social
movements
has
been
largely
the
domain
of
U.S.
sociologists.
More
recently,
however,
research
was
taken
up
within
anthropology
and
area
studies
departments
such
as
Latin
American
Studies,
Pan-
African
Studies,
and
queer
theory.
Recognizing
this
diversity
of
perspectives,
one
may
still
point
out
three,
more
or
less
distinct
schools
of
social
movement
research:
13
Resource
Mobilization
Theory,
Frame
Alignment
Theory,
and
(the
inventively
named)
New
Social
Movement
Theory.
Here,
I
introduce
these
fields
orientations,
discuss
their
shortcomings,
and
explain
how
I
draw
influence
from
both
the
theories
and
critiques.
Resource
Mobilization
Theory.
During
the
1960s
and
1970s,
several
U.S.
sociologists
examined
the
interpersonal
and
economic
assets
underlying
the
inceptions,
spread,
and
(in
some
cases)
collapses
of
social
movements.
Their
interests
stemmed
in
part
from
the
civil
rights
organizations
of
this
era.
However,
their
approach
also
followed
logically
from
sociologys
ongoing
investigations
into
collective
behavior
and
social
conflict
(Park
1967;
Smelser
1962).
They
drew
especially
from
Mancur
Olsons
(1965)
rational
choice
analyses
of
collective
action.
Like
much
of
the
concurrent,
game
theory
research
in
economics
and
political
science,
Resource
Mobilization
confronted
the
problem
of
free-riders
individuals
who
attempt
to
benefit
from
collective
action
but
do
not
contribute
to
the
community
(Gamson
1975;
McCarthy
and
Zald
1977;
Zald
and
Ash
1966;
Zald
and
McCarthy
1975).
Their
focus
fell
on
the
costs
and
benefits
of
participation,
how
movement
organizers
encourage
participation
and
discourage
free-riding,
and
how
funds
and
labor
might
be
motivated
or
(to
wit)
mobilized
toward
collective
action.
Its
theorists
underscored
how
movements
are
maintained
and
spread
by
strategically
engaging
pre-existing
sources
of
money,
labor,
and
interpersonal
obligation.
I
want
to
examine
this
last
point
to
review
how
Resource
Mobilization
theories
have
been
applied.
In
his
analysis
of
the
1848
Sicilian
Revolution,
Charles
14
Tilly
(1973)
argues
that
this
movements
challenge
to
a
regional
social
order
was
simultaneously
dependent
upon
that
same
orders
dominant
assumptions
about
labor
and
capital.
The
movement
tried
to
undermine
the
existing
status
quo,
while
abiding
by
other
norms
for
its
political
and
legal
legitimacy,
procuring
its
funds,
and
attracting
new
participants.
Similarly,
researchers
of
public
protests
(Gamson
1968,
1975;
Turner
1969)
conclude
that
collective
dissent
must
abide
by
some
pre-
existing
norms
so
that
its
goals
will
be
understandable
and
(perhaps)
persuasive
to
outsiders.
Some
critics
argue
that
Resource
Mobilization
privileges
functionalist
models
of
societal
norms
over
more
complex
considerations
of
motives
and
agency
(Benford
1997:418-419;
Escobar
and
Alvarez
1992:5-6;
Friedman
and
McAdam
2002:158).
Others
point
out
that
Resource
Mobilization
favors
a
materialist
approach
that
scrutinizes
money
and
labor
over
other
sociolinguistic
resources
(Cohen
1985;
Snow
and
Oliver
1995:4-10).
These
criticisms
are
valid,
but
it
could
also
be
argued
that
Resource
Mobilization
was
never
aimed
at
answering
these
problems.
Rather,
in
their
own
functionalist
and
materialist
manners,
these
theories
sought
to
normalize
the
organizational
life
of
movements,
seeing
it
as
an
extension
of
organizational
structures
and
behavior
found
elsewhere
in
modern
societies
[].
Movements
push
some
of
the
possibilities
of
existing
cultural
forms
in
new
directions,
to
be
sure,
but
their
cultural
life
is
not
fundamentally
different
in
source
or
mode
of
operation.
[Hart
1992:89]
As
Hart
suggests,
a
movements
people,
money,
labor,
or
meeting
spaces
are
often
reliant
upon
(if
not
appropriated
from)
some
pre-existing
cultural
forms
such
as
governmental
departments,
public
education,
or
religious
establishments.
Further,
15
participants
motives
for
joining
a
movements
activities
may
be
(for
them)
a
reasonable
extension
of
pre-existing
professional,
intellectual,
or
religious
obligations
(Friedman
and
McAdam
2002:162-3).
In
this
sense,
social
movements
often
politicize
the
otherwise
mundane
elements
of
peoples
lives
for
example,
the
labors
they
perform,
their
affiliations
with
other
causes,
or
how
they
spend
their
money.
16
productions
of
(and
conflicts
between)
different
representations
of
social
life.
For
Frame
Alignment
theorists,
social
movements
are
not
viewed
merely
as
carriers
of
extant
ideas
and
meanings
that
grow
automatically
out
of
structural
arrangements
[].
Rather,
movement
actors
are
viewed
as
signifying
agents
actively
engaged
in
the
production
and
maintenance
of
meaning
for
constituents,
antagonists,
and
bystanders
or
observers.
[Benford
and
Snow
2000:613]
Frame
Alignment
theorists
view
social
movements
as
recurring
sets
of
interpretive
possibilities,
which
influence
the
probable
types
of
meanings
introduced
within
participants
interactions
and
relationships
(see
Fisher
1997;
Johnson
and
Noakes
2005;
Snow
2004;
Snow
and
Benford
1992;
Snow
et
al.
1986).
The
framing
of
an
event
sets
the
basis
for
the
kinds
of
comparisons
that
participants
can
make,
and
the
possibilities
for
their
subsequent
actions.
media
to
frame
(or
reframe)
widely
accepted
public
opinions
as
more
problematic
issues.
For
example,
investigating
media
accounts
of
US
anti-nuclear
power
movements
of
the
1970s
and
1980s,
Gamson
and
Modigliani
(1989)
argue
that
activists
succeeded
in
reframing
progress
in
nuclear
technology
as
runaway
progress
(see
also
Gamson
1998).
Activists
can
be
seen
as
engaging
a
pre-existing
framing
of
this
technology
(as
social
and
scientific
advancement),
in
order
to
pose
a
new
interpretive
possibility
technological
advancement
run
amok.
Elsewhere,
reviewing
U.S.
womens
suffrage
movements
at
the
turn
of
the
20th
century,
Hewitt
and
McCammon
(2005)
suggest
that
activists
employed
multiple
frames,
some
of
which
emphasized
gender
stereotypes
of
the
era.
Activists
framed
womens
civil
rights
as
(on
one
hand)
a
matter
of
political
representation,
while
(on
the
other)
a
17
more
conservative
argument
that
women
should
have
a
role
in
politics
because
they
knew
how
to
care
for
people,
including
the
poor,
the
troubled,
and
(especially)
children
(Hewitt
and
McCammon
2005:35).
Womens
suffrage
movements
thus
balanced
their
challenge
with
outsider
perceptions
through
the
two,
contradicting
frames
one
a
call
for
radical
reform,
the
other
a
reaffirmation
of
normative
gender
stereotypes.
Critics argue that Frame Alignment prioritizes the cataloguing of frames and
their
variations,
but
ignores
the
persons
and
processes
that
actually
produce
them.
As
one
critic
points
out,
if
framing
is
seen
as
a
process
of
culture-making
an
active
human
craft
then
the
nature
of
the
craft
and
the
quality
of
the
product
deserve
explicit
attention.
How,
beyond
selecting
for
frame
characteristics
that
will
be
appealing
to
potential
participants,
do
frames
get
made?
What
impact
do
the
craft
products
have,
not
just
on
participants
commitment
to
the
movement,
but
more
significantly
on
their
capacity
to
act
effectively,
the
goals
they
seek,
and
how
they
pursue
them?
[Hart
1992:89]
Frame
Alignment
theorists
may
leave
unexamined
how
framing
is
done
through
sociolinguistic
interaction,
as
well
as
the
power
dynamics
that
might
elicit
particular
interpretations
while
others
are
constrained
or
dismissed
(see
Benford
1997:414-9;
Gamson
2004).
Like
their
predecessors
methodological
dependence
on
rational
choice,
critics
argue,
Frame
Alignment
theorists
isolate
(and
functionalize)
frames
in
ways
that
detach
them
from
their
social
and
historical
origins.
Yet,
like
Resource
Mobilization,
the
contribution
of
Frame
Alignment
lies
in
its
extension
of
the
formers
concern
with
normalizing
social
movements.
The
pre-
existing
resources
(funds,
labor,
spaces,
or
influences)
that
movement
participants
engage
are
likely
also
to
include
ways
of
delivering
their
challenge
to
strike
a
18
responsive
chord
in
that
it
rings
true
with
existing
cultural
narrations
(Snow
and
Benford
1988:210).
Social
movements
find
balances
between
new
and
old
meanings,
such
that
the
interpretive
packages
they
put
forward
represent
views
that
are
by
definition
against
the
grain,
as
they
concern
the
cause
of
the
socially
marginalized
[].
At
the
same
time,
these
interpretive
packages
have
to
sound
natural
and
familiar
to
the
people
addressed.
[dAnjou
and
Van
Male
1998:208]
To
this
end,
no
matter
how
incendiary
its
challenge,
the
representations
employed
within
a
social
movements
activities
will
likely
conform
to
some
pre-existing
communicative
and
interpretive
norms,
while
likely
(and
strategically)
violating
others.
This
is
an
important
contribution
delivered
by
the
Frame
Alignment
theorists,
even
if
their
approach
strayed
from
assessing
the
process
as
an
active
human
craft.
The
latter
concern
would
be
taken
up
by
a
diverse
community
of
researchers
at
the
end
of
the
20th
century.
New
Social
Movement
Theory.
As
they
proliferated
through
the
late
1990s,
academic
studies
of
new
social
movements
branched
into
many
fields,
including
socio-cultural
anthropology,
Latin
American
studies,
gender
studies,
pan-African
Studies,
and
queer
theory.
Much
of
the
motivation
for
New
Social
Movement
studies
can
be
traced
to
interest
in
Identity
Politics
and
its
theorists,
such
as
Spivak
(1988),
Vaid
(1996),
Schlesinger
(1991),
and
Habermas
(1990,
1996).
Considering
these
influences,
this
field
also
differed
from
earlier
investigations
in
a
fundamental
way:
A
conviction
on
the
part
of
its
theorists
that
late-20th
century
social
movements
were
defined
not
by
their
challenges
to
social
orders,
but
rather
the
identities
of
their
participants
(see
Melucci
1988,
1989,
1994).
19
New
Social
Movement
research
attempted
to
document
how
collective
action
arises
from
shared
identities
among
(for
example)
LGBTQ
activists,
disability
rights
movements,
pacifists,
and
environmentalists
(Boggs
1986:39-40;
Kauffman
1990).
In
his
study
of
Dutch
peace
activism,
Bert
Klandermans
(1994)
discusses
how
multiple
socio-political
identities
within
a
single
movement
ultimately
caused
the
movements
fission,
breaking
it
into
non-cooperating
factions
that
respectively
identified
as
primarily
gay,
anarchist,
or
humanist.
New
Social
Movement
perspectives
also
appear
in
ethnographies
on
liberation
movements
that
appropriated
essentialized
identities
as
their
rallying
point.
For
example,
pre-
existing
racial
classifications
(a
common
Blackness)
proved
a
successful,
unifying
focus
for
South
African
anti-Apartheid
movements
(Comaroff
and
Comaroff
1991,
1997),
the
Black
Panthers
(Robnett
2002),
and
Rastafari
activists
in
Jamaica
and
Britain
(Smith
1994).
People
who
feel
themselves
as
marginalized
by
widely
accepted
social
categories
may
make
use
of
these
categories
to
strategically
meet
their
own
ends.
On
this
point,
Judith
Butler
argues:
[C]onventional
and
exclusionary
norms
of
universality
can,
through
perverse
reiterations,
produce
unconventional
formulations
of
universality
that
expose
the
limited
and
exclusionary
features
of
the
former
one
at
the
same
time
that
they
mobilize
a
new
set
of
demands.
[Butler
2000:39-40]
New
Social
Movement
researchers
thus
direct
attention
to
the
ways
that
peoples
pre-existing
identities
may
be
politicized
through
collective
action.
Movements
might
strategically
borrow
(and
transform)
essentialized,
socio-political
categories
to
express
a
unified
identity.
20
Critics
argue
that
the
charged
intellectual
and
political
convictions
of
New
Social
Movement
theorists
upset
the
neutrality
of
their
research.
For
example,
theorists
sometimes
romanticized
movements
as
resisting
Westernization
or
neo-
liberal
capitalism,
ascribing
anti-establishment
or
anti-materialist
identities
to
the
subjects
of
their
studies,
whether
or
not
such
claims
are
ever
made
(Pichardo
1997:414-420;
Plotke
1990).
New
Social
Movement
theorists
could
also
downplay
the
practical
demands
of
social
movement
maintenance
(such
as
funding
and
labor),
while
simultaneously
exaggerating
the
movements
transcendence
of
these
materialist
concerns
(Alvarez
and
Escobar
1992;
Alvarez
et
al.
1998;
Earl
2004).
An
unsurprising
result
has
been
a
preponderance
of
work
prioritizing
Leftist
social
movements,
while
more
politically
conservative
resistance
is
either
ignored
or
disparaged
(Buechler
1995:449-451;
Pichardo
1997:426;
Tarrow
1991).
On
these
matters,
New
Social
Movement
theorists,
like
their
predecessors,
tend
to
decontextualize
what
they
study
from
its
social
and
historical
circumstances.
Yet,
I
want
to
highlight
how
this
field
of
social
movement
research
builds
upon
the
lessons
of
Resource
Mobilization
and
Frame
Alignment
Theory.
To
the
growing
list
of
pre-existing
forms
(funds,
labor,
space,
influence,
meaning,
and
language
use)
that
a
social
movement
might
strategically
engage,
participants
self-
identifications
might
also
be
borrowed
in
to
a
movements
activities
and
relationships.
While
participants
identities
cannot
be
assumed
a
priori,
the
ways
that
they
regularly
identify
(for
example,
their
ethnic
backgrounds,
sexual
orientations,
or
professional
obligations)
may
overlap
with
a
movements
goals.
Present
and
future
participants
might
see
their
engagement
as
a
logical
or
necessary
21
extension
of
their
identities
or
how
others
tend
to
categorize
them.
In
this
sense,
by
appropriating
pre-existing
social
categories
and
self-identifications,
a
social
movement
might
increase
its
coherence
to
broader
audiences.
that
will
shape
my
analysis:
First,
while
critics
are
correct
that
participant
motives
are
often
dismissed
in
past
research,
any
inquiry
into
social
movements
must
attend
to
their
material
necessities.
Movements
require
funding,
places
to
meet,
public
attention,
and
avenues
of
political
and
legal
influence
all
elements
that
will
influence
the
groups
activities
and
its
participants
relationships.
Second,
as
Frame
Alignment
theorists
demonstrate,
the
language
and
media
utilized
by
a
movement
should
be
included
among
these
resources.
Insofar
as
the
goals
of
a
movement
will
often
be
intangible
changes
of
public
opinion,
the
messages
that
it
projects
(both
inward
and
outward)
is
central
to
their
maintenance
and
spread.
Third,
following
New
Social
Movement
theorists,
the
identities
and
social
classifications
of
movement
participants
are
not
only
essential
considerations
in
assessing
their
motivations,
but
should
be
considered
as
further
resources
that
movements
harness
to
meet
their
aims.
Finally,
and
most
important,
social
movements
balance
pre-existing
resources
(funds,
language,
identities,
and
so
on)
with
views
that
are
by
definition
against
the
grain
(dAnjou
and
Van
Male
1998:208).
The
activities
and
relationships
of
social
movements
are
often
mundane,
but
mundane
in
a
quite
strategic
way:
On
one
hand,
social
movements
must
engage
established
norms
in
order
to
exist
(procuring
funds,
setting
schedules,
attracting
participants,
etc.)
On
the
other,
they
22
are
actively
politicizing
the
mundane
in
ways
that
charge
participants
daily
activities
and
relationships
with
representations
of
social
reality
that
diverge
from
accepted
interpretations.
To
this
end,
any
investigation
of
social
movements
is
also
an
inquiry
into
ideology
and
how
it
is
indexed
in
sociolinguistic
practice,
to
which
I
turn
next.
2.
Indexicality
and
Ideology
Indexicality and ideology are two concepts key to this research. Both are
complex,
and
as
I
have
found
through
numerous
trials,
neither
can
be
written
about
without
the
other
surfacing,
in
one
way
or
another.
Discussions
of
topics
cannot
be
readily
broken
up
by
historical
schools
of
thought
or
academic
disciplines.
This
said,
I
begin
here
with
a
discussion
of
the
scholarship
on
indexicality,
as
it
offers
useful
tools
to
introduce
theories
of
ideology
that
prioritize
language
use
and
social
life.
I
conclude
the
parts
of
this
discussion
by
returning
to
consider
the
importance
of
indexicality
and
ideology
(respectively)
to
inquiries
into
social
movements.
To
offer
definitions
of
both,
my
discussion
of
these
two
terms
will
necessarily
be
more
integrative
and
concept-driven
than
my
outline
of
social
movement
theories.
23
Sapir
1985
[1929],
1985
[1933];
Silverstein
1979;
Whorf
1940,
1956[1939]).
Further,
to
dismiss
language
as
a
naming
system
makes
an
unexamined
mystery
of
the
creative
potential
of
language
to
transform
situations
from
one
caliber
of
reality
to
another
(Austin
1962,
1971;
Searle
1976).
Such
transformations
take
place
in
countless
examples
through
the
official
or
sacred
utterances
of
legal
trials,
political
inaugurations,
police
arrests,
marriage
ceremonies,
or
baptisms.
Finally,
in
prioritizing
the
referential
function
of
language
(its
encoding
of
a
reality),
this
popular
viewpoint
sidesteps
discourse
the
histories,
proprieties,
inequalities,
and
other,
often-unstated
elements
of
social
life
that
make
interpersonal
interactions
into
meaningful
events
(Duranti
2006;
Sherzer
1987;
Urban
1991).
Looking
at
such
active
functions
of
language
-
its
creative,
transformative,
and
discursive
potential
compels
a
researcher
to
examine
its
relation
to
social
life,
and
thus
consider
how
language
signals
or
indexes
sociocultural
information
at
the
level
of
particular
communicative
events
(Ochs
1990:292,
original
emphasis).
In
its
most
easily
grasped
formation,
indexicality
refers
to
the
function
of
language
through
which
people
signal
sociocultural
information
about
the
interaction-at-
hand.
Insofar
as
any
act
of
representation
involves
a
context-bound
social
actor
who
does
the
signaling,
that
signifying
act
additionally
points
back
to
that
actor,
the
listeners,
and
the
interactional
circumstances.
Indexical
signs
point
to
meanings
of
the
act,
itself
(Mertz
2007;
Nunberg
1993;
Parmentier
1985;
Silverstein
1976,
1998,
2003).
Indexicals
are
thus
fluidly
shifting
from
interaction
to
interaction:
[w]hen
you
use
the
word
I
it
designates
you;
when
I
use
the
same
word,
it
designates
me.
If
you
use
you
talking
to
me,
it
designates
me
[].
Different
utterances
of
the
same
indexical
designate
different
things,
because
what
is
designated
depends
not
only
on
the
meaning
24
associated
with
the
expression,
but
also
on
facts
about
the
utterance.
An
utterance
of
I
designates
the
person
who
utters
it;
an
utterance
of
you
designates
the
person
to
whom
it
is
addressed,
an
utterance
of
here
designates
the
place
at
which
the
utterance
is
made,
and
so
forth.
[Perry
1997:586]
So,
indexicals
perform
the
deceptively
simple
task
of
pointing
to
an
interactions
participants,
places,
times,
and
other
information
that
orients
these
references
as
particular
phenomena
in
social
reality
(Lyons
1972:
75-80;
Mukarovsky
1977
[1940]:
81-97;
Silverstein
1979).
Insofar
as
such
phenomena
are
indexed
in
relation
to
other
persons,
times,
places
(and
so
on),
a
network
of
social
realities
is
simultaneously
engaged
and
juxtaposed
to
the
situation-at-hand.
What
is
indexed
during
any
interaction
will
(obviously)
be
unique
to
the
circumstances.
A
list
of
such
elements
could
potentially
be
infinite,
shaped
by
the
participants
and
their
roles,
their
interpersonal
histories,
institutional
expectations,
the
time
of
day,
the
participants
health
and
emotional
states,
and
so
on.
As
Michael
Silverstein
comments,
once
we
recognize
that
the
realities
of
meaningful
social
practices
emerge
from
the
experience
of
indexical
semiotic
processes,
we
should
resign
ourselves
to
enjoying
the
fact
that
it's
indexicality
all
the
way
down
(1992:314).
Given
this
infinity
of
possible
indexes,
very
many
of
them
will
be
deeply
presupposed
within
(and
previous
to)
any
interaction.
That
is,
most
potential
indices
will
remain
unexamined
and
un-commented-upon
by
participants.
The
presuppositions
shared
within
(for
example)
conversations
between
parents
and
their
adult
children
are
so
well
understood
by
all
parties
that
attending
to,
or
vocalizing
them
would
be
absurd.
As
Silverstein
further
suggests:
Such
defaults
give
parties
an
idea
of
determinate
contextualization
for
indexicals
in
the
particular
phase
of
interaction
at
issue.
Participants
25
can
presuppose
that
they
share
a
contextualizing
interpretation
according
to
interested
positions
or
perspectives
that
follow
on
some
social
fact
such
as
group
membership,
condition
in
society,
or
achieved
commonalty
of
interests.
[Silverstein
1998:1280]
An
astounding
amount
of
detail
in
every
social
interactions
is
deeply
presupposed
by
participants,
and
further
that
it
is
necessary
that
people
do
not
critically
reflect
upon
such
defaults,
because
doing
so
would
make
social
interactions
and
relationships
incredibly
difficult,
if
not
impossible
(Hawkes
1977:
44-59;
Shen
2006;
Shklovsky
1965
[1917];
Short
1973;
van
Peer
1986).
Considering
the
vast
amount
of
information
that
could
conceivably
be
(intentionally
or
unintentionally)
invoked
within
an
interaction,
this
linguistic
function
could
include
indices
of
far
more
complex
natures.
Certain
presuppositions
play
a
more
or
less
essential
role
in
an
interaction,
and
would
be
more
or
less
likely
to
structure
it.
A
parents
conversation
with
his
or
her
adult
child
would
likely
be
roundly
influenced
by
the
formers
assumed
responsibility
to
correct
the
childs
behavior
(despite
the
childs
protest
Mom!
Im
an
adult
now!).
Considering
more
news-worthy
issues,
the
ways
in
which
persons
engage
in
sociolinguistic
activity
could
index
(real
or
affected)
socio-political
identities
such
as
race
and
ethnicity
(Buckholtz
2001;
Labov
1972;
Urciuoli
1996;
Wilson
2002),
gender
(Cameron
1988;
Silverstein
1985),
socioeconomic
class
(Agha
2003,
2005;
Mertz
1985);
or
nationality
(Gal
1991;
Silverstein
2000;
Woolard
2004).
Linguistic
anthropology
and
sociolinguistics
dealsextensively
with
the
semiotic
processes
through
which
indexicals
point
to
various
interpersonal
categories,
particularly
the
work
of
Judith
Irvine
and
Susan
Gal
(Gal
1998,
2005;
Gal
and
Irvine
1995;
Irvine
1996,
1998,
2004,
2005;
Irvine
and
Gal
2000).
Further,
researchers
examine
how
indices
marking
the
26
belonging
(or
otherness)
of
language
users
in
sociopolitical
categories
can
motivate
persons
toward
individual
or
collective
action,
for
example,
within
US
English
Only
movements
(Silverstein
1996;
Woolard
and
Schieffelin
1994).
Such
social
categorizations
are
often
the
fuel
for
heated
controversy,
but
many
of
the
indices
that
point
to
them
will
be
(more
or
less)
presupposed
by
the
persons
doing
the
interpreting.
Languages
indexical
function
is
clearly
important
to
understand
how
people
experience
the
infinite
possible
presuppositions
of
their
social
activities
and
relationships.
Yet,
just
as
clearly,
people
use
their
activities
and
relationships
to
introduce
new,
unlikely,
or
surprising
information
(for
example,
Mom!
Im
an
adult
now!).
In
this
sense,
the
unfolding
of
indexicals
may
also
thrust
lesser-presupposed
(or
creative)
elements
into
interactions
(Haviland
2005;
Irvine
1996;
Lee
1997:41-
65;
Mertz
2007;
Mertz
and
Wessbourd
1985).
As
Silverstein
(1976:
18-20,
1979:212-217)
explains,
prime
examples
of
creative
indexicals
appear
with
performatives,
originally
described
by
J.L.
Austin
as
what
we
bring
about
or
achieve
by
saying
something
(1962:108),
such
as
I
promise
that
or
I
give
you
my
word
that.
These
performative
utterances
creatively
index
new
information
into
an
interaction
by
simultaneously
saying
and
doing
what
is
being
said
(promising
or
swearing),
and
thus
introduce
a
new
network
of
conventions
and
relationships
into
the
interaction.
To
this
end,
creative
indexes
can
be
said
not
so
much
to
change
the
context,
as
to
make
explicit
and
overt
the
parameters
of
structure
of
the
ongoing
events
(Silverstein
1976:34).
27
As
is
likely
already
apparent,
the
interplay
between
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals
will
be
useful
to
consider
in
examining
the
introduction,
maintenance,
and
spread
of
meanings
by
social
movements.
I
argue
above
that
social
movements
adhere
to
or
abide
by
some
established
norms,
while
strategically
diverging
from
others
by
introducing
unconventional
views
and/or
challenging
some
existing
state
of
affairs.
The
many
of
the
interpersonal
activities
and
relationships
of
social
movements
(like
social
life
at
large)
will
consist
of
presupposed
indexicals,
that
look
and
sound
like
those
of
the
surrounding
sociolinguistic
contexts.
That
is,
much
of
the
time,
participants
will
adhere
to
many
interactional
conventions
(respect
for
authority,
politeness,
taking
turnings
speaking,
etc.)
and
rely
on
many
presupposed
facts
about
their
relationships
and
obligations.
They
do
so
because
these
are
the
ways
that
people
interact
whether
or
not
these
actions
explicitly
benefit
the
movement.
On
the
other
hand,
social
movement
participants
will
be
much
invested
in
creatively
indexing
new
(and
typically
controversial)
information
into
an
increasing
number
(and
increasing
diversity)
of
interactions,
thus
maintaining
and
spreading
the
movements
views.
Broadly,
I
am
proposing
that
the
language
(and
other
signifying
practices)
of
social
movements
can
be
examined
with
the
concepts
that
linguists
use
to
study
social
life
in
general.
Participants
activities
and
relationships
will
be
composed
of
an
interplay
between
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals,
relying
on
some
widespread
understandings
of
social
life,
while
expressly
contesting
others.
Such
a
prediction,
however,
begs
the
question:
What
is
the
nature
of
the
information
that
is
being
indexed?
I
turn
to
this
question
below.
28
inquiries,
and
treatises
on
what
exactly
ideology
might
mean
are
probably
outnumbered
by
those
detailing
the
failure
to
come
to
any
operational
definition
at
all
(for
example,
see
Adorno
1972;
Eagleton
1991;
Geuss
1984;
Kennedy
1979;
Thompson
1990).
I
do
not
intend
to
add
to
the
latter
here,
except
to
say
that
the
capriciousness
of
the
term
is
largely
due
to
(on
one
hand)
its
capacity
to
potentially
subsume
every
facet
of
human
activity
as
an
example
of
ideological
behavior,
and
(on
the
other)
its
seemingly
unavoidable
nature
as
a
non-neutral
concept.
I
hope
to
show
here
that
both
these
qualities,
however
problematic,
are
quite
useful
that
the
utility
of
the
term
lies
in
its
capacity
to
discriminate
between
those
power
struggles
which
are
somehow
central
to
a
whole
form
of
social
life,
and
those
which
are
not
(Eagleton
1991:8).
There
are
many
possible
dangers
of
wielding
such
a
conceptual
tool
(but
then
any
craftsperson
would
tell
us
that
good
tools
are
also
dangerous
ones).
Here,
I
detail
the
more
productive
assessments
of
ideologys
social
functions
and
manifestations,
before
returning
to
discuss
how
this
concept
relates
both
indexicality
and
social
movements.
Socio-cultural
anthropologists,
discourse
analysts,
and
linguists
tend
to
approach
ideologies
as
shared
representations
of
social
reality.
They
are
shared
insofar
as
they
are
regularly
indexed
as
the
presuppositions
of
peoples
interpersonal
activities
and
relationships
(Abu-Lughod
and
Lutz
1990;
Lutz
1988:53-80;
Moore
2007:23-42;
Sahlins
1976:126-165;
Van
Dijk
2006).
The
researchers
task,
as
Clifford
Geertz
argues,
lies
in
searching
out
and
analyzing
the
symbolic
forms
words,
images,
institutions,
behaviors
in
terms
of
which,
in
each
29
place,
people
actually
represent
themselves
to
themselves
and
to
one
another
(1974:30).
For
example,
in
his
analysis
of
Tallensi
kinship
systems,
Meyer
Fortes
writes
the
ideology
of
kinship
is
so
dominant
in
Tale
society,
and
the
web
of
genealogical
connexions
[sic]
so
extensive,
that
no
social
relationships
or
events
fall
completely
outside
the
orbit
of
kinship
(1949:338-340).
Similarly,
Edmund
Leach
(1954:213-254)
explains
that
individuals
who
emerge
as
chiefs
among
the
traditionally
non-hierarchical
Kachin
(of
then
Northeastern
Burma)
adopt
the
mannerisms
and
rituals
of
the
Buddhist
princes
of
the
adjacent
Shan
monarchies.
As
Leach
contends,
the
Kachin
chiefs
are
not
only
adopting
a
set
of
behaviors,
but
shifting
from
one
ideology
to
another
from
the
Kachins
egalitarian
gumlao
to
the
stratified,
hierarchical
gumsa
of
the
Shan
(Leach
1954:197-212).
For
Fortes
and
Leach,
as
well
as
many
other
social
scientists,
the
ideologies
that
explain
and
facilitate
social
relationships
are
encoded
representations
of
external
reality,
though
only
partially
visible
to
the
people
studied.
However,
some
critics
see
this
stance
on
ideology
as
an
exaggeration
of
the
researchers
role
in
decoding
the
totality
of
peoples
social
lives.
As
Talal
Asad
argues,
the
anthropologists
text
claims
for
itself
the
ability
to
represent
that
external
reality
directly,
or
to
reproduce
that
inner
experience
through
very
different
symbols
which
are
nevertheless
assumed
to
be
appropriate
abilities
which
the
exotic
peoples
studied
necessarily
lack.
[1979:621]
The
analysis
of
ideology
cannot
(or
just
should
not)
ignore
the
active
role
that
people
take
in
representing
their
social
realities
through
their
signifying
practices.
30
In
this
sense,
ideology
is
an
emergent
element
within
the
indexical
functions
of
language
(Cameron
2006;
Silverstein
1979).
As
V.N.
Voloinov
argues
the
ideological,
as
such,
cannot
possibly
be
explained
in
terms
of
either
[]
superhuman
or
subhuman,
animalian,
roots.
Its
real
place
in
existence
is
in
the
special,
social
material
of
signs
created
by
man.
Its
specificity
consists
precisely
in
its
being
located
between
organized
individuals,
in
its
being
the
medium
of
their
communication.
[Voloinov
1986[1929]:12]
To
this
end,
an
ideologys
mediating
influence
is
to
make
a
meaning
stick
(Thompson
1984:132,
original
emphasis).
Ideology
in
this
sense
can
be
thought
of
as
semiotic
closure
finalizing
presuppositions,
discourage
criticism,
and
encouraging
a
sense
of
certainty
about
the
meanings
of
peoples
experiences
and
actions
(Eagleton
1991:193-220;
Hall
1982;
Pcheux
1975).
As
Rosalind
Coward
and
John
Ellis
suggest,
ideology
is
an
articulation
of
the
fixed
relations
of
representation
to
a
specific
organization
of
reality,
relations
which
establish
the
positions
that
it
is
possible
for
the
individual
to
inhabit
within
the
social
totality
(1977:78).
The
effect
of
ideology
in
interpersonal
interactions
is
thus
between
indexed
presuppositions
of
social
reality
and
how
people
experience
their
activities
and
relationships.
The
semiotic
closure
effected
by
ideology
introduces
this
concepts
relationship
with
power.
As
is
now
nearly
commonplace
to
observe
in
the
social
sciences:
to
assert
the
meaning
of
some
experience
(its
truth,
falsity,
profanity,
heresy,
logic,
constitutionality,
etc.)
is
to
exercise
power
(Dreyfuss
and
Rabinow
1982:184-204).
As
Eric
Wolf
proposes,
[p]ower
is
implicated
in
meaning
through
its
role
in
upholding
one
version
of
significance
as
true,
fruitful,
or
beautiful,
against
other
possibilities
that
may
threaten
truth,
fruitfulness,
or
beauty.
All
31
cultures,
however
conceived,
carve
out
significance
and
try
to
stabilize
it
against
possible
alternatives.
In
human
affairs,
things
might
be
different
and
often
are
[].
Hence,
symbolic
work
is
never
done,
achieves
no
final
solution.
The
cultural
assertion
that
the
world
is
shaped
in
this
way
and
not
in
some
other
has
to
be
repeated
and
enacted,
lest
it
be
questioned
and
denied.
[1990:593]
Interpersonal
productions
of
meaning
thus
rely
on
ideologies
to
solidify
(on
one
hand)
interpretations
of
social
life
and
(on
the
other)
the
legitimacy
of
these
interpretations
as
authoritative,
truthful,
sage-like,
etc.
Ideologies
may
perform
a
related
function,
stabilizing
the
meanings
of
people
as
well
as
their
actions
and
relationships.
Through
the
ideologies
of
(for
example)
citizenship
or
law,
people
come
to
understand
themselves
and
one
another
as
subjects
within
a
representation
of
social
life,
identifying
them
as
particular
kinds
of
people.
This
perspective
on
ideology
was
the
focus
for
several
late
20th
century
political
philosophers,
particularly
Louis
Althusser
(2008
[1971])
and
Ernesto
Laclau
(1979,
1997).
In
his
essay
Ideology
and
the
State
Apparatus,
Althusser
argues
that
the
central
function
of
political,
religious,
and
educational
ideologies
is
to
motivate
people
to
consider
themselves
as
beings
whose
personhood
is
more-or-
less
realized
within
these
institutions.
The
important
function
of
ideology
is
not
its
capacity
to
represent
a
totality
of
social
life,
but
to
ground
persons
consciousness
within
these
representations,
in
a
sense
ideologizing
identity
and
everyday
experience.
Yet,
critics
challenge
the
overreliance
on
such
a
perspective
as
dismissing
the
possibility
and
the
reality
of
social
change
(Abercrombie
and
Turner
1978;
Abercrombie
et
al.
1984;
Parsons
1967[1959]).
For
example,
Stuart
Hall
comments
that
the
theory
of
ideology
offered
by
Althusser
and
others
32
tended
to
present
the
process
as
too
uni-accentual,
too
functionally
adapted
to
the
reproduction
of
the
dominant
ideology
[].
Indeed,
it
was
difficult,
from
the
base-line
of
this
theory,
to
discern
how
anything
but
the
'dominant
ideology'
could
ever
be
reproduced
in
discourse.
[Hall
1982:78]
Ascribing
such
a
uni-accentual
quality
to
ideology
sidesteps
the
fact
that
ideologies
and
social
organizations
can
and
do
change
(for
better
or
worse),
typically
through
challenges
to
the
logic
of
some
dominant
ideology.
This
observation
is
much
in
keeping
with
Pierre
Bourdieus
(1977:159-197)
explication
of
doxa,
heterodoxy,
and
orthodoxy
here
summarized
by
Eagleton:
Much
in
keeping
with
Bourdieus
argument
(but
shedding
its
loaded
terms),
I
wish
here
to
introduce
the
concepts
of
ideological
scope
and
strength
(Giddens
1984:5-
24;
Glick
2009:7-9;
Kroskrity
1998,
2000).
In
the
former
(greater
scope),
an
ideology
is
widely
presupposed
across
a
diverse
number
of
interactional
contexts.
In
the
latter
(greater
strength),
it
is
relatively
limited
to
a
specific
group
or
target
population
and
could
be
creatively
indexed
in
tense,
antagonistic
contrast
to
ideologies
with
greater
indexical
scope.
The
instances
in
which
ideologies
of
particular
significance
are
explicitly
indexed
are
those
in
which
one
representation
of
social
reality
is
challenged
by
others,
leading
to
confusion
and
controversy.
On
this,
Clifford
Geertz
notes:
33
It
is
a
loss
of
orientation
that
most
directly
gives
rise
to
ideological
activity,
an
inability,
for
lack
of
usable
models,
to
comprehend
the
universe
of
civic
rights
and
responsibilities
in
which
one
finds
oneself
located
[].
Whatever
else
ideologies
may
be
projections
of
unacknowledged
fears,
disguises
for
ulterior
motives,
phatic
expressions
of
group
solidarity
they
are,
most
distinctively,
maps
of
problematic
social
reality
and
matrices
for
the
creation
of
collective
conscience.
[1973:219-220]
The
usefulness
of
this
observation
lies
in
its
predictive
value,
allowing
us
to
seek
out
such
losses
of
orientation
in
various
interactional
controversies
(for
example,
not
coincidentally,
in
the
activities
of
social
movements).
There,
ideologies
of
differing
scope
and
strength
conflict
with
one
another.
Such
phenomena
seem
likely
to
include
creatively
and
perhaps
loudly
indexed
ideologies
dealing
with,
as
Eagleton
says,
power
struggles
which
are
somehow
central
to
a
whole
form
of
social
life
(1991:12).
34
human
nature,
its
perspective
on
human
history,
its
conception
of
justice,
its
view
of
optimal
human
relations,
its
principled
view
of
property,
power,
privilege
and
punishment,
and
its
vision
of
the
human
future
(1996:168).
Such
ideologies
are
paralleled
by
a
concurrent
domain
of
in-house
ideologies
(1996:169,
my
emphasis),
wherein
the
first
principle
is
operationalized,
and
individuals
already
familiar
with
the
groups
first
principle
index
their
representations
of
the
groups
immediate
convictions,
goals,
and
challenges.
Sussers
most
relevant
contribution
to
social
movement
research
is
a
trio
of
enterprises
that
are
more
action-oriented
or
social
forces:
First,
as
a
socializing
force,
ideology
functions
to
initiate
new-comers
into
the
group,
educating
them
on
the
obligations
of
participating,
the
decorum
of
interaction,
and
(of
course)
the
in-
house
ideologies
and
first
principles
of
the
group.
Second,
ideology
as
a
mobilizing
force
is
focused
on
the
loyalty
and
commitment
of
the
groups
participants,
representing
to
them
a
social
reality
that
inspires
individuals
toward
collective
engagement.
Such
an
ideological
domain
will
play
a
marked
role
in
social
movement
activities
and
relationships.
Finally,
as
a
legitimizing
force,
ideology
imparts
coherence
and
ritual
to
a
groups
long-standing
participants.
On
the
matter
of
legitimacy,
Susser
cautions:
This
is
not
to
say
that
ideology
in
its
legitimizing
role
operates
only
in
well-established
polities.
A
radical
ideology
whose
purpose
it
is
to
delegitimize
a
political
system
must
simultaneously
legitimize
itself
in
the
eyes
of
its
own
stalwarts.
It
too
must
sustain
commitment,
induce
compliance,
and
foster
organizational
stability.
Indeed,
despite
their
revolutionary
rhetoric,
radical
ideologies
must
also
seek
legitimation
among
their
own
faithful.
In
this
they
are
often
as
conformity
seeking
and
orthodoxy-bound
as
centrist/
conservative
creeds.
[1996:171]
The
authors
comment
here
dovetails
greatly
with
many
details
I
have
already
given
35
about
social
movements.
Along
with
distinctions
of
ideologies
relative
scope
and
strength,
Sussers
domains
will
prove
useful
in
my
analysis
of
the
language
and
ideologies
of
movement
participants.
Concluding
this
discussion
of
indexicality
and
ideology,
I
will
here
offer
a
working
definition
of
ideology
that
focuses
on
the
indexical
functions
of
language
and
synthesizes
the
most
useful
of
the
theories
of
ideology
I
examine
above.
First,
let
me
reiterate
that
ideologies
are
shared
representations
of
social
reality,
presupposed
or
creatively
indexed
by
people
in
sociolinguistic
interaction
to
stabilize,
solidify,
or
otherwise
semiotically
close
the
meanings
they
ascribe
to
their
experiences.
Second,
ideologies
may
be
said
to
show
relatively
greater
scope
(if
they
are
indexed
widely
across
a
wide
population
or
diverse
number
of
groups)
or
greater
strength
(if
they
are
indexed
more
narrowly
by
a
socio-politically
distinct
group).
The
interplay
of
such
categories
of
ideologies
will
likely
be
a
defining
factor
within
the
language
and
ideologies
of
social
movements.
Third,
along
with
distinguishing
ideologies
of
relatively
greater
strength
or
scope,
they
may
further
be
examined
as
discursive
domains
of
group
activities
and
relationships.
These
ideological
domains
are
first
principles,
in-house
ideologies,
and
social
forces
(socialization,
mobilization,
and
legitimization).
Finally,
the
instances
of
creatively
indexed
ideologies
will
be
especially
high
when
controversial
social
behaviors
come
to
the
forefront
of
public
consciousness.
Social
movements
seem
a
worthwhile
object
for
just
this
kind
of
investigation.
As
I
have
reiterated
throughout
this
chapter,
the
sociolinguistic
lives
of
social
movements
will
also
likely
follow
similar
patterns
as
those
in
any
other
arena
of
their
participants
lives.
This
said,
as
I
36
examine
in
the
final
section
of
this
chapter,
social
movements
would
also
seek
to
creatively
index
their
own
ideologies
against
those
of
the
institutions
that
they
challenge.
I
turn
now
to
ask
just
how
such
creative
indices
can
be
analyzed.
3.
Sociolinguistic
Foregroundings
and
Contextualizations
I
am
now
narrowing
in
on
the
specific
objects
of
study
that
will
inform
this
research.
These
are
the
sociolinguistic
patterns
that
regularly
index
social
movement
ideologies
into
novel
settings,
or
patterns
of
foregrounding
and
contextualization.
Below,
I
address
these
two
concepts,
taking
care
to
understand
their
strengths
and
the
critical
perspectives
on
their
shortcomings.
I
conclude
by
integrating
them
into
my
overall
discussion
of
ideology,
indexicality,
and
social
movements.
Foregrounding.
Foregroundings
are
uses
of
language
or
gesture
that
deviate
from
or
violate
some
setting-specific
presupposition
of
communication.
They
typically
do
this
by
distorting
or
omitting
some
presupposed
element
or
including
some
relatively
unforeseen
action.
For
example,
linguistic
foregroundings
might
include
purposefully
ungrammatical
phrases,
affected
accents,
shouting,
obscenities,
or
pointed
silences
all
are,
of
course,
relative
to
their
context-specific
uses
and
interpretations.
The
origin
of
foregrounding
theory
is
traced
to
Russian
Formalists
argument
that
the
social
function
of
art
is
ostranenie
to
make
strange
the
presupposed
ideologies
and
overly-familiar
aspects
of
daily
life
(Shklovsky
1965[1925]).
The
Formalist
argument
was
later
(perhaps
independently)
developed
by
German
playwright
Bertolt
Brecht
as
the
alienation
effect
(verfremdung)
of
revolutionary
37
theatre,
which
would
challenge
the
ideologies
of
bourgeois
Europeans
by
alienating
the
familiar
(Brecht
1964b:192).
Put
to
this
use,
art
reveals
itself
as
a
representation
for
example,
as
Brecht
suggests,
when
actors
break
the
fourth
wall
to
directly
speak
to
an
audience.
Art
is
thus
purported
to
alienate
(and
subsequently
liberate)
its
audience
from
the
ideologies
that
benefit
the
ruling
class
(Hawkes
1977:63;
Jameson
1972:58).
Taking
up
the
methodology,
but
not
the
politics
of
Russian
Formalism,
Structuralists
in
the
Prague
Linguistic
Circle
thought
of
foregrounding
as
a
purposeful
violation
of
familiar
or
automatized
means
of
communicating,
such
as
introducing
rhyming
patterns
or
alliteration
within
the
text
of
a
newspaper
article
(Havranek
1964;
Mukaovsk
1964).
Some
uses
of
language,
poetic
language
in
particular,
are
thus
aimed
at
deepening
the
aesthetic
experience
of
a
reader
or
listener,
as
most
famously
argued
by
Roman
Jackobson
(1960,
1966).
As
a
result
of
violations
of
presupposed
communicative
norms,
listeners
and
readers
are
forced
to
come
to
grips
with
the
world
of
the
text
in
a
more
strenuous
and
supposedly
more
rewarding
fashion
(Van
Peer
1986:2).
More
recently,
Geoffrey
Leech
offers
a
more
phenomenological
definition:
Foreground
suggests
the
figure/ground
opposition
of
gestalt
psychology:
the
patterns
of
normal
language
are
relevant
to
literary
art
only
in
providing
a
background
for
the
structured
deployment
of
deviations
from
the
norm
(2008:18).
Many
language
theorists
similarly
argue
that
a
foregrounded
linguistic
form
or
act
is,
in
M.A.K.
Hallidays
straightforward
words,
prominence
that
is
motivated
(1971:339).
38
As
is
apparent
in
Formalism
and
Structuralism,
there
persists
within
theories
of
foregrounding
a
dialectical
distinction
between
ordinary
and
deviant
uses
of
language.
The
former
is
(more
or
less)
assumed
as
the
socio-cultural
preconditions
for
successful
communication,
while
the
latter
violations
of
communicative
norms
are
elevated
to,
as
Ren
Wellek
critiques,
a
kind
of
counter-grammar,
a
science
of
discards
(1960:417).
That
is,
the
catalogue
of
violations
might
be
compelling,
but
its
assumptions
about
normal
speech
leave
that
particular
phenomenon
unexamined,
thus
presuming
that
much
of
sociolinguistic
activity
is
uninteresting
and
dedicated
to
the
bare
reporting
of
thought.
Attempting
to
resolve
this
criticism,
Stanley
Fish
argues
that
there
is
no
such
thing
as
ordinary
language,
at
least
in
the
nave
sense
often
intended
by
that
term:
an
abstract
formal
system,
which
[]
is
only
used
incidentally
for
purposes
of
human
communication
(1973:49).
Dispensing
with
the
notion
of
ordinary
language,
investigations
must
turn
to
the
presuppositions
that
people
actually
index
in
their
interactions
a
matter
of
research,
not
theory.
On
one
hand,
foregroundings
simultaneously
index
a
background
of
orthodox
or
traditional
forms
of
communicating.
On
the
other,
they
function
as
deviations
from
(or
agitations
directed
toward)
this
normative
background.
Research
into
violations
of
communicational
norms
is
simultaneously
tasked
with
detailing
the
normative
presuppositions
of
communication
as
they
are
indexed
through
foregrounded
language
use.
In
this
sense,
deviation
from
a
norm
appears
as
both
a
novel
departure
from
and
also
an
appeal
to
the
norms
from
which
it
departs
(Jameson
1972:90-93).
Foregrounding
events
compel
us
to
consider
the
39
interplay
between
the
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals
which
structure
(and
restructure)
sociolinguistic
interaction.
Foregroundings
as
creative
indexicals.
Foregroundings
can
be
studied
as
setting-specific
productions
of
the
dialectic
between
normative
and
deviant
language.
They
are
not
complete
departures
from
these
norms,
but
rather
rest
upon
a
set
of
presupposed
ideologies,
which
contribute
to
their
coherence
(as
violations
of
normative
practices).
Research
on
foregroundings
must
attend
not
only
to
the
presupposed
ideologies
that
are
violated,
but
also
to
those
that
allow
a
violation
to
be
constructed
and
recognized
as
a
violation
(Bakhtin
1986:94;
Glick
2007;
Levin
1963:285;
Shen
2007:179-180;
Short
1973).
In
this
way,
as
Ivan
Fnagy
comments,
the
quality
of
being
different
is
also
governed
by
rules
(1972:288).
These
presuppositions
are
necessary
for
a
foregrounding
to
be
recognizable
for
instance,
when
one
uses
slang
or
profanity
in
an
academic
lecture
and
coherent,
relative
to
a
background
that
does
not
typically
include
these
styles
of
communication.
Just
as
sociolinguistic
interactions
can
be
understood
as
generally
the
interplay
between
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals,
foregroundings
are
bound
up
with
the
larger
act
of
social
signaling,
recognizable
as
a
deviation
or
violation
only
relative
to
the
many
actions
that
are
not.
Considering
this
dialectic,
I
propose
here
to
use
the
term
foregrounding
to
indicate
a
verbal
or
non-verbal
action
that
violates,
mocks,
or
omits
some
setting-specific
presupposition
of
communication,
creatively
indexing
ideologies
that
might
explain
and/or
resolve
its
appearance.
Considering
the
criticisms
of
foregrounding
theory,
I
also
acknowledge
that
this
definition
includes
three
problematic
assumptions:
First,
I
imply
that
deviations
40
are
(more
or
less)
intentional
and
self-conscious
acts.
This
problem
of
intentionality
is
additionally
applicable
to
a
hearer,
who
is
assumed
to
share
the
communicative
norms
that
a
speaker
violates,
thus
experiencing
its
effects
(Widdowson
1973:296-
299).
Such
a
concern
becomes
especially
troublesome
in
ethnographic
analyses,
in
which
researchers
might
infer
the
effect
of
(what
appears
to
them)
strange
language
to
be
the
subjective
experience
of
all.
Second,
but
related,
my
definition
does
not
(as
yet)
account
for
how
deviant
uses
of
language,
repeatedly
encountered,
could
become
mundane,
or
even
tiresome,
once
an
audience
became
conscious
of
their
function
(Jameson
1972:50-53).
Third,
my
definition
of
foregrounding
must
also
account
for
the
scale
of
social
life
within
which
foregroundings
may
appear
and
be
felt.
This
matter
has
received
much
attention
from
critics,
who
point
out
that
the
relational
quality
of
a
foreground/background
might
apply
at
the
levels
of
grammar,
syntax,
semantics,
or
even
entire
genres
of
literary,
dramatic,
or
face-to-face
social
interactions
(Glick
2007;
Levin
1963:277-
280;
Van
Peer
1986:7-10).
The
intentionality,
strangeness
(or
familiarity),
and
scales
of
foregroundings
will
only
become
apparent
through
rigorous
sociolinguistic
research
into
their
regularized
appearance
in
real
interactions.
As
Silverstein
astutely
comments:
We
are
faced
first-off
with
indexical
facts,
facts
of
observed/
experienced
social
practices,
the
systematicity
of
which
is
our
central
problem:
are
they
systematic?
If
so,
how?
with
respect
to
which
institutional
forms?
(re)aligning
whose
values
[]?
[1992:322]
To
increase
the
predictive
value
of
this
conceptual
tool,
I
want
to
turn
now
to
the
ways
that
foregroundings
might
be
grounded
through
contextualization,
thus
solidifying
their
function
as
creative
indices
of
new
ideologies.
41
Contextualization.
Much
of
the
scholarship
on
contextualization
has
the
rather
unfortunate
quality
of
obscuring
the
topic
by
oversimplifying
its
relationship
to
indexicality
and
ideology.
Frequently,
researchers
treat
the
process
of
contextualization
as
a
kind
of
reverse
engineering
project,
in
which
one
or
more
decisive,
interpersonal
actions
are
tracked
down
as
the
likely
sources
of
an
overall
meaning
of
an
interaction.
Certainly,
as
I
examine
below,
there
is
much
to
draw
from
such
sociolinguistic
detective
work.
However,
by
interweaving
a
perspective
on
contextualization
with
my
discussions
on
foregrounding,
indexicality,
and
ideology,
I
wish
to
examine
a
broader
question
of
the
representation
and
reshaping
of
social
life
through
language.
In
this
section,
I
begin
my
discussion
with
approaches
to
(and
critiques
of)
research
on
contextualization
cues,
with
the
goal
of
reaching
this
broader
target
by
introducing
a
more
nuanced
perspective
on
language,
ideology,
and
(finally)
social
movements.
Contextualization
cues.
In
one
sense,
contextualizations
may
be
argued
to
be
the
relevant
resolutions
(or
groundings)
for
the
kinds
of
sociolinguistic
violations
and
deviations
that
I
describe
above.
Foregroundings
may
thus
be
seen
as
a
kind
of
contextualization
cue,
the
theories
of
which
have
been
led
by
John
Gumperz
(1977,
1982,
1992;
Gumperz
and
Cook-Gumperz
1982),
and
figured
heavily
in
much
research
in
sociolinguistics
and
discourse
analysis
(Auer
1992,
1996;
Fairclough
1992,
1995;
Thompson
1984,
1990).
Such
cues,
Gumperz
argues,
are
the
means
by
which
speakers
signal
and
listeners
interpret
what
the
activity
is,
how
semantic
content
is
to
be
understood
and
how
each
sentence
relates
to
what
precedes
or
follows
(1982:131).
The
focus
of
much
of
Gumperzs
extensive
42
research
has
been
to
evaluate
how
different
interpretations
may
arise
from
single
actions,
such
as
his
well-known
investigations
into
service
encounter
complaints
between
British
and
Indian
airport
workers
(Gumperz
1977,
1978).
Here,
he
found
that
Indian
cafeteria
workers
tendency
to
ask
questions
in
English
with
falling
intonations
was
interpreted
by
native
English
speakers
as
both
inappropriate
and
extremely
rude
(Maltz
and
Borker
1982:201).
In
the
sense,
their
accented
English
(likely
unintentionally)
foregrounded
ideologies
of
social
politeness
and
respect
embedded
in
this
workplace,
thus
serving
as
a
cue
toward
the
resolution
of
such
inappropriate
language
use.
Such
an
approach
is
characteristic
of
Gumperzs
research,
which
Maltz
and
Borker
praise
for
not
assuming
that
problems
are
the
result
of
bad
faith,
but
rather
sees
them
as
the
result
of
individuals
wrongly
interpreting
cues
according
to
their
own
rules
(1982:201).
Counter
to
this
praise,
some
critics
suggest
that
it
is
just
this
quality
of
research
on
contextualization
cues
that
marks
it
as
rather
nave.
For
example,
Teun
Van
Dijk
argues:
If
a
recipient,
based
on
previous
experiences,
defines
a
speaker
as
a
male
chauvinist,
then
much
of
what
he
says
will
be
heard
as
an
expression
of
male
chauvinism
whether
or
not
there
are
contextualization
cues
that
warrant
such
an
interpretation
[].
That
is,
the
mental
models
recipients
build
when
interpreting
discourse
may
also
be
construed
on
the
basis
of
inferences
about
ideological
intentions
of
speakers
as
inferred
from
previous
experiences,
hearsay
or
other
reliable
information
about
a
speaker.
[Van
Dijk
2006:130]
As
the
presupposed
ideologies
of
any
interaction
are
not
going
to
be
shared
by
all
participants,
some
sociolinguistic
actions
may
create
foregroundings
for
some
participants
and
not
others.
As
argued
in
other
criticisms
(Auer
1992;
Silverstein
1992),
contextualization
cues
fall
short
of
a
thoroughgoing
examination
by
43
assuming
such
complexities
to
be
(more
or
less)
mysteries
to
be
solved
by
picking
up
the
likely
markers
of
presuppositions
and
tracing
them
back
from
their
interpretive
endpoints,
to
figure
out
where
things
went
awry.
Assessments
of
contextualization
cues
effectively
sidestep
the
multi-participant
nature
of
contextualization
as
the
'aboutness',
as
it
were,
of
discursive
interaction,
the
sense
that
discursive
interaction
makes
or
achieves
a
playing
out
of
certain
cultural
values
through
specific
symbolisms
(Silverstein
1992:70).
To
this
end,
when
Gumperz
concluded
accented
English
in
service
encounters
led
to
individuals
wrongly
interpreting
cues,
his
analysis
can
be
seen
as
notably
one-sided.
These
encounters
may
have
foregrounded
ideologies
of
politeness
and
respect
(for
native
English
speakers),
but
they
resulted
in
contextualizations
that
were
about
the
tensions
and
unequal
power
dynamics
of
a
multi-ethnic
workplace.
Contextualization
as
discursively
achieved,
semiotic
closure.
To
broaden
this
investigation
of
contextualization,
what
is
needed
is
to
return
to
the
terms
(figuratively
and
literally)
of
my
discussion
so
far.
Interactions
are
processes
of
context-making,
in
which
persons
employ
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals
(in
dialectical
relationships
to
one
another)
to
point
to
ideologies,
which
are
then
contextualized
as
the
overarching
meaning
as
Silverstein
remarks,
the
aboutness
of
the
interaction
(see
also
Agha
2007:37-48;
Mertz
1998:450-453;
Parmentier
1994:125).
The
strength
of
this
approach
is
nicely
described
by
Peter
Auer,
who
argues:
context
is
not
given
as
such,
but
is
regarded
as
the
outcome
of
participants'
joint
efforts.
It
is
not
a
collection
of
material
or
social
facts
(such
as
the
interaction
taking
place
in
such-and-such
locale,
with
such-
and-such
social
roles),
but
a
cognitive
scheme
(or
model)
44
about
what
is
relevant
for
the
interaction
at
any
given
point
in
time.
This
scheme
may
exclude
or
include
certain
facts
of
the
material
and
social
surroundings
of
the
interaction
as
they
might
be
stated
by
an
objective
on-looker
who
tries
to
describe
context
without
looking
at
what
takes
place
in
it,
but
it
may
also
include
information
not
statable
before
the
interaction
begins,
or
independently
of
it.
[Auer
1996:20]
Contextualization
is
processual
and
interpersonal
that
is,
it
is
discursive.
Research
into
a
broader
concept
of
contextualization
requires
attention
to
the
regular,
dialectical
interplay
of
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals,
the
ideologies
to
which
they
direct
participants
attentions,
and
the
structuring
(and
restructuring)
of
interactions
that
come
about
as
a
result.
Such
research
is
necessarily,
as
Silverstein
(1992:70)
proposes,
an
ideological
perspective
on
discursive
interaction
that,
in
the
instance,
amounts
to
a
tropological
connoisseurship
of
the
regular
patterns
of
indices,
ideologies,
and
their
discursive
impacts
on
social
life.
If
contextualization
is
inherently
a
matter
of
the
discursively-indexed
ideologies
within
peoples
activities
and
relationships,
there
is
also
something
more
definitive
about
contextualizations,
as
well
the
solidification
or
stabilization
of
what
the
interaction
means,
a
matter
which
V.N.
Volosinov
(1973,
1986)
argued
quite
furiously.
As
Stuart
Hall
explains
(worth
quoting
here
at
length),
the
effect
of
sociolinguistic
contextualization
is
to
produce
a
practice
of
closure:
the
establishment
of
an
achieved
system
of
equivalence
between
language
and
reality,
which
the
effective
mastery
of
the
struggle
over
meaning
produced
as
its
most
pertinent
effect.
These
equivalences,
however,
were
not
given
in
reality
[].
Meanings
which
had
been
effectively
coupled
could
also
be
un-coupled.
The
struggle
in
discourse
therefore
consisted
precisely
of
this
process
of
discursive
articulation
and
disarticulation.
Its
outcomes,
in
the
final
result,
could
only
depend
on
the
relative
strength
of
the
forces
of
struggle,
the
balance
between
them
at
any
strategic
moment,
and
the
effective
conduct
of
the
politics
of
signification.
We
can
think
of
many
pertinent
historical
examples
where
the
conduct
of
a
social
struggle
45
depended,
at
a
particular
moment,
precisely
on
the
effective
dis-
articulation
of
certain
key
terms,
e.g.
'democracy',
the
'rule
of
law',
'civil
rights',
'the
nation',
'the
people',
'Mankind',
from
their
previous
couplings,
and
their
extrapolation
to
new
meanings,
representing
the
emergence
of
new
political
subjects.
[Hall
1982:78]
Here
I
return
to
(and
expand
upon)
a
conceptualization
of
ideology,
indexed
and
contextualized
to
stabilize,
solidify,
or
otherwise
semiotically
close
the
meanings
that
people
assign
to
their
activities,
identities,
and
relationships.
In
such
a
discursive
process,
foregroundings,
with
their
deviations
and
violations
of
presupposed
conversational
norms,
are
likely
to
point
the
direction
toward
such
novel
contextualizations.
Considering
the
centrality
of
foregrounding
events
in
creatively
indexing
the
ideologies
social
movements
into
novel
interactions,
I
suggest
that
the
tropology
which
a
social
movement
researcher
must
become
a
connoisseur
are
regularized
patterns
of
foregroundings
and
contextualizations.
In
this
sense,
returning
again
to
Silverstein,
ideologies
become
parts
of
institutionalized
interaction
patterns
and
interests
with
which
they
dialectically
interact,
while
being
constantly
resubstantiated
in
various
kinds
of
ritualized
-
if
not
actual
ritual
-
interactional
patterns
that
have
a
normative
claim
to
being
prototypes
of
event-genres
in
the
interactional
order.
Ritually,
or
ritualizably,
grounded
interactional
order
has
a
kind
of
relatively
absolute
character
(intentionally
to
use
an
oxymoronic
figure)
in
its
effects
on
those
who
acquiesce
in
its
claim
to
inform
their
ideological
perspectives.
[Silverstein
1992:71,
original
emphasis]
In
one
sense,
this
research
into
foregrounding
and
contextualization
patterns
in
social
movements
is
thus
an
inquiry
into
not
just
how
ideologies
discursively
produce
semiotic
closure
in
the
sociolinguistic
lives
of
participants.
But
it
is
also
addressing
how
they
reappear,
again
and
again,
and
are
thus
constantly
being
46
resubstantiated
through
ritualized
language
that
participants
bring
to
their
activities
and
relationships.
Regularized
foregrounding-contextualization
patterns
fit
both
these
descriptions.
Three
types
of
social
movement
contextualization.
Having
delineated
the
shapes
of
what
I
am
looking
for
in
this
discussion
of
sociolinguistic
contextualization,
I
want
now
to
offer
three
categories
of
contextualization
that
seem
likely
to
be
found
in
social
movement
interactions.
These,
I
suggest,
are
the
probable
social
actions
that
contextualizations
perform
for
the
maintenance
and
spread
of
a
social
movement,
thus
providing
the
grounds
in
which
a
movements
ideologies
become
what
most
or
all
of
its
activities
are
about.
I
discuss
these
categories
in
terms
of
Sussers
ideological
domains
of
social
action
(mobilization,
legitimatization,
and
socialization),
as
well
as
the
conclusions
I
have
drawn
from
the
three
fields
of
social
movement
theory.
Considering
the
very
directed
activities
of
social
movements,
their
most
prominent
social
action
will
likely
be
mobilization.
To
this
end,
many
contextualizations
of
a
social
movement
will
strategically
juxtapose
the
pre-existing,
largely
presupposed
activities,
ideologies,
and
identities
as
belonging
to
the
movement
or,
conversely,
to
the
institution
that
it
challenges.
I
will
add
here
that
these
ideologies
will
exclude
or
include
certain
facts
of
the
material
and
social
surroundings
(Auer
1996:20)
as
they
are
contextualized
in
participant
interactions,
such
that
the
represented
activities,
ideologies,
and
identities
are
represented
as
more
or
less
unified,
homogeneous
socio-cultural
forms.
For
the
purposes
of
this
research,
I
am
going
to
label
abstraction
the
type
of
contextualization
that
47
strategically
grounds
these
representations
of
a
movement
and
its
targeted
institution
as
homogeneous,
oppositional
realities.
A
second
category
of
contextualization
likely
to
appear
in
social
movement
research
provides
legitimization
for
current
participants
in
ways
that
cohere
with
previous
expectations
and
other
highly
valued
ideologies
of
the
group.
I
draw
the
conclusion
(from
Frame
Alignment
Theory)
that
a
social
movements
maintenance
and
spread
largely
depend
on
posing
their
challenge
to
an
institution
in
(more
or
less)
normative
fashions.
As
a
consequence,
the
interplay
of
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals
in
social
movement
activities
will
point
to
other
ideologies,
pertaining
to
(for
example)
individual
expression,
democracy,
equality,
and
so
on.
The
contextualizations
of
these
ideologies
can
in
this
way
be
expected
to
also
include
information
not
statable
before
the
interaction
begins,
or
independently
of
it
(Auer
1996:20).
I
will
label
these
kinds
of
contextualizations
analogical
extensions,
insofar
as
they
incorporate
external
and
less-presupposed
ideologies
as
the
shared
meanings
of
participant
interactions.
A
third
type
of
contextualization,
I
suggest,
might
inspire
its
participants
toward
a
transformed
self-identification
and
perhaps
reevaluation
of
their
subjective
experiences
as
personal
evidence
of
the
movements
goals
a
process
of
socialization
into
the
group
for
new
members
(that
is
likely
shared
with
long-term
participants
as
well).
New
Social
Movement
research
demonstrates
how
the
diverse
identities
among
individuals
can
be
politicized
toward
collective
identification
and
activism.
To
this
end,
the
ultimate
function
of
ideology
is
the
establishment
of
an
achieved
system
of
equivalence
between
language
and
reality
(Hall
1982:78).
48
Contextualizations
may
inspire
among
participants
this
kind
of
collective-
identification
or
self-realization
through
the
ideological
lens
of
the
movement
itself.
This
form
of
contextualization
I
will
label
reflexive
recursion.
4.
Language
and
Ideology
in
the
Maintenance
and
Spread
of
a
Social
Movement
the
basic
question
I
am
asking
of
social
movements
(and
the
EvoS
Program
in
particular)
that
began
this
inquiry:
How
do
people
introduce
and
disseminate
new
meanings
to
the
activities
and
relationships
of
others,
particularly
when
such
interpretations
are
either
unknown
or
unpopular?
Of
course,
the
research
I
present
in
this
dissertation
is
an
attempt
at
a
comprehensive
answer
to
this
question.
But
anticipating
it,
I
want
here
to
synthesize
my
terms
into
a
framework
for
analyzing
language
and
ideology
in
social
movements.
49
challenge
by
representing
the
groups
dissatisfaction,
difference,
and
cohesion
to
existing
members,
new
recruits,
and
outsiders.
Social
action
ideologies
will
work
to:
(1)
mobilize
existing
persons
(and
other
resources)
toward
movement
goals,
(2)
legitimate
the
movement
to
participants
and
outsiders,
and
(3)
socialize
new
members
to
understand
the
groups
first
principles
and
in-house
ideologies.
While
their
primary
motive
is
to
challenge
and
change
institutional
ideologies
and
practices,
much
of
what
goes
on
in
social
movements
will
likely
resemble
sociolinguistic
practices
in
the
surrounding
context.
In
this
way,
the
interplay
of
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals
that
make
up
sociolinguistic
life
in
general
is
enacted
within
social
movements
as
a
balance
between
pre-existing
material
or
ideological
resources
and
those
strategically
introduced
by
the
movements
participants
to
achieve
their
goals.
Research
into
the
ways
that
movements
strike
this
balance
will
demonstrate
both
the
contextual,
sociolinguistic
norms
and
the
ways
that
social
movements
violate
these
norms
while
attempting
to
communicate
a
challenge
that
is
both
coherent
and
forceful.
50
and
that
this
goal
is
tied
to
a
broader
reconceptualization
of
human
existence.
5.
Research
Site
and
Data
Collection
My
experiences
with
the
EvoS
program
stretch
years
before
and
after
the
data
set
I
analyze
in
this
dissertation.
The
programs
self-promotion
was
seemingly
everywhere
in
the
buildings
housing
the
Biological
Sciences,
Social
Sciences,
and
Humanities.
News
about
EvoS
personalities
and
events
pepper
the
physical
and
electronic
landscape
of
Binghamton.
I
chose
to
limit
my
fieldwork
(recorded
events,
interviews,
program
promotions)
to
two
years
because
dozens
of
times
a
day
I
encountered
people,
activities,
and
texts
that
could
be
useful
in
my
research.
Participants
in
the
program
were
my
professors,
classmates,
and
among
the
students
in
the
courses
I
eventually
taught.
Due
to
the
controversial
nature
of
EvoS,
I
was
sometimes
asked
to
weigh
in
on
its
goals
and
scientific
legitimacy,
as
well
as
my
opinions
about
its
organizers,
lectures,
and
(especially)
David
Sloan
Wilson.
I
am
thus
acutely
aware
of
the
interpersonal
tensions
inspired
by
conducting
anthropological
research
on
my
home
turf.
It
is
a
situation
in
which,
as
Rayna
Rapp
comments,
the
outer
reaches
of
the
sample
bleed
into
daily
routine
(1999:16).
I
cannot
hope
to
lessen
any
these
challenges
in
any
way,
other
that
through
rigorous
attention
to
my
evidence.
Here
I
explain
how
that
was
collected:
Audio
recordings.
My
data
collection
is
the
result
of
two
years
of
participant
observation
within
EvoS
events
at
Binghamton
University.
The
bulk
of
my
analysis
will
focus
on
field
recordings
made
during
these
years
of
data
collection.
These
audio
recordings
include
20
lectures,
15
question
and
answer
sessions,
20
post-
51
lecture
discussions,
as
well
as
five
extracurricular
social
events.
In
addition
to
these
field
recordings,
I
have
collected
and
transcribed
many
interviews,
promotions,
panel
discussions,
and
other
activities
sponsored
by
the
EvoS
Program
at
Binghamton
and
also
its
fellow
programs
at
other
universities.
Textual
evidence.
During
these
two
years,
I
also
accumulated
a
wealth
of
textual
information
on
the
program.
These
data
include
the
programs
promotions,
mass
emails
to
participants,
surveys
conducted
by
organizers
to
assess
academic
attitudes
toward
evolutionary
theories,
publications
by
organizers
and
their
colleagues
documenting
the
pedagogical
successes
of
EvoS,
grant
proposals
to
expand
the
program,
and
news
reports
about
the
program
by
both
student
and
professional
journalists.
I
collected
much
information
from
the
EvoS
website,
including
the
organizers
goals,
ways
to
participate,
tutorials,
fund-raising,
and
further
promotions
delivered
via
the
programs
Facebook
page,
Twitter
account,
and
online
blogs
authored
by
faculty
and
student
participants.
To
say
the
very
least,
I
am
well
versed
in
the
academic
and
general
audience
publications
authored
or
edited
by
EvoS
Program
organizers
and
visiting
lecturers.
Participant
interviews.
To
assess
participant
opinions
of
the
program,
I
conducted
two
dozen
individual
or
small
group
interviews.
Most
of
my
discussants
in
these
interviews
were
undergraduate
or
graduate
students
with
at
least
a
semesters
experience
with
the
program,
typically
as
audience
members
in
the
Seminar
Series.
However,
due
to
the
open-door
nature
of
EvoS
events,
some
of
my
informants
were
not
regular
participants,
particularly
those
with
misgivings
toward
the
EvoS
Program.
Further,
many
of
my
interviewees
possessed
knowledge
and
52
shaped
their
opinions
about
the
program
from
interactions
with
colleagues
in
their
own
departments.
While
less
direct
experience
can
make
for
worrisome
evidence,
these
peoples
impressions
are
crucial
for
assessing
the
ways
that
outsiders
understand
the
program,
its
goals,
and
its
academic
legitimacy.
As
a
final
caveat,
I
should
make
clear
that,
wherever
possible,
I
made
audio
recordings
of
these
interviews,
but
some
were
more
or
less
spontaneous
discussions
with
individuals
whose
immediate
opinions
(for
example,
about
a
single
lecturer)
were
necessary
to
document,
but
could
not
sit
for
a
formal
interview.
Wherever
possible,
I
have
tried
to
quote
my
informants
directly,
but
other
participant
impressions
I
have
gleaned
from
opinions
expressed
by
a
majority
(which
I
will
point
out
in
the
course
of
my
analysis).
For
all
my
discussants,
I
made
clear
the
purpose
of
my
research,
the
importance
of
their
opinions
within
it,
and
their
anonymity
in
responding.
These
research
and
analysis
methods
were
reviewed
and
approved
by
Binghamton
Universitys
Human
Subjects
Review
Committee.
53
Chapter
Two:
The
EvoS
Programs
Presupposed
Ideologies,
First
Principle,
and
Movement
Resources
In
this
chapter,
I
examine
elements
of
the
EvoS
Program
that
will
be
necessary
to
understand
it
as
a
social
movement.
In
my
first
section,
I
discuss
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning,
by
which
I
mean
the
four
presupposed
ideologies
that
are
most
frequently
used
by
EvoS
participants
to
explain
human
evolution
and
its
implications.
Second,
I
examine
the
programs
first
principle,
which
I
suggest
is
a
challenge
to
US
higher
education
to
embrace
this
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
foundational
explanation
of
social
life.
Third,
I
discuss
the
programs
resources
(incentives
to
participate,
courses,
membership,
promotional
media,
and
funding),
demonstrating
how
they
tend
to
affirm
the
programs
first
principle,
as
well
as
adhere
to
more
institutional
(that
is,
academic)
requirements.
1.
Evolutionary
Reasoning:
Four
Presupposed
Ideologies
on
Human
Evolution
and
its
Implications
Throughout
my
discussions
of
the
EvoS
Program,
I
use
the
term
evolutionary
reasoning
to
describe
the
ideologies
on
human
evolution
most
frequently
presupposed
by
its
participants
as
scientific
explanations
for
social
behaviors.
My
readers
are
likely
familiar
with
some
evolutionary
theories
about
human
affairs,
and
perhaps
also
that
the
evolutionary
science
community
is
greatly
divided
on
the
relevance
of
these
theories
(see
Levine
2006;
Segerstrle
2000).
I
want
to
be
clear
what
I
mean
by
this
programs
evolutionary
reasoning
54
This
is
not
a
simple
matter,
for
at
least
three
reasons:
First,
these
ideologies
describe
human
social
behavior
in
reference
to
non-human
behaviors.
There
is
nothing
new
or
unique
about
such
slippage
between
the
perpetual
culturalization
of
nature
and
the
naturalization
of
culture
(Sahlins
1976:105).
However,
I
have
learned
that
fellow
researchers
in
linguistics,
anthropology,
and
elsewhere
find
this
almost
fatally
problematic
in
ways
that
(I
stress)
participants
in
EvoS
typically
do
not.
Second,
detailing
the
EvoS
Programs
views
on
evolution
is
complicated
by
its
participants
tendency
to
draw
from
multiple,
sometimes-contradictory
positions
in
the
last
150
years
of
U.S.
and
European
science.
For
instance,
in
some
cases,
the
evolutionary
theories
that
EvoS
participants
(explicitly
or
implicitly)
take
up
positions
previously
forwarded
by
Jean-Baptiste
Lamarck,
Herbert
Spencer,
Pierre
Teilhard
de
Chardin,
and
other
unlikely
sources,
some
of
which
have
been
widely
discarded
by
professional
evolutionary
scientists.
Third,
I
have
found
the
most
common
tension
created
by
the
EvoS
Program
lies
in
readers
and
listeners
reactions
to
the
ambitious,
socio-political
pronouncements
of
its
promoters.
For
example,
the
programs
founder
explains
that
students
and
professional
academics
are
surprised
that
evolutionary
theory
can
potentially
explain
the
evolution
of
behaviors
associated
with
morality
and
immorality.
This
is
vastly
different
than
the
usual
portrayal
of
evolution
as
a
theory
that
explains
immorality
but
leaves
morality
unaccounted
for
[].
When
evolutionary
theory
is
presented
as
a
framework
for
understanding
these
patterns
in
all
their
complexity,
including
the
good,
the
bad,
the
beautiful,
and
the
ugly,
it
is
perceived
as
a
tool
for
understanding
that
can
be
used
for
positive
ends.
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1005]1
1
Two of the central players of my discussion share the same last name (David Sloan Wilson and Edward
O. Wilson). For in-text citations, I add the authors first initials. These sources can be found in Works Cited
under each authors full name.
