The Battered Woman.
The Battered Woman.
The Battered Woman.
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
University of California Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to New
Criminal Law Review: An International and Interdisciplinary Journal.
http://www.jstor.org
S E LF-D E FE N S E, I M M I N E NCE, AN D TH E
BAT T E R E D WO M A N
Whitley R.P. Kaufman*
A traditional element of self-defense doctrine is the imminence rule, restricting the use of force in self-defense to cases where the threatened harm is imminent, about to happen. In recent years, this rule has been subject to increasing criticism, especially in the context of cases involving battered women, and
some commentators have even called for its elimination. This essay presents
the case for the imminence rule as reflecting the requirement that in a civil
society, the use of force be reserved to the state, with only one exception. This
exception applies to cases where an individual is faced with an imminent
threat. In such circumstances, the state would not be able to intervene in time
to protect the person, and hence the individual is permitted to use force in her
own defense.
I N T R O D U CT I O N
We are currently in the midst of a major debate about the scope and limits
of self-defense, and in particular about the restriction of the use of defensive
force to situations where there is an imminent threat. The imminence rule
has come under vigorous attack from two different directions. In the context of international law, the defenders of the United States right to preemptive use of military force have argued that the traditional limitation of
the right of international self-defense to imminent threats is outdated in the
current international situation. A parallel debate in domestic law concerns
New Criminal Law Review, Vol. 10, Number 3, pps 342370. ISSN 1933-4192, electronic ISSN
1933-4206. 2007 by the Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Please
direct all requests for permission to photocopy or reproduce article content through the
University of California Presss Rights and Permissions website, http://www.ucpressjournals.
com/reprintInfo.asp. DOI: 10.1525/nclr.2007.10.3.342.
342
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
343
344
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
account of the purpose of the imminence rule as grounded upon a particular allocation between the state and the individual of the right to use
force. Finally, section IV returns to the question of battered women as a
test case for the application of the imminence rule, and presents an argument for retaining the imminence rule even for these difficult cases. We
will see that the current criticism of the imminence rule is largely premised
on a widespread misunderstanding about the underlying rationale of the
rule. By attending to the origin of the rule, we can better understand its
function and continued importance even in controversial cases such as
that of the battered woman.
I . S E L F - D E F E N S E D O CT R I N E A N D T H E
I M M I N E NCE R U LE
4. See, e.g., Lenore Walker, Battered Women As Defendants, in Legal Responses to Wife
Assault 233, 243 (Zoe Hilton ed., 1993) (imminent is often confused with immediate);
Cynthia Gillespie, Justifiable Homicide 185 (1989).
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 345
5. Richard Schopp, Justification Defenses and Just Convictions 99 (1998). Schopp elsewhere refutes the claim that the immediacy standard, in contrast to imminence, would
preclude consideration of a past history of danger. In fact, a history of past violence is
always relevant to the reasonableness of a belief in the necessity to use force, on any standard. Richard Schopp et al., Battered Woman Syndrome, Expert Testimony, and the
Distinction Between Justification and Excuse, 1994 U. Ill. L. Rev. 45, 65. Cf. Donald
Downs, More Than Victims 247 (1996).
6. 2 Paul H. Robinson, Criminal Law Defenses 131(c)(1) (1984).
7. Blacks Law Dictionary (5th ed. 1979).
8. 1 Wayne LaFave & Austin W. Scott, Substantive Criminal Law, 5.7, at 655 (1986).
9. Model Penal Code 3.02(1)(a) (Proposed Official Draft 1962).
346
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
that the rule often has the effect of depriving her of her right to selfdefense altogether.10
It is the nonconfrontational cases in particular that have received special
attention, even though these constitute only a tiny percentage of the cases
in which battered women kill their abusers.11 In such cases, the woman
attacks her abuser while he is not currently threatening her, indeed sometimes when he is asleep or unconscious. In a case where a woman kills her
sleeping husband, the imminence standard arguably cannot be satisfied as
a matter of law: as Richard Rosen suggests, the threat of death or great
bodily harm was not imminent when [she] shot her husband, not, at least,
by any reasonable interpretation of the word imminent.12 But the same
problem arises in all nonconfrontational cases, albeit not quite as dramatically. Hence a woman may be precluded from asserting self-defense solely
on the grounds of the imminence rule, even if she satisfies all the other
requirements of self-defense, including the necessity for the use of force.
This apparent paradoxhow can force be necessary if the threat is not
imminent?has puzzled many a commentator. But in fact it is no paradox
at all: indeed, the very situation is illustrated by the case of Judy Norman.
