Paradox of Omnipotence and Perfection
Paradox of Omnipotence and Perfection
Paradox of Omnipotence and Perfection
PERFECTION
J E R O M E GELLMAN*
31
SOPHIA
materially).
If (a), God's doing A is logically impossible. Hence, in
accordance with the theological tradition that omnipotence
does not extend to the doing of the impossible, his inability to
do A does .not detract from his omnipotence. Premiss (6) is
true for rational theology only if understood as
(6') If there is something logically possible for God
to do that God cannot do, he is not omnipotent.
and (7) follows from (6') and (5) only if the latter is interpreted as
(5') If God cannot do A, then there is something
logically possible for God to do that e~mnot do.
which is patehtly false, on (a)
essentially.
THE
PARADOX
OF
OMNIPOTENCE,
AND
PERFECTION
SOPHIA
But (13') does not follow f r o m (18) at all; and its a c c e p t a n c e
a m o u n t s to a begging of the v e r y question against G o d ' s
essential omnipotence.
This reply, however, will not do. To see why, let us consider what concept of omnipotence could justify the rejection
of (14) as it stands. The following definition of omnipotence:
(D1) X is omnipotent iff x can do w h a t e v e r it is
logically possible for him to do.
would justify the rejection of (14). F o r even if God cannot do
what a m a t e r i a l l y omnipotent being can, he can still be omnipotent, as long as his inability is a logical one. In the c a s e of
the doing of A, for e x a m p l e , if God is omnipotent essentially
he r e m a i n s omnipotent though he cannot do A, and though (18)
is true. And we m u s t of course consider the possibility of
essential omnipotence, otherwise we beg the question at issue.
As is known, however, (D1) is not a s a t i s f a c t o r y definition.
According to it, no m a t t e r how logically enfeebled, a being
m a y be omnipotent provided it can p e r f o r m each logically
possible act left for him to p e r f o r m . But surely, such a concept
of omnipotence is absurd.
Suppose, now, an opponent of (14) proposes instead this
definition:
(D2) X is omnipotent iff x can do w h a t e v e r it is
logically possible for him to do and x ' s logical
possibilities a r e r e s t r i c t e d (if at all) only with
r e g a r d to the diminishing of his power (as
well as by what is logically impossible for any
being w h a t e v e r ) .
On (D2) a s e v e r e l y logically handicapped being is not omnipotent, since his abilities a r e not r e s t r i c t e d only by the impossibility of losing power. And a n y being who is in any w a y
logically restricted in addition to the restriction on losing power
will not be omnipotent. But God, who can do e v e r y t h i n g except
A, if he is omnipotent essentially, qualifies as omnipotent
on (D2).
But (D2) fails as well. It is a f a v o r e d doctrine of rational
theology that God possesses his omniscience, goodness, etern~
ality, etc. likewise in an essential m a n n e r . So, it is logically impossible for God to forget, for e x a m p l e . But on (D2). God is
t h e r e f o r e not omnipotent. But this can be patched-up as
follows;
(D3) X is omnipotent iff x can do w h a t e v e r it is
34
T H E PARADOX OF O M N I P O T E N C E , AND P E R F E C T I O N
II
The paradox of essential omnipotence arises f r o m :
(18) A m a t e r i a l l y omnipotent being can do A.
I want to argue, however, that (18) is no part of rational
theology, and is indeed rejected therein. So, the paradox of
essential omnipotence collapses. Also, then, the MavrodesPlantinga solution to the first paradox is unacceptable for
rational theology, since that solution depends on (18). But
once we reveal the reasons for rejecting (18), we will be able
to solve the original p a r a d o x easily and without r e f e r e n c e to
material and "essential
omnipotence.
35
sOPHIA
attributes such as omnipotence and omniscience relate explicatively to the fundamental unanalyzed concept of God. Omnipotence, that is, is introduced in partial answer to the question,
"What are the attributes or perfections of the most p e r f e c t
being?" Anselm's way of doing rational theology in the
Proslogion exemplifies this approach paradigmatically. He
begins, in his famous Ontological Argument, with an unanalyzed concept of God, and attempts to establish God's
existence, on what m a y be construed a partial analysis, revealing that the God-concept entails existence. In ensuing chapters
of Proslogion Anselm provides a fuller philosophical explication of what is m e a n t by " t h a t than which none g r e a t e r can
be conceived". This explicative task leads to God's omnipotence, as well as to other attributes.
Given the context in which omnipotence arises, perhaps
a better t e r m for the power of God would be " p e r f e c t p o w e r . "
Now this latter t e r m could be understood analogously with
" p e r f e c t c r i m e " or " p e r f e c t coincidence." In this non-normative nonsense of perfect (Sense I) that x is a p e r f e c t F does not
entail that x, or anything else, possesses a perfection in the
m o r a l sense of perfection or that to that extent x, or anything
else. is worthy of worship. But surely, this is not the meaning
of " p e r f e c t p o w e r " apt for rational theology. In the desired
normative sense of perfect (Sense II), that x is p e r f e c t F
entails that x has a moral perfection or is to that extent
worthy of worship. That God is perfectly powerful, is to be
taken in this second sense.
It should be noted further, that sometimes it is only by
failing to be perfectly F in Sense I that one can be p e r f e c t l y
F in Sense II. Perfect truth-telling, for example, in Sense I
(e.g. telling the truth no m a t t e r what the context or consequences, perhaps better described as: omni-truth-telling) is
destructive of perfect truth-telling in Sense II (the moral
virtue, perhaps better described as: perfection with r e g a r d
to truth-telling).
In light of the above considerations, it is wrong for philosophers to seize upon the " o m n i - " in " o m n i p o t e n c e " as though
it captured the basic intuition of rational theology, and squeeze
it for all its worth, without r e g a r d for its explicative role for
the concept of " m o s t p e r f e c t being." If philosophers insist
that the t e r m omnipotence necessarily encompasses the
ability to do A, then the rational theologian ought to just give
up that particular t e r m as misleading or not adequately
explicative of the previous notion of perfect being. For, the
ability to do A, need not count as an aspect of perfection
T H E P A R A D O X OF O M N I P O T E N C E . A N D P E R F E C T I O N
37
SOPHIA
an
imperfection
in
where an implicit universal quantification over power-curtailing acts (i.e.., " A ' s " ) is understood. Now one might argue
that (19) is false, For there m a y be acts which curtail one's
power in ways wholly irrelevant to one's worshipful status.
P e r h a p s if God creates one tiny stone he cannot move, yet
can do all else he previously could, he ought to count as just
as worshipful as before. The act, A, in this case is neutral
with respcct to perfection in the n o r m a t i v e sense, And if this
is so, then the paradoxes return in full force with the r a n g e
of 'A' restricted to such perfection-neutral acts. (5") will
indeed be true, and so will (13) (since a m a t e r i a l l y omnipotent being can do A, under the restricted interpretation).
38
THE
PARADOX
OF
OMNIPOTENCE,
AND
PERFECTION
39