55
Bold
arguments
such
as
this
are
common
in
the
EvoS
Program.
I
have
learned
that
they
can
evoke
incredulity
at
the
ambition
and
broad
brush
strokes
of
EvoS
promotions,
and
have
been
in
some
cases
are
criticized
as
extremist,
unrealistic,
or
even
delusional
(for
example,
see
Coyne
2011,
2012;
Dawkins
2011;
Marris
2010,
2011;
Webb
2007;
Winegar
2011).
In
all,
the
EvoS
Programs
particular
take
on
evolutionary
science
can
be
challenging.
This
said,
to
understand
the
activities
and
relationships
of
its
participants,
I
must
discuss
how
they
think
and
talk
about
evolution.
This
section
will
present
a
clear
picture
of
what
constitutes
evolutionary
reasoning
within
the
EvoS
Program,
with
the
caveat
that
aspects
of
these
four
ideologies
may
strike
some
readers
as
anthropomorphic,
scientifically
unsupportable,
cavalier,
or
(sometimes)
all
three.
My
goal
is
to
show
that
these
ideologies
are
the
presupposed,
component
parts
of
the
first
principle
of
a
social
movement.
These
ideologies
mark
EvoS
as
distinct
from
the
mainstream
of
U.S.
and
European
evolutionary
science,
in
that
their
narrow
scope
(in
relation
to
professional
evolutionary
science),
but
great
strength
(within
the
EvoS
Program
itself)
are
qualities
that
define
a
social
movements
challenge
to
a
standing
institution.
1a.
Contemporary
human
behaviors
are
adaptations
to
past
and
present
selection
pressures.
Most
popular
understandings
of
evolutionary
science
focus
on
the
common
ancestry
of
all
organisms
(for
example,
humans
and
chimpanzees).
However,
adaptationist
branches
of
evolutionary
science
argue
the
importance
of
selection
in
explaining
organisms
anatomies
and
behaviors.
This
perspective
can
be
56
summarized
as
follows:
As
a
result
of
environmental
pressures
and
genetic
variation,
organisms
of
the
same
species
will
differ
in
their
survival
(avoiding
injury
and
death
due
to
starvation,
disease,
predators,
and
so
on)
and
reproduction
(mating
and
rearing
offspring).
If
they
are
heritable,
the
anatomical
or
behavioral
variations
that
contribute
to
an
organisms
survival
or
reproduction
this
is,
adaptations
will
be
passed
on
to
a
larger
number
of
successive
offspring
than
others
in
the
same
population.
Assuming
the
environmental
pressures
remain
constant
over
many
generations,
organisms
with
these
qualities
will
eventually
outnumber
other,
less
adaptive
ones.
Subsequently,
extreme
specializations
can
be
observed
in
(among
many
possible
examples)
the
camouflage,
defense
mechanisms,
nest
building,
or
migratory
behaviors
of
different
animals.
These
qualities
have
been
selected
for
(and
thus
persist
and
spread)
while
others
have
been
selected
against
(minimized
or
disappearing
altogether).
Seminal
papers
in
the
adaptationist
perspective
include
Levins
(1966),
Maynard-Smith
(1978),
Parker
and
Maynard-
Smith
(1990),
and
Sober
(1987).
Like
some
(though
certainly
not
all)
evolutionary
scientists,
participants
in
the
EvoS
Program
similarly
assess
human
behaviors
as
the
products
of
past
selection
pressures,
and
thus
consider
contemporary
human
behaviors
for
their
significance
as
adaptations.
Conversely,
modern
behaviors
that
seem
problematic
to
individuals
survival
and
reproduction
may
have
been
adaptive
in
past
environments
that
no
longer
exist.
The
behavior
was
once
adaptive,
but
is
now
maladaptive
(Barkow
2006;
Cosmides
and
Tooby
1992;
Richardson
and
Boyd
2005:148-190).
Various
researchers
participating
in
the
EvoS
Program
argue
that
57
behaviors
such
as
marital
infidelity
(Buss
and
Shackelford
1997;
Shackelford
and
Weekes-Shackelford
2004),
rape
and
sexual
coercion
(Gallup
et
al.
2011;
Gottschall
and
Gottschall
2003),
gang
violence
(Daly
and
Wilson
1988),
teenage
pregnancy
(Ellis
et
al
2011),
or
sexual
promiscuity
(Reiber
and
Garcia
2010)
may
have
benefited
the
survival
and
reproduction
of
modern
humans
Stone
Age
ancestors
or
other
non-human
species
in
Homo
sapiens
evolutionary
past.
In
spite
of
their
problematic,
socio-political
nature,
these
behaviors
endure
in
the
present
as
artifacts
of
past
adaptations.
The
EvoS
Programs
founder
is
the
primary
influence
in
this
concentration
on
contemporary
human
behaviors.
In
his
doctoral
research
and
professional
publications
during
the
1970s
and
1980s,
David
Sloan
Wilson
tended
to
investigate
non-human
species,
such
as
ant
lions
and
dung
beetles
(see
D.S.
Wilson
2007a,
2011b).
But
in
the
1990s
and
2000s,
Wilson
began
joint
projects
with
graduate
students
and
faculty
outside
the
Biological
Sciences,
publishing
solo
and
co-
authored
papers
on
topics
such
as
nepotism
(D.S.
Wilson
and
Dugatkin
1991),
gossip
(Kniffin
and
D.S.
Wilson
2005,
2010;
D.S.
Wilson
et
al
2000),
social
constructivism
(D.S.
Wilson
2005b),
language
use
and
semantics
(D.S.
Wilson
1990,
1995),
hunting
and
food-sharing
(D.S.
Wilson
1998),
and
religion
(D.S.
Wilson
2002a,
2002b,
2005c;
Storm
and
D.S.
Wilson
2009).
Throughout,
he
maintains
that
contemporary
human
behaviors
are
best
assessed
as
adaptations
(or
maladaptations).
For
example,
arguing
that
other
academics
have
too
long,
unjustly
perceived
religious
beliefs
as
irrational,
Wilson
poses:
Rationality
is
not
the
gold
standard
against
which
all
other
forms
of
thought
are
to
be
judged.
Adaptation
is
the
gold
standard
against
58
which
rationality
must
be
judged,
along
with
all
other
forms
of
thought.
Evolutionary
biologists
should
be
especially
quick
to
grasp
this
point
since
because
they
appreciate
that
the
well-adapted
mind
is
ultimately
an
organ
of
survival
and
reproduction.
[D.S.
Wilson
2002a:228]
Certainly
this
is
one
of
the
more
ringing
endorsements
for
adaptationism
that
one
could
find
in
the
literature
of
evolutionary
science.
Though
Wilson
is
known
for
such
strong
pronouncements,
as
I
suggest
above,
participants
in
the
EvoS
Program
tend
to
agree
with
this
imperative
to
consider
all
human
behaviors
to
be
products
of
natural
selection.
This
presupposed
ideology
is
a
core
component
of
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning.
However,
it
simultaneously
shows
limited
scope
across
the
evolutionary
science
community.
Critics
argue
that
adaptationist
explanations
lack
empirical
support
from
paleontology,
primatology,
or
archaeology.
Adaptationists
rely
instead
on
Just-So
Stories
persuasive
narratives
for
the
origins
of
an
adaptation
with
little
evidence
that
such
circumstances
ever
existed
(Gottlieb
2012;
Gould
1991,
1994;
Gould
and
Lewontin
1979;
Ingold
2000;
Latour
and
Strum
1986).
Other
critics
argue
that
adaptationists
overestimate
the
influence
of
inheritance,
positing
that
many
human
behaviors
are
better
explained
as
learned
behaviors,
as
opposed
to
inherited
dispositions
(Bargatzky
1984;
Buller
2005;
Caplan
1981/82;
Marks
1995;
2002,
Sahlins
1976).
Despite
these
debates,
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
should
be
understood
as
quite
firmly
adaptationist,
and
further
that
this
quality
distinguishes
the
program
and
its
participants
from
many
other
spheres
of
the
evolutionary
science
community.
1b.
Socio-cultural
change
is
an
evolutionary
process.
The
popularity
of
EvoS
at
Binghamton
University
during
the
2000s
led
many
participants
to
increasingly
(and
59
explicitly)
turn
toward
topics
that
are
rarely
addressed
in
evolutionary
science,
such
as
religion,
language,
visual
art,
and
literature.
These
projects
tended
to
presuppose
that
socio-cultural
change
is,
itself,
a
process
of
variation,
selection,
inheritance,
and
adaptation
an
evolutionary
process.
Cultural
evolutionary
theories
tend
to
blur
the
distinctions
between
the
biological
qualities
of
human
life
(such
as
genes,
hormones,
parasites,
or
viruses)
and
those
dealing
with
socio-political
phenomena
(such
as
government,
laws,
mental
health,
or
gender).
They
often
propose
that
traditions
and
values
may
reproduce,
mutate,
adapt,
and
struggle
to
survive
in
ways
that
are
analogous
to
biological
evolution.
For
example,
the
EvoS
founder
and
a
collaborator
write:
Any
process
that
causes
the
most
successful
strategies
to
increase
in
frequency
counts
as
an
inheritance
mechanism,
including
learning
and
imitation
in
addition
to
genetic
inheritance.
Nongenetic
inheritance
mechanisms
enable
humans
to
adapt
rapidly
to
their
environments,
vastly
accelerating
the
pace
of
evolution
[].
These
unique
human
attributes
are
better
explained
in
terms
of
evolutionary
theory
than
as
a
mysterious
exception
to
the
theory.
Human
uniqueness
cannot
be
used
to
argue
against
the
relevance
of
the
evolutionary
perspective.
[D.S.
Wilson
and
Csikszentmihalyi
2007:330]
Other
participants
similarly
argue
that
social
and
psychological
phenomena
can
be
considered
processes
of
variation
and
selection.
Research
projects
developing
around
this
proposition
include:
adaptation
of
at-risk
youth
to
an
alternative
high
school
(D.S.
Wilson,
Kauffmann,
and
Purdy
2011),
adaptive
responses
to
crime
and
neighborhood
safety
(OBrien
2009,
2010;
OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2010;
OBrien
et
al.
2012),
physical
fitness
programs
using
Stone
Age
diet
and
exercise
(Platek
et
al.
2011),
and
the
heritability
and
adaptive
significance
of
literary
narratives
and
story-
telling
(Gottschall
and
D.S.
Wilson
2005;
Heywood
et
al
2009).
60
There
is
nothing
new
in
extending
evolutionary
analogies
into
explanations
of
socio-cultural
change.
For
nearly
two
centuries,
theorists
have
used
evolutionary
concepts
to
describe
nation
building,
conquest,
warfare,
free-market
capitalism
(see
Crook
1984;
Davies
2009;
Lessl
2012;
Young
1985a,
1985b).
More
recently,
the
term
meme
coined
by
Richard
Dawkins
in
1976
became
a
wildly
popular
term
in
electronic
social
media
(Aunger
2006;
Haig
2006)2.
For
participants
in
the
EvoS
Program,
cultural
evolution
further
extends
selection,
inheritance,
and
adaptation
into
a
discussion
of
consciousness,
morality,
and
diversity.
As
David
Sloan
Wilson
argues,
humans
are
unique
among
other
animals,
but
that
does
not
place
us
outside
the
orbit
of
evolution.
Human
diversity
is
like
biological
diversity,
because
both
are
the
outcomes
of
evolutionary
processes.
We
are
the
product
of
evolution
at
a
variety
of
timescales.
First,
there
is
the
timescale
of
genetic
evolution,
which
is
usually
regarded
as
slow
but
at
times
can
be
quite
fast.
Then
there
is
the
timescale
of
cultural
evolution,
which
is
usually
regarded
as
fast
but
at
times
can
be
quite
slow.
Finally,
there
is
the
timescale
of
psychological
processes,
which
operate
over
the
course
of
a
human
lifetime
or
even
within
a
fraction
of
a
second.
When
you
make
a
decision,
for
example,
it
is
often
the
result
of
neuronal
processes
that
count
as
Darwinian,
of
which
you
are
totally
unaware.
[D.S.
Wilson
2011b:6,
original
emphasis]
This
very
holistic
understanding
of
evolution
requires
analogical
extensions
that
challenge
other
scientists
more
conservative
theories.
For
example,
ecologist
Jerry
Coyne
criticizes
Wilson
for
repeatedly
counting
as
evolutionary
any
human
activity
involving
variation
and
selection,
including
committees
that
have
to
decide
2
In The Selfish Gene, Dawkins argues just as genes propagate themselves in the gene pool by leaping
from body to body via sperms or eggs, so memes propagate themselves in the meme pool by leaping from
brain to brain ...[m]emes should be regarded as living structures, not just metaphorically but technically.
When you plant a fertile meme in my mind you literally parasitize my brain, turning it into a vehicle for the
meme's propagation in just the way that a virus may parasitize the genetic mechanism of a host cell
(1976:192).
61
between
alternative
plans
and
children
who
learn
to
discard
those
behaviors
that
don't
bring
them
rewards,
But
these
issues
[]
are
superficial
and
meaningless
parallels
with
natural
selection's
winnowing
of
genetic
variation.
[2011:24].
Along
with
other
critics
(see
Marris
2010,
2011;
Webb
2007;
Winegar
2011),
Coyne
argues
that
addressing
socio-cultural
change
in
Wilsons
way
deviates
from
the
standing
consensus
of
the
scientific
community.
This
said,
such
marginality
suggests
that
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
can
be
distinguished
by
this
ideologys
great
strength
(within
the
movement)
and
narrow
scope
(within
evolutionary
science
at-large).
To
see
how
the
movements
evolutionary
reasoning
is
further
distinguished
in
this
same
way,
I
turn
next
to
a
more
controversial
conviction.
1c.
Group
selection
has
shaped
human
social
life
to
be
superorganic.
In
the
evolutionary
science
community,
David
Sloan
Wilson
is
best
known
as
a
champion
of
Group
Selection
Theory
a
perspective
that
was
popular
in
the
early
20th
century,
but
then
underwent
thorough
criticism
(Simpson
1941;
Williams
1966)
and
was
generally
dismissed
as
a
result.
Briefly,
Group
Selection
theorists
argue
that
individual
organisms
that
live
in
groups
(such
as
colonies,
hives,
or
herds)
possess
behavioral
adaptations
(selfless
or
altruistic
tendencies)
causing
them
to
sacrifice
their
own
survival
and
reproduction
to
ensure
the
perpetuation
of
the
group.
This
position
is
counter
to
Individual
Selection,
in
which
selfish
organisms
out-survive
and
out-reproduce
those
who
sacrifice
for
the
benefit
of
their
group.
Groups
of
such
individuals
would
out-compete
and
out-reproduce
more
selfish
organisms.
(see
Borrello
2010;
Harman
2010).
62
Many
of
the
EvoS
Programs
participants
argue
that
human
evolution
has
been
driven
by
inter-group
competition
collectives
whose
members
act
selflessly
toward
one
another
and
aggressively
toward
other
groups.
This
proposition
has
come
to
define
much
of
Wilsons
career,
but
it
also
holds
personal
significance
for
him
as
a
scientific
justification
for
benevolence
and
self-sacrifice.
He
has
said
in
a
webcast
interview
that
he
would
like
to
be
remembered
for
reviving
group
selection,
which
explains
basically
how
niceness
evolves
how
goodness
and
niceness
in
all
of
their
forms
how
those
traits
can
win
the
Darwinian
contest
and
that
applies
to
all
creatures
great
and
small
Critics
charge
that
Wilson
and
other
group
selectionists
are
confusing
their
progressive
humanism
with
scientific
facts
(Dawkins
2011;
Marris
2011;
Shavit
2004;
Webb
2007),
to
the
extent
that
Richard
Dawkins
has
accused
Wilson
of
zealotry
(Segerstrle
2000:383).
Even
in
his
earliest
research,
David
Sloan
Wilsons
goals
were
unpopular
with
other
scientists,
such
as
biologist
Robert
Trivers,
who
recalls
Wilson
as
a
young
post-doc
full
of
enthusiasm,
when
he
came
into
Trivers
Harvard
office
in
1975
to
propose
a
renewed
defense
of
Group
Selection.
On
this,
Trivers
writes:
I
begged
him
not
to
do
so.
There
were
so
many
fascinating
and
important
problems
remaining
to
be
solved
using
good
old
individual
selection
reasoning,
while
group
selection
by
necessity
had
to
be
found
in
nature
but
would
be
limited,
so
I
told
him,
to
very
special
circumstances,
very
special
life
cycles,
unusual
constraints
on
migration,
and
so
on.
I
even
tried
to
blow
a
little
smoke
up
his
ass,
so
to
speak,
and
told
him
it
was
obvious
that
he
was
bright
and
that
with
his
theoretical
talents
he
might
make
major
contributions
to
biology
while
a
life
spent
on
group
selection
would
inevitably
come
up
short.
[]
He
obviously
followed
not
a
word
of
my
advice.
[Trivers
1998:83]
63
Despite
these
criticisms,
Wilson
maintains
that
the
theory
will
eventually
be
accepted
as
the
driving
force
of
human
evolution.
The
EvoS
Program
(and
its
founder)
in
this
way
departs
from
majority
opinions
within
evolutionary
science,
although
the
last
two
decades
have
seen
growing
number
of
cultural
evolutionary
theories
based
on
Group
Selection,
largely
due
to
Wilsons
continuous
advocacy
(for
example,
see
Berreby
2005;
Boyd
and
Richerson
2005;
Vermeij
2010;
or
E.O.
Wilson
2012).
In
the
EvoS
Program,
Group
Selection
presents
a
picture
of
human
social
life
that
is
superorganic
that
is,
that
the
group
selection
in
human
evolution
resulted
in
social
collectives
thinking
and
acting
as
one
mind.
As
Wilson
and
a
collaborator
write:
We
now
know
that
evolution
takes
place
not
only
by
small
mutational
change
individuals
from
individuals
but
by
groups
becoming
so
well
integrated
that
they
become
higher-level
organisms
in
their
own
right
individuals
created
from
groups.
Our
ancestors
became
the
primate
equivalent
of
bodies
and
beehives
[].
Our
capacity
for
cooperation
within
groups
enabled
us
to
become
ecologically
dominant,
occupying
the
entire
planet
and
displacing
many
other
species
along
the
way
[D.S.
Wilson
and
OBrien
2009:155-156]
Superorganic
metaphors
between
humans
and
beehives
and
ant
colonies
have
been
central
to
Group
Selection
Theory
for
over
a
century
(see
Borrello
2010:24-39;
Mitchell
1995;
Mitman
1992;
Shavit
2004),
and
have
a
similarly
long
and
contentious
history
in
anthropology
and
sociology.3
3 Superorganic theories are nearly synonymous with the nineteenth century theorist Herbert
Spencer.
In
evolutionary
biology,
the
superorganism
has
held
similar
attraction
for
much
of
the
early
twentieth
century,
beginning
with
William
M.
Wheelers
The
Ant-Colony
as
an
Organism
(1911).
Later,
arguments
of
a
human
superorganism
appeared
most
notably
in
Alfred
L.
Kroebers
(1917)
essay,
The
Super-Organic
(see
Haraway
1991:43-68;
Ingold
1986:7-10;
Stocking
1982:65-68,
263-
268).
64
However,
David
Sloan
Wilson
and
his
colleagues
are
adamant
that
they
are
not
speaking
metaphorically,
but
rather
describing
a
condition
of
socio-historical
reality
in
which
political
and
religious
collectives
operate
as
group
minds
(D.S.
Wilson
1997a,
1997b;
D.S.
Wilson
and
Sober
1989;
D.S.
Wilson
and
E.O.
Wilson
2007a,
2007b;
D.S.
Wilson
et
al
2004).
Politicians,
philosophers,
and
spiritual
leaders
(they
argue)
have
compared
their
communities
to
insect
colonies
or
single
organisms
in
their
essays
and
sacred
texts,
but
these
figurative
comparisons
are
actually
evidence
of
evolved
dispositions.4
For
example,
discussing
an
Anabaptist
text
that
inspired
him
to
examine
religions
as
superorganisms
,
Wilson
comments,
the
writer
of
this
passage
knew
nothing
about
evolution
or
science,
but
his
comparison
of
bodies,
beehives,
and
his
own
religious
group
struck
me
as
much
more
than
a
poetic
metaphor.
If
I
really
wanted
to
study
human
groups
as
comparable
to
bodies
and
beehives,
shouldn't
I
be
studying
religious
groups?
After
all,
that
is
how
at
least
some
religious
believers
describe
themselves!
[2007a:235]
Elsewhere,
Wilson
and
philosopher
Elliot
Sober
criticize
what
they
perceive
as
one-
sidedness
among
geneticists
in
their
use
of
metaphors:
Genes
that
profit
at
the
expense
of
other
genes
within
the
same
individual
are
metaphorically
referred
to
as
"outlaws"
[]
and
the
regulatory
machinery
that
evolves
to
suppress
them
is
referred
to
as
a
"parliament"
of
genes
[].
Ironically,
most
of
the
authors
who
use
these
metaphors
are
reluctant
to
think
of
real
parliaments
as
regulatory
machines
that
reduce
fitness
differences
within
groups,
thereby
concentrating
adaptation
at
the
group
level.
[D.S.
Wilson
and
Sober
1994:592]
Not
surprisingly,
this
view
is
uncommon
in
the
evolutionary
science
community,
and
many
critics
object
simultaneously
to
group
selection
theorizing
and
its
4
Further examples of Wilson and other EvoS participants posing this argument e.g. religious or political
rhetoric of (for example) the body politic as coextensive with the findings of evolutionary science can
be found in Meyer 2008; Sleater 2010; Sober and D.S. Wilson 1998:132-158; D.S. Wilson 1997c, 2004;
D.S. Wilson and Sober 1994; D.S. Wilson and Swenson 2003; D.S. Wilson and E.O. Wilson 2007b.
65
associated
superorganic
metaphors.
For
example,
zoologist
Michael
Ghiselin
agitatedly
writes
that
superorganisms
may
exist,
but
that
this
does
not
imply
the
existence
of
anything
that
even
remotely
resembles
a
mind,
with
foresight,
intentions,
and
intended
consequences.
To
be
consistent,
we
would
be
driven
to
attribute
minds
to
single
cells,
and
even
to
molecules.
We
might
just
as
well
revive
such
occult
metaphysical
doctrines
as
hylozoism
and
pansychism.
[2011:164]
Just
as
unsurprising,
David
Sloan
Wilson
is
undeterred
by
such
criticisms.
Rather,
he
and
his
collaborators
find
evidence
from
religious
and
political
texts
that
demonstrates
the
actual
experience
of
what
critics
like
Ghiselin
dismiss
as
a
convenient
metaphor.
On
this,
Wilson
straightforwardly
declares
super-organisms
aren't
a
metaphor.
They
are
a
fact.
They're
really
out
there
[],
produced
by
the
laws
acting
around
us.
They
are
also
an
essential
part
of
the
human
evolutionary
story.
If
we
choose
to
deny
their
existence
when
we
select
metaphors
to
live
by,
we
are
denying
reality.
[D.S.
Wilson
2011b:70]
Like
the
EvoS
contention
that
socio-cultural
change
is
an
evolutionary
process,
the
scope
of
this
third
ideology
is
narrow
within
the
scientific
community.
However,
it
is
also
a
definitive
part
of
this
programs
evolutionary
reasoning,
strongly
identified
with
its
leader,
his
colleagues,
students,
and
their
research.
Moving
to
the
fourth
and
final
component
part
of
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning,
I
will
examine
the
implications
of
envisioning
contemporary
social
life
in
this
way.
1d.
Humans
continue
to
evolve
and
must
learn
to
guide
future
evolution.
Of
the
many
divided
opinions
within
evolutionary
science,
the
question
of
whether
or
not
humans
continue
to
evolve
is
perhaps
the
most
unsettled
of
arguments.5
EvoS
5
Modern
humans
could
be
understood
as
having
transcended
many
selection
pressures
that
cause
significant
differences
in
the
survival
and
reproduction
of
other
animals.
The
species
has
migrated
across
the
entire
planet,
resulting
in
populations
that
are
quite
similar
genetically.
In
this
sense,
66
participants
tend
to
understand
the
behaviors
of
contemporary
Homo
sapiens
as
adaptations
that
oblige
people
to
think
and
act
as
a
superorganic
group.
Participants
thus
represent
socio-cultural
change
(both
historically
and
at
present)
as
an
on-
going
evolutionary
process.
As
I
suggest
before,
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
allows
for
a
vast
number
of
human
and
non-human
phenomena
to
count
as
selection,
adaptation,
and
inheritance.
To
this
end,
living
persons
and
their
social
behaviors
are
of
interest
to
EvoS,
not
only
because
they
are
products
of
past
selection
pressures,
but
equally
because
these
same
persons
and
behaviors
are
evidence
of
evolution
in
action
in
the
present.6
On
this
matter,
the
intellectual
predecessors
of
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning
are
several
mid-20th
century
scientists
who
argue
that
conscious
steering
of
human
evolution
will
be
both
possible
and
necessary
in
the
future,
in
order
to
avoid
extinction.
For
example,
in
his
introduction
to
the
1963
general
audience
publication
Man
and
His
Future,
biologist
Julian
Huxley
states:
the
new
and
central
factor
in
the
present
situation
is
that
the
evolutionary
process,
in
the
person
of
mankind,
has
for
the
first
time
become
conscious
of
itself.
We
are
realizing
that
we
need
a
global
evolutionary
policy,
to
which
we
shall
have
to
adjust
our
economic
and
social
and
national
policies.
[1963:20]
A
similar
example
can
be
found
in
Edward
O.
Wilsons
On
Human
Nature,
where
the
Homo
sapiens
do
not
exhibit
the
genetic
variation
or
susceptibility
to
selection
pressures
that
could
result
in
further
evolutionary
change.
On
the
other
hand,
some
theorists
cite
historical
evidence
that
some
communities
show
specific,
physiological
resistances
to
disease,
altitude,
and
low-level
toxins
in
available
foods
(for
example,
see
Berreby
2005;
Diamond
1997;
Mindell
2006)
However,
these
arguments
are
in
contrast
to
a
wider
opinion
that
recorded
history
does
not
offer
enough
time
to
demonstrate
that
natural
selection
has
taken
place.
6
Among
other
sources,
examples
of
this
argument
appear
in:
Gray
2007,
2011;
Kniffin
and
D.S.
Wilson
2005;
OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2011;
OGorman
et
al.
2005;
Storm
and
D.S.
Wilson
2009;
D.S.
Wilson,
Kauffman,
and
Purdy
2011;
D.S.
Wilson,
Marshall,
and
Iserhott
2011;
D.S.
Wilson
and
OBrien
2009;
D.S.
Wilson
and
E.O.
Wilson
2007a,
2007b; D.S.
Wilson,
OBrien,
and
Sesma.
2009.
67
author
proposes:
At
some
time
in
the
future
we
will
have
to
decide
how
human
we
wish
to
remain
in
this
ultimate,
biological
sense
because
we
must
choose
among
the
alternate
emotional
guides
we
have
inherited.
To
chart
our
destiny
means
that
we
must
shift
from
automatic
control
based
on
our
biological
properties
to
precise
steering
based
on
biological
knowledge.
[1978:6]
Both
of
these
authors
argue
that
the
continuing
evolution
of
the
human
species,
through
the
present
and
into
the
future,
prophesizing
an
impending
need
for
action
to
guide
the
species,
informed
by
scientific
knowledge
specifically
evolutionary
theory
applied
to
social
policies.7
For
David
Sloan
Wilson
and
the
EvoS
Program,
knowledge
of
human
evolution
should
inform
a
science
of
intentional
change
(D.S.
Wilson
2012:149)
for
decision
makers
in
economics,
law,
and
education.
Publications
and
promotions
in
this
component
of
EvoS
theorizing
are
ambitious,
including:
Evolving
the
Future:
Toward
a
Science
of
Intentional
Change
(D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2013),
Darwins
Invisible
Hand:
Market
Competition,
Evolution,
and
the
Firm
(Johnson
et
al.
2013)
and
Policymaking
the
Darwinist
Way
(D.S.
Wilson
2009b).
In
this
last
publication,
Wilson
argues
that
politicians
and
their
expert
advisers
need
evolutionary
theory
for
the
best
of
reasons:
it
provides
new
tools
for
making
humane
decisions
on
everyones
behalf
(2009b:22).
Unlike
earlier
proclamations
by
Julian
Huxley
and
7 For both, this imperative is ultimately a recommendation for eugenics policy. Considering the
timeframe,
Huxley
is
explicit
on
this
matter:
Our
present
civilization
is
becoming
dysgenic.
To
reverse
this
grave
trend,
we
must
use
our
genetical
[sic]
knowledge
to
the
full,
and
develop
new
techniques
of
human
reproduction,
such
as
oral
contraception
and
multiple
insemination
by
deep-
frozen
sperm
from
desired
donors.
Eventually,
the
prospect
of
radical
eugenic
improvement
could
become
one
of
the
mainsprings
of
man's
evolutionary
advance
(1963:21)
Edward
Wilson
offers
a
more
cautious
opinion
that
we
are
justified
in
considering
the
preservation
of
the
entire
gene
pool
as
a
contingent
primary
value
until
such
time
as
the
almost
unimaginably
greater
knowledge
of
human
heredity
provides
us
with
the
option
of
a
democratically
contrived
eugenics
(1978:
198).
68
others,
the
EvoS
Programs
arguments
are
explicitly
not
in
favor
of
eugenics,
population
control,
laissez-faire
economic
markets,
or
limiting
social
welfare.
Instead,
Wilson
posits:
The
new
version
of
Social
Darwinism
is
very
different.
It
provides
a
powerful,
evolutionary
justification
for
social
equality
and
a
sophisticated
theory
for
how
to
achieve
it
[].
Even
when
evolution
has
made
things
that
are
hard
to
change,
we
need
to
know
about
the
more
enduring
aspects
of
human
nature
so
that
we
can
design
our
current
environments
accordingly.
We
design
zoos
so
that
wild
animals
will
feel
at
home
so
why
not
our
own
environments?
[D.S.
Wilson
2010:15]
The
EvoS
Program
shares
with
earlier
(and
some
contemporary)
evolutionary
scientists
the
conviction
that
human
evolution
has
not
ceased.
The
species
continues
to
demonstrate
its
adaptations
(and
maladapations)
in
the
present,
and
will
need
knowledge
of
these
matters
to
make
social
policy
decisions
to
survive
future
selection
pressures.8
As
Wilson
suggests
above,
the
key
to
survival
(and
the
central
difference
between
EvoS
and
earlier
evolutionary
science)
is
an
evolutionary
justification
for
social
equality,
informing
social
policies
that
oblige
persons
to
treat
one
another
as
part
of
the
same
superorganic
group.
It
bears
noting
that
proponents
of
Evolutionary
Psychology
similarly
propose
that
policy
changes
(for
example,
in
law
enforcement,
mental
health,
labor
regulation,
and
public
education)
should
be
informed
by
evolutionary
science.
Recent
examples
include
publications
such
as
Darwinism
Applied:
Evolutionary
Paths
to
Social
Goals
(Beckstrom
1993),
Evolutionary
Psychology
and
Violence:
A
Primer
for
Policymakers
and
Public
Policy
Advocates
(Bloom
and
Dess
2003),
Evolutionary
Psychology,
Public
Policy
and
Personal
Decisions
(Crawford
and
Salmon
2004).
However,
these
authors
either
do
not
address
or
sometimes
explicitly
reject
the
possibility
Homo
sapiens
continued
evolution.
Rather,
like
the
founding
theorists
of
Evolutionary
Psychology
(Cosmides
and
Tooby
1992),
they
tend
to
argue
that
humans
are
psychologically
adapted
to
Stone
Age
selection
pressures,
not
those
of
industrialized
society.
69
have
been
the
socio-historic
(i.e.
cultural
evolutionary)
processes,
resulting
in
previously
disparate
persons
acting
as
single,
superorganic
entities
seen
in
neighborhood
activism
(Henrich
and
Henrich
2007;
OBrien
2009,
2010;
D.S.
Wilson
2011),
alternative
education
and
play
groups
(Gray
2007;
D.S.
Wilson,
Marshall,
and
Iserhott
2011)
organized
religion
(Storm
and
D.S.
Wilson
2009;
D.S.
Wilson
2002a;
2005c),
and
nation
states
(Turchin
2003;
2006;
D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2013).
David
Sloan
Wilson
expresses
the
urgency
for
such
consensus
to
happen
on
a
global
scale:
[O]ur
future
is
bleak
if
we
don't
turn
our
groups
into
organisms
[].
When
groups
aren't
organisms,
life
becomes
nasty,
brutish,
and
short
for
their
members.
If
conflict
doesn't
get
them,
then
neglect
and
decay
will.
When
groups
do
become
organisms,
life
becomes
good
for
their
members,
but
the
problems
of
conflict,
neglect,
and
decay
reappear
at
a
higher
scale.
The
only
way
to
solve
this
problem
is
by
building
up
the
scale
of
cooperation
until
the
entire
planet
is
a
single
cooperative
group.
Otherwise,
we
will
suffer
from
conflict,
neglect,
and
decay
at
a
massive
scale.
[2011b:365]
Wilsons
proposal
here
is,
obviously,
quite
ambitious.
But,
more
importantly,
this
ideology
draws
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
into
a
total
explanation
of
lived
social
reality
as
it
exists,
and
moreover
as
it
should
be
made
in
the
future.
The
superorganism
is
the
ideal
form
of
organization,
realized
in
some
facets
of
human
life,
but
eluding
others
because
of
policy-makers
uncooperative
neglect
of
evolutionary
knowledge.
reasoning,
I
had
two
goals
in
mind:
First,
I
wanted
to
make
clear
precisely
what
I
mean
by
that
term.
I
introduced
what
I
have
observed
to
be
four,
component
parts
to
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning
the
presupposed
ideologies
shared
within
this
group
regarding
human
evolution
and
its
socio-political
significance.
70
Like
a
social
movement,
these
ideologies
display
great
strength
within
the
EvoS
Program,
but
relatively
narrow
scope
within
a
broader
institution
(U.S.
and
European
evolutionary
science).
Second,
I
sought
to
establish
for
my
readers
a
representative
picture
of
the
programs
take
on
evolution,
because
this
knowledge
will
be
necessary
for
a
basic
understanding
for
this
movements
first
principle
a
subject
to
which
I
turn
below.
2.
The
EvoS
Programs
First
Principle
As
I
will
show
extensively
in
coming
chapters,
the
EvoS
Programs
challenge
to
U.S.
higher
education
lies
in
regularly
contextualizing
each
of
the
movements
activities
as
an
affirmation
of
the
same
message.
Though
of
course
every
instance
is
unique
to
its
setting,
topics,
and
participants,
this
message
is
largely
consistent:
All
disciplines
of
higher
education
should
embrace
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
foundation
to
all
explanations
of
social
life.
To
this
end,
participants
affirm
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
single
method
of
rethinking
the
primary
meanings
of
human
experiences.
Though
program
participants
direct
this
challenge
toward
a
number
of
institutional
targets,
it
is
most
recognizably
an
ultimatum
delivered
to
students
and
professionals
in
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities.
radical
reinterpretation
of
the
epistemic
grounds
upon
which
the
curricula
and
research
of
higher
education
should
rest.
For
several
decades,
professionals
in
many
of
these
same
disciplines
have
themselves
challenged
the
very
possibility
that
such
a
foundation
is
possible
or
desirable
(Moran
2002;
Readings
1996;
Searle
1995;
71
Wiarda
2010).
Despite
the
narrow
scope
of
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning
within
the
broader
scientific
community,
David
Sloan
Wilson
and
other
participants
argue
that
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
provides
an
authoritative,
unifying
framework
for
explaining
human
behaviors
of
all
kinds.
Evolutionary
reasoning
is
posed
as
a
unifying
paradigm,
counter
to
institutional
disciplinary
divisions.
For
example,
on
the
programs
website
(EvoS
Start
Your
Own),
Wilson
argues
that
EvoS
aims
to
resolve
a
general
problem
in
higher
education
the
fragmentation
of
knowledge.
He
elaborates:
The
Ivory
Tower
would
be
more
aptly
named
the
Ivory
Archipelago.
It
consists
of
hundreds
of
isolated
subjects,
each
divided
into
smaller
subjects
in
an
almost
infinite
progression.
People
are
examined
less
with
a
microscope
than
with
a
kaleidoscope
psychology,
anthropology,
economics,
political
science,
sociology,
history,
art,
literature,
philosophy,
gender
studies,
ethnic
studies.
Each
perspective
has
its
own
history
and
special
assumptions.
One
persons
heresy
as
anothers
commonplace.
Unity
of
knowledge
has
always
been
the
ideal
of
a
liberal
arts
education
and
almost
everyone
in
higher
education
agrees
about
the
importance
of
integrating
across
disciplines.
Unfortunately,
these
commonly
held
goals
cannot
be
realized
in
the
absence
of
a
common
language
that
can
be
spoken
across
disciplines.
Evolutionary
theory
provides
a
common
language
a
single
explanatory
framework
that
can
be
used
to
organize
knowledge
across
a
diversity
of
subject
areas
[].
In
short,
we
aim
to
turn
the
Ivory
Archipelago
into
the
United
Ivory
Archipelago!9
Numerous
scholars
previously
argued
that
evolutionary
science
provides
knowledge
that
transcends
differences
in
theory
and
method
between
academic
disciplines
(for
example
Huxley
1963;
Lorenz
1966;
E.O.
Wilson
1975,
1998a,
1998b).
Like
the
EvoS
Program,
these
scholars
propose
that
once
this
this
goal
is
met
in
higher
education,
disciplines
that
have
traditionally
been
unconcerned
with
9
72
evolution
would
be
unified
with
the
Biological
Sciences
through
their
shared
attention
to
evolutionary
reasoning.
Propositions
of
this
sort
stir
controversy
within
the
contemporary
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities,
where
critiques
of
foundationalism
typically
concern
how
such
grand
or
final
explanations
tend
to
favor
the
privileges
and
influence
enjoyed
by
those
who
produce
them.
Focusing
on
this
issue
in
evolutionary
science,
Martha
McCaughey
argues:
Foundationalism
assumes
the
need
for,
and
existence
of,
one
authoritative
framework
for
distinguishing
the
right
from
the
wrong,
the
real
from
the
unreal,
and
the
healthy
from
the
sick
[].
It
is
not
that
evolution
provides
a
bad
foundation,
but
that
foundationalism
itself
is
troubling.
It
sets
up
a
way
to
make
politics
invisible
in
the
knowledge
production
process.
Invoking
God's
will,
or
nature's,
hides
the
political
context
in
which
such
a
will
was
revealed
or
discovered,
the
interests
of
those
who
deem
it
important,
and
the
dissent
of
those
who
are
unwillingly
held
accountable
to
it.
[2008:59]
As
the
previous
passage
from
the
EvoS
website
explicitly
demonstrates,
the
challenge
that
the
program
makes
to
U.S.
higher
education
concerns
promoting
and
implementing
precisely
such
a
singular
authoritative
framework.
The
programs
founder
and
participants
are
by
no
means
unaware
of
the
controversial
nature
of
their
goals,
although
their
general
understanding
of
criticisms
such
as
McCaugheys
is
often
lacking.
For
example,
Wilson
and
a
colleague
attempt
to
sympathize:
Mistrust
of
grand
theorizing
is
understandable,
because
a
succession
of
grand
theories
of
history,
religion,
and
culture
have
come
and
gone.
Nevertheless,
the
fact
that
evolution
is
an
authentic
grand
theory
for
the
rest
of
life
on
earth
suggests
that
it
might
also
succeed
with
respect
to
our
own
species,
even
if
previous
grand
theories
failed.
[D.S.
Wilson
and
Green
2011:227]
Taking
McCaugheys
explanation
above
as
more-or-less
representative
of
the
broader,
academic
criticism
of
foundationalism,
it
is
clear
that
Wilson
and
Green
do
73
not
completely
grasp
the
resistance
to
authoritative
frameworks,
evolutionary
or
otherwise.
Yet,
the
EvoS
Program
is
aimed
at
convincing
these
critics
otherwise.
3.
The
EvoS
Programs
Resources:
Incentives,
Coursework,
Membership,
Promotional
Media,
and
Funding
I
have
so
far
focused
on
(what
I
am
calling)
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning,
those
presupposed
ideologies
about
human
evolution
that
comprise
it,
and
its
central
role
in
this
programs
first
principle
a
challenge
to
higher
education
to
accept
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
foundation
for
all
explanations
of
social
life.
To
more
fully
document
the
EvoS
Programs
activities
and
relationships,
it
is
necessary
now
to
consider
this
movements
resources
the
materials,
practices,
and
interpersonal
obligations
that
participants
harness
to
advocate
the
programs
first
principle
at
Binghamton
University.
Much
of
the
evidence
that
I
describe
here
may
strike
the
reader
as
unremarkable,
resembling
the
usual
goings-on
of
any
university
department,
office,
or
club.
This
to
be
expected,
since
social
movements
push
some
of
the
possibilities
of
existing
cultural
forms
in
new
directions,
to
be
sure,
but
their
cultural
life
is
not
fundamentally
different
in
source
or
mode
of
operation
(Hart
1992:89).
Many
of
the
EvoS
Programs
resources
its
incentives
for
participating,
coursework,
membership,
and
funding
sources
are
tied
to
higher
education,
in
one
way
or
another.
However,
the
program
also
finds
novel
ways
of
harnessing
these
resources,
in
order
to
advocate
a
foundation
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
At this juncture, I need to qualify that the roles played by movement leaders
can pose special problems for discussions of social movements. Certainly, one
74
cannot
ignore
the
influence
of
leaders
such
as
David
Sloan
Wilson
in
guiding
collective
action,
procuring
resources,
inspiring
participation,
and
attracting
new
participants.
Leaders
offer
the
movements
history,
identity,
and
goals,
often
in
frank,
readily
quotable
sound
bites.
However,
such
fortuitous
pronouncements
come
at
a
cost
to
ethnography.
A
researcher
risks
ignoring
the
agency
of
other
participants
for
a
top-down
analysis
of
the
movement,
as
conceptualized
through
the
words
of
its
elites.
Less-vocal
participants
begin
to
appear
as
an
anonymous
crowd
of
supporters,
reifying
the
leaders
perspective
as
though
participant
mobilization
were
simply
a
matter
of
movement
activists
pushing
the
appropriate
rhetorical
button
(Benford
1997:421).
Neither
should
an
ethnographic
assessment
of
leadership
roles
become
a
kind
of
psychoanalysis
of
individuals
that
sidesteps
their
positions
as
historically
and
social-situated
actors
(Goodwin
et
al
2004:418-
419).
No
less
than
other
participants,
leaders
have
complex
motivations
for
their
participation
in
the
movement.
All
told,
discussions
of
movement
leaders
are
crucial
to
the
ethnographic
process,
but
their
influence
should
be
situated
through
an
equally
necessary
discussion
of
the
interpersonal
dynamics
of
the
movement
and
its
contexts.
David
Sloan
Wilsons
great
influence
upon
the
EvoS
Program
will
be
evidence
throughout
this
discussion,
but
I
also
demonstrate
that
the
kinds
of
advocacy
found
in
this
social
movement
are
discursively
produced
through
numerous
participants
and
resources.
My
two
goals
in
this
section
are:
First,
to
detail
the
most
relevant
EvoS
resources
as
I
have
observed
from
my
fieldwork
its
participation
incentives,
required
and
elective
coursework,
membership,
promotional
media,
and
funding
75
and
(doing
so)
further
document
the
material
and
interpersonal
realities
of
the
EvoS
Program
as
a
social
movement.
Second,
I
wish
to
analyze
how
these
resources
adhere
to
(and
sometimes
deviate
from)
institutional
norms
in
higher
education,
a
kind
of
balancing
act
performed
continuously
by
social
movements.
Through
this
evidence-based
analysis,
I
seek
to
ground
my
subsequent
discussion
of
my
fieldwork
as
a
participant-observer
in
the
EvoS
Program.
3a.
Incentives
to
Participate
in
the
EvoS
Program
The
EvoS
Program
has
gone
to
great
lengths
to
encourage
and
reward
the
participation
of
professional
scholars,
university
students,
and
distance
learners.
As
its
website
argues,
participation
in
EvoS
is
easy,
offering
dozens
of
avenues
to
engage
in
the
program.
The
program
is
thus
advertised
as
an
emerging
movement
of
both
persons
and
ideas,
one
that
professional
(and
aspiring
professional)
academics
will
regret
not
joining.
As
the
programs
founder
asserts:
Evolutionary
theory
has
arrived
as
an
important
theoretical
framework
guiding
research
in
the
human
behavioral
sciences.
Any
college
or
university
that
fails
to
teach
evolution
in
relation
to
human
affairs
is
out
of
touch
with
current
scientific
research.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:3-4]
Participation
in
EvoS
is
presented
as
both
academically
rewarding
and
essential
to
the
relevance
of
U.S.
higher
education.
Below,
I
detail
several
of
these
incentives,
as
they
have
been
advertised
by
the
program
and
observed
through
my
own
research.
The
Evolutionary
Studies
Certificate.
To
date,
the
EvoS
Program
offers
no
undergraduate
or
graduate
major.
Rather,
undergraduates
may
work
towards
a
76
certificate
in
Evolutionary
Studies.10
To
earn
the
EvoS
certificate,
students
take
twenty
credits
of
eligible
courses,
an
extensive
catalog
of
classes
taught
by
EvoS
faculty
participants.11
Undergraduates
must
also
complete
the
introductory
Evolution
for
Everyone
course
and
two
semesters
of
the
programs
Seminar
Series.
Graduate
students
may
also
enroll
in
the
EvoS
Program
and
work
towards
a
graduate
certificate
in
Evolutionary
Studies
(in
this
case,
mediated
through
Binghamton
Universitys
Graduate
School).
Like
undergraduates,
graduate
students
wanting
to
earn
an
EvoS
Certificate
must
complete
two
semesters
of
the
programs
Seminar
Series.
Career
Building
and
Networking.
Because
EvoS
relies
upon
pre-existing
resources
to
maintain
and
spread,
it
must
face
(like
other
social
movements)
the
fact
that
participation
also
demands
its
participants
time
and
labor.
The
programs
organizers
that
EvoS
provides
academic
and
intellectual
benefits
contributing
to
a
participants
career
goals.
For
example,
the
programs
website
explains
that
the
certificate
is
only
one
of
many
ways
that
graduate
student
participants
can
benefit:
EvoS
is
intended
to
enable
graduate
students
from
all
academic
units
to
adopt
an
evolutionary
perspective
without
adding
an
undue
burden
to
their
existing
requirements.
Graduate
students
are
a
critical
component
of
the
program,
not
only
as
students
but
also
as
teachers
and
colleagues,
and
are
therefore
encouraged
to
contribute
ideas
to
the
design
and
operation
of
the
program.12
10
The Certificate in Evolutionary Studies is similar to other certificate programs in (for example) teaching
or English as a Second Language. Students receive this certificate at graduation, in addition to their
diplomas.
11
77
Similarly,
for
Binghamton
professors,
the
EvoS
Programs
website
presents
several
incentives
to
enroll
as
participants.
The
programs
founder
explains
that
EvoS
is
intended
to
train
faculty
as
well
as
students:
Fortunately,
it
is
possible
to
do
this
without
imposing
an
unacceptable
additional
workload
on
the
faculty
[].
EvoS
has
already
stimulated
teaching
and
research
activities
in
new
subject
areas,
involving
faculty
members
who
were
not
part
of
the
initial
core.
When
the
evolutionary
perspective
proves
its
worth
to
a
faculty
member,
achieving
a
professional
level
of
competency
becomes
a
priority
that
contributes
to
rather
than
detracting
from
their
career
goals.
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1007]
Becoming
a
faculty
participant
in
the
EvoS
Program,
Wilson
proposes,
professors
may
increase
the
scope
of
their
knowledge
and
expertise,
without
compromising
their
duties
in
other
disciplines
or
their
own
career
development.
The
program
presents
numerous
incentives
for
professional
scholars
to
participate,
including:
networking
opportunities,
grants,
mentoring
positions,
and
interdisciplinary
collaborations.
Additionally,
participating
professors
courses
will
be
advertised
on
the
EvoS
website,
which
undergraduate
students
may
complete
as
part
of
their
requirements
for
the
Evolutionary
Studies
Certificate.13
14
78
In
addition
to
the
professional
and
educational
incentives,
the
programs
organizers
also
look
to
attract
faculty,
graduates,
and
undergraduate
participation
in
research
programs.
The
EvoS
Program
webpage
offers
an
online
registration
page
for
undergraduate
research
opportunities,
and
undergraduates
may
participate
for
academic
credit,
which
additionally
will
count
toward
their
requirements
for
the
EvoS
Certificate.
Research
that
includes
evolutionary
theories
is
eligible
for
small,
yearly
grants
of
up
to
$1000
from
the
Institute
for
Evolutionary
Studies
an
organization
overseen
by
the
EvoS
founder
and
a
group
of
participating
faculty.
Past
and
ongoing
research
projects
funded
by
the
program
include
investigations
of
child
bullying,
college
student
sexual
promiscuity,
models
for
educational
reform,
and
community
outreach
projects
in
the
City
of
Binghamton.15
79
with
current
scientific
research
(2007a:3-4).
If
the
outlook
for
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
so
grim,
why
promote
its
benefits
so
fervently
and
reward
its
participants
so
generously?
As
I
argue
previously,
this
paradox
is
better
understood
as
a
kind
of
balancing
act,
undertaken
by
a
social
movement
that
is
attempting
to
transform
the
very
institution
that
houses
it.
In
my
further
discussion
of
the
programs
resources,
this
will
become
abundantly
clear.
3b.
Students
Coursework
in
the
EvoS
Program
required
and
elective
coursework.
These
classes
are
typically
offered
through
the
universitys
Biology
and
Anthropology
Departments,
but
(as
I
discuss
below)
some
will
occasionally
appear
in
the
catalogues
of
some
unlikely
disciplines.
Evolution
for
Everyone.
Binghamton
undergraduate
students
who
become
familiar
with
the
EvoS
Program
typically
receive
this
introduction
through
the
freshman-level
course
Evolution
for
Everyone,
taught
each
Fall
semester,
with
150
to
170
students
enrolling
each
session.
The
course
was
initially
taught
by
David
Sloan
Wilson,
until
2009,
when
his
graduate
students
assumed
the
majority
of
courses
responsibilities,
teaching
the
course
either
alone
or
in
pairs.
Occasionally,
Wilson
will
give
guest
lectures,
and
his
popular
science
book
Evolution
for
Everyone:
How
Darwins
Theory
Can
Change
the
Way
We
Think
About
Our
Lives
(2007a)
remains
the
courses
required
textbook
(OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2010;
OBrien
et
al.
2009).
80
This course is notable for its special efforts to relate evolutionary theories to
socio-political
issues.
Writing
on
the
courses
objectives,
its
teachers
suggest
that
general
instruction
on
evolution
is
not
enough
to
hold
student
interest.
Rather,
the
framing
of
the
material
must
itself
be
intriguing
[].
We
emphasize
the
generality
of
evolutionary
theory
by
illustrating
each
major
principle
with
parallel
examples
from
both
biological
and
human-related
literatures.
We
find
this
mixing
particularly
effective.
For
instance,
the
quetzals
tail
is
a
classic
example
of
sexual
selection
illustrating
the
handicap
principle
in
a
nonhuman
species,
which
can
be
compared
with
the
use
of
humor
and
creativity
by
human
males
during
courtship
or
the
role
of
costly
signaling
in
religious
ritual.
In
this
fashion,
students
learn
about
evolution
as
a
theory
that
goes
beyond
the
biological
sciences
from
the
very
beginning.
[OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2010:3]
As
this
description
suggests,
by
drawing
parallels
from
evolutionary
research
on
non-human
species
with
that
on
humans,
instructors
attempt
to
engage
students
who
might
otherwise
lose
interest
(especially
in
a
course
requiring
no
prerequisites).
Arguably,
the
course
must
address
topics
such
as
humor
and
creativity
by
human
males
during
courtship
or
the
role
of
costly
signaling
in
religious
ritual
because
it
also
fulfills
an
undergraduate,
general
education
credit
for
Social
Science.
However,
the
course
is
geared
toward
teaching
evolution
as
a
theory
that
goes
beyond
the
biological
sciences,
and
thus
very
much
dovetails
with
the
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program.
Instructors
for
Evolution
for
Everyone
pursue
a
rather
highly-regarded
initiative
in
higher
education,
toward
student-centered
learning.
Like
many
professional
academics,
their
class
topics
are
directed
toward
likely
student
interests,
and
the
students
choose
their
topics
for
class
research
projects
81
themselves.
As
a
graduate
student
instructor
for
the
course
explains
(in
a
university
video
promotion
for
the
course
and
the
EvoS
program):
Students
seem
to
really
enjoy
the
course
they
really
enjoy
the
exploratory
nature
of
it
the
final
project
is
a
poster
project
that
they
choose
a
topic
early
in
the
semester
and
it
can
range
from
-
theres
definitely
every
year
a
poster
jealousy
and
dating
though
theres
also
other
interesting
ones
ranging
from
trying
to
understand
baseball
or
how
people
behave
in
role
player
games
World
of
Warcraft
from
an
evolutionary
perspective
people
trying
to
understand
dance
trying
to
understand
laughter
all
of
these
things
and
they
spend
a
lot
of
the
semester
a
lot
of
their
assignments
are
very
free
form
assignments
that
say
go
develop
hypotheses
from
an
evolutionary
perspective
on
this
topic
-
and
what
you
think
the
relevance
of
laughter
or
dance
is
and
by
the
end
of
the
semester
they
present
a
poster
where
they
propose
novel
research
about
the
topic
research
thats
never
been
done
before
As
this
speaker
comments,
the
flexibility
of
this
course
encourages
students
to
examine
the
evolutionary
concepts
they
have
encountered
in
the
course
with
a
subject
of
their
own
(OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2010:8).
This
is,
as
I
suggest
above,
much
in
keeping
with
institutional
initiatives
in
higher
education
to
engage
students
by
making
classes
about
them
(as
opposed
to
lecture-based,
teacher-centered
education).
Yet,
clearly
the
speakers
description
of
these
students
projects
also
echoes
much
of
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning.
As
I
have
also
observed
in
the
Evolution
for
Everyone
poster
session,
these
projects
employ
cultural
evolutionary
theories
to
explain
activities
and
relationships
that
are
(in
one
way
or
another)
important
to
these
students
lives.
Further,
these
projects
almost
inevitably
presuppose
that
the
human
species
is
continuing
to
evolve,
as
demonstrated
by
these
students
own
observations
of
social
life.
To
this
end,
the
objective
of
the
82
course
parallels
the
mission
statement
in
the
EvoS
Programs
promotional
literature:
[E]volutionary
theory
will
probably
never
be
generally
accepted
no
matter
how
well
supported
by
facts
unless
it
consequences
for
human
affairs
are
fully
addressed.
Once
evolution
is
seen
as
unthreatening,
explanatory,
and
useful
for
solving
lifes
problems,
then
it
becomes
not
just
acceptable
but
irresistible
to
the
average
person.16
The
student-centered
learning
employed
in
Evolution
for
Everyone
can
thus
been
seen
as
encouraging
widespread
acceptance
of
cultural
evolutionary
theories
and
the
continuing
evolution
of
Homo
sapiens
presupposed
ideologies
within
the
evolutionary
reasoning
of
the
EvoS
Program.
EvoS
organizers
similarly
argue
that
Evolution
for
Everyone
is
a
way
to
rectify
the
widespread
doubts
about
evolutions
validity
in
the
United
States.
The
organizers
particularly
fault
relegation
of
evolutionary
science
to
biological
(i.e.
non-human)
science
education
as
a
primary
cause
for
its
unpopularity.
In
a
2009
article,
they
explain,
While
this
ideological
conflict
about
human
origins
is
ongoing
in
society
as
a
whole,
there
is
also
a
divide
within
academia
as
to
the
theorys
applicability
to
human
research.
Some
take
the
stance
that
evolutionary
theory
should
inform
all
behavioral
studies,
be
the
focus
on
individuals
or
societal
institutions
[].
Nevertheless,
evolution
is
still
taught
primarily
as
a
subject
in
the
biological
sciences,
rather
than
a
theory
that
can
help
to
unify
the
human-related
disciplines.
[OBrien
et
al.
2009:445]
In
such
arguments,
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
a
challenge
to
U.S.
higher
education
should
embrace
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
foundation
of
all
explanations
of
social
life
also
appears
as
the
resolution
for
a
much
broader
16
Quoted from About EvoS, a promotional flyer distributed throughout Binghamton University during
the 2012-2013 school year.
83
dispute
between
scientists
and
creationists
in
this
country
(see
also
D.S.
Wilson
2005a,
2007a;
Garcia
et
al.
2011;
Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010).
The
Evolution
for
Everyone
course
can
thus
be
understood
as
(on
one
hand)
an
initiative
to
resolve
the
divide
between
religious
and
scientific
institutions
in
the
U.S.,
while
(on
the
other)
an
introduction
for
incoming,
university
freshman
to
the
EvoS
Programs
challenge
to
higher
education.
As
one
course
instructor
explains
in
a
promotional
video:
the
main
goal
of
the
course
is
to
take
the
theory
of
evolution
which
is
often
treated
as
a
biological
theory
-
and
expanding
it
to
all
the
other
disciplines
that
deal
with
living
things
which
specifically
are
human
oriented
and
I
introduce
them
to
EvoS
Evolution
for
Everyone
is
the
opening
course
to
getting
an
EvoS
certificate
a
certificate
in
Evolutionary
Studies
which
is
a
program
in
the
school
which
includes
many
courses
that
are
evolution
oriented
from
different
human
related
disciplines
ranging
from
psychology
to
anthropology
to
even
the
school
of
management
and
human
development
and
so
we
have
all
these
-
we
have
all
these
courses
and
students
can
take
these
courses
and
earn
an
EvoS
degree
or
EvoS
certificate
alongside
their
standard
major
EvoS
organizers
are
not
shy
about
using
and
advertising
this
course
as
their
main
recruiting
vehicle.
The
student
projects
poster
session
at
the
courses
end
similarly
serves
this
function,
as
it
is
advertised
across
campus,
especially
to
EvoS
students
and
faculty
as
a
way
of
welcoming
a
new
cohort
into
the
multi-course
program
(OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2010:8).
84
resources
are
necessary
and
understandable
inclusions
for
nearly
any
academic
program.
However,
the
program
deviates
from
the
presuppositions
of
higher
education
by
introducing
its
own
ideologies
and
first
principle
to
incoming
students,
who
are
seen
by
program
organizers
as
potential
recruits.
As
these
students
join,
they
will
encounter
other
EvoS
Program
courses,
which
I
turn
to
next.
Other
Courses
Used
for
Evolutionary
Studies
Certificate
Credits.
Around
80
courses
offered
at
Binghamton
University
have
been
approved
by
their
instructors
and
EvoS
organizers
as
coursework
credits
toward
the
Evolutionary
Studies
Certificate.
These
courses
are
primarily
offered
by
the
Biology
or
Anthropology
departments,
but
others
are
occasionally
scheduled
in
Psychology,
Philosophy,
Bioengineering,
Economics,
English,
and
Environmental
Studies.
They
are
often
taught
by
faculty
members
in
the
EvoS
Program
(whom
I
discuss
below).
As
David
Sloan
Wilson
explains
in
one
of
the
programs
tutorial
documents,
the
most
basic
component
in
building
an
EvoS
Program
is
a
group
of
faculty
across
a
variety
of
departments
who
are
already
teaching
and/or
conducting
research
from
an
evolutionary
perspective.
A
very
modest
investment
on
the
part
of
the
Administration
can
be
sufficient
to
create
a
program
that
facilitates
their
interactions
and
makes
their
courses
available
to
students
from
other
departments.
Most
administrators
already
value
integration
and
are
eager
to
reward
this
kind
of
initiative.
Students
who
have
been
turned
on
to
evolution
by
a
single
course
or
their
own
reading
are
eager
to
join
a
multi-course
program.17
Along
with
the
introductory
Evolution
for
Everyone
course,
the
EvoS
Program
argues
that
these
courses
demonstrate
the
institutional
successes
of
the
EvoS
Program
(and
evolutionary
reasoning
in
general),
as
demonstrated
by
the
academic
17
85
benefits
it
provides
for
students.
This
argument
appears
in
the
EvoS
Consortium
organizers
2008
NSF
proposal:
It
is
common
for
EvoS
students
to
report
to
us
that
their
general
academic
performance
improved
after
learning
about
evolution
because
they
made
connections
that
they
were
not
making
before.
Some
even
report
their
frustration
that
these
connections
are
not
being
made
by
their
instructors
in
non-EvoS
courses!
[D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2008:14]
Courses
linked
to
the
EvoS
Program
are
(these
authors
posit)
inspiring
students
toward
improved
educational
engagement,
which
the
students
themselves
report.
Like
Evolution
for
Everyone,
other
EvoS-related
courses
are
engaged
by
this
program
as
a
source
for
new
participants,
who
are
turned
on
to
evolution
by
such
courses
and
apparently
go
on
to
voice
their
disappointments
that
other
university
programs
do
not
offer
a
similar
experience.
This
resource
is
not
only
a
pool
of
potential
members,
but
also
a
source
of
evaluative
data
that
might
further
demonstrate
EvoS
as
achieving
(and
exceeding)
institutional
goals.
As
its
university
presence
grew
between
2008
and
2011,
EvoS
Program
organizers
conducted
surveys
further
testing
the
hypothesis
that
evolutionary
training
increases
general
critical
thinking
skills,
academic
performance,
and
career
attainment
post-graduation
(D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2008:14).
The
first
of
these
tests
matched
a
sample
of
EvoS
and
non-EvoS
students
by
gender,
major,
college
year,
and
incoming
SAT
scores.
All
students
were
then
asked
to
complete
a
number
of
cognitive
reasoning
tasks
and
short
answer
questions
on
both
biological
and
human-related
subjects.
In
this
surveys
results:
EvoS
students
spontaneously
employed
evolutionary
reasoning
more
than
non-EvoS
students
for
both
biological
and
human-related
questions,
demonstrating
the
transfer
of
reasoning
skills
outside
the
86
classroom
[].
In
other
words,
teaching
the
specific
content
of
evolutionary
science
achieves
a
general
goal
of
undergraduate
education.
[D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011:7]
In
a
second
experiment,
the
final
grades
earned
by
163
EvoS
students
were
compared
to
those
of
163
non-EvoS
students
across
several
courses,
additionally
comparing
the
students
by
their
academic
majors.
In
this
second
survey:
Biology
majors
enrolled
in
the
EvoS
program
did
not
earn
higher
grades
than
their
non-EvoS
counterparts,
but
EvoS
students
majoring
in
psychology,
the
social
sciences,
and
the
health
sciences
did
outperform
their
non-EvoS
counterparts.
The
most
reasonable
explanation
for
these
results
is
that
biology
majors
learn
about
evolution
even
when
they
dont
participate
in
EvoS.
Students
from
other
majors
typically
dont
receive
evolutionary
training,
but
when
they
do
through
EvoS
it
increases
their
academic
performance.
Once
again,
teaching
the
specific
content
of
evolutionary
science
achieves
a
general
goal
of
undergraduate
education.
[D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011:7]
Using
the
same
sample
set,
the
researchers
conducted
a
third
analysis,
comparing
the
final
grades
of
EvoS
vs.
non-EvoS
students
in
courses
that
counted
toward
the
EvoS
Certificate
vs.
those
that
did
not.
Assessing
the
results,
the
researchers
are
taken
aback:
Remarkably,
EvoS
students
do
not
outperform
their
non-EvoS
counterparts
for
courses
that
earn
EvoS
credits,
but
they
do
outperform
their
non-EvoS
counterparts
for
courses
in
the
social
sciences
and
humanities
that
do
not
earn
EvoS
credits.
The
most
reasonable
interpretation
of
this
result
is
the
same
as
for
the
comparison
of
majors.
When
a
course
is
explicitly
taught
from
an
evolutionary
perspective,
EvoS
and
non-EvoS
students
benefit
alike.
For
courses
that
are
not
taught
from
an
evolutionary
perspective,
EvoS
students
perform
better
because
only
they
have
received
the
benefits
of
evolutionary
training.
[D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011:7]
As
the
authors
explain,
previous
tests
simply
demonstrate
that
education
in
evolutionary
reasoning
inspires
students
toward
the
general
goal
of
undergraduate
education
earning
higher
grades
and
employing
knowledge
across
diverse
tasks.
87
In
this
final
case,
however,
the
authors
argue
that
this
kind
of
education
might
(potentially)
satisfy
the
democratic
ideals
of
liberal
education:
If
evolutionary
training
increases
academic
performance,
then
the
performance
differential
of
EvoS
vs.
non-EvoS
students
should
be
erased
when
evolutionary
training
is
provided
to
everyone.
[D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011:8].
Were
evolutionary
reasoning
embraced
as
the
foundation
of
all
university
courses
if
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
were
realized
an
academic
inequality
would
be
dissolved.
Here,
I
suggest,
program
organizers
use
a
pool
of
research
subjects
to
argue
the
legitimacy
of
their
movements
first
principle
in
a
quite
complicated
way:
By
extending
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundation
to
a
wide
spectrum
of
courses
(they
argue),
the
academic
performance
of
both
participants
and
non-participants
was
improved.
By
maximally
expanding
these
kinds
of
courses
(such
that
all
courses
become
EvoS
courses),
the
university
could
ensure
that
all
students
democratically
experience
these
same
positive
results.
As I have shown here, courses linked to the EvoS Program provide not just a
resource
for
the
programs
need
to
recruit
new
members,
but
also
a
fruitful
pool
of
research
subjects
that
might
empirically
support
the
programs
successful
implementation
of
the
commonly-argued
goals
of
higher
education.
These
organizers
are
obviously
employing
their
extensive
training
in
surveying
and
analyzing
sample
sets,
in
order
to
meet
administrative
expectations
for
academic
programs
self-evaluation
and
accountability
a
common
enough
practice
in
contemporary
U.S.
higher
education
(Readings
1996).
More
astounding
is
the
researchers
conclusion
that
these
courses
succeed
in
ways
that
demonstrate
the
need
for
evolutionary
reasoning
to
be
extended
to
all
courses,
and
thus
realizing
this
88
social
movements
first
principle.
In
this
way,
there
is
another
balancing
act
being
performed
by
this
movement:
Attention
to
student
performance,
empirical
evaluation,
academic
accountability,
and
equality
in
higher
education
has
been
pressed
toward
a
challenge
to
higher
education,
itself.
Until
such
a
time
as
evolutionary
training
is
provided
to
everyone,
its
benefits
will
only
be
experienced
by
the
EvoS
Programs
members.
3c.
Membership
in
the
EvoS
Program
Establishing
an
accurate
head
count
of
participants
in
a
social
movement
is
a
complex
matter.
While
the
EvoS
Programs
website
lists
faculty
and
graduate
participants
(numbering
around
70),
the
programs
electronic
listserv
likely
includes
hundreds
of
recipients,
reaching
both
former
and
present
participants.
To
complicate
matters
further,
EvoS
membership
must
be
quite
broadly
defined
here,
insofar
as
some
of
these
individuals
no
longer
attend
Binghamton
University
or
live
in
the
area,
although
organizers
still
count
them
as
the
members
of
the
program.
Further,
undergraduates
and
graduates
who
enroll
in
the
programs
classes
are
encouraged
(or
in
some
cases
required)
to
simultaneously
enroll
as
EvoS
Program
members.
The
EvoS
website
lists
approximately
50
participating
faculty
members,
situated
in
various
departments
at
Binghamton
University.
Many
teach
in
biology,
anthropology,
psychology,
systems
science,
bio-engineering,
and
economics.
Other
participating
members
are
professors
come
from
Philosophy,
English,
and
History.
As
the
website
explains:
EvoS
began
with
a
core
of
approximately
15
faculty
who
were
already
employing
the
evolutionary
perspective
in
their
teaching
and
89
research.
Within
a
few
years
it
grew
to
over
50
faculty,
representing
virtually
every
department
on
campus.
The
new
faculty
participants
were
curious
and
open-minded
about
evolution
but
had
not
received
evolutionary
training
during
their
own
graduate
and
post-graduate
education.18
Again,
the
participation
of
these
faculty
is
unclear,
as
some
have
agreed
to
represent
their
departments
(in
EvoS
promotions,
praising
their
curiosity
and
open-mindedness
about
evolution)
but
rarely
participate
in
any
EvoS
activities.
As
I
have
found
in
my
fieldwork,
the
majority
of
active
participants
(those
helping
to
organize
regularly
attending
EvoS
activities)
are
undergraduate
and,
to
a
lesser
extent,
graduate
students.
Students
enrolled
in
EvoS-related
courses
typically
number
between
80-120,
per
semester,
although
often
many
of
these
are
the
same
students,
from
one
semester
to
the
next.
The
diverse
backgrounds
of
these
participants
are
impressive
and
continuously
promoted.
The
programs
founder
observes
that
EvoS
activities
are
attended,
understood,
and
enjoyed
by
a
single
audience
of
undergraduate
students,
graduate
students,
and
faculty
representing
all
departments
on
campus.
The
only
thing
that
makes
this
possible
is
theoretical
integration.
The
speakers
and
audience
alike
share
a
common
conceptual
framework
that
enables
them
to
transcend
disciplinary
boundaries.
[D.S.
Wilson
2005:1007]
An
additional
complexity
in
accounting
for
EvoS
membership
thus
lies
in
the
groups
ardent
promotion
of
itself
as
a
vibrant
entity.
Such
information
often
glosses
the
distinction
between
passive
and
active
group
members.
For
the
promoters
of
EvoS,
the
very
act
of
participating
(in
these
cases,
answering
an
email
or
attending
a
class)
qualifies
one
as
a
member
of
the
program.
18
90
example,
a
recent
EvoS
flyer
includes
a
picture
of
David
Sloan
Wilson
standing
with
students
of
different
genders
and
ethnic
backgrounds,
even
though
the
adjoining
text
lists
the
names
of
the
programs
organizers
and
steering
committee
positions
belonging
to
no
one
pictured,
save
for
Wilson
(see
figure
1).
Like
many
other
sectors
of
higher
education,
the
EvoS
Program
is
committed
to
promoting
its
interdisciplinarity
and
multiculturalism
and
the
diversity
of
its
participants.
Yet,
for
EvoS,
the
spectrum
of
its
membership
does
not
only
adhere
to
institutional
concerns,
but
additionally
(and
more
importantly)
demonstrates
the
relevance
of
its
own
first
principle.
On
this,
Wilson
describes
the
results
of
the
programs
course,
Evolution
for
Everyone:
The
majority
of
students,
not
just
a
select
few,
learned
to
think
about
evolution
as
a
powerful
way
to
understand
the
world
in
general
and
especially
their
own
interests
and
concerns
[]
A
background
in
science
or
prior
knowledge
of
evolution
was
not
required.
Freshman
English
majors
got
the
message
just
as
strongly
as
senior
biology
majors
[].
The
course
succeeded
across
the
entire
range
of
political
and
religious
beliefs,
from
feminists
to
young
Republicans
and
from
atheists
to
believers.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:8-9]
91
EvoS
membership,
as
argued
by
David
Sloan
Wilson
and
other
program
promoters,
exemplifies
the
inherently
interdisciplinary
and
multicultural
appeal
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Clearly,
this
program
exhibits
a
broader
way
of
seeing
its
membership
than
collecting
rosters
or
counting
participants
at
this-or-that
activity.
EvoS
participants
surely
number
into
hundreds
of
individuals
current
students
and
faculty,
administrative
staff,
alumni,
emeritus
professors,
and
non-academics
in
private
and
public
professions.
But,
a
notable
difference
in
this
membership
lies
in
how
these
members
are
accounted
for,
relative
to
most
other
academic
departments,
offices,
or
clubs.
Other
university
organizations
tend
to
include
discussions
of
members
in
promotional
literature
(numbers,
biographies,
testimonies,
etc.)
But
the
EvoS
Program
made
concerted
efforts
to
highlight
its
members
acceptance
and
advocacy
of
the
movements
first
principle.
For
example,
David
Sloan
Wilson
argues
that
many
EvoS
students
regard
EvoS
as
their
academic
home
rather
than
their
particular
department.
As
one
student
put
it,
EvoS
provides
a
stimulating
atmosphere
with
which
biologists,
psychologists,
anthropologists,
philosophers,
social
scientists,
and
even
those
in
the
arts
can
transcend
traditional
academic
boundaries
and
collaborate
in
addressing
mutually
interesting
questions.
It
creates
a
think-tank
atmosphere
of
sorts,
and
its
a
beautiful
thing!
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1007]
In
one
sense,
such
commentary
might
be
seen
as
a
hand-picked
evaluation
of
a
particularly
delighted
individual,
although
program
organizers
fully
document
and
advertise
its
participants
overwhelmingly
positive
feedback
on
EvoS
courses
and
research
projects
(see
Carmen
et
al.
2013;
Corrigan
and
Crooker
2009;
OBrien
and
D.S.
Wilson
2010;
D.S.
Wilson
2005a,
2007a,
2011b).
For
students
taking
EvoS
courses,
the
program
founder
explains,
92
learning
about
evolution
is
like
walking
through
a
door
and
not
wanting
to
return.
Using
it
to
think
about
their
interests
and
concerns
becomes
second
nature,
like
riding
a
bicycle.
They
are
eager
to
develop
their
expertise
in
subsequent
courses
and
disappointed
by
professors
who
do
not
share
their
newfound
perspective.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:9]
Taking
Wilsons
argument
seriously
(and
leaving
aside
his
mixed
metaphors),
EvoS
membership
may
not
be
so
much
a
matter
of
the
numbers
of
individuals
that
the
movement
can
count
among
its
ranks,
as
the
ideological
strength
of
its
presuppositions.
That
is,
membership
implies
the
tendency
for
its
participants
to
index
EvoS
ideologies
in
their
activities
and
relationships,
particularly
as
they
engage
with
the
programs
aims
as
a
social
movement.
Institutional
presuppositions
are
co-opted
into
this
enterprise,
at
once
legitimating
the
movement
but
also
strategically
directed
toward
(as
is
the
case
for
EvoS)
a
radical
revision
of
other
institutional
ideologies.
Movement
membership
represents
the
vibrancy
of
the
groups
first
principle
a
fact
that
is
continuously
advertised
in
the
movements
promotional
media.
I
turn
to
this
issue
next.
3d.
The
EvoS
Programs
Promotional
Media
Promotions
of
the
kind
that
EvoS
distributes
are,
of
course,
unlikely
to
depict
the
program
in
anything
but
the
most
positive
light.
They
are
resources
primarily
directed
toward
recruitment
and
advertisement
of
93
program
activities
to
members.
Other
EvoS
Program
resources
are
typically
harnessed
for
its
promotion,
as
many
of
the
examples
I
offer
above
(cited
from
videos,
tutorials,
flyers,
web
pages,
and
both
popular
and
professional
publications)
more
than
amply
demonstrate.
The
programs
media
are
indeed
widely
disseminated
and
demonstrate
the
program
as
roundly
present
at
Binghamton
University.
During
Fall
and
Spring
Semesters,
one
would
be
hard
pressed
to
find
an
announcement
board
on
campus
without
an
EvoS
flyer
or
a
hallway
anywhere
without
at
least
one
office
door
sporting
a
promotional
poster
(for
example,
see
figures
2
and
3).
The
EvoS
Program
Website.
The
EvoS
website
plays
a
key
role
in
promoting
and
recruiting
with
the
program
19.
This
site
offers
tutorials
in
evolutionary
theory,
news
about
upcoming
EvoS
events,
archives
of
visual
and
audio
recordings
from
past
activities,
and
links
to
related
blogs
by
the
founder
and
his
colleagues.
Visually
prioritized
on
the
website
are
links
for
the
Evos
Events
Calendar,
David
Sloan
Wilsons
webpage,
and
The
EvoS
Fund,
where
visitors
can
contribute
financially
to
the
program.
The
website
explains:
90%
of
your
donation
will
be
entered
into
the
EvoS
account
a
very
low
overhead
compared
to
other
tax-exempt
organizations.
You
will
be
supporting
what
is
arguably
the
boldest
experiment
in
evolutionary
training
in
higher
education.20
Recently,
organizers
added
links
to
the
EvoS
Facebook
page
and
the
programs
Twitter
feed.
