Barzel - Economic Analysis of Property Rights
Barzel - Economic Analysis of Property Rights
Barzel - Economic Analysis of Property Rights
Editors
ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
OF PROPERTY RIGHTS
SECONp EDITION
Economy
Jeffrey S. Banks and Eric A. Hanushek, Modem Political Economy: Old Toptes,
New Directions
Robert Bates, Beyond the Miracle of the Market: The Political Economy of
.
Agrarian Development in Kenya
Peter Cowhey and Mathew McCubbins, Structure and Policy in Japan and the
.
United States
Gary W. Cox, The Efficient Secret: The Cabinet and the Development of
Political Parties in Victorian England
. Jea:nEnsminger; Making a Market!'Th-e 1nstitutional Transformation ofan
. . ..... African. Societ:)!. . .' . . ... ., ...
Murray Horn, The Poltica I Economy of Public Administration: lnstitutional
.
Choice in the Public Sector .
.
Jack Knight, Institutons and Social Conflict
Micnae1 Laver and KeI}neth Shepsle, Cabinet Ministers and Parliamentary
Govemment
Edition)
Mathew D. McCubbins and Terry Sullivan, eds., Congress: Structure and Policy
Gary J. Miller, Managerial Dilemmas: The Political Economy of Hierarchy
. Douglass C. North, Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic
Performance
Collective Action
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
Contents
pagev
ix'
xi
Introduction
1 . The property rights model
.
2
The publc domain: Rationing by waiting and price controls
3 Contract hoice: The tenancy. contract
4 Divided ownership
5 The old firm and the new organization
6 The formation of rigrus
7 Slavery
8 Wealth-maximizing constraints on property rights "
9 Property rights and non-market allocation
10 Additional property rights applications
IX
The property rights model: Recapitulation
- "I
3
"!6
33
55
65
.. 85
"''' 10 5
114"
128
139
14 8
154
References
lndex
159
v.ii
:>"'~.
.."';~'~''.;{''~:.~,~
;:.
- ~
:,-,
,':- ..
-< -
-,~-
~ ~.
..
':
-.~.
,0,'
;.;:,i
Since the publcation of the first edition of this book I have continued to
conduct research regarding economic organization and poltical econ
omy. This work is reflected primarily in Chapters 5 and 6 of the current
edition. I have aIs o separated the discussion of divided ownership from
that of the firmo The former now occupies Chapter 4, whereas in Chapter
5 I offer new thoughts on the latter. In Chapter 6 I briefly speculate on
the emergence of property rights and the state.
Teachingproperty rights courses over the last few years has led me to
discover iriihe fiisfedtiifsome rtots~iiiiihyambigities; a.n:d several ... ' .
instances that call for elabor-ation. I have attempted to correct the mis
takes, clarify the exposition, and elaborate when necessary. I have also
added a numbei of illustrations, some of which derive from new research
on property rights.
I wish to thank Dean Lueck, who read the ~n'tire manuscript, for his
helpful comments; my daughter Tamar, for enlivening the presentation
and protecting the English language; and the Earhart Foundation for its
generous financiaI support.
IX
"
Xl
Introduction
In the slave societies of-the American South and the West Indies, as well
as in others, slaves consistently - albeit rarely - bought their contracts
from their owners in arder to redeem themselves from slavery. In these
societies the law afforded owners virtually absolut rights over their
slaves, only seldom granting any legal rights to ~he slavs themselves;
consequently slaves were not legally entitled to own the pfoperty neces
sary for self-purchase. There was no legal barrier ar authority to stand
in the way of owners' retaining both slave and freedom money. Never.the
less self-purchase; whereby slaves acquired legal rghts to their own la
bor, dd occur.
As will be elaborated upon in Chapter 7, the' study of propert'y rights '.
and of the costs of transacting can yield an explanation as to why slaves
were able to buy their freedom; such explanations an be tested against
the facts. The property rights model I develop in this book can provide
explanations of an array of such phenomena, which standard economic
theory cannot successfully address. These explanations range from iden
tifying the re.asons behind the choice between wage and piece-rate con
tracts to pinpointing the conditons under which charity is more eff1cient
than profit-seeking behavior.
In the followng chapter, I shall define "property rights" and introduce
sotiteof the'certttalideas'ofthis book. In Chapter 2, the examination of
the gasoline shortage of the 1970S illustrates the usefulness and impor
tance of the property rights framework and familiarizes the reader with
its mechanics. Chapters 3,4, and 5 present the property'rights mode! and
its main organizational implcations. Chapters,6 thi:ough Ia expand the
mode!and apply it to various problems, including tights formation, slav
ery, and resource aIlocation in non-market settings. Chapter I I summa
rizes the discussion presented"in'Chapters'I-I0"n~i,pr0simts,some.gen~."
eral conclusions.
-," '
I
I
The property rights model
What are property rights? The term "property rights" carries two distinct
meanings in the economic literature. Qne, primarily developed by Al
chian (:1965, :1987) and Cheung (:1969), is essentially the ability to enjoy
a piece of property. The other, much more prevalent and much older, is
essentially what the state assigns to a person. 1 I designate the first "eco
nomic (proprty) rights" and the second "legal (property) rights." Eco
nomic rights are the end (that is, what people ultimately seek), whereas
.. lgliiglitsare'th' irieiiiis to achieve the end. In this book I am concerned
primarily with economic iights. Legal rights pIay a primarily supporting
role a very prominent mie, however, for they are easier to observe than
economic rights.
I define the economic property rights an individual has over a com
modity (or an asset) to be tbe individual's ability, in ,expected terms, to
consume the good (or the services of the asset) directly or to consume it
indirectly through exchange. 2 According to this definition, an individual
has fewer rights over a commodity that is prone to theft or restrictions
on its exchange.
The notion of rights is closely re1ated to that of residual claimancy.
The residual claimant to, say, an apartment house is its economic owner
in that he is able to gain(here.by.exchange)Jromanincreas(!jJ::uh.evalue
ofthe building, whereas he loses from a reduction in that value. Being its
owner, he is motivated to take any action that will, net of its cost, in
crease the value of .the property. The residual claimancy from an asset or
an operation is often shared by several individuais. An important propo
sition, to be elaborated on in Chapter 3, is that in order to maximize the
value of rights, a person's share in the residiilshould increase as his
1 Ellickson (I99I) makes the same distinction and elaborates on the role of"the
enforcement of rghts wthout the assstance of the state.
2This definition follows that by Alchian (I96S), Alchian (I987), Alchan and AIlen
(I977, pp. II4 and I98), Allen (I99I) and Cheung (I970).
.::tr~(~p;';.tf.:M!5~((..:m:;tt.:. .::L~~:
.\1',;,;,.-i~~_,
. ,--Un'
.'~. ,h
4See
Barzel I9 82 and Allen I99I. What:Jensef.l aI).d Meckling (I97 6 ) define as
agency cost is what is defined here as transaction cost"
4
'T}-,;:::o
fecting exchange.
a store's cherries are worth buying and which particular cherries to buy.
Store owners who allow customers to pick and choose cannot easily pre
..y,c:nt"t;hc:m.from.eating"cherries after they have already decided whether
'9rriOt'tobiiythem~norcaritheyp:revent customer~' careless handling of
cherries. Indeed, th prOcessof picking and choosing itself llows wealth
capture in the form of excess choosing. 7 The fact that the same cherry
may be inspected by multipie customers indicates that some of the cher
ries' artributes are placed in the public domain. The high cost of informa
tion results in transaction costs - costs that would not arise were the
owner and the consumer of cherries the same person. If informaton
about the cherries were costless, their initial owner would not have to
relinquish any rights, and pilfering, damage, and excess choosing would
be avoided. In reality, such public domain problems are unavoidable;
people can take steps, however, to reduce the associated losses . .one of
the main- tasks I will undertake is to discover some methods to reduce
such losses.
some of these attributes, but definitely not all of them. For example, a
firm (or, more accurately, its stockholders) that has a service contract for
a copier to which it has the title does not have fuII economic rights over
the. c;opier . The firm is not the only party that gains when the copier
perfoims.welI and loses when it does noto The service supplier is the
..
Net gains from exchange can often be increased if the original owners of
retaning the resto Cases where only a subset of rights is transferred are
property rights for single commodities: two or more individuais may own
them to the public domain; if they are in the public domain, resources
are spent
their capture.
on
7Barzel 1982..
8Alchian (1965) recognizes that ownership of commodities and of organizations
may be divided. Posner (1992.) discussed property rights; he, too, notes that ownership
can be divided.
. ,. .
...... .
OPERATIONAL FEATURES OF
IO
'':;''<:::-''!. '-'<''',}''.'
'.\. "
,... '
,~- .. ,$-.,""
on the eontrary, the results of such analysis apply everywhere. They are
as applicable to Hong Kong as they are to China during the Red Guard
era 01' to tribes entirely without a market system. Application, of course,
requires knowledge of the underlying constraints, and sueh knowledge
may be harder to come by in some systems than in others. Although
property rights analysis is usually applied to the capitalist market system
only, it is most usefuJ (and the Walrasian model is least usefu1) in systems
in which market prices are least used and aIlowed to adjust. In Chapter
9 J. will discuss briefly how property rights tooIs may be applied to a non
. pric~ economy. .
.
;'VifruallY . llUgoverninentsplaYc.a:major.role.. with.regard.to...pr.operty
prpertiesarid partici
rights; they.s'o maintain the legal rightto
pate directly in economic activities. In addition, governments are heavily
~nvolved with adjudicating and enforcing contracts. A comprehensive
analysis of the' coles of government is beyond the scope of the present
study; these roles will be touched on in Chapter IO in the course of ana
Iyzing the behf\vior of individuaIs and enterprises.
Cqstoms and mores seem to be additional non-price factors that affect
the allocation of resources. However, the effects of these factors on be
havior and 'On the enfoJ:cement of contracts will be ignored; although the
factors to be considred'iire'iiIlwed to hange, customs'andmores, like
tastes, are assum~d to be stable and accordingly haveno effect.on. the
margin.
vrious
'.
THE-DJSTINCTIVENESS OF
THE PROPERTY RIGHTS APPROACH
13
';,';;
parently the first to specifically point out the economic role of property
0
0
10Ross (I973) and Jensen nd Meckling (I976) are early proponents of agency
theory.
eratiire.
12WiIliamson (X975) and Klein, Crawford, and Alchian (X978) initiated the notion
... 13 This approach had been initiated by Arrow (I973) and Spence (1973)0
14
..x. .?
2
The public domain:
Rationing by waiting and price controls
R.ATIO.1'HNG BY WAITING
I will make a single change from the textbook mechanics on the demand
side: consumers exchange commodities for time rather than for money.
Given the fixed supply, forces of demand determine the equilbrium price
per unit of the good being distributed in terms of the amount of time
spent by individuais in the queue. Almost anything that can be said about
by waiting. 1
17
S/Q
Ql
Q*
Figure 2..1
. ). I focs. on below-equilibrium prce controls (i.e., price celings) and ignore above
eqililbritlln price controls (i.e., price floors).
