S.7 Hannan, M.T. - 1984 - Structural Inertia and Organizational Change. Pág. 149-164
S.7 Hannan, M.T. - 1984 - Structural Inertia and Organizational Change. Pág. 149-164
S.7 Hannan, M.T. - 1984 - Structural Inertia and Organizational Change. Pág. 149-164
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
American Sociological Review.
http://www.jstor.org
T.
JOHN FREEMAN
HANNAN
Universityof California,Berkeley
StanfordUniversity
Most prominent organization theories explain variability in organizational characteristics, that is, diversity, throughreferenceto
the history of adaptationsby individualorganizations, Earlier(Hannanand Freeman, 1977),
we challengedthis view and arguedthat adaptation of organizational structures to environmentsoccurs principallyat the population
level, with forms of organization replacing
each other as conditions change. This initial
statementof populationecology theory rested
on a number of simplifying assumptions. A
majorone was the premise that individualorganizationsare subjectto stronginertialforces,
that is, that they seldom succeeded in making
radicalchanges in strategyand structurein the
face of environmentalthreats.
How strong are inertial forces on organizational structure?This question is substantively interesting in its own right. It is also
strategicallyimportant,because the claim that
adaptation theories of organizationalchange
shouldbe supplementedby populationecology
theoriesdependspartlyon these inertialforces
being strong.
Many popularizeddiscussions of evolution
suggest that selection processes invariably
favor adaptableforms of life. In fact the theory
of evolution makes no such claim, as we made
clear earlier (Hannan and Freeman, 1977;
Freemanand Hannan, 1983).This paper goes
beyond our earlier theory in acknowledging
that organizational changes of some kinds
occur frequentlyand that organizationssometimes even manageto make radicalchanges in
strategies and structures. Nevertheless, we
149
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
150
structureare quite strong-much strongerthan
most theorists acknowledge. Moreover, the
assumption that organizations rarely make
fundamentalchanges successfully has proven
to be a useful strategic simplification.It has
allowed a rich and evocative set of ecological
theories and models to be appliedto the probformover time
lem of changesin organizational
(see, e.g., Brittainand Freeman, 1980;Carroll,
1983; Carroll and Delacroix, 1982; Freeman,
1982;Freemanand Hannan, 1983;Freemanet
al., 1983).
However, the claim that organizational
structuresrarely change is the subject of dispute. March(1981:563)summarizeshis review
of research on organizationalchange by asserting:
Organizations are continually changing,
routinely, easily, and responsively, but
change within organizationscannot be arbitrarily controlled . . . What most reports on
implementation indicate .
to us to be particularlyuseful in focusing
attention on the core features of organizations, explaining the life chances of
smaller and more numerous organizations,
and accountingfor changes in organizational
forms over the long run. By contrast the
rational selection or resource dependency
approach emphasizes the more peripheral
featuresof organizations,is betterappliedto
largerand more powerfulorganizations,and
stresses changes occurringover shorter periods of time.
This contrast provides a useful point of departurefor an attemptto clarifythe conditions
under which the two perspectives apply.
TRANSFORMATIONAND
REPLACEMENT
All accepted theories of biotic evolution share
the assumptionthat innovation,the creationof
new strategies and structures,is randomwith
respect to adaptivevalue. Innovationsare not
producedbecause they are useful;they arejust
produced. If an innovation turns out to enhance life chances, it will be retained and
spreadthroughthe populationwith high probability. In this sense, evolution is blind. How
can this view be reconciled with the fact that
humanactors devote so much attentionto predicting the future and to developing strategies
for coping with expected events? Can social
change, like biotic evolution, be blind?
Almost all evolutionary theories in social
science claim that social evolution has
foresight, that it is Lamarckianrather than
151
152
Our definition of structuralinertia implies
that a particularclass of organizationsmight
have high inertia in the context of one environmentbut not in another. For example, the
speed of technicalchangein the semiconductor
industry has been very high over the past
twenty years. Firms that would be considered
remarkablyflexible in otherindustrieshave not
been able to reorganizequicklyenoughto keep
up with changing technologies.