Obviously,
the
programs
embrace
of
electronic
media
(Facebook,
Twitter,
web
tutorials,
and
distance
learning)
is
part
of
a
broader
incentive
across
19
20
94
many
US
universities
to
keep
up
with
the
times
by
employing
social
media
popular
with
young
consumers
to
advertise
their
institution
and
expand
academic
practices
(teaching,
discussions,
certificate
programs,
etc)
to
a
greater
number
of
potential
students.
This
said,
the
number
and
ways
for
people
to
participate
in
EvoS
are
unusually
high
for
an
academic
webpage,
as
is
apparent
from
its
tutorials
for
non-
academic
participants,
intricate
information
on
how
to
Start
Your
Own
EvoS
Program,
and
the
EvoS
Fund.
The
website
additionally
includes
a
great
deal
of
information
about
(and
contributions
from)
undergraduate,
graduate,
and
faculty
EvoS
participants,
in
various
ways
linking
their
professional
and
personal
interests
to
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning.21
Further,
the
website
advertises
ongoing
research
projects
and
clubs
being
organized
by
EvoS
students
and
faculty.
For
example,
the
website
promotes
the
EvoS
Lifestyle
Project,
a
combination
of
Paleolithic
diet
regimes
and
social
organization
intervention
based
on
group
selection.
The
projects
organizers
explain
the
project
is
based
on
a
principle
that
human
metabolism,
physiology
and
behavior
has
not
fully
acclimatized
and
adapted
to
the
dietary
and
lifestyle
changes
that
have
occurred
since
the
advent
of
agriculture
and
especially
more
recently
since
the
industrial
revolution
and,
further
(in
the
spirit
of
group
selection
theory),
individuals
find
it
easier
to
adhere
to
a
diet
as
groups
as
compared
to
when
alone
[].
One
of
the
design
principles
is
forming
strong
group
identity:
identifying
a
unified
group
goal
to
attain
healthy
lifestyle
could
provide
such
an
identity.22
21
22
95
Interestingly,
the
EvoS
website
thus
functions
not
just
as
a
resource
for
program
recruitment
and
funding.
Rather,
like
EvoS-related
courses,
the
webpage
builds
pools
of
research
subjects
that
might
generate
empirical
evidence
on
the
positive
benefits
of
employing
evolutionary
reasoning
in
daily
life.
Emails.
EvoS
participants
often
receive
two
or
three
emails
regarding
program
activities
a
week,
either
directly
from
EvoS
organizers
or
(sometimes)
forwarded
across
departmental
listservs.
Past
and
present
participants
receive
news
about:
upcoming
lectures,
EvoS
events
outside
the
university,
student
research,
grant
applications,
and
calls
for
faculty
and
student
members
to
promote
the
program
via
surveys
and
written
testimonies.
These
surveys
and
testimonials
often
appear
in
the
EvoS
Programs
grant
applications
to
the
National
Science
Foundation
and
other
financial
supporters.
To
this
end,
like
the
EvoS
webpage
and
its
courses,
such
emails
tap
participants
as
resources
that
might
speak
on
the
programs
institutional
successes
and
their
support
of
its
first
principle.
The
EvoS
Illuminate.
One
notable,
promotional
resource
that
organizers
use
to
highlight
EvoS
membership
is
the
programs
newsletter,
the
Illuminate.
The
bulk
of
each
edition
of
the
Illuminate
is
dedicated
to
interviews
with
students
and
faculty
EvoS
participants.
Unsurprisingly,
these
interviews
are
fairly
uncritical
of
the
EvoS
Program.
Yet,
the
Illuminates
Spotlights
section
on
EvoS
students
and
faculty
further
prompts
these
individuals
to
voice
their
convictions
(about
EvoS
and
evolutionary
reasoning)
in
more
striking
ways.
For
example,
when
asked
how
evolutionary
theory
changed
how
you
think
about
the
world,
one
student
replies:
Evolutionary
theory
has
provided
me
with
an
ordered,
logical
lens
with
which
to
view
the
world.
Where
once
I
searched
through
the
96
seeming
chaos
in
vain
for
the
explanations
of
behavior,
now
I
merely
ask
a
single,
simple
question:
How
might
this
behavior
be
evolutionarily
adaptive?
The
answers
are
sometimes
chilling,
sometimes
comforting,
but
they
are
always
interesting,
rational,
and,
in
my
opinion,
the
best
explanations
we
have
for
human
behavior.
[Finn
et
al.
2010:8]
Other
students
responses
to
this
same
question
are
less
melodramatic,
but
similarly
endorse
the
transforming
experiences
of
evolutionary
reasoning
without
reservation.
Another
student
explains:
It
has
changed
how
I
think
about
the
world
in
every
way.
It
gives
me
a
persistently
inquisitive
mind
in
all
aspects
of
my
life.
[]
I
personally
think
evolutionary
theory
is
one
of
the
most
important
things
a
person
can
learn
it
can
truly
change
your
life.
[Chang
2009:3]
While
they
tend
to
offer
more
polemical
responses,
some
professors
interviewed
in
the
Illuminate
are
no
less
explicit
or
colorful
than
their
students
when
they
comment
on
evolutionary
reasonings
potential
for
enlightenment
and
personal
transformation.
For
example,
asked
the
same
question,
a
faculty
participant
states:
Having
a
sophisticated
understanding
[of]
evolutionary
theory
and
evolutionary
principles
is
like
having
a
flashlight
in
the
dark.
Scratch
that.
Its
like
having
a
spotlight
in
the
dark.
Being
exposed
to
the
explanatory
power
of
evolution
by
natural
selection
allows
students
to
make
sense
of,
and
make
predictions
about,
the
world
around
them.
Ive
noticed
that
students
with
a
deep
understanding
of
evolution
are
much
more
critical
when
they
hear
claims
about
human
psychology
and
behavior.
They
recognize
that
a
claim
about
universal
human
behavior,
for
example,
must
jibe
with
evolutionary
theory.
[Chang
2010:3]
As
expected,
this
informal
newsletter
offers
some
rather
ringing
endorsements
of
the
EvoS
Program.
But
what
further
appear
(in
abundance)
are
reiterations
of
the
programs
first
principle,
affirming
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
explanations
of
social
life.
97
3e.
Funding
In
August
2008,
the
National
Science
Foundation
awarded
the
EvoS
Consortium
a
Course,
Curriculum,
and
Laboratory
Improvement
(CCLI),
Phase
II
(or
Full
Implementation)
grant
to
fund
its
Collaborative
Proposal:
Expanding
Evolutionary
Studies
in
American
Higher
Education.
The
total
sum
of
this
grant
($500,000)
was
split
approximately
60/40
between
the
EvoS
Programs
at
Binghamton
and
SUNY
New
Paltz.23
With
funds
from
the
NSF
grant,
the
EvoS
Consortium
underwrote
the
SUNY
New
Paltz
program,
distributed
startup
packages
of
up
to
$2,500
to
other
universities
(see
D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2008
and
D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011).24
For
the
past
10
years,
David
Sloan
Wilson
and
the
EvoS
Program
have
also
been
well
funded
by
the
John
Templeton
Foundation
and
its
Institute
for
Research
on
Unlimited
Love.25
The
Templeton
Foundation
is
a
patron
of
interdisciplinary
research,
founded
in
1987
by
the
multi-millionaire
venture
capitalist,
John
Templeton.
The
research
that
this
institution
funds
often
deals
with
scientific
inquiries
into
quite
challenging
topics,
such
as:
religious
faith,
community
solidarity,
freedom,
and
forgiveness.
The
foundations
website
explains
it
as
23
Details and abstracts for these grants are available from the NSF website: Award Abstract #0817276
(http://www.nsf.gov/awardsearch/showAward.do?AwardNumber=0817276) and #0817337
(http://www.nsf.gov/awardsearch/showAward.do?AwardNumber=0817337), covering the Binghamton and
SUNY New Paltz EvoS Programs, respectively (both addresses accessed Dec. 29, 2011).
24
In
January
2011,
EvoS
Consortium
organizers
submitted
a
proposal
to
the
NSF
for
a
multi-million
dollar
Phase
III
grant,
EvoS:
A
Worldwide
Evolutionary
Studies
Consortium
(D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011),
which
did
not
receive
NSF
approval.
25
For references to EvoS-related projects receiving Templeton Foundation funding, see: Kniffin et al.
2003; Post et al. 2002; Schneider 2010; D.S.Wilson 2002:260, 2005b; 2007a: 11, 2011:102-125 and 312317; D.S. Wilson and Kniffin 2003
98
a
philanthropic
catalyst
for
discoveries
relating
to
the
Big
Questions
of
human
purpose
and
ultimate
reality.
We
support
research
on
subjects
ranging
from
complexity,
evolution,
and
infinity
to
creativity,
forgiveness,
love,
and
free
will.
We
encourage
civil,
informed
dialogue
among
scientists,
philosophers,
and
theologians
and
between
such
experts
and
the
public
at
large,
for
the
purposes
of
definitional
clarity
and
new
insights.26
The
Institute
for
Research
on
Unlimited
Love
previously
granted
$100,000,
to
a
2003-2007
project
headed
by
Wilson,
titled
Altruistic
Love,
Evolution,
and
Individual
Experience,
$13,500
for
his
Annotated
Bibliography
and
Critical
Review
of
Altruism
from
an
Evolutionary
Perspective,
and
an
unknown
amount
for
a
co-
piloted,
2004-2006
project
called
Health
and
the
Ecology
of
Altruism.27
The
John
Templeton
Foundation
itself
awarded
$200,000
to
Wilsons
1998-2000
research
titled
Forgiveness
from
a
Cross-Cultural
and
Evolutionary
Perspective
and
another
$100,000
for
Religious
Conceptions
of
the
Afterlife
from
a
Cultural
Evolutionary
Perspective
and
a
General
Field
of
Evolutionary
Religious
Studies.28
In
2011,
the
foundation
awarded
Wilson
$200,000
for
The
Role
of
Religion
in
Managing
the
Commons.29
Unlike
the
NSF
grant,
these
awards
are
not
directly
demarcated
for
the
EvoS
Program,
but
are
nevertheless
employing
EvoS
Program
participants
as
researchers
and
lecturers.
Further,
funds
from
the
Templeton
Foundation
have
been
significantly
more
fluid
than
that
of
the
NSF,
as
the
former
does
not
require
the
same
kind
of
rigid
budgeting
and
bookkeeping.
26
27
28
See Post et al. 2002 and D.S. Wilson 2007a:11, 2011:102-125 and 312-317
29
99
It
a
bears
noting
that
John
Templeton
was
a
evangelical
Christian
(like
his
son,
the
foundations
current
director)
and
the
foundation
also
awards
millions
of
dollars
to
Intelligent
Design
theorists,
the
American
Bible
Society,
evangelists
such
as
Billy
Graham,
and
Mel
Gibson
for
directing
The
Passion
of
the
Christ
(Horgan
2006;
Schneider
2010).
David
Sloan
Wilson
and
the
EvoS
Program
have
unsurprisingly
received
some
criticism
from
others
in
the
scientific
community
for
engaging
the
Templeton
Foundation
as
a
funding
resource.
For
example,
following
a
largely
negative
review
of
Wilson
in
a
New
York
Times
book
review
(Coyne
2011),
ecologist
Jerry
Coyne
explains
on
his
blog:
Wilsons
efforts,
of
course,
are
heavily
funded
by
the
Templeton
Foundation,
where
hes
on
the
Board
of
Advisors.
It
is,
of
course,
typical
of
the
Templeton
Foundation
that
their
advisors
have
received
some
form
of
Templeton
funding;
its
the
way
they
herd
scientists
into
their
posh
stable.
In
fact,
I
recognize
several
scientists
on
the
advisory
board,
and
all
of
them
that
I
know
have
received
either
a
Templeton
Prize
or
Templeton
funding
for
their
work.
[Coyne
2012]
Coyne
and
others
argue
that
research
performed
by
Wilson
(and
his
several
colleagues,
also
affiliated
with
Templeton)
has
suffered
by
association
with
the
foundation,
while
others
simply
criticize
him
for
lending
his
reputation
to
an
entity
that
supports
individuals
and
anti-evolution
agendas
(Bains
2011;
Plotz
1997).
Besides
its
rather
lavish
funding
of
EvoS
and
David
Sloan
Wilsons
other
projects,
it
is
clear
that
the
Templeton
Foundation
offers
a
wide
number
of
venues
for
Wilson
and
his
colleagues
to
advocate
their
challenge
to
higher
education
and
promote
the
programs
first
principle.
Wilson
regularly
speaks
at
the
Templeton
Foundations
conferences,
serves
on
its
board
of
advisors
(as
Coyne
notes),
and
contributes
to
the
Templeton
Foundations
Big
Questions
Online.
Interestingly,
on
100
at
least
one
occasion,
Wilson
used
the
Big
Questions
venue
as
a
platform
for
fund-
raising
from
another
source
a
grant
from
the
Pepsi
Refresh
Challenge,
a
competitive,
philanthropic
project
(underwritten
by
the
soft
drink
company)
that
was
yearly
awarding
several
million
dollars
to
ideas
that
will
refresh
the
world
in
education,
health,
and
community
renewal.30
Amazingly,
Wilson
writes:
Youve
heard
of
the
Pepsi
Challenge.
I
now
invite
people
who
ask
this
question
to
take
the
Evolution
Challenge.
In
one
cup,
place
any
given
body
of
knowledge
that
has
developed
about
our
species
without
reference
to
evolution.
In
a
second
cup,
place
the
same
body
of
knowledge
viewed
from
an
evolutionary
perspective.
Take
a
sip
of
both.
If
they
taste
exactly
the
same,
then
the
evolutionary
perspective
merely
rediscovers
what
is
already
known.
If
they
taste
different,
then
the
evolutionary
perspective
has
added
something
new
perhaps
a
reorganization
of
existing
knowledge,
a
new
set
of
questions,
the
identification
of
false
claims,
or
the
integration
of
knowledge
across
disciplines
for
a
more
cosmopolitan
flavor.
31
As
demonstrated
by
these
examples
of
the
Templeton
Foundation
and
the
Pepsi
Refresher
Challenge
(which
the
EvoS
Program
did
not
win),
the
funding
resources
of
social
movements
are
combinations
of
more
and
less
institutionally
presupposed
financiers.
By
virtue
of
their
challenge
to
higher
education,
movements
such
as
EvoS
are
less
bound
to
the
monies
that
might
be
found
there.
While
garnering
funding
from
outside
sources
has
drawn
criticism
from
the
scientific
community,
David
Sloan
Wilson
has
continued
to
find
new
patrons,
recruit
participants,
and
fund
projects
that
(in
his
words)
wouldn't
have
had
a
snowball's
chance
in
hell
of
being
funded
by
an
agency
such
as
the
National
Science
Foundation
(D.S.
Wilson
2011b:
312).
30
31
http://www.bigquestionsonline.com/columns/david-sloan-wilson/take-the-evolution-challenge (Accessed
August 10, 2010)
101
Chapter
Three:
The
EvoS
Programs
In-House
Ideologies
In
my
previous
chapter,
I
propose
that
the
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program
is
a
challenge,
posed
to
U.S.
higher
education,
to
accept
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
foundation
for
all
explanations
of
social
life.
Certainly,
this
is
an
ambitious
goal.
But
the
first
principles
of
social
movements
are
idealistic
not
pragmatic,
and
the
methods
by
which
aparticipant
might
pursue
a
radical
change
in
higher
education
are
more
complex
than
repeatedly
saying
(or
writing)
the
first
principle.
As
Bertrand
Susser
explains:
In
and
of
themselves,
first
principles
adumbrate
only
the
broadest
objectives
and
the
most
basic
preferences.
To
be
put
into
practice,
philosophical
ideology
must
be
operationalized,
it
must
become
an'operational
code'.
It
needs
to
be
fleshed
out
in
the
push
and
pull
of
real
political
life
[].
To
operationalize
these
first
principles,
political
actors
need
to
incorporate
pragmatic
and
functional
elements
that
are
not
(protestations
to
the
contrary
notwithstanding)
intrinsic
to
the
ideology's
first
principles.
In
other
words,
knowledge
of
an
ideology's
first
principles
provides'
only
limited
ability
to
anticipate
the
specific
programmes
its
executors
will
actually
adopt.
[Susser
1996:168]
In
order
to
legitimize
the
movement,
mobilize
its
members,
and
socialize
new
recruits,
a
social
movement
must
(in
one
way
or
another)
make
its
first
principle
into
something
real
and
pressing
for
those
both
inside
and
outside
the
movement.
To
borrow
again
from
Susser,
these
are
the
in-house
ideologies
of
a
social
movement,
which
are
understood
and
circulated
among
its
members,
used
to
orient
successes
of
(and
challenges
to)
the
movement,
102
and
function
to
introduce
new
participants
to
the
movements
concerns.
While
an
in-house
ideology
is
related
to
a
movements
first
principle,
it
does
not
need
to
deal
with
objections
at
the
level
of
principle.
It
tends
to
be
power-centered
and
prudential
rather
than
theoretical
and
systematic;
it
is
more
concerned
with
cost
and
benefit
than
with
belief;
it
attempts
to
orient
more
than
it
endeavors
to
explain;
it
is
involved
with
the
relatively
limited
context
and
short-term
rather
than
with
grand
strategic
goals.
[Susser
1996:169]
Given
the
confrontational
nature
of
their
first
principles,
the
in-house
ideologies
of
social
movements
are
likely
going
to
pragmatically
(if
controversially)
address
various
roadblocks
to
seeing
the
first
principle
realized.
The
in-house
ideologies
of
EvoS
do
just
that
they
orient
participant
knowledge
toward
the
various
entities
that
seem
to
resist,
reject,
or
ignore
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education.
EvoS
participants
are
not
the
first
academics
to
promote
this
kind
of
cross-disciplinary
extension
of
evolutionary
science,
nor
are
they
ignorant
of
the
controversies
that
such
arguments
have
stirred.
For
participants,
the
perceived
rejection
or
resistance
to
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is,
in
many
ways,
more
troubling
than
challenges
to
it
in
the
general
U.S.
public.
After
all,
evolutionary
science
has
continuously
been
seen
as
contrary
to
religious
teachings
on
human
origins
and
spiritual
intervention.
But
why
would
professional
academics
(who
are
not,
by-and-large,
creationists)
find
fault
with
evolutionary
reasoning?
The
in-house
ideologies
of
the
EvoS
Program
pose
four
answers
to
this
question:
First,
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
due
to
fears
about
its
political
and
moral
consequences.
Second,
rejection
is
due
to
the
dominance
of
postmodernism
in
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities.
Third,
this
103
rejection
can
be
attributed
to
it
critics
perception
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
politically
incorrect.
Fourth,
EvoS
participants
understand
this
rejection
in
higher
education
is
due
to
its
critics
Ivory
Tower
elitism
and
specialization.
These
ideologies
might
strike
the
reader
(rightly)
as
professional
dissatisfaction
with
the
values
and
structure
of
U.S.
universities
and
colleges.
However,
the
history
of
evolutionary
science
in
higher
education
shows
that
such
dissatisfaction
has
been
shared
by
many
researchers,
theorists,
and
popularizers
of
science,
and
moreover
that
the
EvoS
Program
at
Binghamton
University
is
one
more
entry
in
a
quite
long
and
contentious
struggle.
The
in-house
ideologies
of
the
EvoS
Program
have
significantly
greater
scope
than
those
of
its
evolutionary
reasoning,
many
of
which
(as
I
explained
in
my
previous
chapter)
are
hotly
contested
in
the
evolutionary
science
community.
While
it
is
in
many
ways
internal
to
the
program
(relative
to
Binghamton
Universitys
other
academic
disciplines),
this
realm
of
ideological
discourse
can
be
encountered
in
a
wide
number
of
evolutionary
scientists
writings
and
lectures
in
the
past
five
decades.
The
in-house
ideologies
of
EvoS
might
thus
be
understood
as
a
purposeful
reframing
of
this
movement
as
continuous
with
the
past
and
present
dissatisfactions
voiced
by
evolutionary
scientists
in
general.
Below,
I
examine
these
in-house
ideologies
in
greater
detail,
focusing
on
their
historical
roots
in
U.S.
higher
education
and
offer
examples
of
their
appearance
in
the
EvoS
Program.
In
subsequent
chapters,
I
demonstrate
that
these
ideologies
are
creatively
indexed
with
great
regularity
in
the
EvoS
Programs
Seminar
Series,
and
104
are
furthermore
central
to
the
first
principles
contextualization
as
the
relevant
meaning
of
EvoS
activities.
Rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
due
to
fears
about
its
political
and
moral
consequences.
Confronted
with
the
unpopularity
of
their
goals
in
U.S.
higher
education,
EvoS
program
participants
tend
to
offer
the
following
explanation:
Academic
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
fear
and
disapprove
of
it
because
of
its
historical
and
political
associations
with
Social
Darwinism,
eugenics
policies,
and
the
Third
Reich.
The
historical
roots
of
this
ideology
can
be
most
directly
traced
to
the
controversies
stirred
by
sociobiology
in
several
U.S.
universities
during
the1970s
and
1980s.
As
proposed
by
its
founders,
sociobiology
embarked
on
two,
interdependent
projects:
On
one
hand,
it
was
to
be
a
broad
research
framework,
using
Darwinian
theory
as
its
underlying
logic;
on
the
other,
sociobiology
was
an
impetus
to
restructure
the
Western
university
and
the
goals
of
academic
inquiries.
In
the
former
case,
sociobiology
was
the
systematic
study
of
the
biological
basis
of
all
social
behavior
(E.O.
Wilson
1975a:4).
Proponents
hoped
to
introduce
the
human
and
non-human
sciences
to
the
conclusions
of
The
Modern
Synthesis,
a
mid-20th
century
effort
by
geneticists,
botanists,
ecologists,
and
paleontologists
to
outline
a
Neo-Darwinian
theory
of
evolution.
In
the
second
goal,
sociobiologists
intended
to
bring
the
Modern
Synthesis
to
bear
on
all
research,
and
thus
unify
the
Biological
and
Social
Sciences
through
shared
acceptance
of
a
theory
of
evolution
by
105
natural
selection.
As
I
explain,
this
second
aim
would
largely
go
unnoticed
in
the
controversy
generated
by
the
first.
Many
professors
in
the
1960s
and
1970s
were
actively
publishing
sociobiological
arguments,
but
Edward
Wilsons
Sociobiology:
The
Modern
Synthesis
(1975a)
and
On
Human
Nature
(1978)
became
the
most
widely
promoted,
read
and
discussed,
inside
and
outside
academia.
The
encyclopedic
1975
volume
was
vigorously
advertised
by
Harvard
University
Press,
including
a
widespread
public
relations
campaign
and
book
tour,
a
front-page
article
in
The
New
York
Times,
a
twelve-page
essay
by
Wilson
in
the
Times
Sunday
Magazine,
and
full-page
ads
in
the
Times
Book
Review
(Albury
1980:522-523).
As
a
result,
Edward
Wilson
quickly
became
the
public
face
of
sociobiology,
and
also
the
primary
target
for
a
growing
group
of
critics.
In
the
heated
socio-political
climate
on
many
U.S.
campuses
of
this
time,
Sociobiology:
The
Modern
Synthesis
became
controversial
as
a
political
assertion
on
the
biological
and
social
inevitability
of
warfare,
inequality,
and
oppression.
Critics
saw
Wilsons
argument
as
an
attempt
to
lend
scientific
legitimacy
to
genocide,
eugenics,
and
sterilization
(Kirby
2005;
Laland
and
Brown
2009:95-97).
In
a
November
letter
to
The
New
York
Review
of
Books,
sixteen
authors
(including
such
notables
as
Richard
Lewontin,
Ruth
Hubbard,
and
Stephen
Jay
Gould)
charged
that
sociobiology
promoted
biological
determinism
and
Social
Darwinism.
They
cited
the
historical
roles
of
biological
determinism
in
laissez-faire
capitalism,
eugenics
programs,
sterilization
laws,
and
the
Nazi
mass-murders.
With
the
publication
of
Sociobiology,
the
authors
argue,
Wilson
joins
the
long
parade
of
biological
106
determinists
whose
work
has
served
to
buttress
the
institutions
of
their
society
by
exonerating
them
from
responsibility
for
social
problems
(Allen
et
al.
1975:42).
Shortly
after,
Edward
Wilson
rebutted
to
this
openly
partisan
attack
on
what
the
signers
mistakenly
conclude
to
be
a
political
message
in
the
book.
Every
principle
assertion
made
in
the
letter
is
either
a
false
statement
or
a
distortion
(E.O.
Wilson
1975b:60).
Over
the
next
several
years,
The
New
York
Review
of
Books
became
a
forum
for
the
Sociobiology
Wars.
Month
after
month,
critics
laid
down
accusations
that
sociobiology
was
deterministic,
unscientific,
and
politically
dangerous.
In
return,
Edward
Wilson
and
his
defenders
charged
that
these
accusations
were
misinformed,
politically
biased,
and
a
threat
to
free
intellectual
inquiry
(Segerstrle
2000).
Tensions
over
sociobiology
were
not
limited
to
the
press.
On
Harvards
campus,
the
authors
of
the
initial
letter
denouncing
Wilson
began
identifying
themselves
as
the
Sociobiology
Study
Group
(SSG),
allied
with
the
Boston
chapter
of
Science
for
the
People.
Members
of
the
SSG
helped
to
establish
similar
groups
at
other
universities,
such
as
the
Ann
Arbor
Science
for
the
People
Editorial
Collective,
who
co-authored
publications
such
as
Biology
as
a
Social
Weapon
(1977),
a
collection
of
papers
echoing
the
sentiments
of
sociobiologys
critics
at
Harvard.
Through
the
writings
and
activities
of
the
SSG,
a
critical
industry
was
born,
and
with
it
a
flurry
of
articles
revealing
the
purported
hidden
ideology,
racism,
sexism,
and
so
forth
in
bad
science
(Segerstrle
2006:81).
From
1975
to
the
mid-1980s,
the
SSG
kept
up
a
collective
attack
on
sociobiologists
at
Harvards
campus
and
elsewhere.
107
For
his
part,
Edward
Wilson
explains
that
he
was
a
political
naf
during
the
1970s,
surprised
by
the
outrage
his
publications
had
inspired
(Levine
2006:110-
111).
Each
semester,
students
and
faculty
lined
up
to
picket
and
protest
outside
classes
led
by
Wilson
and
his
colleagues
(Kirby
2005:82;
Pinker
2002:109-112).
The
most
infamous
of
these
confrontations
occurred
at
the
1978
meeting
of
the
American
Association
for
the
Advancement
of
Science
in
Washington
D.C.
There,
as
Wilson
began
to
speak,
protesters
from
the
SSG
and
the
International
Committee
Against
Racism
stormed
into
the
lecture
hall,
chanting
Racist
Wilson,
you
cant
hide,
we
charge
you
with
genocide!
One
member
of
the
group
leapt
onto
the
stage
and
doused
Wilson
with
a
pitcher
of
ice
water,
shouting,
Wilson,
youre
all
wet!
(Malik
2000:148-159;
Segerstrle
2000;
2001:549).
In
the
early
1980s,
members
of
the
SSG
co-authored
a
general-audience
book,
Not
In
Our
Genes:
Biology,
Ideology,
and
Human
Nature
(Lewontin
et
al.
1984),
further
criticizing
sociobiology
as
a
right-wing,
sexist,
and
racist
use
of
science.
Around
this
same
time,
Wilson
quietly
announced
that
he
would
no
longer
publicly
promote
or
defend
sociobiology
(Kirby
2005:82).
Though
some
of
its
members
(particularly
Lewontin
and
Gould)
continued
to
challenge
sociobiologists
in
the
popular
press,
the
SSG
dissolved
in
the
1980s
into
the
non-profit
Counsel
for
Responsible
Genetics
(Moore
2008:177).
Despite
this
rather
anticlimactic
end,
how
these
debates
unfolded
would
profoundly
shape
the
kinds
of
academic
criticisms
or
defenses
that
would
(or
could)
be
made
about
evolutionary
science
over
the
following
decades.
108
As
it
is
understood
in
the
EvoS
Program,
contemporary
academic
resistance
to
evolutionary
reasoning
is
similar
to
earlier
reactions
to
sociobiology.
This
ideology
finds
its
historical
roots
in
the
polemics
of
the
sociobiology
debates,
where
(from
their
initial
criticism
in
1975)
the
SSG
took
a
stance
of
moral
outrage,
charging
that
biological
determinist
theories
provided
an
important
basis
for
the
enactment
of
sterilization
laws
and
restrictive
immigration
laws
by
the
United
States
between
1910
and
1930
and
also
for
the
eugenics
policies
which
led
to
the
establishment
of
gas
chambers
in
Nazi
Germany
(Allen
et
al.
1975:42).
At
the
same
moment,
similar
imagery
was
evoked
by
protestors
who
gathered
outside
sociobiology
classes
at
Harvard
(Kirby
2005:80-81).
Interestingly,
in
the
public
media,
the
interpersonal
dynamic
of
the
debate
seemed
unfairly
asymmetrical
(Albury
1980:532-3).
The
SSG
forwarded
criticisms
that
were
thematically
consistent,
unified,
and
jointly
outraged.
Sociobiologists
began
to
publicly
appear
like
a
misunderstood
and
persecuted
minority,
and
often
argued
themselves
as
such
(Kirby
2005;
Prindle
2009:118-143).
For
instance,
in
his
rebuttal
to
Allen
et
al.,
Edward
Wilson
writes
that
the
authors
actions
represent
the
kind
of
self-righteous
vigilantism
which
not
only
produces
falsehood
but
also
unjustly
hurts
individuals
and
through
that
kind
of
intimidation
diminishes
the
spirit
of
free
inquiry
and
discussion
crucial
to
the
health
of
the
intellectual
community
[E.O.
Wilson
1975b:61]
The
SSGs
collective
criticism
of
individual
scientists
such
Edward
Wilson
was
understood
by
many
of
their
targets
(and
interested
onlookers)
as
a
reactionary
and
narrow-minded
assault.
109
For
EvoS
Program
participants,
frustrated
by
other
scholars
non-
engagement
with
their
goals,
such
politicizations
of
evolutionary
reasoning
four
decades
ago
provide
a
historical
explanation
for
their
oppositions
behaviors.
Like
Edward
Wilson,
they
see
this
fear
as
irrational,
leading
to
undemocratic
persecution.
For
example,
the
programs
founder
argues:
With
respect
to
Hitler
and
others
who
used
evolution
to
advance
their
nefarious
causes,
its
not
as
if
the
world
was
a
nice
place
before
Darwin
and
became
nasty
on
the
basis
of
his
theory.
America
was
colonized
before
Darwin
and
the
pioneers
used
the
principle
of
divine
right
to
dispossess
the
natives
[].
Before
Darwin,
religious
tracts
claimed
that
Negroes
didnt
have
souls
and
women
were
designed
by
God
and
Nature
for
a
life
of
domestic
servitude.
Is
it
a
surprise
that
the
theory
of
evolution
would
be
pressed
into
the
same
kind
of
service?
Is
that
a
reason
to
reject
the
theory?
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:13]
Narratives
of
anti-evolutionist
persecution
are
commonplace
in
EvoS
participants
writings.
For
example,
EvoS
lecturer
Barbara
Ehrenreich
and
co-author
Janet
McIntosh
retell
how
their
friend,
Phoebe
Ellsworth,
was
persecuted
at
a
conference:
Colleagues
who'd
presented
earlier
had
warned
her
that
the
crowd
was
tough
and
had
little
patience
for
the
reduction
of
human
experience
to
numbers
or
bold
generalizations
about
emotions
across
cultures.
Ellsworth
had
a
plan:
She
would
pre-empt
criticism
by
playing
the
critic,
offering
a
social
history
of
psychological
approaches
to
the
topic.
But
no
sooner
had
the
word
experiment
passed
her
lips
than
the
hands
shot
up.
Audience
members
pointed
out
that
the
experimental
method
is
the
brainchild
of
white
Victorian
males.
Ellsworth
agreed
that
white
Victorian
males
had
done
their
share
of
damage
in
the
world
but
noted
that,
nonetheless,
their
efforts
had
led
to
the
discovery
of
DNA.
This
short-lived
dialogue
between
paradigms
ground
to
a
halt
with
the
retort:
You
believe
in
DNA?
[Ehrenreich
and
McIntosh
1997:11]
Stories
of
this
kind
pepper
publications
by
EvoS
participants
(see
Geher
2006;
Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010;
Glass
et
al.
2012;
Gottschall
2008:17-39;
Gottschall
and
D.S.
Wilson
2005;
Tiger
1996).
They
complain
of
evolutionary
scientists
persecuted
in
110
U.S.
universities,
characterizing
institutional
critics
as
an
unrelenting
mob,
who
attack
individual
researchers
without
concern
for
professional
decorum.
David
Sloan
Wilson
writes
that
these
reactions
have
always
been
based
on
fear
of
the
consequences
of
accepting
evolution
why
else
would
people
who
know
so
little
about
it
feel
so
strongly
about
rejecting
it?
Once
evolutionary
theory
is
seen
as
a
tool
for
positive
change,
it
can
be
easily
accepted,
leading
to
insights
that
in
retrospect
appear
like
just
plain
common
sense.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:99]
Clearly,
these
commentaries
share
a
view
that
their
critics
are
afraid
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
EvoS
participants
understand
these
fears
as
reactionary
and
typically
misguided,
and
further
that
movement
members
experience
persecution
from
their
colleagues
because
the
latter
see
evolutionary
reasoning
as
morally
and
politically
dangerous.
For
EvoS
participants,
this
in-house
ideology
historically
grounds
contemporary
tensions
between
the
movement
and
those
disciplines
it
most
directly
challenges,
drawing
particularly
on
its
similarities
to
the
polemical
sociobiology
debates.
Below
I
will
expand
this
argument
and
suggest
that
(for
program
participants)
a
second
in-house
ideology
logically
follows:
While
the
first
EvoS
ideology
represents
critics
as
rejecting
evolutionary
reasoning
out
of
fear,
this
second
ideology
explains
that
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities
dogmatically
embrace
postmodernist
explanations
for
human
behaviors,
thus
relegating
evolutionary
science
to
the
(non-human)
Biological
Sciences.
111
Rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
due
to
the
dominance
of
postmodernism
in
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities.
In
some
ways
related
to
the
first,
a
second
EvoS
ideology
represents
this
resistance
to
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
more-or-less
unshakable
commitment
to
contrary
intellectual
traditions.
Though
of
course
these
traditions
are
more
diverse
than
this
ideology
presents
them,
EvoS
participants
commonly
understand
their
critics
as
adhering
to
postmodernism.
For
EvoS,
this
moniker
is
shorthand
for
the
principles
and
concepts
that
seem
to
dominate
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities
in
the
absence
of
evolutionary
reasoning
during
the
last
three
decades:
constructivism,
relativism,
deconstruction,
skepticism
toward
grand
theorizing,
attention
to
social
inequality,
and
(most
importantly)
criticism
of
the
authoritative
explanations
of
science.
To
understand
the
historical
grounds
of
this
ideology,
it
is
necessary
to
consider
how
reinvigoration
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
1990s
occurred
within
the
terse
academic
climate
surrounding
the
authority
of
science.
Over
a
decade
after
stepping
away
from
sociobiology
debates,
Edward
Wilson
delivered
the
June
1996
keynote
address
to
the
Human
Behavior
and
Evolution
Society
(HBES).
There,
he
identified
and
vilified
the
opponents
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
postmodernists
in
the
Humanities
and
Social
Sciences.
Historian
Ullica
Segerstrle
describes
his
audiences
confusion
as
Wilson
lashed
out
against
Jacques
Derrida
and
deconstruction,
of
all
things.
(My
first
reaction
was
that
Wilson
had
brought
the
wrong
manuscript,
or
mistaken
the
HBES
audience
for
another
one
say,
a
gathering
of
the
National
Association
of
Scholars.)
It
was
all
rather
embarrassing:
Wilson
went
on
to
treat
the
audience
as
a
kind
of
big
in-
group,
using
a
conspiratorial
tone
and
acting
as
if
we
all
knew
what
he
was
talking
about
and
automatically
agreed.
[Segerstrle
2000:363]
112
While
his
HBES
audience
was
confused,
Edward
Wilson
was
attempting
to
position
evolutionary
science
within
the
debates
over
scientific
objectivity
that
took
place
in
many
U.S.
universities
in
the
1990s.
The
book
Wilson
was
writing,
Consilience:
The
Unity
of
Knowledge,
would
become
a
central
reference
in
these
debates.
As
Segerstrle
elaborates:
With
hindsight,
everything
falls
into
place.
Although
at
the
time
the
audience
didnt
have
a
clue,
Wilsons
keynote
address
was
obviously
adapted
from
his
newest
book,
then
in
progress.
Consilience
in
different
ways,
indeed,
urges
the
natural
sciences
and
humanities
to
unite
around
the
tenets
of
evolutionary
biology.
It
is
also
clear
why
Derrida
and
postmodernism
were
introduced:
they
were
perfect
as
anathema
to
Wilsons
proposed
unification
scheme,
because
they
epitomized
the
skeptical
and
relativistic
accounts
of
socially
constructed
realities
supplied
by
intellectuals
who
have
lost
faith
in
the
original
Enlightenment
quest
for
unified
knowledge,
as
Wilson
later
formulated
it.
[Segerstrle
2000:363-364]
This
keynote
address
was
thus
a
particularly
illustrative
moment
in
U.S.
higher
education,
in
which
Edward
Wilson
and
others
began
to
juxtapose
evolutionary
reasoning
to
the
intellectual
interests
that
(they
believed)
most
inhibited
its
acceptance
in
the
Humanities
and
Social
Sciences.
Consilience
was
a
product
of,
and
contribution
to,
the
debates
over
the
neutrality
of
professional
science
within
numerous
U.S.
and
European
universities.
These
are
now
popularly
(perhaps
regrettably)
remembered
as
the
Science
Wars.
During
the
late
1980s
and
1990s,
antagonism
surged
over
critiques
of
scientific
objectivity
and
authority,
posed
by
scholars
in
Science
and
Technology
Studies,
Cultural
Studies,
History
of
Science,
among
others.
These
critics
argued
that
scientific
texts
uncritically
employed
stereotypes
about
(among
others)
gender,
race,
class,
disability,
sexuality,
and
reproduction
(for
example,
see
Bordo
1987;
113
Fausto-Sterling
1992,
1997,
2000;
Martin
1991,
1994).
Others
were
dissatisfied
with
professional
ethics,
positing
that
contemporary
science
had
flourished
through
unequal
access
to
education
and
socio-economic
inequality
between
researchers
and
their
subjects
(Haraway
1989,
1991;
Harding
1998,
Latour
1987,
1993).
Critics
varied
in
the
intensity
of
their
deliveries,
but
generally
posited
that
scientific
facts
and
(as
well
as
their
authors
motives,
authority,
and
neutrality)
should
be
considered
relative
to
the
times
and
places
in
which
they
are
authored
and
disseminated.
Needless
to
say,
such
critiques
did
not
sit
well
with
many
professional
scientists.
Among
the
more
vitriolic
responses
were
Paul
Gross
and
Norman
Levitts
Higher
Superstition:
The
Academic
Left
and
its
Quarrels
with
Science
(1994)
and
physicist
Alan
Sokals
infamous
hoaxing
of
the
Cultural
Studies
journal
Social
Text
in
1996.
The
most
lasting
effect
of
these
reactions
and
the
most
damaging
consequence,
for
their
targets
was
the
widespread
conflation
of
the
disciplines
and
critics
I
describe
above
into
a
single,
supposedly-unified
academic
trend,
postmodernism,
whose
advocates
supposedly
doubted
the
existence
of
mind-
independent
reality,
empirical
inquiry,
and
even
the
objectivity
of
math,
chemistry,
and
physics.
In
this
terse
academic
landscape,
Edward
Wilson
re-emerged
to
position
evolutionary
science
as
intellectually
and
professionally
opposed
to
postmodernism.
In
Consilience:
The
Unity
of
Knowledge,
he
argues
that
the
Social
Sciences
are
dedicated
to
theories
and
theorists
whose
conclusions
cannot
be
confirmed
or
denied
through
experiment.
They
adhere
instead
to
cultural
relativism,
which
114
obliges
them
to
argue
folk
psychologies
as
equally
valid
explanations
for
human
practices
as
those
found
in
contemporary
science
(E.O.
Wilson
1998a:186-204).
Further,
Wilson
argues,
relativism
in
the
Social
Sciences
is
politically
nave,
citing
the
concern
of
many
social
scientists
to
accord
all
cultures,
and
the
people
who
inhabit
them,
equality
of
respect
[]
which
then,
however,
makes
it
completely
obscure
why
certain
cultural
practices
should
be
looked
at
askance
colonialism,
child
labour,
judicial
torture,
and
so
on
(E.O.
Wilson
1998a:203-204).
The
Humanities,
he
argues,
are
in
an
equal
state
of
chaos.
Its
professors
and
students
have
embraced
deconstructionist
philosophies
at
the
expense
of
producing
usable
information
that
is
understandable
outside
their
disciplines.
Under
this
influence,
Wilson
worries,
the
Humanities
similarly
drifted
toward
anti-reason
and
anti-
reality:
In
this
view,
truth
is
relative
and
personal.
Each
person
creates
his
own
inner
world
by
acceptance
or
rejection
of
endlessly
shifting
linguistic
signs.
There
is
no
privileged
point,
no
lodestar,
to
guide
literary
intelligence.
And
given
that
science
is
just
another
way
of
looking
at
the
world,
there
is
no
scientifically
constructible
map
of
human
nature
from
which
the
deep
meaning
of
texts
can
be
drawn.
[E.O.
Wilson
1998a:214]
In
Consilience
and
later
publications,
Wilsons
argument
against
postmodernist
academics
centered
not
just
on
their
rejection
of
science,
but
evolutionary
science
in
particular.
For
example,
Wilson
argues
that
Homo
sapiens
sensory
organs
limit
the
ways
the
species
can
investigate
mind-independent
reality,
but
that
humans
are
also
adapted
to
grasp
their
experiences
empirically.
He
writes,
[o]utside
our
heads
there
is
free-standing
reality.
Only
lunatics
and
a
sprinkling
of
constructivist
philosophers
doubt
its
existence.
Inside
our
heads
is
a
reconstruction
of
reality
based
on
sensory
115
input
and
the
self-assembly
of
symbol-based
concepts
(E.O.
Wilson
1998b:18).
Postmodernist
academics
commitment
to
constructivism
and
relativism
is
an
intellectual
liability.
As
literary
theorist
George
Levine
comments,
for
Edward
Wilson,
unless
one
believes
implicitly
that
the
world
is
(secretly)
totally
ordered,
and
commits
oneself
absolutely
to
the
pursuit
of
the
full
unification
of
knowledge
that
will
demonstrate
and
make
use
of
that
order,
one
is
merely
a
Romantic
[]
or
now
much
worse,
of
course
a
postmodernist
(2006:113-114).
In
this
way,
Edward
Wilson
drew
upon
the
earlier
polemics
of
the
Science
Wars,
placing
academic
acceptance
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
marker
of
ones
allegiance
to
the
side
of
reason
and
sanity.
Although
Edward
Wilsons
attack
on
postmodernism
at
the
HBES
conference
took
his
audience
by
surprise,
other
evolutionary
scientists
in
the
1990s
were
challenging
relativism
and
skepticism
of
scientific
objectivity.
For
example,
in
one
infamous
passage,
Richard
Dawkins
challenges
academics
that
debate
the
supremacy
of
Western
science
and
technology:
Show
me
a
cultural
relativist
at
30,000
feet
and
I'll
show
you
a
hypocrite.
Airplanes
built
according
to
scientific
principles
work.
They
stay
aloft,
and
they
get
you
to
a
chosen
destination.
Airplanes
built
to
tribal
or
mythological
specifications,
such
as
the
dummy
planes
of
the
cargo
cults
in
jungle
clearings
or
the
beeswaxed
wings
of
Icarus,
don't.
If
you
are
flying
to
an
international
congress
of
anthropologists
or
literary
critics,
the
reason
you
will
probably
get
there
the
reason
you
don't
plummet
into
a
ploughed
field
is
that
a
lot
of
Western
scientifically
trained
engineers
have
got
their
sums
right.
[1995:31-
32]
Elsewhere,
in
what
remains
the
seminal
text
for
evolutionary
psychology,
John
Tooby
and
Leda
Cosmides
took
lengthy
exception
to
(what
they
name)
the
116
Standard
Social
Scientific
Model
(SSSM),
and
particularly
the
position
in
such
disciplines
that
what
complexly
organizes
and
richly
shapes
the
substance
of
human
life
what
is
interesting
and
distinctive
and,
therefore,
worth
studying
is
the
variable
pool
of
stuff
that
is
usually
referred
to
as
culture.
Sometimes
called
extrasomatic
or
extragenetic
[]
to
emphasize
its
nonbiological
origins
and
nature,
this
stuff
is
variously
described
as
behavior,
traditions,
knowledge,
significant
symbols,
social
facts,
control
programs,
semiotic
systems,
information,
social
organization,
social
relations,
economic
relations,
intentional
worlds,
or
socially
constructed
realities.
[1992:27]
In
The
Language
Instinct
(1994),
Steven
Pinker
drew
on
Tooby
and
Cosmides
to
pose
a
similarly
cutting
criticism
to
anthropology
and
sociolinguistics,
challenging
the
groundings
of
these
disciplines
in
the
linguistic
relativism
of
Edward
Sapir
and
Benjamin
Whorf.
He
would
later
extend
this
argument
to
the
entirety
of
contemporary
Social
Science
in
his
widely
popular
book,
The
Blank
Slate:
The
Modern
Denial
of
Human
Nature
(2002).
For
EvoS
participants,
academic
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
(in
part)
due
to
investment
in
postmodernism
(that
is
assumed
of
evolutions
critics).
One
of
the
most
vehement
arguments
of
this
sort
appears
in
Ehrenreich
and
McIntoshs
The
New
Creationism:
Biology
Under
Attack,
positing
that
academic
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
have
adopted
an
outlook
eerily
similar
to
that
of
religious
creationism
(1997:12).
The
authors
explain:
Like
their
fundamentalist
Christian
counterparts,
the
most
extreme
antibiologists
suggest
that
humans
occupy
a
status
utterly
different
from
and
clearly
"above"
that
of
all
other
living
beings
[]
It
was
only
with
the
arrival
of
the
intellectual
movements
lumped
under
the
term
"postmodernism"
that
academic
antibiologism
began
to
sound
perilously
like
religious
creationism.
Postmodernist
perspectives
go
beyond
a
critique
of
the
misuses
of
biology
to
offer
a
critique
of
117
biology
itself,
extending
to
all
of
science
and
often
to
the
very
notion
of
rational
thought.
[1997:13]
More
recently,
Jonathan
Gottschall
(a
Binghamton
University
alum
and
frequent
collaborator
with
EvoS)
writes
that
he
finds
his
own
evolutionary
literary
theories
regularly
resisted
by
his
colleagues.
The
Humanities,
he
writes,
are
rather
committed
to
endlessly
asking
questions
while
despairing
of
more
valid
answers;
to
deconstruction
without
a
clear
sense
of
how
to
reconstruct
once
things
are
made
to
fall
apart;
to
smothering
the
flame
of
Enlightenment
without
a
clear
vision
of
how
to
light
a
world
that
deprived
of
reason
is
demon
haunted
[].
The
quintessence
of
the
dominant
paradigm
is,
then,
constitutional
and
reflexive
pessimism
about
the
ability
of
humans
to
really
know
anything.
[Gottschall
2008:11]
The
EvoS
Programs
own
leader
more
explicitly
argues
the
intellectual
positions
most
fiercely
opposed
to
sociobiology
and
evolutionary
psychology
include
social
constructivism,
postmodernism,
and
deconstructionism
[].
These
debates
usually
become
so
polarized
that
they
reveal
the
worst
aspects
of
tribalism
in
our
species
(D.S.
Wilson
2005b:20).
Echoing
Ehrenreich
and
McIntoshs
proposal
that
postmodernism
is
a
new
creationism,
David
Sloan
Wilson
further
argues
that
cultural
relativism
is
a
central
reason
for
the
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities:
Secular
creationists
insist
upon
an
anything-goes
conception
of
human
nature
because
they
think
it
is
required
to
establish
their
vision
of
the
good
life.
Ironically,
their
own
vision
is
better
achieved
by
adopting
a
conception
of
human
nature
that
fights
tenaciously
to
survive
and
reproduce.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:99]
For
EvoS
participants,
their
in-house
ideology
offers
a
relatively
uncomplicated
representation
of
the
EvoS
Programs
goal
of
integrating
the
academic
disciplines,
and
the
irrationality
of
its
critics.
Further,
epithets
like
secular
creationism
suggest
118
that
this
ideology
also
capitalizes
on
popular
knowledge
of
ongoing
debates
between
science
educators
and
religious
fundamentalists
in
the
United
States.
This
conflict
is
characterized
by
the
rationalization
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
argued
by
its
proponents
as
a
unified
(or
unifying)
science,
relative
to
the
fragmented
knowledge
production
of
the
postmodernist
academy.
To
this
point,
I
have
suggested
that
participants
in
the
EvoS
Program
understand
the
anti-evolutionism
of
U.S.
higher
education
in
two
ways:
On
one
hand,
critics
fear
the
moral
and
political
consequences
of
embracing
evolutionary
explanations
for
social
life.
On
the
other,
they
dismiss
evolutionary
reasoning
due
to
their
commitment
to
postmodernist
trends
in
their
own
disciplines.
For
EvoS
Program
participants,
these
in-house
ideologies
represent
a
landscape
of
academic
antagonism
in
which
more-or-less
unified,
homogenous
sides
are
placed
into
dynamic
opposition
to
one
another.
Attending
to
the
intellectual
and
political
tensions
in
U.S.
universities
during
the
20th
century,
the
programs
ideologies
can
be
seen
as
rooted
in
earlier
disputes
over
evolutionary
science
(such
as
the
Science
Wars
and
sociobiology
debates),
and
broader
episodes
in
which
the
structure
and
functions
of
higher
education
where
challenged
(such
as
campus
peace
movements
during
the
Vietnam
War
and
the
rising
influence
of
feminism
in
academic
settings
during
the
1970s
and
1980s).
These
broader
events
in
the
last
half-century
of
higher
education
reinforced
representations
of
antagonistic,
typically
two-sided
controversies
over
evolutionary
reasoning.
Such
dichotomizations
take
shape
in
the
immediate
historical
contexts
of
the
Sociobiology
Debates
and
Science
Wars,
as
well
as
the
contemporary
activities
of
the
EvoS
Program.
119
Rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
due
to
critics
perception
of
it
as
politically
incorrect.
The
third
in-house
ideology
I
wish
to
discuss
arises
from
recent
disputes
in
US
colleges
and
universities
over
political
correctness
in
publications,
administrative
policies,
student
conduct,
and
numerous
other
arenas.
Participants
in
the
EvoS
Program
understand
scholars
in
the
Humanities
and
Social
Sciences
as
rejecting
evolutionary
reasoning
as
politically
incorrect.
That
is,
critics
of
EvoS
are
offended
by
the
subject
matters
of
human
evolutionary
research
gender
violence,
warfare,
racism,
rape,
infanticide,
among
others
as
well
as
the
unapologetic
frankness
with
which
evolutionary
scientists
discuss
them.
The
PC
reaction
of
these
critics
thus
leads
them
to
dismiss
the
application
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
human
behaviors,
typically
without
considering
its
scientific
legitimacy.
As
I
have
underscored
with
other
EvoS
ideologies,
the
shape
of
political
correctness
(or
incorrectness)
in
this
program
is
primarily
influenced
by
the
role
of
evolutionary
scientists
in
this
complex
set
of
historical
debates
in
higher
education.
first
in
higher
education,
then
in
popular
media,
and
was
for
many
associated
with
the
strengthening
of
feminist
and
post-colonial
concerns
in
research,
curricula,
administration,
and
(more
broadly)
the
growing
number
of
influential
women
and
ethnic
minorities
in
media,
business,
and
government
(Hughes
2010;
Lauter
1995)
Yet,
there
seems
to
no
clear
definition
for
the
term
itself,
and
no
movement
promoting
it
with
a
unified
voice,
although
critics
of
political
correctness
argued
to
120
the
contrary
(Cameron
1995:116-165).
Generally,
concerns
over
political
correctness
aimed
to
decrease
the
alienation
of
these
people,
advocating
more
inclusive
and
accurate
language
use
and
policies,
as
well
as
greater
sensitivity
to
the
ways
that
assumptions
about
race,
ethnicity,
gender,
sexuality,
class,
and
disability
lead
to
the
privileges
of
some
and
the
disenfranchisement
of
others
(Andrews
1996).
It
was
the
emphasis
upon
sensitivity
that
angered
many
critics,
who
charged
that
Leftist
activism
feminists,
in
particular
had
begun
finding
injustice
in
trivial
places,
and
sought
to
police
and
sanitize
peoples
language
and
thoughts.
In
this
sense,
political
correctness
became
a
pejorative
descriptor,
associated
by
many
with
a
highly
vocal
and
reactionary
brand
of
feminism,
whether
or
not
this
association
was
in
any
way
accurate.
Further,
during
the
mid-1990s,
proponents
of
(often
explicitly
labeled)
political
incorrectness
gained
popularity
in
popular
media,
politics,
and
academia.
Within
this
trend,
speakers
and
writers
offered
a
marked
irreverence
toward
issues
of
(among
others)
gender
or
race,
similarly
conspicuous
intention
to
offend
those
who
are
overly-sensitive
to
such
issues,
and
often
a
fair
amount
of
parodying
and
contempt
for
PC
concerns
(for
example,
Garner
1994).
Further,
overlapping
with
academic
and
popular
criticisms
of
postmodernists,
the
politically
incorrect
subversion
of
these
sensitivities
is
typically
accompanied
with
much
lip
service
paid
to
unfettered,
scientific
facts.
During
the
1980s,
1990s
and
2000s,
evolutionary
science
particularly
Evolutionary
Psychology
has
been
squarely
targeted
by
feminist
critics.
In
these
criticisms,
feminist
scholars
charge
that
Evolutionary
Psychology
tends
to
frame
women
as
reproductive
commodities,
uncritically
assume
Western
kinship
systems
121
to
be
an
universal
social
organization,
naturalize
monogamy
and
heterosexuality
as
human
and
non-human
norms,
and
conceptualize
gender
hierarchies
and
violence
as
inherent
elements
in
both
human
and
non-human
existence
(see
Blackman
1985;
Harding
1985;
Helmreich
and
Paxson
2005;
Lloyd
2005;
McCaughey
2008;
McKinnon
2005a;
2005b;
Travis
2003).
Critics
were
especially
catalyzed
by
publications
and
lectures
by
Randy
Thornhill
and
his
colleagues,
who
propose
that
rape
is
a
behavioral
adaptation
in
both
Homo
sapiens
and
non-human
species,
through
which
males
ensure
reproduction
by
physically
assaulting
and
socially
controlling
females
(Gangestad
1993;
Palmer
1988,
1989,
1991;
Thornhill
1980;
Thornhill
and
Palmer
2000;
Thornhill
and
Thornhill
1990a,
1990b,
1990c,
1991;
Thornhill
and
Thornhill
1983;
Thornhill
et
al.
1986).
These
feminist
interrogations
of
the
last
two
decades
are
likely
the
most
sweeping
set
of
academic
criticisms
ever
made
of
evolutionary
science.
Given
the
subject
matter
that
these
critics
address,
some
were
expressed
with
notable
vehemence.
Some
responses
from
evolutionary
science
tended
to
understand
these
criticisms
as
reactionary
feminism
a
PC
reaction
against
evolutionary
science.
Addressing
this
explicitly
in
his
New
Republic
essay
(Feminists,
Meet
Mr.
Darwin),
science
journalist
Robert
Wright
explains
It
would
be
misleading
to
say
that
feminists
casually
disregard
Darwinism.
A
fair
amount
of
effort
goes
into
the
disregard.
A
few
feminists
have
actually
studied
and
then
dismissed
the
Darwinian
view
of
human
nature.
Unfortunately,
they
seem
to
have
expended
more
energy
on
the
dismissal
than
on
the
study.
[1994b:34]
Elsewhere,
discussing
the
severe
attention
paid
to
their
evolutionary
explanations
for
rape
and
sexual
coercion,
Randy
Thornhill
and
Craig
Palmer
write,
122
the
biophobia
that
has
led
to
the
rejection
of
Darwinian
analyses
of
human
behavior
is
an
intellectual
disaster
[].
Most
of
what
is
scientifically
inaccurate
and
counter
productive
about
how
the
social
sciences
and
academic
feminism
approach
the
study
of
rape
stems
directly
from
the
aversion
to
modern
theoretical
biology
in
those
fields.
[Thornhill
and
Palmer
2000:122]
Understanding
criticism
as
part
of
an
aversion
or
dismissal,
proponents
of
evolutionary
science
positioned
themselves
(some
more
willingly
than
others)
as
part
of
the
backlash
against
academic
feminism
in
the
late
1990s.
One
of
the
more
purposeful
voices
in
this
counter-criticism
remains
sociobiologist
Lionel
Tiger,
who
has
extended
his
challenges
to
feminism
and
affirmative
action
into
proposals
for
Male
Studies
programs
in
higher
education.
Arguing
that
men
are
evolutionarily
predisposed
toward
maximizing
their
number
of
offspring
by
controlling
womens
sexual
behaviors,
Tiger
proposes
that
womens
widespread
access
to
birth
control
since
the
mid-20th
century
creates
conflicts
with
mens
evolved
predispositions,
and
thus
produces
among
men
a
continual
sense
of
paternity
uncertainty
(1999:45-
58).
Such
uncertainties
result
in
a
plethora
of
anti-male
policies
in
U.S.
education
and
government,
as
well
as
the
self-righteous
and
automatic
public
support
for
womens
interests
and
issues
(Tiger
2005).
It
should
be
noted
that
evolutionary
scientists
courted
such
controversy
decades
before
political
correctness
was
a
widely
used
moniker,
and
they
have
been
targets
of
academic
criticism
precisely
because
they
so
frequently
(sometimes
cavalierly)
engage
politically
sensitive
issues.
In
the
earliest
developments
of
Sociobiology,
evolutionary
explanations
for
human
behaviors
were
being
presented
as
subversive
material
to
academic
audiences.
For
example,
in
1971,
Harvard
professors
Robert
Trivers
and
Irven
DeVore
introduced
a
co-taught,
undergraduate
123
course:
The
Biological
Basis
of
Sex
Differences.
Their
approach
to
the
class
was
apparent
on
the
first
day:
Standing
before
the
class,
DeVore
boasted
that
he
and
Trivers
would
systematically
explain
why
men
and
women
differ
in
everything
from
physical
stature
to
dating
habits.
Trivers
went
further:
This
semester,
he
said,
we
will
do
no
less
than
reveal
the
previously
unknown
biological
purpose
of
the
clitoris
[].
Some
students
gasped;
others
laughed.
Outside
the
classroom,
a
group
of
female
students
chanted
in
protest
at
the
very
idea
of
a
biological
basis
to
human
behavior.
[Kirby
2005:80]
As
the
course
progressed,
Professors
Trivers
and
DeVore
openly
opposed
their
scientific
perspectives
to
the
political
sensitivities
of
the
early-1970s
university.
As
Kirby
describes,
Irven
DeVore
opened
each
semester
by
announcing
that,
during
the
semester,
he
would
offend
every
race,
sex,
philosophy,
and
creed
imaginable.
He
usually
did
(2005:83).
Like
their
predecessors
in
sociobiology,
many
contemporary
evolutionary
scientists
recognized
their
arguments
as
controversial
themes
in
higher
education,
and
often
flaunted
this
irreverence.
For
instance,
Martha
McCaughey
discusses
her
participation
in
a
1989
HBES
conference,
where
a
male
participant
in
a
panel
on
morality
and
evolution
asked
the
participants
If
you
were
stranded
on
a
deserted
island
with
a
woman,
would
you
rape
her?
(2008:1).
Elsewhere,
biologist
John
Alcock
relates
an
anecdote
about
sexual
harassment
of
female
employees
in
a
supermarket,
proposing
that
the
example
tells
you
something
about
men,
namely,
that
they
almost
always
view
women
of
reproductive
age
as
potential
sex
objects
(no
matter
what
they
say
in
the
interest
of
political
correctness
or
a
desire
to
deceive
women
or
to
ingratiate
themselves
with
possible
sexual
partners).
It
cannot
hurt
to
know
this
fact
of
life,
and
a
few
others,
such
as
the
willingness
of
even
nice
guys
to
resort
to
coercive
tactics
to
secure
sex.
[2001:215]
124
Authors
such
as
Alcock
are
conscious
of
the
broadly
controversial
nature
of
their
explanations,
and
some
(like
Devore
and
Trivers)
go
so
far
as
to
exploit
its
potential
to
shock,
offend,
and
amuse.
As
evolutionary
psychologist
Edward
Hagen
writes:
Slavish
support
for
reigning
political
and
moral
attitudes
is
a
sure
sign
of
scientific
bankruptcy.
It
is
reassuring,
then,
that
[Evolutionary
Psychology]
has
something
to
offend
just
about
everyone.
Surely
you
[],
if
you
are
not
already
a
jaded
evolutionary
psychologist,
are
offended
by
at
least
one
of
EPs
speculations
that
there
might
be
innate,
genetically
based
adaptations
hardwired
into
our
brains
for
rape,
homicide,
infanticide,
war,
aggression,
exploitation,
infidelity,
and
deception.
I
know
I
was.
[2005:
169-170]
Whether
or
not
they
are
appalled
by
their
own
topics
and
findings,
many
evolutionary
scientists
during
the
late
20th
century
made
use
of
the
fact
that
the
behaviors
they
researched
were
like
those
Hagen
describes
problematic
and
controversial,
both
inside
and
outside
of
higher
education.
Given
this
history
of
controversy,
it
is
unsurprising
that
evolutionary
scientists
attracted
(sometimes
fierce)
criticism
from
feminists
during
this
same
period.
As
I
explain
above,
the
backfire
against
feminism
became
a
broader,
popular
reaction
to
political
correctness,
as
did
the
arguments
of
many
evolutionary
scientists
most
notably
Lionel
Tiger
and
Randy
Thornhill,
but
also
more
widely-
read
authors
such
as
Steven
Pinker
(2002).
The
resulting
ideology
resonates
through
much
of
the
U.S.
and
European
evolutionary
community:
Evolutionary
reasoning
is
rejected
by
reactionary
(predominantly
feminist)
critics,
who
are
offended
by
its
politically
incorrect
topics
and
presentations.
Conversely,
this
same
ideology
represents
proponents
of
evolutionary
science
and
evolutionary
reasoning,
itself
as
a
subversive,
often
irreverent
alternative
to
the
political
hyper-
125
sensitivities
of
its
critics.
The research projects of some EvoS participants have drawn criticism from
feminist
scholars
and
others,
most
notably
Gordon
Gallups
inquiries
into
the
possible
anti-depressant
effects
of
semen
for
women
(Gallup
et
al.
2002)
and
correlations
between
a
Dopamine
receptor
gene
and
test
subjects
tendencies
toward
relationship
infidelity
and
sexual
promiscuity
(Garcia
et
al.
2010).
Like
the
individuals
I
quote
above,
participants
in
EvoS
tend
to
see
such
criticisms
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
(in
part)
explainable
as
PC
reactions
to
the
subject
matter
of
their
research.
For
example,
Glenn
Geher
returns
to
the
juxtaposition
between
Evolutionary
Psychology
(EP)
and
the
Standard
Social
Science
Model
(SSSM),
arguing:
Adherents
of
the
SSSM
perspective
argue
that
appealing
to
evolutionarily
shaped
differences
between
the
psychologies
of
men
and
women
to
explain
something
such
as
universal
sex
differences
in
desire
for
multiple
sex
partners
is
an
inherently
sexist
approach.
In
short,
these
new
creationists
believe
that
any
appeals
to
an
evolutionarily
shaped
human
nature
to
explain
psychological
phenomena
(regardless
of
how
well
the
said
phenomena
are
documented)
imply
that
human
behavior
is
highly
constrained
by
our
nature,
is
genetically
determined,
and
is,
in
effect,
immutable.
As
such,
adherents
of
the
SSSM
feel
something
of
an
obligation
to
fight
EP,
as
they
believe
they
are
fighting
an
intellectual
doctrine
which
sees
human
behavior
as
largely
immutable
and
which
ultimately
provides
a
scholarly
rationale
for
the
status
quo.
[Geher
2006:183]
Participants
in
EvoS
(such
as
this
author)
understand
their
critics
as
rejecting
evolutionary
reasoning
due
to
a
commitment
to
Leftist
political
obligations.
As
other
participants
elaborate,
universities
are
strongholds
of
the
ideological
Left
and
resistance
from
the
Left
has
been
a
major
hurdle
for
EP
since
its
inception
[even
though]
EP
is
no
more
politically
conservative
than
other
academic
areas
(Garcia
et
126
al.
2011:757).
The
authors
go
on
to
worry
that
the
strained
relationship
between
feminism
and
evolutionary
theory
might
result
in
the
renewal
of
the
sociobiology
debates,
and
that
Evolutionary
Psychology
might
become
a
similarly
taboo
area
of
inquiry
unfairly
framed
as
sexist,
racist,
and
politically
conservative
(Garcia
et
al.
2011:757-758).
Other
EvoS
participants
argue
that
the
(perceived)
political
incorrectness
of
their
topics
has
already
established
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
subversive
or
irreverent
movement
in
higher
education.
For
example,
when
discussing
how
evolution
is
shunned
outside
of
these
portions
of
the
university,
David
Sloan
Wilson
often
refers
to
evolution
as
the
E-Word
(D.S.
Wilson
2007a,
2008b,
2010,
2011b)
as
if
the
very
term
cannot
be
uttered
in
certain
spaces.
While this in-house ideology is admittedly quite complex, its relevance in the
EvoS
Program
is
difficult
to
overstate.
Participants
are
often
highly
aware
of
the
controversies
surrounding
Evolutionary
Psychology,
and
many
of
them
consider
themselves
to
be
quite
politically
progressive,
if
not
explicitly
identifying
as
feminists.
As
I
stress
throughout
this
discussion,
these
ideologies
are
quite
functional
and
pragmatic,
working
to
orient
EvoS
participants
within
a
representation
of
the
academic
landscape
that
seems
fraught
with
resistance
to
evolutionary
reasoning
and
the
movements
first
principle.
Rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
due
to
Ivory
Tower
elitism
and
specialization.
As
is
likely
apparent,
the
outsider
status
of
EvoS
in
higher
education
is
a
characteristic
that
its
participants
simultaneously
resent
and
foster.
The
forth
and
final
in-house
ideology
of
the
EvoS
Program
127
underscores
this
matter,
explaining
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
due
to
its
critics
Ivory
Tower
elitism.
While
EvoS
participants
are
distressed
by
what
they
perceive
as
dismissals
of
evolutionary
reasoning
by
professional
academics,
there
is
(I
have
observed)
a
certain
nonconformist
pride
derived
from
this
as
well.
This
ideology
functions
to
juxtapose
the
academic
institution
(as
intellectually
conservative
and
elitist)
to
the
movement
(understood
as
intellectually
progressive
and
of
the
people).
As
I
examine
below,
this
ideology
has
its
historical
roots
in
the
rise
of
science
writing
for
general
audiences
popular
science
over
the
last
four
decades.
From
the
mid-20th
century
to
the
present,
general-audience
science
writing
became
a
lucrative
genre
in
the
book
publishing
industry
(and
more
recently
in
online
publishing).
The
influence
of
popular
science
upon
academic
practice
should
not
be
underestimated,
as
it
gradually
but
profoundly
reshaped
the
public
personae
of
individual
scientists
from
stuffy
professionals
to
intrepid,
opinionated
truth
seekers.
Similarly,
popular
science
forced
a
transformation
in
academic
representations
of
scientific
practice.
Doing
science
no
longer
conjured
up
only
images
of
intense
laboratory
work,
but
dramatic
narratives
full
of
adventure,
danger,
and
self-discovery.
Few
areas
of
popular
science
writing
delivered
up
this
kind
of
drama
as
thoroughly
as
evolutionary
science.
Moreover,
some
evolutionary
science
writers
have
become
public
celebrities
of
a
sort
quite
rare
for
academic
professionals
(see
Broks
2006;
McCaughey
2008).
128
contemporary
social
dilemmas.
Some
of
these
writers
were
some
practicing
researchers
and
professors
(such
as
Konrad
Lorenz
and
Desmond
Morris)
while
others
were
outsiders.
A
dramatist
by
training,
Robert
Ardrey
was
particularly
well
known,
not
only
for
his
sometimes
gruesome
descriptions
of
innate
human
aggression,
but
equally
for
his
polemical
arguments
about
the
academic
elitism
that
(he
argued)
alienated
the
public
from
scientific
knowledge
about
human
nature.
These
unflattering
depictions
were
central
to
the
anti-academic
flare
of
his
works,
and
many
professional
academics
objected
to
these
representations
of
academic
elitism
as
much
as
the
questionable
veracity
of
his
science
all
of
which,
of
course,
further
legitimated
the
revolutionary
spirit
of
Ardreys
endeavor
(Weidman
2011).
His
critics
were
loath
to
call
his
work
into
question,
realizing
that
their
objections
would
only
lend
credence
to
his
stereotypes.
Pointing
out
this
ironic
turn
of
events,
anthropologist
Marshall
Sahlins
comments
that
Ardreys
work
falls
into
the
Kon
Tiki
genre.
He
explains:
It
portrays
a
theory
that
sounds
sensible,
but
which,
for
fuddy-duddy
reasons,
the
professors-that-be
generally
ignore.
Right
away,
Ardrey
is
an
underdog.
And
to
add
to
the
appeal:
simply
by
reading
the
book
approvingly,
anyone
can
prove
that
he
is
the
intellectual
equal
indeed,
the
superior
of
the
so-called
scholars
[].
Obviously,
it
becomes
difficult
to
enter
the
lists
against
Ardrey.
Who
wants
to
be
accused
of
being
a
counter-revolutionary?
What
an
improbable
position
for
an
anthropological
critic.
To
admit
to
intellectual
conservatism
is
contrary
to
the
spirit
of
any
science,
and
not
the
least
so
to
anthropology.
In
this
context
of
conspiratorial
allegation,
how
can
an
anthropologist
convey
the
impression
that
the
theory
seems
to
him
unsound?
[Sahlins
1968:117]
Sahlins
here
suggests
something
more
general
about
popular
science:
its
assumed
status
as
an
external
critique
of
institutional
academics.
Such
criticisms
were
delivered
by
both
non-professionals
(like
Ardrey)
or
practicing
scientists,
who
129
claimed
to
be
exasperated
with
the
conservatism
of
their
colleagues
and
faced
with
no
other
options
than
to
go
public
with
their
knowledge.
Examples
of
such
criticisms
appear
in
the
works
of
Robert
Ardrey,
Konrad
Lorenz,
and
Desmond
Morris,
as
well
as
other
mid-20th
century
popular
science
publications
like
Rachel
Carsons
Silent
Spring
(1962)
and
James
Watsons
The
Double
Helix:
A
Personal
Account
of
the
Discovery
of
the
Structure
of
DNA
(1968).
These
authors
chide
university
professors
as
stuffy,
impersonal,
and
conservative
more
intent
on
defending
their
careers
and
reputations
than
informing
the
public
or
putting
their
knowledge
to
practical
use.
Popular
scientists,
conversely,
are
independent
from
academic
infighting
and
bureaucracies,
and
(more
importantly)
intent
on
showing
science
to
be
a
means
of
personal
transformation
and
solving
enduring
socio-
political
problems.
While popular science writers like Ardrey and Morris made science exciting
or
subversive
for
general
audiences,
it
was
Stephen
Jay
Gould
who
most
consistently
represented
scientific
practice
as
a
personal
journey.
In
his
books
and
monthly
essays
for
Natural
History,
Gould
readily
mixed
scientific
theories
with
memories
of
childhood,
interpretations
of
popular
culture,
even
his
love
of
baseball.
As
Prindle
notes,
Gould
likes
to
bring
the
reader
along
on
a
voyage
of
discovery.
He
does
not
so
much
present
us
with
a
conclusion
we
are
to
accept,
as
admit
us
to
his
own
experience
and
permit
us
to
participate
vicariously
in
the
process
of
realization
[].
By
letting
the
reader
in
on
the
hunt
for
knowledge,
Gould
creates
what
rhetorical
scholars
call
identification
between
himself
and
his
readers.
The
members
of
the
audience
join
emotionally
with
the
author
and
exult
in
his
conquest
of
truth.
[Prindle
2009:28-29]
130
The
popularization
of
science
was,
in
this
sense,
simultaneously
about
the
personalization
of
scientific
endeavors.
For
Gould,
learning
scientific
facts
was
tied
to
making
sense
of
ones
own
life.
Further,
while
Gould
was
critical
of
many
of
his
contemporaries
(including
Robert
Ardrey),
he
similarly
pursued
scientific
explanation
through
personal
essays,
attempting
to
make
evolutionary
theories
interesting
and
exciting
to
a
non-scientific
audience.
The only other evolutionary theorist who has achieved Goulds level of
131
Like
Gould,
the
approach
that
Dawkins
took
in
publicizing
his
ideas
was
widely
enjoyed
by
non-scientists,
to
whom
he
delivered
both
scientific
facts
and
a
revolutionary
new
philosophy.
He
strove
to
make
them
feel
privy
to
a
process
of
scientific
discovery,
while
simultaneously
attempting
to
transform
their
perspectives
about
themselves
as
organic
beings,
and
thus
turn
their
whole
world
upside
down.
As
Ridley
suggests,
this
was
not
just
a
clever
way
to
attract
readers
and
sell
books.
Figures
like
Gould
and
Dawkins
took
evolutionary
reasoning
to
the
people,
presenting
it
as
a
broadly
applicable,
life-changing,
and
personally
transformative
first
principle.
To
do
so,
like
Ardrey
and
Morris
before
them,
these
authors
stripped
evolution
of
the
elitism
of
professional
academics,
and
(as
Sahlins
comments)
their
fuddy-duddy
criticisms.
One
result
of
this
popularization
was
a
breakdown
in
the
distinction
between
professional
and
general
audience
publications
as
primary
sources,
which
Gould
makes
explicit
in
his
final
collection
of
essays,
I
Have
Landed:
I
refuse
to
treat
these
essays
as
lesser,
derivative,
or
dumbed-down
versions
of
technical
or
scholarly
writing
for
professional
audiences,
but
insist
upon
viewing
them
as
no
different
in
conceptual
depth
(however
distinct
in
language)
from
other
genres
of
original
research
[].
In
scholars'
jargon,
I
hope
and
trust
that
my
colleagues
will
regard
these
essays
as
primary
rather
than
secondary
sources.
[2002:6-7,
original
emphasis]
Even
more
than
Gould,
Richard
Dawkins
works
are
among
the
most
widely
referenced
popular
texts
in
evolutionary
science.
Further,
as
I
comment
previously,
The
Selfish
Gene
and
Dawkins
subsequent
writings
helped
to
spearhead
memetics,
which
examines
the
endurance
and
spread
of
socio-cultural
phenomena
as
analogous
to
biological
(typically
genetic)
survival
and
reproduction.
Subsequently,
132
the
term
meme
entered
common
vernacular
use,
describing
influential
or
infectious
ideas
(see
Sterelny
2001).
In
all,
the
late-20th
century
popularization
of
science
marks
a
breakdown
of
distinctions
between
academic
and
general
audiences.
Professional
scientists
encountered
more
numerous
and
diverse
publishing
opportunities.
At
the
same
time,
university
presses
begin
publishing
a
broader
range
of
authors,
including
non-
professionals,
and
professional
academics
began
to
publish
for
general
audiences
earlier
in
their
careers.
As
I
suggest
above,
the
authors
of
popular
science
are
often
notable
for
their
critical
representations
of
academic
professions
and
research
as
elitist
conservative,
mired
in
their
careers
and
reputations,
and
detached
from
the
personally
or
socially
transformative
potential
of
science.
Conversely,
popular
scientists
represent
themselves
(and
one
another)
as
progressive
revolutionaries
who
have
been
personally
transformed
by
science,
and
thus
challenge
professional
dogma
by
going
public
with
their
conclusions.