I9
I8
~r~!"
" ".' - '-:." - , .;1 'I!;;: :';1;';: (,;' ;. :)t:'};{\}!~l<: '; ~ tl,~;~td~:"I~{:<. :'~::;< ~;,'.
Q/time
Qo
"J'
"I, n ' .
"
such a tax is that it equals the triangle berween the demand and supply
curves to the right of Qt; the excess of the amount consumers are willing
to pay over the resource cost of producing the quantity (Q* - Ql) which
is not produced beca use of the taxo This is sometimes also asserted to be
,the deadweight loss from controlling the price at Pc; as the rationing by
waiting dscusson suggests, this is not the case.
Because consumers can pay only Pc in money, they will spend re
sources equivalent to the difference (P 1 - Pd by waiting in line. For ex
"".mpJ~,jtQl.=,!9.9.""fc=}".P.l = $1.80, and the opportunity cost for con
sliinet:nS$Y'p,e:tJi6t;tI1efibuYrS'hth~~g~egate wll spend a total of
$1"OOlf money an<leight hours ih timeto'ptirchseone hundred ,units..
The amount represented by the rea P 1 - Pc X Ql is the dollar value of
the time expenditure. Because queuing is the only margin of competition,
this is the new equilibrium under the price controI. As the discussion
proceeds, various simplifying assumptions underlying the generic mode!
will be dropped. It is essential, however, to descrihe the control itself and
its background.
The Economic Stabilization Act of 1970 gave the president of the
United States the authority to impose controls on prices. On August 15,
1971, President Richard Nixon imposed a ninety-day economywide
.freeze,ofall..prices at their May 1971 leveI. This freeze was known as
Phase I of the price control and was succeeded by several more phases,
each involving som.e voluntary and some mandatory controls. 4 The final
one, Phase IV, lasted int 1974 and was essentially a period of gradual
price deregulation.
For many commodities the price controls caused inconveniences:
Fewer sales were maae on credit, a smaller variety of goods was avail
able, and free delivery was less frequento As a rule, however, shortages
did not arise. In the case of gasoline, the discrepancy between the con
trolled price and the market-dearing price that would have prevailed
without the controls was too large to mask some of the efiects of the
price controls. 5 In the wake oi the eruption of the Arab--lsraeli war on
October 6, 1973, the Organization of Petroleum Exporting Countries
(OPEC) restricted exporrsaiidised'i:hpiceofildepeti6Ieum. Prior
to the war, the world price of crude oi! had been around $3 a barreI. On
4 Much ofthe information on the Nixon administration price controls comes from
Kalt (1981) and Rockoff (1984)' In the case of retail gasoline, prices were not explc
itly controlJedj instead, the margins, or markups, were controlled at various stages.
Only the price of crude petroleum was controlled. (This information was provided by
Bruce Peterson of the Ameeican Petroleum Instirute and Del Fogelquist of the Western
Oil and Gas Assocation.) The Cost of Living Council and the Internai RevenueSer-..
vice were the primary agencies involved in policing and enforcement of the controls.
5The meaning of "too laege" is clacified in the last paragraph of the section entitled
"The Minimization ofDissipation" in this chapter_
20
.The
. 6The average per-barrei regulated price of crude oi! in the United States was $3. 8 9
. for 1973 and $6.87 for 1974. See Statistical Abstract of the United States I986, p.
~~
7 Cntro!
21
$IGaIloII
P 1=O.8S
~=.().SS
IC =0.35
Ql
Q*
QO
GaIlooslDay
Figure 2.2
seems to be the most likely resuIt from eXt:ending that framework. 10 The
view adopted here asserts that in reality people have many margins of
action that the Walrasian model abstracts from. Given these margins of
aoi~ wealih maxii:iiZioii wiU -giii:e a deterrnliiate equilibrium.
. Wealth maximization implies that individuaIs will carry on an activity
untiI (for the marginal unit)net gains are zero. Even' when a price is
controlled, the question 'must be asked: Can the buyer or the seller take
additional steps to obtain or provide another unit at a cost below the
added gain? If the answer is yes, an equilibrium has not yet been reached.
The notion of a ''''market-dearing'' equilibrium requires that alI individu
aIs make whatever moves they wish under the exisring property rights
arrangement. The textbook analysis of a binding price ceiling that con
dudes that a shortage will emerge implicitly assumes that buyers pay in
cash and that they receive the right amount of the right quality of the
commodity at the right time and place. It ignores the possibility of adjust
ments, thus impIicit1y denying that individuaIs maximize ifadjustments
are available. The way in which margins of adjustment were expIoited
under the gasoline price controIs will be examined in the following sec
tion.
lOIf the Ql available units are allocated randomly among the demanders of the Qo
units, then the deadweight loss is not the conventional welfare triangle. Rather, it is
proportionate to the. entire area under the demand curve above Pc (up to quantity
Qo), the factor of proportionality being (Qo - Ql)/Q1'
22
levei below the market-deacing price. It was noted earlier that there are
lines did emerge late in I973. It is curious that the regulators never for
assumption that the pecu,niary price is zero, but as long as the controlled
.ow:.rred by sellers was IlQt charged for; thus gasoline was partially placed
in the public domain, and the queue serv-ed to establish rights over the
joining the queue. If the wage rate of the marginal waiter had been $6
quired, but not how much they will pay in terms of a combination of
the price is stated in minutes per gallon, given that 35 cents per gallon
-:ci.
.. _.
'.
tire
gasoline was rationed by the (capacity of the) tank. A person who drove a car with a
small tank could get less gasoline for each waiting episode than someone whose car
had a large tank. Since waiting time was independent of the size of the gas tank,
According to the present llodel, running out of gas was not the resuIt of the price
controI. By waiting in !ine and then paying 35 cents a gallon, one couId always get
gasoline. Independent of shortages, a person can save resources (time) by filling the
tank less otten, and people occasionally do run out of gas by postponing purchase too
24
25
during this period would have had its maximum price fixed at 38 cents.
that the regulators could easily ascertain the actual base price and could
easily enforce it, delineation was dear in one important respect: Each
seller knew exactIy what price he or she could legally charge. 13. In other
". thirigs aspuichase frequency aiid to get gasofneat the lciwest riet re
source cost for a given quality service. Like alI transacted commodities,
gasoline has a large number of valuable attribttes. For example, when is
it available? Is the gas.station open nine or twenty-four hours per day? Is
the octane rating 88 or 98? Is tbe station self- or full-service? In addition,
the costliness of the transaction ncludes travei and search time as well as
time in the station. It is essential to have"specific informatio~'bout t).le
regulation of the attributes of gasoline before its effects can be agequately
examined. Ambiguity surrounded the regulation of such attributes ullder.
price controls.
Much of the ambiguty in the scope of controls stems from the great
number and variability of attributes of gasoline. The attributes of gaso
line transactions can be classified into those-. of. the gasolitle" itself .aJ;ld
those of the services provided with the gasoline. One of tpe' attributes of
the gasoline itself is its octane rating. Gasoline is comiflQnly gr~ded as"
regular or premium, depending on that rating. 14 Hence "premum gaso
line" describes a range of products of octane 90 and above, rather than
strictly defining a single product. (I assume, more or less in conformity
with actual practice, that under the price control premium gasoline had
to have a minimum octane rating of 90.) There are other variations
among premium gasolines. For example, Exxon's premium gasoline had
performance additives different from Shell's, and the premum gasolne
".sold in the Rocky Mountains was refined differently from that sold at
sea-Ievellocations. The prce contraI essentially ignored most of the vari
ations in gasoline quality. Because it is prohibitively costly to delineate
rights to alI the valuable atuibutes of a commodity, it is not surprising
that the control specfications were not fully detailed. Correspohdingly,
13 Actually,
th;;K~ii~~~~~~J~S.p~ii~r:::%rii:cliu~:7At~~~!J\h:*~~~~i~!ni~i~i~iif~~i:f~:
and Methods (ASTM). Brpce Pet~rson of the API reports that the standards are volun
tary, although there are some state.regulations, with varying degrees of enforcement.
No single octane rating is specified'to'distinguish regular from premium.
26
27
priori reason to accept the modeI that generated the preceding conclu
attempted to capture the value that was placed in the public domain.
ethyI-Iead used to boost the octane levei should have declined. Second,
28
29
to
$}GaIIon
'0
Clt
Q2
Q.3Q"
Qo
Gallon!f/l)ay
Figure 203
and demand curves for the new quality must be redrawn. S2 is the new
supply of gasoline, the production of which required fewer resources per
gallon beca use of the elimination of services. Consumers' valuati~n of the
no-service gasoline was less than that of full-service gasoline; Dz is the
newdemand.The"eIiminated.services, however, were valued by consum
ers more than they cost to produce; this is why they were provided to be
gin with. The intersection between the no-service curves S2 and D 2 at
quantity Q3 must therefore be to the left of the intersection between Do
and S1 at quantity Q*. The falI in quantity from Q* to Qj is a reflection
of a cost of regulaton that the adjustments could not Ilminate. The dissi
pation peigallon was reduce.<i.(to 20 cents in the example), aridthe num
ber of gallons of gasoline (Q2) was larger.than.inthe..absence..Qfthe..adjust::_
ment (Q1)' The total dissipation after service reduction:, whlth- is shown
by the crosshatched area (combined with the appropria'tt-: ~'welfare trian
gles"), is Iess than the dissipation without the service reduion..
even
CONCLUSION
At the heart of the study of property rights Iies the study of contracts.
Contracts, whether formal or informal, reallocate rights among con
tracting parties. I will focus here on private contr.acts that are enforceable
by the courts and the police. The tenancy contract between tenant and
landlord - between the owner of labor and the owner of land - is rela
tively simple and is thus a suitable point from which to begin the study
Ofcritiacts.
..... Ona' family fa:nn;a:' !iliigleopettt ot a' smgl fafuly' :,:.thewne.r'of
labor - undertakes the bulk of farm activities. Family farming is common .
and relatively simply organized. By studying tenancy contracts in the con- .
text of family farming, it is possible to isolate some basic contracting
problems that may be obscured in more complex organizations. 1 As a
background t:the analysis of the tenancy contract I offer a criticaI review
of the traditional approach to the rellitfonship between tenant and land
lord.
THE SHARE CONTRACT AND'
CHEUNG'S CONTRIBUTION
32
33
Conttact choice
Produt
labor
~ffffff/,/h",
LT
"LO
.T.enan.t lab.or.
Figure 3.I
(I -r)' ~f his own marginal product and will apply LT units of time to the
fartn to mximi,ze his wealth. For units of labor between LT and L" , the
output value of the tenant exceeds the wage rate; hOWl:!ver, the tenant
will prefer to sll these units of labor service in the.market because her
share in the farm output is less than W per unit of labor. Such tenants,
then, will stop short of producing the output when the value of their
marginal product equals their alternative earning. The shaded area in
Figure 3.1: i8 the alleged inefficiency induced by the share contract, which
is likened to the tax. distortion.