One of the most importantkindsof threatsto
the success of extant organizationsis the creation of new organizations designed specifically to take advantage of some new set of
opportunities. When the costs of building a
new organization are low and the expected
time from initiationto full productionis short,
this kind of threat is intense (unless there are
legal barriers to the entry of new organizations). If the existing organizationscannot
change their strategies and structures more
quickly than entrepreneurscan begin new organizations, new competitors will have a
chance to establish footholds. Other things
being equal, the faster the speed with which
new organizationscan be built, the greater is
the (relative) inertia of a set of existing
structures.
Even such a successful and well-managed
firm as IBM moves ponderously to take advantage of new opportunities.Granted, IBM
eventually moved into the market for
minicomputersand microcomputersand appears poised to dominatethem. Still, the protracted period of assessing these markets,
waitingfor technologies to stabilize, and reorganizingproductionand marketingoperations
created the opportunityfor new firms to become established. As a consequence, the
structure of the computer industry is almost
certainlydifferentthan it would have been had
IBM been willing and able to move quickly.
The point is that IBM did change its strategy
somewhat, but this change took long enough
that new firms using different strategies and
structureswere able to flourish.
REPRODUCIBILITY,INERTIA,
AND SELECTION
As we have emphasized elsewhere, organizations are specialcorporateactors. Like other
corporate actors, they are structures for accomplishingcollective action as well as repositories of corporate resources. Unlike other
collective actors, organizationsreceive public
legitimationand social support as agents for
accomplishingspecific and limited goals. Although individual members often manipulate
organizationsto serve private goals and organizationspursueother goals in additionto their
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
public goals, the basis on which organizations
mobilize resources initially and gain support
from society is theirclaim to accomplishsome
specific set of ends (e.g., making a profit,
treatingthe sick, producingbasic scientific research).
Creating an organizationmeans mobilizing
several kindsof scarce resources.Organization
buildersmust accumulatecapital, commitment
of potential members, entrepreneurialskills,
and legitimacy(see Stinchcombe, 1965).Once
such resources have been invested in building
an organizationalstructure,they are difficultto
recover. Although one can sell the physical
assets of a disbandedorganizationand sometimes its name, most resources used to build it
are lost when it is dissolved. Not only are the
costs of startingan organizationnontrivial,but
organizationscontinually use substantialportions of their resources in maintainingand reproducingtheir structures ratherthan in performing collective action. Just as in the case
of biotic creatures, there is a substantial
metabolic overhead relative to the amount of
work performed.Thus the creationof a permanent organizationas a solution to a problemof
collective action is costly compared to other
alternatives.
Why do individualsand other social actors
agree to commit scarce resources to such expensive solutions to problemsof collective action? A number of answers to this question
have been put forth (see Scott, 1981:135-63,
for an insightfulreview). The new institutional
economics argues that organizationsarise to
fill the gaps created by marketfailure(Arrow,
1974). Williamson's(1975) influentialanalysis
proposes that organizationsare more efficient
than markets in situations in which economic
transactionsmust be completed in the face of
opportunism,uncertainty,and small-numbers
bargaining.Althoughsociologists tend to deny
that organizationsarise mainly in response to
marketfailures, they tend to agree that organizations have special efficiency properties,but
emphasize their efficiency and effectiveness
for coordinating complex tasks (Blau and
Scott, 1962;Thompson, 1967).
Although these efficiency arguments are
plausible, it is not obvious that they are correct. Many detailed accounts of organizational
processes raise serious doubts that organizations minimizethe costs of completingmany
kinds of transactions.Indeed, there appearsto
be a strong tendency for organizationsto become ends in themselves and to accumulate
personnel and an elaborate structure far beyond the technical demands of work.
Moreover, many organizationsperform very
simple tasks that involve low levels of coordination. In contrast, collections of skilledwork-
153
Coleman (1974) has arguedthat corporateactors favor other corporateactors over individuals. We add that corporateactors especially
favorother corporateactors thatgive signalsof
proceduralrationalityand accountability.