The Norman case is the most widely cited example of a battered
woman prevented from claiming self-defense solely by an application of
the imminence rule.13 Ms. Norman at the time of the incident had been
10. Gillespie, supra note 4, at 76, 186. Cf. Kym Miller, Abused Women Abused by the
Law: The Plight of Battered Women in California and a Proposal for Revising the
California Self-Defense Law, 3 S. Cal. Rev. L & Womens Stud. 303 (1994); Richard Rosen,
On Self-Defense, Imminence, and Women Who Kill Their Batterers, 71 N.C. L. Rev. 371,
372 (1993); Schopp, supra note 5, at 68 (some BW cases would not qualify as self-defense
if imminence is separate from necessity).
11. Holly Maguigans study indicates that the vast majority (from 70 to 90 percent) of
battered women killings occur in confrontational situations, i.e., during an actual or imminent attack by the batterer. Holly Maguigan, Battered Women and Self-Defense: Myths
and Misconceptions in Current Reform Proposals, 140 U. Pa. L. Rev. 379, 384 (1991).
12. Rosen, supra note 10, at 375.
13. State v. Norman, 378 S.E.2d 8 (N.C. 1989). See, e.g., Jeffrey Murdoch, Is Imminence
Really Necessity? Reconciling Traditional Self-Defense Doctrine with the Battered Woman
Syndrome, 20 N. Ill. U. L. Rev. 191, 199 (2000) (the best known case where the imminence
requirement served as a bar to a claim of self-defense being made by a battering victim);
Alan J. Tomkins et al., Self-Defense Jury Instructions in Trials of Battered Women Who Kill
Their Partner, in Legal Responses to Wife Assault, supra note 4, at 258, 263 (Norman epitomizes the problems that several commentators claim exist for battered women defendants
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 347
married for twenty-five years and had several children. She testified that her
husband had begun drinking and abusing her about five years after they
were married. The abuse, according to Norman, included hitting her, kicking her, throwing objects at her, putting out cigarettes on her, and throwing hot coffee on her. Numerous times he threatened to kill or maim her.
Ms. Norman testified that she was afraid to press charges against her husband or leave him, claiming that she had several times left home but that
he had always found her and brought her back and beaten her. The day
before Mr. Normans death, sheriff s deputies were called to the Norman
home, and Ms. Norman complained that her husband had been beating
her all day and that she could not take it anymore. She was advised to file
a complaint, but said she was afraid her husband would kill her if she had
him arrested. The deputies said they needed a warrant in order to arrest
him, and left. An hour later, the deputies returned after Ms. Norman had
attempted suicide. In the hospital, she talked to a therapist who discussed
filing charges and having her husband committed. The next day, after
returning home from the hospital, she decided to take matters into her own
hands. Her husband had been asleep for some time; Ms. Norman walked
to her mothers house, obtained a gun, and then returned and shot her husband three times in the back of the head while he slept, killing him. At trial,
Ms. Norman claimed self-defense, but the court did not allow this defense
on the sole ground that she could not have been under an imminent threat
at the time of the shooting, since her husband was asleep. Ms. Norman was
convicted of manslaughter and sentenced to six years imprisonment.
The Norman case is not the only such case of an abused wife killing her
husband while he is asleep, but it has served as the rallying point for the
movement to revise or eliminate the imminence rule. Advocates for battered women have argued that the law of self-defense, including the imminence rule, is constructed with men in mind, based on the paradigm of
two strangers of equal size and strength in a public place.14 The battered
wife, so the argument goes, cannot rely on a rule designed for the onetime confrontation in a public sphere; instead, she is involved in a longterm abusive relationship in her own home, which she cannot easily leave
who ought to have the protection of a self-defense claim); Rosen, supra note 10, at 372
(the first thing that turned my attention to the subject of battered women, self-defense,
and the imminence requirement was the case of Judy Norman).
14. See, e.g., Gillespie, supra note 4, ch. 1.
348
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
I I . I S T H E I M M I N E N C E R U L E R E A L LY N E C E S S A RY ?
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 349
350
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
the more common view is (as we have seen) that immediacy is stricter than
imminence. However, the phrase immediately necessary could also be
interpreted in a more radical way: that it means to shift the focus away
from whether the harm is immediate/imminent to whether the necessity is
immediate: that is, even if the harm is far off, the necessity to act is now.
The problem with this view is that it creates a redundancy: the necessity
condition has always meant necessary now (for what else could it mean?).24
It is hard to avoid the conclusion that the drafters of the MPC themselves
lacked a clear conception of the purpose of the imminence rule.