As Cheung demonstrates, this analysis is seriously flawed. Given the
frros and spending half of L T units of time in each. Indeed, the tenant
will do best by working a tiny bit on each of several farros. Even on only
one facm, the tenant earns on average more than W per unit of time.
compete simply by lowering the share they are willing to accept, but then
the equilibrium labor input wll falI as well. The logical conclusion of the
35
Contract choice
would plummet to zero. This model, then, suffers from an internaI incon
sistency.
Before I turn to Cheung's solution, it should be noted that the tax
analogycontains two implicit- and by no means innocent- assumptions.
The first is that landlords find it prohibitively expensve to stipulate and
police the amount of labor input. The second is that landlords encounter
no cost in policing the receipt of their share of the output. Whereas either
assumption may be a good approximation of real circumstances in any
particular case, the two are unlikeIy to hold true simultaneously. Simi-.
tracting does distribute the crop of a single plot between the two parties,
but there are other ways to distribute variability that can remove more
of the risk. For instance, because two persons residing on opposite sides
of the globe are not subject to common random forces, pooling the risks
between them reduces the risk each would face alone. Under the assump
tion of costless transactions, such popling woull inv()lve nq' added costs
1~J,"~Yfimplidtiii'thetiaditi6iiaFappioadi::to::jhe:~shire:'contract::ir;i'ihe'
assumptions that the cost of monitoring ouwut is" ruwaYI> zero' and thar
th cost of monitoring labor inpuf isalways prohibitive: these assump':
tions are ad hoc. Models based on ad hoc assumptions are likely to be
refuted when put to an empirical testo
.
In his ground-breaking work on the theory of share tenancy, which he
tested empirically against observed practices in China, Cheung (1969)
makes several points that are pertinent to the present discussion. First,
he notes that sharecropping is unlikely to hve been inefficient, given its
long history of survival. Second, consistent with rhe Coase Theorem, in
a world of zero transactions costs the share contract will yield an efficient
, ()u~c()llle>. .a:s, \!Vll. ()~h,e.r. (;()llt.r!lc:t .f()r:IfiS,-. "~C:!llls(! S9M.r~;tQr~q,n costlessly
add and police contract stipulations in such a way that alI inefpciency is
elimina1:ed. Third, in attempting to add emprical content to the Coase
Theorem, Cheung spells our some of ihe stipulations that were itecessary
for efficiency to have been attained in sharecropping. He finds that prac
tic~:ijn China were consistent with the implications he derives involving
fixed plot size, required leveIs of other inputs, and restrictions orr allow
able crops. Since the impiementation of these conditions consumes re
sources, the question remains as to why share tenancy was nevertheless
utilized. Cheung argues that risk aversion may explain the prevalence of
share tenancy because under share tenancy the landlord and the tenant
share the vagaries of variations in output and in output value. Whereas
Cheung's critique of the received analysis, which claims that the share
contract distorts the allocation of resources, is well taken~' hisrisk~
aversion explanation is noto
Risk aversion does not satisfactorily explain the share contract. Atti
tude toward risk is a matter of taste. If, as we usual1y 'assume, taste is
a personal matter that may vary unpredictably among individuaIs, an
explanation based on ris!c..aversion is not refutable. Moreover, how
someone may act with regard to a risky prospect depends on his or her
other actions and how risky they are - something we usual1y do not
know. Under uniformity..of taste toward risk, risk aversion is a function
36
Given the total amounts of land and labor, there is some pIot -size or,
more generally, some size distribution of plots that maximizes total out
amount of land. Those who own more land than they alone can most
are toa small. In order to realize the gains, the factor owners must con
tract with each other. I will here consider three methods by which two
the wage contract, (2) the rental contract;and (3) the share contract..
labor are uniform. Before analyzing the general case in which both fac
tors are variabIe, I will consider the special cases in which either.the land
or the labor is uniform. Suppose that .1and .is entire1y uniform and un
2 When the sole contractual problem between tenant and landlord is the method of
. dividing output, the role of risk aversion seemS ooth .simple and important. As a rui e,
however, many. sources of variabiliry confront the parties. The effect of crop-sharing
on overall riskiness th~ll.~.Qm.,$..J!:~s."l.r..;nld.,l~lilt imp!tant,.F.QI;..in~tam;~,. t.,iS..lJ.QL .....
at ali <;lear how transferring the maintenance of iriigation: ditches from the landlord
to the tenant affects the distribution oI risk. .
37
-fixed amount for its use. ActuaI output will differ fcom expected output
beca use of random fluctuations and to tlle't!xtent that the tenants alter
their own efforts. Because land is uniform, it does not contribute'to -out
their own effort. The tenant is the "residual daimant": Barring bank
ruptcy, the landlord receives a fixed amount, while the tenant receives
. whatever is left over after paying the rent (of course, this diffe.rence may
rewards are strictly a function of their own efforts. In the case of uni
form land, tenants will make the optimal effort under the fixed rent
contract.
(and labor effort) is uniform is the mirror image of the one just presented.
tiye t.. t:ll:ima~9!i:lI1<i.imPJ:'Y:etheir Iand and will not gain from misrepre
"senng its quality. In this casethe landlords are the residual daimants
and are the only ones affected by their own actions, A rentaI (r a: share)
contract would be inefficient here, producing less total income for the
38
Contract choice
contracting parties.3 The more efficient contract, that of the fixed wage,
would prevail under such conditions.
In reality, neither land nor labor is uniform. It follows that ali three
contract forms are subject to efficiency problems. When discrepancies
between costs and valuations are inevitable, an arrangement in which
such discrepancies are observed cannot be thought of as inefficient. Inef
ficiency implies preventable waste - waste that would not ocenr if people
were to maximize. In an imperfect world, even the best solution is still
:.:s.ubjectto:discr:epancies:.between.marginal costs and marginal valuations;
flOt ali suchdiscrepanciescan be eliminated economi~ally.When we dis-'
cover discrepancies, elur task is to detrmine how resource allocation will
change when the costs of or the returns from reducing the discrepancies
change. In order to be able to analyze changes in resource allocation, a
more detaited analysis of the nature of variability is necessary.
THE EFFECTS OF VARIABILITY WITHIN FACTORS
Contract choice
$/acre
~+Lr.r
I " .. .. 'il;,;.:j)i'iicre'iiiiOWifl.,:'::::,:.::
..
.."NQ."."l'k"
. exttaCted nutrients.
$/acre
fi)
In this section, I will analyze the' n~ture of the deadweight losss that
arise with a fixed-rent contract as a result of not pricing a~.tributes at t1}e ,
margin, ana in the following sction I will indicate methods available to
contain these deadweight losses. Suppose a tenant rents a plot of land on
a fixed-rent basis. I ass!lme that soil nutriel).ts ar~ pJaced under t:he ten
ant's control, permitting the extractiOl}.:of whatver amount li or she' .
wishes without paying a m~rginal charge, and that .the mainenanc~ of
land improvements is left under the landowner's control and 'not prced
on the margin either. The three parts of Figure }.2, depicting different
aspects of the land rental, will be used to analyze the nature of the equi
librium and the forces that lead to it; parts A and B reflect behavi9r
within the transaction, and part C relates to market behayior."
The horizontal axis in part A is the per-acre mount of nutrients ex
tracted from the soil and the vertical axis is dollars per aCre. LN is ihe
marginal falI in land value du'e to the depletion of the nut:ients. Alth6tigh'
tothe tenant the nutrient is free, its use is constrained by 'lhe cost of
extraction. CN is the marginal cost of extracting the nutrients - arising,
for instance, from the need to use water to transform the nutrient into a
form that plants can utilize~ C~ + LN is the sum of the two COSts. DN is
the demand for the nutrients reflecting the (marginal) increase in the
>.i;<
:>
iA
= index of quantty of
$/acre
7+T{
D
I
OR
Qo
41
Contract choice
C N , the latter being the cost borne by the tenant. 5 It is as if the tenant
heighr of L N , the marginal &11 in land value, at NR' Since the tenant wiU
extract an "excessive" amount, such as NR' per acre, that control is ulti
mately at his own expense. A tenant who could somehow cOl1l1llit to use
only No soil nutrients per acre would produce a lower output. However, ,
he would have to pay a lower fixed rent such that his net income could
enjoy "free" perks must, under competition, pay for the privilege by an
amount that exceeds in expected terms the valu~ of the privilege. The
. .
."
Glven measurement costs, the tenant wlll use such nutnents to the pomt at which
the estimated rather than the actual net gan from an extra unir is zero. For simplcity
of exposition, such inccures are ignored whenever the consequences are not ger.
Labor and land are complex factors, each possessing many attributes,
but contracts betWeen pairs of owners are, usualIy quite simple. How,
then, are th~ individual ttdb'ies 'conrrolled by contract, and wniiffrces
determine which contr,,\ct will maximize the va:Iue' oI' the" rstces?' A " ."
~eq-rent land co~tract can simply stipulate duration and rent; alterna9
tivly~ it cal b-s detailed as the;. contracting parties wish it to be.
Wher~as coq~ractors are free to stipulate whatever they wish, not alI at
tributes are worth stipulating nd.monitoring. Any attribute that is not
stipulated and that can be varied becomes a free attribute. Tenants who
are in control of such an attribute will use extra units so long as they
generate added positive (net) income; landlords will similarly use attri
butes under their control.
Although by~ssumption he loss associated with free attributes is too
costly to avrt directly, it can'be controlled in two distinct ways. First,
contract 'stipulations regarding attributes related to the ones subject to
excessive exploitation or inadequate provision may be altered. Second,
an altogether different contract may be used, one that controls those at
tributes left uncontrolled under the first contract.
h
' . W + (U + T)Q .s the cost of transaction as I define it in
7In thls case, t e quannty
RI
Barze119 8 5 See also AlIen 199 1 .
..
11 d b the tenant
sPanel C incorporates only tw? ~mspeclfied attrl~utesl.oI:t con~ro t e tt 'butes how
and one by the landlord. Generahzmg for any num er Olnepen en a ri
,
'"''''ever;'isstraightfiW:td~'''''''''''''''"'''''''''''''''''''''''""'"'''''''''' "''''''''':'
, :d' Such a
9In either case, a mech~nism to enforce contract performanc~ ISbrelulr: 'rts The
mechanism is usually provl~ed P3:rt1y by the contractors. and part y y e c u .
existence of such a mechamsm wIll here be taken as a glven.
43
;. {~n~'~ ;:!'~~~5~'~~~~':l~t '.:' !!.~ ~~.!-;~~-,~.;; :;;{~<:~~.:: ':';;" ~;: ii~:~,~ ;-~~;J~ ;., {o: ~n~:::, >.:.: ;,':. ~~ (;,; ,
'.;;':';0'
.,.,.)~
';".'.':.,.H.~_ /-;::~~::1.~i>.