Testing for accountability is especially intense duringorganizationbuilding,the process
of initial resource mobilization. Potential
members want assurance that their investments of time and commitment will not be
wasted. When membership involves an employment relation, potential members often
want guaranteesthat careerswithinthe organization are managed in some rational way.
Potentialinvestors (or supporters)also assess
accountability.In fact, the professionof public
accountancy arose in the United States in response to the desires of British investors in
American railroads for assurances that their
investments were being managedin appropriate ways (Chandler, 1977). Demands for accounting rationalityin this narrow sense are
both widespread and intense in modern
societies. For example, the federalgovernment
will not allocate researchgrantsand contracts
to organizationsthat have not passed a federal
audit, meaningthat they have given evidence
of possessing the appropriaterules and procedures for accounting for the use of federal
funds.
Accountability testing is also severe when
resources contract. Membersand clients who
would otherwise be willing to overlook waste
typicallychange their views when budgetsand
services are being cut.
In our judgment, pressures for accountability are especially intense when (1) organizations produce symbolic or informationloaded products (e.g., education, branded
products versus bulk goods)-see DiMaggio
and Powell (1983); (2) when substantial risK
exists (e.g., medical care); (3) when long-term
relationsbetween the organizationand its employees or clients are typical;and (4) when the
organization's purposes are highly political
(Weber, 1968). Our arguments presumably
apply with special force to organizations in
these categories. Still, we thinkthat pressures
towards accountability are generally strong
and getting stronger.The trend toward litigating disputes and pressures for formal equality
in modern polities intensifiesdemandsfor accountability. All organizations seem to be
subject to at least moderatelevels of accountability testing.
We argue that the modernworld favors collective actors that can demonstrateor at least
reasonably claim a capacity for reliable performanceand can account rationallyfor their
actions. These forces favor organizationsover
other kinds of collectives and they favor cer-
154
tain kinds of organizationsover others, since
not all organizationshave these properties in
equal measure. Selection withinorganizational
populations tends to eliminate organizations
with low reliability and accountability. The
selection processes work in several ways.
Partly they reflect testing by key actors and
environments in the organization-building
stage. Potentialmembers,investors, and other
interestedparties apply tests of reliabilityand
accountabilityto proposednew ventures. Such
testing continues after founding. Unreliability
and failuresof accountabilityat any stage in a
subsequent lifetime threatens an organization's ability to maintain commitment of
membersand clients and its ability to acquire
additionalresources.
Assumption 1. Selection in populations of organizations in modern societies favors forms
with high reliability of performance and high
levels of accountability.
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
come moral and political ratherthan technical
issues. Attempts at redesigning structures in
organizationsbuilt on moral commitmentare
likely to spark bursts of collective opposition
premisedon moralclaims in favor of the status
quo. Even if such oppositiondoes not prevail,
it delays change considerably.
As a brake on structural change, institutionalizationapplies both to the organization as a whole and to its subunits. But what
aboutthe diversityamongsets of differentiated
activities within the organization?Some kinds
of organizationsperformdiverse sets of activities, sometimes in paralleland sometimes sequentially. Military organizations provide a
striking example; they maintain"peacetime"
and "wartime" structures.' Similarly, labor
unions gear up for organizing drives or for
waves of strikesand then returnto more placid
bread-and-buttercollective bargaining. Manufacturingfirms sometimes concentrateon redesigningproductsand at other times concentrate on marketingan extant set of products.
Each phase of organizationalactivity involves
mobilizing different kinds of structures of
communication and coordination. In a real
sense these kinds of organizationscan be said
to use differentstructuresin differentphases.
Does this meanthatthese organizationshave
somehow escaped inertial tendencies? We
think not, at least from the perspective of attempts at building theories of organizational
change. These organizations have multiple
routines; they shift from one routine(or set of
routines) to another in a fairly mechanical
fashion. We thinkthat organizationshave high
inertia both in the sets of routines employed
and in the set of rules used to switch between
routines.