The first question for us then is whether the Proxy Thesis is correct: is
the function of the imminence rule merely to serve as an indicator for
necessity? A close analysis will show that the thesis is false: the imminence
and the necessity rules are logically independent. It is certainly to be conceded that there is a close factual relation between imminence and necessity, in that ordinarily when a threat is not yet imminent, it will not be
necessary yet to resort to defensive force. Similarly, in most cases where the
use of defensive force is judged to be necessary, it will typically be the case
that the danger is either imminent or actual. There is an obvious explanation for this close connection: the further off in the future a potential
threat lies, the less likely it is that it will be necessary to counter it with
present force, since there is ample time to find other (nonviolent) responses.
Further, since temporally distant harm is usually highly uncertain and
even speculative, it is harder to justify a claim that a violent response is
necessary right now. Lots of things could happen between now and then
to make the use of force unnecessary. But by the time the threat becomes
imminent, there is a far more plausible case to be made that it is necessary
to take decisive action.
Moreover, the relation between imminence and necessity is imperfect. It
is easy to conceive of situations involving imminence but not necessity, and
vice versa. For example, if a security guard yells out to me: identify yourself or Ill shoot! here there is an imminent threat, but since I can avoid
any harm by simply identifying myself, there is no necessity to use force.
Somewhat more counterintuitively, it is also easy to conceive of cases where
force is necessary even though there is not an imminent threat. Indeed, we
need look no further than the very sort of case that has inspired the current
debate: the woman who has been repeatedly abused in the past and has no
24. Cf. Robinson, supra note 6, 131(c)(2).
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 351
alternative for protecting herself against future harm than to attack her
abuser preemptively. It is true that in general the further off in the future
the threat is, the less likely it will be necessary to act now. However, this
relation is a matter of degree, not of intrinsic connection. Sometimes the
best or indeed the only time to act defensively is before the threat ripens
into an imminent danger, and in such cases it is perfectly reasonable to
assert that it is necessary to act now, rather than risk disaster by waiting too
long. Indeed, this is precisely how some commentators interpret the case of
Judy Norman: that in her judgment, it was necessary to act decisively, as
the police were unable to help her, and to wait until the moment of attack
by her husband would be to risk serious abuse or even death if she did not
take the opportunity to act preemptively.25 The question then is how to
handle cases where necessity and imminence diverge.
According to the Proxy Thesis, the use of force by the individual should
be permitted whenever it is necessary, even if the threat is not imminent.
It would be simply absurd to deny a person the right to defend herself
where force was necessary, based on a rigid, formalistic adherence to a
requirement of imminence. The problem for the Proxy Thesis, however, is
that it fails to recognize how in fact our legal system handles cases where
imminence and necessity diverge. Where there is the necessity for the
use of force, but no imminent threat, the individual is not permitted to
resort to force herself. This does not mean she must passively surrender to
the threat, or wait until it becomes imminent before she can act; rather,
the law permits her to turn to the authorities for protection, i.e., call the
police. Crucially, the lack of an imminent threat does not entail that the
police or courts are prohibited from using force (or the threat of force) as
necessary to protect the individual. The authorities may use all necessary
and proportionate force to protect the woman, including for example
arresting the abuser, or issuing a protective order (backed by the threat of
force). Thus we have identified a function for the imminence rule that is
wholly distinct from its role as an indicator of necessity: it establishes a
strict division of the right to use force. The individual may use force only
25. The widespread confusion as to how force can be necessary but not imminent
appears to result from an overly literal reading of necessary. But of course, on a strictly
literal interpretation, force would not be necessary even when the threat was imminent: as
Richard Rosen points out, supra note 10, at 397, even when a gun is pointed at your head,
the attacker could change his mind, or miss.
352
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
when such force is necessary and the threat is imminent; the state however
may use force when it is necessary, even if the threat is not imminent
(assuming proportionality and other requirements are satisfied). Just why
there exists this division of labor has, of course, not yet been established.
But the Proxy Thesis fails to recognize this division, and the crucial role of
imminence in establishing the division, and hence must be rejected.
The alternative contemporary theory of imminence, presented in
Kimberly Ferzans Defending Imminence: From Battered Women to
Iraq, rejects the Proxy Thesis (though, as we will see, falls prey to the same
error as the Proxy Thesis does).26 Ferzan argues that the compelling need
to aid battered women has made the self-defense argument too easy. In this
context, the integrity of self-defense has been undermined by the jettisoning of imminence.27 She insists that imminence is more than a proxy for
necessity, but has an independent ethical basis.28 Her argument is based on
the conceptual distinction between self-defense and self-preference. The
distinctive feature of self-defense, according to Ferzan, is precisely that it is
a defense against an act of aggression: Self-defense is only understandable
as a response to anothers aggressive conduct.29 And it is imminence that
is the measure of aggression: when the right to self-defense is broadened
to any person that might potentially inflict harm, we blur the distinction
between offense and defense. . . . We then have no ability to distinguish
self-defensive conduct from aggressive conduct.30 This requirement that
there be prior aggression is a moral one, for Ferzan: the moral assessment
of both the aggressors and the defenders rights hinges on some notion of
aggression.31 One who invokes self-defense before there is an imminent
threat loses the moral high ground and thus the justification for his act:
The aggressors action starts it. We can only understand defense by comparison with offense. The aggressors action signifies the breach of the community rules and the lack of respect for the defender. It is this action that
makes self-defense understandable.32 The imminence requirement thus
ensures that the force really is defensive and therefore morally justified.