.....
lOThe general proposition regarding rhe demand" ('spply) curve is thar around an
equilibriuI1l position, fixing the levei of either-a complementary or a substitute good,
c: .. ..theowrrdemand (supply) elasticity will be less than it is when the quantity of the
related good is allowed to adjust (see Slberberg:J:,990 ).
44
Contract choice
$/acre
J .!
.-'
'.
Contract choice
46
14The incentive to exploit free attributes ntensifies toward the end of the contract
perodo The more acute this problem, the more likely it is that the parties will sign a
new contract before the olper one.expires. In professional sports,such phasing in of
contracts is common both fo.r athletes and for coaches. The motivation is to prevent
underperformance by athletes as the expiration of their own contracts approaches,
_ .~hile avoiding the overuse of athletes by coaches whose contracts are .about to expire.
15If landlo.rds are legally required to. keep certain improvements present on the plo.t
at the time the contract is signed, there is no need to spell this out in the contract.
Similarly, if a landlord plans to maintain the improvements, she or he will not require
such maintenance from the tenant. So.me contracts may appear to be lacking in detail
but may, nevertheless, diifer significantly from similarly worded tenancy contracts in
areas in which the particular improvements are simply absent.
47
Contract choice
can be specified, however, under which a shift from one contract form to
the other is expected to occur. For example, the more valuable the land
attributes that are difficult to measure and to police, the more likely it is
The share "tenancy contract stands halfway between the fixed-rent and
the wage contract. When sharing, both Iandow,!ler and tenant are resid:- ... _
uaI claimants because each is remunerated bya fraction of whatever the .
output is. At the same time, each gains from shrking: The landowner
wiIl not maintain Iand improvements as vigorousIy as he or she wouId
have'under the wage contract, and the tenant will not work as hard S
he or she would have under the fixed-rent contract. The margins subject
i:o distortion undei theshare contract indude all those of the other two
contracts. In addition, the specification and monitoring of output are
Iikely to consume more resources under the share contract than under
the other contract forms. Although more margins are subject to distor
tion when the corii:i-act calls for sharing, the loss from some margins of
distortion is reduced more than proportionately. Adoptng a new per
spective on the previously discussed tax analogy may demonstrate how
the share contract can ,r:eslllt in a 10wer leveI of distortions than that
"assoCla:i:e(rwrththeother'twocontr~:rs ...
is well known that the distorcion associated with a tax (or with a subsidy)
49
Contract choice
rises as the square o the tax (or subsidy) rate. Thus, the welfare-loss
trangle of a 1:0 percent tax on a commodty is (approximately) four times
as large as that of a 5 percent tax on the same commodity. In the wage
contract, to the extent that supervision is not perfect, the reduction in
effort is a free attribute available to the worker, because the worker is
not penalized for the reduced effort. It is as if the worker were to pay a
.100 percent tax on the increase in output induced by greater effort. Smi
lady, under the .6xed-rent contract it is as if the tenant were to receive a
:,:t:'PfJl'9.~nt,!)!l~~4Y:Q,R~~l,lJ..tr:i~m$.~nd the landlord were to pay a 100
percent tax ou lnd imptovements, yielding returnswithin the contract , '
perodo In a share contract the taxes are reduced from' 100 percent to the
worker's share in the case of the extra effort and to the landlord's share
in the case of the maintenance expenses. Since the deadweight loss rises
quadratically with the tax rate, the rate reduction brought about by shar
ing results in a more than proportionate reduction in losses. For instance,
a fifty-fifty sharing arrangement would reduce the distortions from each
of the taxed attributes to one-fourth of their leveis at the 100 percent tax
or subsidy. The proposition, however, does not apply to the subsidized
attributes, since these continue to receive a 100 percent subsidy. For ex
ample, to the tenant the nutrient is fu11y subsidized under both the .6xed
'" rennind the shatecontract. Whereas ali of these items are taxed or subsi
dized in a share con'tract, compared with only about half of them being
taxed or subsidized when one or the other of the two contract forms is
used, the quadratic relacionship is capable of lessenng the total burden
under the share contract to a levei below that of the burden either of the
other forms generates .. The share contract, however, entails an ncrease
in monitoring costs, which may tip the scales against it.
Monitoring serves to reduce the losses associated with margins of dis
tortion. The monitoring of each margin of distortion, however, entails
.its own start-up cost. Since the share contract is subject to more margins
of distortion than are the other two contracts, its costs of monitoring are
higher. The gains the share contract is capable of generating in reduced
,distortions may not.belarge.enough,.and.the,.sharecontract,may fail to
be adopted. As conditions gradualIy shift, favoring, say, the wage con
tract over the fixed-rent contract, the share contract becomes attractive
as an interme.diate step; nevertheless, because of the required extra moni
toring costs, the share contract may be skipped altogether. 16 As the fixed
rent contract becomes less attractive, the fraction of rent contracts is ex
pected to falI and the fraction of wag coni:racts is expected to increase;
but it is not possible to state, a priori, whether the fraction of share con
16 As the value of the contributions of the twO parties becQmes more equal, a sharing
arrangement is more likely to emerge. This is beca use a fifty-fifty sharing formula
tends to yield the highest reduction in distortions and is also simpler to administer
than others.
I have thus far focused on the costs and gains associated with fixed
wages, fixed rents, and share contracts between owners of land and la
problems that arise when'land and labor are not ownd by the same
inputs in a production processo The first set of costs arises beca use the
5I
The contracting model discussed thus far can generate many implications
with regard to actual tenancy practices. Because infoqnation problems
are at the heart of the high cost of transacting, I will concentrate on
tliose implications that are a direct consequence of these problems. Two
sources of change in information costs virill be considered, one associated
with the introduction of a new crop and the other with the arrival of new
"",workers., , ,
When a cr.op, !ie,w., ~(),a.I1" g~~, l>,~::tl1~~, PXQ,6.~aJ~l~>infQ".maJim,o.n, h.ow"
well it will do in different locations within the area is more costly to
obtain than is similar information on old crops. Landowners who per
.sonally cultivate only part of their holdings and contract with others to
cultivate the rest of their land know, as a rule, more about their land than
do their tenants. Because they are aIso. the main benefidaries of good
decisions about new crops, the discrepancy in landlord-.v.~.~qs-tenant
knowledge for the new crop is likely to be higher than it was for the old
crop. Tenants who are offered fixed-rent contracts may suspect that the
rent Iandlords' demand is excessive and that the landlords are exaggerat
ing the productiveness of their plots in growing the new crop. Such suspi
dons are hard to allay; hence tenants' demand for land and their associ
atedcoUhteroffers are likely to be low. Wage contracts are free of this
particular problem because landlords who pay fixed wages bear the en
tire new-crop risk, about which they are better informed than are tenants.
Landowners who switch to the n,ew crop are more IikeIy to offer wage
contracts to their tenants than they were with the old, established crop.
In addition, it is expected that: with the passage of time the direction of
the trend will be reversed: The cost of determining the suitabilit:y of land
parcels for the new crop will decline, inducing the readoption of fixed
"'fei'ifcoi'itra:ctswherethy Were preferred before.
Another nformation problem arises concerning immigration. Little is
52
Contract cboice
known abol.lt how workers who are new to an area will perform. Land
owners are reluctant to commit themselves to paying new workers the,
prevailing wage. Given the Iack of knowledge regarding workers' abili
ties and attitudes, the demand for the services of such workers and, con
sequently, the wages offered are likely to be low. A new worker who
believes that he or she is more productive than the wage being offered
indicates can "guaraI!tee" his or her output by offering to operate as a
fixed-rent tenant.'These workers, then, bear the onus of the information
, .... p~ob~~~:.~t}s..e;X:p"ected that relatively more new workers than established
'ones wiU 'Operate aS' 'fixed"'rept tenants. Moreover, new tenants will be
givenparcels that are more'difficlllt to exploit,suh as diose containing
few improvements. Some old-time tenants may acquire a reputation for
being gentle on the land and on improvements; these individuaIs will be
the favored fixed-rent tenants on the easy-to-exploit parcels. Newcomers
do not haVe such reputations and are therefore expected to get land par
cels for which the lack of information makes less difference. Here, too,
the trend is expected to be reversed as the new workers become more
established in the area.
CONCLUSION
The owners of labor and of land can increase the value of their assets by
collaborating. beca use total output is rendered larger than it would be
were they to operate alone. However, effecting the collaboration, is tself
costly because it is difficult to prevent wealth capture whencooperation
is attempted. Measuring each factor's contribution to output is necessary
for cooperationto be successful. Such measurements are costly and there
fore will not be precise. This lack of precision, coupled with the variabil
ity in output due to unpredictable factors such as the weather, implies
that individuaIs can gain at each other's expense and that they will spend
resources in order to capture these gains. Together owners of labor and
owners of land (bolstered by competition from other owners) will adopt
the contract form that generates the largest net output value where max
imization is sbjecftcnverifirialproductiricostsas well as to the
costs associated with the capture of wealth.
Neither labor nor land is uniform; specimens of each vary in terms of
the leveis of their respective attributes. The contract between the owners
will therefore attempt to control not onIy the factors as a whole but ais o
various individual attributes. Someof these attributes may be controlled
directly (e.g., a tenant pays for irrigation water supplied by the landIord);
those difficult to controI directly may be controlled indire"C1:Iy'"hy'"fixing'...... '"'"
quantities and altering prices. A basic principie underlying the maximiza
53
Polidng
land '
High losses
FW
Inrerrnediatelosses
Lpw ar no losses
se
FR, 50
Polidng
output
Lack of
specializing
FR
se
se
FW
SO,FR
so
se
FW,SO
Divided ownership
FW, FR
no
'.
54
DiiJided ownership
than they did before. The management of entities with divided ownership
requires organization, which is one of the subjects of the present chapter.
The discussion of divided ownership and its management is also a useful
introduction to the fum, which is the subject of Chapter 5.
56
that they can be unbundled to reveal. a rights ~tructure of some comp. eXlty. d
d
3The mec hanl'cs of how a free attrtbute avallable. to a transactor wlil be use un er
fixed pay or under a share contract are presented In Chapter 3.
57
.......i:Z.e.4gJ:'g:!)i:Z.~lJi..n...J#;~i!! .;h;\IJ;g~.Lfu.~Hng.them,.~
.
SevetlW6ikeiS'ifjyoeiequiid':f'mak'e'largenichine ftfuction. If...
all of them share ih. its wnerilhip,thentheabsehc ofconstrintSon ,
individual behavior will permit many of the attributes of such a mae,hine
to become common property. As a result, incentives for sueh activities as
earefuI handling and maintenance may be greatly weakened. As will be
expIained later in this chapter, this problem may be alleviated if many of
the individuaIs who work with the machine beeome employees of the
machine's owner. Not all those working with the machine are expected
to be the owner's employees, however. For instance, the machine's manu
faeturer may have sold it with a guarantee, while retaining the function
of servcing it. In that case; contrary to the standard model, some of
.the indivduals..w:or:king.. with..the maehine are not the employees of its
(nominal) owner.