According to Nelson and Winter (1982:96)
routines are the "source of continuity in the
behavioral patterns of organizations." They
are patterns of activity that can be invoked
repeatedlyby membersand subunits.One way
of conceiving of routines is as organizational
memory-an organization's repertoire of
routines is the set of collective actions that it
can do from memory. Nelson and Winteremphasize that organizationsrememberby doing.
Like knowledgeof elementaryalgebraor high
school Latin, collective knowledgeis the basis
of organizationalroutines and decays rapidly
with disuse. Even occasional use reveals some
decay in recall and demonstratesthe need to
reinvest in learning to keep skills at their
I Janowitz (1960) discusses various conflicting
demands of organizing military activities in
peacetime and war. Etzioni (1975) discusses the
shifts in control problems that arise in armies and
labor unions as a result of such changes.
155
156
would have a lesser role in such an institution
can be expected to resist such a change. The
curriculumis difficultto change, then, because
it representsthe core of the university'sorganizational identity and underlies the distribution of resources across the organization. In
these ways, it can be said to lie at the university's "core."
This view of organizationsas having a core
which is more difficult to modify than more
peripheralparts of its structureis not new. As
Parsons (1960:59-69) pointed out, organizational authorityhierarchiesare not continuous; qualitative breaks occur between the
technical, managerial,and institutionallevels.
The technicalsystem is that partof the organization that directly processes the "materials"
used by the organization.The resources used
by the technical system to do the organization's basic work are allocated by a broader
organizational apparatus, the managerial or
administrativesystem, which also relatesthose
technicalactivities to the public served. While
each depends on the other, the managerial
level standsin a superordinateposition. It both
controls and services the technical level's operations, while the reverse is less often the
case.
The third part, the institutionalsystem, articulates the whole organization with the
broadersociety. Parsonsemphasizedits role in
legitimatingthe organization.Boards of trustees and directorsare responsiblefor long-run
policy and for the conduct of the organization
with regardto its reputed goals. Because the
institutionaland manageriallevels of the organization stand prior to the technical level in
controllingthe flow of resources, any importantchange in theiroperationsleads to changes
in the details of the operationsof the technical
system, while the reverse is less often true.
Thompson(1967)adopted these distinctions
in arguingthat organizationsare builtin such a
way as to protect structuralunits carryingout
the primary technology from uncertainties
emanatingfrom the environment.Thompson,
however, drew core-periphery distinctions
with reference to the organization'soperating
technology. Since we thinkthat the importance
of technology in determiningstructurevaries
greatly across kinds of organizations,we emphasize institutionalcharacteristicsmore than
technical ones. In this way our approach is
closer to Parsons than to Thompson.
An argument similar to ours has been advanced by Downs (1967:167-68)in his use of
the metaphorof organizationaldepth:
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
of the specific actions taken by the bureau,
the second of the decision-makingrules it
uses, the thirdof the institutionalstructureit
uses to make those rules, and the deepest of
its general purposes.
The layers supposedly differ in characteristic
speeds of response.
We conceptualizeorganizationalstructureas
composed of hierarchicallayers of structural
and strategicfeatures that vary systematically
in flexibility and responsiveness. Our theory
emphasizes the claims used to mobilize resources for beginningan organizationand the
strategies and structures used to maintain
flows of scarce resources. Thus we classify
items of structureaccordingto theirbearingon
resourcemobilization.Fromthe perspectiveof
resource mobilization,the core aspects of organizationare (1) its statedgoals-the bases on
which legitimacy and other resources are
mobilized; (2) forms of authority within the
organization and the basis of exchange between membersand the organization;(3) core
technology, especially as encoded in capital
investment, infrastructure,and the skills of
members; and (4) marketing strategy in a broad
157
As Stinchcombe(1965)pointed out, new organizations typically have to rely on the cooperation of strangers. Development of trust and
smoothly working relationshipstake time. It
also takes time to work out routines. Initially
there is much learningby doing and comparing
alternatives. Existing organizations have an
advantageover new ones in that it is easier to
continue existing routines than to create new
ones or borrowold ones (see the discussion in
Nelson and Winter, 1982:99-107). Such
arguments underlie the commonly observed
monotonicallydecliningcost curve at the firm
level-the so-called learningcurve.