26. Ferzan, supra note 1.
27. Id. at 213.
28. Id. at 262.
29. Id. at 257.
30. Id. at 259.
31. Id. at 258.
32. Id. at 259.
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 353
354
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
and obvious moral basis. Thus one may not use force unless it is against an
attacker who is himself unjustified (that is, the defender has to have the
moral high ground), one may only use force if necessary, and one may only
use a proportionate degree of force (e.g., not kill someone to protect against
trivial harm). In contrast to these, as we have seen, it is far from obvious
why on moral grounds defensive force should be limited to cases where the
threat is imminent. Second, it is equally striking that all of the other three
requirements apply to all uses of force, whether by the state or by the individual, whereas the imminence rule is unique in binding only the individual, not state actors. What could explain these two important differences?
I I I . T H E I M M I N E N C E R U L E : P O L I T I CA L N OT M O R A L
The central thesis of this essay is that the imminence rule is independent
of the necessity rule, and that it derives not from morality but from political theory. As so often, George Fletcher correctly grasps this point: the
requirement properly falls into the domain of political rather than moral
theory. The issue is the proper allocation of authority between the state and
the citizen.33 Fletcher here invokes what is traditionally called the Public
Authority restriction on the use of force. The basic idea is that the state
claims a monopoly on force, under which no individual or non-state
group is permitted to resort to force without the states authorization.
There is, however, one major exception to the societal monopoly on violence. Where the danger is present and immediate, and there is no time to
resort to a central authority, the individual is permitted to resort to force
without seeking the prior authorization of the state. Self-defense thus
remains a private right for just this reason. It is the one exception to the
Public Authority requirement, on the grounds that the individual cannot
reasonably be expected to submit passively to self-destruction. But all
preemptive forcebefore there is an imminent threatand punitive or
33. Fletcher, supra note 2, at 570. Fletcher is, however, wrong to suggest that this makes
individual self-defense somehow derivative from the states monopoly on force. Fletcher,
supra note 23, at 867. There is no meaningful sense in which the states use of force is prior
to the individuals, nor is there any reason to think the individuals right of self-defense exists
only at the pleasure of the state. Indeed, the natural law account that I will be defending
here is premised on the idea of a natural right of the individual to self-defense.
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 355
34. Frederick H. Russell, The Just War in the Middle Ages 42 (1979).
35. Id.
36. Id. at 4243.
37. Id.
38. Cicero, Pro Milone, in The Speeches 3, 17 (Nevile Watts trans., 1964).
356
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
39. Gratian, Decretum, Part II, Causa 23, in The Ethics of War 104, 110 (Gregory
Reichberg et al. eds., 2006).
40. Raymond of Penafort, Summa de Casibus Poenitentiae 18 (12341245), quoted in
The Ethics of War, supra note 39, at 139.
41. Saint Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica II-II.Q. 40 A.1 (Fathers of the English
Dominican Province trans., 2d rev. ed. 1920), available at http://www.newadvent.org/summa.
42. Id. I-II Q. 96. A. 1.
43. G.N. Clark, The Seventeenth Century 140 (2d ed. 1961).
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 357
358
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
assistance of the magistrate to repel an injury by which life or some irreplaceable good, as valuable as life itself, is thrown into immediate danger.
But this is confined to repelling the danger; vengeance and a guarantee
against attack in the future must be left to the judgment of the magistrate.48
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 359
52. Rosen, supra note 10, at 387 n.45. We cannot therefore accept Rosens historical
skepticism about the imminence rule, that it is apparent that the imminence requirement
does not have an unquestioned historical lineage as a fundamental requirement for a finding of self-defense. Id. This is of course not to deny that different legal traditions have not
always consistently endorsed the rule, for complex historical reasons.
53. Grotius, supra note 44, at 55.
54. See, e.g., Publius Syrus, The Moral Sayings of Publius Syrus, a Roman Slave 51
(D. Lyman trans., 1856) (No one should be a judge in his own cause.); Edmund Burke,
Reflections on the Revolution in France 89 (1962) (One of the first motives in civil society, and which becomes one of its fundamental rules, is, that no man should be judge in his
own cause.); Federalist No. 10 (No man is allowed to be a judge in his own cause, because
his interest would certainly bias his judgment, and, not improbably, corrupt his integrity.)