The
EvoS
Program
has
been
shaped
by
this
recent
history
popular
science,
appearing
primarily
as
an
in-house
ideology,
representing
evolutionary
reasoning
as
broadly
accessible
and
personally
transformative.
Generally,
science
is
presented
as
a
blue
collar
activity,
which
can
be
pursued
by
anyone,
regardless
of
his
or
her
educational
credentials
or
socio-economic
situation.
For
example,
midway
through
Evolution
for
Everyone
(2007a),
David
Sloan
Wilson
explains
to
his
readers:
Science
is
often
portrayed
as
an
exalted
and
difficult
activity
accessible
only
to
an
elite
caste
of
intelligent
and
highly
trained
individuals.
I
have
made
every
effort
to
portray
it
as
a
down-to-earth
activity,
like
farming,
brick
making,
and
house
building
[].
If
you
have
accompanied
me
this
far
[in
the
book],
then
you
have
the
makings
of
a
scientist,
who
with
a
little
clear
thinking
and
a
lot
of
hard
work
can
133
help
to
create
something
both
personally
gratifying
and
larger
and
more
durable
than
yourself.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:65-66]
Leaving
aside
the
fact
that
the
down
to
earth
professions
that
Wilson
mentions
also
require
significant
training,
this
passage
expresses
the
authors
everyman
approach
to
science.
Similarly,
Wilson
argues
that
evolutionary
reasoning
can
be
personally
transformative
a
position
which
pervades
his
book.
Opening
his
tenth
chapter
(Your
Apprentice
License),
Wilson
addresses
his
readers,
cheering,
Congratulations!
I
have
finished
conveying
the
barest
essentials
of
evolutionary
theory,
as
I
said
I
would
do
in
Chapter
1.
If
you
have
accompanied
me
this
far,
you
can
regard
yourself
as
an
apprentice
evolutionist.
[2007a:63]
The
author
here
attempts
to
make
science
into
a
journey
that
he
shares
with
his
readers,
in
the
tradition
of
Stephen
Jay
Gould.
Fascinatingly,
as
Marshall
Sahlins
comments
about
Robert
Ardreys
writing,
David
Sloan
Wilson
here
posits
that
the
very
act
of
reading
his
book
partially
accredits
them
as
evolutionary
thinkers.
Like
the
popular
science
writers
I
discuss
above,
EvoS
participants
are
also
dissatisfied
with
the
elitism
they
perceive
among
academic
professionals
and
disciplines.
David
Sloan
Wilson
recalls
that
early
receptions
to
his
EvoS
Program
were
mixed
in
Binghamton
Universitys
Anthropology
Department,
where
some
of
his
colleagues
were
aghast
at
the
idea
they
didn't
want
the
apartheid
to
end.
(2011b:17).
This
apartheid
metaphor
appears
in
Wilsons
publications
and
those
of
other
EvoS
participants
(Tiger
1996:17;
D.S.
Wilson
2008a,
2008b:17;
D.S
Wilson
et
al.
2013:4;),
and
also
grant
applications
by
program
organizers,
who
posit
that
they
and
their
colleagues
worry
about
an
apartheid
between
evolutionary
theory
and
most
human-related
subjects
and
hope
that
breaking
down
the
apartheid
will
134
automatically
result
in
the
integration
of
the
humanities,
human-related
sciences,
and
biological
sciences
(D.S.
Wilson
and
Heywood
2008:16).32
Similar
dissatisfaction
is
present
in
other
metaphors
used
by
EvoS
participants
to
describe
academic
conservatism.
One
especially
common
example
of
this
is
David
Sloan
Wilsons
comment
in
numerous
publications,
interviews,
and
lectures
that
that
Ivory
Tower
would
be
more
aptly
named
the
Ivory
Archipelago
in
the
past
decade,
this
observation
on
academic
over-specialization
has
nearly
become
a
mantra
for
dozens
of
other
EvoS
participants
in
their
own
blog
postings,
lectures,
and
publications
(for
example,
see
Carmen
et
al.
2013;
Garcia
et
al.
2011;
Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010;
Geher
et
al.
2011)
As
I
suggest
throughout
this
discussion
of
the
EvoS
Programs
movement
in-
house
ideologies,
the
ways
that
participants
understand
their
critics
are
rooted
in
the
history
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education.
The
academic
disputes
that
arise
over
evolutionary
explanations
for
human
behaviors
are
typically
parts
of
bigger
socio-political
disagreements
that
take
place
beyond
academic
settings
in
(among
other
realms)
popular
media.
Proponents
and
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
thus
tended
to
borrow
from
the
broader
concerns,
such
as
anti-war
movements,
challenges
to
and
defenses
of
modern
science,
and
the
growth
of
(and
response
to)
academic
feminism
in
the
late
20th
century.
These
earlier
debates
over
32
Arguably, the political incorrectness of such commentary is almost literal, but more importantly they
express a shared (if complicated) understanding of evolutionary reasoning as a subversive activity in higher
education. That is, in naming the plight of evolutionary reasoning in an apartheid in higher education,
Wilson and his fellow EvoS participants are pointing to the politically incorrect subversive-ness of their
movement, as well as recreating this incorrectness in their choice of metaphors.
135
evolutionary
reasoning
produced
ideologies
that
continue
to
be
indexed
by
EvoS
participants
in
the
present.
These
in-house
ideologies
are
useful
in
the
EvoS
movement
because
they
represent
the
often
extremely
complex
interactions
of
evolutionary
scientists
as
the
unified
concerns
of
a
movement,
which
is
at
odds
with
a
similarly
unified
set
of
academic
critics.
EvoS
represents
these
critics
as
rejecting
evolutionary
explanations
for
human
behaviors
due
to
their:
fears
about
its
moral
and
political
implications,
commitment
to
postmodernism,
reactions
to
such
explanations
political
incorrectness,
and
academic
(Ivory
Tower)
elitism.
Understanding
the
critics
motivations
in
this
way,
EvoS
participants
are
able
to
represent
the
purpose
and
struggles
of
their
own
movement
in
juxtaposition
to
their
critics:
They
are
marginalized
or
persecuted
by
those
who
fear
the
implications
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
They
are
rational
and
scientific,
relative
to
their
critics
postmodernism.
They
are
compelled
to
be
subversive
and
irreverent
by
those
critics
who
see
their
arguments
as
politically
incorrect.
Further,
seeing
themselves
and
their
critics
as
more-or-less
homogenous,
oppositional
parts
of
a
shared
social
institution
(US
higher
education),
the
EvoS
imperative
to
re-conceptualize
and
restructure
higher
education
becomes
a
coherent
and
vital
challenge,
targeting
an
institution
that
(they
argue)
has
tended
to
unfairly
favor
the
positions
of
their
critics.
There
is
obviously
significant
overlap
between
these
ideologies.
They
tend
to
merge
and
reinforce
one
another
for
EvoS
participants
such
as
Jonathan
Gottschall,
who
writes
about
his
graduate
studies
in
Binghamtons
English
Department:
[A]s
in
most
English
departments
around
the
country,
Binghamton
University's
was
tolerant
of
a
profusion
of
different
disciplinary,
136
ideological,
and
theoretical
approaches.
This
tolerance
reached
its
limits,
however,
when
it
came
to
evolutionary
theories
of
human
behavior
and
psychology,
toward
which
students
and
professors
evinced
nothing
but
skepticism,
hostility,
and,
most
of
all,
fear.
Older
professors,
like
my
epics
professor,
seemed
to
see
the
naked
ape
perspective
as
a
churl's
insult
to
humanity
and
to
great
art.
The
younger
professors,
as
well
as
my
fellow
graduate
students,
saw
it
as
something
far
worse.
I
quickly
learned
that
when
I
spoke
of
human
behavior,
psychology,
and
culture
in
evolutionary
terms,
their
minds
churned
through
an
instant
and
unconscious
process
of
translation,
and
they
heard
Hitler,
Galton,
Spencer,
IQ
differences,
holocaust,
racial
phrenology,
forced
sterilization,
genetic
determinism,
Darwinian
fundamentalism,
and
disciplinary
imperialism.
[Gottschall
2005:xx]
Further,
these
same
ideologies
tend
to
overlap
and
reinforce
one
another
in
the
arguments
by
other
champions
of
evolutionary
scientists
who
are
(it
should
be
noted)
not
EvoS
participants.
For
example,
evolutionary
psychologist
Steven
Pinker
writes
in
a
recent
New
Republic
article:
The
humanities
have
yet
to
recover
from
the
disaster
of
postmodernism,
with
its
defiant
obscurantism,
dogmatic
relativism,
and
suffocating
political
correctness.
And
they
have
failed
to
define
a
progressive
agenda.
Several
university
presidents
and
provosts
have
lamented
to
me
that
when
a
scientist
comes
into
their
office,
its
to
announce
some
exciting
new
research
opportunity
and
demand
the
resources
to
pursue
it.
When
a
humanities
scholar
drops
by,
its
to
plead
for
respect
for
the
way
things
have
always
been
done.
[Pinker
2013:32]
The
historical
precedents
of
these
ideologies
lead
to
their
appearance
in
the
arguments
of
both
EvoS
participants
(like
Gottschall)
and
non-participants
(like
Pinker).
They
evince
much
greater
scope
than
the
EvoS
Programs
own
evolutionary
reasoning.
That
is,
the
EvoS
Programs
scientific
arguments
are
less
widely
known
or
presupposed
than
its
assessments
of
the
academic
opposition
to
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
first
principle
in
U.S.
higher
education.
These
it
shares
with
a
wide
range
of
authors,
both
now
and
in
the
past.
137
Chapter
Four:
Foregrounding
and
Contextualization
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
In
Chapter
Two,
I
discussed
what
I
call
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
and
related
it
to
the
movements
first
principle
a
challenge
posed
to
U.S.
universities
and
colleges
to
radically
restructure
its
disciplines,
curricula,
and
research,
embracing
evolutionary
reasoning
as
its
foundation.
In
the
following
chapter,
I
detailed
the
programs
in-house
ideologies
four
representations
of
the
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
past
and
present
of
U.S.
higher
education.
I
suggested
these
ideologies
can
be
seen
as
answering
this
particularly
nagging
question
for
the
EvoS
Program
(and
many
others
in
contemporary
evolutionary
science).
Why
would
professional
academics
who
are
not,
typically,
creationists
find
fault
with
the
argument
that
their
disciplines
should
be
foundationally
based
on
evolutionary
reasoning?
Four
possible
responses
for
this
problematic
situation
come
from
(what
I
have
called)
the
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies:
First,
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
due
to
fears
about
its
political
and
moral
consequences.
Second,
this
rejection
is
due
to
the
dominance
of
postmodernism
in
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities.
Third,
the
rejection
can
be
attributed
to
critics
perception
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
politically
incorrect.
Fourth,
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
due
to
Ivory
Tower
elitism
and
specialization.
Each
of
these
ideologies
carries
with
it
a
rather
complex
history,
but
these
histories
also
demonstrate
how
enduring
and
widespread
these
ideologies
138
have
become.
To
this
end,
I
argued
that
the
in-house
ideologies
of
the
EvoS
Program
possess
significant
scope
within
the
evolutionary
science
community.
More
importantly,
they
operationalize
the
movements
first
principle
by
calling
attention
to
the
various
professional
grievances
that
proponents
of
evolutionary
reasoning
have
voiced
over
several
decades.
While
these
grievances
are
undoubtedly
felt
by
many
professional
academics,
this
does
not
entirely
explain
the
functionality
of
these
ideologies
for
the
EvoS
Program.
Certainly,
social
movements
of
any
kind
are
most
visible
(and
audible)
in
their
complaints
about
the
institutions
that
participants
feel
are
mistreating
them
and
dismissing
their
concerns.
But
how
would
such
complaints
contribute
to
the
maintenance
and
spread
of
the
movement?
The
answer
is
that
movements
may
creatively
index
their
in-house
ideologies
regularly
over
time
(and
into
increasingly
diverse
settings),
such
that
the
ideologies
become
the
overarching
meaning
of
every
movement
activity.
By
regularly
voicing
complaint
in
this
way,
we
should
find
that
the
first
principle
of
a
social
movement
will
also
be
consistently
affirmed
as
the
relevant
(i.e.
logical,
ethical,
pragmatic)
solution
to
these
problems.
In
this
way,
the
overarching
message
of
a
social
movement
remains
consistent
over
time
and
across
settings,
where
it
will
reach
new
potential
members,
mobilize
those
already
participating,
and
(arguably)
legitimate
the
continued
existence
of
the
movement
for
those
inside
and
outside
its
ranks.
Now,
the
question
remains
as
to
how
the
in-house
ideologies
of
EvoS
become
creatively
indexed
into
its
activities.
Put
another
way,
how
does
one
go
about
convincing
undergraduates
(or
anyone
else)
that
the
rejection
of
evolutionary
139
reasoning
in
higher
education
is
a
significant
injustice,
and
that
(instead)
evolutionary
reasoning
should
be
embraced
across
all
disciplines
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life?
To
answer
this,
I
turn
to
the
most
active
and
diverse
setting
for
EvoS
at
Binghamton
University
its
Seminar
Series.
There,
as
I
will
demonstrate,
participants
create
foregroundings
that
(in
some
way)
draw
attention
to
one
or
more
of
the
programs
in-house
ideologies.
These
foregroundings
appear
most
frequently
in
EvoS
lectures
as
four,
regularly
occurring
types:
(1)
attacks
on
the
structure
of
academics,
(2)
gratuitous
displays
or
mentioning
taboo
subjects,
(3)
personal
testimonies,
and
(4)
marked
modes
of
speaker
performance/audience
participation
As
I
explain
in
greater
detail
below,
all
four
types
share
a
common
capacity
to
violate
the
norms
of
academic
lecturing,
in
one
way
or
another.
They
tend
to
evoke
shock,
confusion,
or
laughter
from
an
audience,
and
potentially
hold
a
listeners
attention
until
some
kind
of
resolution
is
reached.
As
I
will
show,
these
foregoundings
function
as
creative
indexicals
that
direct
listeners
attentions
toward
the
various
complaints
about
the
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
U.S.
higher
education.
EvoS
lectures
typically
contextualize
these
foregroundings
(and
their
creatively
indexed
ideologies)
by
reaffirming
that
evolutionary
reasoning
should
be
prioritized
as
the
new,
cross-disciplinary
foundation
within
university
education
and
research.
While
this
resolution
is
typically
an
intellectual
and
political
proposition
made
by
the
speakers,
it
is
no
less
an
attempt
at
semiotically
closing
140
the
overarching
meaning
of
an
interaction.
The
first
principle
and
the
programs
in-
house
ideologies
are
thus
contextualized
as
the
promotions
take-away
messages.
These
contextualizations
tend
to
perform
further
kinds
of
ideological
labor
for
speakers:
abstractions
that
represent
higher
education
as
opposing
groups
of
intellectuals
(for
or
against
evolutionary
reasoning),
analogical
extensions
that
tie
evolutionary
reasoning
to
various
other
socio-political
concerns
(such
as
public
health
or
civil
rights),
and
reflexive
recursions
that
encourage
audiences
to
consider
elements
of
their
own
lives
(including
their
participation
in
the
context-at-hand)
as
foundationally
explainable
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Lectures
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
are
different
from
many
academic
lectures,
in
large
part
because
of
the
types
and
numbers
of
foregroundings
appearing
there.
However,
I
am
not
arguing
that
the
foregroundings
found
in
EvoS
lectures
are
entirely
different
from
lecturing
styles
that
might
be
found
elsewhere.
As
I
remind
my
readers
throughout
this
discussion,
lecturers
might
employ
a
variety
of
foregrounding
devices
(some
similar
to
the
four
I
describe
below)
to
punctuate
important
concepts,
differentiate
their
perspectives
from
others,
make
learning
fun
for
their
audiences,
or
simply
to
keep
them
awake.
Readers
with
experience
studying
or
teaching
in
U.S.
higher
education
will
likely
find
some
similarities
between
the
practices
of
EvoS
speakers
and
lectures
they
themselves
have
attended
or
delivered.
The
foregroundings
taking
shape
in
EvoS
lectures
(like
those
appearing
in
its
promotions)
are
violations
of
academic
norms,
but
they
must
also
be
recognizable
and
likely
sensible
to
their
academic
audiences.
As
might
be
said
of
foregroundings
in
general,
the
quality
of
being
different
is
also
governed
by
rules
141
(Fnagy
1972:288).
To
this
end,
that
EvoS
Seminar
Series
lectures
are
dynamic
interplays
between
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals,
which
(as
I
have
said
before)
are
surprising
to
find
in
a
social
movement,
given
that
such
interplay
is
a
basic
reality
of
sociolinguistic
life.
This
said,
there
exist
four
notable
differences
between
the
foregroundings
of
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
and
those
found
in
departmental
seminars
or
academic
lectures
at-large:
First,
these
foregroundings
occur
quite
frequently
within
and
across
the
Seminar
Series
lectures.
That
is,
these
four
types
of
foregroundings
exhibit
high
statistical
regularity
within
my
data
set.
Second,
these
foregroundings
consistently
index
the
same
combinations
of
combinations
of
the
EvoS
Programs
in-
house
ideologies,
described
in
Chapter
Three.
Lecturers
thus
contextualize
their
foregroundings
by
assuming
or
even
explicitly
stating
that
these
ideologies
are
central
to
the
relevant
meanings
to
be
drawn
from
their
actions.
Third,
almost
always,
the
contextualizations
of
these
foregrounding
types
reaffirm
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education.
Finally,
most
broadly,
these
foregroundings
distinguish
EvoS
as
a
social
movement
reproducing
implicit
and
explicit
representations
of
its
institutional
opposition,
reiterating
the
movements
challenge
to
higher
education,
and
leading
to
repeated
affirmations
of
the
movements
first
principle.
In
my
analysis
below,
I
will
present
examples
of
these
foregrounding-
contextualization
orders
in
the
following
way:
I
describe
the
defining
characteristics
of
each
foregrounding
type,
stressing
the
reasons
behind
my
classifications.
Then
I
will
lay
out
examples
from
the
lectures
in
my
data
set.
In
each
example,
I
discuss
the
142
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies
that
are
creatively
indexed
by
these
foregroundings,
how
these
ideologies
are
subsequently
contextualized,
and
the
role
of
the
programs
first
principle
in
contextualizing
them
(sometimes
through
semiotic
association
with
other,
external
ideologies).
Next,
I
document
the
statistical
support
for
each
foregrounding
type,
within
individual
lectures
and
across
the
entirety
of
data
set.
Finally,
I
offer
additional
ethnographic
evidence
from
my
fieldwork,
further
demonstrating
how
these
foregroundings
function
to
index
and
contextualize
the
EvoS
Programs
ideologies
and
first
principle
into
diverse
interpersonal
settings.
1.
Attacks
on
the
Structure
of
Academics
Speakers in the EvoS Seminar Series often present critical attacks on the
143
of
each
foregrounding
as
an
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
first
principle.
Perhaps
unsurprisingly,
as
it
appears
in
EvoS
lectures,
this
foregrounding
type
often
indexes
an
in-house
ideology
representing
the
institutional
opponents
as
academic
elitists
who
cling
to
disciplinary
specialization.
Additionally,
this
foregrounding
type
commonly
indexes
a
representation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
feared
by
its
critics
in
U.S.
higher
education.
Recalling
the
historical
background
I
laid
out
in
Chapter
Three,
I
show
that
these
lecturers
index
combinations
of
these
ideologies,
characterizing
evolutionary
reasoning
as
unfairly
feared
in
U.S.
higher
education
by
elitist
or
overly
specialized
academic
professionals.
While
every
speaker
presents
a
unique
kind
of
attack,
each
invokes
this
shared
account
of
a
movements
challenge
to
(and
resistance
from)
an
academic
institution.
As
each
foregrounding
is
contextualized,
lecturers
also
affirm
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
(or
should
be
considered)
a
foundation
for
questions
of
human
social
life
that
would
resolve
the
various
shortcomings
of
contemporary
U.S.
higher
education.
Example
1a:
You
would
want
to
get
the
whole
story
This
first
example
of
an
attack
on
academic
structure
is
posed
by
a
Seminar
Series
lecturer
who
objects
to
the
disciplinary
divisions
of
higher
education.
Proposing
that
disciplinary
specialization
obstructs
free,
intellectual
inquiry,
she
tells
her
audience:
I
cant
understand
how
you
could
say
Im
a
this
and
I
dont
go
out
of
my
intellectual
cage
for
the
rest
my
life
I
just
dont
understand
it
If
you
were
interested
in
some
subject
like
well
marriage
or
table
manners
or
dueling
you
wouldnt
arbitrarily
say
Im
only
going
to
read
things
that
are
about
these
things
after
1800
you
know
I
just
144
draw
the
line
there
thats
all
Im
interested
in
no
you
would
want
to
get
the
whole
story
Here,
the
speaker
attacks
the
disciplinary
divisions
in
academic
inquiry,
which
she
finds
arbitrary
and
illogical.
She
contrasts
this
academic
structure
to
an
intellectual
imperative
to
get
the
whole
story.
In
this
way,
she
creatively
indexes
an
ideology
representing
an
institutional
structure
marked
by
fragmentation
and
dogmatism.
If
there
is
any
uncertainty
that
this
is
indeed
her
meaning,
the
lecturer
next
clarifies:
Now
I
turn
to
biology
particularly
evolutionary
biology
just
because
I
want
to
get
the
whole
story
or
I
want
the
back
story
on
something
that
fascinates
me
in
human
history
and
prehistory
and
it
irritates
me
when
friends
who
are
often
very
intellectually
curious
people
will
get
dismayed
if
I
start
going/roaming
back
into
prehistory
in
this
quest
or
raising
questions
about
human
evolution
in
this
quest
The
speakers
juxtaposition
of
disciplinary
divisions
to
getting
the
whole
story
has
here
become
the
historically
informed,
ideologically
grounded
message
of
her
attack.
To
get
the
whole
story,
one
must
turn
to
a
perspective
unbounded
by
such
divisions
evolutionary
biology.
To
contextualize
this
foregrounding
(and
its
indexed
in-house
ideology),
the
speaker
reaffirms
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
first
principle
that
gets
the
whole
story,
because
it
transcends
the
disciplinary
limitations
of
intellectuals
who
ignore
or
reject
it.
Two
points
deserve
our
attention
concerning
this
contextualization:
First,
it
effectively
abstracts
the
intellectual
universe
that
this
speaker
describes
into
two,
oppositional
representations
groups
of
discipline-bound
and
trans-disciplinary
intellectuals.
These
groups
are
distinguishable
through
their
rejection
or
embrace
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Second,
insofar
as
the
speaker
also
describes
dismay
among
friends
who
are
often
very
intellectually
curious
people,
the
speaker
also
145
projects
upon
these
abstracted
groups
the
qualities
of
(on
one
hand)
fearing
evolutionary
reasoning
and
(on
the
other)
experiencing
undue
criticism
also
an
in-
house
ideology
of
the
EvoS
Program).
Even
in
this
quite
simple
example,
this
is
overlap
in
the
creative
indexing
of
another
in-house
ideology
(and
the
beginnings
of
another
affirmation
of
the
programs
first
principle).
Example
1b:
It
thinks
of
itself
as
so
progressive,
but
its
actually
become
rather
regressive
My
second
example
comes
from
a
visiting
EvoS
lecturer
wishing
to
extend
evolutionary
theory
into
literary
criticism.
While
his
foregrounding
addresses
a
narrower
portion
of
professional
academics
(the
Modern
Languages
Association)
he
crafts
his
attack
in
a
quite
similar
fashion
as
in
my
first
example:
The
Modern
Languages
Association
it
thinks
of
itself
as
so
progressive
but
its
actually
become
rather
regressive
and
allows
sort
of
very
little
room
for
substantial
dissent
from
its
parties
and
no
room
for
anything
as
reactionary
as
they
imagine
anything
evolutionary
studies
of
anything
human
must
be
This
speakers
foregrounding
charges
an
academic
institution
with
hypocrisy
this
influential
entity
represents
itself
in
a
positive
light,
but
contradicts
its
ideals
in
practice.
The
speaker
explains
that
this
institution
resists
internal
dissent,
and
shows
very
specific
resistance
toward
his
mode
of
dissent.
It
objects
to
evolutionary
studies
of
anything
human
as
reactionary,
all
the
while
thinking
of
itself
as
so
progressive.
As
is
likely
clear,
this
speaker
indexes
here
an
in-house
ideology
within
EvoS:
institutional
critics
fear
and
misunderstand
evolutionary
reasoning,
and
relegate
its
application
to
non-human
disciplines.
Yet,
as
the
speaker
continues,
he
reports
on
a
kind
of
reversal
of
fortunes:
146
But
now
that
literary
studies
are
in
dire
straits
they
have
put
out
a
call
for
papers
on
new
directions
in
twenty-first
century
literary
criticism
I
submitted
something
in
response
to
their
call
that
I
rather
enjoyed
writing
something
that
just
might
have
a
chance
of
passing
their
defenses
those
who
think
theyre
in
opposition
to
evolution
whether
despite
my
efforts
to
make
it
palatable
to
them
it
provokes
a
gag
reflex
I
dont
yet
know
The
irony
of
this
scenario
is
underpinned
by
the
ideologies
the
speaker
previously
indexed
a
supposedly
progressive
institution
encounters
(likely
financial)
dire
straits,
forcing
it
to
seek
the
help
of
scholars
it
once
suppressed.
The
speaker
uses
this
opportunity
to
push
an
evolutionary
argument
through
the
defenses
of
those
who
think
theyre
in
opposition
to
evolution.
To
this
end,
the
evolutionary
reasoning
is
a
subversive
challenge
to
the
institutional
elitism
and
dogma.
The
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
is
less
explicitly
affirmed
than
my
first
example,
but
appears
here
an
interesting
way.
As
the
speaker
argues,
the
targeted
institution
is
not
genuinely
in
opposition
to
evolutionary
reasoning,
they
only
think
theyre
in
opposition
to
it.
They
misunderstand
its
foundational
potential,
and
so
convince
themselves
that
they
must
oppose
it.
They
might
be
convinced,
however,
as
he
subversively
delivers
evolutionary
reasoning
past
their
defenses
or
gag
reflex
an
act
of
persuasion
akin
to
feeding
castor
oil
to
an
obstinate
child.
This
contextualization
is
an
abstraction
of
the
same
kind
as
above
(example
1a),
although
this
speaker
takes
a
more
revolutionary
stance,
hoping
to
convert
those
who
resist
the
first
principle
by
delivering
a
palatable
version
of
it.
Example
1c:
Theyre
all
thinking
in
little
silo
hats
In
this
third
example,
an
EvoS
lecturer
discusses
several
health
problems
experienced
by
US
children
(obesity,
depression,
bipolar
disorder,
and
ADHD).
He
complains
that
health
professionals
147
inside
and
outside
the
academy
are
separated
by
the
specializations
of
their
disciplines:
We
have
to
start
connecting
the
dots
to
see
how
things
are
tied
together
cause
right
now
in
nursing
and
public
health
you
know
theyre
all
thinking
in
little
silo
hats
We
have
the
obesity
problem
Here,
the
speaker
lifts
his
hands
to
the
sides
of
head,
delineating
an
imaginary,
cylindrical
silo
hat.
The
speaker
then
steps
to
his
right,
repeating
the
gesture:
We
have
the
depression
problem
Again,
the
speaker
steps
to
his
right,
repeating
his
silo
hat
gesture:
148
academic
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
obsessively
policing
disciplinary
divides.
149
evolutionary
reasoning
is
aligned
with
the
happiness
and
welfare
of
children.
The
relevance
of
Darwinian
theories
to
childrens
health
and
happiness
is
a
relatively
novel
connection,
and
so
the
extension
pushes
evolutionary
reasoning
into
semiotic
association
with
a
previously
unrelated
ideology.
This
said,
the
importance
of
maintaining
childrens
health
and
welfare
is
likely
a
concern
presupposed
of
students
and
faculty
in
his
audience,
if
not
U.S.
higher
education
in
general.
Data
Summary
1:
Attacks
on
Academic
Structure
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
Lecture
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
#Attacks
150
children)
to
further
ground
EvoS
Programs
ideologies
and
first
principle
as
socially
and
politically
important.
The
frequency
of
this
foregrounding
type
(and
its
subsequent
contextualizations)
in
my
data
set
suggests
that
it
performs
a
regular
function:
indexing
combinations
of
the
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies
and
its
first
principle
as
the
relevant
meanings
of
these
lectures
as
a
whole.
Surely,
there
is
nothing
inherently
revolutionary
in
conducting
a
lecture
or
a
series
of
lectures,
any
more
than
attending
weekly
religious
services,
going
to
school
board
meetings,
or
gathering
at
a
local
pub.
Yet,
as
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Two,
it
is
precisely
these
mundane
activities
where
the
challenges
of
social
movements
become
interpersonal
realities,
as
participants
index
a
movements
ideologies
into
the
normal
interactions
of
their
lives.
To
this
end,
it
will
be
instructive
to
examine
a
few
broader
examples
of
the
EvoS
Programs
attacks
on
academic
structure.
The
EvoS
Programs
founder
also
poses
attacks
on
academic
structure.
For
instance,
in
one
of
his
most
widely
read
books,
he
criticizes
the
Social
Sciences
as
a
vast
archipelago
of
disciplines
that
only
partially
communicate
with
each
other.
My
status
as
an
outsider
makes
it
easy
for
me
to
island-
hop
the
social
sciences,
and
I
am
struck
by
the
lack
of
consistency
[]
You
know
there
is
a
problem
when
one
mans
heresy
is
another
mans
commonplace.
It
signals
a
need
to
step
back
and
rebuild
the
social
sciences
from
first
principles,
making
the
various
subdisciplines
consistent
with
each
other
and
with
evolutionary
biology.
[D.S.
Wilson
2002a:83-4]
Here,
Wilson
complains
of
the
lack
of
communication
between
an
institutions
constituent
parts,
and
the
absence
of
a
common
theme
across
the
whole.
He
poses
that
the
resolution
lies
in
rebuilding
the
Social
Sciences
with
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
all
disciplines.
Considering
his
central
role
in
the
151
EvoS
Program,
his
comment
is
an
explicit
statement
of
his
movements
primary
challenge
to
U.S.
higher
education.
It
should
be
noted
that
the
challenge
that
the
attack
on
academic
structure
echoes
similar
challenges
in
previous
evolutionary
science
literatures
(Huxley
1963:20-21;
Marayanski
and
Turner
1992:2-7;
E.O.
Wilson
1978:
4-11,
1998a,
1998b;
Wright
1994b:4-8),
and
has
further
been
taken
up
by
others
more
recently
(Barkow
2006;
Garcia
et
al.
2011;
Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010;
Geher
et
al.
2011;
Gottshall
and
D.S.
Wilson
2005;
Hlodan
2008;
Lustick
2005;
Platek
et
al.
2011;
Robertson
2007;
Vieth
2010).
David
Sloan
Wilson
frequently
moderates
the
Seminar
Series
lectures,
question
and
answer
sessions,
and
social
events.
His
introductions
for
visiting
lectures
commonly
index
EvoS
in-house
ideologies,
suggesting
that
the
speaker
is
representative
of
(if
not
in
fact
convinced
of)
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Introducing
one
lecturer,
Wilson
comments:
She
just
said
to
me
last
night
You
know
the
traditional
academic
disciplines
just
dont
make
much
sense
and
when
she
tackles
a
topic
she
consults
the
anthropological
literature,
the
biological
literature,
neurobiological
shes
just
crossing
these
disciplinary
boundaries
all
the
time
and
thats
what
were
striving
to
do
here
Moreover,
Wilson
argues
that
students
are
similarly
unsatisfied
with
disciplinary
limitations,
and
(through
their
participation
in
EvoS)
come
to
understand
the
transcending
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Returning
to
a
quote
I
present
in
my
second
chapter,
Wilson
explains:
EvoS
students
regard
EvoS
as
their
academic
home
rather
than
their
particular
department.
As
one
student
put
it,
EvoS
provides
a
stimulating
atmosphere
with
which
biologists,
psychologists,
anthropologists,
philosophers,
social
scientists,
and
even
those
in
the
arts
can
transcend
traditional
academic
boundaries
and
collaborate
in
addressing
mutually
interesting
questions.
It
creates
a
think-tank
152
atmosphere
of
sorts,
and
its
a
beautiful
thing!
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1007]
Of
course,
this
report
is
handpicked
by
the
programs
founder
as
evidence
of
its
academic
success.
It
is
remarkable,
nevertheless,
that
this
students
evaluation
reads
as
a
nearly
verbatim
reiteration
of
the
foregrounded
attacks
and
contextualizations
posed
by
Wilson
and
EvoS
lecturers.
How
the
stimulating
atmosphere
that
the
student
describes
is
created
is,
I
suggest,
largely
due
to
the
varieties
of
foregroundings
that
take
place
there.
This
should
become
even
clearer
as
my
analysis
of
them
continues
below.
2.
Gratuitous
Displays
and
Mentioning
Taboo
Topics
153
contextualize
these
foregroundings
as
ways
of
challenging
stereotypes,
catalysts
for
in-class
debates,
or
simply
as
means
for
entertaining
their
students
while
they
learn.
Whatever
the
case,
such
shocking
and
unexpected
materials
create
foregroundings
because
both
lecturers
and
audiences
recognize
the
materials
as
taboo
within
an
institutional
setting
presupposed
to
be
politically-correct
or
humorless.
The
brunt
of
the
foregrounding
lies
in
their
disruption
of
these
expectations.
Foregroundings
in
EvoS
lectures
are
thus
(at
least
on
the
surface)
comparable
to
other
lecturing
methods
that
might
attempt
to
shock,
offend,
or
amuse
an
audience
for
one
purpose
or
another.
As
these
foregroundings
appear
in
my
data
set
however,
they
are
distinguished
again
by
several
qualities
relevant
to
this
case
study:
First,
they
appear
with
great
statistical
regularity,
both
within
individual
lectures
and
across
the
whole.
Second,
like
lecturers
attacks
on
academic
structure,
gratuitous
displays
and
taboo
topicalizations
regularly
index
one
or
a
combination
of
the
in-house
ideologies
I
describe
in
Chapter
Three.
Third,
this
foregrounding
type
(like
attacks
on
academic
structure)
is
regularly
contextualized
through
a
lecturers
affirmation
of
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle.
As
will
become
clear
through
my
examples
and
other
ethnographic
evidence,
these
gratuitous
and
taboo
instances
show
a
very
specific
ideological
affiliation
with
violations
of
politically
correct
topics
particularly
those
dealing
with
sex
and
violence.
Through
their
introduction
in
academic
settings,
speakers
are
demonstrating
that
their
work
can
handle
topics
that
others
are
too
touchy
to
address.
154
Below, I will proceed as I did above. I will break down a few, step-by-step
examples
of
this
foregrounding
from
lectures
in
my
data
set,
focusing
within
each
example
on
the
creation
of
the
foregrounding,
the
in-house
ideologies
that
are
creatively
indexed
there,
and
the
lecturers
subsequent
contextualization
of
the
foregrounding
(again
affirming
EvoS
Programs
first
principle).
After
these
examples,
I
detail
the
statistical
significance
of
this
foregrounding
type
across
the
lectures
in
my
data
set.
Lastly,
I
offer
further
ethnographic
evidence
of
this
foregrounding
type
as
it
is
put
to
similar
use
in
settings
outside
the
lectures.
I
will
argue
there
as
elsewhere
that
a
primary
use
of
this
foregrounding
type
(and
the
three
others)
is
to
regularly
contextualize
the
in-house
ideologies
and
first
principle
of
EvoS
into
increasingly
numerous
and
novel
settings.
Example
2a:
The
butt
surgery.
In
my
first
example,
an
EvoS
lecturer
describes
his
research
on
neurology
and
sexual
attraction.
Apparent
within
the
set
up
to
his
foregrounding,
his
research
methods
are
rather
unorthodox.
He
explains:
I
was
in
the
unique
position
to
have
photographs
of
women
who
went
to
have
surgical
procedures
to
increase
their
waist
to
hip
ratio
the
procedure
that
by
the
way
is
called
the
butt
surgery33
So
I
had
pictures
of
these
girls
prior
to
their
surgery
and
I
have
pictures
of
these
girls
after
the
surgery
and
I
can
then
show
these
pictures
to
men
while
Im
looking
at
their
neurological
response
to
these
images
At
this
point,
the
speaker
uses
his
hand-held
remote
control
to
bring
up
a
new
PowerPoint
slide.
This
slide
contains
a
collage
of
a
dozen,
close-up
photographs
of
33
Gluteal Augmentation is a cosmetic surgery procedure in which doctors draw subcutaneous fat from
other regions of a patients body (typically lower stomach or inner thighs) and inject it into the patients
buttocks. The aim of this surgery is to increase the size and curvature of the buttocks, relative to the
patients waist and upper legs (see Mendieta 2006a; 2006b)
155
womens
naked
butts,
taken
previous
to
or
following
cosmetic
surgery.
The
lecture
audience
immediately
bursts
into
loud
laughter.
156
In
his
next
statement,
the
speaker
explains
the
evolutionary
significance
of
this
research:
But
what
we
found
is
that
if
you
look
at
the
effects
of
pre/post
we
get
activation
in
frontal
lobe
and
anterior
superior
and
some
posterior
visual
areas
that
males
preferentially
find
attractive
females
that
vary
in
the
level
of
their
curve-asious-ness
or
what
is
called
their
waist
to
hip
ratio
and
interestingly
enough
the
waist
to
hip
ratio
appears
to
be
an
honest
biological
signal
of
things
like
fertility
health
and
mental
abilities
of
your
offspring
Logically,
of
course,
he
could
have
made
his
argument
without
displaying
these
slides.
However,
by
introducing
the
pictures,
the
speaker
created
a
foregrounding
that
both
he
and
his
audience
had
to
deal
with.
To
contextualize
his
foregrounding,
the
speaker
reaffirms
the
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program.
The
scientific
relevance
of
his
unorthodox
research
(showing
nude
photos
to
test
subjects)
lies
in
the
support
it
provides
to
an
evolutionary
hypothesis
on
sex
and
sexuality.
As
I
suggest
above,
both
the
lecturer
and
his
audience
contrast
the
inappropriateness
of
this
display
as
a
violation
of
the
serious,
humorless,
or
politically
correct
delivery
of
other
academic
lectures.
This
foregrounding
indexes
an
in-house
ideology
contrasting
the
subversiveness
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
a
relatively
politically
correct
academic
institution.
Contextualizing
his
foregrounding,
the
speaker
thus
legitimates
this
gratuitous
display
(given
its
relevance
to
evolutionary
science)
and
moreover
situates
his
own
work
within
the
revolutionary
spirit
of
evolutionary
reasoning
that
is
also
valued
within
the
EvoS
Program.
While
the
abstraction
created
in
this
interaction
is
(arguably)
more
subtle
than
those
appearing
in
my
previous
examples,
it
can
be
observed
that
the
lecturer
glibly
suggests
that
some
in
his
audience
might
have
a
soft
stomach
toward
images
157
of
naked
female
bodies
a
nod
to
the
EvoS
Programs
understanding
of
higher
education
as
divided
into
politically
correct
intellectuals
and
those
who
advocate
evolutionary
reasoning.
Example
2b:
You
probably
know
someone
like
this.
The
lecturer
in
my
first
example
introduced
visual
material
to
shock
and
amuse
his
audience.
However,
EvoS
lecturers
also
construct
taboo
moments
through
verbal
descriptions,
such
as
narrating
sexually
explicit
or
violent
scenarios
for
their
audiences.
In
this
second
example,
a
speaker
describes
the
qualities
of
an
individual
with
borderline
personality
disorder:
You
probably
know
someone
like
this
maybe
its
someone
whos
a
big
cardiologist
here
in
town
well
liked
well
respected
very
popular
everybody
loves
the
guy
and
he
goes
home
and
when
the
doors
close
he
is
absolutely
a
monster
to
his
family
aggressive
abusive
emotionally
abusive
abuses
his
kids
his
wife
and
his
wife
can
do
nothing
about
it
because
if
she
tried
to
if
she
tried
to
tell
people
about
it
they
would
never
believe
her
Here,
the
lecturer
poses
a
hypothetical
situation
involving
social
deception,
emotional
manipulation,
and
domestic
violence.
The
speakers
tone
throughout
is
emphatic,
contrasting
this
mans
spotless
public
veneer
to
his
private
violence.
Clearly,
the
speaker
is
trying
to
move
her
audience
(You
probably
know
someone
like
this),
and
perhaps
even
frighten
them.
She
frames
the
violence,
deception,
and
injustice
as
near
to
those
listening,
likely
happening
in
their
very
community,
whether
they
know
it
or
not.
She
further
suggests
that
the
wife
of
this
abusive
man
can
do
nothing
to
escape
her
horror,
because
of
biases
toward
publicly
successful
men,
although
their
success
may
conceal
an
abusive
or
exploitative
private
life.
158
Next, the speaker builds upon her unpleasant narrative, describing a female
159
foregrounding
similarly
indexes
an
in-house
ideology,
juxtaposing
institutional
austerity
or
soberness
to
the
dramatic
performance
of
her
narrative.
160
objects
to
domestic
violence,
she
arrives
at
a
reiteration
of
the
EvoS
Programs
challenge
to
their
audiences
to
embrace
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life.
161
whore,
easy,
bitch,
cocktease,
and
several
more.
Many
in
the
audience
immediately
begin
to
laugh
or
mumble
to
one
another.
He
comments:
Here
are
these
very
derogatory
terms
that
get
used
by
folks
that
we
gathered
through
our
interviews
As
in
Example
2a,
this
speaker
introduces
(without
much
warning)
a
slide
likely
to
shock,
amuse,
and
possibly
offend
an
academic
audience.
Like
that
speaker,
he
explains
the
derogatory
terms
on
this
slide
as
a
part
of
an
unorthodox
research
method;
and
rather
than
omitting
material
that
might
be
considered
sexist
or
vulgar,
he
unflinchingly
introduces
it
to
his
audience.
The
audiences
reaction
is
a
combination
of
shock
and
laughter,
suggesting
that
the
success
of
this
foregrounding
(like
those
above)
rests
on
its
subversion
of
the
appropriate
(typically,
politically
correct)
material
that
one
would
presuppose
of
a
serious
academic
lecture.
audience
reaction:
Now
we
might
just
think
of
it
as
a
way
of
being
derogatory
of
being
mean
but
it
turns
out
that
these
terms
are
used
in
very
specific
kinds
of
ways
guys
in
particular
will
use
the
word
easy
when
theyre
thinking
about
mate-seeking
more
so
when
they
have
other
kinds
of
motivation
women
particularly
use
the
words
sluts
or
whores
when
theyre
thinking
about
mate-retention
as
a
way
of
stigmatizing
and
controlling
other
women
who
threaten
mate
retention
This
speaker
contextualizes
the
taboo
topics
(and
the
emotional
shock
they
are
likely
to
invoke)
as
understandable
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
That
is,
he
argues,
derogatory
words
are
not
just
ways
of
being
mean.
Rather,
men
and
women
use
them
to
maximize
their
own
reproductive
opportunities,
stigmatizing
others
who
pose
threats
to
those
opportunities.
The
speaker
here
indexes
an
in-
162
house
ideology
common
to
the
EvoS
Program,
criticizing
its
critics
as
reactionary,
while
evolutionary
reasoning
uncovers
truths
about
human
behaviors
that
are
hidden
beneath
a
veneer
of
political
correctness.
On
this
revealing
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
the
speaker
explains
further:
An
evolutionary
perspective
says
that
being
mean
is
not
enough
different
groups
pose
different
threats
and
therefore
they
require
different
kinds
of
emotional
responses
some
prejudices
ought
to
be
characterized
by
fear
some
should
be
characterized
by
disgust
some
should
be
characterized
by
anger
in
response
to
the
different
kinds
of
threats
these
groups
are
posing
Introducing
a
potentially
shocking
set
of
terms
to
his
audience,
this
lecturer
explains
that
the
shock
these
terms
are
known
to
cause
(and
have,
in
fact,
caused
in
this
very
setting)
has
an
evolutionary
explanation.
It
is
probable
that
his
audiences
reaction
was
a
result
of
encountering
these
terms
in
the
midst
of
an
academic
lecture,
an
anomalous
development
when
opposed
to
institutional
practices
typically
presupposed
to
be
serious
or
politically
correct.
The
speakers
contextualization,
however,
speaks
to
the
ultimate,
biological
function
of
these
terms.
No
less
than
the
speaker
in
Example
2b,
he
analogically
extends
the
uses
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
way
to
see
the
functionality
(controlling
others
reproductive
strategies)
underlying
a
problematic
social
practice
that
normative
ideologies
inadequately
explain
as
just
a
way
of
being
derogatory
of
being
mean.
In
this
way,
like
my
previous
examples
of
this
foregrounding
type,
this
speaker
contextualizes
his
subversive
or
politically
incorrect,
derogatory
terms
as
a
necessary
bit
of
evidence
on
the
semiotic
course
toward
the
radical
explanation
of
social
life.
163
Data
Summary
2:
Gratuitous
Displays/Mentioning
Taboo
Topics
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
Lecture
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
#Attacks
#Taboos
14
In
greater
numbers
than
my
first
foregrounding
type,
gratuitous
displays
and
taboo
topics
appear
within
all
the
lectures
in
my
data
set:
93
foregroundings
appear
across
20
of
20
(100%)
of
all
lectures,
with
an
average
of
4.65
per
lecture.
This
second
type
of
foregrounding
appears
at
least
once
in
all
20
lectures
in
my
data
set,
and
two
or
more
times
in
18
out
of
20
(90%).
How
a
lecturer
might
create
this
type
of
foregrounding
is
unique
to
the
individual
and
content
of
the
lecture.
Yet,
these
individual
instances
may
be
legitimately
typified
into
a
single
category.
Their
commonality
lies
not
only
the
in
frequency
of
this
type
across
all
lectures,
but
also
each
foregroundings
tendency
to
index
combinations
of
the
same
set
ideologies
and
the
speakers
final
contextualization
through
an
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life.
Moreover,
the
lecturers
contextualizations
in
Examples
2b
and
2c
analogically
extend
the
first
principle
to
impress
upon
their
audiences
the
social
and
ethical
importance
of
embracing
evolutionary
reasoning
as
an
ultimate
cause,
underlying
problematic
social
behaviors.
164
Chapter
Three.
They
invoke
domestic
violence,
child
abuse,
sexual
promiscuity
and
manipulation,
and
other
topics
of
a
politically
sensitive
nature.
Evolutionary
scientists
like
Edward
O.
Wilson,
Stephen
Jay
Gould,
and
Richard
Dawkins
were
uncommonly
able
to
stir
strong
reactions
from
their
audiences,
often
by
presenting
controversial
arguments
about
equally
controversial
topics,
such
as
racism,
sexual
orientation,
or
the
existence
of
God.
In
the
last
four
decades,
evolutionary
theorists
sparked
more
widespread
criticism
by
publishing
and
lecturing
on
the
biological
functions
of
politically
sensitive
subjects,
such
as
rape
(Thornhill
and
Palmer
2000),
homicide
(Wrangham
and
Peterson
1997;
Daly
and
Wilson
1988),
genocide
(Diamond
1992,
1999),
and
despotic
regimes
(Oakley
2007).
My
point
here
is
not
to
argue
that
evolution
is
controversial.
Rather,
as
evinced
by
lecturers
in
my
data
set
and
the
authors
I
describe
here,
proponents
of
evolutionary
reasoning
strategically
employ
aspects
of
this
controversy
to
draw
audiences
attention
to
their
arguments.
The
EvoS
Programs
founder
also
utilizes
this
type
of
foregrounding
within
his
own
publications
and
promotions
of
the
program.
For
example,
he
describes
a
classroom
lesson
on
the
evolutionary
explanations
for
infanticide.
David
Sloan
Wilson
instructs
students
to
collaborate
for
five
minutes
to
identify
situations
in
which
infanticide
is
biologically
adaptive
for
the
parents
(D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1003).
In
their
discussion
groups,
his
students
are
eager
to
talk,
and
reliably
identify
the
three
major
adaptive
contexts
of
infanticide:
lack
of
resources,
poor
offspring
quality,
and
uncertain
paternity
(D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1003).
On
this,
Wilson
wonders
at
his
students
insightful
conclusions:
How
can
they,
mere
undergraduate
students,
who
know
almost
nothing
about
evolution
and
(one
hopes)
know
nothing
at
all
about
165
infanticide,
so
easily
deduce
the
major
hypotheses
that
are
in
fact
employed
in
the
study
of
infanticide
for
organisms
as
diverse
as
plants,
insects,
and
mammals?
That
is
just
one
example
of
the
power
of
thinking
on
the
basis
of
adaptation
and
natural
selection
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1003]
In
this
lesson,
Wilson
introduces
a
practice
carrying
substantial
moral
taboos.
This
arguably
contributes
to
his
students
enthusiasm
to
discuss
it.
However,
despite
its
controversial
nature
(he
argues),
evolutionary
reasoning
can
be
used
even
by
mere
undergraduates
to
arrive
at
profound
scientific
conclusions
about
such
troublesome
social
problems.
On
the
taboo
nature
of
his
classroom
topic,
Wilson
notes:
It
might
seem
that
boldly
discussing
subjects
such
as
human
infanticide
(which
the
students
quickly
connect
to
the
contemporary
issue
of
abortion),
along
with
other
topics
such
as
sex
differences
and
homosexuality
later
in
the
course,
is
the
ultimate
in
political
incorrectness
[].
In
the
case
of
infanticide,
evolutionary
theory
doesnt
say
thats
right
it
is
used
to
make
an
informed
guess
about
when
it
occurs.
All
the
students
want
to
know
if
the
guess
proves
to
be
correct
for
humans
in
addition
to
other
creatures,
regardless
on
their
moral
stance
on
abortion
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1004]
Here,
Wilson
acknowledges
that
his
topic
is
taboo
and
thus
subverts
the
political
correctness
commonly
presupposed
of
human-related
subjects
in
U.S.
universities.
The
evolutionary
explanations
for
infanticide
(Wilson
argues)
successfully
transcend
students
moral
stance
on
abortion.
This
transcendence
is
complimented
by
the
ease
with
which
Wilsons
students
reached
the
three,
dominant
theories
on
infanticide,
employing
nothing
more
than
the
power
of
thinking
on
the
basis
of
adaptation
and
natural
selection.
Further,
evolutionary
reasoning
demonstrates
the
hidden
functionality
of
troubling
social
problems:
The
picture
that
emerges
makes
sense
of
cases
of
infanticide
that
appear
periodically
in
the
news
(typically
young
women
with
few
166
resources
and
under
the
influence
of
a
male
partner
who
is
not
the
father)
and
that
previously
seemed
inexplicable.
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1004]
Like
the
lecturer
in
my
final
example,
Wilson
here
affirms
the
potential
in
evolutionary
reasoning
to
reveal
heretofore
inexplicable
truths
about
even
the
most
emotionally
charged
human
behaviors.
Though
he
risks
his
students
moral
outrage,
Wilson
boldly
introduces
a
taboo
topic
for
open
discussion.
To
be
sure,
this
act
is
subversive
in
contrast
to
a
presupposed,
politically
correct
representation
of
academic
lecturing.
Like
the
speakers
in
my
Examples
2b
and
2c,
Wilson
extends
his
contextualization
of
this
foregrounding
toward
an
ideology
less-readily
associated
with
Darwinian
theories
humanistic
science.
He
explains:
Including
humans
along
with
the
rest
of
life
vastly
increases
students
interest
in
evolution
and
acceptance
to
the
degree
that
it
seems
to
lead
to
understanding
and
improvement
of
the
human
condition.
[D.S.
Wilson
2005a:1004]
Posing
unpleasant
or
controversial
topics
to
his
class
is
a
necessary
step
toward
impressing
upon
students
the
rationality
and
the
humanistic
necessity
of
embracing
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundation
in
explanations
of
social
life.
This
combination
of
ugly
facts
and
hopeful
positivism
is
by
no
means
new.
It
is,
rather,
a
hallmark
of
arguments
in
favor
of
an
evolutionary
first
principle.
Numerous
examples
of
this
argument
could
be
trotted
out,
but
few
are
more
dramatic
or
explicit
than
Julian
Huxleys
comments
shortly
after
the
Darwin
Centennial
in
1959:
Looking
back,
we
see
that
evolving
man
has
lurched
from
one
crisis
to
another.
Great
empires
have
collapsed,
whole
civilizations
have
been
violently
destroyed;
thought
has
been
muzzled,
common
people
cruelly
exploited,
habitats
ruined
[]
If
we
fail
to
control
our
economic
system,
we
over-exploit
our
resources.
If
we
fail
to
prevent
167
atomic
war,
we
destroy
civilization.
If
we
fail
to
control
our
population,
we
destroy
our
habitat
and
our
culture.
However,
our
increasing
knowledge
is
indicating
how
we
might
remodel
our
psychosocial
organization
and
escape
from
the
apparent
impasse.
The
new
and
central
factor
in
the
present
situation
is
that
the
evolutionary
process,
in
the
person
of
mankind,
has
for
the
first
time
become
conscious
of
itself.
We
are
realizing
that
we
need
a
global
evolutionary
policy,
to
which
we
shall
have
to
adjust
our
economic
and
social
and
national
policies.
[Huxley
1963:20]
Despite
its
distinctly
Cold
War
rhetoric,
Huxleys
passage
poses
the
same
challenge
as
the
examples
I
offer
here,
which
he
frames
as
no
less
a
moral
imperative
for
his
audience.
Debates
over
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
are
rarely
characterized
by
what
one
might
call
intellectual
detachment.
This
same
sort
of
emotional
investment
is
evident
in
what
I
have
already
described
in
EvoS
lectures:
Some
speakers
charge
academic
institutions
with
ignoring
or
marginalizing
their
science.
Others
argue
an
urgent
need
to
embrace
evolutionary
reasoning
to
increase
human
happiness,
fight
social
injustice,
and
avoid
self-extinction.
There
is
a
sense
that
something
quite
personally
profound
is
at
stake
in
arguing
this
first
principle.
This
deeply
personal
something
appears
in
the
EvoS
Program
lectures
as
well,
which
I
explain
as
the
third
type
of
foregrounding
commonly
found
there.
3.
Introducing
Personal
Testimonies
EvoS
speakers
commonly
introduce
personal
testimonies
into
their
lectures,
offering
various
details
from
their
own
professional
and
private
live
a
third
type
of
foregrounding
regularly
appearing
in
my
data
set.
Employing
this
foregrounding,
speakers
creatively
index
the
same
in-house
ideologies
of
the
EvoS
Program
as
my
168
previously
described
foregrounding
types.
In
particular,
their
personal
testimonies
appeal
to
representations
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
unfairly
feared
by
critics
and
marginalized
to
non-human
academic
subjects.
To
contextualize
these
foregroundings,
speakers
again
reaffirm
the
explanatory
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
first
principle.
These
contextualizations
may
also
include
complicated
semiotic
processes
I
describe
in
Chapter
Two
(analogical
extension
and
reflexive
recursion),
through
which
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
is
put
to
some
surprising
uses.
On
the
violation
that
this
foregrounding
type
seems
to
require,
I
should
make
clear
(as
I
do
above)
that
university
lecturers
are
certainly
not
forbidden
from
detailing
personal
information
or
subjective
narratives
to
their
audiences.
Professors
might
relate
personal
stories
to
their
students
for
any
number
of
reasons:
to
demonstrate
some
conceptual
point
in
a
lesson,
attempting
to
humanize
their
classroom
persona,
or
simply
as
means
to
amuse
their
students
and
lighten
the
mood.
As
I
suggest
of
those
using
gratuitous
displays
or
taboo
topics,
a
lecturer
interjecting
personal
information
in
an
academic
lecture
will
likely
be
a
foregrounding
act.
That
is,
it
subverts
a
widespread
(if
stereotypical)
presupposition
of
lecture
settings
as
impersonal
and
serious.
When
professors
attempt
to
subvert
these
stereotypes,
their
actions
may
often
be
grounded
as
attempts
to
entertain,
inspire
student
participation
and
debate,
and
pose
(arguably)
interesting
examples
in
their
lectures.
Yet,
as
I
suggest
of
my
other
foregrounding
types,
the
lecturers
personal
testimonies
in
my
data
set
are
special
to
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
in
four
ways:
First,
169
they
appear
with
great
statistical
regularity,
developed
both
within
individual
lectures
and
across
the
whole.
Second,
like
the
other
foregrounding
types
I
observe
in
the
lectures,
these
personal
testimonies
regularly
index
combinations
of
the
in-
house
ideologies
I
describe
in
Chapter
Three.
Third,
speakers
regularly
contextualize
this
foregrounding
type
(like
the
others)
by
affirming
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundation
in
explanations
of
social
life.
Finally,
but
importantly,
these
lecturers
are
contextualizing
their
own
experiences
as
examples
of
the
personally
transformative
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
here
applied
to
make
sense
of
problematic
or
confusing
episodes
in
their
own
lives.
Example
3a:
And
I
saw
this
and
I
was
like
oh
my
god
he
got
it
all!
In
this
first
example,
a
visiting
lecturer
explains
to
the
audience
that
he
initially
began
studying
ethics
because
his
childhood
was
such
an
emotionally
explosive
period.
He
relates
that:
I
had
two
sisters
growing
up
and
that
we
fought
every
single
day
and
it
was
a
very,
very
passionate
kind
of
morality
The
speaker
here
introduces
a
piece
of
his
childhood
to
his
audience.
Such
intimate
details
are
not
forbidden
from
academic
lectures,
though
his
story
does
seem
to
be
an
uncommonly
personal
reason
for
pursuing
studies
in
ethical
philosophy.
This
kind
of
intimate
information
is
in
implicit
contrast
to
a
stereotypical
representation
of
academic
lectures
as
typically
impersonal
and
serious.
Next,
the
lecturer
makes
explicit
this
contrast
between
personal
convictions
to
institutional
austerity.
After
explaining
that
he
was
drawn
to
philosophy
and
170
ethics
because
of
his
emotionally-charged
childhood,
he
describes
his
disappointment
that
My
graduate
studies
in
ethics
were
very,
very
dry
and
very
cerebral,
with
no
bearing
at
all
on
my
own
experiences
The
ideology
he
indexes
here
has
appeared
in
similar
manifestations,
though
through
other
foregrounding
types.
As
in
previous
examples
(particular
those
attacking
academic
structure),
this
ideology
represents
academic
traditions
(broadly
conceived)
as
elitist,
conservative,
and
impersonal
a
critical
characterization
of
university
education
and
professions
as
an
Ivory
Tower.
This
conflict
between
the
speakers
personal
knowledge
and
his
academic
pursuits
persisted
until
he
encountered
the
first
chapter
of
Edward
Wilsons
Sociobiology:
A
New
Synthesis
(1975),
titled
The
Morality
of
the
Gene.
In
this
chapter,
the
speaker
was
introduced
to
a
new
perspective
on
ethics,
which
he
loosely
explains:
Humans
have
passionate,
emotional
reactions
to
everything
we
experience
we
have
these
brains
our
brains
give
us
these
emotions
and
these
emotions
are
adaptations
they
are
adaptations
to
the
lives
our
ancestors
used
to
lead
This
argument
resulted
in
a
kind
of
epiphany,
as
he
reports:
I
read
this
chapter
and
I
saw
this
and
I
was
like
oh
my
god
he
got
it
all!
Here,
the
lecturer
describes
his
elation
over
encountering
a
field
of
philosophy
that
more
closely
relates
to
the
very,
very
passionate
kind
of
morality
of
his
childhood.
Contextualizing
his
personal
testimony,
he
relates
an
intellectual
transformation
that
(for
him)
affirms
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
of
social
life
with
intuitive
truth-value.
Also
contextualized
is
his
previous
index
of
a
salient
171
EvoS
in-house
ideology,
which
juxtaposes
representations
of
an
impersonal,
elitist
academic
institution
to
the
diametrically
opposite
nature
of
evolutionary
reasoning
its
anti-elitism,
broad
applicability,
and
the
personal
revelations
one
might
experience
in
embracing
it
as
a
first
principle
(and
thus
getting
it
all).
Here
and
in
subsequent
examples,
I
point
out
that
a
rather
complicated
semiotic
process
takes
place
in
speakers
contextualizations
of
foregrounded
personal
testimonies,
wherein
evolutionary
reasoning
acquires
a
new
ideological
status
as
a
foundation
that
reflexively
explains
individuals
own
social
life
back
to
them.
On
a
final
note,
the
reader
no
doubt
sees
that
an
integral
part
of
the
speakers
personal
testimony
here
is
an
attack
on
academic
structure.
This
is
a
yet
another
overlap
of
indexical
signs,
essentially
one
foregrounding
within
another
foregrounding.
My
next
example
will
show
this
quality
as
well.
Example
3b:
Why
do
we
need
evolutionary
psychology?
Thats
what
we
have
biology
for!
In
this
second
example,
an
EvoS
lecturer
interjects
a
personal
narrative
into
his
lecture
on
evolutionary
psychology
and
neuroscience.
Like
Example
3a,
this
personal
testimony
overlaps
with
his
initially
lighthearted
attack
on
academic
structure,
which
becomes
more
explicit
and
cynical
as
he
proceeds.
The
speaker
begins
by
describing
his
current
teaching
position
and
the
complications
he
faces:
When
I
teach
evolutionary
psychology
the
students
sometimes
say
to
me
Well
why
do
we
need
evolutionary
psychology
thats
what
we
have
biology
for
and
after
my
heart
mends
from
its
breaking
I
describe
to
them
the
importance
of
using
the
evolutionary
approach
172
Here,
the
lecturer
voices
a
misunderstanding
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
expressed
by
his
students.
As
he
describes
it,
his
students
ignorance
is
understandable,
even
cute,
and
the
EvoS
audience
here
chuckles
at
the
heartbreak
that
their
confusion
causes
for
the
speaker.
Arguably,
their
skepticism
harkens
to
the
a
stereotypical
challenge
from
a
student
to
a
teacher
(When
are
we
going
to
need
this
in
real
life?)
However,
the
skepticism
he
reports
also
indexes
a
representation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
institutionally
misunderstood
and
marginalized
(considered
a
biological
rather
than
human
science).
In
this
way,
like
my
previous
example,
his
personal
testimony
overlaps
with
an
implicit
(though
soon-to-be
explicit)
attack
on
academic
structure.
As
he
continues,
it
becomes
clear
that
this
the
speakers
struggles
to
legitimate
his
convictions
against
skepticism
do
not
end
with
his
students:
Well
I
recently
submitted
a
paper
about
using
the
evolutionary
cognitive
neuroscience
approachand
one
of
the
reviewers
wrote
What
can
we
do
with
evolutionary
cognitive
neuroscience
in
fact
why
do
we
need
evolutionary
cognitive
neuroscience
at
all?
And
after
I
was
able
to
again
re-conceive
my
thoughts
and
mend
my
heart
The
professional
complications
within
this
speakers
testimony
have
now
shifted
from
his
students
to
an
institutional
source
with
real
influence.
The
referee
of
a
professional
journal
questions
the
legitimacy
of
his
field.
The
speaker
repeats
that
this
skepticism
caused
him
heartbreak
(at
which
his
audience
again
chuckles).
One
might
guess
that
the
speaker
is
about
to
rebut
this
referees
skepticism
as
he
did
he
previously
did
for
his
students.
Instead,
the
speaker
carries
this
skepticism
even
further:
173
And
I
thought
its
really
an
interesting
question
because
at
the
very
lowest
level
we
dont
need
an
evolutionary
cognitive
neuroscience
This
development
presents
an
interesting
and
certainly
more
complicated
twist
to
attacking
academic
structure
than
those
in
Examples
1a,
1b,
and
1c.
Here,
the
speaker
unexpectedly
agrees
with
the
institutional
skepticism
that
has
caused
him
heartbreak
twice
over.
Arguably,
he
could
not
have
done
this
without
overlapping
foregroundings
the
personal
narrative
foregrounds
(first)
his
students
skepticism,
(second)
a
journal
referees
skepticism,
and
finally
seems
to
foreground
this
speakers
own
capitulation
to
these
difficulties.
Instead
of
defending
evolutionary
reasoning,
he
gives
in
to
the
institution
that
doubts
its
worth
something
of
a
heresy
in
this
setting.
However,
as
it
turns
out,
his
capitulation
was
only
a
set-up
to
leverage
a
more
powerful
appeal
to
the
first
principle:
In
fact
it
should
all
be
evolutionary
like
psychology
for
example
should
be
evolutionary
just
because
it
is
a
biological
science
we
shouldnt
need
to
qualify!
The
speakers
contextualization
thus
turns
out
to
be
a
rather
crafty
reworking
of
his
skeptics
arguments.
Challenged
first
by
his
students,
then
by
an
academic
institution,
he
finally
concludes
that
his
critics
are
right,
though
certainly
not
in
the
way
they
intended.
The
skepticisms
are
groundless
that
contest
evolutionary
reasoning
in
one
discipline
or
another.
Scholars
shouldnt
need
to
qualify
whether
their
disciplines
are
evolutionary
-
they
are
evolutionary,
because
they
answer
to
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundation
(whether
acknowledged
or
not).
The
speakers
personal
testimony,
which
includes
two
embedded
attacks
on
academic
174
structure,
thus
ends
with
an
affirmation
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
a
foundation
underlying
all
other
modes
of
academic
inquiry.
Outside the remarks of the EvoS founder, it would be difficult to find a more
explicit
statement
of
the
programs
challenge
to
higher
education
than
this.
His
convictions
echoes
those
of
David
Sloan
Wilson,
such
as
his
argument
that
I
cite
in
Chapter
Three:
Evolutionary
theory
has
arrived
as
an
important
theoretical
framework
guiding
research
in
the
human
behavioral
sciences.
Any
college
or
university
that
fails
to
teach
evolution
in
relation
to
human
affairs
is
out
of
touch
with
current
scientific
research.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007b:4,
original
emphasis]
This
said,
the
speaker
contextualizes
his
personal
testimony
in
an
interesting
way:
Positing
that
it
should
all
be
evolutionary
and
we
shouldnt
need
to
qualify,
the
speaker
uses
the
inherent
trans-disciplinarity
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
console
and
defend
himself
after
facing
critics
skepticism
regarding
its
application
in
a
particular
field.
On
this
note,
like
Example
3a,
the
reflexive
recursion
of
the
first
principle
taking
shape.
This
speaker
comes
to
terms
with
his
professional
struggles,
reminding
himself
of
the
transcendent
(albeit
subversive)
knowledge
that
evolutionary
reasoning
imparts
to
those
who
embrace
it
as
a
foundation,
and
(conversely)
the
limited
understandings
of
those
who
do
not.
Example
3c:
Thats
the
kind
of
environment
we
had
in
evolutional
[sic]
times
In
my
first
example
(3a),
an
EvoS
lecturer
foregrounded
personal
information
about
his
childhood
in
order
to
index
a
representation
of
an
impersonal
academic
institution,
in
the
end
contextualizing
his
foregrounding
by
affirming
the
personally
175
transformative
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
In
my
second
example
(3b),
the
lecturer
introduced
a
similar,
though
more
complicated
set
of
overlapping
foregroundings
relating
a
personal
narrative
of
the
institutional
skepticisms
he
has
faced
as
an
evolutionary
scientist.
This
speaker
contextualized
his
foregrounded
testimony
(and
its
overlapping,
foregrounded
attacks
on
academic
structure)
by
affirming
evolutionary
reasoning
as
special
(transcendent)
knowledge
that
has
not
yet
been
embraced
in
higher
education.
This
speaker
my
third
example
delivers
a
lecture
dealing
with
collective
punishment
of
individual
offenses
against
group
welfare.
As
she
does,
she
relates
to
the
Seminar
Series
audience
a
story
of
her
participation
in
a
South
Pole
research
team:
My
husband
is
here
today
[she
gestures
to
a
man
in
the
front
row,
who
raises
his
hand]
He
just
retired
last
week
and
we
got
to
work
in
a
South
Pole
station
together
and
what
I
want
to
say
about
The
South
Pole
station
is
that
it
a
small
environment
we
had
thirty
people
or
so
per
station
and
of
course
there
always
was
one
person
per
section
who
was
extremely
obnoxious
Introducing
her
husband
and
some
details
of
their
co-employment
at
this
research
station,
the
speaker
shifts
her
talk
into
a
subjective
mode.
As
her
husband
raises
his
hand,
the
audience
chuckles
at
this
somewhat
unorthodox
maneuver
on
the
speakers
part.
As
she
continues,
the
speaker
describes
an
uncomfortable
confrontation
with
the
extremely
obnoxious
person
at
this
research
station:
I
remember
this
one
fellow
he
came
in
about
six
oclock
in
the
morning
I
was
just
finishing
off
a
shift
I
had
all
my
papers
all
spread
out
there
and
he
came
up
and
said
to
me
Youre
a
bitch
and
women
shouldnt
be
here
he
took
my
papers
threw
them
on
the
176
floor
broke
my
pencil
threw
it
on
the
floor
so
what
do
I
do?
I
threw
coffee
in
his
face
hot
coffee
At
this
point
in
her
story,
many
audience
members
gasp
or
laugh.
Her
personal
anecdote
has
taken
a
surprising
turn:
a
sexist
co-worker
violently
confronted
her
and
she
retaliated.
This
foregrounded
personal
narrative
now
overlaps
with
a
second
foregrounding
a
taboo
topicalization,
replete
with
prejudice,
aggression,
and
profanity.
The
audiences
reaction
suggests
that
this
foregrounding
has
(at
least)
succeeded
in
surprising
them
with
a
story
including
such
details.
Arguably,
this
foregrounding
works
because
it
violates
presuppositions
about
impersonal
academic
lectures
that
likely
would
not
include
such
entertaining
topics.
Whether
or
not
the
speakers
last
foregrounding
performed
this
indexical
function,
her
next
statement
clearly
introduces
information
that
would
be
uncommon
in
the
stereotypical
boring
lecture.
Gesturing
to
her
husband
in
the
front
row,
she
tells
what
happened
next:
So
later
that
night
-
someone
I
know
who
might
be
in
this
room
helped
gather
a
group
of
people
who
did
something
called
packing
and
what
packing
is
you
take
a
person
and
you
put
snow
into
various
orifices
and
its
very
intense
and
its
very
uncomfortable
And
Ive
got
to
say
this
he
never
troubled
me
again
in
any
way,
shape,
or
form
This
explanation
of
packing
draws
peals
of
laughter
from
her
audience.
The
speaker
has
introduced
an
unusual
punishment,
carried
out
by
her
fianc
and
his
colleagues,
which
involved
(one
infers)
stuffing
snow
into
this
mans
butt.
Her
third
foregrounding
overlaps
with
the
second,
presenting
similarly
shocking
retribution
for
the
extremely
obnoxious
persons
sexist
offense.
Further,
as
a
contributing
part
177
of
her
narrative,
this
foregrounding
is
like
the
one
previous
to
it
built
into
her
personal
recollection.
Finally,
the
speaker
contextualizes
these
overlapping
foregroundings
by
arguing
the
evolutionary
significance
of
her
experience.
She
proposes
that
Thats
the
kind
of
environment
we
had
in
evolutional
[sic]
times
we
lived
in
small
bands
of
thirty
or
so
people
if
someone
was
really
troublesome
you
either
put
him
in
his
place
by
things
like
packing
or
you
actually
took
him
off
and
-
pushed
him
off
the
edge
of
an
ice
flow
or
just
otherwise
got
rid
of
him
so
there
were
mechanisms
if
you
wanted
to
be
sly
or
vicious
you
couldnt
hide
very
well
if
you
werent
very
functional
or
very
altruistic
or
very
helpful
for
other
people
you
wouldnt
last
very
long
The
speaker
here
employs
evolutionary
reasoning
to
contextualize
her
foregroundings.
This
happens
in
two
ways:
First,
she
contextualizes
the
violence
of
her
second
and
third
foregroundings
as
explainable
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Her
recollection
unfolded
as
a
recapitulation
of
Homo
sapiens
evolutionary
ancestors
an
offender
within
the
speakers
small
band
was
punished
to
maintain
group
equilibrium.
Second,
the
speakers
initial
foregrounding
is
now
interpretable
as
a
personal
testimony
on
the
explanatory
power
of
the
evolutionary
reasoning.
While
she
might
have
simply
admired
her
husband
as
defending
her
honor,
evolutionary
reasoning
has
shown
her
that
his
actions
were,
in
fact,
examples
of
adaptive
group
behaviors,
first
exhibited
by
contemporary
humans
distant
ancestors.
The
speakers
testimony
also
indexes
some
unexpected
ideologies,
but
these
further
contextualize
her
foregrounding.
In
particular,
her
story
carries
an
undertone
of
chivalry.
In
this
sense,
her
testimony
is
also
a
relationship
story,
including
a
mans
act
of
bravery
to
protect
a
woman
from
violence.
As
the
audience
can
clearly
interpret,
this
story
results
in
the
couples
happy
life
together.
178
Example
3d:We
are
creatures
who
need
to
know.
In
this
fourth
example
of
personal
testimony,
a
Seminar
Series
speaker
describes
her
struggles
with
her
colleagues
in
the
Humanities.
The
resistance
her
associates
toward
biological
explanations
for
human
practices
is
a
source
of
continual
disagreement.
She
explains:
I
was
very
surprised
and
saddened
in
the
last
ten
years
to
find
that
some
very
good
friends
of
mine
often
intellectuals
very
smart
people
would
shrink
back
if
I
mentioned
the
possible
relevance
of
of
biology
to
something
they
were
raising
and
theyd
say
things
like
uh
Oh
we
dont
want
any
biological
reductionism
here
you
know
as
if
somehow
theyre
going
to
be
reduced
to
something
under
a
microscope
if
I
started
talking
that
way.
Like
my
previous
example,
this
foregrounding
embeds
an
attack
of
academic
structure,
developing
into
a
testimony
of
personal
and
professional
conflict.
The
speakers
friends
and
colleagues
misunderstand
and
fear
evolutionary
reasoning.
In
this
way,
her
complaint
about
their
positions
indexes
a
representation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
politicized
in
US
higher
education.
179
discrimination.
But,
this
speaker
argues,
those
uses
of
evolution
were
not
science,
but
were
in
fact
part
of
the
dodgy
history
of
ridiculous
things
said
that
claimed
to
be
scientific.
Closing her testimony, this lecturer underscores that she is not deterred by
180
fields
or
questions
it
leads
me
into
you
know
okay
you
know
Im
ready
In
defiance
to
the
skepticism
of
her
academic
friends
and
the
institutional
marginalization
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
she
tells
her
audience
that
she
will
courageously
proceed.
Fascinatingly,
in
contextualizing
her
personal
testimony,
the
speaker
poses
evolutionary
reasoning
as
an
explanation
for
her
own
actions:
And
actually
-
thats
one
part
of
our
evolved
human
nature
thats
really
interesting
to
think
about
is
that
we
are
creatures
who
need
to
know
even
when
it
seemingly
has
very
little
to
do
with
our
material
existence
or
capacities
for
reproduction
we
need
to
know
The
speakers
affirmation
of
a
first
principle
here
contextualizes
her
intellectual
struggles
and
quest
for
absolute
truths
as
itself
a
behavior
that
can
be
explained
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Doing
so,
she
presents
an
example
of
the
third,
semiotic
process
of
contextualization
that
I
describe
in
Chapter
Two
reflexive
recursion.
Referring
to
a
universal,
human
need
to
know,
she
legitimates
(and
valorizes)
her
own
struggles
against
marginalization
as
a
lived
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasonings
foundational
explanations
for
her
own
convictions.
Data
Summary
3:
Personal
Testimonies
Introduced
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
Lecture
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
#Attacks
#Taboos
14
#Testimonies
majority
(17
out
of
20,
or
85%)
of
the
Seminar
Series
lectures
in
my
data
set,
with
69
instances
total
at
an
average
of
4.1
per
lecture.
Further,
in
this
majority,
16
of
17
lectures
include
two
or
more
personal
testimonies.
This
statistical
frequency
181
demonstrates
the
commonality
of
this
brand
of
foregrounding
within
and
across
Seminar
Series
lectures.
Further,
like
the
examples
above,
personal
testimonies
typically
index
a
combination
of
ideologies
expressed
in
the
EvoS
Program.
More
often
than
not,
lecturers
contextualizations
of
their
personal
testimonies
reaffirm
the
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life.