In addition,the reliabilityand accountability
of organizationalaction depend on members
having acquired a range of organizationspecific skills (such as knowledge of specialized rules and tacit understandings).Because such skills have no value outside the
organization,membersmay be reluctantto invest heavily in acquiringthem until an organization has proven itself (see Becker, 1975).
Once an organizationsurvivesthe initialperiod
of testing by the environment,it becomes less
costly for members to make investments in
organization-specificlearning-early success
breeds the conditions for later success. Thus
collective action may become more reliable
and accountablewith age simply because of a
temporalpatternof investments by members.
Moreover, the collective returns to investments in organization-specificlearning may
take time to be realized,just like the case for
other formsof humancapital.For bothof these
reasons, the levels of reliabilityand accountabilityof organizationalaction should increase
with age, at least initially.
Once membershave made extensive investments in acquiringorganization-specificskills,
the costs of switching to other organizations
rise. Consequently the stake of members in
keeping the organizationgoing tends to rise as
it ages.
Finally, processes of institutionalizationalso
take time. In particular,it takes time for an
organizationto acquire institutionalreality to
its membersand to become valued in its own
right.
Assumption 4. Reproducibility of structure increases monotonically with age.
Theorem 2. Structural inertia increases
monotonically with age. (From Assumptions 2
and 4)
Theorem 3. Organizational death rates decrease with age. (From Assumption 4 and
158
been well documented empirically (see
Freeman et al., 1983). Death rates appear to
decline approximatelyexponentiallyas organizations age. One explanationfor this findingis
that reproducibilityrises roughlyexponentially
with age over the early years in an organization's life.
Processes of external legitimationalso take
time. Although an organization must have
some minimal level of public legitimacy in
order to mobilize sufficientresources to begin
operations, new organizations(and especially
new organizationalforms) have rather weak
claims on public and official support.Nothing
legitimates both individual organizationsand
forms more than longevity. Old organizations
tend to develop dense webs of exchange, to
affiliatewith centers of power, and to acquire
an aura of inevitability. External actors may
also wait for an initial period of testing to be
passed before makinginvestmentsin exchange
relations with new organizations. Thus processes of institutionalizationin the environment and exchange relationshipswith relevant
sectors of the environmentmay accountfor the
relationshipsstated in Theorems 2 and 3. The
argumentto this point cannot distinguishbetween the internaland external sources of the
relationships.
SIZE AND INERTIA
We argued above that dampenedresponse to
environmentalthreats and opportunitiesis the
price paid for reliableand accountablecollective action. If this argumentis correct, organizations respond more slowly than individuals
on average to environmentalchanges. However, some organizationsare little more than
extensions of the wills of dominantcoalitions
or individuals;they have no lives of their own.
Such organizationsmay change strategy and
structurein responseto environmentalchanges
almost as quickly as the individualswho control them. Changein populationsof such organizationsmay operate as much by transformation as selection.
Except in exceptional cases, only relatively
small organizationsfit this description.An organizationcan be a simple tool of a dominant
leader only when the leader does not delegate
authority and power down long chains of
command. Failure to delegate usually causes
problems in large organizations. Indeed, the
failureof moderate-sizedorganizationsis often
explained as resulting from the unwillingness
of a founder-leaderto delegateresponsibilityas
the organizationgrew.
One way to conceptualize the issues involved is to assume that there is a criticalsize,
which may vary by form of organization(and
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
also, perhaps,by age), at which failureto delegate power sharply limits viability. In such a
threshold model, organizationsmay be quite
responsive below the threshold level of size.
Above the threshold, organizations tend to
have higher inertia. Or the relationship between size and inertiamay be roughlycontinuous. Downs (1967:60)argues that for the case
of public bureaus: ". . . the increasing size of
ORIGINAL
NEW
REORGANIZATION
STRUCTURE
STRUCTURE
rb
re
DEATH
159
160
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
reorganizationrobs an organization'shistoryof
survivalvalue. That is, reorganizationreduces
the reliabilityof performanceto that of a new
organization. The stability of the previous
structuredoes not contributeto reducingvariability with new sets of procedures, role relations, etc.