(Madison).
360
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
interest in the case.55 Thus the state reserves the right to the use of retaliatory (punitive) force against past harm, as well as preemptive/preventive
force against future threats. The single exception to this principle is where
the immediacy of the threat rendered it impossible to resort to external
protection, and thus licensed self-help. Even in such cases, notably, the
state has always reserved the right to be the arbiter after the fact as to
whether the defensive force used was justified from an impartial perspective. Note that this analysis suggests a pragmatic standard for defining the
imminence restriction: a threat is imminent when there is insufficient
time to enlist the aid of the authorities to protect oneself.
I V. I M M I N E N C E A N D T H E BAT T E R E D WO M A N
Having set out the underlying rationale for the imminence rule, it remains
for us to address the problem of the application of this rule to battered
women. This discussion must be more tentative, given the enormous complexity of the issue and the vast literature on the subject, and there is no
attempt here to settle this debate. Nonetheless, if the argument of this essay
is correct, then the debate itself has been so far conducted on mistaken
premises about the rationale for the imminence rule. A proper understanding of the imminence rule demonstrates that, even as regards battered
women, there are strong grounds for retaining the requirement in its present form. It should go without saying, of course, that to make such an argument is not in any way to diminish the seriousness of the problem of
domestic violence. The very limited issue here is whether the solution to
this problem is the suspension or alteration of the imminence restriction.
The thesis of this essay is that the imminence rule reflects a powerful presumption against the individual using force in her own protection. Even if
one accepts this thesis, however, it is possible to argue that certain individuals are entitled to a waiver of the imminence rule. For there is an important
corollary of the thesis not yet made explicit: if the imminence restriction is
premised on the fact that the state can otherwise provide protection against
violence, it follows that if the state is unable to do so then the imminence
55. Both Hobbes and Locke also made the need for a central, objective decision making
authority central to their theory of the social contract. See discussion in Richard Tuck, The
Rights of War and Peace 12639 (1999).
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 361
rule is suspended. In that case, the right to use preemptive (or even retaliatory force) could, it might be argued, revert back to the unprotected individual or group. Hence one way of interpreting (or reconstructing) the
position of battered women advocates is that they can endorse the thesis of
this essay, but claim that battered women are not adequately protected by
the state, and hence should be exempted from the imminence rule.
However, any individual or group claiming a special exemption from the
societal monopoly on force must meet a very high standard indeed. No
society, of course, can ever be even close to perfectly effective in preventing
illegal violence and guaranteeing justice, nor is the imminence restriction
premised on any such utopian ideal. The declaration of a return to a state
of nature is an extraordinary claim, appropriate only in the most extreme
and unambiguous circumstances. The classic case is the true state of nature
where there is no effective state presence at all and hence no access to judicial procedure, for example, as Hugo Grotius explains, on the seas, in a
wilderness, or desert islands, or in any other place where there is no civil
government.56 More pertinent to the battered woman, however, are two
other kinds of cases. First, in kidnap cases where the victim is wholly in the
power of her captors, it is widely accepted that, at least in some cases, a captive can use deadly force against her captor even in the absence of an imminent threat. Second, in cases where the state systematically and deliberately
denies legal protection entirely to an individual or a group (for example,
black slaves in the antebellum South or Jews in Nazi Germany), there is a
strong case for declaring a return to the right to private violence.57 The
question for us then is whether the situation of battered women can be
considered a return to the state of nature on either of these two grounds.
It is in fact frequently suggested that battered women are in situations
amounting to hostage or captivity, given the difficulties for women trying
to leave an abusive relationship, including threats of retaliation if they try
to leave. Martha Mahoney, for example, argues that a batterers threats
against a woman create an imprisoning effect that provides a persuasive
analogy with hostages or prisoners of war, hence helps shift the paradigm of the battered woman to the image of a hostage resisting her own
56. Grotius, supra note 44, at 56.
57. For a discussion of some of the limits on the permissibility of private violence, even
in a slave state, see Kent Greenawalt, Violence: Legal Justification and Moral Appraisal, 32
Emory L.J. 437 (1983).