182
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series.
To
be
sure,
the
personal
importance
that
these
speakers
attach
to
evolutionary
reasoning
is
by
no
means
exclusive
to
the
EvoS
Program.
In
one
of
the
more
celebrated
texts
of
human
evolutionary
science,
Darwinism
and
Human
Affairs,
Richard
Alexander
argues
that
evolutionary
reasoning
offers
the
means
to
both
progressive
social
change
and
personal
happiness:
It
does
this
by
telling
us
who
we
really
are
and
how
to
become
whatever
we
may
want
to
become.
Evolutionary
understanding,
then,
more
than
anything,
has
the
power
to
make
humans
sufficiently
plastic
to
accomplish
whatever
they
wish.
This
grandiose
notion,
of
course,
loses
all
its
glamour
if
there
is
any
doubt
at
all
about
the
centrality
of
evolutionary
theory
as
explanatory
of
human
nature.
From
my
personal
viewpoint,
however,
to
have
discovered
that
I
love
my
child,
not
because
it
shares
my
genes,
but
because
I
have
associated
with
it
in
certain
fashions,
and
to
discover
that
I
am
likely
to
prefer
my
own
child
to
an
adopted
one
like
it
solely
because
of
my
reproductive
history,
are
realizations
that
have
simultaneously
made
me
more
likely
to
adopt
a
child,
less
likely
to
reproduce
compulsively,
more
likely
to
reflect
in
a
calm
and
reasonable
fashion
over
tensions
associated
with
sexual
competition,
more
tolerant
of
others
in
connection
with
all
of
these
enterprises,
and,
I
believe,
more
likely
to
maintain
an
enjoyable
existence,
tolerable
to
others,
as
well
as
worthwhile
to
myself.
[Alexander
1979:277]
The
reflections
that
Alexander
provides
here
illustrate
a
similarly
recursive
application
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
self-knowledge
in
the
examples
from
my
data
set.
I
might
also
point
out
that
Alexanders
comments
speak
to
the
complex
sentiments
that
such
testimonies
tend
to
produce.
While
Alexander
clearly
takes
evolutionary
reasoning
as
the
foundation
in
explaining
human
social
life,
the
lessons
that
Darwinism
has
taught
him
have
led
him
(counter-intuitively)
to
higher
expectations
of
himself
and
greater
tolerance
of
others.
In
a
virtually
identical
fashion,
the
founder
of
the
EvoS
Program
also
employs
personal
testimonies
on
how
evolutionary
reasoning
has
empowered
him.
Truly,
it
183
might
be
argued
without
exaggeration,
that
Wilsons
(2007a)
Evolution
for
Everyone:
How
Darwins
Theory
Can
Change
the
Way
We
Think
About
Our
Lives
is
a
book-length
version
of
this
type
of
foregrounding.
Even
for
a
popular
science
publication,
it
is
remarkably
autobiographical,
particularly
in
describing
his
terse
relationship
with
his
own
father,
the
novelist
Sloan
Wilson.
The
younger
Wilson
describes
his
life,
spent
in
the
shadow
of
this
creative
giant.
For
many
years,
he
felt
unappreciated
and
misunderstood
as
a
person
drawn
to
science
who
is
also
the
son
of
an
artist,
in
a
family
of
literary
intellectuals.
Yet,
a
redemption
of
sorts
took
place
for
Wilson
in
the
1980s
and
1990s,
when
he
became
a
champion
of
group
selection
theory,
which
he
has
since
used
to
explain
numerous
human
social
practices.
He
explains:
One
reason
that
I
became
so
passionate
about
group
selection
was
because
it
so
clearly
related
to
the
human
condition,
in
addition
to
the
rest
of
life.
My
professors
and
peers
regarded
themselves
as
evolutionary
biologists.
They
respected
the
academic
convention
that
studying
humans
is
somehow
not
biology,
as
if
we
were
set
apart
from
the
rest
of
nature.
I
had
become
an
evolutionist,
perhaps
because
I
am
the
son
of
a
novelist.
For
me
it
was
an
unexpected
homecoming.
I
had
been
paddling
away
from
my
father,
but
now
I
had
returned
to
ponder
our
own
species,
just
like
him,
except
through
the
lens
of
evolutionary
theory
rather
than
the
lens
of
fictional
narrative.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:342]
Here,
and
throughout
his
book,
Wilson
builds
a
kind
of
extended
testimony
of
existential
struggle.
Like
lecturers
in
the
Seminar
Series,
this
foregrounding
indexes
ideologies
representing
his
pursuits
as
unjustly
feared
or
marginalized,
despite
their
populist
potential
and
applications
to
increase
human
happiness.
As
in
Wilsons
passage
(and
my
examples
above),
contextualizations
of
foregrounded
personal
testimonies
can
affirm
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundation
in
an
individuals
search
for
meaning.
For
example,
Wilson
describes
184
the
reaction
of
an
audience
member
to
a
lecture
he
delivered
on
how
evolutionary
theory
had
been
applied
by
agricultural
scientists
to
increase
egg
production.
In
this
lecture,
Wilson
explained
to
them
that
chickens
who
lay
the
most
eggs
are
often
those
that
have
achieved
their
success
by
suppressing
the
productivity
of
their
cagemates
(2005a:34)
continuously
pecking
the
hens
around
them,
sometimes
to
death.
Following
Wilsons
lecture,
he
reports:
a
professor
ran
up
to
me
and
exclaimed,
That
first
slide
describes
my
department!
I
have
names
for
those
three
chickens!
Evidently
her
department
had
adopted
a
policy
of
promoting
members
entirely
for
their
individual
accomplishments,
with
results
comparable
to
the
first
method
of
breeding
chickens
[]
Genetic
evolution
had
not
taken
place,
of
course,
but
something
had
taken
place
that
gave
comparable
results.
[DS
Wilson
2007a:35]
Like
my
previous
examples
(particularly
3a),
an
individuals
self-transformation
has
taken
place,
reported
here
by
Wilson
as
an
audience
members
excited
discovery
that
struggles
in
her
own
profession
matched
his
evolutionary
explanation
for
aggression
between
farm
chickens.
grounds
for
ones
self-identification,
as
(on
one
hand)
a
product
of
natural
selection
and
(on
the
other)
a
participant
in
a
movement
that
encourages
others
to
recognize
the
same
of
themselves.
Admiring
that
the
biodiversity
in
his
own
backyard
is
the
result
of
the
sculpting
action
of
natural
selection,
Wilson
writes:
Its
awesome
and
humbling
to
contemplate
that
we
are
the
product
of
that
same
sculpting
action,
not
only
our
bodies
but
also
our
minds
and
the
very
thoughts
that
run
through
our
minds.
I
sometimes
wonder
what
it
must
have
been
like
to
be
present
during
the
early
days
of
Darwins
theory,
when
the
idea
was
so
new
and
so
much
remained
to
be
discovered.
Then
I
realize
that
I
am
present
during
the
early
days
of
Darwins
theory.
The
intellectual
events
taking
place
right
now
are
as
foundational
as
the
events
of
150
years
ago.
How
amazing
that
185
virtually
everyone
can
partake
in
the
excitement,
as
an
observer
or
a
participant
[]
Evolutionary
theory
is
not
the
kind
of
belief
system
that
hurls
you
like
an
arrow
in
a
previously
chosen
direction.
It
is
more
like
a
sailboat
or
kayak
bobbing
by
the
shore,
inviting
you
to
take
your
own
voyage
of
discovery.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007a:348-349]
This
passage
obviously
includes
most
of
the
points
I
argue
above,
and
likely
requires
little
commentary.
To
Wilsons
thinking,
evolutionary
reasoning
has
the
potential
to
explain
not
only
our
bodies
but
also
our
minds
and
the
very
thoughts
that
run
through
our
minds
a
foundational
proposition
if
I
ever
saw
one.
His
emphatically
personal,
nearly
evangelical
tone
in
this
passage
(and
throughout
the
book)
is
indeed
signaling
his
genuine
astonishment
at
what
he
has
learned
about
himself
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
4.
Marked
modes
of
speaker
performance/audience
participation
186
ideologies,
and
ultimately
arriving
at
contextualizations
that
reaffirm
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life
sometimes
even
the
context-
at-hand.
and
audience
participation
are
not
exclusive
to
the
settings
in
my
data
set.
In
other
academic
lecturers,
speakers
may
oblige
their
audiences
to
participate
by
asking
questions,
taking
votes,
or
taking
volunteers
from
the
audience
to
illustrate
their
lecture
topics.
Academic
lecturing
may
also
include
unusual
speaker
performances,
breaking
the
fourth
wall
when
a
speaker
sits
with
audience
members,
roams
about
a
lecture
hall,
or
otherwise
violates
one
or
more
(typically
implicit)
rules
of
personal
space
and
lecturer-student
decorum.
As
I
suggest
in
Chapter
three,
for
several
decades,
U.S.
higher
education
has
become
increasingly
influenced
by
student-centered
pedagogical
strategies.
These
strategies
argue
for
greater
student
participation
(in-class
discussions,
real-time
demonstrations,
hands-on
learning,
etc.)
and
for
lecture
content
and
delivery
that
stimulates
students
attention
and
(arguably)
entertains
them.
The
rising
popularity
of
these
strategies
has
resulted,
conversely,
in
a
steady
critique
of
content-centered
or
teacher-centered
methods
as
antiquated,
boring,
and
ultimately
ineffective.
It
is
worth
noting
that
several
recent
articles
on
science
education
argue
that
these
strategies
are
necessary
to
increase
students
acceptance
of
evolutionary
theories
(Alters
2010;
Alters
and
Nelson
2002;
Brem
et
al
2003;
Griffith
and
Brem
2004;
Lord
and
Marino
1993;
Smith
2010a,
2010b;
D.S.
Wilson
2005a).
These
authors
encourage
student
participation,
group
discussions
in-class
demonstrations,
and
storytelling
as
means
187
to
shift
evolution
education
from
its
stereotypical
moorings
in
impersonal
science
toward
an
experience
that
is
(perhaps)
more
relevant
to
students.
188
delivers
this
knock.
Many
in
the
audience
laugh.
Stepping
back,
the
speaker
explains:
I
can
predict
with
pretty
good
accuracy
that
youre
going
to
start
acting
a
little
differently
as
a
consequence
because
Ive
damaged
that
part
of
your
brain
-
thats
a
brain
-
behavior
relationship.
And
cognitive
neuroscience
is
founded
on
understanding
the
brain-
behavior
relationship
in
its
very
basic
nature
Next,
the
speaker
elaborates
this
brain-behavior
relationship,
as
it
has
been
studied
in
people
with
brain
injuries
or
undergoing
neurosurgery:
People
who
had
lesions
in
particular
parts
of
the
brain
people
who
had
surgical
recessions
of
particular
parts
of
the
brain
people
who
had
their
corpus
callosum
cut
so
they
had
split
brain
procedures
acted
differently
but
in
many
cases
acted
similarly
to
other
people
who
had
similar
injuries
or
surgical
procedures
So
whats
come
from
cognitive
neuroscience
is
that
there
is
a
relationship
between
the
brain
Here,
the
speaker
interrupts
himself.
Rather
than
saying
and
behavior
(as
expected),
he
again
steps
toward
the
front
row
of
his
audience
and
strikes
them
with
a
hammer.
He
comments
that
If
I
hit
you
in
the
frontal
lobe
with
a
hammer
youre
gonna
act
differently
The
audience
again
chuckles
at
their
lecturers
gesture.
Again
stepping
back,
he
quips
to
the
audience
as
a
whole:
I
mean
if
you
dont
believe
me
then
see
me
after
the
lecture
and
well
do
an
experiment
But
I
would
hate
to
have
to
show
you
in
that
way
The
audience
laughs
more
at
this
remark.
As
their
laughing
subsides,
he
finishes
the
sentence
that
he
interrupted
to
hit
his
audience:
So
certainly
theres
a
relationship
between
the
brain
and
behavior
189
This
speaker
has
now
twice
struck
his
audience
with
an
imaginary
hammer
the
pantomimed
violence
of
these
two
foregroundings
akin
to
the
taboo
images
and
topics
I
discuss
above.
He
subsequently
comments
on
his
gestures,
jokingly
suggesting
that
any
doubters
in
his
audience
should
see
me
after
the
lecture
to
have
it
demonstrated
on
them
for
real,
although
he
would
hate
to
have
to
show
you
in
that
way.
He
continues:
But
what
people
have
been
ignoring
is
the
relationship
between
the
inherited
characteristics
and
how
they
are
organized
in
the
brain
Here,
the
speaker
contextualizes
his
previous
foregoundings
by
complaining
of
an
institutions
negligence
in
applying
evolutionary
reasoning
to
their
science.
He
asserts
that
We
need
to
think
about
what
are
the
genes
that
impact
behavior
and
the
brain
activation
that
drives
those
behaviors
and
theyre
the
genes
that
led
to
differences
among
species
and
not
just
in
this
case
this
is
pitted
as
the
gene
that
made
up
the
big
brained
Homo
sapiens
but
the
genes
that
made
the
coraciids34
pretty
darn
smart
in
the
bird
world
and
humans
pretty
darn
smart
in
the
primate
world
and
every
other
organism
uniquely
adapted
to
solve
problems
in
their
environment
The
speakers
unorthodox
performance
thus
arrives
at
a
familiar
conclusion,
affirming
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
brain-behavior
relationships.
Example
4b:
The
fact
that
youre
here
right
now.
In
this
example,
an
EvoS
lecturer
discusses
the
benefits
and
costs
faced
by
social
organisms,
such
as
bees,
ants,
and
mammals
such
as
elephants,
whales,
and
most
primate
species.
He
describes
humans,
in
particular
as
ultra-social
organisms:
34
190
Were
these
creatures
were
these
social
creatures
were
highly
interdependent
upon
one
another
and
our
ancestors
lived
in
highly
interdependent
cooperative
groups
gained
significant
survival
and
reproductive
advantages
over
those
who
maintained
more
solitary
independent
kind
of
lifestyles
over
time
and
humans
as
a
species
developed
a
strong
preference
for
social
life
and
people
talk
about
this
idea
under
the
label
of
ultra-sociality
Next,
continuing
his
explanation
of
ultra-sociality,
the
speaker
qualifies:
But
there
are
costs
to
social
living
as
well
in
fact
-
most
critters
are
not
social
animals
and
theyre
certainly
not
social
animals
in
the
way
that
were
social
animals
theres
a
reason
for
that
there
are
costs
to
ultra-sociality
just
based
on
mere
proximity
to
other
folks
At
this
point,
the
speaker
creates
his
first
foregrounding:
The
person
next
to
you
right
now
thisll
freak
you
out
the
person
next
to
you
right
now
at
any
moment
without
you
realizing
it
could
take
their
elbow
and
smash
it
into
your
face
At
this,
he
lifts
his
arm
and
violently
mimes
elbowing
an
imaginary
person
beside
him.
Chuckling,
he
quips
You
didnt
want
to
think
about
that
did
you?
But
thats
the
circumstance
that
you
put
yourself
in
as
a
social
creature
The
lecture
audience
lightly
laughs
at
this
comment.
The
speaker
here
points
to
an
audience
members
immediate
proximity
to
other
folks
as
evidence
that
the
costs
of
ultra-sociality
include
possible,
unprovoked
attacks.
He
then
elaborates
that
an
audience
members
situation-at-hand
(attending
a
lecture
in
the
company
of
strangers)
is
a
risky,
but
evolutionarily
explainable
circumstance
that
you
put
yourself
in
as
a
social
creature.
Insofar
as
he
attempts
to
freak
out
his
audience
and
remind
them
of
risks
that
they
didnt
want
to
think
about,
this
speakers
marked
performance
also
191
embeds
a
taboo
topic
as
a
further
foregrounding.
The
speaker
subsequently
builds
upon
this
foregrounding:
Or
contagious
disease
The
fact
that
youre
in
here
right
now
you
put
yourself
at
risk
for
catching
a
contagious
disease
from
the
other
people
here
Thus,
just
as
present
audience
members
risk
unanticipated
attacks
from
strangers,
their
evolved
tendencies
toward
ultra-social
behaviors
(for
example,
attending
EvoS
Seminar
Series
lectures)
also
threatens
them
with
contagious
disease.
In
this
way,
the
lecturers
foregrounding
reminds
his
audience
of
the
risks
involved
in
the
fact
that
youre
in
here
right
now
which
are
the
unexpected
side
effects
of
Homo
sapiens
adaptations.
To
this
end,
he
points
out
that:
If
you
were
a
solitary
creature
and
you
werent
just
hanging
around
with
other
human
beings
you
wouldnt
need
to
be
worrying
about
that
Beginning
with
a
marked
performance
(pantomiming
an
audience
member
attacking
another),
this
lecturer
further
introduces
two
taboo
topics
(vulnerability
to
violence
and
contagious
diseases).
While
these
taboo
topics
do
not
approach
the
shock-value
of
the
examples
of
my
second
foregrounding
type,
they
arguably
deviate
from
appropriate
behaviors
for
an
academic
lecture.
That
is,
on
one
hand,
this
speakers
foregrounding
relies
on
the
presupposed
seriousness
of
institutional
tradition,
which
he
violates
by
mentioning
uncomfortable
topics.
On
the
other
hand,
the
speaker
directs
these
taboo
topics
toward
personalizing
his
argument
for
audience
members.
complicated role in this speakers conclusion. It is not only being affirmed in this
192
example,
but
also
applied
to
creatively
contextualize
the
audience
itself
as
a
group
of
ultra-social
beings.
This
contextualization
may
be
interpreted
as
an
extension
of
the
lecturers
attempt
to
personalize
his
argument.
However,
in
further
examples,
I
will
show
that
the
first
principle
is
repeatedly
employed
to
reflexively
Darwinize
attending
Seminar
Series
audiences.
Example
4c:
Anyone
notice
something
that
I
did
to
a
lot
of
people
in
this
room
earlier?
In
this
third
example,
the
EvoS
speaker
obliges
his
audiences
participation
before
his
talk
even
begins.
For
around
20
minutes
prior,
as
attendees
enter
and
seat
themselves,
he
busily
circulates
around
the
lecture
hall,
introducing
himself
and
shaking
hands
with
nearly
everyone.
This
is
no
small
feat,
considering
an
audience
headcount
of
close
to
100
people.
His
lecture
begins
and
he
speaks
for
roughly
another
20
minutes.
Then,
the
he
abruptly
pauses,
asking
the
audience:
Anyone
notice
something
that
I
did
to
a
lot
of
people
in
this
room
earlier?
He
waits
for
a
response,
but
the
audience
remains
silent.
Raising
his
own
hand
in
a
handshaking
gesture,
he
reminds
them:
I
came
over
and
shook
[some
in
the
audience
chuckle
and
raise
their
own
hands]
your
hand
The
lecturer
then
explains:
Now
that
it
is
actually
proven
to
improve
participation
attendance
and
attention
of
people
in
a
classroom
in
experimental
studies
At
this
explanation,
some
members
of
the
audience
nod
or
grunt
approvingly.
This
speaker
has
here
introduced
a
rather
unusual
twist
into
his
lecture.
His
assertive
friendliness
before
the
lecture
was
certainly
unexpected.
Several
audience
193
members
(including
myself)
were
confused
by
his
actions.
Reminding
us
later
of
what
he
did
to
a
lot
of
people
in
the
room,
the
lecturer
informs
us
that
he
was,
applying
the
results
of
experimental
studies
to
stimulate
our
attention
and
participation.
In
this
sense,
his
surprising
performance
prior
to
the
lecture
has
obliged
our
(unwitting)
participation
in
a
real-time
recreation
of
past
studies.
However,
the
lecturer
has
not
yet
made
his
point
or
finished
engaging
his
audience.
He
qualifies
his
last
explanation:
But
we
have
informal
policies
such
as
school
districts
might
imply
All
teachers
and
staff
should
not
He
waits
for
his
audience,
apparently
expecting
them
to
fill
in
the
blank
of
these
informal
policies.
After
a
few
seconds,
several
people
in
the
audience
respond,
in
unison:
Touch.
The
lecturer
approvingly
echoes
their
answer:
Touch
the
children
Together,
he
and
the
audience
contrast
the
actions
encountered
within
this
setting
to
policies
in
public
schools
forbidding
those
same
actions.
The
former
actions
are
informed
by
science,
while
the
basis
of
the
latter
are
unclear
and
(likely)
not
grounded
on
science.
After
the
lecturer
and
his
audience
concede
on
this
informal
school
policy,
he
sighs
emphatically,
explaining:
Now
those
policies
are
impacting
the
fundamental
mechanisms
of
evolution
and
at
the
bottom
level
manipulating
our
perception
of
the
most
fundamental
issue
in
human
life
friend
or
foe
The
policies
of
public
schools
(unlike
the
actions
taking
place
inside
this
lecture)
are
not
just
neglectful
of
the
findings
of
science,
but
evolutionary
science.
With
his
audiences
help,
the
speaker
has
here
created
a
new
foregrounding,
which
is
akin
to
194
an
attack
on
academic
structure,
but
challenging
instead
the
absence
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
structure
of
primary
education.
Pursuing
this
issue
of
friend
or
foe,
the
lecturer
next
asks
his
audience:
What
is
the
principle
predator
of
human
beings
outside
of
single
cell
organisms?
Several
voices
in
the
audience
enthusiastically
respond:
Humans.
As
he
did
before,
the
lecturer
echoes
their
answer:
Humans
He
elaborates:
For
example
in
some
societies
we
have
anthropological
and
forensic
evidence
that
somewhere
between
four
to
forty
percent
of
adolescents
died
as
a
result
of
intra-species
conflict
also
called
homicide.
Now
you
notice
that
it
was
mostly
boys
they
took
the
women
off
and
the
girls
off
to
be
sex
slaves
they
killed
the
boys
With
the
audiences
assistance,
the
lecturer
here
crafts
yet
another
foregrounding.
After
they
correctly
identify
that
humans
prey
upon
each
other,
he
describes
a
gruesome,
prehistoric
scenario,
involving
the
sexual
enslavement
of
girls
and
women
and
slaughter
of
adolescent
boys.
Contextualizing
this
series
of
foregroundings,
the
lecture
poses
yet
another
question
to
his
audience:
Now
have
you
ever
noticed
that
boys
are
more
aggressive
toward
figures
of
authority?
The
audience
chuckles
at
this,
some
nodding
and
muttering,
Yes.
Finally,
the
lecturer
concludes
this
long
series
of
foregroundings,
asking:
Could
conduct
disorders
defiance
of
authority
be
an
evolutionary
mechanism
to
promote
survival
when
humans
in
authority
become
predatory?
[16:29-33]
Given
the
series
of
questions
and
responses
that
precede
it,
this
question
is
quite
obviously
hypothetical.
Neither
the
lecturer
nor
his
audience
comment
further.
195
The
lecturers
conclusion
is
a
clear
appeal
to
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life
the
unsurprising
resolution
of
this
complex
interaction.
To
reconstruct
his
argument
in
reverse:
Certain
boys
who
survived
prehistoric
mass
slaughters
because
they
distrusted
threatening
authority
figures.
Today,
boys
exhibit
this
inherited
trait
when
they
perceive
teachers
and
other
authority
figures
as
foes,
not
friends.
Boys
are
likely
to
perceive
authority
figures
as
foes
because
informal
school
policies
forbid
physical
contact
between
students
and
teachers.
If
school
policies
employed
evolutionary
reasoning,
these
boys
conduct
disorders
could
be
recognized
as
what
they
really
are:
manifestations
of
an
evolved
survival
strategy.
Schools
would
then
(arguably)
adopt
policies
that
encourage
physical
exchanges
between
teaches
and
students,
such
as
the
lecturer
performed
with
his
audience,
prior
to
his
talk.
Despite
its
complexity,
this
example
contains
the
same
elements
as
other
foregrounding
types.
Two
in-house
ideologies
are
indexed
that
are
common
to
the
EvoS
Program.
Respectively,
these
ideologies
represent
evolutionary
reasoning,
firstly
as
neglected
by
academic
institutions
(in
this
case,
public
schools),
and
secondly
as
tackling
various
politically
incorrect
topics
(mass
slaughter,
sexual
slavery)
from
which
its
institutional
opponents
shrink.
Further,
these
ideologies
are
contextualized
through
an
appeal
to
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
first
principle,
which
enters
this
speakers
argument
as
a
means
toward
educational
reform.
Most
importantly,
the
ideologies
and
first
principle
in
this
example
were
indexed
and
contextualized
in
a
joint
effort
by
the
lecturer
and
his
audience.
Beginning
with
the
lecturers
initial,
marked
performance,
a
series
of
(somewhat
leading)
questions
are
196
posed
and
answered,
attacks
are
leveled
at
institutions
and
taboo
topics
mentioned,
together
building
to
a
dramatic,
evolutionary
explanation
for
behaviors
occurring
both
outside
and
inside
this
very
lecture.
Example
4d:
Most
of
you
I
hope
had
a
quick
visceral
reaction.
In
this
fourth
example,
a
Seminar
Series
lecturer
engages
his
audience
in
a
series
of
tests
that
recreate
past
experiments
he
conducts
on
morals
and
emotional
responses.
These
tests
involve
introducing
various
gross
and
morally
confounding
scenarios
to
subjects
(and,
here,
the
lecture
audience)
and
recording
their
reactions.
Setting
up
his
foregroundings,
the
lecturer
tells
his
audience
that
he
hopes
to
convince
them
(though
he
will
likely
not
need
to
do
much
convincing
with
this
group)
that
their
immediate
responses
to
these
scenarios
reflect
a
set
of
universal
psychological
adaptations
the
results
of
selection
pressures
(such
as
contagious
disease
and
food
poisoning)
in
Homo
sapiens
evolutionary
history.
He
adds:
All
of
you
already
had
an
emotional
reaction
to
me
you
had
an
instant
first
impression
based
on
my
accent
based
on
my
appearance
based
on
whatever
I
said
first
so
first
impressions
are
really
important
whatever
your
initial
emotional
reactions
are
theyre
going
to
sort
of
tilt
you
toward
accepting
or
rejecting
whatever
it
is
that
I
have
to
say
Interestingly,
unlike
other
examples,
this
lecturer
introduces
his
foregroundings
by
explicitly
stating
that
he
wishes
to
convince
them
of
evolutionary
reasonings
worth
as
a
foundation.
Commenting
that
he
will
likely
not
need
to
do
much
convincing
for
some,
the
speaker
also
acknowledges
that
he
is
preaching
to
the
choir
by
making
this
argument
in
this
setting.
Many
in
the
audience
subsequently
chuckles
and
nods
at
this
side
comment.
197
Okay
so
a
family
sees
their
dog
run
over
in
the
street,
so
they
cut
it
up
and
serve
it
for
dinner
how
many
think
its
okay
and
how
many
think
it
is
not?
Many
in
the
audience
raise
their
hands
in
response
that
it
is
not
okay.
The
lecturer
comments,
Okay
so
dogs
are
much
safer
in
Binghamton
that
they
were
where
I
was
at.
The
audience
chuckles.
He
describes
one
test
subject,
disgusted
by
this
scenario:
He
said
Well
get
sick
get
sick
from
the
meat
and
I
said
No
you
wont
its
cooked
so
theres
no
bacteria
so
does
that
make
it
okay
and
he
said
oh
um
well
no!
A
second
story
he
tells
his
test
subjects
(and
the
lecture
audience):
Jennifer
is
a
morgue
technician
and
though
she
is
a
vegetarian
she
sees
an
opportunity
to
sample
the
flesh
of
an
unclaimed
corpse
while
she
prepares
it
for
cremation.
She
cooks
it
and
eats
it,
with
no
negative
consequences.
Is
this
is
right
or
wrong?
Many
audience
members
reply
wrong.
The
lecturer
comments
now
most
of
you
I
hope
had
a
quick
visceral
reaction
most
of
you
wouldnt
say
well
on
the
one
hand
The
audience
laughs,
and
he
continues:
Most
of
you
are
just
Whoa
thats
terrible
its
gross
its
horrible
Next,
the
lecturer
describes
a
third
experiment
in
which
he
and
his
adviser
stored
and
sterilized
a
cockroach
in
pure
alcohol
which
they
explained
to
test
subjects
then
dipped
the
cockroach
in
a
glass
of
apple
juice
and
asked
the
subjects
to
sip
from
the
glass.
Without
asking
for
an
audience
vote,
he
explains:
Most
people
say
no
why
not?
well
itll
make
me
sick
No
it
wont
its
totally
sterilized
there
are
no
germs
now
will
you
have
a
sip?
NO!
why
not
well
uh
uh
its
just
gross!
198
Finally
the
lecturer
describes
a
fourth
experiment,
inspired
by
an
episode
of
The
Simpsons
in
which
Bart
sells
his
soul
to
another
child
for
two
dollars:
We
wanted
to
model
that
situation
in
the
lab
and
we
gave
people
this
piece
of
paper
that
said
I
Joe
Smith
hereby
sell
my
soul
after
my
death
to
[this
lecturer]
for
the
sum
of
two
dollars
And
it
says
this
at
the
top
it
says
This
is
not
a
legally
binding
contract
and
we
said
Here
Ill
give
you
this
piece
of
paper
and
if
youll
sign
you
name
on
it
Ill
give
you
two
dollars
for
real
and
you
can
rip
up
the
paper
instantly
just
sign
it
and
rip
it
up
and
Ill
give
you
two
dollars
The
lecturer
puts
the
question
to
the
audience,
raise
your
hand
if
youd
sign
that
piece
of
paper
for
two
dollars.
Nearly
everyone
raises
their
hands,
and
thenlaughter
breaks
out
in
the
audience.
Seemingly
dejected
that
his
experiment
has
failed,
he
comments,
okay
so
I
guess
you
guys
hate
your
own
souls.
199
resolvable
through
evolutionary
reasoning
before
he
posed
them.
This
creative
structure
is
met
with
a
high
degree
of
audience
participation,
suggesting
that
the
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program
has
a
presupposition
of
the
lecture
that
is,
the
foundational
explanatory
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
a
proposition
for
which
the
speaker
will
likely
not
need
to
do
much
convincing.
It may not seem especially noteworthy that the EvoS Programs first
principle
has
here
shown
itself
to
be
a
presupposed
indexical
in
this
lecture.
One
could
imagine
that
this
first
principle
would
necessarily
inhabit
the
entirety
of
these
activities,
given
that
it
is
so
frequently
reaffirmed
through
the
foregrounding-
contextualization
patterns
that
I
detail
in
this
discussion.
While
this
is
likely,
I
wish
to
point
out
that
my
previous
examples
have
continuously
shown
the
first
principle
to
be
creatively
and
explicitly
indexed
as
the
relevant
resolution
to
previous
foregroundings.
In
this
case,
evolutionary
reasonings
foundational
status
is
casually
mentioned
and
set
aside
as
a
forgone
assumption
of
this
interpersonal
context.
Data
Summary
4:
Marked
Modes
of
Speaker
Performance/Audience
Participation
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Lectures
Lecture
#Attacks
#Taboos
#Testimonies
#Performances/
Participation
1
2
3
4
4
2
3
2
2
0
3
1
1
1
1
4
2
2
0
0
5
2
6
3
4
6
4
5
2
0
7
6
7
3
2
8
3
3
4
2
9
3
3
2
1
10
3
3
3
0
11
2
2
2
6
12
6
8
8
7
13
5
9
4
8
14
1
1
0
2
15
4
3
2
2
16
5
8
8
10
17
2
5
4
1
18
0
3
0
0
19
3
5
3
4
This type of foregrounding does not show the very high frequencies across
my
data
set
as
the
other
three
types.
Considering
the
complexity
involved
in
my
examples
above,
it
might
be
argued
that
this
type
still
shows
notable
statistical
regularity
across
lectures:
57
instances,
across
15
of
20
lectures
(75%),
at
an
20
4
14
4
3
200
average
of
3.8
per
lecture.
This
foregrounding
also
appears
more
than
once
within
single
lectures,
14
of
15
lectures
(93%).
Arguably,
these
relatively
lower
frequencies
are
due
to
the
lecturing
styles
of
individual
speakers
and
the
receptiveness
of
their
audiences.
The
kinds
of
elaborate
performances
and
participation
in
my
examples
above
are
rarely
seen
in
academic
seminars,
in
which
visiting
speakers
deliver
talks
to
audiences
they
have
typically
never
met
and
will
likely
never
lecture
to,
again.
Further,
as
Data
Summary
4
details,
there
are
remarkably
high
frequencies
in
certain
lectures,
suggesting
that
these
speakers
were
more
comfortable
or
practiced
than
others
with
delivering
performances
and
encouraging
participation.
foregroundings
of
other
types,
such
as
the
sets
of
taboo
topics
in
Examples
4b
and
4d.
As
these
foregroundings
build
upon
each
other,
the
repeated
instances
of
speaker
performance
and
audience
participation
are
similarly
building
into
setting-
specific
parallelisms.
As
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Two,
these
patterned
rituals
of
language
use
possess
great
potential
to
grab
and
hold
participants
attention
and
direct
it
toward
a
possible
conclusion.
In
my
interviews
with
participants,
these
instances
were
variously
described
as
fun
or
exciting
as
well
as
another
example
of
how
EvoS
pushes
the
envelope.
Conversely,
those
lecturers
who
did
not
perform
or
oblige
audience
participation
my
respondents
overwhelming
judged
as
delivering
the
boring
talks
in
the
Seminar
Series.
201
poses
that,
by
attending
his
lecture,
audience
members
are
vulnerable
to
the
risks
inherent
to
their
evolutionary
status
as
social
animals.
The
lecturer
in
Example
4c
explains
that
he
took
time
to
shake
everyones
hands
because
this
practice
recreates
a
conclusion
from
evolutionary
science
regarding
students
perceptions
of
friend
or
foe.
Fascinatingly,
these
contextualizations
attempt
to
Darwinize
the
interaction-
at-hand
in
ways
that
echo
my
earlier
examples,
such
as
the
speaker
in
Example
C4,
who
explains
her
intellectual
inquiries
into
human
evolution
as
part
of
our
evolved
human
nature,
that
we
are
creatures
who
need
to
know.
That
speaker
contextualizes
her
personal
testimony
as
an
example
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
action.
The
role
of
the
first
evolutionary
reasoning
in
this
fourth
type
of
foregrounding-contextualization
is
similar,
but
projected
onto
the
audience
as
an
evolutionary
explanation
for
their
participation
in
the
lecture,
itself.
202
lessons
in
Darwinian
theory:
More
Offspring
Than
Survive
Survival
of
the
Fittest
and
Heritable
Variation.
Students
assume
one
of
24
unique
postures
in
the
initial
round
of
each
lesson,
and
then
(in
the
following
rounds)
perform
the
effects
of
differential
rates
of
survival
and
reproduction,
natural
selection,
and
subsequent
generations
inheritance
of
the
beneficial
adaptations
of
their
ancestors.
Elsewhere,
several
EvoS
contributors
propose
that
evolutionary
education
programs
(such
as
EvoS,
itself)
should
not
be
constrained
to
classrooms,
but
could
be
complemented
by
a
fitness
and
nutrition
course
that
is
similarly
informed
by
evolutionary
reasoning.
Such
a
course
would
be,
the
authors
argue,
a
carefully
prescribed
physical
fitness
and
nutrition
regimen
that,
based
on
what
we
can
surmise
from
anthropology,
psychology,
biology,
physiology,
exercise
science,
and
sports
psychology,
approximates
what
our
ancestors
faced
on
a
daily
basis
and
modern
hunter
gatherer
groups
undergo
daily.
This
physical
fitness
and
nutrition
program,
which
we
are
tentatively
calling
EvoT
(pronounced
evo-tee;
Evolutionary
Training),
makes
use
of
three
basic
principles
to
aid
education
about
evolution
while
simultaneously
increasing
student
physical
health
and
fitness.
First,
the
students
are
exposed
to
evolutionarily
inspired
physical
fitness
programming
[]
Second,
students
are
exposed
to
the
Paleolithic
diet
(http://www.
thepaleodiet.com/),
which
is
our
best
estimation
of
what
our
ancestors
subsided
on.
And
third,
students
will
be
taught
why
this
particular
exercise
and
nutrition
program
works
to
aid
their
weight
loss,
muscular
development,
general
physical
fitness
and
preparedness,
athletic
performance,
mental
acuity,
and
psychological
well-being.
[Platek
et
al.
2011:42-43]
The
EvoT
proposal
bears
similarities
to
the
EvoS
Lifestyle
Project
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Three,
although
an
interesting
difference
is
the
formers
assertion
that
EvoT
is
a
way
of
a
means
of
helping
students
learn
about
evolution
and
how
it
can
be
used
to
increase
their
own
quality
of
life
(Platek
et
al.
2011:41).
203
204
It
is
important
to
note
that
his
argument
attempts
to
contextualize
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Encountering
educational
strategies
based
on
evolutionary
theories,
Wilson
posits
that
his
own
program
(one
dealing
with
evolutionary
theories)
is
already
modeling
these
educational
strategies.
While
argued
at
a
more
ambitious
scale,
this
is
a
similar
process
of
reflective
recursion
as
I
identify
in
Examples
3d,
4b,
and
4c.
In
later
chapters,
I
will
examine
how
Wilson
and
other
EvoS
participants
attempt
to
further
explain
and
promote
the
programs
activities
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
My
data
set
and
fieldwork
presents
sufficient
evidence
for
me
to
make
six,
interrelated
observations:
First,
the
foregroundings
occurring
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
lectures
regularly
appear
as
these
four
types.
Second,
EvoS
speakers
employ
these
foregroundings
to
draw
their
audiences
attention
lodging
critical
attacks,
introducing
gratuitous
or
taboo
material,
offering
personal
narratives,
and
obliging
their
audiences
to
participate
in
more
or
less
elaborate
ways.
Third,
participants
in
these
lecturers
recognize
and
report
upon
the
foregroundings
in
predictable
ways
(for
example,
as
shocking,
confusing,
or
humorous).
Fourth,
these
foregroundings
regularly
index
the
in-house
ideologies
and
first
principle
the
EvoS
Program
into
the
situation-at-hand,
thus
contextualizing
the
lecture
as,
in
part,
sharing
the
programs
goals
and
beliefs.
Fifth,
these
contextualizations
tend
to
perform
further
kinds
of
ideological
labor
for
participants:
abstractions
that
represent
higher
education
as
opposing
groups
of
intellectuals
(for
or
against
evolutionary
reasoning),
analogical
extensions
that
tie
evolutionary
reasoning
to
various
other
socio-political
concerns
(such
as
public
health
or
civil
rights),
and
reflexive
recursions
that
encourage
205
audiences
to
consider
elements
of
their
own
lives
(including
their
participation
in
the
context-at-hand)
as
foundationally
explainable
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Finally,
and
most
importantly,
the
unique
iterations
of
these
foregrounding-
contextualization
patterns
sometimes
involve
complexly
creative
structures.
In
many
cases,
these
appear
as
inside
jokes
to
an
audience
who
is
likely
amiable
to
suggestions
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
a
foundational
explanation
for
all
social
life.
In
this
sense,
considering
the
interplay
of
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals
that
make
up
every
one
of
these
patterns,
I
find
evidence
that
the
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program
does
not
need
to
be
explicitly
stated,
as
it
is
presupposed
within
these
interpersonal
contexts
(see
Auer
1996;
Silverstein
1992).
Lectures
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
offer
a
partial
answer
to
my
broader
research
question:
How
do
social
movements
index
their
core
ideologies
into
interpersonal
activities,
thus
maintaining
the
movements
message
over
time
and
spreading
into
new
social
settings?
As
this
case
study
suggests,
movement
leaders
and
other
speakers
create
various
kinds
of
foregroundings
to
enrage,
shock,
amuse,
or
inspire
other
participants.
These
foregroundings
typically
index
the
core
ideologies
of
the
movement
as
the
relevant
meanings
necessary
to
make
sense
of
the
foregrounding.
Through
repetition
and
increasingly
complex
combinations,
the
movements
ideologies
may
come
to
define
the
very
settings
and
activities
in
which
they
are
indexed.
By
employing
similar
kinds
of
foregroundings
over
time
and
in
novel
settings,
the
social
movement
may,
in
this
sense,
endure
and
spread.
206
In
Chapters
Five
and
Six,
I
will
analyze
how
the
EvoS
Programs
ideologies
and
first
principle
are
indexed
within
the
activities
following
the
Seminar
Series
lectures.
207
Chapter
Five:
Criticism
and
Modes
of
Defense
in
The
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
In
this
chapter,
I
turn
my
analysis
toward
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
that
follow
most
Seminar
Series
lectures,
focusing
particularly
on
the
ways
that
EvoS
participants
respond
to
audience
criticisms.
While
these
sessions
are
significantly
shorter
than
the
Seminar
Series
lectures
(typically
around
ten
minutes)
and
sometimes
do
not
take
place
at
all
(as
I
explain
below),
they
are
important
for
my
discussion
for
three
reasons:
First,
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
include
further
examples
of
the
foregroundings
and
contextualizations
that
I
detail
in
my
previous
chapter.
To
this
end,
they
can
be
viewed
as
a
pattern
that
seems
to
appear
in
numerous
interpersonal
settings,
throughout
the
EvoS
Programs
activities.
Second,
these
sessions
demonstrate
what
transpires
when
the
programs
first
principle
and
in-house
ideologies
are
directly
challenged.
The
modes
of
defense
that
I
discuss
here
will
show
that
program
participants
rarely
take
on
a
critics
challenge
directly,
but
do
so
in
observably
similar
ways
across
different
sessions.
Finally,
I
argue
that
the
critics
attending
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
are
yet
another
resource
that
is
harnessed
by
this
movement
(albeit
an
often
unpredictable
one).
By
engaging
critics
of
their
ideologies
and
first
principle
in
strategic
ways,
EvoS
participants
are
able
to
further
index
and
contextualize
these
same
ideologies
and
first
principle
in
fashions
that
would
likely
not
be
possible,
had
they
not
been
explicitly
challenged.
208
1.
Time
Limits
and
Moderation
It
should
first
be
observed
that
these
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
are
(like
the
Seminar
Series
lectures)
fulfilling
general
expectations
of
higher
education.
That
is,
whether
delivered
by
visiting
speakers
or
residents,
academic
seminars
will
typically
conclude
with
questions
from
the
lecture
audience.
Though
this
practice
is
not
always
followed
(in
EvoS
or
other
academic
contexts),
the
Q
&
A
can
be
said
to
be
an
anticipated
epilogue
to
any
university
seminar.
Generally,
such
sessions
proceed
with
little
explicit
direction:
Audience
members
raise
their
hands
before
speaking
and
those
raising
their
hands
are
responded
to
in
the
order
that
their
hands
went
up.
Further,
audience
members
address
their
questions
to
the
lecturer,
and
the
lecturer
addresses
his
or
her
response
to
the
questioner,
as
well
as
the
audience
as
a
whole.
However,
the
EvoS
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
differ
notably
from
other
academic
seminars
in
three
important
ways:
First,
the
audience
comments
in
the
question
and
answer
are
limited
to
individuals
not
enrolled
in
the
Current
Topics
class.
Because
Current
Topics
students
will
be
able
(in
fact,
obliged)
to
contribute
to
the
subsequent
Social
Event
discussion,
an
EvoS
organizer
expressly
dissuades
them
from
posing
questions
in
this
setting.
Second,
EvoS
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
are
notable
because
the
lecturer,
organizers,
and
a
large
portion
of
the
audience
are
obliged
to
leave
five
to
ten
minutes
after
the
lecture.
A
program
organizer
will
typically
remind
all
in
attendance
that
they
will
shortly
walk
to
the
Social
Event
at
another
location
on
campus,
for
dinner
and
continued
discussion.
Typically,
the
209
organizer
includes
with
this
a
general
invitation
to
the
entire
audience
to
join
them.
Finally,
in
conducting
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions,
it
is
common
for
the
EvoS
organizer
to
act
as
moderator,
selecting
among
the
raised
hands
in
the
audience,
the
order
in
which
these
persons
may
speak,
and
announcing
when
the
question
and
answer
session
is
over.
Further,
the
moderator
may
add
responses
to
those
of
the
lecturer
or,
in
some
events,
responding
in
place
of
the
lecturer.
Though
the
EvoS
organizers
may
not
have
intended
them
as
such,
the
results
of
this
situation
are
rather
predictable:
Due
to
the
instructions
of
the
EvoS
organizer,
many
questions
come
from
persons
who
do
not
often
(or
ever)
attend
EvoS
events.
These
individuals
often
represent
disciplines
addressed
(and
attacked)
in
the
preceding
lecture,
and
their
comments
are
frequently
critical
of
the
lecturers
representation
of
that
discipline,
as
well
as
proposals
that
evolutionary
reasoning
should
be
embraced
as
the
foundational
principle
in
their
professions
and
research.
Further,
the
time
constraints
of
the
Question
and
Answer
Session
affect
the
general
tenor
of
the
setting.
Both
questions
and
responses
are
rushed,
and
there
is
rarely
time
for
audience
members
to
ask
follow-up
questions.
The
noise
level
of
the
setting
rises
as
well.
The
audience
is
composed
largely
of
students
in
the
Current
Topics
course,
who
have
been
asked
to
wait
while
other
audience
members
to
engage
the
speaker.
Many
of
these
students
grow
impatient,
and
the
lecture
hall
echoes
with
the
sounds
of
dozens
of
people
whispering,
shuffling
papers,
zipping
bags,
checking
cell
phones,
and
so
on.
Few
seem
to
pay
attention
to
the
questions
others
ask,
and
they
do
not
ask
questions
themselves
(as
they
have
been
instructed).
210
The EvoS organizers moderation of Question and Answer Sessions not only
reinforce
these
time
constraints,
but
also
presents
a
situation
in
which
audience
members
may
find
themselves
talking
not
just
with
lecturers,
but
representatives
of
the
EvoS
Program
as
well.
As
I
remark
above,
the
moderator
may
respond
in
addition
to
or
in
the
place
of
a
visiting
lecturer.
Also,
many
visiting
speakers
were
previously
introduced
as
colleagues
who
are
aligned
with
the
goals
of
the
EvoS
Program,
and
most
index
the
in-house
ideologies
and
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program
during
their
lectures.
To
this
end,
the
EvoS
Question
and
Answer
sessions
are
marked
by
a
palpable
tension,
such
that
an
individuals
criticisms
of
a
lecturers
argument
are
(to
a
greater
or
lesser
degree)
also
criticisms
of
the
program.
2.
Critics
in
the
EvoS
Audience
It is not my intention to paint the Question and Answer Sessions that follow
Seminar
Series
lectures
as
all-out
arguments
between
non-EvoS
members
and
the
lecturers.
Many
genuine
compliments
and
non-critical
questions
come
from
attendees
at
these
activities,
as
expected
in
any
academic
seminar.
On
the
other
hand,
the
first
principle
of
the
EvoS
Program
must
be
recognized
for
what
it
is:
a
challenge
to
the
structure
and
values
of
the
institution
within
which
it
operates.
As
I
have
suggested
this
challenge
is
posed
primarily
toward
the
Humanities
and
Social
Sciences.
Given
the
topics
often
covered
in
Seminar
Series
lectures,
there
are
likely
to
be
many
representatives
from
these
academic
spheres
in
any
EvoS
audience
(professors,
graduate
students,
and
undergraduates).
Further,
since
not
everyone
in
a
Seminar
Series
audience
is
an
EvoS
participant
or
familiar
with
the
types
of
211
foregroundings
that
regularly
appear
in
the
series
lectures,
it
is
not
surprising
that
there
will
be
some
who
remain
unconvinced
by
lecturers
arguments
and
perhaps
even
upset
with
the
socio-political
implications
they
see
there.
Given
the
kinds
of
directives
and
time
constraints
that
EvoS
organizers
have
placed
upon
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions,
it
would
seem
almost
inevitable
that
the
most
intent
persons
will
pose
challenges
to
the
lecturers.
(professors
and
graduate
students
from
the
Social
and
Biological
Sciences,
primarily)
are
dissatisfied
with
the
EvoS
Program,
but
regularly
attend
Seminar
Series
lectures
because
of
their
interests
in
evolutionary
science.
Though
they
are
often
dissatisfied
with
the
arguments
of
EvoS
lecturers,
these
persons
have
told
me
in
interviews
that
they
are
committed
to
the
programs
survival.
Often
times,
these
same
individuals
will
link
their
commitment
to
EvoS
with
concerns
about
spreading
creationist
and
Intelligent
Design
movements
in
the
United
States.
Unsurprisingly,
given
their
investment
in
the
explanatory
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
these
persons
have
often
not
been
shy
about
raising
their
objections
in
the
EvoS
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
Other
audience
members
are
less
interested
in
evolutionary
science,
but
attend
the
Seminar
Series
somewhat
regularly
because
they
have
been
persuaded
to
do
so.
During
my
fieldwork,
I
learned
that
some
graduate
students
and
professors
(most
in
the
Humanities)
began
jokingly
calling
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
The
Church.
From
further
interviews,
I
was
told
that
these
individuals
felt
obliged
to
attend
what
they
perceived
to
be
a
ritualistic
worship
at
the
feet
of
Darwin
(as
one
212
grad
student
put
it).
Several
of
my
interviewees
complained
that
the
EvoS
organizers
and
lecturers
were
obsessive
or
single-minded
regarding
evolutionary
reasoning.
Typically,
their
motivations
for
attending
the
Seminar
Series
stemmed
from
their
colleagues
participation
fellow
graduate
students
or
professors,
advisors,
and
sometimes
their
undergraduate
students
would
persuade
them
to
go
(though
they
often
left
with
many
misgivings).
For
example,
two
of
my
interviewees
discussed
a
recent
Seminar
Series
lecture
(which
one
had
attended
but
the
other
had
not).
When
the
interviewee
who
attended
the
lecture
said
That
was
the
worst
EvoS
Ive
ever
been
to,
the
other
responded,
Everyone
I
know
always
says
that
the
last
EvoS
was
the
worst
EvoS
theyve
ever
been
to.
These
individuals
would
occasionally
raise
criticisms
in
the
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer,
but
their
disenchantments
were
largely
expressed
outside
EvoS
activities.
Other individuals attend only a few or one Seminar Series lecture, likely
213
the
sexual
tensions
between
its
characters.
Incensed
by
this
argument,
she
did
not
return
to
the
Seminar
Series
again.
Though
the
organizers
of
EvoS
almost
certainly
did
not
intend
this
situation,
those
who
choose
to
raise
criticisms
in
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
are
put
into
a
rather
compromised
situation.
In
this
setting,
the
time
constraint
and
audience
impatience
will
likely
limit
or
interrupt
a
subsequent
exchange
with
the
lecturer.
If
they
wish
to
challenge
a
speakers
assumptions,
methods,
or
conclusions,
audience
members
are
offered
two,
unsatisfactory
options:
On
one
hand,
they
may
pose
their
question
in
this
setting,
where
it
will
likely
be
cursorily
addressed
by
the
speaker
and
ignored
or
resented
by
the
majority
of
the
audience.
On
the
other
hand,
they
may
hold
their
questions
and
join
the
throng
of
people
walking
to
the
Social
Event,
a
90-minute
to
two-hour
commitment
including
dinner
and
discussion.
While
the
EvoS
organizers
typically
invite
any
and
all
audience
members
to
the
Social
Event,
they
also
seem
unaware
that
this
might
be
inconvenient
or
unreasonable
for
persons
not
involved
in
the
Program.
In
my
interviews,
when
asked
why
they
were
not
attending
the
following
Social
Event,
persons
in
the
lecture
audience
typically
responded
that
they
could
not
spare
the
time.
Another
suggested
that
the
practice
itself
was
weird
and
scary,
and
still
another
complained
that
he
would
feel
out
of
place.
Further,
these
audience
members
were
often
annoyed
by
the
lecture
topic
and
its
delivery,
and
so
not
attracted
to
the
possibility
of
casual
dining
and
conversation
with
the
speaker.
For
example,
when
I
asked
one
audience
member
why
he
would
not
be
attending
the
Social
Event,
he
explained
I
cant
stand
listening
to
that
asshole
talk
for
another
hour.
214
3.
Modes
of
Defense
Against
Audience
Critiques
EvoS
lecturers
often
respond
by
dismissing
the
criticism
and,
in
one
way
or
another,
dismissing
the
person
who
poses
it.
This
type
of
response
may
take
a
variety
of
forms
for
example,
joking
or
teasing.
The
audience
member
is
typically
pointed
out
as
unreasonably
skeptical
toward
the
lecturers
argument
and
the
EvoS
Program.
In
this
sense,
dismissing
audience
criticism
also
indexes
(sometimes
explicitly)
in-
house
ideologies
juxtaposing
the
EvoS
Program
to
the
elitism
and
conservatism
of
215
the
academic
institution,
stereotyping
the
audience
member
as
a
representative
of
the
latter.
Dismissal
Example
1:
He
and
I
go
a
long
way
back.
In
this
example,
an
audience
member
(known
to
many
EvoS
participants
as
a
skeptic)
challenges
a
lecturers
evolutionary
explanation
of
religious
belief
systems.
Calling
on
this
audience
member,
the
EvoS
moderator
admonishes
him:
Okay
I
see
a
couple
more
hands
and
I
dont
want
to
stop
the
conversation
so
just
make
it
quick
thats
all
I
have
to
say
to
you
and
then
we
can
have
the
next
person.
Knowing
that
this
individuals
comment
will
likely
be
deeply
skeptical,
many
in
the
audience
chuckle
lightly
at
this
warning.
As
the
laugher
subsides,
this
audience
member
comments:
Well
I
was
going
to
say
speaking
of
belief
systems
your
ultimate
category
has
essentially
to
do
with
function
and
function
as
it
plays
out
and
this
one
could
assert
is
a
dominant
almost
religious
view
of
our
western
civilization
and
this
is
bleeding
into
your
work
as
a
belief
phenomenon
While
politely
stated
(considering
the
moderators
warning),
the
audience
members
criticism
poses
quite
a
serious
problem
for
an
evolutionary
explanation
of
religious
belief.
Specifically,
he
asserts
that
functionalist
methodology
an
almost
ubiquitous
element
in
evolutionary
reasoning
is
an
ideology
that
is
revered
with
near-religious
conviction
in
the
history
of
Western
science.
In
this
sense,
the
audience
member
charges
that
the
speaker
has
used
one
religion
to
explain
all
others.
The
visiting
lecturer
is
observably
confused
by
the
interaction
between
the
audience
member
and
the
EvoS
moderator.
There
is
a
tense
silence
for
several
seconds,
after
which
the
lecturer
turns
to
the
moderator
and
asks
for
assistance:
216
Okay
do
you
want
to
comment
on
that
one?
The
EvoS
moderator
chuckles:
Oh
No
he
and
I
go
a
long
way
back
After
a
moment,
the
moderator
turns
the
lecturer,
asking
him:
Would
you
like
to
comment
on
that
one?
The
lecturer
considers
and
declines:
Uh
perhaps
not
if
were
running
out
of
time
The
EvoS
moderator
then
moves
on
to
another
audience
question,
commenting:
Quite
plainly,
this
individuals
criticism
has
been
dismissed,
seemingly
owing
to
both
his
history
as
a
perennial
skeptic
and
the
time
constraints
of
the
Question
and
Answer
Session.
While
the
lecturer
appears
confused
by
the
EvoS
moderators
warning
and
reaction
to
the
audience
member,
the
moderators
explanation
that
he
and
I
go
a
long
way
back
partially
resolves
this
confusion
that
is,
dismissing
this
audience
members
criticism
is
acceptable.
Citing
his
concern
for
the
time
schedule,
the
visiting
lecturer
opts
out
as
well.
academic
lecture
asking
them
to
account
for
issues
outside
their
arguments
or
address
the
concerns
of
disciplines
quite
outside
their
own
expertise.
Some
may
also
pose
these
same
sorts
of
trying
criticisms
to
at
multiple
lectures,
leading
moderators
to
dismiss
their
questions.
However,
what
transpires
here
in
this
EvoS
Question
and
Answer
Session
is
a
combination
of
factors
that
distinguish
the
Seminar
Series
from
other
academic
lectures.
This
audience
members
criticism
is
dismissed
as
a
result
of
217
the
sessions
time
constraints
and
moderation
by
an
EvoS
organizer
whose
professional
history
with
this
individual
marks
the
latter
as
a
nuisance.
The
audience
members
criticism
is
a
particularly
challenging
sort
for
the
EvoS
Program.
This
challenge
in
essence
suggests
that
evolutionary
analyses
of
human
practices
and
ideologies
uncritically
accept
their
own
practices
and
ideologies
as
those
most
suited
to
explain
all
others.
In
this
way,
the
audience
members
criticism
echoes
those
of
my
interviewees
who
refer
to
EvoS
as
The
Church.
A
similar
challenge
is
posed
in
my
next
example,
with
a
similar
(if
less
one-
sided)
outcome.
Dismissal
Example
2:
Well
let
me
turn
the
argument
back
on
you.
In
this
example,
a
member
of
the
audience
criticizes
an
EvoS
speakers
arguments
about
supernatural
phenomena,
which
the
speaker
proposes
are
descriptions
of
empirical
reality
without
evidential
support,
but
nevertheless
hold
adaptive
value
for
their
believers.
The
audience
member
challenges
that,
in
the
lecturers
analysis,
nearly
any
activity
could
be
classified
as
supernatural.
He
posits:
In
your
argument
I
dont
think
you
have
really
shown
how
to
understand
supernatural
events
it
seems
to
me
that
even
causal
explanations
in
science
or
anywhere
else
could
count
as
supernatural
and
in
that
case
then
even
the
most
mundane
interactions
in
everyday
life
are
supernatural
and
well
I
dont
get
the
point
The
audience
member
here
critiques
that
the
lecturer
has
defined
supernatural
too
broadly,
and
one
could
include
any
shared
conviction
that
cannot
(as
yet)
be
supported
by
empirical
evidence.
What
is
supernatural
might
then
include
phenomena
that
are
so
mundane
as
to
require
no
reflection
upon
their
factual
basis.
218
More
unsettling
to
the
speakers
position,
the
supernatural
could
also
apply
to
scientific
hypotheses.
Thus,
like
my
first
example,
this
audience
critic
points
to
an
over-extension
of
foundational
thinking.
In
response,
the
EvoS
lecturer
attempts
to
distinguish
natural
from
supernatural
explanations:
Well
thats
probably
because
I
didnt
make
clear
the
definition
of
what
supernatural
would
be
supernatural
would
be
by
definition
contrary
to
the
natural
laws
as
we
understand
them
and
secondly
without
any
basis
of
evidence
in
terms
of
reputable
phenomena
whereas
the
things
youre
talking
about
are
natural
and
do
have
reputable
phenomena.
Unlike
my
previous
example,
the
speaker
does
not
immediately
dismiss
his
challenger.
Neither
does
the
EvoS
moderator
interrupt.
Rather,
the
lecturer
attempts
to
hedge
his
argument
through
appeal
to
a
commonly-indexed
ideology.
However,
the
audience
member
pushes
the
issue:
No
if
we
follow
with
your
line
of
thought
even
causation
would
be
supernatural
I
think
you
are
committed
to
accept
that
and
in
that
case
I
dont
see
the
distinction
between
everyday
pragmatic
relations
with
objects
and
sensations
and
what
you
call
supernatural
beliefs
because
theres
not
yet
proof
that
everyday
relations
Becoming
impatient,
the
lecturer
interrupts
the
audience
member,
challenging:
Well
let
me
turn
the
argument
back
on
you
so
youd
say
then
theres
no
supernatural
events?
By
this
point,
the
interaction
between
the
audience
member
and
lecturer
has
turned
into
something
of
a
sparing
match.
The
lecturer
prods
his
critic
to
defend
a
position
(that
the
audience
member
has
not
argued)
that
would
totally
dismiss
supernatural
phenomena.
The
audience
member
is
nonplused,
and
retorts
after
a
moments
pause:
219
Well
I
think
that
the
burden
of
proof
is
on
you.
The
audience
begins
to
laugh,
likely
because
the
last
comment
was
a
clever
rebuttal,
and
also
because
this
interaction
has
become
so
tense.
At
this
point,
the
moderator
steps
in,
announcing:
Okay
so
we
have
time
for
one
more
question!
As
in
my
first
example,
the
time
constraints
and
moderation
of
the
session
have
resolved
a
potential
challenge
by
dismissing
the
criticism.
Interestingly,
this
lecturer
briefly
entertains
the
audience
members
disagreement,
but
attempts
to
turn
the
argument
back
upon
the
critic,
such
that
his
challenge
amounts
to
a
denial
of
the
possibility
of
supernatural
events.
The
lecturers
maneuver
here
is
a
creative
twist
on
an
in-house
ideology
indexed
several
times
in
examples
from
EvoS
Seminar
Series
lectures,
as
well
as
my
historical
sketches
from
Chapter
Three.
That
is,
while
Edward
Wilson,
Richard
Dawkins,
and
others
equate
intellectual
skepticism
toward
evolutionary
reasoning
with
an
irrational
(postmodernist)
denial
of
empirical
reality,
this
EvoS
lecturer
suggests
that
his
critic
denies
the
possibility
of
something
beyond
reality
(not
so
much
irrational
but
closed-minded).
The
audience
member
does
not
reciprocate,
however,
and
in
fact
turns
the
argument
back
upon
the
lecturer,
before
the
EvoS
moderator
intercedes.
than
the
second),
academic
critics
at
EvoS
lecture
often
challenge
the
priority
given
to
an
evolutionary
reasoning
in
socio-cultural
analyses.
This
is
unsurprising,
considering
the
academic
skepticism
of
foundational
thinking
(meta-narratives
or
220
meta-theories).
Lecturers
and
moderators
often
dismiss
such
criticisms
and,
in
the
case
of
my
first
example,
admonish
or
stigmatize
returning
critics
for
their
skepticism.
These
dismissals
are
not
out
of
keeping
with
EvoS
ideologies
representing
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
postmodernists
and
academic
elitists.
Insofar
as
EvoS
participants
understand
academic
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
unreasonable
and
(possibly)
anti-science,
critics
and
their
challenges
are
responded
to
as
nuisances
or
attacks.
Dismissals
of
critiques
are
not
surprising.
Seminar
Series
lectures
repeatedly
contextualize
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
principle
in
explaining
human
social
life.
To
this
end,
challenges
to
evolutionary
reasoning
(such
as
those
critiquing
it
as
a
kind
of
religious
belief)
may
be
dismissed
as
incongruent
with
a
working
presupposition
in
numerous
EvoS
activities.
The
in-house
ideologies
indexed
by
the
respondents
typically
stereotype
the
audience
critic
as
part
of
the
institutional
resistance
to
this
movement
a
consequence
of
the
critics
elitism
and
irrationality.
3b.
Diversions
from
Audience
Critiques
what
I
label
diversions.
These
responses
typically
introduce
a
foregrounding
into
the
interaction
of
a
similar
variety
as
I
describe
in
the
EvoS
lectures.
Thus,
an
audience
members
challenge
to
a
lecturer
may
be
met
with
an
attack
on
academic
structure
or
a
gratuitous
or
taboo
topic.
This
type
of
response
effectively
steers
away
from
the
specifics
of
an
audience
members
criticism,
re-introducing
commonly
indexed,
221
in-house
ideologies
into
the
Question
and
Answer
session.
More
practically,
diversions
from
audience
critiques
may
entertain
other
audience
members
and
run
down
the
clock
of
the
limited
time
allotted
for
questions
after
the
lecture.
Diversion
Example
1:
He
was
ousted
then
and
there.
In
this
example,
an
audience
member
takes
issue
the
lecturers
assertion
that
contemporary
psychologists
ignore
or
avoid
genetic
explanations
within
their
diagnoses
and
theories.
The
audience
member
comments:
You
had
said
earlier
that
a
lot
of
psychologists
ignore
biological
components
I
actually
would
argue
that
most
psychologists
would
agree
it
is
both
environment
and
biology
its
nature
and
nurture
for
everything
its
not
just
nurture
Such
a
criticism
is
common
in
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions,
in
which
an
audience
member
(typically,
university
faculty
or
graduate
students)
questions
a
lecturers
representation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
marginalized
within
academic
disciplines.
It
is
likely
this
in-house
ideology
(often
indexed
through
a
foregrounded
attack
on
academic
structure)
draws
challenges
from
representatives
of
those
disciplines
or
professions
that
have
been
accused
of
ignoring
or
marginalizing
evolutionary
reasoning.
In
their
challenges
to
this
ideology,
audience
members
suggest
that
the
representation
of
the
non-evolutionary
institution
is
an
exaggeration
of
the
extent
to
which
professional
academics
ignore
or
avoid
evolutionary
reasoning.
222
the
president
dared
of
[loudly]
EVEN
INSINUATING
AN
IDEA
that
there
might
be
differences
in
the
biology
between
men
and
women
he
was
ousted
then
and
there
so
there
is
a
lot
of
reaction
and
force
behind
just
insinuate
the
idea
that
there
are
any
differences
that
are
genetic
that
have
genetic
underpinnings
that
any
differences
were
due
to
nature
The
speaker
here
refers
to
Lawrence
H.
Summers
controversial
2005
talk
at
the
National
Bureau
of
Economic
Research
Conference
on
Diversifying
the
Science
and
Engineering
Workforce.35
This
reference,
it
would
seem,
functions
as
a
recent
historical
example
of
the
fear
of
evolutionary
reasonings
socio-political
implications.
Intensifying
this
foregrounding,
the
speakers
voice
rises
sharply
as
she
relates
that
even
insinuating
the
idea
of
genetic
explanations
resulted
in
Summers
ousting.
Following
her
response,
the
EvoS
moderator
announces
Okay
one
more
question
and
reminds
the
audience
that
the
lecturers
book
will
be
for
sale
at
the
following
Social
Event,
where
she
will
also
be
available
to
sign
copies.
35
While Summers was the focus of several controversies and disputes with Harvard faculty, his comments in this talk
were explicitly intended to provoke his critics. Specifically, many objected to his argument that men and women are
unequal in their mental abilities, and that in the special case of science and engineering, there are issues of intrinsic
aptitude, and particularly of the variability of aptitude, and that those considerations are reinforced by what are in fact
lesser factors involving socialization and continuing discrimination (Summers 2005). The academic and public
backlash to his speech was fierce, and Summers resigned his position soon thereafter.
223
Seminar
Series
lectures
in
Chapter
Four.
Like
my
previous
examples
in
this
chapter,
an
EvoS
moderator
intercedes
to
move
to
another
question.
Diversion
Example
2:
Your
ejaculates
just
a
little
bit
bigger
than
if
you
were
just
by
yourself
In
this
example,
an
audience
member
poses
a
problem
in
the
speakers
application
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
explain
romantic
jealousy.
During
this
speakers
lecture,
he
proposed
that
experiments
using
Rhesus
Macaques
demonstrated
the
violent
responses
when
males
witness
their
female
partners
mating
with
other
males.36
This
audience
member
argues
that
the
Rhesus
Macques
experiments
are
problematic
as
an
analogy
to
human
jealousy,
because
these
animals
do
not
pair
bond
in
the
wild.
If
experimental
conditions
were
to
be
consistent
with
Macques,
human
subjects
would
have
to
be
tested
for
jealous
responses
to
viewing
both
their
sexual
partners
and
strangers
engaged
in
intercourse.
The
latter
scenario
would
not
produce
the
same
effects
for
humans
as
Macques,
because
humans
pair
bond.
In
this
way,
she
says,
she
finds
the
evidence
from
Macques
un-interpretible.
At
this
point,
the
lecturer
interrupts
her:
Wellllllll
Wellll
Well
I
do
agree
theres
certainly
going
to
be
differences
would
it
eradicate
the
effect?
I
dont
think
so
36
Experimenters in this project (Rilling et al. 2004) placed male Macaques behind a two-way mirror, allowing them to
see another male Macaque with a female with whom the former had previously mated. Hormonal, behavioral, and
neurological measures suggested that the reactions of these male witnesses were similar to reactions to violent attacks
from rival monkeys. The experimenters propose that their findings are analogous to situations in which human males
learn of a partners (real or suspected) infidelity, a frequently reported motive in cases involving spousal abuse
(Rilling et al. 2004:364). The authors argue that sexual jealousy in male humans is also often accompanied by
vigilance behavior and anxiety and might recruit a similar neural network (Rilling et al. 2004:364), and as this
lecturer argues possibly paralleling human romantic jealousy.
224
The
lecturer
goes
on
to
explain
that
the
scenario
he
describes
of
Macques
could
also
be
true
in
human
subjects:
If
you
put
up
a
situation
and
this
is
particularly
for
men
if
you
put
up
a
situation
where
you
have
a
reproducably
[sic]
viable
female
and
another
male
is
having
access
to
her
men
do
get
upset
and
the
evidence
for
that
is
not
neurological
but
its
based
in
sperm
competitions
theres
some
data
suggesting
that
a
male
can
modulate
the
volume
of
ejaculate
as
a
function
of
watching
another
female
be
mated
even
though
he
has
no
familiarity
with
that
female
whatsoever
Here,
the
lecturer
begins
to
steer
his
response
into
rather
odd
territory.
While
the
research
he
is
discussing
remains
unnamed37,
he
suggests
that
the
amount
that
men
ejaculate
might
be
influenced
by
test
conditions
in
which
they
view
intercourse
between
strangers.
Clearly, the lecturer is introducing taboo topics and his foregrounding only
37
The speaker is likely referring to research by Australian zoologists Sarah J. Kilgallon and Leigh W. Simmons. In
2005, these researchers published the results of an experiment in which 52 heterosexual men (ages 18 to 35) were asked
to masturbate to images of two, different sexual scenarios - one depicting three women having sex, the other depicting
two men and one woman (a sperm competition image). The test subjects then collected their ejaculated semen and
the experimenters measured its volume, number of sperm, and sperm motility. The researchers concluded that men
viewing images of sperm competition produced ejaculates with a higher proportion of motile sperm (Kilgallon and
Simmons 2005:254).
225
Here
the
lecturer
holds
his
thumb
and
forefinger
up,
spreading
them
as
if
he
were
estimating
the
contents
in
a
test
tube:
Your
ejaculates
just
a
little
bit
bigger
than
if
you
were
just
by
yourself
But
if
she
were
getting
mated
by
ten
guys
The
lecturer
spreads
the
distance
between
his
thumb
and
forefinger,
estimating
the
difference
in
volume.
Much
of
the
audience
is,
by
now,
roaring
with
laughter.
Then
the
stakes
are
higherSo
testes
modulate
ejaculate
as
a
consequence
and
as
to
how
that
would
play
out
in
the
brain
The
lecturer
pauses,
shrugging
dramatically,
and
comments:
Hell
Ive
been
tryin
to
do
that
experiment
my
whole
life!
As
the
audiences
laughter
continues,
the
EvoS
moderator
announces
that
it
is
time
that
we
head
over
to
the
discussion
room,
and
thus
ends
the
Question
and
Answer
session.
226
doubts
went
largely
unaddressed
during
the
session.
Lecturers
instead
sought
to
avoid
criticisms
by
entertaining
the
audience
or
introducing
new
and
typically
unrelated
topics.
Many
of
the
individuals
I
interviewed
attended
Seminar
Series
lectures
in
the
past,
but
were
put
off
by
the
lecturers
arguments
and
the
cursory
treatment
of
criticisms
during
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
critiques
demonstrate
a
continuity
that
stretches
not
just
across
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer
Sessions,
but
between
these
sessions
and
the
lectures
I
detail
in
my
previous
chapter.
As
in
the
examples
above,
dismissals
tend
to
index
the
in-
house
ideologies
also
included
in
(and
observable
across)
Seminar
Series
lectures.
The
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
are
similarly
imbued
with
representations
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
feared
or
considered
politically
incorrect
by
its
academic
critics
though,
in
my
second
example,
the
lecturer
is
clearly
using
such
a
stereotype
to
his
advantage.
227
3c.
Assimilating
228
The
moderator
then
calls
on
an
audience
member
who
raises
his
hand.
The
audience
member
challenges
the
speakers
use
and
understanding
of
evolutionary
reasoning:
According
to
Darwinian
theory
whats
selected
is
the
average
so
if
youre
talking
about
personality
you
have
to
be
an
average
personality
all
these
traits
are
recessive
that
youve
looked
at
theyre
not
adaptive
for
the
rest
of
a
population
theyre
not
the
traits
the
rest
of
the
population
is
going
to
get
evolutionary
theory
does
not
predict
what
youve
looked
at
This
attendee
poses
that
the
behaviors
that
this
lecturer
attempts
to
explain
with
evolutionary
reasoning
would
not
contribute
to
an
individuals
reproduction
or
survival.
Even
if
psychopathic
or
sociopathic
behaviors
could
demonstrated
as
heritable
(the
critic
humors
the
lecturer
on
this
contentious
matter),
persons
exhibiting
them
would
be
less
likely
to
live
longer
lives
or
have
more
children
than
people
who
do
not
suffer
from
these
conditions.
As
a
result,
the
critic
argues,
evolutionary
reasoning
is
misapplied
in
the
speakers
argument.
Such a criticism is doubtlessly difficult for an EvoS lecturer to hear, let alone
engage.
In
their
promotions,
the
EvoS
Programs
organizers
praise
their
Seminar
Series
speakers
for
applying
evolutionary
reasoning
in
novel
areas
of
research
(see
D.S.
Wilson
2005a,
2007a;
D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011;
Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010).
However,
such
arguments
are
vulnerable
to
critics
who
(like
this
audience
member)
express
their
skepticism
by
demonstrating
their
own
familiarity
with
Darwinian
theories.
229
of
a
certain
length
yes
but
looking
more
carefully
what
theyve
found
is
evolutionary
forces
act
very
very
strongly
and
different
types
different
groups
different
individuals
with
different
shapes
of
beaks
can
depending
on
their
circumstances
have
a
very
beneficial
environment
for
themselves
so
what
Im
trying
to
say
here
is
that
humans
are
almost
like
within
the
human
species
theres
room
for
the
wolves
and
theres
room
for
-
the
rabbits
and
each
of
these
can
have
utility
in
places
depending
on
their
concentration
in
the
society
Remarking
on
the
widely
known
research
on
Galapagos
Island
finches
(one
of
Charles
Darwins
own
examples
of
adaptation),
the
speaker
here
struggles
with
the
audience
members
challenge
to
her
application
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Her
response
borders
on
diverting
from
the
topic
altogether,
until
she
draws
a
shaky
analogy
between
finches
and
humans.38
And
both
of
these
things
can
be
explained
by
the
same
principle
you
can
see
things
that
might
or
might
not
be
adaptive
and
you
wind
up
with
an
individual
whose
behavior
is
not
only
bad
for
others
but
also
bad
for
herself
that
isnt
necessarily
an
adaptive
strategy
so
some
are
adaptations
and
some
perhaps
not
The
moderator
here
reaffirms
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
first
principle
more
explicitly
than
the
lecturer
would
be
able
to
achieve.
Evolutionary
reasoning
illuminates
both
the
adaptive
and
maladaptive
aspects
of
human
social
life.
Having
stated
this,
the
moderator
quickly
moves
on,
reminding
the
audience
that
(unlike
other
Seminar
Series
events)
university
caterers
will
momentarily
be
leaving
for
the
Social
Event:
38
Arguably,
the
speaker
means:
just
as
these
different
varieties
of
finches
(isolated
on
different
islands
for
generations)
possessed
beaks
adapted
to
foraging
the
food
in
their
respective
habitats,
varieties
of
psychopathic
or
sociopathic
behaviors
might
thrive
in
the
right
kinds
of
socio-historic
circumstances.
In
her
preceding
lecture,
she
posited
that
such
behaviors
might
positively
contribute
to
an
individuals
survival
and
reproduction
in
prisons
or
military
regimes,
as
well
as
busy
urban
settings
where
(she
suggests)
an
individuals
deception
or
abuse
of
others
would
likely
go
unnoticed
by
police
or
social
workers.
230
Okay
-
lets
just
have
just
two
more
and
then
its
time
to
eat
and
I
hope
youll
all
come
and
we
can
continue
the
conversation.
Like
respondents
dismissals
of
and
diversions
from
audience
criticisms,
this
explicit
restatement
of
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
appears
within
a
moderated
and
time-constrained
setting.
The
organizational
practices
of
the
Question
and
Answer
Session
both
elicit
and
delimit
particular
types
of
interactions.
Here,
a
two-person
response
poses
the
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
defense
to
an
audience
members
criticism
an
interaction
then
swiftly
concluded
by
the
sessions
moderator.