If internal processes are solely responsible
for the tendency of organizationaldeath rates
to decline with age (Theorem3), the deathrate
for an organizationthat has just entered the
state "new structure"should be no lower than
the deathrate of a completelynew organization
with that structure(andlevels of resources).In
this sense, reorganizationsets the "liabilityof
newness" clock back towards zero.
Assumption 8. Structural reorganization produces a liability of newness.
where to is the time of foundingand y is positive. The liability of newness in this model is
expressed by f3,because the initialdeathrate is
a + f8 and the asymptotic death rate is a.
Imaginean organizationcreated at time to that
successfully changes its structureat tn, that is,
it enters the state "new organization"at that
time. The argument that the liability-ofnewness clock is set back towardszero implies
that its deathrate at timet approximatesthatof
a new organizationwith the same structure.In
particular,suppose that the deathrate of a new
organizationwith structurelike this one has the
following age-dependencein death rates
rd(t Ito) = a' + f'e-v'(' -to),
:
where y' 0. Then for the case of an organization born at to that switches to this structureat
tn > to, the death rate is given by
rd(tltn) = a' + /3'e-V'('-'t).
That is, developmentover the period(to,tn) has
no impacton its death rate, other things being
equal.
The argumentin the preceding paragraphs
can be viewed as one way to formalize some
long-standing notions about organizational
crises. Childand Kieser (1981:48)put the issue
as follows: "To some extent, a crisis successfully overcome may representa new birth,
in the sense that changes initiated are sufficiently radical for a new identity to emerge."
We suggest that such questions be viewed in
161
ENVIRONMENTALCHANGE,
SIZE, AND INERTIA
Assumption 5 states that large organizations
are less likely than smallones to initiateradical
structuralchange. Does this mean that larger
organizationshave greater inertia, as Downs
(1967) and others have claimed? If inertia is
equated with low absolute rates of initiating
structural change, it does. When inertia is
viewed in comparativeterms, as we argue it
should be, the relationshipof size to inertiais
more complicatedthan the literaturehas indicated.
According to Assumption 7, the death rate
declines with size. This statementis equivalent
to the propositionthat time-scales of selection
processes stretch with size, as we noted earlier. One way to visualize such a relationshipis
to consider environmentalvariationsas composed of a spectrumof frequenciesof varying
lengths-hourly, daily, weekly, annually,etc.
Small organizations are more sensitive to
/..
high-frequency variations than large organizations. For example, short-termvariationsin
the availabilityof creditmay be catastrophicto
small businesses but only a minor nuisance to
giant firms. To the extent that large organizations can buffer themselves against the effects of high-frequencyvariations,their viabilFigure 2. Hypothetical death-rate functions for a ity depends mainly on lower-frequencyvariapopulationof organizationsexposed to a tions. The latter become the crucial adaptive
shift in selectionpressuresat t1. The solid problem for large organizations. In other
decreasing curves represent the death words, the temporal dimensions of selection
rates of organizationsthat retain their environmentsvary by size.
strategiesand structures.The risingsolid
We proposedabove that inertiabe definedin
curve representsthe death-ratefunction terms of speed of adjustmentrelative to the
of organizationsthat undergoattemptsat temporal pattern of key environmental
reorganizationat t2. The dashed curve changes. Althoughsmallorganizationsare less
representsthe new (betteradapted)strategy and structureat t3. The dotted curve ponderous than large ones (and can therefore
representsthe death-ratefunction of or- adjust structures more rapidly), the enviganizationsthat revertto their old strate- ronmentalvariationsto which they are sensitive tend to change with much higher fregies at t4.
:1
12
V3
=4
162
quency. Therefore, whether the adjustment
speeds of small organizationsexceed those of
large ones compared to the volatility of relevant environments is an open question. One
can easily imaginecases in whichthe reverse is
true, in which elephantine organizationsface
environmentsthat change so slowly that they
have relatively less inertia than the smallest
organizations.