362
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 363
there is a deeper issue here: the analogy with cases of total and systematic
exclusion (slaves, Jews in Nazi Germany) is highly questionable. Indeed,
given the extraordinary attention paid to protecting battered women since
the issue became prominent three decades agoincluding the passage of
domestic violence reform statutes in all fifty states, the federal Violence
Against Women Act, statutes authorizing mandatory warrantless arrests
for misdemeanor assaults in domestic violence cases, specialized domestic
violence courts in some states, statutes authorizing expert testimony on
battered womens syndrome, mass clemencies for convicted battered
women killers (including twenty-five women freed in Ohio in 1991), and
even the rise of an entire new tort for battered womenit would be difficult to defend the claim that women in general, or abused women in particular, are systematically excluded from the protection of the law. One
can of course acknowledge the seriousness of the problem of domestic violence and the need for the government to do much better in protecting
victims of abuse, without resorting to the nuclear option of declaring
that battered women are in a state of nature and may resort to any force
they see fit against their abuser.
Consider for example the standard that some commentators have suggested for suspension of the imminence rule: when the state is not effective in protecting the individual, she may resort to violent self-help.62 The
problem is that the notion of effectiveness is so vague and open-ended,
it would exceedingly complicate jury trials, resulting in lengthy, complex
debates over how to define effective, whether the state was effective, and
just how effective it had to be before force was justified. It is doubtful that
such a standard could constrain the danger of the resort to vigilante violence, and there is a great danger of sliding down the slippery slope to
cases such as Bernhard Goetz, who felt justified in resorting to vigilante
justice on the grounds that the state was not doing enough to keep the
streets safe.63 It is worth recalling that the lynching of blacks in the South
was widely defended on the grounds that state punishment was too lax
62. See, e.g., Schopp, supra note 5, at 104; Gauthier, supra note 17, at 618; Murdoch,
supra note 13, at 213.
63. George Fletcher, With Justice for Some 14 (1996). Note also that the notion of failed
effectiveness in protecting women also does not distinguish between effectiveness in protecting against a future threat, and effectiveness in punishing past offenses. If a killer
escapes punishment, can the relatives of the victim carry out their own private vengeance
on grounds that the state was ineffective in avenging the death?
364
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
and too slow to adequately protect Southern women from rape.64 Whereas
in cases of an imminent threat, the individuals judgment is least susceptible to bias or wrongful motives as the danger is clear and unmistakable
because immediate (it is also more easily susceptible to proof of necessity
after the fact), the very opposite may be said of the effectiveness exception: that it is highly susceptible to subjective bias and partiality.
It bears emphasizing that the very rationale for a bright-line rule (or at
least as bright a line as can reasonably be drawn) in the case of violent selfhelp is to minimize the room for the exercise of human judgment as to
when and how much to impose harm on others in order to protect oneself.
Without it, people are likely to overestimate future risks and to err in the
direction of acting preemptively regardless of cost to others, as David
Gauthier warns.65 However, the literature on battered women again does
not appear to acknowledge these inevitable limitations and distortions of
human judgment; thus Downs criticizes Lenore Walker: Nothing in
Walkers writings indicates how we or a jury could divine when a battered
womans perception of danger is not reasonable.66 Indeed, quite the opposite: advocates of battered women repeatedly insist on these womens
enhanced perceptual capacities to recognize imminent threats that would
not be perceptible to the ordinary person, by entering into a state of
hypervigilance which permits them to recognize subtle signs of danger.67
Yet such claims appear to go far beyond any documented evidence demonstrating how reliable such abilities are, how many battered women
develop them, or how to identify which women have them (Lenore
Walker, for example, simply tells us unhelpfully that behavioral principles
support this conclusion68). Elizabeth Schneider, despite repeatedly
admonishing us not to generalize about battered women since each case is
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 365
69. Elizabeth Schneider, Battered Women and Feminist Lawmaking 120, 124, 136
(2000).
70. Id. at 131. See also Downs, supra note 5, at 231; Kinports, supra note 67, at 180 n.138;
Mary Ann Dutton, Empowering and Healing the Battered Woman 61 (1992). Oddly, the
concept of hypervigilance as used in discussions of PTSD more generally seems typically
to emphasize the very opposite: the increased unreliability of perception of danger due to
repeated stress. Thus Jonathan Shay describes the hypervigilance of returned soldiers as the
inappropriate reaction to perceived risk and as the loss of trustworthiness of perception.
Jonathan Shay, Achilles in Vietnam 17274 (1995). See also Jane Moriartys characterization
of PTSD victims as tending to respond to perceived events in an exaggerated manner
because of compromised sensory perceptions. Moriarty, supra note 1, at 182 n.145.
71. See, e.g., Schopp, supra note 5, at 13; cf. Downs, supra note 5, at 226. Nor should
we overlook the obvious potential for abuse of an after-the-fact claim that there was an
imminent threat visible only to the defendant.