Where an Qffice building aecommodates many workers, common
property problems such as the use of eorridors and access to utilities need
to be addressed. Still, most of the structure ean be assigned to distinet
individuaIs, and individuaIs' rights can be reasonably well delineated.
The.b.uilding's users do not have to be sevei:ely constrained not to damage
it and can conveniently belong to more than one organization. Before
moving on to discuss the nature and the organization of offiee building
ownership in greater detaiI, Iet me summarize the discussion up to this
point.
.
The preceding examples address common-property problems that arise
when the ownership of goods is divided among individuaIs. These exam~
pIes also illustrate' that the severity oi thcaptureprohleill 'varisf~om .
one case to another and, indeed, that the severity of the capture problem
is not uniform for different attributes of a single pieee of equipment.
Because different attributes of apiece of equipment are not equally sus
ceptible to capture, it may be advantageous to handle its various attri
butes.. differently. Attributes suseeptible to serious commmFproperty
problems, such as equipment lubrication, will tend to be owned by orga
4 By the saroe token, rental cars - even fancy ones - are expected to be equipped
with engines requiring regular gasoline.
58
Divided ownership
..
',,-:,__ ~,~,,;:.,~.::::';;':';~~:'~_;"_.-'i:/,;',"..
'*
assumes the liabilty for its operation and is, in turn, the owne;r of another
subset of rights.
Given that severa! organizations hoId rights over an asset such as an
office buiIding, the question arises as to the principIe that 'governs the
aIlocation of these rights. As I have suggested, the structure of rights is
expected to be designed so as to allocate ownership of individual attri
butes such that the parties who have a comparative advantage in affect
ing ,the income flow over the attributes that are susceptibIe to the
common-property probIem will obtain rights over them.
.
,.
".
I shall discuss one additional right, namely, that associated with fire in
surnce, in greater detail than others because the fire insurer's role as
residual clamant is easy to grasp and because it seems to counter the
perception of the funetion of fire insurance held by many economists.
'li is corrpnonly ass.umed that building 'owners buy fire insurance be
caqse they are risk-averse and would like to shift the financiaI risk of fire
te those PloJ;e willing to assume such a risk, I, however, assume rsk
neutrality' (WhiCh :is not unreasonable in this"casej~ Risk-neutrality im
plies that the sole objective of thebiiildiriif owner' igardrig' firt; 18 i:h
minimization of the expected net loss from it. What can explain the fire
inSurance.transact{on? I sl1all argue that one explanaton for such a trans
action is 'that fire" insurers are more efficient than are the titleholders of
.. .-buildings as whers of the fire-risk attribute of office buil4.i.~$s.
Not being a fire-prevention expert, an office-buiIding owner would like
to secure the services of someone to minimize the expecl:ed loss from fire.
The specialist could be hired for a fixed wage; however, the owner lacks
the proper knowledge to drect the employee to do the right job. Under
';1" fixed wage, the employee would find it easy to shirk and would have
no strong inentive to ensure that the fire-prevention program is efficient.
It is possble to overcometrusdifficulty by making the specalst responsi
ble for his or her own actions. The specialist who charges a fixed fee
for his services, while assumng the residual claimancy to his actions, s
providing fire insurance at a fixed premium. 5 As an insurer, the specialist
wilI lose from fire and gaio from its absence. He is, therefore, motivated
to take such preventative actions as minimizing fire hazards, conducting
fire drills, and enhancng speedy fire fighting when fire does occur, in
order to reduce the level- or, more accurateIy, the net expected cost of
SThe need for capital to guarantee the actions will be discussed in the next chapter.
60
Divided ownership
fire losses. "I:'he insurer is thus one of the owners of the building: He or
she owns the fire occurrence attribute of the building.6
This analysis of fire insurance constitutes the application of a general
principIe. As a rule, specialists know more about their line of business
than do their customers. They are therefore in a position to charge for
service that is of a higher quality than what they actualIy provide. For
this reason people would be reIuctant t9 deal with them were their ser
vices not guaranteed. Insurance may be viewed as one form of the sale of
guaranteed service. It also amounts to a division of the ownership of the
.::;::::':::":lnsmea::assets::hetvVeeilihe::nomiiiifownersand 'the insurers. themse1ves.
,~;,." Fir~ insuranceis setdom"aH.:encompassing. FuIl insur~~ce C6verage im- '
. plies that the insurer is the sole residual claimant of the fire hazard facing
the insured firm.? It is unlikeIy, however, that only the insurer can affect
the incidence of fire and the loss from it; the insured is also expected to
affect fire losses. The latter usually makes decisions about where and how
flammable materiaIs are stored, whether or not smoking is discouraged,
and how well its employees keep fire escapes unobstructed. Both parties,
then, contribute to the mean effect of fire hazard, and both are expected
to bear some of the effect. Consequently, coverage is not fuH and both
the insured and the insurer become, to varying degrees, residual claim
,apt$,t;ha:Us, .9.WAers of the fire hazard.
There are two refutable implications that could test the hypothesized
role of insurance. Dne relates directly to fire insurance, whereas the other
is Iess specialized. The first states that when a party's contributon to the
mean loss of fire decreases, the fire-insurance contract will be modified
to decrease that party's share of the fire losses. For instance, suppose that
motors are used in the insured oprations. A switch by the insured - due,
say, to a change in relative fuel prices - from gasoline motors, which are
a serious fire hazard, to electric motors, which are less of a fire hazard,
constitutes a reduction in the insured's contribution to fire hazard. Be
sides the reduction in total insurance payments, his or her share in, the
income variability due to fire hazard ought to be reduced; in this case his
or her coinsurance rate should be lowered. li
The send implication concerrisadistiridpatteriifaii:dbute'owner~
ship between two types of condominiums. In the first ali the units are
6The expected value pi sLlh o:wnershp is nega tive; hence the insurer makes a nega
tive payment (i.e., he or she receives a premium) in order to acquire the right to the
fire-occurrence attribute.
7For coverage to be full, ir must indude, besides direct losses,such effects as those
due to lost business, to inconvenience, and to suffering.
8Insurers indirectly perform another service: the policing of employees' diligence in
reducing expected fire losses. A relative increase in some premiums signals to owners
that their employees have become too lax. For a related discussion, see Hall I986.
6r
62
Divided ownership
tbe tools de~igned for non-professionals. These are otten low-cost, low
afford the higher prices because they use the tools more intensively. If a
pear, however, since individual users would have little incentive to han
dle tbe tools carefully. The problem seems severe enough that amateurs
prefer to be the sole owners of low-quality tools rather than share the
~~~~;~~~~:~~~n~l:~i~~~~~~~~~~~~~~h~~hd~~~:i~voiv~i~~~::"'"""
order to reduce their excessive and careless use of it. The wage contract
the worker for his or her time, that contract abates the excessive and
wage workers as well. Since such workers do not gain from extracting
63
For many years the theory of economic. lrganization was nearly synony
mous 'with the theory of the fum. Standard economics textbooks occa
sionally referred to other forros of organization, such as the family and
government, butthe firm was the only.organization conslstently and sys
temattcally discussed. Nevertheless, the exact functon. of the fum re
mained unclear. Knight's (1921) attempt to add substance to the con
struct called tl}e "firm" did not fare v~ry:Wt'!II"a.Ilcl. Coase~s.(:I937)
revolutionary approaGh to organization required several deides, as well
as his own work on social cost, to begin to influence economists. Both' ol""
these efforts focused. OJ.1 the firmo In".more recent years, Coase's transac
tion cost icl:eas have been explite'by econmists itempting to generate
. a theory of the firm, as well aS py oths;:rs whQ guestion the usefulness
of such a theory.l The insights gained through these efforts have been
considerable, yet our understanding of organization is only in its infancy.
In this chapter the transaction cost approach to organization will be ex
tended.
In order. to appreciate the need for the transaction cost approach
ando its contribution, one must first examine. the received model of the
. firm extensively and critically. I attempt' to show that as a description of
real fums the received mdel is unteriable, and that under conditions
that would allow a textbook firm to exist, its function would become
inconsequential. Turning to general problems of organization, I first con
sider the distinction between market and fum transactions and the sig
nificance of Coase's discussion of liability. I then briefly outline the major
contributions to the theory of the firmo Finally, I describe in greater detail
my own contribution, which stresses the guaranteeing role of equity
....;....;.capitat.......
1 Prominent
among these are Alchian and Demsetz (I97 2 ), Williamson (1975), Jen
8
. sen' and Meckling (197 6 ), Klein, Crawford, and Alchian (197 8 ), and Cheung (19 3)'
65
64
...................
.........
2Duality theory relates costs and production functions. Varian (1992.), for instance,
defines the firm in terms ohhe production function (p.x). He discusses technology in
some detail (pp. 2.-2.2.), and states (p. 84) that it is straightforward to derive the cost
function given the technology.
66
whereas one can presume that Japan and the United States exploit the
same production function, Japanese car manufacturers are less vertically
integrated, buying more parts from other fums, than are their American
counterparts. To speak more generally, the determination of whether to
perform any function in-house, that is, within a single fum, or to have it
performed in the market by separate firms does not seem to depend on
technology. It does not seem that the differences among such firms are
attributable to production function considerations.
One could argue that Japanese cars differ Erom -Amc:;;riean, afs, ap,Q
ancy across fums between the production and cost functons may be at
3
is contrived and should not be used to describe real firms. . .
The absence of dose relations between tpe prodution and cost func
tions is further illustrated by noting that some firms are housed in more
than one plant, whereas sometimes the same physical plant houses more
than one firm. The observation that production is organized "in-b9 use "
fum's production are not alI owned by the same person . The ownership
analysis, even though the typical implicit ownership assumptions are not
innocuOus. Firms are assumed to own the capital equipment they use and
to hire labor. Hiring labor means r~nting labor services from the owners
the use of labor is similarly problematic. In reality, firms do not own all
the capital they use; capital is .also partly rented. To the extent that firms
are financed by borrowing, they are renting rather than owning the capi
tal. Moreover, firms often rent space and equipment. It is not self-evident
that those firm owners who borrow or rent capital and who employ labor
have interests that coincide with the interests of the oWners of the rented
on
assets as to how these assets should be employed. As a rule, the questi
of whether these interests coincide is simply ignored in the textbook anal
..... ysi:;.<J fthe firmo If assets owners' interests do not coincide, then methods
of recondlig 'i:herii iiiustbe' considered. 5 " ......... ". '.'
Returning briefly to the notion of duality, it is possible to write a pro
duction function for any process, however complex, even for one incor
porating monitoring technology. It seemS unlikely that attempting such
an indusion here would be useful. The usefulness of a production func
tion in economic analysis lies in its economy in describing economic rela
tionships. If rriiiitring were included, this economy wuld be lost. The
inclusive function would depend, for instance, on whether labor is em
ployed by the hour or by the pieee, which, in turn, depends in part on
the market prices both for labor and for the output. Even if it could be
successfully formulated, the complexity of such a function would render
it unrnanageable, and there is little chance that it could be tested.