COMPLEXITYAND INERTIA
The complexity of organizational arrangements may also affect the strength of inertial forces. Althoughthe term complexity is
used frequentlyin the literatureto refer to the
numbersof subunitsor to the relative sizes of
subunits,we use the termto referto patternsof
links amongsubunits.FollowingSimon (1962),
we identifya simple structurewith a hierarchical set of links, which means that subunitscan
be clustered within units in the fashion of
Chineseboxes (what mathematicianscall a lattice).
Hierarchicalsystems have the propertythat
flows (of information,commands, resources)
are localized: an adjustmentwithin one unit
affects only units withinthe same branchof the
hierarchy.Simon (1962)arguedthat hierarchical patterns appearfrequentlyin nature("nature loves hierarchy")because the probability
that a complex assembly is completed in an
environment subject to periodic random
shocks is higher when stable subassemblies
exist, as in a hierarchy. More complex
structures do not have many stable subassemblies and thus are vulnerable to shocks
duringthe whole developmentalsequence.
Recent work on populationecology supports
Simon's argument.For example, May (1974),
Siljak(1975),and Laddeand Siljak(1976)show
analytically and with simulation experiments
that ecological networksare destabilizedwhen
links (of predation,competition,or symbiosis)
are introduced.Both the numberof links and
the complexity of the patternaffect stability.
We think that similar arguments apply to
structuralchange within organizations.When
links among subunits of an organizationare
hierarchical,one unit can change its structure
without requiring any adjustment by other
units outside its branch. However, when the
pattern of links is nonhierarchical,change in
one subunitrequiresadjustmentby manymore
subunits. Such adjustmentprocesses can have
cycles; change in one unit can set off reactions
in otherunits, which in turnrequireadjustment
by the unit that initiated the change. Long
chains of adjustmentsmay reduce the speed
with which organizationscan reorganizein re-
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
sponse to environmentalthreats and opportunities.
163
REFERENCES
Aldrich, Howard E.
1979 Organizations and Environments. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Arrow, KennethJ.
1974 'The Limits of Organization.New York:
Norton.
Astley, W. Grahamand Andrew Van de Ven
1983 "Centralperspectivesand debates in organization theory." AdministrativeScience
Quarterly28:245-73.
Becker, Gary S.
1975 HumanCapital.Secondedition.New York:
ColumbiaUniversity Press.
Blau, Peter M. and W. RichardScott
1962 Formal Organizations. San Francisco:
Chandler.
Burawoy, Michael
1979 ManufacturingConsent: Changes in the
Labor Process Under Monopoly Capitalism. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Brittain,Jack and John Freeman
1980 "Organizationalproliferationand densitydependentselection." Pp. 291-338 in John
Kimberlyand Robert Miles (eds.), Organizational Life Cycles. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Carroll,Glenn R.
1983 "Concentration and specialization: dynamics of niche width in populations of
organizations."Unpublishedmanuscript.
Carroll,Glenn R. and Jacques Delacroix
1982 "Organizationalmortalityin the newspaper
industries of Argentina and Ireland: an
ecological approach."AdministrativeScience Quarterly27:169-98.
Chandler,Alfred D.
1977 The Visible Hand:The ManagerialRevolution in American Business. Cambridge:
Belknap.
164
Child, John and Alfred Kieser
1981 "Developmentof organizationsover time."
Pp. 28-64 in WilliamH. Starbuckand Paul
C. Nystrom (eds.), Handbook of OrganizationalDesign, Volume 1. Oxford:Oxford
University Press.
Coleman,James S.
1974 Power and the Structureof Society. New
York: Norton.
DiMaggio,Paul J. and WalterW. Powell
1983 "The iron cage revisited: institutional
isomorphismand collective rationalityin
organizationalfields." AmericanSociological Review 48:147-60.
Downs, Anthony
1967 InsideBureaucracy.Boston:Little, Brown.
Edwards,Richard
1979 Contested Terrain:The Transformationof
the Work Place in the TwentiethCentury.