366
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
of the men in her book, who are regularly depicted as motivated by anger
and a desire to retaliate against their spouses. Nor is this one-sided portrayal unique to Gillespie. As Belinda Morrissey argues, Rage has traditionally been denied in representation of women in Western societies. . . .
Even Lenore Walker, who acknowledges its existence, downplays the significance of anger as a catalyst when battered women kill, claiming that
fear is the most important factor in these homicides.72
But it is hardly plausible that none of these women, enduring the abuse
that Gillespie describes, were at all motivated by anger towards their tormenter or a desire to retaliate against him. Indeed, there is evidence of a
retaliatory motive even in some of the textbook cases, including the case
of Judy Norman: her therapist testified that the day before the killings,
Norman expressed considerable anger toward her husband and said she
should kill him because of the things he had done to heri.e., for past
wrongs rather than future threats.73 Dershowitz suggests that Lorena
Bobbitt may also have been motivated by retaliation; there is evidence that
her attack may have been an attempt to get back at her husband when he
said he was leaving her.74 Numerous commentators have warned that
expanding the law of self-defense would in effect license retaliation:
George Fletcher suggests we are witnessing the beginning of a transformation of the battered womans syndrome into a general defense of abuse
as a justification for retaliation.75 Dershowitz also sees a growing justification for vigilante violence by those who claim they cannot receive justice from the legal system.76 Joshua Dressler argues that the underlying,
unstated premise in many battered women cases is that the woman is justified in killing her abuser for the simple reason that he deserves it.77
Indeed, some feminists have even explicitly argued that the battered woman
should be allowed to carry out vigilante justice and punish her abuser.78
72. Belinda Morrissey, When Women Kill 98 (2003).
73. State v. Norman, 378 S.E.2d 8, 1011 (N.C. 1989).
74. Alan M. Dershowitz, The Abuse Excuse 58 (2000).
75. Fletcher, supra note 63, at 140.
76. Dershowitz, supra note 74, at 59.
77. Joshua Dressler, Battered Women Who Kill Their Sleeping Tormentors, in
Criminal Law Theory 259, 269 (Stephen Shute ed., 2002).
78. See Elizabeth Ayyildiz, When Battered Womans Syndrome Does Not Go Far
Enough: The Battered Woman As Vigilante, 4 J. Gender & L. 141, 148 (1995), cited in
Dressler, supra note 77, at 271.
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 367
Relaxing the imminence rule only invites retaliation by blurring the line
between defensive force and retaliatory after-the-fact force.79
Finally, we need to address one more indirect attack on the imminence
rule: the argument for subjectivizing the perception of imminence.
Variously described as reinterpreting imminence, contextualizing it, or
subjecting it to a narrative logic, the idea is the same: should a woman
believe she is in imminent danger, she is justified in resorting to force,
whether or not her belief was objectively valid or even reasonable. At its
extreme, this position draws on a postmodernist, relativist theory of
womens ways of knowing, for example Lenore Walkers notorious claim
that a concern solely for facts and rationality reflects male thinking,
whereas to women opinions count as much as facts.80 Most commentators of course avoid such excesses and acknowledge the objective reality of
whether there was an imminent threat or not. Even so, they may adopt
equally dubious strategies, such as insisting on individualizing or subjectivizing the concept of reasonableness, a strategy that Richard Schopp
has rightly criticized as incoherent, since the very notion of reasonableness
entails adherence to common, shared standards of inference and evidencegathering.81 Alternatively, victim advocates sometimes suggest eliminating
the reasonableness requirement altogether in favor of a purely subjective
standard: if the victim felt in danger (even if there was no real danger),
then she was justified in using force.82 It is even sometimes suggested that,
79. Dershowitz gives one example of such a blurring from Lorena Bobbitts lawyer, who
claimed an after-the-fact self-defense: Moments after the last rape, he was cut. Thats about
as fundamental a self-defense plea as you can ask for. Dershowitz, supra note 74, at 58.
80. Lenore Walker, Terrifying Love 257 (1989); cf. Legal Responses to Wife Assault,
supra note 4, at 243; Downs, supra note 5, at 81. Elizabeth Schneider comes close to endorsing such a view in suggesting that the very concept of objective inherently embod[ies]
male values. Schneider, supra note 69, at 139. One occasionally comes across the claim
that victims in general have access to a higher or more special form of truth.
81. Schopp, supra note 5, at 9192. Equally problematic is the idea of a reasonable battered woman standard; see criticism in Maguigan, supra note 11, at 44350, Schopp, supra
note 5, at 100.
82. The Model Penal Code notably drops the reasonableness requirement, so that honest
belief alone suffices. Model Penal Code 3.04(2)(1) (Proposed Official Draft 1962) (defendant charged with murder need only show that he believe[d] that [the use of ] deadly force
was necessary). See discussion in Schopp, supra note 5, at 10002. Several states follow this
rule, though the majority require that the belief be not only honest but reasonable as well.