I
will
also
note
that
the
moderator
through
analogical
extension
links
the
first
principle
to
a
concern
about
the
causes
and
consequences
of
mental
illness
in
an
individual
whos
behavior
is
not
only
bad
for
others
but
also
bad
for
herself.
A
similar
extension
appears
more
explicitly
in
my
next
example.
Assimilation
Example
2:
WellI
guess
it
depends
on
how
you
define
feminism
Detailing
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
in
Chapter
Three,
I
suggested
that
some
Seminar
lecture
topics
are
more
likely
to
inspire
passionate
challenges
from
audience
members
than
others.
In
this
example,
a
visiting
lecturer
presented
his
research
on
martial
rape
as
explicable
in
terms
of
sperm
competition
an
incendiary
topic
in
evolutionary
science
that
has
drawn
criticism
in
the
past,
particularly
from
feminist
theorists
and
activists.39
During
this
his
lecture,
the
speaker
acknowledged
this
39
Most notably, Randy Thornhill and Craig Palmer (2000) provoked both academic and public outcries
with A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion. In their book, the authors argue that
male-female rape may have an evolutionary explanation as a violent means of ensuring reproduction. The
authors compare human rape to examples of forced mating in other, non-human species, and propose that
231
controversy,
reporting
(tactlessly)
that
he
and
his
colleagues
had
experienced
a
lot
of
bruhaha
from
feminists
in
the
past.
As
his
talk
continued,
a
few
audience
members
dramatically
stormed
out
of
the
lecture
hall.
In
the
subsequent
Question
and
Answer
Session,
the
lecturer
and
moderator
field
a
few
queries
about
the
details
of
the
speakers
research.
Then,
an
audience
member
who
is
observably
upset
stands
and
haltingly
comments:
I
was
listening
to
your
language
and
I
noticed
a
few
things...
like
you
use
the
word
bruhaha
And
I
wondered
do
you
have
any
feminists
working
on
this
with
you?
While
not
particularly
clearly
phrased,
the
audience
members
challenge
to
the
speaker
deals
with
the
socio-political
implications
of
evolutionary
reasoning
about
human
social
life,
as
well
as
his
somewhat
flippant
assessment
of
previous
challenges.
Likely,
her
question
for
him
is
similarly
pained,
but
arguably
suggests
that
he
is
dismissive
of
feminist
concerns
about
his
research.
The
speaker
responds
to
her
question:
Well
I
guess
it
depends
on
how
you
define
feminism
you
know
Ive
got
two
daughters
two
sisters
a
mother
and
I
think
that
its
incredibly
important
that
we
figure
out
everything
we
can
about
why
this
behavior
occurs
if
we
ever
want
to
have
a
shot
at
stopping
it.
The
lecturer
thus
appeals
to
feminist
concerns
by
describing
the
women
in
his
family.
This
would
likely
be
an
unsatisfactory
explanation
for
his
critic,
if
not
ridiculous
for
anyone
remotely
familiar
with
feminism
in
academic
institutions.
This
said,
this
portion
of
the
lecturers
response
echoes
back
the
diversions
created
by
forced copulation in humans may have evolved in the Pilo-Pleistocene, in response to womens preferential
mating with high-status men.
232
respondents
in
my
previous
examples,
here
foregrounding
intimate
details
of
the
speakers
life
as
a
defense
against
audience
criticism.
In
his
following
position
that
researchers
should
figure
out
everything
we
can
about
why
this
behavior
occurs,
the
lecturer
reaffirms
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
principle.
That
is,
evolutionary
reasoning
illuminates
the
ultimate
cause
for
contemporary
problems
in
human
social
life.
Further,
he
introduces
an
analogical
extension
to
the
first
principle,
posing
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
an
integral
part
of
rape
prevention.
It
is
debatable
whether
or
not
this
extension
could
be
called
an
extension
to
feminist
ideologies,
but
clearly
the
lecturer
seeks
to
link
evolutionary
explanation
to
socio-political
concerns
about
sexual
violence.
Admittedly,
both
the
audience
criticism
and
the
lecturers
response
in
this
example
should
be
considered
in
light
of
the
emotional
tension
that
resonated
throughout
this
event.
Acknowledging
this,
the
lecturer
responds
to
an
audience
challenge
with
the
first
principle,
creatively
extended
to
the
critiques
that
have
historically
been
leveled
against
it.
Following
this
response,
as
the
moderator
closes
the
session,
reminds
the
students
in
Current
Topics
in
Evolutionary
Studies
to
head
to
the
Social
Event,
and
invites
the
rest
of
the
audience
to
join
them
for
dinner
and
continued
discussion.
Assimilation
Example
3:
Thats
why
I
say
look
if
you
want
to
improve
reasoning
lets
understand
adaptation.
In
this
final
example,
the
visiting
speakers
talk
described
a
variety
of
ethically
challenging
situations
(involving
incest,
cannibalism,
and
blasphemy,
among
others),
and
documenting
his
subjects
233
immediate
reactions
to
these
scenarios.
He
subsequently
posed
that
these
responses
reflected
the
universal
psychological
adaptations
to
morally
confounding
situations.
An
audience
member
questions
the
affective
approach
of
the
lecturers
experiments.
It
is
flawed,
argues
the
questioner,
to
record
the
gut-reactions
in
his
experiment
designs,
rather
than
allowing
his
test
subjects
to
think
over
their
judgments
and
offer
more
thorough
responses.
234
you
want
to
improve
reasoning
lets
understand
adaptation
to
try
to
have
external
restraints
on
our
thinking
The
speaker
here
affirms
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
within
a
fascinatingly
complicated
proposition:
evolutionary
reasoning
about
the
adaptive
potentials
of
human
social
life
(one
product
of
human
reasoning
among
many)
offers
an
ultimate
cause
for
the
weaknesses
and
strengths
inherent
to
different
applications
of
human
reasoning.40
The
lecturers
conclusion
bears
similarity
to
David
Sloan
Wilsons
argument
that
rationality
is
not
the
gold
standard
against
which
all
other
forms
of
thought
are
to
be
judged.
Adaptation
is
the
gold
standard
against
which
rationality
must
be
judged,
along
with
all
other
forms
of
thought
(D.S.
Wilson
2002a:228).
Further,
the
lecturer
extends
this
already
complicated
use
of
evolutionary
reasoning
toward
an
ideological
position
on
the
practical
applications
of
science
to
improving
reasoning
by
establishing
external
constraints
on
our
thinking.
What,
exactly,
these
external
restraints
might
be,
the
lecturer
does
not
say.
Rather,
like
other
EvoS
participants,
he
relies
upon
the
presupposition
that
such
changes
are
necessary
to
fix
the
(also
unidentified)
pitfalls
of
human
social
life,
and
that
evolutionary
reasoning
offers
the
means
to
do
just
that.
The
complexity
of
this
speakers
response
should
not
distract
from
the
setting
in
which
he
speaks.
This
example
of
audience
criticism
and
lectures
40
Obviously,
my
reconstruction
of
the
speakers
response
(a
post
hoc
rationalization
on
my
behalf)
presents
his
creative
and
recursive
uses
of
the
first
principle,
much
of
which
his
audience
members
were
not
likely
to
notice
or
dwell
upon,
in
situ.
Granting
this
point,
the
appearance
of
the
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
lecturers
response
follows
the
pattern
established
many
times
over
in
other
Seminar
Series
lectures
and
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
235
response
appear
within
the
moderation
and
time-constraints
shared
by
all
other
examples
from
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
Declaring
the
session
to
be
satisfactorily
concluded,
the
EvoS
moderator
announces:
Okay
Thats
a
great
way
to
end
so
lets
head
over
to
have
more
discussion
Like
my
previous
examples
in
this
chapter,
this
moderator
maintains
the
time
limit
of
the
session,
announcing
when
no
more
questions
may
be
taken
so
that
the
lecturer,
and
the
programs
organizers,
and
Current
Topics
students
can
leave
for
the
Social
Event.
4.
Critics
of
EvoS
as
Resources
for
the
Movement
should
be
noted
throughout
that
EvoS
lecturers
and
moderators
are
(at
the
very
least)
able
to
sidestep
these
challenges
until
the
time
comes
for
the
majority
of
the
audience
to
leave.
Just
as
often,
though,
they
engage
their
critics
in
ways
that
allow
them
to
create
new
foregroundings,
index
the
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies,
and
contextualize
criticisms
as
further
problems
that
could
be
resolved
using
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
all
social
life.
To
this
end,
I
suggest
that
the
critics
of
EvoS
(and,
indeed,
other
social
movements)
are
not
treated
necessarily
as
enemies
of
the
program,
but
as
potential
resources
that
EvoS
participants
sometimes
harness
to
further
their
cause.
In one sense, this argument could be made very simply: Critics who are
236
effective
shut
down
of
their
arguments
might
encourage
other
audience
members
to
join.
While
these
may
be
possibilities,
I
want
to
suggest
that
critics
are
useful
resources
because
they
personify
the
rejections
of
evolutionary
reasoning
that
are
represented
by
the
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies.
Insofar
as
these
ideologies
are
not
immediately
apparent
(or
relevant)
to
younger
members
of
an
EvoS
Seminar
Series
audience,
critics
reify
the
kinds
of
professional
dissatisfaction
that
is
voiced
by
many
EvoS
lecturers.
That
is,
as
my
examples
above
demonstrate
they
represent
those
who
are
fearful
of
evolutionary
reasonings
socio-political
implications,
those
who
are
invested
in
postmodernism,
those
convinced
of
evolutionary
reasonings
political
incorrectness,
and
the
elitist,
over-specialized,
Ivory
Tower
academics.
Given that the sample set I offer in this discussion is markedly small (a
237
5.
EvoS
New
Paltz
and
The
Tiger
Incident
The
EvoS
Program
at
SUNY
New
Paltz
began
in
late
2006,
founded
and
led
by
evolutionary
psychologist
Glenn
Geher.
The
New
Paltz
Seminar
Series
began
on
February
12,
2008
(on
Charles
Darwins
birthday).
Their
first
invited
lecturer
was
Lionel
Tiger,
an
evolutionary
anthropologist
whose
books
Men
in
Groups
(1969)
and
The
Imperial
Animal
(1972,
with
coauthor
Robin
Fox)
contributed
to
the
rise
of
sociobiology
in
the
mid-1970s.
Like
other
sociobiologists,
Lionel
Tiger
(whom
I
also
discuss
in
Chapter
Three)
was
at
the
center
of
no
small
amount
of
academic
tension
for
the
last
four
decades.
His
books
and
articles
draw
criticisms
that
he
has
misused
the
authority
of
science
to
popularize
deterministic
explanations,
particularly
regarding
gender
and
sexuality
(see
Degler
1991:227-231;
Segerstrle
2000:27-28).
In
the
1970s
and
1980s,
he
was
a
primary
target
for
participants
in
the
Sociobiology
Study
Group
at
Harvard
(Bart
1977;
Lewontin
1977;
Lewontin
et
al.
1984:
156-162;
Sociobiology
Study
Group
1977).
Since
then,
he
has
inspired
critiques
that
could
rival
the
attention
given
to
Edward
O.
Wilson
or
any
other
sociobiologist
(for
example,
see
Bock
1980:7-35;
Geertz
1984:267;
Haraway
1989:146-150;
Sperling
2008).
On
these
criticisms,
Tiger
comments:
For
venturing
to
explore
the
role
of
biology
in
our
social
lives,
I
have
had
more
than
my
share
of
interesting
moments.
In
addition
to
slander
and
calumny
depressingly
standard
fare
in
the
academy
today
I
have
received
bomb
threats
at
lectures
in
Vancouver
and
Montreal
and
the
promise
of
a
kneecapping
at
the
New
School
for
Social
Research
in
New
York.
I
have
been
the
object
of
a
demonstration
of
angry
male
transvestites
at
the
Royal
Institution
in
London,
and
I
have
seen
one
of
the
books
I
co-authored,
The
Imperial
Animal,
compared
to
Mein
Kampf!
[Tiger
1996:14]
238
Tiger
persevered,
however,
and
in
1999
published
The
Decline
of
Males,
arguing
that
men
are
psychologically
driven
toward
ensuring
their
reproductive
success
by
controlling
womens
sexual
behaviors.
Womens
widespread
access
to
birth
control
since
the
mid-20th
century
(this
book
contends)
creates
conflicts
with
mens
evolved
predispositions,
and
thus
gives
men
a
continual
sense
of
paternity
uncertainty
(1999:45-58).
As
I
suggest
in
my
third
chapter,
Tiger
is
known
as
a
critic
of
feminism
and
affirmative
action.
In
a
Wall
Street
Journal
article
(Youve
Got
Male!),
he
writes:
Civic
celebrations
of
antipathy
to
men
such
as
the
Violence
Against
Women
Act
are
finally
generating
specific
and
pointed
responses
by
men
fatigued,
if
still
baffled,
by
the
knee-jerk
assumption
that
they
suffer
irredeemably
from
what
I
call
Male
Original
Sin.
[Tiger
2005]
The
New
Paltz
EvoS
Program
could
hardly
have
selected
a
more
contentious
first
speaker
to
begin
its
Seminar
Series.
It
seems
likely
that
the
controversy
he
stirred
at
New
Paltz
was
actually
desired
by
EvoS
Program
organizers
there,
who
would
subsequently
harness
the
critical
responses
within
this
event
to
further
index
EvoS
in-house
ideologies
and
argue
evolutionary
reasonings
explanatory
potential.
Even
before
his
visit
to
New
Paltz,
tensions
were
aroused
throughout
the
university.
Like
the
Binghamton
EvoS
Program,
students
enrolled
in
the
Seminar
Series
for
credits
were
to
read
a
preparatory
article
by
each
lecturer
in
the
series,
and
New
Paltz
organizers
assigned
Tigers
polemical
Wall
Street
Journal
article.
This
decision
did
not
simply
promote
Tiger
as
an
evolutionary
scientist,
and
thus
his
relevance
to
the
Seminar
Series.
Rather,
organizers
were
likely
attempting
to
foreground
this
individuals
antagonistic
anti-feminism
and
thus
make
sure
that
Tigers
reputation
would
precede
him.
239
If
this
was
indeed
the
organizers
intention,
it
worked
very
well.
The
week
before
Tigers
visit,
professors
from
the
biology,
sociology,
womens
studies,
and
psychology
departments
printed
and
distributed
an
unsigned
flyer
(Morrow
et
al.
2008)
that
challenged
the
scientific
validity
of
his
books
and
articles
(see
also
Hewett
et
al.
2008).
As
one
of
these
critics
later
comments,
at
the
heart
of
the
debate
was
whether
Tiger
was
justified
in
making
some
of
the
broad
claims
he
had
made
based
on
rather
weak
evidence
and
the
questionable
methods
he
used
to
come
to
his
conclusions
(Brooks
2008).
Their
dissatisfaction
became
more
widely
known
in
the
days
approaching
the
visit,
and
Glenn
Geher
responded
by
scheduling
a
Question
and
Answer
Session
for
such
criticisms
to
be
addressed.
He
innocently
recounts,
it
occurred
to
me
that
this
was
someone
who
is
not
very
friendly
towards
womens
studies
necessarily,
and
someone
people
on
campus
would
want
to
talk
to
[]
I
wanted
to
provide
a
forum
for
discussion
for
those
who
wanted
one
(Geher
in
Hanmer
2008).
At
the
Question
and
Answer
Session,
critics
distributed
their
fliers
to
the
audiences,
and
many
of
its
authors
attended
to
challenge
Tiger
in
person
(Brooks
2008).
As
EvoS
organizers
recalls:
This
relatively
small
event
apparently
got
a
lot
of
attention
well
over
100
people
packed
the
small
room
where
the
event
took
place.
Something
of
a
small
protest,
organized
largely
by
faculty,
transpired.
Accordingly,
the
event
was
contentious
and
even
somewhat
unpleasant.
[Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010:33]
Stipulating
that
he
would
not
respond
to
this
anonymous
flier
or
a
hostile
audience,
Tiger
refused
to
address
the
challenges
he
received.
In
subsequent
interviews,
Tiger
calls
the
flier
unsigned
propaganda
(Hanmer
2008)
and
argue,
if
students
are
240
taught
that
shouting
and
pamphlets
are
an
effective
way
to
deal
with
issues,
they
are
doomed
as
effective
members
of
society
(Brooks
2008).
In
their
flier
and
in
later
comments,
Tigers
critics
insist
that
they
were
opposed
to
the
speakers
lack
of
empirical
support,
not
his
application
of
evolutionary
theories
(Murrow
et
al.
2008;
Obach
2008).
On
Tigers
refusal
to
address
them,
one
critic
recalls:
When
Tiger
initially
mentioned
that
the
authors
of
the
flier
were
not
known,
I
raised
my
hand
fully
within
his
view
in
order
to
identify
myself.
He
did
not
acknowledge
me
and
I
did
not
feel
comfortable
interrupting
his
talk
to
clarify
the
matter.
I
did
attempt
again
at
the
end
during
the
question
and
answer
period
to
identify
myself
and
the
other
authors,
but
I
was
not
called
upon
by
the
moderator.
[Obach
2008]
While
this
is
one
persons
description
of
these
events,
it
parallels
the
dismissals
of
EvoS
critics
I
discuss
above,
such
that
Tigers
Question
and
Answer
Session
was
moderated
by
the
EvoS
director,
and
the
moderator
and
lecturer
together
dismissed
an
audience
challenge.
As
this
same
author
elaborates,
other
people
in
this
same
audience
seemed
to
feel
the
speaker
dismissed
their
critiques:
Several
of
Tigers
comments
were
personal
and
cruel.
Among
his
many
offensive
comments
during
the
afternoon
session
was
when
he
told
womens
studies
majors
that
they
would
grow
out
of
it.
In
another
instance,
when
one
student
challenged
Tigers
patently
flawed
logic
regarding
the
relationship
between
oral
contraceptives
and
single
motherhood,
Dr.
Tiger
was
unable
to
offer
a
coherent
defense
and
instead
declared
that
there
must
be
something
wrong
with
her
given
that
his
point
was
so
simple.
[Obach
2008]
Again,
Obachs
report
is
the
impressions
of
one
audience
member.
This
said,
he
here
poses
examples
similar
to
the
dismissals
I
detail
above
the
speaker
here
dismissing
two
more
audience
members
by
signaling
them
out
as
unreasonable
or
uninformed
critics.
241
This
event
suggests
that
the
indexical
patterns
in
the
Binghamton
EvoS
Seminar
Series
were
duplicated
in
this
second
program.
Arguably,
given
his
reputation,
the
New
Paltz
EvoS
Program
was
setting
the
stage
for
controversy
by
inviting
Lionel
Tiger.
The
Seminar
Series
reading
(Tigers
Wall
Street
Journal
article)
and
his
earlier
lecture
posed
several
foregrounded
attacks
on
academic
structure,
as
well
as
numerous
taboo
topics
(abortion,
birth
control,
the
battle
of
the
sexes,
and
so
on)
introduced
by
both
Tiger
and
the
EvoS
moderator.41
Further,
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
included
moderation
by
an
EvoS
organizer
and
dismissals
of
audience
challenges
similar
to
those
in
the
Binghamton
EvoS
Seminar
Series.
I argue that the organizers of the EvoS Program at New Paltz recognized their
critics
as
potential
resources,
and
thus
means
of
communicating
the
movements
in-
house
ideologies
and
first
principle.
In
the
wake
of
Lionel
Tigers
visit,
the
New
Paltz
EvoS
director
and
other
program
members
argued
that
the
controversy
was
indicative
of
evolutionary
reasoning
perceived
as
politically
correct
and
fears
about
its
socio-political
implications
in
U.S.
higher
education.
Interviewed
by
the
New
Paltz
student
newspaper,
the
programs
director
quips,
Guess
what?
Evolution
is
controversial!
[]
I
can't
imagine
a
speaker
who
could
have
made
this
point
more
manifest
on
our
campus
than
Dr.
Tiger
(Geher
in
Brooks
2008).
In
another
interview,
a
SUNY
New
Paltz
journalist
writes
that
Geher
understands
evolutionary
thinking
is
notorious
for
eliciting
hostility
and
that
he
was
not
surprised
with
the
41
While introducing the speaker, the EvoS Program moderator recounts a camping trip with his two young
daughters and son, who he and his wife catch causing mischief inside the family tent. The girls had opened
their mothers cosmetics bag and were applying makeup to each other, while their younger brother was
urinating in the corner. The moderator poses this as evidence of the inborn differences between males and
females.
242
response
Tigers
talks
evoked
(Hanmer
2008).
Fascinatingly,
in
following
months,
the
EvoS
response
to
this
controversy
took
a
decidedly
more
complex
turn,
although
one
that
strongly
supports
my
argument
here.
In
Spring
2008,
Glenn
Geher
co-authored
an
online
survey,
ostensibly
to
assess
the
possible
reasons
for
the
heated,
academic
reaction
to
Tigers
visit,
positing
that
the
majority
of
critical
response
seemed
to
come
from
a
particular
sector
of
professional
academics
(those
in
Sociology
and
Womens
Studies)
with
notably
Leftist
political
orientations,
who
he
poses
are
also
(by-and-large)
not
parents
qualities
that
might
predispose
an
individual
toward
rejecting
evolutionary
arguments
on
psychological
differences
between
men
and
women.
With
this
survey
sought
to
answer
a
research
question
that
could
probably
only
be
posed
by
EvoS
members:
When
it
comes
to
accepting
the
idea
of
natural
(evolved)
behavioral
sex
difference
between
males
and
females
in
our
species,
are
there
important
effects
of
(a)
political
orientation,
(b)
status
as
an
employed
academic,
and
(c)
status
as
a
parent?
[Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010:34].42
As
they
explain,
the
researchers
hypothesized
that
skepticism
toward
evolutionary
explanations
of
this
sort
might
be
influenced
by
(on
one
hand)
a
persons
status
as
a
non-parent,
and
(on
the
other)
ones
status
as
a
student
or
professor
in
womens
studies
or
sociology
(Wind
2010).
Justifying
this
direction
in
their
investigation,
they
explain:
42
Two
(possibly
obvious)
points
need
mention
here:
First,
EvoS
New
Paltz
organizers
clearly
did
not
recognize
(or
forgot)
that
several
of
the
most
vocal
authors
of
the
critical
pamphlet
were
Biology
Department
faculty
or
from
his
own
department
(Psychology).
Second,
we
should
recognize
that
the
question
these
researchers
are
asking
(about
acceptance
or
rejection
of
the
idea
of
natural
(evolved)
behavioral
sex
difference
between
males
and
females
in
our
species)
is
very
much
shaped
by
Gehers
role
as
an
evolutionary
psychologist.
As
I
have
detailed
above,
the
primary
contentions
voiced
by
critics
of
Lionel
Tiger
had
little
to
do
with
this
foundational
question
of
nature
vs.
nurture.
243
There
are
particular
areas
of
academia
that
seem
most
relevant
to
the
current
research.
In
particular,
scholars
in
the
areas
of
Sociology
and
Womens
Studies
are
especially
known
for
denying
the
relevance
of
biology
to
an
understanding
of
human
nature
[].
Further,
Sociology
and
Womens
Studies
are
fields
that
are
directly
acknowledged
by
Tiger
as
politically
motivated
and
faculty
from
these
fields
were
particularly
interested
in
protesting
his
presence
on
campus
during
the
Tiger
Incident
at
New
Paltz.
Thus,
a
new
variable
was
created
exclusively
among
academics.
Participants
were
divided
into
categories
based
on
whether
they
reported
holding
affiliations
with
Womens
Studies
or
Sociology
(or
not).
[Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010:42]
This
survey
is
premised
on
an
abstraction
of
a
similar
sort
that
I
document
in
the
(Binghamton)
EvoS
Seminar
Series
lectures.
That
is,
from
the
onset,
the
researchers
have
divided
the
local
academic
landscape
into
groups
likely
to
reject
evolutionary
reasoning
about
human
behaviors
and
those
likely
not
to.
More
importantly,
however,
note
that
these
EvoS
Program
researchers
like
those
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Two
have
engaged
students
and
faculty
as
research
subjects,
whose
responses
might
empirically
demonstrate
the
programs
in-house
ideologies,
and
thus
be
used
to
further
promote
its
first
principle.
A
total
of
268
individuals
took
this
survey
online
during
Spring
and
Summer
of
2008,
although
97
did
not
complete
it
and
so
the
final
sample
size
included
171
people.
The
researchers
asked
these
participants
to
estimate
the
degree
to
which
behavioral
differences
between
males
and
females
using
a
five
point
scale
with
1
corresponding
to
Definitely
mostly
due
to
nature
(biology)
and
5
corresponding
to
Definitely
mostly
due
to
nurture
(environment)
(Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010:36).
Participants
were
asked
for
their
opinions
on
male/female
differences
in
men
and
women,
boys
and
girls,
roosters
and
hens,
and
dogs
and
cats.
The
researchers
then
sought
correlations
between
these
responses
and
participants
gender,
age,
parental
244
status,
political
orientation
(very
liberal
to
very
conservative),
career
(academic
vs.
non-academic),
and
their
academic
field.
After over a year of research, the results of Geher and Gambacortas survey
245
supported
by
this
survey.
Specifically,
their
results
support
a
representation
of
the
critics
rejecting
evolutionary
reasoning
due
to
their
political
correctness
and
Ivory
Tower
elitism.
As
Geher
explains
in
a
subsequent
radio
interview:
I
think
that
one
of
the
implications
here
is
that
these
things
are
politicized
there
is
clearly
a
political
underpinning
to
beliefs
about
whether
things
are
due
to
nature
versus
nurtureWere
at
a
particular
time
culturally
now
where
there
are
certain
norms
sort
of
political
norms
and
cultural
norms
that
I
think
very
much
play
into
this
particularly
regarding
acknowledging
sex
differences
as
due
to
nature
I
think
that
has
become
a
somewhat
politically
incorrect
kind
of
comment
to
make
under
modern
times
Arguably,
the
in-house
ideologies
predestined
the
kinds
of
conclusions
that
Geher
draws
here.
But
the
more
important
point
is
this:
EvoS
organizers
have
engaged
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
new
and
unlikely
kind
of
resource
for
creatively
indexing
these
in-house
ideologies
into
new
venues
such
journal
articles,
local
news,
and
radio
interviews.
researchers
use
this
opportunity
to
reaffirm
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
they
posit:
[t]he
goal
of
an
EvoS
education
is,
decidedly,
not
to
convince
students
that
everything
is
due
to
nature.
Rather,
a
major
goal
of
this
program,
steeped
in
an
interdisciplinary
approach
[],
is
to
provide
a
deep
and
broad
education
on
the
variegated
kinds
of
organic
evolutionary
forces
that
exist
as
well
as
the
nature
of
cultural
evolution
and
other,
not-directly-organic
evolutionary
forces.
[Geher
and
Gambacorta
2010:44]
The
authors
downplay
the
role
of
naturalizing
explanations,
given
that
the
entirety
of
their
research
was
explicitly
about
the
acceptance
or
rejections
of
them.
Yet,
they
quite
certainly
affirm
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
here,
giving
a
sweeping
vision
of
evolutionary
reasonings
interdisciplinary
potential.
This
sentiment
246
echoes
an
earlier,
multi-authored,
EvoS
Journal
article
(EvoS:
Completing
the
Evolutionary
Synthesis
in
Higher
Education)
that
references,
but
does
not
specifically
name,
the
Tiger
Incident.
Here,
the
authors
explain:
In
addition
to
highly
positive
interactions
among
members
of
the
EvoS
community,
there
have
also
been
some
negative
reactions,
especially
to
seminars
on
controversial
topics
such
as
human
sexual
behavior
and
religion.
This
has
manifest
[sic]
itself
in
the
form
of
critical
questioning
of
the
speaker
following
the
talks,
distribution
of
flyers
protesting
a
speakers
work
and
a
series
of
letters
to
the
student
newspaper.
The
entire
academic
community
has
been
forced
to
examine
long-held
assumptions
and
explore
new,
unfamiliar
territory.
As
faculty,
we
are
used
to
being
experts,
and
it
is
healthy
(if
not
necessary)
for
us
to
explore
radically
new
and/or
different
ideas,
to
hear
others
perspectives
and
to
articulate
our
own,
just
as
we
expect
our
students
to
do.
While
these
attributes
may
be
at
the
heart
of
scholarship
within
ones
discipline,
the
thing
that
makes
these
interactions
surrounding
EvoS
different
is
the
cross-disciplinary
nature
of
the
discussion.
These
instances
have
allowed
us
to
model
this
type
of
discourse
for
students
as
an
example
of
life-long
learning.
[D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2009:8]
The
authors
here
use
the
very
fact
of
criticism
to
leverage
new,
creative
indices
of
the
programs
in-house
ideologies
and
affirmations
of
its
first
principle,
often
in
ways
that
would
not
be
possible,
had
the
critical
response
not
taken
place.
The
authors
here
affirm
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
as
inherently
preferable
to
the
disciplinary
specialization
and
elitism
commonly
found
in
U.S.
higher
education.
Further,
they
analogically
extend
this
affirmation
to
a
positively
valued
situation
in
which
they
have
been
able
to
model
this
type
of
discourse
for
students
as
an
example
of
life-long
learning
(although
how
EvoS
organizers
have
accomplished
this
remains
unexplained).
The EvoS Seminar Series Question and Answer Sessions are tense but, as I
have shown, also useful activities for the EvoS Program. These are moments when
247
audience
members
who
have
found
significant
fault
with
the
lecturers
arguments
may
pose
serious
challenges
to
the
programs
in-house
ideologies
and
the
relevance
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life.
As
I
show
above,
these
challenges
may
be
emotionally
charged,
given
the
taboo
topics
and
other
foregroundings
that
EvoS
lecturers
tend
to
include
in
their
delivers.
Furthermore,
audience
members
may
in
fact
be
more
well-versed
in
the
topics-at-
hand
(or
even
evolutionary
science,
itself)
than
some
of
the
lecturers,
whose
attempts
to
apply
evolutionary
reasoning
in
novel
ways
can
raise
skepticism
and
result
in
challenges
for
which
they
are
not
prepared.
My
own
fieldwork
suggests
that
the
time
constraints
and
requests
for
non-EvoS
member
contributions
seem
to
encourage
such
terse
challenges,
more
than
might
unfold
if
the
sessions
were
allowed
to
develop
more
freely.
The
modes
of
defense
that
I
outline
above
have
become
regularized
ways
of
dismissing,
deflecting,
or
assimilating
audience
criticisms.
These
practices
can
additionally
create
new
foregroundings,
direct
attention
to
in-house
ideologies,
or
reaffirm
the
programs
first
principle
as
ways
to
deal
with
challenges
to
the
integrity
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
In
this
sense,
EvoS
lecturers
and
moderators
can
make
use
of
audience
critics
as
real-time
examples
of
the
academic
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Certainly,
this
particular
resource
is
a
capricious
one,
but
considering
the
examples
I
offer
above
(including
the
Tiger
Incident
at
SUNY
New
Paltz),
the
lecturers
and
moderators
of
the
program
(if
not
much
more
of
the
membership)
have
sufficiently
internalized
the
in-house
ideologies
of
EvoS
that
audience
critics
are
recognized
as
embodiments
of
this
academic
rejection.
248
The
SUNY
New
Paltz
EvoS
Program
(modeled
almost
exactly
to
the
Binghamton
program)
includes
many
of
the
same
modes
of
defense
that
I
outline
in
this
chapter,
as
well
as
the
foregrounding-contextualization
patterns
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Four.
It
is
a
similar
if
more
extreme
example
of
Seminar
Series
critics
becoming
resources
for
this
social
movement.
As
I
describe
above,
the
organizers
of
the
New
Paltz
EvoS
Program
went
so
far
as
to
investigate
the
causes
for
the
skepticism
they
encountered,
in
essence
making
their
academic
critics
into
parts
of
a
science
experiment.
Publishing
and
popularizing
their
findings,
these
researchers
use
such
opportunities
to
creatively
index
the
in-house
ideologies
of
EvoS
and
its
first
principle.
They
have
used
criticisms
of
their
own
programs
ideologies
to
create
new
avenues
for
promoting
the
movement
and
dissemination
of
its
message.
Lastly,
I
point
out
that
these
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
function
to
socialize
students
into
the
activities,
relationships,
ideologies,
and
first
principle
of
EvoS.
They
see
how
criticism
of
evolutionary
reasoning
tends
to
be
formulated
and
how
such
interactions
are
likely
to
unfold.
In
this
sense,
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
perform
the
challenges
faced
by
evolutionary
science
in
higher
education
they
bring
to
life
the
in-house
ideologies
of
the
program.
Further,
as
in
most
other
academic
events,
students
are
here
shown
the
spaces
and
times
that
their
contributions
are
expected.
For
the
time
being,
they
are
asked
to
observe
while
(typically)
faculty
and
graduate
students
in
the
audience
engage
the
lecturer
and
EvoS
moderator
in
critical
discussions.
Of
course,
such
criticisms
and
confrontations
are
an
expected
part
of
academic
discussions.
These
interactions
are
demonstration
for
undergraduate
249
participants
in
how
to
meaningfully
engage
with
visiting
lecturers
and
faculty.
Indeed,
this
is
one
of
the
primary
compliments
paid
to
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
by
both
the
programs
founder
and
some
of
its
visiting
lecturers.
However,
during
my
fieldwork,
I
also
witnessed
a
dramatic
drop
in
the
number
of
faculty
and
graduate
student
participants
in
the
Seminar
Series.
In
interviews,
former
participants
voiced
displeasure
with
what
they
perceived
as
unproductive
and
even
rude
responses
to
their
critiques.
I
also
witnessed
this
dissatisfaction
among
undergraduates
who
were
largely
annoyed
by
a
particular
visiting
speaker.
Many
students
discussed
complained
to
me
and
one
another
that
the
lecture
was
condescending,
unscientific,
and
even
offensive.
But
their
complaints
were
not
part
of
the
following
Question
and
Answer
Session,
nor
were
they
heard
at
the
subsequent
Social
Event.
Although
most
were
roundly
unimpressed
with
the
logic
and
conclusions
of
this
lecture,
once
they
were
presented
with
the
opportunity
to
voice
these
complaints,
they
chose
not
to.
Instead
they
asked
superficial,
non-confrontational
questions
or
remained
quiet.
When
I
enquired
afterwards,
students
explained
that
they
did
not
have
the
right
to
criticize
a
professional
researcher.
These
experiences
are
obviously
problematic,
considering
the
bold
convictions
(of
the
organizers
and
promotions)
that
EvoS
provides
numerous
opportunities
for
critical
thinking
and
open
discussion.
Still
more
troubling
is
the
abandonment
of
the
program
by
disgruntled
graduate
students
and
faculty,
who
might
otherwise
have
inspired
more
interrogation
by
student
participants.
Though
the
consequence
is
not
a
desirable
one,
the
time
limits,
methods
of
moderation,
and
250
modes
of
defense
of
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions
may
socialize
students
to
contribute
in
ways
that
do
not
cause
confrontation.
In
the
next
chapter,
I
investigate
how
student
participation
takes
shape
in
the
following
Social
Events.
251
Chapter
Six:
Practice,
Demonstration,
and
Criticism
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
Social
Events
In
this
chapter,
I
examine
the
Social
Events
that
follow
the
EvoS
Seminar
Lectures
and
Question
and
Answer
sessions.
I
argue
that
these
activities
include
a
rather
complicated
set
of
patterns:
First,
in
the
Social
Events,
students
are
encouraged
to
practice
creating
the
types
of
foregrounding-contextualizations
that
visiting
speakers
created
during
their
lectures
(discussed
in
Chapter
Four),
and
to
further
analogically
extend
evolutionary
reasoning
toward
previously
unrelated
ideologies.
These
patterns
(when
performed
by
students)
tend
to
omit
the
in-house
ideologies
of
the
EvoS
Program,
which
are
likely
not
especially
meaningful
to
them.
If
these
students
contributions
do
not
reaffirm
the
EvoS
first
principle,
lecturers
will
correct
them,
adding
the
affirmation
and
typically
analogical
extensions
as
well.
If
they
have
successfully
affirmed
the
first
principle
and
analogically
extended
evolutionary
reasoning,
lecturers
praise
these
students,
and
furthermore
help
them
to
further
analogically
extend
it
by
creating
new
foregroundings
off
of
these
students
contextualizations.
To
this
end,
EvoS
lecturers
and
moderators
are
guiding
these
students
toward
a
particular
way
of
expressing
their
commitment
to
both
the
program
and
evolutionary
reasoning
more
broadly.
Second,
in
these
Social
Events,
lecturers
and
moderators
further
demonstrate
foregrounding-contextualization
patterns
for
the
benefit
of
other
252
attendees.
As
I
show,
these
foregroundings
are
often
unsubtle
attacks
on
academic
structure,
especially
ribald
taboo
topicalizations,
and
quite
intimately
personal
testimonies,
none
of
which
would
likely
have
been
appropriate
in
the
Seminar
Series
lectures.
These
demonstrations
are
often
quite
elaborate,
including
multiple
foregroundings
and
contextualizations
in
succession.
Importantly,
as
I
show
below,
these
individuals
tend
to
leave
their
final
foregroundings
unresolved,
suggesting
that
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle
has
become
the
presupposed
resolution
to
be
employed
in
this
setting.
Finally,
in
very
few
instances
do
Social
Event
attendees
challenge
the
lecturers
in
ways
comparable
to
the
criticisms
I
detail
in
Chapter
Five.
In
the
examples
I
discuss
here,
lecturers
sometimes
employ
the
modes
of
defense
in
their
responses,
but
typically
they
answer
these
students
challenges
in
ways
that
are
noticeably
more
frank
than
in
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
While
these
patterns
are
similar
to
other
activities
in
the
Seminar
Series
(outlined
in
my
previous
chapters),
they
are
different
because
the
Social
Events
are
marked
by
a
general
tone
of
camaraderie,
informality,
and
openness
among
many
of
the
participants.
These
events
are
a
surprisingly
warm
and
welcoming
experience
for
many
visiting
lecturers,
considering
they
share
a
sense
that
evolutionary
reasoning
has
been
widely
rejected
and
ignored
throughout
U.S.
higher
education.
Generally,
I
found
in
my
fieldwork
that
the
Social
Events
offer
a
sensation
that
one
is
in
the
fold
here,
participants
can
speak
freely
about
evolutionary
reasoning,
without
professional
reprisals
or
outsider
criticism.
253
The Social Events are a particular favorite activity for David Sloan Wilson,
who
wished
them
to
recreate
the
kinds
of
solidarity
and
excitement
he
experienced
in
graduate
school.
He
fondly
recalls
participating
in
a
similar
initiative
as
the
Seminar
Series:
Our
little
group
was
not
prestigious,
consisting
of
only
a
few
young
professors
and
their
students,
but
we
were
brash
and
not
intimidated
by
even
the
greatest
authorities
of
our
day.
Most
evolutionists
are
wonderfully
egalitarian
and
even
the
most
eminent
would
cheerfully
come
to
East
Lansing
to
talk
about
their
work
for
little
more
than
their
travel
expenses.
My
fellow
graduate
students
and
I
would
often
set
upon
them
like
a
team
of
young
lawyers,
challenging
them
on
every
point.
They
in
turn
would
be
pleased
that
their
work
had
generated
so
much
interest,
and
when
we
left
the
biology
building
it
was
merely
to
continue
the
conversation
over
dinner
and
beer
at
the
house
of
one
of
the
professors.
Work
merged
with
play,
and
the
people
with
whom
I
worked
were
the
same
as
those
with
whom
I
enjoyed
relaxing.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007:340-341]
But,
as
I
discuss
below,
the
EvoS
Social
Events
are
different
Wilsons
recollections
of
his
graduate
schooling,
because
student
attendance
and
participation
are
required
at
the
former,
in
order
to
successfully
pass
the
Current
Topics
course.
In
this
sense,
the
Social
Events
oblige
the
EvoS
Program
to
adhere
to
certain
institutional
obligations,
such
as
taking
attendance,
facilitating
discussions,
and
grading
student
participation.
Meeting
such
obligations
requires
significant
structure
and
energy
on
behalf
of
EvoS
organizers.
Like the EvoS Program in general, the Social Events strike a tense balance,
254
censor
themselves.
On
the
other
hand,
a
large
percentage
of
these
Social
Event
participants
are
not
only
required
to
attend,
but
also
to
ask
questions
and
discuss
their
ideas,
lest
they
lose
points
or
fail
the
course.
That
said,
it
is
not
so
different
than
any
other
activity
within
this
social
movement,
as
its
participants
are
continuously
striking
this
balance
between
adhering
and
subverting
the
norms
of
higher
education.
255
asked
to
form
discussion
groups
and
submit
summaries
of
the
discussions
that
take
place
during
the
event.
At
other
times,
organizers
have
assigned
students
to
groups
and
required
them
to
jointly
decide
on
a
question
for
the
visiting
lecturer,
to
be
asked
by
a
group
leader
a
role
that
will
have
been
filled
by
every
member
of
the
group,
at
least
once,
by
the
semesters
end.
During
a
few
semesters,
student
participation
was
more-or-less
left
open
to
each
individual,
although
this
(predictably)
led
to
some
students
regular
contribution
to
discussion,
while
others
remained
silent
for
the
entire
semester.
Like
the
Seminar
Series
lectures,
an
attendance
sheet
is
circulated
around
the
Social
Event
for
students
to
sign
in,
thus
ensuring
that
course
participants
are
at
least
physically
present
(unless
friends
sign
their
names
for
them,
which
doubtlessly
takes
place).
Pizza
and
Beer.
From
its
inception
in
2004,
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
garnered
a
notable
reputation
at
Binghamton
for
offering
free
food
(typically
pizza)
and
beer
to
its
participants.
David
Sloan
Wilson
is
well
known
among
Seminar
Series
participants
as
a
lover
of
dark
beers
such
as
Guinness
Stout,
and
additionally
enjoys
patronizing
independent
breweries
in
Upstate
New
York.
The
Seminar
Series
Social
Events
have
typically
followed
his
tastes,
with
a
cooler
full
of
40
or
more
bottles
of
high-quality
beers.
As
the
Current
Topics
course
grew
to
over
80
undergraduate
enrollees,
this
meant
a
much
greater
expense,
as
well
as
attending
to
the
legal
drinking
ages
of
many
of
the
students.
Wilsons
graduate
students
and
office
staff
needed
to
book
large
rooms,
handle
delivery
payments,
ensure
that
the
food
remained
hot
(and
the
beer
cold),
provide
plates
and
utensils,
and
so
on.
Organizational
problems
developed
as
this
large
group
of
students
would
arrive
at
256
the
Social
Event
en
masse
(sometimes
bringing
friends),
and
immediately
begin
lining
up
for
pizza
and
beverages.
These
problems
were
likely
inevitable
for
a
course
of
this
size,
and
particularly
unsurprising
for
one
that
provides
such
staple
sustenance
of
university
students
for
free!
On
this
note,
it
would
not
be
overly
cynical
to
suggest
that
these
rewards
for
students
have
been
incentives
to
contribute
to
the
Social
Event
discussion,
and
also
to
attraction
for
enrolling
in
Current
Topics
course
which,
as
I
have
pointed
out,
requires
students
to
enroll
as
members
of
the
EvoS
Program.
While
a
further
point
might
be
obvious,
the
injection
of
alcohol
into
these
events
is
an
element
that
should
not
be
underestimated.
Not
only
does
the
beer
function
to
(psychologically)
break
down
the
inhibitions
of
students
who
might
otherwise
not
participate
in
discussions,
but
also
its
very
presence
lends
the
Social
Events
a
distinctly
club-like
tone.
Since
most
of
these
students
(and
certainly
David
Sloan
Wilson)
associate
beer
with
socialization
among
friends,
its
capacity
to
lighten
the
mood
of
ostensibly
academic
interactions
has
likely
shaped
their
outcomes
in
powerful
ways.
The
Role
of
the
Founder.
David
Sloan
Wilsons
presence
and
participation
are
important
influences
in
obliging
students
to
participate
in
Social
Event
discussions,
for
a
number
of
reasons.
As
I
have
observed,
some
students
enrolled
in
Current
Topics
are
also
cooperating
with
Wilson
in
his
various
research
projects.
It
is
unsurprising
that
such
students
regularly
contribute
to
these
discussions
without
extra
prompting.
They
have
surely
spoken
with
Wilson
(and
likely
the
visiting
lecturer)
previously,
probably
feeling
that
they
have
relevant
ideas
to
offer,
257
and
might
also
be
interested
in
impressing
Wilson
and
his
colleagues.
This
is
an
opportunity
that
Wilson
is
quick
to
point
out
in
one
Social
Event,
commenting:
I
really
want
to
emphasize
what
an
extraordinary
opportunity
this
is
especially
for
undergraduate
students
to
be
participating
in
intellectual
life
at
the
same
level
as
graduate
students
and
faculty
especially
undergraduate
students
who
are
contemplating
going
to
graduate
school
you
are
going
to
be
learning
what
graduate
school
is
like
what
it
is
like
to
basically
be
engaged
in
intellectual
inquiry
for
its
own
sake
and
to
be
dealing
only
with
the
best
and
the
brightest45
As
might
be
expected,
other
students
are
more
reticent
to
contribute
and
the
Social
Event
discussions
will,
on
occasion,
fall
silent.
Acting
as
moderator
for
most
of
these
events,
Wilson
will
sometimes
chide
the
audience,
for
instance
saying
Okay
youve
gotta
be
brain
dead
not
to
have
questions
here
do
I
have
a
volunteer?
At
any
given
Social
Event
discussion,
Wilson
can
be
seen
roaming
about
the
audience,
sometimes
leaning
in
to
inform
individual
students
that
he
will
be
calling
on
them
to
contribute
in
a
few
minutes
time.
As
he
light-heartedly
warns
the
audience
at
one
Social
Event:
Usually
I
have
my
own
microphone
so
often
Ill
go
around
and
often
usually
theres
a
lot
of
questions
but
I
do
reserve
the
right
to
call
upon
people
at
random
and
so
that
puts
everyone
on
edge
right?
Anyone
of
you
-
everyone
of
you
needs
to
come
up
with
a
question
because
I
can
approach
you
and
just
thrust
this
into
your
hand
-
and
theres
nothing
you
can
do
about
it!
Such
assertive
moderating
on
Wilsons
part
is
no
doubt
a
response
to
the
large
class
sizes
of
the
Current
Topics
course,
but
is
unlikely
to
be
witnessed
at
any
other
academic
seminar
series.
This
practice
seems
a
likely
way
to
encourage
students
45
No comment.
258
toward
contributions
that
(in
one
way
or
another)
positively
value
the
explanatory
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning
and
reaffirm
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle.
The moderator role that Wilson plays is also significant for his consistent of
the
Social
Events
to
further
promote
the
EvoS
Program.
His
explanations
at
such
moments
are
likely
intended
for
visiting
lecturers
and
other
attendees
who
are
not
Current
Topics
students.
At
one
Social
Event,
Wilson
informs
the
audience:
The
Current
Topics
course
which
has
to
be
taken
twice
to
earn
the
EvoS
certificate
and
so
the
students
in
that
course
as
those
of
you
who
are
in
the
course
know
read
something
in
preparation
write
something
in
preparations
attend
the
seminar
and
then
attend
this
continuing
discussion
and
we
provide
just
enough
structure
to
force
you
to
do
this
in
terms
of
writing
in
on
time
we
take
attendance
which
makes
it
sound
as
if
the
undergraduates
taking
this
course
are
an
unwilling
bunch
and
theyre
just
here
because
they
have
to
be
here
but
that
is
not
the
case
at
all
The
EvoS
founder
here
is
clearly
ad-libbing
his
introduction
to
the
Current
Topics
course
(for
the
benefit
of
those
not
taking
the
class).
However,
he
here
adds
an
important
piece
of
legitimating
information:
the
undergraduates
in
this
course
are
not
just
here
because
they
have
to
be
here,
but
rather
they
are
responding
to
the
structure
of
a
program
that
they
engage
in,
even
if
there
were
not
rewards.
He
continues:
I
actually
learned
something
by
studying
religion
that
religions
often
do
this
they
provide
a
bit
of
structure
and
you
know
they
make
you
go
to
church
but
thats
what
you
want
to
do
and
you
get
a
lot
out
of
it
but
when
you
make
something
voluntary
even
when
you
really
want
to
do
it
because
everyone
is
busy
and
because
other
things
intervene
that
very
often
you
end
up
not
doing
exactly
what
you
want
to
do
and
so
we
provide
just
enough
structure
so
that
we
make
you
do
this
Wilsons
reasoning
here
is
perhaps
a
bit
nave,
but
he
is
speaking
for
the
benefit
of
the
visiting
lecturer
and
others
who
(perhaps)
wonder
just
how
genuinely
259
interested
a
large
group
of
undergraduates
could
be
in
a
semester-long
seminar
series.
Chuckling
to
himself,
Wilson
adds:
And
hell
were
drinkin
beer
at
least
those
of
us
that
are
over
twenty-one
and
were
socializing
what
could
be
better
than
that?...
To
combine
a
pleasant
social
event
and
a
world
class
intellectual
event?
The
founders
enthusiasm
about
the
EvoS
Program
is
palpable
here,
though
there
is
reason
to
suspect
that
he
is
self-consciously
trying
to
legitimate
the
Current
Topics
course
for
his
listeners,
as
well
as
the
markedly
large
audiences
that
it
provides
for
the
Seminar
Series.
A
similar
kind
of
qualification
appears
when,
writing
about
the
series,
Wilson
recalls
how
his
colleagues
lecture
was
followed
by
a
boisterous
reception
with
pizza
and
beer,
which
in
turn
was
followed
by
a
continuing
discussion
attended
by
over
sixty
graduate
and
undergraduate
students,
who
surrounded
[the
lecturer]
in
a
big
semicircle.
They
are
taking
a
course
designed
around
the
seminar
series
that
has
become
hugely
popular,
and
there
was
nothing
required
about
the
spontaneous
applause
that
ended
the
discussion.
[D.S.
Wilson
2007:346]
Arguably,
Wilson
is
here
(and
above)
making
too
much
of
rather
usual
practices
in
an
academic
seminar,
such
as
students
sitting
around
a
lecturer
or
applauding
once
the
discussion
has
ended.
To
this
end,
Wilson
is
arguing
that
the
presupposed
behaviors
of
interpersonal,
quasi-formal,
academic
activities
are
(in
fact)
indexing
students
unrestrained
enthusiasm
for
the
subject
matter
and
evolutionary
reasoning
in
general.
His
intention
here
is
clearly
toward
promotion.
But,
there
is
reason
to
anticipate
that
such
enthusiasm
is
(for
some
participants)
quite
genuine.
260
2.
Student
Practice
and
Lecturer
Guidance
From my observations of the Social Events, it seems clear that these are
activities
in
which
audience
members
from
the
Seminar
Series
lectures
are
encouraged
to
practice
the
foregrounding-contextualization
patterns
that
I
describe
in
Chapter
Four.
Their
contributions
often
include
complaints
about
higher
education,
taboo
topics,
and
personal
testimonies
that
they,
themselves,
attempt
to
resolve
through
an
application
of
evolutionary
reasoning
typically
drawing
from
what
they
have
learned
from
the
present
lecturer,
previous
speakers,
and
David
Sloan
Wilson.
Significantly,
these
student
contributions
are
often
then
corrected
by
the
visiting
lecturer
or
Seminar
Series
moderator,
who
will
typically
instruct
the
student
on
the
appropriate
way
to
apply
evolutionary
reasoning
and
reaffirm
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle.
As
I
will
show
below,
sometimes
student
contributions
reach
this
affirmation
without
lecturer
or
moderator
assistance,
in
which
case
the
student
is
praised.
I want to stress two caveats from the outset: First, these practice-correction
episodes
are
of
course
not
the
only
types
of
participant
interactions
in
the
Social
Events,
or
the
only
kinds
of
contributions
made
to
discussions
there.
Often
students
will
ask
visiting
lecturers
to
clarify
some
complicated
issue
in
their
theories
or
discuss
research
methods.
First,
as
I
will
show
in
a
later
session,
Social
Event
participants
also
occasionally
raise
challenging
criticisms
during
Social
Event
discussions,
demonstrating
that
they
have
not
been
persuaded
(or
have
actually
been
offended)
by
the
lecturers
arguments.
Second,
by
proposing
these
practice-
correction
interactions
are
common
in
EvoS
Social
Events,
neither
I
am
suggesting
261
that
they
are
anything
totally
out
of
the
ordinary
for
higher
education.
A
great
deal
of
the
business
of
higher
education
is
teaching
and
learning.
It
is
not
unreasonable
to
suggest
that
many
students
are
not
just
interested
in
learning
the
information
presented
in
a
course,
but
also
in
demonstrating
that
they
can
apply
it
in
new
ways.
If
they
are
mistaken,
an
instructor
will
correct
them.
What
distinguishes
these
interactions
from
others
in
university
practice
is
the
reappearance
of
the
EvoS
Programs
foregroundings,
in-house
ideologies,
and
contextualizations
here
enacted
by
a
broader
set
of
participants
than
I
have
so
far
shown.
Example
1a
(Lecturer
guides
student):
Dont
say
you
believe
in
evolution.
In
this
example,
the
preceding
lecturer
dealt
with
the
relationship
between
evolutionary
science
and
literary
criticism,
particularly
as
the
latter
has
offered
critical
histories
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
During
her
lecture,
the
visiting
speaker
challenged
arguments
of
evolution
as
narrative
for
example,
that
evolutionary
theories
of
human
origins
are
heroic
tales,
thus
reflecting
the
patriarchal
socio-
political
circumstances
of
the
time
and
place
in
which
they
were
written
(see
Landau
1991).
Such
proposals
tend
to
question
the
scientific
factuality
of
human
evolutionary
theories,
which
was
this
speakers
problem
with
them.
During
the
following
Social
Event,
a
contributing
student
generally
agrees
with
the
speaker,
explaining:
I
wanted
to
push
the
issue
that
evolution
is
a
narrative
which
Ive
heard
from
some
of
my
Comp
Lit
professors
and
I
guess
I
partially
agree
though
I
dont
think
that
its
just
another
story
you
cant
just
make
up
any
story
you
want
262
This
student
is
more
or
less
complaining
about
her
Comparative
Literature
instructors
postmodernist
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
just
another
story
among
other
possible
explanations.
Doing
so,
she
is
indexing
an
in-house
ideology
of
the
EvoS
Program,
similar
to
several
comments
made
by
the
lecturer
during
her
earlier
talk.
As
the
student
continues,
she
attempts
a
more
conciliatory
reading
of
the
problem:
What
bothers
me
is
there
is
the
assumption
that
narrative
is
inherently
untrue
is
a
fiction
because
to
my
mind
you
know
I
believe
in
evolution
but
I
believe
that
evolution
is
a
narrative
that
has
changed
over
time
Im
wondering
if
theres
something
about
the
word
narrative
If
we
use
paradigm
maybe
why
does
the
word
narrative
necessarily
imply
fiction?
The
visiting
lecturer
is
impressed
with
this
students
contribution,
although
her
praise
is
much
more
an
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation:
Hmm
I
hadnt
thought
about
that
its
an
interesting
point
Im
a
fiction
addict
I
read
a
lot
of
novels
all
the
time
and
I
guess
I
dont
see
anything
wrong
if
we
talk
about
evolution
as
a
narrative
But
I
want
to
know
how
narrative
began
you
know
the
origins
of
narrative
as
an
adaptation
thats
the
story
that
I
want
to
know
To
some
degree,
the
lecturer
has
accepted
and
praised
the
student,
although
she
is
clear
to
remind
her
that
evolutionary
reasoning
explains
the
origins
of
all
others.
This
is
not
only
an
affirmation
of
the
foundational
explanatory
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
but
also
an
analogical
extension
of
it
toward
explaining
narrative
story
telling.
Importantly,
the
lecturer
argues
that
whether
or
not
we
think
of
evolution
as
a
narrative,
evolutionary
reasoning
provides
the
foundational
story
(that
would
explain
why
other
stories
are
told).
263
As
if
to
hammer
home
this
final
point,
the
lecturer
is
also
sure
to
correct
the
student
on
another
matter:
And
if
I
could
I
just
make
one
little
Dont
say
you
believe
in
evolution
Lets
say
you
think
the
scientific
approach
is
probably
the
most
convincing
explanation
But
the
word
believe
is
I
think
misused
in
the
case
of
science
I
just
dont
want
to
use
the
language
of
belief
in
science
On
this
comment,
the
student
agrees
with
the
lecturer,
commenting
Yes
yeah
it
implies
a
kind
of
fiction
The
lecturer
has
here
corrected
the
student
on
her
word
choice,
which
she
seems
to
suggest
is
inappropriate
for
its
implication
that
science
is
something
to
be
believed
or
disbelieved
(somewhat
ironic,
given
the
earlier
theme
of
this
interaction).
As
I
suggest
above,
the
students
contribution
has
been
more-or-less
satisfactory
to
the
lecturer
as
a
demonstration
of
her
belief
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
a
relevant
matter
to
consider
in
literary
studies.
The
lecturers
subsequent
remarks
more
fully
affirmed
the
EvoS
first
principle
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
to
be
considered
the
foundational
narrative,
analogically
extended
to
explain
the
origins
of
narrative
as
an
adaptation.
Example
1b
(Lecturer
guides
student):
There
have
always
been
people
killing
people.
In
this
second
example
of
a
lecturers
correction
of
a
students
contribution,
a
young
man
asks
a
follow-up
question
about
the
lecturers
previous
talk
on
evolutionary
reasoning
in
moral
psychology.
In
that
talk,
the
visiting
speaker
posed
a
number
of
innate
psychological
mechanisms
that
inform
philosophers
that
there
are
foundational
truths
to
be
found
about
the
human
condition,
but
that
these
are
facts
264
about
the
adaptations
that
benefited
Homo
sapiens
evolutionary
ancestors.
The
student
poses
this
contribution:
Youve
said
that
we
can
find
cases
where
our
instincts
serve
us
wrong
like
with
food
with
overindulgence
where
people
eat
more
fats
now
than
they
did
in
the
Stone
Age
and
maybe
our
instincts
as
far
as
loyalty
or
inter-group
violence
that
kind
of
thing
these
find
cases
where
our
instincts
serve
us
wrong
and
so
philosophers
can
find
moral
universals
The
lecturer
agrees
that
these
are,
indeed,
cases
where
human
instincts
have
served
them
wrong.
Clearly,
the
student
is
making
an
argument
about
maladaptation
(which
also
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Two),
wherein
contemporary
environments
and
behaviors
do
not
match
because
the
behaviors
were
adaptations
to
a
now
no-
longer-existing
environment
(i.e.
the
Stone
Age).
The
student
then
poses
Then
that
kind
of
implies
that
there
is
an
external
absolute
truth
outside
of
our
own
instincts
that
is
outside
the
power
of
evolution
to
change
The
lecturer
here
objects,
as
the
student
has
(rather
clumsily)
posed
an
argument
that
challenges
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation.
The
lecturer
responds:
No
no
I
think
that
philosophers
need
to
recognize
that
we
have
an
evolved
architecture
which
was
not
optimized
to
work
well
in
every
single
setting
It
was
optimized
to
work
as
well
as
it
could
work
across
the
whole
range
of
settings
in
which
it
was
expected
to
work
so
even
in
the
ancestral
environment
there
have
always
been
people
killing
people
over
misunderstandings
when
they
could
have
easily
forgiven
each
other
there
have
always
been
people
who
resist
changing
things
because
they
are
afraid
for
their
families
So
liberal
academics
in
general
need
to
understand
this
too
these
biological
systems
are
never
expected
to
be
perfect
The
lecturers
response
here
is
far
more
of
an
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life:
Philosophy
should
be
informed
by
the
265
universal
architecture
(of
human
brains)
that
predispose
people
to
make
poor
decisions
because
these
organs
were
adaptations
to
selection
pressures
in
the
ancestral
environment.
In
this
sense,
the
student
was
wrong
to
propose
that
any
absolute
truth
outside
our
own
instincts
could
be
found
that
would
somehow
be
beyond
the
explanatory
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
Moreover,
as
is
clear
here,
the
lecturer
has
extended
the
explanatory
potential
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
argue
it
as
relevant
to
liberal
academics
in
general.
That
is,
because
resistance
to
socio-political
change
is
an
inherent
part
of
the
evolved
architecture
of
morality,
Left-leaning
individuals
would
be
wise
to
use
such
evolutionary
reasoning
to
understand
the
social
and
psychological
decisions
of
conservatives.
Example
1c
(Lecturer
guides
student):
The
predators
are
wrapped
up
in
blue
suits
In
this
example,
a
student
is
praised
for
using
evolutionary
reasoning
to
try
to
explain
a
public
health
issue.
During
the
preceding
lecture,
the
visiting
speaker
discussed
the
problem
of
contaminated
food
and
water
supplies.
He
argued
that
the
physiological
effects
of
such
contaminants
were
best
explained
as
a
mismatch
between
the
types
of
toxins
that
human
bodies
are
adapted
to
tolerate
and
those
that
people
encounter
in
the
present
day.
Upon
hearing
his
lecture,
a
student
comments
at
the
following
Social
Event:
I
was
right
away
reminded
of
this
really
blunt
incident
back
in
China
last
year
of
tainted
melons
so
after
listening
to
your
lecture
and
you
also
mentioned
how
these
biochemical
factors
from
our
food
from
our
environment
also
influence
behavior
because
toxins
like
the
ones
in
these
melons
we
wouldnt
have
encountered
ten
thousand
years
ago
so
Im
interested
how
do
you
think
your
discoveries
and
your
methods
could
frame
into
corporate
responsibility?
266
The
speaker
is
vocally
impressed
with
the
students
question,
and
responds:
I
must
say
I
have
really
enjoyed
the
tenor
and
intensity
of
these
questions
greatly
because
they
stretch
my
mind
for
what
we
might
need
to
do
in
the
world
I
suspect
as
our
culture
grows
more
and
more
complex
with
more
and
more
innovations
and
other
kinds
of
tools
were
going
to
have
to
explore
experiment
and
test
interventions
that
would
reduce
the
corporate
greed
and
predatory
behavior
its
nothing
short
of
predation
its
basically
anti-social
behavior
preying
on
other
people
for
economic
gain
and
well
need
to
understand
predation
its
just
that
the
predators
are
wrapped
up
in
blue
suits
nice
blue
suits
-
Armani
blue
suits
Interestingly,
the
speaker
has
here
like
the
student
he
responds
to
affirmed
the
explanatory
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
but
additionally
created
an
analogical
extension
from
evolutionary
reasoning
to
white-collar
crime.
That
is,
as
he
argues,
corporate
greed
is
comparable
to
non-human
predators,
and
understanding
how
predation
works
will
provide
the
foundation
for
policy
interventions.
Example
1d
(Lecturer
guides
student):
Joshua
Thank
you
for
peeing
in
the
potty.
In
this
example,
a
lecturer
has
just
spoken
on
evolutionary
educational
theories,
which
are
critical
of
teacher
over-involvement
with
students
learning,
particularly
when
teachers
over
praise
children
for
unexceptional
things.
Rather,
the
lecturer
argued,
children
should
be
allowed
to
learn
in
ways
that
allow
them
to
fail,
thus
creating
a
process
of
selection
among
the
strategies
they
learn
for
the
future
(see
D.S.
Wilson
b;
D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2011).
At
the
following
Social
Event,
a
student
offers
a
personal
testimony
that
supports
this
argument:
I
went
to
a
high
school
where
they
used
positive
reinforcement
all
the
time
they
had
an
awards
ceremony
and
everyone
got
an
award
for
everything
you
know
most
improvement
most
this
most
that
and
I
also
went
to
one
of
those
school
districts
where
you
know
theres
a
lot
of
wealthy
parents
where
if
the
kid
didnt
get
an
A
they
called
up
the
teacher
and
there
was
a
lot
of
pressure
on
the
school
to
inflate
267
grades
so
do
you
ever
think
its
possible
that
theres
too
much
positive
reinforcement?
that
we
isnt
it
okay
to
sometimes
let
kids
fail
and
isnt
that
the
way
that
humans
probably
used
to
do
things?
-
to
say
honestly
they
really
did
a
better
job
than
you
so
maybe
you
should
work
a
little
harder
The
student
here
offers
his
version
of
a
foregrounding,
similar
to
those
observable
in
the
Seminar
Series
lectures.
His
story
of
overused
positive
reinforcement
also
evokes
a
number
of
nods
and
chuckles
from
other
students
in
the
room,
who
seem
familiar
with
the
situation
themselves.
In
his
own
way,
this
statement
additionally
contextualizes
the
problems
presented
in
his
personal
narrative
by
asking
isnt
this
the
way
that
humans
probably
used
to
do
things?
Given
that
this
is
almost
precisely
what
the
visiting
speaker
argued
during
his
earlier
lecture,
it
is
not
likely
that
he
will
disagree.
He
does
not,
and
furthermore
praises
the
student,
both
directly
and
with
a
bit
of
humor:
The
answer
is
yes
and
youre
absolutely
right
But
let
me
backtrack
the
first
assumption
is
that
what
you
experienced
at
that
school
was
positive
reinforcement
it
wasnt
it
was
hot
air
it
was
the
equivalent
of
telling
a
thirteen
year
old
boy
The
lecturer
at
this
moment
turns
to
face
the
student
and
asks
him
his
name.
The
student
tells
him
his
name
is
Joshua.
The
lecturer
then
says:
Joshua
thank
you
for
peeing
in
the
potty
At
this
point,
the
audience
begins
to
laugh
at
the
speakers
remark,
which
he
delivers
in
a
high
school
marm
voice.
In
the
spirit
of
the
joke,
the
student
replies,
No
problem!
The
lecturer
continues:
It
is
not
appropriate
to
say
to
a
thirteen
year
thank
you
for
peeing
in
the
potty
because
a
thirteen
year
old
boy
because
a
thirteen
year
old
boy
does
know
that
peeing
in
the
potty
is
where
you
do
it
hes
learned
it
now
thirteen
year
old
boys
sometimes
forget
one
to
lift
the
lid
and
two
to
put
the
lid
down
but
thats
a
different
problem
268
By
this
point
the
audience
is
laughing
out
loud,
including
the
student
who
made
the
initial
contribution.
The
lecturer
has
here
created
a
taboo
topic
of
sorts,
although
there
seems
no
need
to
resolve
it.
The
student
has
apparently
satisfactorily
demonstrated
his
ability
to
apply
evolutionary
reasoning
(albeit
in
a
cursory
manner)
to
explain
problems
that
he
experienced
in
his
own
life.
In
this
sense,
the
student
has
performed
the
analogical
extension
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
assess
problems
in
U.S.
primary
schools
such
as
empty
rewards,
grade
inflation,
and
over-
protective
parents.
typically
do
not
index
the
EvoS
in-house
ideologies
in
their
discussion
contributions.
Rather
they
create
foregroundings
of
their
own
(from
the
personal
experiences
and
knowledge
about
current
events)
and
attempt
to
contextualize
them
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Arguably,
this
is
because
they
do
not
feel
the
kinds
of
professional
grievances
that
are
more-or-less
commonplace
among
the
lecturers
and
organizers
of
the
EvoS
Program.
That
is,
while
they
have
heard
about
the
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education,
they
have
few
(if
any)
actual
experiences
that
might
make
it
real
for
them.
Student contributions of this kind are key to the EvoS Programs first
269
readings
on
the
subject)
readily
agree
upon
three
likely
scenarios
that
that
make
infanticide
adaptive.
These
three
explanations
are,
Wilson
explains,
the
primary
explanations
that
evolutionary
scientists
have
developed
to
explain
this
phenomenon.
Wilson
ponders:
How
did
my
students
become
so
smart?
They
hadn't
read
anything
on
infanticide,
and
I
certainly
hope
that
they
hadn't
experienced
it
for
themselves.
Their
evolutionary
training
had
only
just
begun,
but
even
a
tiny
bit
enabled
them
to
become
experts,
honing
in
like
heat-seeking
missiles
on
the
predictions
that
are
made
by
the
experts.
That
is
the
power
of
natural
selection
thinking
that
makes
it
such
a
big
deal.
[2007:19]
The
contributions
made
by
students
to
the
Social
Events
suggest
that
there
is
some
validity
to
Wilsons
reflection.
However,
considering
the
various
rewards,
encouragement,
organization,
correction,
and
praise
that
I
have
documented
so
far,
this
process
of
embracing
evolutionary
reasoning
is
a
more
complexly
discursive
one
than
Wilsons
rather
simple
example.
The
Social
Events
demonstrate
how
many
mundane
resources
and
energy
must
be
expended
to
encourage
even
the
most
cursory
participation
in
a
social
movement.
Further,
they
show
us
how
unpredictable
such
activities
can
be,
in
a
sociolinguistic
sense,
in
that
the
amateur
participants
of
such
a
group
do
not
share
the
same
knowledge
or
motivations
of
longer-term
members,
but
rather
make
sense
of
the
movement
in
new
ways
that
may
or
may
not
contribute
to
its
first
principle.
In
talking
with
undergraduates
in
the
Current
Topics
course,
I
found
that
most
juxtaposed
evolutionary
reasoning
to
creationism,
and
some
had
actually
attended
schools
where
teachers
and
parents
protested
their
school
boards
for
not
including
Intelligent
Design
theories
in
science
curricula.
Several
other
informants
explained
270
to
me
that
they
were
not
especially
interested
in
evolutionary
science,
but
found
themselves
enrolled
in
a
number
of
courses
that
counted
toward
the
EvoS
Certificate,
and
so
figured
it
worthwhile
enroll
in
the
two
semesters
of
Current
Topics
to
complete
the
requirements.
Others
had
more
personal
reasons
for
participating:
three
(unacquainted)
male
students
told
me
that
they
were
interested
in
evolutionary
science
because
they
hoped
to
better
understand
female
psychology.
To
say
the
least,
some
of
these
are
not
factors
that
David
Sloan
Wilson
could
have
predicted
would
influence
student
participation
in
EvoS.
As
is
apparent
from
student
contributions,
patterns
of
foregrounding-
contextualization
that
are
regularly
performed
in
EvoS
Seminar
Series
lectures
have
travelled
into
the
Social
Events.
In
these
settings,
they
are
practiced
by
students
and
corrected
(or
praised)
by
senior
members
of
the
program.
In
many
cases,
student
contributions
are
attempts
at
analogically
extending
evolutionary
reasoning
to
explain
their
personal
experiences
and
other
socio-political
phenomena.
Next,
I
examine
how
EvoS
lecturers
and
moderators
at
these
events
further
demonstrate
foregrounding-contextualization
patterns
for
the
benefit
of
attendees.
3.
Further
Lecturer
Foregrounding-Contextualizations
As I suggest above, the Social Events are special settings for EvoS
participants,
because
these
activities
are
outside
the
realm
of
academic
criticism
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
In
these
settings,
students
may
practice
creating
foregroundings,
contextualizing
them
by
analogically
extending
evolutionary
reasoning
to
new
ideologies,
and
receive
instruction
from
EvoS
lecturers
and
271
moderators
all
in
a
gathering
in
which
the
foundational,
explanatory
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
presupposed.
contextualization
patterns
in
the
Social
Events,
many
of
which
would
have
been
inappropriate
in
the
Seminar
Series
lectures.
I
suggest
that
these
instances
can
be
best
understood
as
further
demonstrations
(performed
for
the
benefit
of
students)
of
how
to
think
and
speak
about
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation
of
social
life.
As
I
show
in
the
examples
below,
these
foregroundings
are
often
bitter
attacks
on
academic
structure,
taboo
topicalizations
that
tend
toward
ribald
humor,
and
personal
testimonies
that
divulge
surprisingly
intimate
details
about
the
speakers
own
life.
Unlike
the
student
participants,
the
lecturers
and
moderators
will
often
index
the
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies
in
creating
these
foregroundings.
Further,
these
individuals
foregroundings
are
typically
much
more
complex
and
elongated
than
those
of
the
preceding
lectures.
Importantly,
the
last
foregrounding
of
such
series
often
remains
unresolved
through
any
explicit
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
or
its
foundational,
explanatory
power.
In
this
sense
(like
Example
4d
in
my
fourth
chapter),
these
speakers
do
not
need
to
invoke
the
EvoS
Programs
first
principle,
as
the
foundational
relevance
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
so
thoroughly
presupposed
in
this
setting.
Example
2a:
The
darkness
hides
in
the
shadow
of
the
light.
The
Social
Event
in
this
first
example
follows
a
lecture
on
applying
evolutionary
reasoning
to
policy
reforms
in
business
and
politics.
Through
a
personal
testimony,
the
lecturer
272
explains
to
his
audience
that
he
was
once
a
member
of
the
conservative
youth
group,
Young
Americans
for
Freedom:
the
Y.A.F.
if
youve
ever
heard
of
that
is
somewhere
right
wing
of
Ghingis
Khan
The
audience
laughs
at
the
speakers
comparison.
He
continues
with
his
personal
testimony.
It
is
likely
that
they
are
not
only
amused
by
his
comment,
but
also
at
the
very
fact
that
this
individual
once
belonged
to
a
conservative
youth
group,
given
that
he
now
sports
multiple
earrings
and
other
jewelry,
and
previously
disclosed
to
the
Social
Event
audience
that
he
is
gay.
As
the
audience
chuckles,
the
speaker
continues
more
seriously:
I
actually
have
a
picture
of
me
when
I
was
sixteen
at
a
YAF
meeting
and
the
founder
of
the
YAF
was
an
elected
representative
of
the
House
used
to
rail
against
the
homosexual
conspiracy
and
then
was
arrested
four
years
later
in
a
House
restroom
for
attempting
to
solicit
sex
from
a
sixteen
year
old
boy
Here
several
in
the
audience
gasp,
as
the
lecturers
personal
testimony
has
shifted
into
a
taboo
topic.
Not
only
was
the
founder
of
this
conservative
group
a
hypocritical
opponent
of
the
homosexual
conspiracy,
but
the
young
man
with
whom
he
was
attempting
to
have
sex
when
he
was
arrested
was
the
same
age
as
the
lecturer.
This
leads
him
to
contextualize
this
foregrounding,
gesturing
to
David
Sloan
Wilson
in
the
front
of
the
audience:
And
this
reminds
me
of
a
conversation
that
David
and
I
had
about
the
problem
of
cheaters
in
evolutionary
theory
it
is
common
-
for
people
who
are
engaging
in
a
cheating
strategy
to
site
themselves
in
the
very
protective
or
regulatory
environment
where
people
are
cooperating
and
playing
by
the
rules
and
then
engage
in
cheating
we
saw
this
with
the
Wall
Street
crisis
weve
seen
this
with
lots
of
things
273
Not
only
has
the
speaker
affirmed
evolutionary
reasoning
as
an
explanation
for
his
previous
foregroundings,
but
he
furthermore
extends
that
explanation
to
cheaters
in
other
institutions,
such
as
unethical
Wall
Street
executives.
Given
the
time
that
this
Social
Event
took
place
(in
the
wake
of
the
U.S.
financial
crisis
of
2008),
the
lecturers
reference
is
no
doubt
familiar
to
his
audience.
Concluding
his
commentary,
the
speakers
tone
grows
even
more
serious:
Im
not
quite
sure
how
to
solve
this
problem
but
the
darkness
hides
in
the
shadow
of
the
light
so
this
is
the
issue
of
making
sure
that
the
light
does
not
allow
the
shadow
to
be
present
The
speakers
conclusion
here
carries
the
same
kind
of
urgency
as
his
previous
foregrounding,
although
t
he
explicitly
comments
that
he
is
not
quite
sure
how
to
solve
this
problem.
Although
certainly
the
kinds
of
abusive,
dishonest
behaviors
he
discusses
are
complex
issues
to
confront,
this
more-or-less
unresolved,
final
foregrounding
would
be
contextualized
through
reference
to
evolutionary
reasoning.
To
this
end,
I
propose
that
this
speaker
does
not
do
this
(and
does
not
need
to)
because
this
foundation
is
already
presupposed
from
his
previous
comments,
and
more
broadly
in
the
Social
Event
setting
itself.
Example
2b:
Blah
blah
blah
blah
blah!
In
this
example,
the
visiting
professors
preceding
lecture
dealt
with
fear
and
disgust,
focusing
specifically
on
the
ways
that
certain
qualities
of
human
physiology
(such
as
outward
signs
of
disease
or
mental
illness)
cause
people
to
react
negatively
to
others.