New York: Basic Books.
Etzioni, Amitai
1975 The ComparativeAnalysis of ComplexOrganizations. Second edition. New York:
Free Press.
Freeman,John
1982 "Organizational life cycles and natural
selection processes." Pp. 1-32 in BarryM.
Staw and Lawrence L. Cummings(eds.),
Researchin OrganizationalBehavior, Volume 4. Greenwich,CT: JAI Press.
Freeman, John, Glenn R. Carrolland Michael T.
Hannan
1983 "The liabilityof newness: age-dependence
in organizationaldeath rates." American
Sociological Review 48:692-710.
Freeman,John and MichaelT. Hannan
1983 "Niche width and the dynamicsof organizationalpopulations."AmericanJournalof
Sociology 88:1116-45.
Hannan,Michael T. and John Freeman
1977 "The populationecology of organizations."
AmericanJournalof Sociology 82:-929-64.
Hawley, Amos H.
1968 "Humanecology." Pp. 328-37 in David L.
Sills (ed.), InternationalEncyclopedia of
the Social Sciences. New York:Macmillan.
Hermann,C. F.
1963 "Some consequences of crisis which limit
the viabilityof organizations."Administrative Science Quarterly8:61-82.
Janowitz, Morris
1960 The ProfessionalSoldier.Glencoe, IL: Free
Press.
Ladde, G. S. and D. D. Mijak
1976 "Stability of multispecies communitiesin
randomly varying environments."Journal
of MathematicalBiology 2:165-78.
Lawrence, Paul and Jay Lorsch
1967 Organization and Environment. Cambridge:HarvardUniversity Press.
March,James G.
1981 "Footnotes on organizational change."
Science Quarterly
Administrative
26:563-97.
AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICALREVIEW
March,James G. and Johan P. Olsen
1976 Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations.
Bergen, Norway: Universitetsforlaget.
McKelvey, Bill
1982 Organizational Systematics. Berkeley:
University of CaliforniaPress.
May, Robert M.
1974 Stability and Complexity in Model
Ecosystems. Second edition. Princeton:
PrincetonUniversity Press.
Mayhew, L. B.
1979 Surviving the Eighties. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Merton, Robert'K.
1957 Social Theoryand Social Structure.Second
edition. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Meyer, John W. and Brian Rowan
1977 "Institutionalized organizations: formal
structureas myth and ceremony." American Jourpalof Sociology 83:340-63.
Nelson, RichardR. and Sidney G. Winter
1982 An Evolutionary Theory of Economic
Change. Cambridge:Belknap.
Parsons, Talcott
1960 Structureand Process in ModernSociety.
Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Perrow, Charles
1979 Complex Organizations:A CriticalEssay.
Second edition. Glencoe, IL: Scott Foresman.
Pfeffer, Jeffrey and GeraldSalancik
1978 The ExternalControl of Organizations:A
Resource Dependence Perspective. New
York: Harper& Row.
Scott, W. Richard
1981 Organizations:Rational,Natural,and Open
Systems. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall.
Simon, HerbertA.
1962 "The architecture of complexity." Proceedingsof the AmericanPhilosophicalSociety 106:67-82.
?iljak, D. D.
1975 "When is a complex ecosystem stable?"
MathematicalBioscience 25:25-50.
Stinchcombe,ArthurS.
1%5 "Social structure and organizations."Pp.
153-93 in JamesG. March(ed.), Handbook
of Organizations.Chicago:RandMcNally.
1%8 ConstructingSocial Theories. New York:
Harcourt,Brace & World.
Thompson,James D.
1967 Organizations in Action. New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Williamson,Oliver E.
1975 Marketsand Hierarchies:Analysisand AntitrustImplications.New York:Free Press.
Weber, Max
1968 Economy and Society: An Outline of InterpretiveSociology. Three volumes. New
York: Bedmeister.
Weick, Karl
1976 "Educational organizations as loosely
coupled systems." AdministrativeScience
Quarterly21:1-19.