It is desirable to reexamine;albeit briefly, the relation between the in
dustry's supply function and the firm's cost. Applyingcompaiativestatics
to the received model yields the prediction that firm size will ncrease
when the market price of its product increases.. The service "use of office
4It is sometimes asserted that it is impossible to separately measure individuais'
contributions to ufput. Under the given information assumptions, workers should...
nevertheless;be rewarded for their aggregate effort and not for their time.
sIn some texts, particularly those regarded as advanced, the issue is further obfus
cated since productive factors are introduced generically, with no recognition of insti
tutional differences among factors.
69
ancy, only that of sharing is output-based. Both the fixed-rent and the fixed-wage
71
are costly. In o~der to incorporate such costs into the analysis, a precise
definition o( the term "market transactions" must fust be provided.
Two distinct definitions of market transactions are seemingly consis
tent with the common understanding of the termo One is that they are
properly and fully priced transactions and therefore free of distortions.
In other words, in such transactions individual buyers and sellers bear
the full costs of their actions. Whereas Coase does not explicitly suggest
that transacting in the market involves deadweight losses, the asserted
costliness of ~uch trans:i!-ctions mus(iIpply.that some marginal equalities
of the zero tJ;ansacti'on cost ndel are violated. 8 This view of market
.',trnsations impiel by Ca'aseseems to ~et()be a correct view of reality.'
Indeed, it is my contentiori that the Pareto onditions for efficiency are
violated in every transaction. 9 - It does not seem useful, then, to define'
market transactions as those free of distortionif that set ~s empty.
The other, ,riot well-recognized, de:finition of market transactions is
that, once conclu~ed, such transactions leave no obligations remaining
between transactors, that is, ~ese. transactions are go:verned by caveat
emptor. This d~finition'of market transactions.is attractive not'only be
cause price alone affect~ buyers' decisions but also because of its precise
correspondence with a useful and clear-cut practice: Howev!'!~:l~q:welilt:,
emptor transactions are costly ad gov~rn onlr a small fra'ction of the
total volume of trade. Although it is attractive, this definition of market
transactions is often in conflict with the current indiscriminate use of the
not uniquely' defined termo W.hen using die term; it iS ~ecessaty to make
clear one's intend~d meaning and to stay.alert t$?' t~e pitf~lls of u!:rent
usage.
It is useful to relate the notion that market transactions leave no obli
gations between the transactors to Cheung's (1983) analysis of the firmo
Cheung points out that the organizations falling under the label "firm"
are diverse; that the wage contract does not suffiiently characterize
them; and, most iInportant, 'that there is no satisfactory operational
definition of the termo He suggests that economists should' abandon the
firm as a vehicle of their analysis and instead 'should focus' on contracts.
Nevertheless, Cheung retains the distinction between firm transactions
and market transactions. He says that the " 'firm' is ... a way to organize
actvities under contr,actual arrangements that differ from those of ordi
nary product mar,ket'S" (p. 3). Given costly transacting, organizing activi-
::,"',',:::,'::":liast1,ve:'::bf'iii::hotK:'cas~'s::eaai'of:ihe:t\iiio"'ty.pes"o!,.,in!eraction. ~eelJ1s
72
BNote that becaQse of the costs of conductng market exchanges, the net amount
the seJler receives' is less than the total amount spent by the buyer: Money prices
convey only partial information about the tenns of exchange.
'
"..... """,,,~The,,:vi<:w,,that,,aside.f:rom,QCcasioRal,~extemalities,::"maJ:Ckets, ar.e.fr.ee ,of. distortion ,'" ,
is pervasive, I believe 'that' this view is at the root of ali sorts of confusion, especally
when particular :distortions are considered to be exceptions and therefore to call for
exceptional measures, where,as in reality they are instances of the general case.
73
his or her employer, is the one Coase singled out as characterizing the
arebound.tothe,firm.bya..nexus,of contracts. In team production, the
ter 3, I showed why the share contract and the fixed-rent contract are no
firm, the firm consists of a residual claimant-supervisor, who:is ar its
more in the market than is the wage contract, even though only thelatter.,
center, and others whose output is difficult to observe and who produce
to faU neatly within any single category. Consider the services one secures
claimant. Becuse'the supervis.or is the residual daimant, he 01' she is
.. suchservices take at least two basic forros. In one the charges are by units
Both Williamson (1975) and Klein, Crawford, and Alchian (l~n8) sug
instantaneous market transaction, since the other sde of such a transaction is the
specific endeavors. If such inputs are owned by different individuaIs, then
'.
ownership. They state that'such ownership gives the owner' control over
ali its attributes and makes him or her the residual claimant to the income
they generate. By combining the ownership over arrays of assets, the firm
saves .on contracting costs with individual asset owners. By merging, the
fum also gains controI 'i:hat it does not hav.~ under exchange between the
the incentive structure from a different angle. Both Milgrom and Roberts
empirical work that demonstrates tht the size and structure of actual
firms conform to these models. Casual empiricism does not provide sup
port for the notion that these are the main reasons behind the existence
of actual firms. For instance, it is difficult to see how the size and struc
76
has come to be known as the Coase Theorem: When property rghts are
well defined and transacting is costless, resources will'be used where they
are most valued, rega.r:d1(!s.s o(:vv.l1:~~ll"<?!..!h.:~.~~.n..s.~.<;:~<>,r.~.. ~~~~~~Ji.a.l:>W!Y, ....."..,,
erty rights, renderng redundant the requirement that property rights be well defined.
77
The considerations that apply to labor also apply to both the prices
in quantities, firms may purchase their trucks and then bear the effects of
varying durabilities across trucks, or they may rent the trucks, shifting
the variability il) longevity to rental agents. In the same fashion, employ
ers who pay uniform hourly wages to non-uniform workers bear the vari
pid &yi:h 'piece be~u more of thie .Yli~i~l>ility .in tll.eir. .()'Yf!. p~r.fQrl."O.ane ..
itY for purch,,!-ses subject to caveat emptor; if the purchase is not govemed
who are usually passive participants in the operations of their firms, are
transactors who can affect the outcome is expected to assume the effects
guarantees the constancy of the price of his or her commodity, and thus
bad debts is expected to become the bearer of the variability in the repay
ment rate. Each of these resource owners who transacts with the firm is
an owner of his or her operation than is one who is paid a fixed wage...
12 Each contract will induce a different performance. The total variability also de
pends on the contract chosen.
rate, placing it more within the fum. This is 50 because as the writer gains
the value that ontracts can generate from a given set of resources. For
the publisher is better induced to advertise the book if the marginal pay
with substantial on-the-job training. Workers may be reluctant to invest
while contracts with salespeople' who work on commission are less so.
to provide such a guarantee for its employees; ceteris paribus, the higher
The latter are likely to be even less within the publishing firm when used
the outstanding equity'capital, the doser to optimal the leveI of training
for sales abroad, where the publisher's expertise relative to that of the
will be. Equity capital is productive, and its amount wll be expanded to
salespeople is less than for domestics.1~~k.P.1J.Us.b~!'$~~fJ,tr.1;$:::with::::: :::::the:point:at:whiclrthecost.ofexpanding it by one more unit brings an
sales and, of course, the publisher must have the means for the buyviewed as the set,or nexus, of contracts guaranteed by the equity capital.
losses increases. Before concluding this discussion of the fum, I shall offer
scale economies arises from the fact that by its very nature the occurrence
when the market wage exceeds the contract wage - simply by showing
!
amount of gurantee capital as long as the prospects are not perfectly
.. ' up for work. 14 Owners of labor are, therefore, more likely to enter into .
correlated. ThIs factor, then, favors large-scale firms .
Guarantee capital is not capital itself but the command over it. When
. 'contracts in which they ale required to guarantee the difference between
their market wage and their actual wage than they are to enter into cona guarantee has to be effected, the capital is transferred from its current
tracts that require them to guarantee otner possible effects of their behavowner to the beneficiary of the guarantee. The ease of .transfer is im
ior. The inability to personally gUtlrantee large losses appliell" to many
portant here, but it is costly as well. The guarantor who holds enough
professionals, including lawyers. For this reason, one expects only large
cash to be able to effect the guarantee loses the return that an asset would
law firms to undertake large contingency cases requiring a substantial
have provided. On the other hand, the guarantor who holds physical
amount of legal services without the guarantee of reward. in particular
.i
capital will incur a cost of transfer when effecting a guarantee; as the size
.
of the payment increases, the cost rses per dollar of transfer, since the
cases. Smalllaw firms may be unable to finance the up-front legal services
required in such cases.
assets that must be used for the transfer are progressively less liquido
Owners of productive factors other than labor may also lack sufficient
Although the .guaJ.'antoris.assumedto berisk-neutral; because of this
wealth to guarantee their actions fuUy. Any asset may be used to provide
lquidity problem he or she is expectedto act as if risk-averse.
a guarantee. Equity capital, however, is a factor specializing in guaranDiseconomies of scale to guarantee capital arise whendifferent indi
viduals take part in assembling it. lf individuaIs simply guarantee each
tees. ..
The buyers or employers of any productive factor are able to affect the
other's prospects without constraint, then the incentive for caution is
outcome of the transaction and are therefore expected to guarantee their
weakened. They may pool their <:::tpit:al, as is done in stock corporations,
actions. The better their ability to provi de such guarantees, 'i:h higher
thereby resolving the free-ride problem. But whenindividual shares are
....13 .... .:...... .,..
..... ...
. .
.
.'
..
small, ownership and control tend to diverge. In either case,thisproblem
. The pu~hsher demonstrates such an ablhtr by slmply. selbng on credlt, whJch
limits the size of the equity capital and consequently firm size.
mlght expiam why wholesalers often seU to retallers on credlt.
. ...
. . .
.'
' . .
. 14In other words, workers simply continue to work at the contract wage, and the
One final pomt worth r,nentlOmng IS that the role of eqmty capl~al may
dlHerence between that wage and the market wage accrues to their employers.
be usefully contrasted wlth that of the share contract. The eqmty firm
82
'I
'"
who seU their 'ser,!,ices to it. Under the share contract, the cooperating
tees among factors is difficult (as is the case when the cooperating factors
consist mostly of workers) and when their output is easy to divide. The
'no.tgu~rlteed.~;<..
">".';
".,:,
, , : .
;.<::-',
CONCLUSION
84
. 1
Having analyzed the causes that allow properties to be kept in the public
domain, I can now address the issue of the f>rmation of economic
(though not necessarily legal) rights. It might be tempting to trace the
pattern of currently existing property rights holdings to its point of origin
to determine how and why it carne about, yet such an effort would be
futile. The ability to consume commodities, including those necessary to
'" sustain life, implies, the,possession of rights over them. Once this is under
stood, .it, b!eome,s, ,dear, that one,annot, ,e~pe~to ~;u.s,oyex,anY, !,:yj4ene,
of a pre-property rights state, since it is not possible to endow a pre
property rights state of affairs with meaning. In order to gain a toehold
on the evolution of property rights, one must start with the simultaneous
emergence of life and property rights and then consider a world where
some rights are already in place..One must resort to something less dra
matic than, but similar to, the physidst's big-bang .tho~y. Once some
rights are already in existence, it is possible to explore their evolution
with respect to changes in economic conditions and legal constraints.