The
lecturer
(a
social
psychology
professor)
posed
an
evolutionary
explanation
for
such
responses:
Fear
or
disgust
toward
the
physically
or
mentally
ill
likely
benefited
the
survival
of
ancestral
humans
in
the
distant
274
past,
and
so
remains
a
common
(if
socio-politically
problematic)
experience
in
the
present.
In
the
following
Social
Event,
the
lecturer
extends
a
similar
kind
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
explain
racial
prejudice
and
violence.
The
commentary
he
presents
here
offers
several
foregrounding-contextualizations
in
succession,
opening
with
a
personal
testimony:
I
grew
up
mostly
in
Pittsburgh
and
so
Pittsburgh
had
its
sort
of
very
Wonder
Bread
sort
of
suburban
areas
and
it
has
its
sort
of
African
American
sort
of
inner
city
area
the
Hill
District
in
Pittsburgh
and
on
Friday
every
once
in
a
while
thered
be
football
games
between
the
suburban
kids
out
in
the
suburbs
and
the
African
American
kids
in
the
inner
city
and
it
wouldnt
be
uncommon
for
there
to
be
some
violence
and
some
hostility
between
the
fans
of
these
two
teams
when
theyd
get
together
for
these
games
But
let
me
ask
you
a
question
what
if
those
games
were
played
on
Saturday
mornings?...
do
you
think
youd
have
the
same
problems?
No
one
in
the
Social
Event
responds
to
the
speakers
question
here,
so
he
rephrases
it:
What
does
darkness
mean
in
terms
of
what
does
darkness
afford?
At
this
point,
an
audience
member
suggests
secrecy?
The
lecturer
continues:
Right
and
that
will
be
one
of
the
things
that
people
will
say
to
you
in
the
dark
you
dont
know
who
might
be
approaching
you
that
you
all
get
more
wary
when
youre
walking
around
unfamiliar
places
in
the
dark
and
even
familiar
places
in
the
dark
thats
when
you
saw
this
particular
threat
pop
up
the
perception
of
the
outgroup
males
being
threatening
there
was
a
cue
out
there
in
the
situation
like
encountering
someone
with
a
face
thats
malformed
engages
sort
of
disease-protective
kinds
of
psychology
that
now
might
lead
to
other
kinds
of
behaviors
that
is
the
nature
of
the
situation
darkness
sort
of
pulls
the
evolved
inclination
out
into
expression
The
speaker
is
here
beginning
to
contextualize
his
personal
testimony,
reasoning
that
the
inter-racial
violence
of
his
hometown
was
due,
in
part,
to
fans
of
opposing
275
sports
teams
encountering
one
another
at
night
(an
evolved
inclination
pulled
out
into
expression).
276
Here,
the
speaker
returns
to
his
contextualization
an
argument
that
evolutionary
reasoning
must
be
recognized
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
inter-group
prejudice.
The
lecturer
has
quite
seamlessly
moved
from
a
criticism
of
evolutionary
reasonings
rejection
by
professional
academics
to
its
urgent
usefulness
for
resolving
socio-political
tension.
The
lecturer
uses
this
last
statement
to
offer
one,
final
attack
on
(what
he
sees
as)
a
broader
naivet
of
anti-racism
campaigns:
Thats
why
people
fail
when
they
say
okay
well
just
take
a
bunch
of
people
from
different
groups
well
put
em
together
and
well
have
a
nice
big
happy
family
where
everyone
will
love
each
other
[he
begins
to
sing]
We
are
the
world
we
are
the
children
Many
in
the
audience
laugh
at
the
speakers
reference
to
a
particularly
cheesy
song
(although
a
good
percentage
of
them
are
probably
too
young
to
know
this
was
not
associated
with
an
anti-racism
campaign).
Notably,
this
final
foregrounding
the
speaker
leaves
unresolved,
and
he
arguably
does
not
need
to
do
so.
The
explanatory
power
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
already
presupposed
in
his
commentary
(and
this
Social
Event
setting).
By
applying
evolutionary
reasoning
to
anti-racism
initiatives,
reformers
could
alleviate
the
kinds
of
ineffectual
naivet
that
he
criticizes
here.
Example
2c:
Its
an
emperor
with
no
clothes.
In
this
example,
a
lecturer
who
spoke
on
the
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
economics
is
in
discussion
with
students
at
the
Social
Event,
where
he
has
outlined
a
current
problem
with
his
discipline.
He
argues
that
academic
economists
do
not
accept
the
possibility
that
humans
are
(by
nature)
capable
of
unselfish
behavior.
The
lecturer
draws
heavily
on
277
arguments
posed
by
David
Sloan
Wilson
that
Homo
sapiens
are
actually
group-
oriented,
and
readily
make
economic
decisions
that
do
not
directly
benefit
their
own
survival
and
reproduction,
but
rather
contribute
to
their
social
group
(see
D.S.
Wilson
2009;
D.S.
Wilson
et
al.
2013).
This
foregrounded
attack
on
his
own
discipline
is
then
taken
up
by
the
Social
Event
moderator
(Wilson),
who
jumps
in:
I
just
want
to
make
clear
this
perspective
is
flying
in
the
face
of
self
regarding
preferences
one
question
I
want
to
ask
or
comment
I
want
to
make
is
to
just
make
crystal
clear
this
concept
of
self
regarding
preferences
we
have
to
keep
in
mind
that
economics
is
the
emperor
with
no
clothes
right?
To
this,
the
lecturer
responds
Yeah,
and
Wilson
continues:
Economic
theory
is
this
huge
gigantic
thing
and
its
an
emperor
with
no
clothes
and
how
did
it
get
that
way?
It
got
that
way
by
privileging
this
sort
of
mathematical
formula
where
in
order
to
proceed
mathematically
you
had
to
make
assumptions
about
human
beings
which
were
absurd
the
way
people
are
could
not
be
included
in
this
mathematical
model
because
then
it
wouldnt
be
practical
and
from
that
beginning
which
was
a
century
ago
As
his
commentary
here
demonstrates,
Wilson
has
taken
this
lecturers
foregrounding
to
greater
extremes,
posing
that
the
working
assumptions
of
the
latters
discipline
are
absurd
for
their
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning.
He
makes
accusations
that
could
not
be
made
in
the
Seminar
Series
lecture,
not
only
because
he
has
interrupted
the
lecturer,
but
also
because
his
attack
is
so
vehement.
278
ever
to
the
kind
of
species
that
we
are
lets
be
clear
about
this
this
is
amazing
when
you
think
about
it
this
state
of
affairs
just
to
appreciate
the
enormity
of
it
and
to
convince
yourself
that
thats
the
way
it
is
is
so
hard
so
complicated
you
know
this
cant
be
true
but
it
is
Even
more
so
than
my
previous
examples,
Wilson
leaves
his
foregroundings
here
almost
entirely
uncontextualized.
In
one
sense,
this
is
unsurprising
because
(as
is
apparent
by
now)
Wilson
is
continuously
championing
this
very
proposition
in
nearly
every
public
appearance
he
makes.
However,
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is
presupposed
in
this
setting,
and
its
relevance
to
resolving
the
problems
of
both
academic
and
non-academic
economics
should
be
obvious
to
all
present.
Example
2d:
If
we
were
all
baboons
wed
be
beating
the
shit
out
of
each
other
In
this
last
example,
a
visiting
lecturer
(also
discussed
in
Example
2b)
has
given
a
talk
about
evolutionary
reasoning
and
moral
philosophy.
In
this
lecturer
(and
the
following
Social
Event)
he
argues
that
U.S.
liberals
need
to
use
evolutionary
reasoning
to
understand
conservatives
value
systems.
These
values,
he
proposes,
reflect
group-level
adaptations
of
ancestral
humans,
and
function
to
enforce
social
hierarchies
that
liberals
tend
to
criticize.
Understanding
these
innate,
social-
psychological
adaptations
will
ground
liberalism
in
evolutionary
knowledge
about
human
nature.
Here,
he
explains:
If
you
took
any
other
species
of
primate
and
stuck
us
all
together
this
room
I
mean
with
food
and
females
and
beer
thered
be
chaos
and
pandemonium
trust
me
if
we
were
all
baboons
wed
be
beating
the
shit
out
of
each
other
279
The
audience
laughs
at
this
lecturers
profanity,
and
likely
also
the
fact
that
he
indexes
the
Social
Event-at-hand
as
an
example
of
the
inherent
orderliness
of
human
(as
opposed
to
baboon)
nature.
He
continues:
but
we
do
this
really
really
well
somehow
were
able
to
live
among
complete
strangers
and
get
along
pretty
well
our
evolved
systems
here
are
sorta
designed
to
make
us
good
group
members
these
systems
are
designed
to
help
us
uh
take
care
of
our
kin
and
develop
profitable
alliances
The
speaker
then
moves
to
analogically
extend
this
affirmation
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
explain
the
values
of
conservatives:
If
you
really
get
into
the
conservative
culture
and
most
importantly
this
is
a
crucial
thing
if
you
can
truly
understand
-
what
these
people
are
after
so
I
dont
think
that
anybody
can
understand
conservatism
unless
they
understand
what
this
stuff
is
about
then
a
lot
of
mystery
will
vanish
However,
like
the
lecturer
in
Example
3b,
this
lecture
interrupts
this
contextualization
to
create
yet
another
foregrounding,
which
he
punctuates
by
pounding
on
the
desk
beside
him
and
yelling:
But
if
you
go
to
conservatives
and
you
say
[pounding
on
a
desk]
This
is
morality!
If
theyre
not
equal
Its
wrong!
Im
right
women
have
to
be
equal
everyone
has
to
be
equal
youre
going
to
get
ignored
and
not
get
anywhere
everywhere
cuz
the
people
youre
studying
dont
agree
with
you
The
lecturers
foregrounding
then
becomes
a
more
explicit
attack
on
liberal
academics:
and
my
sense
from
dealing
with
the
people
who
do
this
is
that
theyre
Marxists
theyre
extreme
liberals
they
dont
get
this
theyre
very
self-righteous
they
think
that
in
every
other
culture
-
that
hierarchy
is
fascism!
Clearly,
the
speakers
foregrounding
here
is
quite
unsubtle.
Not
only
is
he
banging
on
the
desk
at
his
side,
but
he
is
more-or-less
accusing
liberal
academics
of
being
280
fanatical
reactionaries.
This
is
something
like
a
creative
index
of
an
EvoS
in-house
ideology,
insofar
as
participants
tend
to
accuse
this
same
group
of
rejecting
evolutionary
reasoning.
To
this
end,
it
would
seem
that
the
speaker
would,
once
again,
resolve
his
final
foregrounding
by
reaffirming
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
explanation.
But
he
does
not,
because
as
I
have
remarked
before
he
does
not
need
to.
4.
Criticisms
and
their
Consequences
in
the
Social
Event
instances
of
serious
audience
criticism
directed
toward
a
lecturer
that
is,
the
kind
of
criticisms
that
led
to
the
kinds
of
modes
of
defense
that
I
detail
in
my
discussion
of
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
Given
the
general
tenor
of
these
events,
this
relative
absence
of
criticism
is
perhaps
not
surprising.
The
safe
space
of
the
Social
Event
it
seems
is
primarily
defined
by
the
presupposition
shared
by
most
attendees
that
evolutionary
reasoning
offers
foundational
explanations
about
social
life,
and
is
therefore
relevant
across
all
academic
disciplines.
The challenges that I witnessed in the EvoS Social Events came from Current
Topics
students
that
is,
not
from
outsiders,
but
from
individuals
well
versed
in
evolutionary
science
and
familiar
with
the
work
of
the
visiting
lecturer
from
preparatory
readings
for
the
course.
Unsurprisingly,
these
challenges
are
rather
intense,
given
these
students
knowledge
base.
Certainly
this
is
the
case,
and
these
two
instances
(particular
the
second)
caused
significant
tensions
when
they
took
place.
281
However, I am not so much concerned here with the challenges that these
students
offer
as
the
manner
of
response
they
receive
from
visiting
lecturers.
Interestingly,
while
the
modes
of
defense
I
describe
in
Chapter
Five
appear
here
briefly,
these
lecturers
are
astonishingly
straightforward
in
their
replies
to
these
criticisms.
Rather
than
dismissing,
deflecting,
or
attempting
to
assimilate
the
students
challenge,
they
offer
answers
that
are
(for
lack
of
a
better
phrase)
bluntly
honest
responses
that
likely
would
have
avoided
(if
not
more
thoroughly
critiqued)
in
the
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
To
this
end,
I
take
these
responses
as
further
evidence
of
the
safe
space
that
has
been
created
in
this
setting,
and
the
shared
presuppositions
of
participants
within
it.
Example
3a:
Im
not
a
cultural
anthropologist
Im
an
evolutionary
psychologist.
In
this
example,
a
Current
Topics
student
challenges
the
research
assumptions
of
a
visiting
lecturer.
At
the
time,
I
was
sitting
next
to
this
individual,
who
was
previously
a
student
in
a
class
in
which
I
was
a
teaching
assistant.
During
the
Social
Event,
he
was
told
by
the
Social
Event
moderator
(who
was
disappointed
by
poor
participation)
that
he
would
be
expected
to
ask
a
question
in
a
few
minutes
time.
This
student
informed
me
in
the
following
moments
how
much
he
disliked
this
practice,
and
decided
he
was
going
to
use
the
opportunity
to
criticize
(what
he
viewed
as)
weaknesses
in
the
lecturers
research.
Handed the microphone by the EvoS moderator, this student poses to the
lecturer:
All
these
studies
youve
done
they
were
on
Americans
right?...
So
Im
thinking
like
if
you
did
tests
on
other
areas
like
say
a
society
that
is
run
by
communism
do
you
think
the
tests
might
be
different
and
282
youd
have
to
come
to
different
conclusions?...
I
just
wanted
to
know
because
you
havent
done
studies
really
outside
the
U.S.
how
can
you
come
to
conclusions
youre
assuming
that
the
entire
world
will
come
up
with
the
same
answers
but
you
really
havent
tested
it
So?
It
is
important
to
note
that
this
question
is
an
extremely
controversial
matter
in
evolutionary
research.
Many
critics
have
challenged
theorists
claims
that
they
have
uncovered
universal
behaviors
or
values
the
universiality
of
such
phenomena
being
more-or-less
a
precondition
for
an
argument
that
they
are
adaptations
from
a
distant
evolutionary
past
(see
McKinnon
2005a,
2005b;
McCaughey
2008;
Smith
2005:130-152).
These
critics
point
out
that
theories
in
fields
like
evolutionary
psychology
tended
to
assume
such
human
universals,
although
research
is
not
conducted
outside
the
U.S.,
and
sometimes
is
restricted
to
surveys
at
a
single
university.
In
this
sense,
this
student
is
posing
a
challenge
to
adaptationism,
one
of
the
basic
presuppositions
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
EvoS
Program,
as
well.
283
of
a
similar
kind
as
I
detail
in
the
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
Pressed
by
an
exceedingly
difficult
audience
criticism,
speakers
sometimes
make
jokes
at
the
audience
members
expense.
In
this
case,
however,
the
lecturers
attempt
at
humor
has
backfired.
Instead,
he
takes
a
more
assertive
approach:
Okay
-
its
an
entirely
fair
question
I
have
a
couple
of
reactions
nothing
has
actually
been
studied
in
every
single
place
and
in
every
single
kind
of
way
so
Ill
throw
it
back
to
you
and
that
is
why
would
you
expect
a
difference?
The
lecturer
has
here
attempted
posed
a
deflection
to
the
students
criticism,
similar
to
an
example
I
offer
in
Chapter
Five.
He
throws
the
question
back
to
the
student,
rather
than
answering
directly.
However,
the
students
response
is
reasonably
well
founded:
Well
couldnt
it
be
through
kinds
of
cultural
transmission
that
say
in
a
communist
society
theyd
be
brought
up
with
different
values
than
in
America
Interestingly,
in
a
maneuver
that
we
did
not
witness
in
the
Seminar
Series
Question
and
Answer,
the
lecturer
decides
to
give
a
quite
straightforward
explanation:
I
guess
this
sort
of
implicates
my
bias
Im
not
a
cultural
anthropologist
Im
an
evolutionary
psychologist
I
start
from
the
point
of
view
that
were
a
human
animal
and
that
weve
evolved
certain
kind
of
inclinations
that
are
likely
shared
that
exist
so
we
spread
out
across
the
globe
we
develop
these
cultures
and
all
this
kind
of
stuff
thats
relatively
recent
but
weve
sort
of
been
human
and
humanoid
or
whatever
you
wanna
say
for
a
much
longer
time
than
that
so
I
sort
of
presume
at
a
fundamental
level
universality
Responding
to
this
students
rather
intense
criticism,
the
lecturer
attempted
two
modes
of
defense:
First
he
tried
to
dismiss
the
students
challenge
by
pointing
out
his
accent
(a
maneuver
that
failed),
and
second
he
attempts
to
deflect
the
challenge
by
284
throwing
the
question
back
to
the
student
(a
maneuver
which
evokes
a
fairly
lucid,
if
not
equally
challenging
rebuttal).
Finally,
the
lecturer
simply
comes
clean
and
explains
that
the
assumptions
of
his
research
are
much
in
keeping
with
evolutionary
reasoning
in
general,
particularly
the
adaptationist
arguments
of
evolutionary
psychology.
As
I
mention
above,
this
final
move
is
a
response
to
criticism
that
did
not
take
place
in
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions.
Allowing
that
there
are
very
few
criticisms
of
that
kind
in
the
Social
Events,
I
suggest
that
the
speakers
openness
in
this
instance
is
influenced
by
the
setting
itself,
most
especially
the
possibility
that
the
ideologies
that
comprise
the
EvoS
Programs
evolutionary
reasoning
are
the
presuppositions
of
this
context.
Unlike
the
Question
and
Answer
Sessions,
it
is
more
or
less
appropriate
for
a
lecturer
to
admit
that
he
or
she
is
a
member
of
this
social
movement
in
this
setting.
Further,
considering
the
kinds
of
practice
and
demonstration
of
students
and
lecturers
in
this
event,
it
seems
likely
that
this
lecturer
was
unconcerned
with
the
immediate
implications
of
an
admission
of
the
kind
he
makes
here.
To
this
end,
he
is
in
the
fold
of
like-minded
colleagues.
Example
3b:
I
wanted
to
write
something
which
annoyed
people.
This
second
example
of
a
Social
Event
criticism
became
rather
infamous
during
my
fieldwork,
for
reasons
that
will
become
clear.
The
critic
was
a
graduate
student,
well
known
in
the
EvoS
Program
for
voicing
strong
opinions
(although,
to
this
point,
not
directly
to
a
lecturer
in
a
Seminar
Series
Social
Event).
During
the
previous
week,
this
student
and
I
interacted
several
times,
and
she
explained
her
deep
agitation
at
the
weeks
285
readings.
In
her
interpretation
of
the
assigned
article,
the
upcoming
Seminar
Series
lecturer
was
disparaging
indigenous
belief
systems
by
labeling
them
superstitions.
To
her
credit,
I
(and
other
participants)
found
this
lecturers
article
egregious
for
its
glib
tone
and
egregious
examples
of
human
sacrifice
and
cannibalism.
I
was
surprised,
however,
that
this
student
was
so
angered
by
it,
to
the
extent
that
she
was
trembling
while
she
confronted
him,
with
tears
in
her
eyes.
This example takes place approximately 40 minutes into a Social Event, when
286
emotive
issues
and
that
is
why
it
was
killers
and
stuff
like
that
it
was
a
ploy
deliberately
chosen
to
catch
the
attention
of
readers
While
his
comments
do
not
explicitly
invoke
evolutionary
reasoning,
this
lecturers
response
(to
a
quite
cutting
criticism)
parallels
that
of
response
eventually
given
by
the
visiting
EvoS
speaker
in
Example
4a.
He
does
not
attempt
to
dismiss
or
deflect
this
students
challenge,
but
rather
assumes
that
his
take
on
this
matter
is
part
of
the
presuppositions
and
openness
of
this
setting.
That
is,
he
is
up
front
about
his
intentions
to
annoy
and
provoke
his
reading
audience
with
(arguably)
an
article-
length
foregrounding
of
taboo
topicalizations.
What happens next in this interaction demonstrates just how successful the
287
The
EvoS
moderator
attempts
to
defuse
the
situation
as
audience
members
mutter
to
one
another:
Yeah
I
think
that
might
be
a
misinterpretation
of
the
article
but
your
point
is
taken
I
think
what
you
[the
lecturer]
said
is
that
you
were
intentionally
taking
on
a
different
framework
here
its
not
the
only
framework
possible
But
he
lecturer
is
offended,
nearly
shouting:
I
do
take
objection
to
calling
it
eugenics
I
mean
YOU
CANT
SAY
THAT
The
student
does
not
back
down:
Well
I
did
At
this
point,
the
moderator
immediately
decides
to
end
the
Social
Event,
announcing:
So
we
want
to
thank
our
speaker
hes
been
very
gracious
What
took
place
next
remains
(to
me)
unclear.
The
lecturer
left
the
hall
quite
quickly,
before
even
any
of
the
students
had
risen
to
leave.
In
later
conversation
with
the
student
who
posed
this
challenge,
she
explains
that
he
was
ushered
from
the
room
by
the
EvoS
moderator,
perhaps
out
of
fear
that
the
argument
would
escalate.
Upon
reflection,
however,
it
seems
likely
that
he
simply
stormed
out.
In
any
case,
this
interaction
remained
for
some
time
the
most
controversial
and
remarked-
upon
episode
in
the
Binghamton
EvoS
Program.
Though I think this confrontation is important for its heated subject matter, I
want
here
to
reiterate
the
point
that
I
have
made
throughout
this
chapter:
This
speakers
initial
response
to
a
student
criticism
was
not
a
mode
of
defense,
but
rather
a
quite
frank
explanation,
delivered
in
a
setting
that
was
agreeable
to
the
288
presuppositions
of
his
research
although
clearly
not
as
much
as
he
would
have
liked.
I
suggest
that
his
openness
in
responding
in
this
way
is
indicative
of
the
safe
space
of
the
Social
Events.
Allowing
that
her
remarks
would
have
been
inflammatory
anywhere,
but
considering
the
many
examples
that
I
present
above,
I
further
suggest
that
the
problems
caused
by
the
students
challenge
was
a
result
of
this
safety
and
openness
being
violated.
Her
accusation
can
be
seen
as
the
ultimate
challenge
to
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
insofar
it
calls
into
question
the
relevance
of
evolutionary
reasoning
for
explaining
social
life
or
resolving
its
problems.
5.
EvoS
at
the
University
of
Lisbon
and
The
Inquisition
against
Evolution
In
Chapter
Five,
I
offer
additional
ethnographic
details
on
the
first
Seminar
Series
events
at
SUNY
New
Paltz,
where
the
Tiger
Incident
resulted
in
some
rather
surprising
new
resources
for
promoting
EvoS.
There,
I
proposed
that
participants
had
recreated
the
in-house
ideologies
and
first
principle
of
the
Binghamton
EvoS
Program,
as
well
as
the
foregrounding-contextualization
patterns
of
its
lectures
and
the
modes
of
defense
employed
in
its
question
and
answer
sessions.
Organizers
of
that
program
additionally
reframed
their
critics
and
criticisms
as
new
resources,
which
they
used
to
challenge
academic
rejections
of
evolutionary
reasoning
and
further
promote
this
movement.
Here,
I
discuss
another
EvoS
Program,
focusing
on
the
Social
Event
which
followed
its
end-of-semester
symposium.
Like
EvoS
at
SUNY
New
Paltz,
this
program
recreates
many
of
the
ideologies
and
first
principle
of
the
original
EvoS
at
Binghamton.
While
this
Social
Event
does
not
include
the
kinds
of
drama
that
289
transpired
at
New
Paltz,
its
participants
utilize
the
safe
space
of
this
event
in
ways
quite
similar
to
those
I
describe
in
this
chapter.
In
2009,
David
Sloan
Wilson
announced
the
formation
of
the
first
EvoS
Program
outside
North
American,
at
the
University
of
Lisbon
(UL),
and
the
program
held
its
first
classes
and
symposium
in
2011.
That
spring,
two
EvoS
courses
(one
undergraduate
and
one
graduate-level)
were
offered
at
the
universitys
Faculty
of
Science
(Faculdade
de
Cincias)
in
Campo
Grande,
a
northern
municipality
of
Lisbon.
Like
the
introductory
EvoS
course
at
Binghamton
and
New
Paltz,
Wilsons
Evolution
for
Everyone
is
the
central
textbook
for
both.46
The
UL
EvoS
website
offers
a
description
of
the
programs
goals
directed
more
at
affirming
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning:
Like
all
other
species
on
Earth,
we
evolved
through
natural
selection:
evolution
should
thus
enable
us
to
learn
more
about
ourselves
and
our
societies
by
providing
a
framework
that
helps
us
understand
how
we
learn,
how
we
interact,
how
we
negotiate,
how
our
brains
function,
etc.
Because
of
this
potential
explanatory
power
evolutions
importance
extends
from
biology
to
other
fields,
including
economics,
linguistics,
history,
political
science,
education,
or
psychology.
With
the
exception
of
biology
and
closely
related
areas
(medicine,
agriculture),
the
theory
of
evolution
has
not
been
used
to
its
full
interdisciplinary
potential.
Sadly,
in
instances
where
it
has
been
used,
results
have
been
poor
or
controversial,
due
to
misunderstandings
of
what
evolution
is
or
of
what
it
tells
us
about
ourselves.47
Clearly,
the
Lisbon
website
echoes
its
predecessors
by
quite
explicitly
affirming
evolutionary
reasonings
status
as
a
foundational
explanation
for
social
life.
Further,
this
description
indexes
the
in-house
ideologies
of
the
EvoS
Program
by
praising
the
46
A Evoluco para Todos, the Portuguese translation of Wilsons (2007) general-audience book was
released in 2009 by the Lisbon publishing house, Gradiva.
47
290
great
potential
for
academic
and
public
enlightenment
that
can
be
found
through
evolutionary
reasoning,
while
lamenting
that
it
has
been
dismissed
for
its
controversial
nature.
At the end of the Spring 2011 semester, the UL EvoS founders organized a
symposium,
which
(like
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series
at
Binghamton
and
SUNY
New
Paltz)
students
were
required
to
attend.
The
keynote
speaker
at
this
event
was
David
Sloan
Wilson,
resulting
in
his
online
essay
titled
Evolution
Comes
Out
of
Hiding
in
Lisbon
(2011a).
The
six-hour
symposium
included
a
reception
and
welcoming
words
from
the
UL
EvoS
organizers,
a
coffee
break,
and
an
hour-long,
general
discussion
at
its
close.
The
visiting
lecturers
were
professors
of
biology,
economics,
and
social
psychology
at
universities
in
the
U.S.,
Spain,
and
Holland.
According
to
Wilson,
the
room
filled
to
overflowing
with
people
eager
to
hear
what
evolutionary
science
might
have
to
say
about
our
capacity
to
decide
our
own
future
[].
[F]or
the
people
who
overflowed
the
lecture
hall
for
the
symposium,
it
was
obvious
that
disciplines
such
as
social
psychology
and
economics
cry
out
for
an
evolutionary
perspective.
[D.S.
Wilson
2011a]
The
UL
EvoS
Symposium
obviously
proceeded
without
the
kinds
of
controversy
of
the
first
Seminar
Series
event
at
New
Paltz.
However,
David
Sloan
Wilson
recounts
the
following
Social
Event
with
a
strongly
worded
description
of
the
academic
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning
that
he
and
his
fellow
participants.
For
dinner,
Wilsons
hosts
served
him
Farinheira,
a
beef
sausage
invented
during
the
Spanish
Inquisition
by
Jews
who
fooled
their
persecutors
into
believing
they
were
breaking
tradition
by
eating
pork.
Learning
the
historical
significance
of
this
sausage,
Wilson
poses
a
comparison:
291
I
couldn't
help
noticing
a
similarity
between
Jews
hiding
their
faith
during
the
Inquisition
and
the
way
that
evolution
has
been
hiding
for
the
study
of
humanity
during
the
last
half-century
or
so.
How
else
can
the
sheer
novelty
of
an
EvoS
program
and
the
symposium
that
took
place
earlier
in
the
day
be
explained?
[D.S.
Wilson
2011a]
Admittedly,
Wilsons
analogy
is
something
of
a
logical
leap.
But
his
(very)
creative
index
of
an
EvoS
in-house
ideology
is
clear
the
novelty
of
EvoS
and
the
symposium
suggests
to
him
that
scientists
must
be
hiding
their
evolutionary
reasoning
from
critics
who
fear
and
attempt
to
marginalize
it
(like
the
Jews
hid
their
traditions
from
the
Inquisition).
Continuing
his
discussion
of
this
Social
Event,
Wilson
explains
that
one
speaker
from
the
UL
EvoS
Symposium
offered
his
hosts
a
personal
testimony
about
witnessing
some
of
the
mid-1970s
debates
over
sociobiology
at
Harvard
(which
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Two).
This
speaker
recalled
how
he
attended
an
early
gathering
of
the
Sociobiology
Study
Group,
just
after
the
publication
of
Edward
O.
Wilson's
Sociobiology.
The
story
of
how
Richard
Lewontin
and
Stephen
Jay
Gould
organized
a
Marxist
attack
against
Wilson
for
the
final
chapter
of
Sociobiology
on
humans
is
well
known,
but
Michael
actually
witnessed
one
of
the
first
meetings
during
his
visit.
He
was
shocked,
describing
it
during
our
dinner
in
Lisbon
as
like
the
thought
control
that
took
place
in
Maoist
China.
[D.S.
Wilson
2011a]
Wilsons
dinner
companion
became
a
full
professor
in
biology,
but
since
his
graduate
education
became
profoundly
interested
in
an
evolutionary
explanations
for
free
will.
Wilson
writes
that
this
UL
EvoS
speaker
has
been
developing
his
ideas
ever
since,
but
always
hidden,
based
on
his
experience
at
Harvard,
which
convinced
him
that
going
public
might
ruin
his
career.
His
talk
at
Lisbon
was
one
of
the
first
times
that
he
has
come
out
of
hiding.
[D.S.
Wilson
2011a]
292
As
Wilson
relates
this
story,
it
functions
similarly
to
his
sausage
analogy
as
an
elongated
and
intensifying
index
of
the
academic
rejection
of
evolutionary
reasoning,
and
testimonial
evidence
of
its
impact
upon
the
intellectual
freedoms
of
professional
scientists.
Finally, after documenting his dinner guests struggles, Wilson offers his own
293
Given
that
Wilsons
essay
is
likely
the
sole
English
language
report
on
the
UL
EvoS
Symposium
(and
certainly
the
most
easily
accessed),
it
is
curious
that
he
includes
such
esoteric
details
about
evolutionary
reasoning
in
U.S.
higher
education.
Moreover,
considering
that
he
spent
two
years
excitedly
promoting
this
new
Evo
Program,
it
is
remarkable
that
Wilson
uses
this
essay
to
compare
the
academic
critics
of
evolutionary
reasoning
to
(respectively)
the
Spanish
Inquisition,
Maoist
China,
and
Hitlers
Germany.
Even
with
these
dire
comparisons,
Wilsons
commentary
ends
on
a
positive
note,
quipping,
let's
hope
that
the
inquisition
against
evolution
is
over,
and
what
better
way
to
celebrate
than
over
good
food,
good
wine,
and
good
company
in
Lisbon
(D.S.
Wilson
2011a).
The interactions that Wilson describes taking place in Lisbon parallel those
The details of my research suggest that EvoS organizers put a good deal of
energy
and
money
into
attracting
students
to
the
program.
The
Social
Events
are
the
most
conspicuous
example
of
these
efforts.
Students
are
given
free
food
and
beverages,
in
an
often-celebratory
atmosphere.
They
are
encouraged
to
practice
their
understanding
of
evolutionary
reasoning
(with
the
guidance
of
experts).
They
can
be
entertained
with
ribald
or
unrestrained
narratives
by
their
elders,
and
on
294
occasion
treated
to
unabashed
disclosure
of
the
lives
of
professional
academics.
In
addition
to
all
of
this,
they
are
earning
course
credits
and
grades
for
their
attendance
and
participation
in
the
Seminar
Series.
These
activities
and
incentives
require
the
EvoS
Program
to
organize
spaces
for
its
events,
advertise
across
campus
with
paper
and
electronic
promotions,
and
pay
for
graduate
student
labor,
lecturers
travel
and
speaking
fees,
as
well
as
food
and
beer
for
participants.
Moreover,
organizers
and
lecturers
must
commit
their
time
and
energy
to
coaxing
students
to
participate,
dealing
with
those
who
break
various
rules,
and
maintaining
general
order
in
these
activities.
The
sum
total
is
an
extraordinary
investment
in
maintaining
and
spreading
this
programs
ideologies,
while
simultaneously
satisfying
the
requirements
of
an
institution
that
EvoS
(somewhat
ironically)
aims
to
criticize
and
transform.
Considering
such
investment
of
resources,
the
question
emerges
of
whether
or
not
the
program
successfully
persuades
students
toward
its
way
of
thinking
about
higher
education
and
(ultimately)
human
social
life
in
general.
That
is,
do
the
contextualizations
of
new
meanings
stick
in
students
perspectives
of
their
education
and,
more
broadly,
their
explanations
of
human
existence?
To
consider
if
(and
how)
students
are
persuaded
to
think
about
higher
education,
I
would
like
to
first
assess
the
fate
of
the
EvoS
Programs
in-house
ideologies.
As
I
have
shown,
the
in-house
ideologies
show
a
good
deal
of
consistency
across
settings
and
over
time.
Following
my
arguments
in
Chapter
Three
(and
after),
they
may
be
understood
as
rather
commonplace
within
the
broader
evolutionary
science
community.
Professional
proponents
of
evolutionary
reasoning
consider
the
295
dismissal
and
rejection
of
their
perspectives
to
be
a
matter
of
dire
importance
in
U.S.
society.
They
end
to
perceive
this
as
doubt
about
the
authority
of
scientific
knowledge,
as
well
as
an
affront
to
their
professions,
disciplines,
and
research.
296
greatly
concern
them,
because
the
foundational
status
of
evolutionary
reasoning
is,
for
them,
largely
presupposed.
They
understood
the
real
threat
to
evolutionary
theory
to
be
the
various
challenges
of
creationism
and
Intelligent
Design,
which
they
knew
from
the
news,
popular
science
readings,
and
even
arguments
with
their
friends
and
families.
In
this
sense,
the
maintenance
and
spread
of
this
social
movement
is
a
process
in
which
the
in-house
ideologies
simply
lose
their
utility.
But
this
is
hardly
surprising.
The
EvoS
events
I
detail
in
this
research
complement
(in
an
academic
setting)
students
presuppositions
that
evolutionary
reasoning
is
superior
to
counter-arguments
in
the
non-academic
realm.
The
interactions
in
these
academic
settings
rely
upon
such
presuppositions,
but
they
are
information
not
statable
before
the
interaction
begins,
or
independently
of
it
(Auer
1996:20).
In
plainer
terms,
the
organizers
and
visiting
speakers
in
EvoS
cannot
simply
ask
We
all
believe
in
evolution,
right?
Instead,
the
belief
in
evolution
that
participants
presumably
share
must
be
oriented
toward
a
less
obvious
goal
using
evolutionary
science
to
restructure
higher
education
and
(ultimately)
other
social
institutions.
Their
continued
participation
in
the
EvoS
is
thus
re-conceptualized
as
something
more
directly
political
than
their
simple
conviction
that
evolution
is
true.
This
conviction
becomes
charged
with
new
significance,
such
that
the
students
become
(knowingly
or
not)
ambassadors
of
the
movements
conviction
that
evolution
is
not
only
true,
but
should
be
employed
as
an
explanation
for
all
social
life.
Of
course,
student
participants
are
required
to
attend
and
participate
in
the
EvoS
Seminar
Series.
To
this
end,
something
quite
mundane
is
being
argued
by
EvoS
297
promoters
as
driven
by
the
students
commitment
to
the
programs
goals.
The
movements
reconceptualization
of
student
participation
is
reinforced
by
various
other
means:
They
appear
in
promotional
photos.
Their
evaluations
of
the
programs
activities
are
used
in
popular
publications
and
grant
proposals.
EvoS
organizers
weigh
their
performances
in
other
courses
against
those
of
non-EvoS
students.
Most
simply,
students
must
register
as
members
of
EvoS
to
enroll
in
the
Seminar
Series
course,
adding
to
the
programs
ranks
through
their
interest
in
taking
a
2-credit
class.
As
I
suggest
in
Chapter
One,
such
actions
are
much
in
keeping
with
a
social
movements
modus
operandi.
As
the
arguments
of
the
movement
extend
to
more
and
more
settings,
the
mundane
routines
and
obligations
of
peoples
everyday
lives
become
representations
of
the
movements
spread
and
endurance.
As
Benford
and
Snow
comment,
social
movements
are
not
viewed
merely
as
carriers
of
extant
ideas
and
meanings
that
grow
automatically
out
of
structural
arrangements
[].
Rather,
movement
actors
are
viewed
as
signifying
agents
actively
engaged
in
the
production
and
maintenance
of
meaning
for
constituents,
antagonists,
and
bystanders
or
observers.
[2000:613]
For
the
EvoS
Program,
extensive
student
participation
signals
their
commitment
to
the
aims
of
EvoS
and
spreading
acceptance
of
evolutionary
reasoning
in
higher
education.
Certainly the organizers of EvoS put great effort into persuading students of
298
overestimate
their
successes.
Many
graduate
students
and
faculty
have
abandoned
the
series,
some
of
who
voiced
their
displeasure
at
the
programs
rather
flippant
way
of
dealing
with
their
critiques.
Some
undergraduate
participants
felt
a
similar
dissatisfaction.
They
explained
to
me
that
they
found
the
Seminar
Series
events
condescending,
redundant,
and
occasionally
downright
strange.
Like
others,
they
described
EvoS
in
religious
terms,
sometimes
complaining
that
it
felt
more
like
a
cult
than
an
education
program.
Some
were
also
disappointed
by
the
programs
very
broad
application
of
evolutionary
science,
methods
that
they
saw
as
contrary
to
the
basic
principles
of
Darwinism.
Likely
the
most
common
complaint
that
I
heard
was
that
the
Seminar
Series
was
just
too
simple
unstimulating
and
lacking
in
meaningful
challenges.
299
Chapter
Seven:
Contextualization,
Socialization
and
the
Fate
of
EvoS
In
this
research,
I
gather
together
the
driving
linguistic
and
ideological
components
within
the
EvoS
Programs
activities
and
relationships
those
interpersonal
elements
of
the
program
that
seem
necessary
for
its
endurance
and
spread.
I
have
shown
that
these
are
numerous
and
often
complexly
intertwined.
In
any
of
the
interactions
that
I
analyze
here,
the
presuppositions
are
potentially
infinite.
They
include
dozens
of
typically
un-remarked-upon
assumptions,
ranging
from
students
conduct
in
a
classroom
to
the
socio-cultural
authority
of
science.
However,
as
I
suggest
from
the
outset,
countless
presuppositions
could
be
cataloged
for
any
social
interaction.
The
most
relevant
presuppositions
are
uncovered
when
some
instance
of
foregrounding
takes
place.
In
this
way,
socio-linguistic
life
can
be
understood
as
a
continuous
interplay
of
relatively
presupposed
and
creative
indexicals,
and
such
an
approach
will
offer
useful
insights
whether
examining
the
mundane
or
the
very
contentious
moments
of
social
life.
The EvoS Program demonstrates the quite exaggerated ways that this
300
cultural
research,
controversy
has
the
benefit
of
drawing
out
those
core
values
that
people
find
worth
advocating
or
defending.
In
a
sense,
controversy
makes
people
shout
the
values
that
they
normally
do
not
find
worth
mentioning.
Further,
controversy
may
show
the
processes
by
which
these
values
(and
their
associated
practices,
relationships,
identities,
and
symbols)
undergo
change.
Insofar
as
social
movements
are
determined
to
transform
what
they
see
as
an
unacceptable
status
quo,
their
activities
and
relationships
give
unsubtle
demonstrations
of
the
broader
dynamics
of
socio-linguistic
life.
repetitive
and
self-reinforcing
process.
In
this
case
study
of
EvoS,
I
identify
several
component
parts
of
this
process:
New
meanings
must
be
contextualized
as
the
dominant
and
resonating
message
through
a
variety
of
settings
and
over
time.
While
these
meanings
are
necessarily
novel,
the
settings
in
which
they
are
introduced
must
include
a
variety
of
normal
or
unsurprising
elements.
These
might
include
the
identities
and
roles
of
the
people
who
participate,
rules
for
participation,
expectations
for
interactions
and
good
conduct,
and
deference
to
authority.
These
elements
normalize
the
introduction
of
new
meanings
for
participants,
suggesting
to
participants
(and
outsiders)
that
it
is
enduring,
spreading,
and
gaining
broader
acceptance.
The
introduction
and
promotion
of
new
meanings
will
undoubtedly
be
challenged
as
they
enter
wider,
more
diverse
settings.
Proponents
of
these
meanings
are
obliged
to
defend
them,
and
EvoS
provides
many
examples
of
how
this
might
be
done:
Critics
may
be
dismissed
or
ridiculed
as
unreasonable,
conservative,
301
or
reactionary.
In
the
face
of
criticism,
proponents
of
new
meanings
may
reiterate
them
in
increasingly
egregious
ways,
thus
underscoring
the
radical
or
innovative
nature
of
their
own
positions
to
the
stogy
ways
of
their
critics.
Conversely,
new
meanings
may
be
analogically
linked
to
other,
less
disputable
ideologies
those
dealing
with
freedom,
democracy,
public
health,
or
the
protection
of
children.
New,
often-contentious
meanings
are
thus
argued
as
intertwined
with
indispensible
social
values,
forcing
critics
into
less-defensible
positions.
Finally,
EvoS
shows
us
that
the
successful
contextualization
of
new
meanings
requires
not
just
their
repetition
and
defense,
but
the
socialization
of
new
proponents.
Previously
un-persuaded
individuals
must
be
taught
new
ways
of
interpreting
their
relationships
and
experiences.
They
need
to
practice
making
their
own
arguments,
be
praised
or
corrected,
and
shown
how
to
defend
their
positions
against
doubters.
Those
instructing
them
must
present
compelling
connections
between
these
new
meanings
and
the
most
valued
ideologies
of
the
society,
thus
interweaving
them
with
more
taken-for-granted
truths.
The
initiates
must
be
rewarded
for
their
efforts,
given
meaningful
responsibilities,
and
encouraged
to
apply
new
ways
of
thinking
to
their
daily
lives.
In
short,
these
newly
recruited
individuals
need
to
see
themselves
(and
be
seen
by
spectators)
as
a
growing
group
of
people
who
think
differently.
From
this,
I
conclude
that
the
introduction,
endurance,
and
spread
of
new
ideas
are
facilitated
by
their
continual
contextualizations,
which
should
ultimately
understand
as
a
process
of
socialization.
To explain this point more thoroughly, I would like to return to the three
302
analogical
extension,
and
reflexive
recursion.
Doing
so,
I
want
to
take
my
evidence
in
this
research
as
a
whole,
drawing
broader
conclusions
about
the
ways
that
people
might
be
socialized
toward
new,
controversial
ways
of
thinking.
As
is
surely
apparent,
this
will
directly
address
my
central
research
question
on
the
introduction
and
spread
of
new
meanings.
1.
Abstraction
without
the
simultaneous
representation
of
the
program
and
its
critics
as
relatively
autonomous
socio-cultural
forms.
This
involves
strategically
juxtaposing
the
pre-
existing,
largely
presupposed
activities,
ideologies,
and
identities
of
the
university
as
belonging
to
the
movement
or
(conversely)
those
that
the
program
challenges.
This
is
an
absolutely
essential
component
of
social
movement
activities.
Movement
interactions
necessarily
exclude
or
include
certain
facts
of
the
material
and
social
surroundings
(Auer
1996:20)
as
they
are
contextualized
in
participant
interactions.
Both
insiders
and
outsiders
are
represented
as
unified,
homogeneous
communities,
despite
the
diversity
of
opinions
and
identities
that
doubtlessly
exist
there.
More
or
less
definitive
boundaries
are
drawn
around
and
between
groups.
In
my
analysis,
I
call
this
process
abstraction,
precisely
because
its
actors
abstract
useful
and
juxtaposable
units
from
an
obviously
more
complicated
and
diverse
socio-cultural
landscape.
303
the
in-house
ideologies.
The
non-evolutionary
status
quo
of
academic
disciplines
and
inquiries
has
marginalized
(or
outright
rejected)
evolutionary
reasoning,
privileging
instead
a
variety
of
political
and
professional
convictions.
The
programs
deliveries
of
such
dichotomous
representations
are
not
simply
a
matter
of
telling
event
participants
that
such
institutional
divisions
exist.
Rather,
critics
are
invited
to
these
events
and
encouraged
to
voice
their
dissatisfaction
with
the
programs
arguments.
These
living
representations
of
the
movements
opponents
are
then
(in
one
way
or
another)
dispensed
with,
through
humor,
distraction,
or
outright
dismissal.
Of
course,
to
invite
such
critical
interactions
is
a
risky
maneuver.
Critics
could
show
speakers
or
organizers
to
hold
untenable
convictions
about
evolution,
science,
or
other
institutions
that
audiences
likely
hold
in
high
regard.
This
said,
critics
at
the
programs
events
are
consistently
outnumbered,
constrained,
or
simply
ignored.
304
understood
as
belonging
to
one
side
or
the
other
will
likely
be
presupposed
to
index
a
particular
ideology
of
that
side.
As
Theo
Van
Dijk
argues
of
the
problem
of
contextualization
in
general,
If
a
recipient,
based
on
previous
experiences,
defines
a
speaker
as
a
male
chauvinist,
then
much
of
what
he
says
will
be
heard
as
an
expression
of
male
chauvinism
whether
or
not
there
are
contextualization
cues
that
warrant
such
an
interpretation
[].
That
is,
the
mental
models
recipients
build
when
interpreting
discourse
may
also
be
construed
on
the
basis
of
inferences
about
ideological
intentions
of
speakers
as
inferred
from
previous
experiences,
hearsay
or
other
reliable
information
about
a
speaker.
[2006:130]
Importantly,
what
controversy
shows
us
is
that
such
presupposed
knowledge
must
come
from
somewhere.
A
significant
source
of
such
presuppositions
will
likely
be
the
abstractions
of
individuals
(and
groups
of
individuals)
into
juxtaposed
representations
of
belonging
and
opposition.
305
Events.
These
events
unfold
in
a
space
that
is
separate
from
the
other
academic
settings,
where
organizers
and
visiting
lecturers
offer
extensive
criticisms
of
higher
education
while
coaching
students
to
understand
their
own
university
as
divided
into
evolutionary
thinkers
and
their
critics.
to
the
fate
of
the
in-house
ideologies
indexed
throughout
the
Seminar
Series.
As
I
explain
in
Chapter
Six,
the
programs
in-house
ideologies
do
not
seem
to
particularly
resonate
with
many
student
participants.
This
is
unsurprising,
because
these
students
are
not
professionally
threatened
by
the
(argued)
challenges
and
discrimination
faced
by
evolutionary
thinkers
in
higher
education.
Though
some
were
persuaded
of
the
importance
such
tensions,
these
complaints
were
largely
background
noise
for
many
others,
some
of
whom
considered
them
irritating
digressions.
Students
who
found
importance
in
the
complaints
of
EvoS
speakers
and
organizers
typically
understood
this
division
of
the
university
in
non-academic
terms.
In
this
sense,
they
equated
doubts
about
evolutionary
reasoning
in
the
Social
Sciences
and
Humanities
with
the
broader
rejection
of
evolutionary
science
in
the
United
States.
They
were
often
incredulous
toward
the
non-academic
challenges
of
evolutionary
science
posed
by
Intelligent
Design
and
creationism,
and
were
confused
or
exasperated
why
such
doubts
would
exist
in
higher
education.
2.
Analogical
Extension
In
my
first
chapter,
I
suggest
that
a
social
movements
maintenance
and
spread
largely
depend
on
challenging
an
institution
in
(more
or
less)
normative
fashions.
The
contextualizations
of
social
movement
activities
are
thus
likely
to
306
point
to
other
ideologies.
Further,
these
ideologies
most
probably
possess
greater
scope
than
those
of
the
movement,
and
would
more-or-less
ground
the
movements
legitimacy.
That
is,
the
movement
(an
agitating
force
in
the
social
landscape)
is
aligned
with
more
unquestionable
ideologies
and
unshakable
institutions.
The
contextualizations
of
these
ideologies
can
in
this
way
be
expected
to
include
information
not
statable
before
the
interaction
begins,
or
independently
of
it
(Auer
1996:20).
I
term
these
kinds
of
contextualizations
analogical
extensions,
insofar
as
they
incorporate
external
ideologies
as
the
shared
meanings
of
participant
interactions.
Given
the
rather
ambitious
arguments
and
goals
of
the
EvoS
Program,
I
was
unsurprised
to
find
an
abundance
of
analogical
extensions
(of
various
kinds)
present
in
the
programs
events,
publications,
and
promotions.
The
ideologies
that
make
up
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning
possess
great
strength
within
the
EvoS
community,
but
(as
I
explain
in
Chapter
Two)
are
significantly
less
known
or
accepted
across
the
breadth
of
evolutionary
science.
For
the
yet-uninformed
outsider,
the
programs
take
on
evolution
requires
some
quite
specific
positions
on
the
human
condition.
One
must
be
willing
to
entertain
adaptationist
explanations
for
human
behaviors,
the
similarity
of
cultural
change
to
genetic
evolution,
comparisons
between
human
institutions
and
(among
others)
insect
colonies,
and
a
conviction
that
evolutionary
science
should
inform
law,
education,
government,
and
other
socio-political
policies.
On
the
local
level
of
university
education,
EvoS
participants
entertain
a
related
position
that
academic
disciplines,
research,
and
teaching
should
be
re-conceptualized,
restructured,
and
thus
unified
by
307
evolutionary
reasoning.
These
are
obviously
strong
arguments,
and
I
found
their
contextualizations
continuously
linked
to
other,
less
controversial
ideologies.
In
many
instances,
participants
and
organizers
drew
analogical
extensions
between
the
programs
first
principle
and
the
(argued)
purposes
and
values
of
higher
education.
The
most
persistent
linkages
were
drawn
between
the
spread
of
evolutionary
reasoning
and
the
benefits
of
interdisciplinary
collaboration,
student-
centered
learning,
and
the
unification
of
academic
knowledge.
Through
such
combinations,
EvoS
participants
and
proponents
attempted
to
bridge
two
not-
necessarily
obvious
sets
of
ideologies
those
that
were
(again,
arguably)
unquestionably
valued
across
the
university
community
and
the
evolutionary
explanations
for
all
facets
of
social
life.
Of
course,
EvoS
is
an
academically
situated
program,
so
the
appearance
of
such
combined
contextualizations
is
predictable.
Not
all
participants
understood
how
the
ultimate
goals
of
higher
education
could
be
best
achieved
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
But
the
mechanics
of
such
transformations
are
not
the
point
of
such
contextualizations.
They
primarily
function
to
index
the
convictions
that
the
EvoS
Program
shares
with
the
academic
community.
However
one
feels
about
EvoS
and
evolutionary
reasoning,
the
invoked
values
of
higher
education
are
less
likely
to
be
in
question.
Predictably,
the
events,
publications,
and
promotions
of
EvoS
often
drew
analogical
extensions
between
the
programs
first
principle
and
the
value
of
scientific
knowledge.
The
majority
of
attendees
at
Seminar
Series
events
were
students
and
faculty
in
the
Social
or
Biological
Sciences
at
Binghamton
University.
Their
commitment
to
testable
inquiries
and
empirical
research
could
not
only
be
308
presupposed,
but
these
commitments
to
science
were
also
invariably
indexed
by
the
EvoS
speakers
and
promoters.
Visiting
speakers
who
wished
to
make
evolutionary
arguments
about
topics
in
the
Humanities
(theatre,
literature,
visual
arts,
etc.)
were
often
careful
to
index
their
respect
for
the
authority
of
scientific
knowledge.
It
should
also
be
noted
that
drawing
such
connections
between
EvoS
and
authoritative
science
was
a
necessary
(sometimes
preemptory)
defense
of
the
unconventional
ideologies
of
the
programs
evolutionary
reasoning.
The
localized
strength
of
the
programs
(often
controversial)
ideologies
about
human
evolution
was
thus
paired
with
a
consistently-indexed
deference
to
the
ability
of
scientific
inquiries
to
produce
objective
knowledge.
Other
analogical
extensions
were
less
commonly
drawn
between
the
EvoS
first
principle
and
other
academic
and
non-academic
ideologies
and
institutions,
though
I
want
to
briefly
underscore
their
importance.
As
I
showed
in
Chapter
Two,
EvoS
promotions
and
special
events
on
Binghamton
campus
frequently
include
the
programs
commitments
to
multiculturalism
in
the
university.
Further,
the
diversity
of
student
and
faculty
participants
is
attributed
to
the
wide
acceptability
of
evolutionary
thinking.
For
example,
discussing
the
programs
introductory
Evolution
for
Everyone
course,
David
Sloan
Wilson
reports:
Freshman
English
majors
got
the
message
just
as
strongly
as
senior
biology
majors
[].
The
course
succeeded
across
the
entire
range
of
political
and
religious
beliefs,
from
feminists
to
young
Republicans
and
from
atheists
to
believers.
[2007:9]
As
Wilson
contends,
the
broad
acceptability
of
evolutionary
reasoning
across
diverse
groups
is
understandable:
The
perspective
offers
foundational
explanations
309
for
social
life
that
can
explain
the
diversity
in
(among
other
phenomena)
human
ethnicity,
religion,
sexuality,
government,
and
law.
Very
much
following
from
such
extensions
of
the
first
principle,
we
have
also
seen
that
participants
offer
evolutionary
reasoning
as
means
to
positively
change
social
life.
Such
a
conviction
is
underwritten
by
the
final
ideological
component
of
evolutionary
reasoning
that
I
discuss
in
Chapter
Two
an
understanding
that
the
findings
of
evolutionary
science
must
inform
public
policy
in
order
to
prevent
human
suffering
and
extinction.
Analogical
extensions
between
evolutionary
reasoning
and
social
activism
speak
to
the
progressive
political
leanings
of
the
university
community.
In
particular,
they
are
intended
to
inspire
students
to
see
themselves
as
the
active
agents
of
positive
change,
legitimating
their
continued
(and
hopefully
intensifying)
participation
in
the
program.
Considering
analogical
extension
as
part
of
a
process
of
socialization,
EvoS
demonstrates
that
this
may
be
the
most
powerful
method
for
contextualizing
a
social
movements
ideologies.
As
I
propose
in
Chapter
One,
social
movements
strategically
deliver
their
challenge
in
ways
that
strike
a
responsive
chord
in
that
it
rings
true
with
existing
cultural
narrations
(Snow
and
Benford
1988:210).
The
EvoS
Programs
challenge
to
restructure
higher
education
is,
quite
plainly,
a
deeply
ambitious
vision.
Further,
its
founder
and
organizers
positions
on
social
change
through
evolutionary
science
would
likely
seem
strange,
if
not
alarming
to
many
people.
Analogical
extensions
offer
persuasive,
normalizing
messages
for
audiences,
linking
a
contentious
argument
against
some
status
quo
with
the
presupposed
310
ideologies
that
many
in
the
audience
are
likely
to
share.
As
dAnjou
and
Van
Male
argue,
the
interpretive
packages
they
put
forward
represent
views
that
are
by
definition
against
the
grain,
as
they
concern
the
cause
of
the
socially
marginalized
[].
At
the
same
time,
these
interpretive
packages
have
to
sound
natural
and
familiar
to
the
people
addressed.
[1998:208]
Insofar
as
a
social
movement
seems
invested
in
such
ideals
as
democracy,
multiculturalism,
justice,
and
education,
its
participants
may
argue
as
EvoS
does
that
such
socio-political
goals
could
be
achieved
better
through
the
transformations
that
they
demand.
Expanding
the
ideological
reach
of
a
movements
first
principle
can
thus
engage
(and
so
socialize)
a
broader
swath
of
potential
recruits.
Their
most
deeply
held
convictions
are,
after
all,
the
same
as
those
of
the
movement.
From this, I suggest that the introduction and dissemination of new meanings
rely
upon
an
intricate
web
of
less
novel
interpretations.
One
might
be
socialized
into
new
meanings
by
their
repeated
contextualization
in
association
with
more
normal,
uncontroversial
assumptions.
A
Marxist
challenge
to
consumer
capitalism,
for
example,
may
be
framed
in
terms
of
human
rights
or
workplace
safety.
Or
a
movement
forwarding
womens
reproductive
freedoms
might
draw
connections
to
gender
equality
and
the
need
to
alleviate
poverty.
In
this
sense,
people
may
be
socialized
into
new
ways
of
interpreting
their
world
by
recognizing
their
own
values
within
them.
These
values
can
be
seen
as
inextricably
tied
to
ideologies
that
otherwise
might
seem
strange
or
dangerous.
3.
Reflexive
Recursion
311
A
third
type
of
social
movement
contextualization
urges
its
participants
toward
a
transformed
self-identification
and
perhaps
reevaluation
of
their
subjective
experiences
as
personal
evidence
of
the
groups
ideologies.
For
new
members,
this
will
be
an
experience
that
is
likely
shared
with
long-term
participants.
Contextualizations
of
this
kind
may
inspire
a
kind
of
collective-
identification
or
self-realization
through
the
ideological
lens
of
the
movement
itself.
I
call
this
reflexive
recursion.
Profoundly
persuaded
of
a
movements
central
ideologies,
participants
might
discover
themselves
not
only
as
proponents
of
the
movement,
but
also
living
embodiments
of
it.
As
in
the
Seminar
Series
Lectures
and
Social
Events,
participants
in
the
EvoS
Program
recognized
evolutionary
reasoning
as
potentially
explaining
various
complexities
and
uncertainties
in
their
lives.
For
the
speakers
in
the
series,
it
offered
ways
of
proceeding
through
their
educations
and
professional
lives.
In
more
surprising
instances,
I
observed
speakers
offering
up
quite
intimate
directions
of
their
lives
their
romances,
marriages,
children,
and
sexualities
as
thinkable
through
evolutionary
reasoning.
Lecturers
encouraged
audience
members
to
consider
their
actions,
memories,
and
bodies
as
evolutionary
adaptations
and
draw
comparisons
between
their
own
social
experiences
and
the
behaviors
of
non-human
animals.
Student
participants
in
the
Social
Events
shared
their
(sometimes
problematic)
relationships
with
siblings,
parents,
and
teachers
as
examples
of
evolution
in
action
in
their
own
lives.
Further,
both
students
and
faculty
participated
in
the
programs
research
programs
and
intervention
projects,
such
as
312
the
Evolutionary
Training
initiative,
which
applies
evolutionary
science
to
personal
health,
nutrition,
and
emotional
well
being.
In
my
interviews
with
student
participants
in
EvoS,
I
found
it
remarkable
that
some
individuals
actively
used
evolutionary
reasoning
as
an
explanation
for
uncertainties
about
their
own
social
relationships.
For
example,
as
I
report
in
Chapter
Six,
I
spoke
with
three
male
students
who
wished
to
understand
their
difficulties
in
communicating
and
forming
romantic
relationships
with
women.
These
men
described
to
me
the
various
mysteries
involved
in
understanding
(as
one
put
it)
the
female
mind,
and
felt
that
they
were
being
assisted
by
lectures
and
discussions
on
psychology
and
emotions
in
the
EvoS
Program.
In several sections of this research, I also posed that the EvoS founder and
Certainly all of these examples are quite particular to EvoS and its goals in
313
movements
activities
suggest
that
this
conviction
is
experienced
at
a
very
deep
personal
and
interpersonal
level.
Participants
experience
a
transformation
in
the
ways
they
view
their
relationships,
health,
diets,
and
even
their
interpretations
of
the
past
and
hopes
for
the
future.
It
might
be
argued
that
such
deeply
transformative
experiences
are
unlikely
to
result
from
scientific
knowledge,
which
is
supposed
to
be
impersonal,
detached,
and
politically
neutral.
But
recent
ethnographies
have
demonstrated
that
peoples
receptions
of
scientific
knowledge
is
profoundly
internalized,
reshaping
the
ways
they
think
about
their
bodies
and
minds
(Franklin
1997,
2007;
Rapp
1999;
Strathern
1992).
New
developments
in
(for
example)
reproductive
technology
and
gene
therapy
produce
great
existential
and
interpersonal
impacts
upon
peoples
decisions.
meanings
into
peoples
social
lives.
Understanding
some
ideology
as
their
lived,
daily
experiences,
people
might
be
inspired
to
feel
great
empathy
toward
disenfranchised
groups
or
solidarity
with
other
advocates
for
social
change.
They
could
recognize
evidence
for
this
ideologys
veracity
in
daily
activities
that
once
seemed
mundane
and
dismissible.
Simple
tasks
like
buying
food
could
become
an
exercise
in
seeing
inequalities
in
labor
practices
or
the
inhumane
treatment
of
animals.
Newly-learned
interpretations
of
social
life,
once
reflexively
directed
inside,
could
move
a
person
beyond
advocacy
for
change
to
radically
different
experiences
of
his
or
her
work,
family,
romance,
learning,
or
health.
314
They
wished
to
persuade
students
and
faculty
to
repeatedly
contextualize
evolutionary
reasoning
as
a
foundational
principle
in
teaching,
learning,
and
research.
Once
this
principle
was
accepted
across
the
academy,
the
abstracted
sides
of
the
evolution
debates
would
dissolve.
The
motives
and
goals
of
higher
education
would
be
unified
within
a
single
community
of
scholars
and
researchers.
They
would
come
to
understand
that
human
problems
such
as
warfare,
disease,
and
poverty
are
matters
explainable
through
evolutionary
science.
They
would
analogically
extend
evolutionary
reasoning
toward
other
social
institutions
and
ideologies,
seeking
greater
knowledge
about
the
socio-political
issues
that
the
contemporary
university
had
failed
to
explain
and
(moreover)
been
unable
to
fix.
Importantly,
this
new
community
of
higher
education
would
see
their
own
lives
as
examples
of
the
power
of
evolutionary
thinking
a
transformative
experience
they
would
want
to
teach
to
others.
The
reformed
academy
would
apply
its
knowledge
and
energy
to
progressive
social
programs
that
would
alleviate
human
suffering
and
guide
the
course
of
the
species
future
evolution.
4.
The
Fate
of
the
EvoS
Program
at
Binghamton
University
In
the
three
years
following
this
case
study,
the
EvoS
Program
at
Binghamton
University
has
significantly
mellowed
in
its
activities,
promotions,
and
ambitions.
Constrained
by
budget
limitations,
the
Seminar
Series
events
became
less
directed
toward
celebration
and
camaraderie.
There
is
no
more
pizza
and
beer.
Instead,
the
Social
Events
are
limited
to
more
focused
discussions,
directly
following
the
lectures.
The
programs
budget
has
also
clearly
impacted
the
range
of
visiting
315
speakers.
Instead
of
well
known,
widely
read
lecturers,
the
program
now
invites
more
Binghamton
graduate
students,
faculty,
and
alumni
to
present
their
research.
Wilsons
ventures
into
non-academic
projects
and
away
from
the
regular
maintenance
and
participation
in
the
programs
activities.
As
the
programs
founder
and
primary
advocate,
this
poses
an
obvious
problem
for
the
consistent
delivery
of
316
its
message.
He
also
attracts
the
widest
funding
opportunities,
as
well
as
authoring
its
grant
applications.
As
a
regular
moderator
in
the
Seminar
Series,
Wilson
was
also
its
most
vehement
defender
against
on-the-spot
criticisms.
His
near-celebrity
status
in
the
evolutionary
science
community
clearly
helped
to
spread
information
about
this
program
to
other
universities
and
outside
academic
contexts.
His
distance
from
the
program
resulted
in
difficulties
for
the
EvoS
support
staff
and
the
graduate
students
he
advises
(Marris
2011).
One last, important shortcoming for EvoS deserves mention here, which is a
matter
of
the
targets
toward
which
the
movement
was
directed.
Though
the
programs
organizers
always
voiced
university-wide
transformations,
the
majority
of
its
activities
foregrounded
a
need
to
reorient
and
restructure
those
disciplines
dealing
with
questions
of
human
social
life
that
is,
the
Humanities
and
Social
Sciences.
On
one
hand,
such
a
quest
would
be
a
predictably
uphill
battle
for
EvoS.
As
its
participants
voice
time
after
time,
individuals
in
these
areas
of
higher
education
are
the
most
consistently
critical
toward
(and
dismissive
of)
evolutionary
reasoning
applied
to
human
affairs.
Of
course,
the
programs
intentions
have
always
been
to
persuade
these
people
otherwise.
But,
as
the
history
of
evolutionary
science
in
higher
education
demonstrates,
such
initiatives
were
likely
to
meet
with
strong
skepticism.
Sciences
have
always
been
somewhat
nave.
These
arenas
of
professional
academia
are
among
the
most
rapidly
shrinking
parts
of
U.S.
colleges
and
universities.
Institutions
such
as
Binghamton
are
increasingly
prioritizing
research
and
317
professional
development
programs
in
management,
finance,
accounting,
and
the
numerous
fields
of
engineering.
These
are
topics
that
EvoS
did
not
directly
engage.
Instead,
its
proponents
took
aim
at
anthropology,
sociology,
cultural
studies,
literature,
and
the
arts.
To
this
end,
perhaps
the
most
important
strategy
for
a
social
movement
is
to
direct
its
goals
and
analogically
extend
its
ideologies
toward
the
right
things.
A
movements
criticisms
should
find
targets
that
are
broadly
seen
as
vibrant,
essential,
authoritative,
and
financially
salient.
In
short,
the
old
meanings
must
be
considered
worth
the
effort
of
changing.
318
Works
Cited
Abercrombie,
Nicholas
and
Bryan
S.
Turner
1978
The
Dominant
Ideology
Thesis.
British
Journal
of
Sociology
29(2):
14970.
Abercrombie,
Nicholas,
Stephen
Hill,
and
Bryan
S.
Turner
1980
The
Dominant
Ideology
Thesis.
London:
G.
Allen
and
Unwin.
Abu-Lughod,
Lila
and
Catherine
A.
Lutz
1990
Introduction:
Emotion,
Discourse,
and
the
Politics
of
Everyday
Life.
In
Language
and
the
Politics
of
Emotion.
C.A.
Lutz
and
L.
Abu-Lughod,
eds.
Pp.
1-
23.
Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Adorno,
Theodor
1972
Ideology.
In
Aspects
of
Sociology.
J.
Viertel,
transl.
Pp.182-205.
Agha,
Asif
2003
The
Social
Life
of
Cultural
Value.
Language
and
Communication
23:
231-273.
2005
Voice,
Footing,
Enregisterment.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
15(1):
3859.
2007
Language
and
Social
Relations.
New
York:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Albury,
W.R.
1980
Politics
and
Rhetoric
in
the
Sociobiology
Debate.
Social
Studies
of
Science
10(4):
519-536.
Alcock,
John
2001
The
Triumph
of
Sociobiology.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Allen,
Elizabeth,
Barbara
Beckwith,
Jon
Beckwith,
Steven
Chorover,
David
Culver,
Margaret
Duncan,
Steven
Gould,
Ruth
Hubbard,
Hiroshi
Inouye,
Anthony
Leeds,
Richard
Lewontin,
Chuck
Madansky,
Larry
Miller,
Reed
Pyeritz,
Miriam
Rosenthal,
and
Herb
Schreier
1975
Against
Sociobiology.
The
New
York
Review
of
Books
22
(18):
42-43.
319
Alters,
Brian
J.
2010
Apprehension
and
Pedagogy
in
Evolution
Education.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
3:
231-235.
Alters,
Brian
J.
and
Craig
E.
Nelson
2002
Perspective:
Teaching
Evolution
in
Higher
Education.
Evolution
56(10):
1891-1901.
Althusser,
Louis
2008
[1971]
On
Ideology.
London:
Verso.
Alvarez,
Sonia
E.
and
Arturo
Escobar
1992
Conclusion:
Theoretical
and
Political
Horizons
of
Change
in
Contemporary
Latin
American
Social
Movements.
In
The
Making
of
Social
Movements
in
Latin
America:
Identity,
Strategy,
and
Democracy.
A.
Escobar
and
S.E.
Alvarez,
eds.
Pp.
317-329.
Boulder,
CO:
Westview
Press.
Alvarez,
Sonia
E.,
Evelina
Dagnino,
and
Arturo
Escobar
1998
Introduction:
The
Cultural
and
the
Political
in
Latin
American
Social
Movements.
In
Cultures
of
Politics/Politics
of
Cultures:
Re-Visioning
Latin
American
Social
Movements.
S.E
Alvarez,
E.
Dagnino,
and
A.
Escobar,
eds.
Pp.
1-29.
Boulder,
CO:
Westview
Press.
Andrews,
Edna
1996
Cultural
Sensitivity
and
Political
Correctness:
The
Linguistic
Problem
of
Naming.
American
Speech
71(4):
389-404.
Ann
Arbor
Science
for
the
People
Editorial
Collective,
eds.
1977
Biology
as
a
Social
Weapon.
Minneapolis:
Burgess
Publishing
Company.
Asad,
Talal
1979
Anthropology
and
the
Analysis
of
Ideology.
Man
14(4):
607-627.
Auer,
Peter
1992
Introduction:
John
Gumperz'
Approach
to
Contextualization.
In
The
Contextualization
of
Language.
P.
Auer
and
A.
Di
Luzio.
Pp.
Amsterdam:
John
Benjamins
Publishing
Company.
1996
From
Context
to
Contextualization.
Links
and
Letters
3:11-28.
Aunger,
Robert
2006
Whats
the
Matter
with
Memes?
In
Richard
Dawkins:
How
a
Scientist
Changed
the
Way
We
Think.
A.
Grafen
and
M.
Ridely,
eds.
Pp.
176-188.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
320
Austin,
John
L.
1962
How
to
Do
Things
with
Words.
London:
Oxford
University
Press.
1971
Performative-Constative.
In
The
Philosophy
of
Language.
J.R.
Searle,
ed.
Pp.
13-22.
London:
Oxford
University
Press.
Bains,
Sunny
2011
Questioning
the
Integrity
of
the
John
Templeton
Foundation.
Evolutionary
Psychology
9(1):
92-115.
Bakhtin,
Mikhail
M.
1986
Speech
Genres
and
Other
Late
Essays.
V.W.
McGee,
transl.
Austin:
University
of
Texas
Press.
Bargatzky,
Thomas
1984 Culture,
Environment,
and
the
Ills
of
Adaptationism.
Current
Anthropology
25(4):
399-415.
Barkow,
Jerome
H.
2006
Introduction:
Sometimes
the
Bus
Does
Wait.
In
Missing
the
Revolution:
Darwinism
for
Social
Scientists.
J.
Barkow,
ed.
Pp.
3-59.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
Bart,
Pauline
B.
1977
Biological
Determinism
and
Sexism:
Is
It
All
in
the
Ovaries?
In
Biology
as
a
Social
Weapon.
The
Ann
Arbor
Science
for
the
People
Editorial
Collective,
eds.
Pp.
69-84.
Minneapolis:
Burgess
Publishing
Company.
Beckstrom,
John
H.
1993
Darwinism
Applied:
Evolutionary
Paths
to
Social
Goals.
Westport,
CT:
Praeger.
Benford,
Robert
D.
1997
An
Insiders
Critique
of
the
Social
Movement
Framing
Perspective.
Sociological
Inquiry
67(4):
409-430.
Benford,
Robert
D.
and
David
A.
Snow
2000
Framing
Processes
and
Social
Movements:
An
Overview
and
Assessment.
Annual
Review
of
Sociology
26:
211-239.
Berreby,
David
2005
Us
and
Them:
Understanding
Your
Tribal
Mind.
New
York:
Little,
Brown
and
Company.
321
Betzig,
Laura
1997
Introduction:
People
are
Animals.
In
Human
Nature:
A
Critical
Reader.
L.
Betzig,
ed.
Pp.
1-17.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
Blackman,
Julie
1985
The
Language
of
Sexual
Violence:
More
than
a
Matter
of
Semantics.
In
Violence
Against
Women:
A
Critique
of
the
Sociobiology
of
Rape.
S.R.
Sunday
and
E.
Tobach,
eds.
Pp.
115-127.
New
York:
Gordian
Press.
Bloom,
Richard
W.
and
Nancy
Dess,
eds.
2003
Evolutionary
Psychology
and
Violence:
A
Primer
for
Policy
Makers
and
Public
Policy
Advocates.
Westport,
CT:
Praeger.
Bock,
Kenneth
1980
Human
Nature
and
History:
A
Response
to
Sociobiology.
New
York:
Columbia
University
Press.
Boggs,
Carl
1986
Social
Movements
and
Political
Power.
Philadelphia:
Temple
University
Press.
Bordo,
Susan
1987
The
Flight
to
Objectivity:
Essays
on
Cartesianism
and
Culture.
Albany:
SUNY
Press.
Borrello,
Mark
E.
2010
Evolutionary
Restraints:
The
Contentious
History
of
Group
Selection.
Chicago:
The
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Bourdieu,
Pierre
1977
Outline
of
a
Theory
of
Practice.
R.
Nice,
transl.
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Boyd,
Robert
and
Peter
J.
Richerson
2005
The
Origin
and
Evolution
of
Cultures.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Brecht,
Bertolt
1964a
Alienation
Effects
in
Chinese
Acting.
In
Brecht
on
Theatre:
The
Development
of
an
Aesthetic.
J.
Willett.
Pp.
91-99.
New
York:
Hill
and
Wang.
1964b
A
Short
Organum
for
the
Theatre.
In
Brecht
on
Theatre:
The
Development
of
an
Aesthetic.
J.
Willett,
ed
and
transl.
Pp.
179-205.
New
York:
Hill
and
Wang.
322
Brem,
Sarah
K.,
Michael
Ranney,
Jennifer
Schindel
2003
Perceived
Consequences
of
Evolution:
College
Students
Perceive
Negative
Personal
and
Social
Impact
in
Evolutionary
Theory.
Science
Education
87:181206.
Broks,
Peter
2006
Understanding
Popular
Science.
Berkshire,
UK:
Open
University
Press.
Brooks,
Paul
2008
Decline
of
Males
Author
Sets
Off
SUNY
Controversy.
Times
Record-
Herald
March
7.
Bucholtz,
Mary
2001
The
Whiteness
of
Nerds:
Superstandard
English
and
Racial
Markedness.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
11(1):
84-100.
Buechler,
Steven
M.
1995
New
Social
Movement
Theories.
The
Sociological
Quarterly
36(3):
441-464.
Buller,
David
J.
2005
Adapting
Minds:
Evolutionary
Psychology
and
the
Persistent
Quest
for
Human
Nature.
Cambridge,
MA:
The
MIT
Press.
Buss,
David
M.
and
Todd
K.
Shackelford
1997
From
Vigilance
to
Violence:
Mate
Retention
Tactics
in
Married
Couples.
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology
72(2):
346-361.
Butler,
Judith
2000
Restaging
the
Universal:
Hegemony
and
the
Limits
of
Formalism.
In
Contingency,
Hegemony,
Universality:
Contemporary
Dialogues
on
the
Left.
J.
Bulter,
E.
Laclau,
and
S.
iek,
eds.
Pp.
11-43.
London:
Verso.
Cameron,
Deborah
1988
Performing
Gender
Identity:
Young
Mens
Talk
and
the
Construction
of
Heterosexual
Masculinity.
In
Language
and
Gender:
A
Reader.
J.
Coates,
ed.
Pp.
270-284.
Oxford:
Blackwell.
1995
Verbal
Hygiene.
London:
Routledge
2006
Ideology
and
Language.
Journal
of
Political
Ideologies
11(2):
141-152.
Caplan,
Arthur
L.
1981
Say
It
Just
Aint
So:
Adaptational
Stories
and
Sociobiological
Explanations
of
Social
Behavior.
The
Philosophical
Forum
13(2-3):
144-160.
323
Carmen,
Rachael
A.,
Glenn
Geher,
Daniel
J.
Glass,
Amanda
E.