368
N E W C R I M I N A L L AW R E V I E W
VO L. 10
NO. 3
S U M M E R 2 0 07
to the battered person, the threat always feels imminent83thus licensing violence at any time or place, if one accepts the subjective standard of
imminence.
But any such radical subjectivization of the law of self-defense, even apart
from the moral relativism on which it is based, overlooks the problem of
potential bias in ones perception of the need for the use of force against others. Indeed, it would legitimize those biases by accepting them as valid legal
defenses. Such a position ignores the idea of responsibility to others, especially when it comes to the use of deadly force; merely feeling afraid of someone else does not entail the right to shoot him. The criminal law exists in part
to demand that individuals live up to higher standards of moral responsibility than they might otherwise. Nor would civil society even be possible if
each individual were granted a license to resort to vigilante violence any time
he felt in danger. Not only would such a law be subject to gross abuse, but
recall that the very reason for the objective imminence standard in the first
place is the natural human tendency to overreact to possible future threats,
and to err on the side of imposing costs on others rather than risk any danger to oneself. It bears emphasizing that the victim of the killing will not be
available to rebut the claim that he was presenting an imminent threat. It is
certainly possible to consider unreasonable mistakes as excusing (rather than
justifying) conditions, but even here it is important that the law insist that
people aspire to the highest possible standard of objectivity, particularly when
making a decision about taking the life of another. As David Gauthier argues,
A legal system which failed to recognize the right, which failed to recognize
the justification each person has to act in her own protection in the light of
imminent danger, could have no valid claim on the allegiance or obedience
of those it sought to bring within its sway. But in recognizing the right, the
law brings self-defense within its ambit; while it may not deny the right, it
may and must, of course, delimit it. The right of each person to defend herself is not, and could not be understood as, a right to do whatever she might
allege to be required for her defense. Such a subjectivism would be altogether corrosive to a legal system.84
83. Sheryl McCarthy, Injustice After All, USA Today, May 9, 2006, at 15A, available at
http://www.usatoday.com/news/opinion/editorials/2006-05-08-forum-injustice_x.htm?
csp=34 (May 8, 2006).
84. Gauthier, supra note 17, at 616. For other critiques of subjectivism, see George
Fletcher, A Crime of Self-Defense 6162 (1988); Downs, supra note 5, at 20450; Stephen
Morse, The New Syndrome Excuse Syndrome, 14 Crim. Just. Ethics 3, 316 (1995).
S E L F - D E F E N S E , I M M I N E N C E , A N D T H E B AT T E R E D W O M A N
| 369
CONCLUS ION
In recent years we have seen a major attack on the imminence rule, especially in its application to battered women. The wide range of proposals
for modifying the imminence restriction for battered women include
eliminating the rule entirely, subordinating it to necessity, modifying it,
supplementing it, making it more flexible, subjectivizing it, contextualizing it, broadening it, and so forth. My purpose here has been to sound a
cautionary note in this debate. While there may well be some genuine
cases where the application of the imminence rule serves an injustice, one
ought to be very careful in tinkering with a crucial limitation on the right
to violent self-help. This is particularly important given the serious doubts
that have been raised about whether the proposed reforms would have
much impact on battered women homicides. As Holly Maguigan emphasizes, the existing law of self-defense in most jurisdictions is consistent
with the self-defense claims of battered women who kill; to the extent
there is a problem, it has to do with unfair application of existing law,
not with the current standards of self-defense per se.85
The imminence rule, as we have seen, is a crucial, independent restriction
on the individual right to resort to violence against others, especially deadly
violence. The first task of the state is the control of violence, and the restriction of individual violence to cases of genuine emergency when there is no
recourse to state protection is crucial to establishing this monopoly on violence. Civil life is, as Pufendorf warned, too fragile to allow each man to
exact what he believes to be his due by violent self-help.86 Moreover, it is an
essential element of the rule of law that each personeven batterershave
a right to due process of law, especially when their lives are at stake. If the
rules of self-defense permit an exception to this principle in the case of imminent danger, it is an exception that is best kept to an absolute minimum. As
Joshua Dressler cautions, we should hesitate long and hard before we promote a criminal defence that categorically justifies the taking of life before it
is immediately necessary.87 Before we proceed with any modification (let
alone elimination) of the imminence restriction, we had better consider very
carefully the implications of such a radical change in the long-established and
highly effective principles controlling the private resort to violence.
85. Maguigan, supra note 11, at 458.
86. Pufendorf, supra note 48, at 156.
87. Dressler, supra note 77, at 275.