Inferences about the creation of property rights may be drawn by
studying instances of anarchy or violent upheaval that necessitated radi:.
cal acts of rights redeflnition. A spectacular example is that of the Cal
foinia gold rush, described and analyzed in detail by Umbeck (1977).
Rich deposits of gold were discovered in California in 1848 when i:he
region was under U.S. military occupation, just days before the signing
of the peace treaty between the United States and Mexico. The gold
bearing land was not privately owned, and according to the treaty it be
came the property of the U.S. government. The United States flnalized
the transfer of power from Mexico to itself by abolishing the Mexican
law pertaining to mining rights on government land, but it failed to enact
'aliw"regulii:ing'i:heprivate acquisition of rights to mineral land until
I 866. Although the U .S. governrnent was the nominal Qwner of the gold
bearing land, it lacked sufflcient power to enforce its ownership or main
85
2 Attempts are often made to' describe the "ideal" state. This is not my intento
Rather, I am concemed only with how the state actually evolved.
. .
l.
1
j
l!
1
87
than each of their clieIits. Before installing a king, subjects are expected
of law; consequc;:ntly, we see that history has been dominated by dictator
ShipS.5
to have formd a collective-action mechanism to control him. 3 This is a
non-Hobbesian feature of the model.
Constraints placed on the mler must accompany his installation. 4 One
THE COMMONPROPERTY/PRIVATE PROPERTY
likely constraint Is on the size of the force under his personal command;
DICHOTOMY
others inc1ude the form of his remuneration and the length of his tenure.
By employing him only partIy on the basis of a residual from the outcome
U~til recently, most economists had not explicitly adopted a property
of protection but mostly for a wage, and by also supervising him, subjects
rights framework from which to analyze economic problems. The earliest
will have made the ruler largely an employed, supervised manager of the
and most notable exception is Frank Knight's discussion of social cOst ".
protection effo,rtl'atherthanIt&:'piinia:ij"iesiaU"ardaim-aiit~::Maiiy:me(f~ :::.::::.:..: :::::::::(i9Z4l:In-his analysis of the useof roadshedemonstrateddds~ve!y:the ...
vrai:Y.::states in Italy iqtported a mIei (podesra), typkally for a one
. rle of ownership in lhe allocationof resources. In a similar v.ein, several .
deeades laterH. Seott Gordon (I954) analyzed the e.ommon-property.
yearperiod, and paid him a :6xedreward. Sueh eontrols and remunera
tion methods redueed the possibility that he could organize a takeover
problem of flshing in international (public domain) waters. After Knight,
and amass enough wealth to finance it.
and even subsequent to Gotdon's eontribution, economists did not con
It also seems plausible that there would be seale economies in the delin
cern themselves much with property rights. Economists; infrequent use
--eation of borders between neighbors and the adjudication of disputes
of property-rights considerations may reflect a belief that such consdera
tions are unlikely to produee useful results. Indeed, because most prop- .
that might occur. Moreover, the delineation of assets that the mler pro
vides for protection is eomplementary with that required for trade, so he
erty does not appear to be common property and, more~portIlt.. be
is the low-eost provider of the service. To lower the cost of erp.ploying
cause the transformation of what is c1early eonsidered common property
him,.hj~)~ubjects are expected to encourage him to provide legal services
ioto what is dearly considered private property is rarely observed,
aIlclt().fac:ilit.a.teC:()Iltl':ict: .tradf::,tl1:itis,. t.ra~.~t~.~~w.ak..~l' "!lS~ ..o. thixd7...
property-rights notions as expounded do not seem to be especi~lly use fuI.
party adjudication. The more standardized the traded commodities, the
The perception that property-rights considerations are not useful in
easier it is to trade by contraet and the greater is the advantage of the
the analysis of resource allocation seems to stem from.an all-or-nothing
scale economies to delineation. The more homogeneous an area, the
view of rights. Both Knight and Gordon assumed that property rights are
either present and perfectly well deflned or totally absent. They neglected
larger the expected state size; likewise, the more standardized the goods
produeed in the f.ea, the greater the expeeted seope of the state.
the possibility of an intermediate state in which rights are oo1y imper
fectly deflned.
In this scenario, where subjeets maintain tight control over the protec
tor, there must be a balance of powe;'between them, along with safe
The usual eharacterization of commodities as homogeneous entities,
often with only one attribute, makes it easy to condude that commodities
guards to preserve the balance. The safeguards cannot be perfect, how
ever, and externaI shocks due to such events as foreign conquest or
are either owned or not owned, and that there are no intermediate states
plagues wll upset the balance. The likely outcome of ao upset balance
of ownership. Such a view seemS to have been bolstered by the. assump
is a dictatorship. Once a dictator takes over, the state's economy is
ton that economic rights are equal to legal rights and that the litter are
likely to decline and stagnate. Nevertheless the initial dictator and his
either present or absent. Moreover, the position usually taken has been
suceessors are likely to ding to power. It is difficult to return to the mIe
thafpiopertyiightsarTirgely,:,:,:perhaps entirely - created and enforced
by government. Correspondingly, it has traditionally been asserted that
3The organization preceding the emergence of specialized protectors as described
it
is the government's fauIt that rights are left in the public domain, sub
here seems similar to organizations that have been observed in a number of anthroplJ.-..
ject to "open access.,,6 Knight and Gordon implied that if the govern- .
logical studies.
ment had turned roads or flsheries ioto private property,.1;he assocated
4 Given the English model that served Hobbes, the notion of a king (and a hereditary
regime) seems natural. The city-state of Venice, however, is a better example. Starting
its independent existence around A.D. 600 andencling in I797 with the Napoleonic
S().Qquest, Venice seems to be the foremost"c~xample of a constitutional, or rule of law,
regime dat did not turn into a dictatorship. The ruler position in Venice (th.e
dogeship) was not hereditary, and the powel?of the doge was rigidly constrained.
5 Another
88
89
Rights that ar:e explicidy delineated by the state constitute only a small
fraction of alI legal rights. The rest are delineated contractually by their
owners in the process of exchanging them. In a contract transaction, the
buyer becomes the legal owner of the commodity sold by the selIer where
the contract (often supplemented by common law) delineates the attri
butes of the commodity. For example, a buyer of a ticket to a play is
legally entitled to certain services delineated on the ticket. Contracts,
ECONOMIC RIGHTS AND LEGAL RIGHTS
I however, seldom if ever delineate alI the attributes of the transaction.
The v~ry~ucce~s of Umbeck's study derives",ill"p,a..:r.t.~J!()mtheuniqeness::,:"' ':I,::,,::'The::huyer:bec:omes:the':~'Conomic'O\v.ner::notonIY?,.f the attributes the .
,of the Cahforma gold rush. Umbeckis ble to explain therole of violence'
!
sellerlegallyagrees to dehver but also of othets where, beca!lseoHactors
or, more ~c'curately, the threat of violence when the state's authority is
! such as reputa~ion, the 'seller chooses to deliver even ~ough he or she is
absent. H1S results, however, do not apply easily to more orderly circumnot legally obhged to do so. In the case of a play, the tlcket holder has no
~ta~ces. A~ a rule, in an ~lready functioning society, the creation of rights
legal recourse in case.of.a shoddy perform~nce, but he or she knows t?at
IS an ongomg processo RlghtS are created in the presence of state authorthe theater company IS hkely to do a good Job nevertheless. When buymg
ity, which has a con;tparative advantage over private individuais in the
the ticket, the buyer here becomes the claimant to and therefore the ecouse of violence and tends to discourage its private use? When a state
nomic owner of the expected leveI of performance.
authority is in place,. the role of allocation devices other than violence is
To clarify further the distinction between economic and legal rights,
greatly enhanced. As I shall argue, as economic conditions change proplet us consider inventions. Many inventions, especially minor ones, are
erty ri~ht~a,r~ .. t:()1t~tantl:y created and abandoned; therefore the~e is a
developed in~o sal~ble p~oducts without any legal protection. The own
need.for an analysis that fits contin\li I1g,5.111()<:>rh. (;h.aQg~~ jIl qp.,<;litim:'J.s. , ' " ,ers, ()~ o~?~r. .1n.~~I1tl()ns,sl~p'I:r..~o not seek l~gal .protection beca use the
It IS .useful here to reiterate the definition of economic property rights
.
cost of acqumng and exerclsmg s~ch protectlOn IS greater than the gain
o~fered in the introductory chapter. These defined an individual's "ecothey would generate. Still, inventors often gain from their unpatented
:-nomic rightS" Ovet an asset as the individua/'s ability to direct/y consume
inventions, at least for a short span of time. Although these inventors
. the s'!rv.ices ?f.. the asset, or to consume t indirectly through exchange.
lack legal rights over. t~eir ~nventions, they. have econo~ic rights over
. Th~ delmeatI(~n. of property rights is itself subject to indhdduals' optimithem. To pursue the dls:mctl0n f~rther, con~lder the afterhfe of patented
zatlOn. Descnbmg what the property is and protecting it consume re,
drugs. A drug patented m the UmtedStates IS legally protected for seven
s~)Urces, and perfect delineation is prohibitively costfy. Hence property
.,.... 'teen years. ~e:e, as in the general case, the legal ri?hts tend ~o enhanc.e
nghts are never pedectly delineated. Moreover, transacted commodities
the economlC nghts. When the patent for a drug expIres, genenc competI
. "have many attributes, and the rights to differem attributes of a given
tors often emerge. Nevertheless, the originally patented drugs typically
(physical) commodity or to different attributes of a transaction are not
sell at a large,premium relative to the generic ones. In spite of the loss of
all eqally well defined.
legal protection, inventors retain substantial economic rights over their
Legal rights, as mightbeexpected, are a major factor in terms of their
drugs. The reason seems to be that many buyers find it too costly to
effect on economic rights. "Legal rights" are defined as what the governascertain theproperties of the generie,medicinesandal'ewillingtepaya
n:ent delineates and enforces as a person's property. By granting legal
pre~ium for the established brand-name ones. The rights the inventors
r~ghts, the government participates in defining and protecting economic
retam result from consumers' ignorance.
nghts. Legal delineation"is likewise both costly andincomplete. More
over, individuaIs have a comparative advantage over the government in
THE DELINEATION OF NEW RIGHTS
various delineation activities and actually undertake many of them. Cor
.'The seed for the analysis of rights creation in an ~ngoing society was
r~spondingly,. individuais' behavior must be considered in the study of
.. .. nghtsJotmatrrc ................"" ........", ... ,.. ,..
planted in Demsetz's (I967) study of the Montagnais Indians of Labra
7EIlickson (1991) shows how rights may be established within existing srates, but
New rights are created in respon~e to new economic forces that increase
are not exercis~d are placed in the public domain, it follows that people
deliberately place some of their properties in the public domain. Two
examples will illustrate this point. Both restaurant owners who supply
their patrons with "free" salt and owners of movie theaters who charge
the same price for better or worse seats, thereby providing the differential
free of charge, place some valued properties in the public domain. Pa
trons capture the rights to free salt by consuming it to the point at which
its marginal value to them is zero. Restaurateurs price menu items high
enough to cover the cost of the salt; however, they still re~~9\lil)1l.. ~1l.e. ........................ .
marginal unit of salt to the public dOl"l?:~i~h ..fiip.:C:~Jhe..~romaJ;ginalcharge
~-,-:t()paJ;J:<:ms isless thantne cost ofthe margiIlall.lnit. Theaterowners forgo
the differential in value between better and worse seats, while moviegoers
capture the right to the better seats by getting to the theater early enough
topreempt the occupation of such seats by others, with the value of wait
ing time of the marginal person in the queue equal to the differenc~ in
Owners are ilot prohibited by law from exercising their rights and im
l- Rather, for some attributes they deem the returns to be less than the
rest:auranteurs would take the form of higher prices, net of the cost of
the salt, received for meals they provide, whereas the theater owners
1
... ";
wiuld b rewarded by higher revenues from ticket sales. Buyers, of
!