Guitar,
Terry
L.
Grandis,
Laura
Johnsen,
Melvin
M.
Philip,
Rebecca
L.
Newmark,
Grant
T.
Trouton,
&
Briana
R.
Tauber
2013
Evolution
Integrated
Across
All
Islands
of
the
Human
Behavioral
Archipelago:
All
Psychology
as
Evolutionary
Psychology.
EvoS
Journal
5(1):
108-126.
Carson,
Rachel
1962
Silent
Spring.
Boston:
Houghton
Mifflin.
Chang,
Rosemarie
Sokal
2009
Spotlight
on
an
EvoS
Faculty
Member.
The
EvoS
Illuminate:
The
Newsletter
of
the
EvoS
Consortium
1:
3-4.
2010
Spotlight
on
an
EvoS
Faculty
Member.
The
EvoS
Illuminate:
The
Newsletter
of
the
EvoS
Consortium
2(1):
3-4.
Cohen,
Jean
L.
1985
Strategy
or
Identity:
New
Theoretical
Paradigms
and
Contemporary
Social
Movements.
Social
Research
52:
663-716.
Comaroff,
Jean
and
John
Comaroff
1991
Of
Revelation
and
Revolution,
Volume
One:
Christianity,
Colonialism,
and
Consciousness
in
South
Africa.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
1997
Of
Revelation
and
Revolution,
Volume
Two:
The
Dialectics
of
Modernity
on
a
South
African
Frontier.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Corrigan,
Alina
and
Erin
Cooker
2009
Evolution
for
Everyone:
An
Undergraduate
Perspective.
Journal
of
Social,
Evolutionary,
and
Cultural
Psychology
3(1):
62-67.
Cosmides,
Leda
and
John
Tooby
1992
Cognitive
Adaptations
for
Social
Exchange.
In
The
Adapted
Mind:
Evolutionary
Psychology
and
the
Generation
of
Culture.
J.H.
Barkow,
L.
Cosmides,
and
J.
Tooby,
eds.
Pp.
163-228.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
Coward,
Rosalind
and
John
Ellis
1977 Language
and
Materialism:
Developments
in
Semiology
and
the
Theory
of
the
Subject.
London:
Routledge
and
Kegan
Paul.
Coyne,
Jerry
A.
2011
Mr.
Darwins
Neighborhood.
The
New
York
Times
Book
Review
(Sept.
11):
24.
324
2012
David
Sloan
Wilson
Loses
It
Again.
Electronic
document.
https://
whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2012/03/09/david-sloan-wilson-loses-
it-again/.
Accessed
June
3,
2014.
Crawford,
Charles
and
Catherine
Salmon,
eds.
2004
Evolutionary
Psychology,
Public
Policy,
and
Personal
Decisions.
Mahwah,
NJ:
Lawrence
Erlbaum
Associates,
Publishers.
Crook,
Paul
1994
Darwinism,
War,
and
History.
Cambridge,
MA:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Daly,
Martin
and
Margo
Wilson
1988
Homicide.
New
york:
Aldine
de
Gruyter.
dAnjou,
Leo
and
John
Van
Male
1998
Between
Old
and
New:
Social
Movements
and
Cultural
Change.
Mobilization:
An
International
Journal
3(2):
141-161.
Davies,
Paul
Sheldon
2009
Subjects
of
the
World:
Darwins
Rhetoric
and
the
Study
of
Agency
in
Nature.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Dawkins,
Richard
1976
The
Selfish
Gene.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
1995
River
Out
of
Eden:
A
Darwinian
View
of
Life.
London:
Weidenfeld
and
Nicolson.
2011
Richard
Dawkins
Replies
to
David
Sloan
Wilson.
eskeptic.
Electronic
document.
Http://www.skeptic.com/eskeptic/07-07-11/#reply.
Accessed
July
10,
2011.
Degler,
Carl
N.
1991
In
Search
of
Human
Nature:
The
Decline
and
Revival
of
Darwinism
in
American
Social
Thought.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
Diamond,
Jared
1992
The
Third
Chimpanzee:
The
Evolution
and
Future
of
the
Human
Animal.
New
York:
Harper
Collins.
1997
Guns,
Germs
and
Steel:
The
Fates
of
Human
Societies.
New
York:
W.W.
Norton
and
Company.
325
Dreyfus,
Hubert
L.
and
Paul
Rabinow
1983
Michel
Foucault:
Beyond
Structuralism
and
Hermeneutics,
Second
Edition.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Duranti,
Alessandro
2003
Language
as
Culture
in
U.S.
Anthropology:
Three
Paradigms.
Current
Anthropology
44(3):
323-347.
2006
The
Social
Ontology
of
Intentions.
Discourse
Studies
8(1):31-40.
Eagleton,
Terry
1991
Ideology:
An
Introduction.
London:
Verso.
Earl,
Jennifer
2004
The
Cultural
Consequences
of
Social
Movements.
In
The
Blackwell
Companion
to
Social
Movements.
D.A.
Snow,
S.A.
Soule,
and
H.
Kriesi,
eds.
Pp.
508-530.
Malden,
MA:
Blackwell
Publishing.
Ehrenreich,
Barbara
and
Janet
McIntosh
1997
The
New
Creationism:
Biology
Under
Attack.
The
Nation
264(22):
11-
16.
Ellis,
Bruce
J.,
Marco
Del
Giudice,
Thomas
J.
Dishion,
Aurelio
Jos
Figueredo,
Peter
Gray,
Vladas
Griskevicius,
Patricia
H.
Hawley,
W.
Jake
Jacobs,
Jenee
James,
Anthony
A.
Volk,
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2012
The
Evolutionary
Basis
of
Risky
Adolescent
Behavior:
Implications
for
Science,
Policy,
and
Practice.
Developmental
Psychology
48(3):598-623.
Embry,
Dennis
D.
2004
Community-Based
Prevention
Using
Simple,
Low-Cost,
Evidence-
Based
Kernels
and
Behavior
Vaccines.
Journal
of
Community
Psychology
32:
575-591
Embry,
Dennis
D.
and
Anthony
Biglan,
2008
Evidence-Based
Kernels:
Fundamental
Units
of
Behavioral
Influence.
Clinical
Child
and
Family
Psychology
Review
11:
75-113.
Escobar,
Arturo
and
Sonia
E.
Alvarez
1992
Introduction:
Theory
and
Protest
in
Latin
America
Theory.
In
The
Making
of
Social
Movements
in
Latin
America:
Identity,
Strategy,
and
Democracy.
A.
Escobar
and
S.E.
Alvarez,
eds.
Pp.
1-15.
Boulder,
CO:
Westview
Press.
Fairclough,
Norman
1992
Discourse
and
Social
Change.
Cambridge,
MA:
Polity
Press.
326
1995a
Critical
Discourse
Analysis:
Papers
in
the
Critical
Study
of
Language.
London:
Longman.
Fausto-Sterling,
Anne
1992
Myths
of
Gender:
Biological
Theories
About
Women
and
Men.
New
York:
Basic
Books.
1997
Feminism
and
Behavioral
Evolution:
A
Taxonomy.
In
Feminism
and
Evolutionary
Biology:
Boundaries,
Intersections,
and
Frontiers.
P.A.
Gowaty,
ed.
Pp.
42-60.
New
York:
Chapman
and
Hall.
2000
Sexing
the
Body:
Gender
Politics
and
the
Construction
of
Sexuality.
New
York:
Basic
Books.
Finn,
Mary,
Rosemarie
Sokal
Chang,
and
Daniel
Glass
2010
Spotlight
on
an
EvoS
Student.
The
EvoS
Illuminate:
The
Newsletter
of
the
EvoS
Consortium
2(2):
7-8.
Fish,
Stanley
1973
How
Ordinary
is
Ordinary
Language?
New
Literary
History
5:
41-54.
Fisher,
Kimberly
D.
1997
Locating
Frames
in
the
Discursive
Universe.
Sociological
Research
Online
2(3).
Electronic
Document.
http://www.socresonline.org.uk/
socresonline/2/3/4.html.
Accessed
1
November
2009.
Fisher,
Walter
R.
1984
Narration
as
a
Human
Communication
Paradigm:
The
Case
of
Public
Moral
Argument.
Communication
Monographs
51:1-22.
Fnagy,
Ivn
1972
Communication
in
Poetry.
In
Readings
in
Modern
Linguistics.
B.
Malmberg,
ed.
Pp.
282-305.
Stockholm:
Lromedelsfrlagen.
Fortes,
Meyer
1949
The
Web
of
Kinship
Among
the
Tallensi.
London:
Oxford
University
Press.
Franklin,
Sarah
1997
Embodied
Progress:
A
Cultural
Account
of
Assisted
Conception.
London:
Routledge.
2007
Dolly
Mixtures:
The
Remaking
of
Genealogy.
Durham:
Duke
University
Press.
327
Friedman,
Debra
and
Doug
McAdam
1992
Collective
Identity
and
Activism:
Networks,
Choices,
and
the
Life
of
a
Social
Movement.
In
Frontiers
in
Social
Movement
Theory.
A.D.
Morris
and
C.M.
Mueller,
eds.
Pp.
156-173.
New
Haven:
Yale
University
Press.
Gal,
Susan
1991
Bartks
Funeral:
Representations
of
Europe
in
Hungarian
Political
Rhetoric.
American
Ethnologist
18(3):
440-458.
1998
Multiplicity
and
Contention
Among
Language
Ideologies:
A
Comment
In
Language
Ideologies:
Practice
and
Theory.
B.B.
Schieffelin,
K.A.
Woolard,
and
P.V.
Kroskrity,
eds.
Pp.
317-331.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
2005
Language
Ideologies
Compared:
Metaphors
of
Public/Private.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
15(1):
23-37.
Gal,
Susan
and
Judith
T.
Irvine
1995
The
Boundaries
of
Languages
and
Disciplines:
How
Ideologies
Construct
Difference.
Social
Research
62(4):
967-1001.
Gallup,
Andrew
C.,
Daniel
T.
OBrien,
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2011
Intrasexual
Peer
Aggression
and
Dating
Behavior
During
Adolescence:
An
Evolutionary
Perspective.
Aggressive
Behavior
37:
258-267.
Gallup,
Gordon
G,
Jr.,
Rebecca
L.
Burch,
and
Steven
M.
Platek
2002
Does
Semen
Have
Antidepressant
Properties?
Archives
of
Sexual
Behavior
31(3):
289-293.
Gamson,
William
A.
1968
Power
and
Discontent.
Homewood,
IL:
Dorsey.
1975
The
Strategy
of
Protest.
Homewood,
IL:
Dorsey.
1998
Social
Movements
and
Cultural
Change.
In
From
Contention
to
Democracy.
M.G.
Giugni,
D.
McAdam,
and
C.
Tilly,
eds.
Pp.
57-77.
Lanham,
MD:
Rowman
and
Littlefield.
2004
Bystanders,
Public
Opinion,
and
the
Media.
In
The
Blackwell
Companion
to
Social
Movements.
D.A.
Snow,
S.A.
Soule,
and
H.
Kriesi,
eds.
Pp.
242-261.
Malden,
MA:
Blackwell
Publishing.
Gamson,
William
A.
and
Andre
Modigliani
1989
Media
Discourse
and
Public
Opinion
on
Nuclear
Power:
A
Constructionist
Approach.
The
American
Journal
of
Sociology
95(1):
1-37.
328
Gangestad,
Steven
W.
1993
Sexual
Selection
and
Attractiveness:
Implications
for
Mating
Dynamics.
Human
Nature
4:
205-236.
Garcia,
Justin
R.,
James
MacKillop,
Edward
L.
Aller,
Ann
M.
Merriwether,
David
Sloan
Wilson,
J.
Koji
Lum
2010
Associations
between
Dopamine
D4
Receptor
Gene
Variation
with
Both
Infidelity
and
Sexual
Promiscuity.
PloS
One
5(11):
e14162.
Garcia,
Justin
R.,
Glenn
Geher,
Benjamin
Crosier,
Gad
Saad,
Daniel
Gambacorta,
Laura
Johnsen,
and
Elissa
Pranckitas
2011
The
Interdisciplinarity
of
Evolutionary
Approaches
to
Human
Beahvior:
A
Key
to
Survival
in
the
Ivory
Archipelago.
Futures
43:
749-761.
Garner,
James
Finn
1994
Politically
Correct
Bedtime
Stories.
London:
Souvenir
Press,
Ltd.
Geary,
David
C.
2007
Educating
the
Evolved
Mind:
Conceptual
Foundations
for
an
Evolutionary
Educational
Psychology.
In
Educating
the
Evolved
Mind:
Conceptual
Foundations
for
an
Evolutionary
Educational
Psychology.
J.
S.
Carlson
and
J.
R.
Levin,
Eds.
Pp.
1-99.
Charlotte,
NC:
Information
Age
Publishing.
2008
An
Evolutionarily
Informed
Education
Science.
Educational
Psychologist
43(4):
179-195.
Geertz,
Clifford
1973
The
Interpretation
of
Cultures.
New
York:
Basic
Books.
1974
From
the
Natives
Point
of
View:
On
the
Nature
of
Anthropological
Understanding.
Bulletin
of
the
American
Academy
of
Arts
and
Sciences
28(1):
26-45.
1984
Distinguished
Lecture:
Anti
Anti-Relativism.
American
Anthropologist
86(2):
263-277.
Geher,
Glenn
2006
Evolutionary
Psychology
is
Not
Evil!
(
and
Heres
Why).
Psychological
Topics
15(2):
181-202.
Geher,
Glenn
and
Daniel
Gambacorta
2010
Evolution
is
Not
Relevant
to
Sex
Differences
in
Humans
Because
I
Want
it
That
Way!
Evidence
for
the
Politicization
of
Human
Evolutionary
Psychology.
EvoS
Journal:
The
Journal
of
the
Evolutionary
Studies
Consortium
2(1):
32-47.
329
Geher,
Glenn,
Benjamin
Crosier,
Halley
Moss
Dillon,
Rosemarie
Sokol
Chang
2011
Evolutionary
Psychologys
Place
in
Evolutionary
Studies:
A
Tale
of
Promise
and
Change.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
4:
11-16.
Geuss,
Raymond
1981
The
Idea
of
A
Critical
Theory:
Habermas
and
the
Frankfurt
School.
Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Giddens,
Anthony
1984
The
Constitution
of
Society:
Outline
of
the
Theory
of
Structuration.
Cambridge,
UK:
Polity
Press.
Glick,
Douglas
J.
2007
Some
Performative
Techniques
of
Stand-Up
Comedy:
An
Exercise
in
the
Textuality
of
Temporalization.
Language
and
Communication
27(3):
291-
306.
2009
Language,
Culture,
and
Communication
in
the
U.S.
Dubuque,
IA:
Kendall
Hunt
Publishing.
Glass,
Daniel,
David
Sloan
Wilson,
and
Glenn
Geher
2012
Evolutionary
Training
in
Relation
to
Human
Affairs
is
Sorely
Lacking
in
Higher
Education.
EvoS
Journal
4(2):
16-22.
Goffman,
Erving
1974
Frame
Analysis:
An
Essay
on
the
Organization
of
Experience.
London:
Harper
and
Row.
1981
Forms
of
Talk.
Philadelphia:
University
of
Pennsylvania
Press.
Goodwin,
Jeff,
and
James
M.
Jasper,
and
Francesca
Polletta
2004
Emotional
Dimensions
of
Social
Movements.
In
The
Blackwell
Companion
to
Social
Movements.
D.A.
Snow,
S.A.
Soule,
and
H.
Kriesi,
eds.
Pp.
413-432.
Malden,
MA:
Blackwell
Publishing.
Gottschall,
Jonathan
2008
Literature,
Science,
and
a
new
Humanities.
New
York:
Palgrave
MacMillan.
Gottschall,
Jonathan
A.
and
Tiffani
A.
Gottschall
2003
Are
Per-Incident
Rape-Pregnancy
Rates
Higher
than
Per-Incident
Consensual
Pregnancy
Rates?
Human
Nature
14(1):
1-20.
330
Gottshall,
Jonathan
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2005
Introduction:
Literature
a
Last
Frontier
in
Human
Evolutionary
Studies.
In
The
Literary
Animal:
Evolution
and
the
Nature
of
Narrative.
J.
Gottschall
and
D.
S.
Wilson,
eds.
Pp.
xvii-xxvi.
Evanston,
IL:
Northwestern
University
Press.
Gottlieb,
Anthony
2012
It
Aint
Necessarily
So.
The
New
Yorker
(Sept
17):
84-89.
Gould,
Stephen
Jay
1991
Exaptation:
A
Crucial
Tool
for
an
Evolutionary
Psychology.
Journal
of
Social
Issues
47(3):
43-65.
1994
Challenges
to
Neo-Darwinism
and
Their
Meaning
for
a
Revised
View
of
Human
Consciousness.
Paper
presented
at
The
Tanner
Lectures
on
Human
Values.
Cambridge,
UK.
2002
I
Have
Landed:
The
End
of
a
Beginning
in
Natural
History.
New
York:
Harmony
Books.
Gould,
Stephen
Jay
and
Richard
C.
Lewontin
1979
The
Spandrels
of
San
Marco
and
the
Panglossian
Paradigm:
A
Critique
of
the
Adaptationist
Programme.
Proceedings
of
the
Royal
Society
of
London
205(1161):
581-598.
Gray,
Peter
2007
Natures
Powerful
Tutors:
The
Educative
Functions
of
Free
Play
and
Exploration.
Eye
on
Psi
Chi
12(1):
18-21.
2011
The
Evolutionary
Biology
of
Education:
How
Our
Hunter-Gatherer
Educative
Instincts
Could
Form
the
Basis
for
Education
Today.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
4:
28-40.
Gray,
Peter
and
David
Chanoff
1986
Democratic
Schooling:
What
Happens
to
Young
People
Who
Have
Charge
of
their
Own
Education?
American
Journal
of
Education
94:
182-213
Griffith,
Joyce
A.
and
Sarah
K.
Brem
2004
Teaching
Evolutionary
Biology:
Pressures,
Stress,
and
Coping.
Journal
of
Resources
in
Science
Teaching
41:
791-809.
Gross,
Paul
R.
and
Norman
Levitt
1994
Higher
Superstition:
The
Academic
Left
and
Its
Quarrels
With
Science.
Baltimore:
Johns
Hopkins
University
Press.
331
Gumperz,
John
J.
1977
Sociocultural
Knowledge
in
Conversational
Inference.
In
28th
Annual
Round
Table
Monograph
Series
on
Language
and
Linguistics.
M.
Saville-Troike,
ed.
Washington
DC:
Georgetown
University
Press.
1978
The
Conversational
Analysis
of
Interethnic
Communication.
In
Interethnic
Communication.
E.
Lamar
Ross,
ed.
Pp.
172-186.
Athens:
University
of
Georgia
Press.
1982
Discourse
Strategies.
Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press.
1992
ContextuaIization
Revisited.
In
The
Contextualization
of
Language.
P.
Auer
and
A.
Di
Luzio.
Pp.
39-54.
Amsterdam:
John
Benjamins
Publishing
Company.
Gumperz,
John
J.
and
Jenny
Cook-Gumperz
1982
Introduction:
Language
and
the
Communication
of
Social
Identity.
In
Language
and
Social
Identity.
J.
Gumperz,
ed.
Pp.
1-21.
Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Habermas,
Jrgen
1990
The
Philosophical
Discourse
on
Modernity:
Twelve
Lectures.
F.
Lawrence,
transl.
Cambridge,
MA:
The
MIT
Press.
1996
Between
Facts
and
Norms:
Contributions
to
a
Discourse
Theory
of
Law
and
Democracy.
W.
Rehg,
transl.
Cambridge,
MA:
The
MIT
Press.
Hagen,
Edward
H.
2005
Controversial
Issues
in
Evolutionary
Psychology.
In
The
Handbook
of
Evolutionary
Psychology.
D.M.
Buss,
ed.
Pp.
145-173.
Hoboken,
NJ:
John
Wiley
and
Sons.
Haig,
David
2006
The
Gene
Meme.
In
Richard
Dawkins:
How
a
Scientist
Changed
the
Way
We
Think.
A.
Grafen
and
M.
Ridely,
eds.
Pp.
50-65.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Hall,
Stuart
1982
The
Rediscovery
of
Ideology:
Return
of
the
Repressed
in
Media
Studies.
In
Culture,
Society,
and
the
Media.
M.
Gurevitch,
T.
Bennet,
J.
Curran,
and
J.
Woollacott,
eds.
Pp.
56-90.
London:
Methuen.
Halliday,
M.A.K.
1971
Linguistic
Function
and
Literary
Style:
An
Enquiry
into
the
Language
of
William
Goldings
The
Inheritors.
In
Literary
Style:
A
Symposium.
S.
Chatman,
ed.
London:
Oxford
University
Press.
332
Hanmer,
Kristen
2008
Lionel
Tiger
Speaks
in
Honor
of
Darwin
Day.
The
New
Paltz
Oracle
13(79).
Haraway,
Donna
J.
1989
Primate
Visions:
Gender,
Race,
and
Nature
in
the
World
of
Modern
Science.
New
York:
Routledge.
1991
Simians,
Cyborgs,
and
Women:
The
Reinvention
of
Nature.
New
York:
Routledge.
Harding,
Cheryl
F.
1985
Sociobiological
Hypotheses
About
Rape:
A
Critical
Look
at
the
Data
Behind
the
Hypotheses.
In
Violence
Against
Women:
A
Critique
of
the
Sociobiology
of
Rape.
S.R.
Sunday
and
E.
Tobach,
eds.
Pp.
23-58.
New
York:
Gordian
Press.
Harding,
Sandra
1998
Is
Science
Multicultural?:
Postcolonialisms,
Feminisms,
and
Epistemologies.
Bloomington:
Indiana
University
Press.
Harman,
Oren
2010
The
Price
of
Altruism:
George
Price
and
the
Search
for
the
Origins
of
Kindness.
New
York:
W.W.
Norton.
Hart,
Stephen
1996
The
Cultural
Dimension
of
Social
Movements:
A
Theoretical
Reassessment
and
Literature
Review.
Sociology
of
Religion
57(1):
87-100.
Haviland,
John
B.
2005
Whorish
Old
Man
and
One
(Animal)
Gentleman:
The
Intertextual
Construction
of
Enemies
and
Selves.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
15(1):
81-94.
Havrnek,
Bohuslav
1964
The
Functional
Differentiation
of
the
Standard
Language.
In
A
Prague
School
Reader
on
Esthetics,
Literary
Structure,
and
Style.
P.
Garvin,
ed.
and
transl.
Pp.
3-16.
Washington,
D.C.:
Georgetown
University
Press.
Hawkes,
Terence
1977
Structuralism
and
Semiotics.
Berkeley:
University
of
California
Press.
Helmreich,
Stefan
and
Heather
Paxson
2005
Sex
on
the
Brain:
A
Natural
History
of
Rape
and
the
Dubious
Doctrines
of
Evolutionary
Psychology.
In
Why
Americas
Top
Pundits
Are
Wrong:
333
Anthropologists
Talk
Back.
C.
Besteman
and
H.
Gusterson,
eds.
Pp.
180-205.
Berkeley:
University
of
California
Press.
Henrich,
Natalie
and
Joseph
Henrich
2007
Why
Humans
Cooperate:
A
Cultural
and
Evolutionary
Explanation.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press
Hewett,
Heather,
Amy
Kesselman
and
Cookie
Chandler
2008
Crouching
Tiger
Meets
Hidden
Dragon
at
SUNY
New
Paltz.
Womens
Studies
News
(March):
2.
Hewitt,
Lyndi
and
Holly
J.
McCammon
2005
Explaining
Suffrage
Mobilization:
Balance,
Neutralization,
and
Range
in
Collective
Action
Frames.
In
Frames
of
Protest:
Social
Movements
and
the
Framing
Perspective.
H.
Johnston
and
J.A.
Noakes,
eds.
Pp.
33-52.
Lanham,
MD:
Rowman
and
Littlefield
Publishers,
Inc.
Heywood,
Leslie
L.,
Justin
R.
Garcia,
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2010
Mind
the
Gap:
Appropriate
Evolutionary
Perspectives
Toward
the
Integration
of
the
Sciences
and
Humanities.
Science
and
Education
19:
505-522.
Hlodan,
Oksana
2008
Evolution:
Applications
in
Human
Health
and
Populations.
BioScience
58(6):
480-483.
Horgan,
John
2006
The
Templeton
Foundation:
A
Skeptics
Take.
The
Chronicle
of
Higher
Education
52:
31.
Hughes,
Geoffrey
2010
Political
Correctness:
A
History
of
Semantics
and
Culture.
Malden,
MA:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Huxley,
Julian
1963
The
Future
of
Man
Evolutionary
Aspects.
In
Man
and
His
Future.
G.
Wolstenholme,
ed.
Pp.
1-22.
London:
J.
&
A.
Churchill,
Ltd.
Ingold,
Tim
1986
The
Appropriation
of
Nature.
Manchester:
Manchester
University
Press.
2000
The
Poverty
of
Selectionism.
Anthropology
Today
16
(3):
1-2.
334
Irvine,
Judith
T.
1996
When
Talk
Isn't
Cheap:
Language
and
Political
Economy.
In
The
Matrix
of
Language:
Contemporary
Linguistic
Anthropology.
D.
Brenneis
and
R.K.S.
Macaulay,
eds.
Pp.
258-283.
Boulder,
CO:
Westview
Press.
1998
Ideologies
of
Honorific
Language
In
Language
Ideologies:
Practice
and
Theory.
B.B.
Schieffelin,
K.A.
Woolard,
and
P.V.
Kroskrity,
eds.
Pp.
51-67.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
2004
Say
When:
Temporalities
in
Language
Ideology.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
14(1):
99-109.
2005
Commentary:
Knots
and
Tears
in
the
Interdiscursive
Fabric.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
15(1):
72-80.
Irvine,
Judith
T.
and
Susan
Gal
2000
Language
Ideology
and
Linguistic
Differentiation.
In
Regimes
of
Language:
Ideologies,
Polities,
and
Identities.
P.V.
Kroskrity,
ed.
Pp.
35-84.
Santa
Fe:
School
of
American
Research
Press.
Jakobson,
Roman
1960
Closing
Statement:
Linguistics
and
Poetics.
In
Style
in
Language.
T.A.
Sebeok,
ed.
Pp.
350-377.
Cambridge,
MA:
The
Technology
Press
of
the
Massachusetts
Institute
of
Technology.
1966
Grammatical
Parallelism
and
Its
Russian
Facet.
Language
42
(2):
399-
429.
Jameson,
Fredric
1972
The
Prison-House
of
Language:
A
Critical
Account
of
Structuralism
and
Russian
Formalism.
Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press.
Journet,
Debra
2010
The
Resources
of
Ambiguity
:
Context,
Narrative,
and
Metaphor
in
Richard
Dawkins's
The
Selfish
Gene.
Journal
of
Business
and
Technical
Communication
24(1):
29-59.
335
Kauffman,
Larry
A.
1990
The
Anti-Politics
of
Identity.
Socialist
Review
20:
67-80.
Kennedy,
Emmet
1979
'Ideology'
from
Destutt
De
Tracy
to
Marx.
Journal
of
the
History
of
Ideas
40(3):
353-368.
Klandermans,
Bert
1994
Transient
Identities?
Membership
Patterns
in
the
Dutch
Peace
Movement.
In
New
Social
Movements:
From
Ideology
to
Identity.
E.
Larana,
H.
Johnston,
J.
Gusfield,
eds.
Pp.168-184.
Philadelphia:
Temple
University
Press.
Kirby,
Mark
2005
The
Simian
Seminar.
Seed
(Oct/Nov):
80-85.
Kniffin,
Kevin
M.
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2005
Utilities
of
Gossip
across
Organizational
Levels:
Multilevel
Selection,
Free-Riders,
and
Teams.
Human
Nature
16(3):
278-292.
2010
Evolutionary
Perspectives
on
Workplace
Gossip:
Why
and
How
Gossip
Can
Serve
Groups.
Group
and
Organizational
Management
35(2):
150-176.
Kroeber,
Alfred
L.
1917
The
Superorganic.
American
Anthropologist
19(2):
163-213.
Kroskrity,
Paul
V.
1998
Arizona
Tewa
Kiva
Speech
as
a
Manifestation
of
a
Dominant
Language
Ideology.
In
Language
Ideologies:
Practice
and
Theory.
B.B.
Schieffelin,
K.A.
Woolard,
and
P.V.
Kroskrity,
eds.
Pp.
103-122.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
2000
Regimenting
Languages:
Language
Ideological
Perspectives.
In
Regimes
of
Language:
Ideologies,
Polities,
and
Identities.
P.V.
Kroskrity,
ed.
Pp.
1-34.
Santa
Fe:
School
of
American
Research
Press.
Labov,
William
1972
Language
in
the
Inner
City:
Studies
in
the
Black
Vernacular
English.
Philadelphia:
University
of
Pennsylvania
Press.
336
Laclau,
Ernesto
1979
Politics
and
Ideology
in
Marxist
Theory:
Capitalism-Fascism-Populism.
London:
Verso.
1997
The
Death
and
Resurrection
of
the
Theory
of
Ideology.
MLN
112:297-
321.
Laland,
Kevin
N.
and
Gilian
R.
Brown
2009
Sense
and
Nonsense:
Evolutionary
Perspectives
on
Human
Nature.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Landau,
Misia
1991
Narratives
of
Human
Evolution.
New
Haven,
CT:
Yale
University
Press.
Latour,
Bruno
1987
Science
In
Action:
How
to
Follow
Scientists
and
Engineers
Through
Society.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
1993
We
Have
Never
Been
Modern.
C.
Porter,
transl.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Latour,
Bruno
and
Shirley
C.
Strum
1986
Human
Social
Origins:
Oh
Please,
Tell
Us
Another
Story.
Journal
of
Social
and
Biological
Structures
9:169-87.
Lauter,
Paul
1995
Political
Correctness
and
the
Attack
on
American
Colleges.
In
Higher
Education
Under
Fire:
Politics,
Economics,
and
the
Crisis
of
the
Humanities.
M.
Brub
and
C.
Nelson,
eds.
Pp.
73-90.
New
York:
Routledge.
Leach,
Edmund
R.
1954
Political
Systems
of
Highland
Burma:
A
Study
of
Kachin
Social
Structure.
London:
G.
Bell
and
Sons,
Ltd.
Lee,
Benjamin
1997
Talking
Heads:
Language,
Metalanguage,
and
the
Semiotics
of
Subjectivity.
Durham:
Duke
University
Press.
Leech,
Geoffrey
N.
2008
Language
in
Literature:
Style
and
Foregrounding.
Harlow,
UK:
Pearson
Education
Limited.
Levin,
Samuel
R.
1963
Deviation
Statistical
and
Determinate
in
Poetic
Language.
Lingua
12:
276-290.
337
Levine,
George
2006
Darwin
Loves
You:
Natural
Selection
and
the
Re-Enchantment
of
the
World.
Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press.
Lessl,
Thomas
M.
2012
Rhetorical
Darwinism:
Religion,
Evolution,
and
the
Scientific
Identity.
Waco,
TX:
Baylor
University
Press.
Levins,
Richard
1966
The
Strategy
of
Model-Building
in
Population
Biology.
American
Scientist
54:
421-31.
Lewontin,
Richard
C.
1977
Biological
Determinism
as
a
Social
Weapon.
In
Biology
as
a
Social
Weapon.
The
Ann
Arbor
Science
for
the
People
Editorial
Collective,
eds.
Pp.
6-
20.
Minneapolis:
Burgess
Publishing
Company.
Lewontin,
Richard
C.,
Steven
Rose,
and
Leon
J.
Kamin
1984
Not
in
our
Genes:
Biology,
Ideology,
and
Human
Nature.
New
York:
Pantheon
Books.
Lloyd,
Elizabeth
A.
2005
The
Case
of
the
Female
Orgasm:
Bias
in
the
Science
of
Evolution.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Lord,
Thomas
and
Suzanna
Marino
1993
How
University
Students
View
the
Theory
of
Evolution.
Journal
of
College
Science
Teaching
22:
353-357.
Lorenz,
Konrad
1966
On
Aggression.
M.K.
Wilson,
transl.
New
York:
Harcourt,
Brace,
and
World.
Lustick,
Ian
S.
2005
Daniel
Dennett,
Comparative
Politics,
and
the
Dangerous
Idea
of
Evolution.
American
Political
Science
Association-Comparative
Politics
Newsletter
16(2):
19-24.
Lutz,
Catherine
A.
1988
Unnatural
Emotions:
Everyday
Sentiments
on
a
Micronesian
Atoll
and
Their
Challenge
to
Western
Theory.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Lyons,
John
1972
Human
Language.
In
Non-Verbal
Communication.
R.A.
Hinde,
ed.
Pp.
49-85.
London:
Cambridge
at
the
University
Press.
338
Malik,
Kenan
2000
Man,
Beast,
and
Zombie:
What
Science
Can
and
Cannot
Tell
Us
About
Human
Nature.
New
Brunswick:
Rutgers
University
Press.
Maltz,
Daniel
N.
and
Ruth
A.
Borker
1982
A
Cultural
Approach
to
Male-Female
Miscommunication.
In
Language
and
Social
Identity.
J.
Gumperz,
ed.
Pp.
196-
215.
Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press.
Marayanski,
Alexandra
and
Jonathan
H.Turner
1992
The
Social
Cage:
Human
Nature
and
the
Evolution
of
Society.
Stanford:
Stanford
University
Press.
Marks,
Jonathan
1994
Human
Biodiversity:
Genes,
Race,
and
History.
New
York:
Aldine
De
Gruyter.
2002
What
It
Means
to
be
98%
Chimpanzee:
Apes,
People,
and
Their
Genes.
Berkeley:
University
of
California
Press.
Marris,
Emma
2010
All
Evolution,
All
the
Time.
Nature
(May
25).
Electronic
document.
Http://www.nature.com/news/2010/100525/full/news.2010.260.html.
Accessed
May
25,
2010.
2011
Darwins
City.
Nature
474:
146-149
Martin,
Emily
1991
The
Egg
and
the
Sperm:
How
Science
Has
Constructed
a
Romance
Based
on
Stereotypical
Male-Female
Roles.
Signs
16(3):
485-501.
1994
The
Ethnography
of
Natural
Selection
in
the
1990s.
Cultural
Anthropology
9(3):
383-397.
Maynard
Smith,
John
1978
Optimization
Theory
in
Evolution.
Annual
Review
of
Ecology
and
Systematics
9:
31-56
McCarthy,
John
D.
and
Mayer
N.
Zald
1977
Resource
Mobilization
and
Social
Movements:
A
Partial
Theory.
The
American
Journal
of
Sociology
82
(6):
1212-1241.
McCaughey,
Martha
2008
The
Caveman
Mystique:
Pop-Darwinism
and
the
Debates
over
Sex,
Violence,
and
Science.
New
York:
Routledge.
339
McKinnon,
Susan
2005a
On
Kinship
and
Marriage:
A
Critique
of
the
Genetic
Calculus
of
Evolutionary
Psychology.
In
Complexities:
Beyond
Nature
and
Nurture.
S.
McKinnon
and
S.
Silverman,
eds.
Pp.
107-131.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
2005b
Neo-Liberal
Genetics:
The
Myths
and
Moral
Tales
of
Evolutionary
Psychology.
Chicago:
Prickly
Paradigm
Press.
Melucci,
Alberto
1988
Getting
Involved:
Identity
and
Mobilization
in
Social
Movements.
In
International
Social
Movement
Research,
Vol.
1:
From
Structure
to
Action.
B.
Klandermans,
H.
Kriesi,
and
S.
Tarrow,
eds.
Pp.329-348.
New
York:
JAI
Press.
1989
Nomads
of
the
Present:
Social
Movements
and
Individual
Needs
in
Contemporary
Society.
Philadelphia:
Temple
University
Press.
1994
A
Strange
Kind
of
Newness:
What's
'New'
in
New
Social
Movements.
In
New
Social
Movements:
From
Ideology
to
Identity.
Pp.
101-130.
E.
Larana,
H.
Johnston,
and
J.
Gusfield,
eds.
Philadelphia:
Temple
University.
Mendieta,
Constantino
2006a
Classification
System
for
Gluteal
Evaluation.
Clinics
in
Plastic
Surgery
33(3):
333-346.
2006b
Intramuscular
Gluteal
Augmentation
Technique.
Clinics
in
Plastic
Surgery
33(3):
423-434.
Mertz,
Elizabeth
1985
Beyond
Symbolic
Anthropology:
Introducing
Semiotic
Mediation.
In
Semiotic
Mediation:
Sociocultural
and
Psychological
Perspectives.
E.
Mertz
and
R.J.
Parmentier,
eds.
Pp.
1-19.
Orlando,
FL::
Academic
Press,
Inc.
1994
Legal
Language:
Pragmatics,
Poetics,
and
Social
Power.
Annual
Review
of
Anthropology
23:435-455.
1998
Linguistic
Ideology
and
Praxis
in
US
LAS
School
Classrooms.
In
Language
Ideologies:
Practice
and
Theory.
B.B.
Schieffelin,
K.A.
Woolard,
and
P.V.
Kroskrity,
eds.
Pp.
149-162.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
2007
Semiotic
Anthropology.
Annual
Review
of
Anthropology
36:
337-353.
Mertz,
Elizabeth
and
Bernard
Weisbound
1985
Legal
Ideology
and
Liguistic
Thery:
Variability
and
Its
Limits.
In
Semiotic
Mediation:
Sociocultural
and
Psychological
Perspectives.
E.
Mertz
and
R.J.
Parmentier,
eds.
Pp.
262-286.
Orlando,
FL:
Academic
Press,
Inc.
340
Meyer,
Peter
2008
Cooperation
Without
Coercion?
Responses
to
Sanderson's
Conflict
Perspective.
In
The
New
Evolutionary
Social
Science:
Human
Nature,
Social
Behavior,
and
Social
Change.
H.J.
Niedenzu,
T.
Meleghy,
P.
Meyer,
eds.
Pp.
79-
88.
Boulder:
Paradigm
Publishers.
Mindell,
David
P.
2006
The
Evolving
World:
Evolution
in
Everyday
Life.
Cambridge:
Harvard
University
Press.
Mitchell,
Sandra
D.
1995
The
Superorganism
Metaphor:
Then
and
Now.
In
Biology
as
Society,
Society
as
Biology:
Metaphors.
S.
Maasen,
E.
Mendelsohn,
and
P.
Weingart,
eds.
Pp.
231-247.
Dordrecht,
The
Netherlands:
Kluwer
Academic
Publishers.
Mitman,
Gregg
1992
The
State
of
Nature:
Ecology,
Community,
and
American
Social
Thought,
1900-1950.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Moore,
Henrietta
L.
2007
The
Subject
of
Anthropology:
Gender,
Symbolism,
and
Psychoanalysis.
Cambridge,
UK:
Polity
Press.
Moore,
Kelly
2008
Disrupting
Science:
Social
Movements,
American
Scientists,
and
the
Politics
of
the
Military,
1945-1975.
Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press.
Moran,
Joe
2010
Interdisciplinarity,
Second
Edition.
London:
Routledge.
Morrow,
Maureen,
Brian
Obach,
Giordana
Grossi
,
Morgan
Gwenwald,
Anne
Roschelle,
Peter
Kaufman,
Alison
Nash,
Eve
Waltermaurer,
Gowri
Parameswaran,
Karl
Bryant,
Maryalice
Citera,
Amy
Kessleman,
Judy
Dorney,
Susan
Kelly,
Nancy
Schniedewind
2008
Faculty
Reactions
to
Lionel
Tigers
Lecture
Regarding
Evolution.
The
New
Paltz
Oracle
13(79).
Mukaovsk,
Jan
1964
Standard
Language
and
Poetic
Language.
In
A
Prague
School
Reader
on
Esthetics,
Literary
Structure,
and
Style.
P.
Garvin,
ed.
and
transl.
Pp.
17-30.
Washington,
D.C.:
Georgetown
University
Press.
Nunberg,
Geoffrey
1993
Indexicality
and
Deixis.
Linguistics
and
Philosophy
16(1):
1-43.
341
Oakley,
Barbara
A.
2007
Evil
Genes:
Why
Rome
Fell,
Hitler
Rose,
Enron
Failed,
and
My
Sister
Stole
My
Mothers
Boyfriend.
Amherst,
NY:
Prometheus
Books.
Obach,
Brian
2008
Faculty
Reactions
to
Lionel
Tigers
Lecture
Regarding
Evolution
2.
The
New
Paltz
Oracle
13(79).
OBrien,
Daniel
T.
2009
Sociality
in
the
City:
Using
Biological
Principles
to
Explore
the
Relationship
Between
High
Population
Density
and
Social
Behavior.
In
Advances
in
Sociology
Research,
Volume
8.
J.A.
Jaworski,
ed.
Pp.
1-14.
Nova
Science
Publishers,
Inc.
2010
The
Development
and
Expression
of
Positive
Social
Behaviors
in
Urban
Settings:
A
Multidisciplinary,
Evolutionary
Approach.
Ph.D.
Dissertation.
Binghamton
University,
Binghamton,
New
York.
OBrien,
Daniel
T.
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2010
Using
Evolution
for
Everyone
as
a
Guide
for
New
General
Education
Courses
in
Evolution.
EvoS
Journal
2(1):
1-11.
2011
Community
Perception:
The
Ability
to
Assess
the
Safety
of
Unfamiliar
Neighborhoods
and
Respond
Adaptively.
Journal
of
Personality
and
Social
Psychology
100(4):
606-620.
OBrien,
Daniel
T.,
Andrew
C.
Gallup,
and
David
Sloan
Wilson
2012
Residential
Mobility
and
Prosocial
Development
Within
a
Single
City.
American
Journal
of
Community
Psychology
50:
26-36.
OBrien,
Daniel
T.,
David
Sloan
Wilson,
and
Patricia
H.
Hawley
2009
Evolution
for
Everyone:
A
Course
that
Expands
Evolutionary
Theory
Beyond
the
Biological
Sciences.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
2:
445-457.
Ochs,
Elinor
1990
Indexicality
and
Socialization.
In
Cultural
Psychology.
J.W.
Stigler,
R.A.
Shweder,
and
G.
Herdt,
eds.
Pp.
287308.
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press.
OGorman,
Rick,
David
Sloan
Wilson,
and
Ralph
R.
Miller
2005
Altruistic
Punishing
and
Helping
Differ
in
Sensitivity
to
Relatedness,
Friendship,
and
Future
Interactions.
Evolution
and
Human
Behavior
26:
375-
387.
342
Olson,
Macur
1965
The
Logic
of
Collective
Action:
Public
Goods
and
the
Theory
of
Groups.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Palmer,
Craig
1988
Twelve
Reasons
Why
Rape
is
Not
Sexually
Motivated:
A
Skeptical
Examination.
Journal
of
Sex
Research
25(4):
512-530.
1989
Is
Rape
a
Cultural
Universal?
A
Re-Examination
of
the
Ethnoevidence.
Ethnology
28:
1-16.
1991
Human
Rape:
Adaptation
or
By-Product?
Journal
of
Sex
Research
28:
365-386.
Park,
Robert
E.
1967
On
Social
Control
and
Collective
Behavior:
Selected
Papers.
R.H.
Turner,
ed.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Parker,
Geoffrey
A.
and
John
Maynard
Smith
1990
Optimality
Theory
in
Evolutionary
Biology.
Nature
348:
27-33.
Parmentier,
Richard
J.
1985
Signs'
Place
in
Media
Res:
Peirce's
Concept
of
Semiotic
Mediation.
In
Semiotic
Mediation:
Sociocultural
and
Psychological
Perspectives.
E.
Mertz
and
R.J.
Parmentier,
eds.
Pp.
24-48.
Orlando,
FL:
Academic
Press,
Inc.
1994
Signs
in
Society:
Studies
in
Semiotic
Anthropology.
Bloomington:
Indiana
University
Press.
Parsons,
Talcott
1967
[1959]
An
Approach
to
the
Sociology
of
Knowledge.
In
Sociological
Theory
and
Modern
Society.
Pp.
139-165.
New
York:
The
Free
Press.
Pcheux,
Michel
1982
Language,
Semantics,
and
Ideology:
Stating
the
Obvious.
H.
Nagpal,
transl.
London:
The
Macmillan
Press
Ltd.
Perry,
John
1997
Indexicals
and
Demonstratives.
In
A
Companion
to
the
Philosophy
of
Language.
R.
Hale
and
C.
Wright,
eds.
Pp.
586-612.
Oxford:
Blackwell
Publishers
Inc.
Pichardo,
Nelson
A.
1997
New
Social
Movements:
A
Critical
Review.
Annual
Review
of
Sociology
23:
411-430.
343
Pinker,
Steven
1994
The
Language
Instinct.
New
York:
W.
Morrow
and
Co.
2002
The
Blank
Slate:
The
Modern
Denial
of
Human
Nature.
London:
Penguin
Books.
2013
Science
is
Not
Your
Enemy.
New
Republic
244
(13):
28-33.
Platek,
Steven
M.,
Glenn
Geher,
Leslie
Heywood,
Hamilton
Stapell,
J.
Ryan
Porter,
Tia
Y.
Walter
2011
Walking
the
Walk
to
Teach
the
Talk:
Implementing
Ancestral
Lifestyle
Strategies
as
the
Newest
Tool
in
Evolutionary
Studies.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
4:
41-51.
Plotke,
David
1990
Whats
So
New
About
New
Social
Movements?
Socialist
Review
20:
81-
102.
Plotz,
David
1997
Gods
Venture
Capitalist:
The
Strange
Quest
of
Sir
John
Templeton.
Slate
(June
8).
Electronic
document.
Http://www.slate.com/id/1822/.
Accessed
July
1st,
2011.
Post,
Stephen
G.,
Lynn
G.
Underwood,
Jeffrey
P.
Schloss,
William
B.
Hurlbut,
eds.
2002
Altruism
and
Altruistic
Love:
Science,
Philosophy,
and
Religion
in
Dialogue.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Price,
Rebecca
M.
2011
Performing
Evolution:
Role-Play
Simulations.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
4:
83-94.
Prindle,
David
F.
2009
Stephen
Jay
Gould
and
the
Politics
of
Evolution.
Amherst,
NY:
Prometheus
Books.
Rapp,
Rayna
1999
Testing
Women,
Testing
the
Fetus:
The
Social
Impact
of
Amniocentesis
in
America.
New
Haven:
Yale
University
Press.
Readings,
Bill
1996
The
University
in
Ruins.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Reiber,
Chris
and
Justin
R.
Garcia
2010
Hooking
Up:
Gender
Differences,
Evolution,
and
Pluralistic
Ignorance.
Evolutionary
Psychology
8(3):
390-404.
344
Richerson,
Peter
J.
and
Robert
Boyd
2005
Not
By
Genes
Alone:
How
Culture
Transformed
Human
Evolution.
Chicago:
The
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Ridley,
Matt
2006
Richard
Dawkins
and
the
Golden
Pen.
In
Richard
Dawkins:
How
a
Scientist
Changed
the
Way
We
Think.
A.
Grafen
and
M.
Ridely,
eds.
Pp.
265-
269.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Rilling,
James
K.,
James
T.
Winslow,
and
Clinton
D.
Kilts
2004
The
Neural
Correlates
of
Mate
Competition
in
Dominant
Male
Rhesus
Macaques.
Biological
Psychiatry
56(3):
64-375.
Robertson,
Ross
2007
Can
Darwin
Save
Dartmouth
from
Derrida?
EnlightenNext
Magazine
37.
Http://www.enlightennext.org/magazine/j37/sloan-wilson.asp.
Accessed
July
17,
2010.
Robnett,
Belinda
2002
External
Political
Change,
Collective
Identities,
and
Participation
in
Social
Movement
Organizations.
In
Social
Movements:
Identity,
Culture,
and
the
State.
D.S.
Meyer,
N.
Whittier,
and
B.
Robnett.
Pp.
266-285.Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Salhins,
Marshall
D.
1968
African
Nemesis:
An
Off-Broadway
Review.
In
Man
and
Aggression.
M.F.A.
Montagu,
ed.
Pp.
116-140.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
1976
Culture
and
Practical
Reason.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
1976
The
Use
and
Abuse
of
Biology:
An
Anthropological
Critique
of
Sociobiology.
Ann
Arbor:
University
of
Michigan
Press.
Sapir,
Edward.
1985[1929]
The
Status
of
Linguistics
as
a
Science.
In
Selected
Writings
of
Edward
Sapir
in
Language,
Culture
and
Personality.
D.G.
Mandelbaum,
ed.
Pp.
160-166.
Berkeley:
University
of
California
Press.
1985[1933].
Language.
In
Selected
Writings
of
Edward
Sapir
in
Language,
Culture
and
Personality.
D.G.
Mandelbaum,
ed.
Pp.
7-32.
Berkeley:
University
of
California
Press.
Schlesinger,
Arthur
M.
1991
The
Disuniting
of
America.
Knoxville:
Whittle
Direct
Books.
345
Schneider,
Nathan
2010
God,
Science,
and
Philanthropy:
The
Politics
of
The
John
Templeton
Foundation's
'Big
Questions'.
The
Nation
290(24):
11-17.
Searle,
John
R.
1976
A
Classification
of
Illocutionary
Acts.
Language
in
Society
5:
1-23.
1995
Postmodernism
and
the
Western
Rationalist
Tradition.
In
Campus
Wars:
Multiculturalism
and
the
Politics
of
Difference.
J.
Arthur
and
A.
Shapiro,
eds.
Pp.
28-48.
Boulder,
CO:
Westview
Press.
Segerstrle,
Ullica
2000
Defenders
of
the
Truth:
The
Battle
for
Science
in
the
Sociobiology
Debate
and
Beyond.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
2001
World
Views
and
Trojan
Horses
in
the
Sociobiology
Debate.
Journal
of
Bioscience
26(5):
549-554.
2006
An
Eye
on
the
Core:
Dawkins
and
Sociobiology.
In
Richard
Dawkins:
How
A
Scientist
Changed
the
Way
We
Think.
A.
Grafen
and
M.
Ridley,
eds.
Pp.
75-97.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Shackelford,
Todd
K.
and
Viviana
A.
Weekes-Shackelford
2004
Why
Don't
Men
Pay
Child
Support?
Insights
From
Evolutionary
Psychology.
In
Evolutionary
Psychology,
Public
Policy,
and
Personal
Decisions.
C.
Crawford
and
C.
Salmon,
eds.
Pp.
231-247.
Mahwah,
NJ:
Lawrence
Erlbaum
Associates,
Publishers.
Shavit,
Ayelet
2004
Shifting
Values
Partly
Explain
the
Debate
Over
Group
Selection.
Studies
in
the
History
and
Philosophy
of
Biology
and
Biomedicine
35:
697-720.
Shen,
Yeshayahu
2007
Foregrounding
in
Poetic
Discourse:
Between
Deviation
and
Cognitive
Constraints.
Language
and
Literature
16(2):
169-181.
Sherzer,
Joel
1987
A
Discourse-Centered
Approach
to
Language
and
Culture.
American
Anthropologist
89(2):
295-309.
Shklovsky,
Viktor
1965
[1917].
Art
as
Technique.
In
Russian
Formalist
Criticism:
Four
Essays.
L.
T.
Lemon
and
M.
J.
Reis,
eds.
and
transl.
Pp.
3-57.
Lincoln,
NE:
University
of
Nebraska
Press.
346
Short,
M.H.
1973
Some
Thoughts
on
Foregrounding
and
Interpretation.
Language
and
Style
6:
97-108.
Silverstein,
Michael
1976
Shifters,
Linguistic
Categories,
and
Cultural
Description
In
Meaning
in
Anthropology.
K.
Basso
and
H.
Selby,
eds.
Pp.
1155.
Albuquerque:
University
of
New
Mexico
Press.
1979
Linguistic
Structure
and
Linguistic
Ideology.
In
The
Elements:
A
Parasession
on
Linguistic
Units
and
Levels.
P.R.
Cline,
W.F.
Hanks,
and
C.L.
Hofbauer,
eds.
Chicago:
Chicago
Linguistic
Society.
1985
Language
and
the
Culture
of
Gender:
At
the
Intersection
of
Structure,
Usage,
and
Ideology.
In
Semiotic
Mediation:
Sociocultural
and
Psychological
Perspectives.
E.
Mertz
and
R.J.
Parmentier,
eds.
Pp.
220-260.
Orlando,
FL:
Academic
Press,
Inc.
1992
The
Indeterminacy
of
Contextualization:
When
Is
Enough
Enough?
In
The
Contextualization
of
Language.
P.
Auer
and
A.
Di
Luzio.
Pp.
55-76.
Amsterdam:
John
Benjamins
Publishing
Company.
1996
Monoglot
'Standard'
in
America:
Standardization
and
Metaphors
of
Linguistic
Hegemony.
In
The
Matrix
of
Language:
Contemporary
Linguistic
Anthropology.
D.
Brenneis
and
R.K.S.
Macaulay,
eds.
Pp.
284-306.
Boulder,
CO:
Westview
Press.
1998
The
Uses
and
Utility
of
Ideology:
Some
Reflections.
In
Language
Ideologies:
Practice
and
Theory.
B.B.
Schieffelin,
K.A.
Woolard,
and
P.V.
Kroskrity,
eds.
Pp.
123-145.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
2000
Whorfianism
and
the
Linguistic
Imagination
of
Nationality.
In
Regimes
of
Language:
Ideologies,
Polities,
and
Identities.
P.V.
Kroskrity,
ed.
Pp.
85-138.
Santa
Fe:
School
of
American
Research
Press.
2003
Indexical
Order
and
the
Dialectics
of
Social
Life.
Language
and
Communication
23(3-4):
193-229.
Simpson,
George
Gaylord
1941
The
Role
of
the
Individual
in
Evolution.
Journal
of
the
Washington
Academy
of
Sciences
31(1):
1-20.
Sleater,
Roy
D.
2008
The
Human
Superorganism
Of
Microbes
and
Men.
Medical
Hypotheses
74:
214-215.
347
Smelser,
Neil
J.
1962
Theory
of
Collective
Behavior.
New
York:
The
Free
Press.
Smith,
Anne
Marie
1994
Rastafari
as
Resistance
and
the
Ambiguities
of
Essentialism
in
the
`New
Social
Movements'.
In
The
Making
of
Political
Identities.
E.
Laclau,
ed.
Pp.
171-204.
London:
Verso.
Smith,
Barbara
Herrnstein
2005
Scandalous
Knowledge:
Science,
Truth,
and
the
Human.
Durham,
NC:
Duke
University
Press.
Smith,
Mike
U.
2010a
Current
Status
of
Research
in
Teaching
and
Learning
Evolution:
I.
Philosophical/
Epistemological
Issues.
Science
and
Education
19:
523-538.
2010b
Current
Status
of
Research
in
Teaching
and
Learning
Evolution:
II.
Pedagogical
Issues.
Science
and
Education
19:
539-571.
Snow,
David
A.
2004
Framing
Processes,
Ideology
and
Discursive
Fields.
In
The
Blackwell
Companion
to
Social
Movements.
D.
A.
Snow,
S.
A.
Soule
and
H.
Kriesi,
eds.
Pp.
380-412.
Malden,
MA:
Blackwell
Publishing:
Snow,
David
A.
and
Robert
D.
Benford
1988
Ideology,
Frame
Resonance,
and
Participant
Mobilization.
International
Social
Movement
Research
1:
197-217.
1992
Master
Frames
and
Cycles
of
Protest.
In
Frontiers
in
Social
Movement
Theory
A.
D.
Morris
and
C.
McClurg-Mueller,
eds.
Pp.133-155
New
Haven,
CN:
Yale
University
Press.
Snow,
David
A.,
and
Pamela
E.
Oliver
1995
Social
Movements
and
Collective
Behavior:
Social
Psychological
Dimensions
and
Considerations.
In
Sociological
Perspectives
on
Social
Psychology.
K.S.
Cook,
G.A.
Fine,
and
J.S.
House,
eds.
Pp.
57
I
-599.
Boston:
Allyn
and
Bacon.
Snow,
David
A.,
E.
Burke
Rochford,
Jr.,
Steven
K.
Worden
and
Robert
D.
Benford
1986
Frame
Alignment
Processes,
Micromobilization
and
Movement
Participation.
American
Sociological
Review
51(4):
464
-481.
Sober,
Elliot
1987
What
is
Adaptationism?
In
The
Latest
on
the
Best:
Essays
on
Evolution
and
Optimality.
J.
Dupre,
ed.
Pp.
105-118.
Cambridge:
MIT
Press.
348
Sober,
Elliott
and
David
S.
Wilson
1998
Unto
Others:
The
Evolution
and
Psychology
of
Unselfish
Behavior.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Sociobiology
Study
Group
1977
Sociobiology:
A
New
Biological
Determinism.
In
Biology
as
a
Social
Weapon.
The
Ann
Arbor
Science
for
the
People
Editorial
Collective,
eds.
Pp.
133-150.
Minneapolis:
Burgess
Publishing
Company.
Sokal,
Alan
D.
1996
Transgressing
the
Boundaries:
Toward
a
Hermeneutics
Of
Quantum
Gravity.
Social
Text
46/47:
217-252.
Sperling,
Susan
2008
Ashleys
Ghost:
McCarthyism,
Science,
and
Human
Nature.
In
Anthropology
at
the
Dawn
of
the
Cold
War.
D.M.
Wax,
ed.
Pp.
17-36.
London:
Pluto
Press.
Spivak,
Gayarti
Chakravorty
1988
Can
the
Subaltern
Speak?
In
Marxism
and
the
Interpretation
of
Culture.
C.
Nelson
and
L.
Grossberg,
eds.
Pp.
271-313.
Urbana:
University
of
Illinois
Press.
Sterelny,
Kim
2001
Dawkins
vs.
Gould:
Survival
of
the
Fittest.
Cambridge,
UK:
Icon
Books
Ltd.
Stocking,
George
W,
Jr.
1982
Race,
Culture,
and
Evolution:
Essays
in
the
History
of
Anthropology.
Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press.
Storm,
Ingrid
and
David
S.
Wilson
2009
Liberal
and
Conservative
Protestant
Denominations
as
Different
Socioecological
Strategies.
Human
Nature
20:
1-24.
Strathern,
Marilyn
1992
Reproducing
the
Future:
Essays
on
Anthropology,
Kinship,
and
the
New
Reproductive
Technologies.
New
York:
Routledge.
Summers,
Lawrence
H.
2005
Remarks
at
NBER
Conference
on
Diversifying
the
Science
&
Engineering
Workforce.
Lecture
delivered
January
14,
2005,
Cambridge,
MA.
Electronic
document.http://web.archive.org/web/20080130023006/
http://www.president.harvard.edu/speeches/2005/nber.html.
Accessed
June
14,
2011.
349
Susser,
Bernard
1988
The
Grammar
of
Modern
Ideology.
London:
Routledge.
1996
The
Domains
of
Ideological
Discourse.
Journal
of
Political
Ideologies
1(2):
165-182.
Tarrow,
Sidney
G.
1991
Struggle,
Politics,
and
Reform:
Collective
Action,
Social
Movements,
and
Cycles
of
Protest.
Ithaca,
NY:
Cornell
University
Press.
Thompson,
John
B.
1984
Studies
in
the
Theory
of
Ideology.
Berkeley:
University
of
California
Press.
1990
Ideology
and
Modern
Culture.
Stanford:
Stanford
University
Press.
Thornhill,
Nancy
W.
and
Randy
Thornhill
1990a.
An
Evolutionary
Analysis
of
Pain
of
Rape
Victims
I:
The
Effects
of
Victim's
Age
and
Marital
Status.
Ethology
and
Sociobiology
11:
155-176.
1990b
An
Evolutionary
Analysis
of
Pain
of
Rape
Victims
II:
The
effects
of
Stranger,
Friend
and
Family
Members.
Ethology
and
Sociobiology
11:
177-
193.
1990c
An
Evolutionary
Analysis
of
Pain
of
Rape
Victims
III:
The
Effects
of
Force
and
Violence.
Aggressive
Behavior
16:
297-320.
1991
An
Evolutionary
Analysis
of
Pain
of
Rape
Victims
IV:
The
Effect
of
the
Nature
of
the
Sexual
Act.
Journal
of
Comparative
Psychology
105:
243-252.
Thornhill,
Randy
1980
Rape
in
Panorpa
Scorpion
Flies
and
a
General
Rape
Hypothesis.
Animal
Behavior
28:
52-59.
Thornhill,
Randy
and
Craig
Palmer
2000
A
Natural
History
of
Rape:
Biological
Bases
of
Sexual
Coercion.
Cambridge,
MA:
The
MIT
Press.
Thornhill,
Randy
and
Nancy
W.
Thornhill
1983
Human
Rape:
An
Evolutionary
Analysis.
Ethology
and
Sociobiology
4:
137-173.
Thornhill,
Randy,
Nancy
W.
Thornhill,
and
Gerard
A.
Dizinno
1986
The
Biology
of
Rape.
In
Rape.
S.
Tomaselli
and
R.
Porter.
Pp.
102-121.
New
York:
Blackwell
350
Tiger,
Lionel
1969
Men
in
Groups.
New
York:
Random
House.
1996
My
Life
in
the
Human
Nature
Wars.
The
Wilson
Quarterly
20(1):
14-25.
1999
The
Decline
of
Males:
The
First
Look
at
an
Unexpected
New
World
for
Men
and
Women.
New
York:
St.
Martins
Griffin.
2005
Youve
Got
Male!
Wall
Street
Journal
Dec.
17:
A10.
Tilly,
Charles
1973
Does
Modernization
Breed
Revolution?
Comparative
Politics
5(3):
425-447.
Tooby,
John
and
Leda
Cosmides
1992
The
Psychological
Foundations
of
Culture.
In
The
Adapted
Mind:
Evolutionary
Psychology
and
the
Generation
of
Culture.
J.H.
Barkow,
L.
Cosmides,
and
J.
Tooby,
eds.
Pp.
19-136.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
Travis,
Cheryl
Brown
2003
Talking
Evolution
and
Selling
Difference.
In
Evolution,
Gender,
and
Rape.
C.B.
Brown,
ed.
Pp.
3-27.
Cambridge:
The
MIT
Press.
Trivers,
Robert
1998
As
They
Would
Do
to
You.
Skeptic
6(4):
81-83.
Turchin,
Peter
2003
Historical
Dynamics:
Why
States
Rise
and
Fall.
Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press.
2006
War
and
Peace
and
War:
The
Life
Cycles
of
Imperial
Nations.
New
York:
Pearson.
Turner,
Ralph
H.
1969
The
Public
Perception
of
Protest.
American
Sociological
Review
34(6):
816-831.
Urban,
Greg
1991
A
Discourse-Centered
Approach
to
Culture.
Austin:
University
of
Texas
Press
Urciuoli,
Bonnie
1996
Exposing
Prejudice:
Puerto
Rican
Experiences
of
Language,
Race,
and
Class.
Boulder,
CO:
Westwiew
Press.
351
Vaid,
Urvashi
1996
Virtual
Equality:
The
Mainstreaming
of
Gay
and
Lesbian
Liberation.
New
York:
Random
House.
Van
Dijk,
Teun
A.
2006
Ideology
and
Discourse
Analysis.
Journal
of
Political
ideologies
11(2):
115-140.
Van
Peer,
Willie
1986
Stylistics
and
Psychology:
Investigations
of
Foregrounding.
London:
Croom
Helm.
Vermeij,
Geerat
J.
2010
The
Evolutionary
World:
How
Adaptation
Explains
Everything
from
Seashells
to
Civilization.
New
York:
Thomas
Dunne
Books.
Vieth,
Erich
2010
Evolution
Imprisoned
in
Biology
Classrooms.
Dangerous
Intersection:
June
6th.
Electronic
document.
Http://dangerousintersection.org/2010/
06/06/evolution-imprisoned-in-biology-classrooms/.
Accessed
July
11th,
2011.
Voloinov,
V.
N.
1986
[1929]
Marxism
and
the
Philosophy
of
Language.
L.
Matejka
and
I.R.
Titunik,
transl.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Watson,
James
D.
1968
The
Double
Helix:
A
Personal
Account
of
the
Discovery
of
the
Structure
of
DNA.
New
York:
Atheneum.
Webb,
Stephen
H.
2007
Three
Musings
on
the
Slow
and
Steady
Descent
of
Darwinism.
Reviews
in
Religion
and
Theology
14:4:
616-624.
Weidman,
Nadine
2011
Popularizing
the
Ancestry
of
Man:
Robert
Ardrey
and
the
Killer
Instinct.
Isis
102(2):
269-299.
352
Wellek,
Ren
1960
Closing
Statement
from
the
Viewpoint
of
Literary
Analysis.
In
Style
in
Language.
T.A.
Sebeok,
ed.
Pp.
408-419.
Cambridge,
MA:
The
Technology
Press
of
the
Massachusetts
Institute
of
Technology.
Wheeler,
William
M.
1911
The
Ant-Colony
as
an
Organism.
Journal
of
Morphology
22(2):
307-
325.
Whorf,
Benjamin
1940
Science
and
Linguistics.
Technological
Review
42(6):
229-231,
247-248.
1956
[1939]
The
Relation
of
Habitual
Thought
and
Behavior
to
Language.
In
Language,
Thought,
and
Reality:
Selected
Writings
of
Benjamin
Lee
Whorf.
J.B.
Carroll,
ed.
Pp.
134-159.Cambridge:
MIT
Press.
Wiarda,
Howard
J.
2010
Introduction.
In
Grand
Theories
and
Ideologies
in
the
Social
Sciences.
H.J.
Wiarda,
ed.
Pp.
1-18.
New
York:
Palgrave
MacMillan.
Widdowson,
H.G.
1973
The
Deviance
of
Literary
Discourse.
Style
6:
294-305
Williams,
George
C.
1966
Adaptation
and
Natural
Selection.
Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
1990
Species
of
Thought:
A
Comment
on
Evolutionary
Epistemology.
Biology
and
Philosophy
5:
37-62.
1995
Language
as
a
Community
of
Interacting
Belief
Systems:
A
Case
Study
Involving
Conduct
Toward
Self
and
Others.
Biology
and
Philosophy
10(1):
77-
97.
1997a
Biological
Communities
as
Functionally
Organized
Units.
Ecology
78(7):
2018-2024.
1997b
Human
Groups
as
Units
of
Selection.
Science
276(5320):
1816-1817.
1997c
Incorporating
Group
Selection
into
the
Adaptationist
Program:
A
Case
Study
Involving
Human
Decision
Making.
In
Evolutionary
Social
Psychology.
J.A.
Simpson
and
D.T.
Kenrick,
eds.
Pp.
345-386.
Mahwah,
NJ:
Lawrence
Erlbaum
Associates,
Publishers.
353
2002b
Evolution,
Morality
and
Human
Potential.
In
Evolutionary
Psychology:
Alternative
Approaches.
S.
J.
Scher
and
F.
Rauscher,
eds.
Pp.
55-
70.
New
York:
Kluwer.
2004
The
New
Fable
of
the
Bees:
Multilevel
Selection,
Adaptive
Societies,
and
the
Concept
of
Self
Interest.
Advances
in
Australian
Economics
7:
201-
220.
2005a
Evolution
for
Everyone:
How
to
Increase
Acceptance
of,
Interest
in,
and
Knowledge
about
Evolution.
PLoS
Biology
3(12):
1001-1008.
2007b
Evolutionary
Theory
Has
Arrived
in
the
Human
Behavioral
Sciences
But
Not
The
Structure
of
Higher
Education.
Electronic
Document.
http://evolution.binghamton.edu/
evos/wp-content/uploads/2009/08/DSW-BBS-analysis.pdf.
Accessed
July
11,
2010.
354
2009a
On
the
Importance
of
Mixed-Age
Learning
and
How
to
Make
the
Most
of
It
in
an
EvoS
Program.
Electronic
Document.
Http://evostudies.org/blog/?p=107.
Accessed
Oct
10,
2010.
2010
Social
Darwinism
Shows
We
Control
Our
Environment.
Sydney
Morning
Herald
(Sept
29):
15.
2011a
Evolution
Comes
Out
of
Hiding
in
Lisbon.
Evolution
for
Everyone.
Electronic
document.
Http://scienceblogs.com/evolution/2011/05/evolution_comes_out_of_
hiding.php.
Accessed
May
19,
2011.
2011b
The
Neighborhood
Project:
Using
Evolution
to
Improve
My
City,
One
Block
at
a
Time.
New
York:
Little,
Brown
and
Company.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
Mihaly
Csikszentmihalyi
2007
Health
and
the
Ecology
of
Altruism.
In
Altruism
and
Health:
Perspectives
from
Empirical
Research.
Pp
314-331.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
Lee
A.
Dugatkin
1997
Group
Selection
and
Assortative
Interactions.
The
American
Naturalist
149(2):
336-351.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
William
Scott
Green
2011
Evolutionary
Religious
Studies:
A
Beginners
Guide.
In
Creating
Consilience:
Integrating
the
Sciences
and
Humanities.
E.
Slingerland
and
M.
Collard,
eds.
Pp.
225-242.
New
York:
Oxford
University
Press.
Wilson,
David
S.
and
Leslie
Heywood
2008
Integrating
the
Humanities
and
Sciences:
A
Campus-Wide
Program
at
Binghamton
University
That
Addresses
a
General
Problem
in
Higher
Education.
Grant
proposal
to
the
National
Endowment
for
the
Humanities.
http://evolution.binghamton.edu/evos/wp-content/uploads/2009
/08/Wilson-02.pdf.
Accessed
July
1,
2011.
355
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
Daniel
T.
OBrien
2009
Evolutionary
Theory
and
Cooperation
in
Everyday
Life.
In
Games,
Groups,
and
the
Global
Good:
Springer
Series
in
Game
Theory,
Part
2.
S.A.
Levin,
ed.
Pp.
155-168.
Berlin:
Springer
Psycia-Verlag.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
Elliott
Sober
1989
Reviving
the
Superorganism.
Journal
of
Theoretical
Biology
136(3):
337-356.
1994
Reintroducing
Group
Selection
to
the
Human
Behavioral
Sciences.
Behavioral
and
Brain
Sciences
17:
585-654.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
William
Swenson
2003
Community
Genetics
and
Community
Selection.
Ecology
83(3):
586-
588.
Wilson,
David
Sloan
and
Edward
O.
Wilson
2007a
Rethinking
the
Theoretical
Foundation
of
Sociobiology.
The
Quarterly
Review
of
Biology
82(4):
327-348.
2007b
Survival
of
the
Selfless.
New
Scientist
196:
42-46
Wilson,
David
S.,
Glenn
Geher,
and
Jennifer
Waldo
2008
Collaborative
Research:
Expanding
Evolutionary
Studies
in
American
Higher
Education.
National
Science
Foundation
Grant
Proposal.
Electronic
document.
Http://evolution.binghamton.edu/evos/wp-content/uploads/
2008/09/CCLI2008final.pdf.
Accessed
March
29,
2010.
2009
EvoS:
Completing
the
Evolutionary
Synthesis
in
Higher
Education.
EvoS
Journal
1(1):
3-10.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Richard
A.
Kauffman
Jr.,
and
Miriam
S.
Purdy
2011
A
Program
for
At-Risk
High
School
Students
Informed
by
Evolutionary
Science.
PLoS
One
11(6):
e27826.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Danielle
Marshall,
and
Hindi
Iserhott
2011
Empowering
Groups
That
Enable
Play.
American
Journal
of
Play
3(4):
523-537.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Daniel
T.
OBrien,
and
Artura
Sesma
2009
Human
Prosociality
from
an
Evolutionary
Perspective:
Variation
and
correlations
at
a
City-Wide
Scale.
Evolution
and
Human
Behavior
30:
190-200.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
John
J.
Timmel,
and
Ralph
R.
Miller
2004
Cognitive
Cooperation:
When
the
Going
Gets
Tough,
Think
as
a
Group.
Human
Nature
15(3):
225-250.
356
Wilson,
David
S.
Glenn
Geher,
Jennifer
Waldo,
Rosemarie
Sokal
Chang
2011
The
EvoS
Consortium:
Catalyzing
Evolutionary
Training
in
Higher
Education.
Evolution
Education
and
Outreach
4:
8-10.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Steven
C.
Hayes,
Anthony
Biglan,
and
Dennis
D.
Embry
2013
Evolving
the
Future:
Toward
a
Science
of
Intentional
Change.
Behavioral
and
Brain
Sciences.
In
Press.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Carolyn
Wilczynski,
Alexandra
Wells,
and
Laura
Weiser
2000
Gossip
and
Other
Aspects
of
Language
as
Group-Level
Adaptations.
In
The
Evolution
of
Cognition.
C.
Heyes
and
L.
Huber,
eds.
Pp.
347-365.
Cambridge,
Massachusetts:
MIT
Press.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Daniel
T.
OBrien,
Glenn
Geher,
Jennifer
Waldo,
Patricia
Hawley,
Brian
Wiegmann
2011
EvoS:
A
Worldwide
Evolutionary
Studies
Consortium.
National
Science
Foundation
Grant
Proposal.
Electronic
document.Http://evolution.binghamton.
edu/evos/wp-content/uploads/2011/01/EvoS-Worldwide-Consortium.pdf.
Accessed
July
10th,
2011.
Wilson,
David
Sloan,
Jerry
Lieberman,
Daniel
B.
Berch,
Anthony
Biglan,
David
F.
Bjorklund,
Bruce
J.
Ellis,
Dennis
D.
Embry,
David
C.
Geary,
and
Peter
Gray
2011
Learning
from
Mother
Nature
About
Teaching
Our
Children:
Ten
Simple
Truths
About
Childhood
Education
from
an
Evolutionary
Perspective.
Electronic
document.
https//:evolution-institute.org/files/Ten-Truths-Aug-
27-2009.pdf.
Accessed
Nov
1st,
2011.
Wilson,
Edward
O.
1975
Sociobiology:
The
New
Synthesis.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
1978
On
Human
Nature.
New
York:
Bantam
Books.
1998a
Consilience:
The
Unity
of
Knowledge.
New
York:
Alfred
A.
Knopf.
1998b
Resuming
the
Enlightenment
Quest.
The
Wilson
Quarterly
22(1):
16-
27.
2012
The
Social
Conquest
of
Earth.
New
York:
Liveright
Publishing
Corporation.
Wilson,
Jacqueline
Zara
2002
Invisible
Racism:
The
Language
and
Ontology
of
'White
Trash'.
Critique
of
Anthropology
22(4):
387-401.
357
Winegard,
Bo
2011
Searching
for
the
Grand
Narrative:
David
Sloan
Wilsons
Passionate
Plea
for
an
Evolution-Based
Unification
of
Disciplines.
EvoS
Journal
3(2):
20-
25.
Wolf,
Eric
R.
1990
Facing
Power
Old
Insights,
New
Questions.
American
Anthropologist
92(3):
586-96.
Woolard,
Kathryn
A.
2004
Is
the
Past
a
Foreign
Country?
Time,
Language
Origins,
and
the
Nation
in
Early
Modern
Spain.
Journal
of
Linguistic
Anthropology
14(1):
57-80.
Woolard,
Kathryn
A.
and
Bambi
B.
Schieffelin
1994
Language
Ideology.
Annual
Review
of
Anthropology
23:
55-82.
Wrangham,
Richard
and
Dale
Peterson
1996
Demonic
Males:
Apes
and
the
Origins
of
Human
Violence.
Boston:
Houghton
Mifflin.
Wright,
Robert
1994a
Feminists,
Meet
Mr.
Darwin:
The
Evolution
of
the
Female
Mind.
The
New
Republic
Nov.
24:
34-48.
1994b
The
Moral
Animal:
The
New
Science
of
Evolutionary
Psychology.
New
York:
Pantheon
Books.
Young,
Robert
1985a
Darwins
Metaphor:
Natures
Place
in
Victorian
Culture.
Cambridge,
MA:
Cambridge
University
Press.
1985b
Darwinism
is
Social.
In
The
Darwinian
Heritage.
D.
Kohn,
ed.
Pp.
609-
640.
Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press.
Zald,
Mayer
N.
and
Roberta
Ash
1966
Social
Movement
Organizations:
Growth,
Decay
and
Change.
Social
Forces
44(3):
327-341.
Zald,
Mayer
N.
and
John
D.
McCarthy
1975
Organizational
Intellectuals
and
the
Criticism
of
Society.
The
Social
Service
Review
49(3):
344-362.