_ course1 "Y0u1d have to pay extra for the higher-quality seats and sepa
rately for the salt they consume. Still, they would.gain more from the
lower meal price, and their aggregate net valuation of the movie would.. '.'
still be higher. The owners, however, deem some of their rights toa ex
pensive to exercise and choose to place them in the public domain. l l
Since owners cannot capture such values without incurring even greater
costs,.their actions are not dissipating. Even while seemingly placing such
values in the public domain, owners are still able to extract some value .
.Ih the case of niove theaters, for instance, owners who seU alI seats at
the same price have the choice of either preassigning the seats or leaving
them unassigned. It is assumed that they choose the method that yields
the higher net income, thus reducing loss to capture.
Cases in which oWners place attributes in the public domain, as in the
preceding iIlustrations, are ubiquitous. Salt is just one of the many "free"
10 An additional cost is that of convincing patrons that prices will not be rased after
ter 5. Because of the cost of exercising rights, the polcy prescription tbat alI rights
should be made private and enforced by the state is inconsistent with individual max~'
92
93
.....
12Chapter 3 includes a discussion of attributes that are placed in the public domain
for each of the tenancy contracts,
.
13 Cheung (1977) provides an example of an unusual policing method. He argues
that theater owners in Hong Kong underprice the more expensive movie-theater seats
in order to get them fully occupied and that such occupancy constitutes a relatively
cheap method of policing, In other words, ownei:iipay holders of expensve seats a fee
(in the form of a lower ticket price) to perform the policing funcion.
14 A confirmation of this mplication - observing a more detailed price"structUre'
when the costs of policing fali - would also confirm that t:ansactions consst of many
attributes whose leveis vary from one specimen to another; otherwise, one price per
dass of transactions would suffice.
'
Economic analysis
of property rights
The formation
of rights
The courts participat~ in rights ~elineation in two ways. The first is indi
.rect: When the parties choosetosettletheirdisptes without resoitirigto
the co'Urts. their actions are influenced by their perceptions'ofhow the
courts would have acted in their dispute. The second is direct: The dis. putes aFe actually.settled by. the courts. The balance of this section con
siders the second componentof rights delineation.
In countries ogerating- at least in p'art under common law, such as the
United States and England, common-Iaw court rulings serve as prece
dents for new rulings. The courts serve to resolve disputes. When private
disputes end in common-Iaw courts, the resolution of the particular dis
putes contributes to the production of a public good, namely, the delinea
tion. of rights in situations similar to the one litigated. Since court rulings
become precedents for similar' cases, litigants are resolving others' dis
putes. 16
Private contrators play several indirect but crucial roles that comple
ment those of the comt. One role relates to the gains that result from
anticipating and avoiding disputes. Because disputes and litigation are
costly, contractors gain if their contracts, ,anticipate potential trouble
spots and provide for them. When such contracts do nevertheless reach
the courts, court rulings are likely to delineate rights dearly beca use they
are dealing with careful1y crafted contracts. This effect is enhanced by
. ,[Qon;:esoof..sele.ctivity"which,partial1ydetermineo,w:hichdisputes.will.be.liti
COMMON PROPERTY
I have stated that econonllsts tend to classify ownership status into all
or-nothing categories, the latter. being termed "common property"
property that has no restrictions placed on its use. The term originated
in the English vllagers' practice of using certain areas for, among other
things, collectively grazing theiranimaIs and cutting .firew.o.od.Thecucc.
rent meaning of "common property" certainly does not fit the English
villagers' actuaI practice, as shown by Dahl~an (1980).18 Dahlman's de
scription makes it clear that the village cOmmOIl. was open only to the
villagers, not to outsiders, and that the villagers' own rights were stinted.
They couId neither add livestock to the herd nor cut whatever amount of
wood they wanted.. On the contrary, they were allowed to place in th .
17Landes (1971) was apparently the first to argue that disputes result from errors
o excess optimism. Priest (1980) applied the notion to the decision to litigate, and
Priest and Klein (1984) conclusively demonstrated the effect empirically.
18See also Ostrom 1990.
16Private rights are constrained by both common and statutory law. I shall not
discuss the forces that affect statutory law, since that would require an analysis of
legislative behavior beyond the scope oi the present work.
98
99
gated. Focusing on the case where parties litigate for direct (mostly fi
nanciaI) gains ooly, disputants go to court only if they are optimistic
about the outcome. 17 Indeed, between them they must err in the direction
of excessive optimism. A court ruling that is expected to be too ambigu
ous to truIy settIe a dispute deters the parties fcom litigating. Only if
disputants expect a ruling that will dearly delineate rights, thus incurring
few added future delineation costs~ will they litiga te. Among alI- potential
litigants in a given class of disputes, self-seIection will bring out the actual
..... i.........
~t!g':lJ.:l~~ :v.v:~(;)O ~~Pt!~t.::~:rt:II!~K:t.~;;t~'\I\lmS~/j\a,r.Iy: 4:e.~in.:~t,~:J:~gl1ts. . ~llt . h.(l.<i.
. previously been in dispute.
-~_.~.~~._"""'-'!
cause of the costliness of pricing and policing, market prices are subject
then, that the value of roads will increase if they are made private.
(see Dam 1965). The provisions 'of the convention divided among the
countries bordering the North Sea 21 some of the commonly heId att~i
butes of that sea, particularly those related to minerais. Two factors had
been working to enhance the value of the North Sea in the years preced
ing the agreement. First, underwater drilling, which was becoming more
that the region contained natural gas and crude oil reserves. 22 The coun
tended their territorial rights toward the middle of the sea. Oil compa
nies, however, were not going to invest resources in searching for oil
20Lueck (I989) demonstrates that state action regarding wildlife is consistent with
21 Belgium, Denrnark, France, the Netherlands, Norway, the United Kingdom, and
......West.Ger.many.......
'c.. : .... , .. , ......
22For example, gas was discovered in the NetherIands and beneath the North Sea
IOO
rOI
capital asset is rented, the unit cost of measuring the reduction in the
value of the asset declines as the rental period gets longer, since these
costs are independent of the length of the rental perodo Determining how
productive the asset is requires only one measurement of the output; de
termining how intensely it has been utilized requires just a pair of mea
surements - one at the beginning and one at the end of the rental period.
The availability of such scale economies, with regard to both a transac
tion's size and its duration, reduces the costs of rghts delineation and,
therefore, the loss othe.rwise :.ssoc;iated with' placing attributes in the
public domain. ....
.
An ntirelydiffe~ent'methodof lowering the.costs associated with plac
ing attributes in the public domain is to induce the parties to act as if the
attributes were owned even if they are not:When supermarket shoppers
are allowed to choose items such as apples, they are in a position to
capture the value'of the. befier apples, which are sold at the same price as
the inferior apples. Sellers .ke deliber,ilte action to make the displayed
apples appear uniform. Indeed, were all buyers to choose iahdomly from
the available selec60n (and given competition amng sellers), the cost to
consumers of apples of a given average quality net of.tle expense of
chuosing would be less than it is when consumers actually do .p"ickand
choose. 23
.
Here are three predictions that relate to delineation: (I) As rental
length increases, the falI in the rental fee ..will exceed th.e:decline.in .uni.t ..
cost, owing to the sheer cost of finding additional customers; (2) th more'
costly the measurement of the asset, the greater the price decline wiEh
duration'of rental and the fewer the rentals relative to sales; and (3) the
more diverse the product offered for sale, the more prepackaging will
occur, and, in addition, the sellers who are more reputable will more
commonly engage in prepackaging.
One reason attributes are placed in the public domain is that it is toa
pected to seek ways to curb sueh costs. One such method is to exploit
surements.
single manufacturing batch or from a given field than when they are ob
CONCLUSION
By their own actions, individuaIs are able to control and to affett the
delineation of their rights over "their" property. IndividuaIs wilI exercise
such control as part of their maximizing processo Whenever individuais
find the existing level of:delineation to be unsatisfactory, they will alter it
until they are satisfied. In the same sense that individuaIs are always in
equilibrium with r:egard to their asset holdings, they are ais o in equilib
rium with regard to their. rights over their assets. At any given moment,
..... theiLghts..r.e..~.Q.PJ:ei~.~lY.9.~.6.~.d..rha.r..~hey....gQr .:w.:i~h.r. l:t:,tI,lg~.J4~m,.
Economic conditions;' however, are constantly changing, and with
23
...................I.'?3. ...
I02
il
t(.;:):,':-:' ::':~~..'.:'::~-. ~~~ ~:<\i~:iJ:::;'~!;~:~:~:::..;'~;
. :: ~.,;
,H::~::i~~;;:'.~'; .:,
"1
THESTAVE CONTRACT
I05
-!i
Slavery
who bid the shortest number of years of service and bought the loan
conttact from its previous holder - often the captain of the passage ship.
The servant worked out his or her debt to the final lender, usually an
American farmer.
deed,.3. relati<?nship.from wh~~h both parties expect to gain. The term fits
. It Is der.that
persons',having be fored intoslavery, did notex
pect to gain 'from their change in status. Therefore, if theterm is appro
. priate at all to forced sfavery, it applies only to the period of time after
which the persons had already become slaves. Even then, such usage
stretches the definition of "contract" to its "limito NevertheIess, it will be
seen that the notion of a slave contract is useful in analyzing the institu
tion' of slavery.
.
free
is
S/da'
en
~k
oI
"\:
,m
Hours of leisure/day
Mil
3The supply of labor also depends on the intensity of work, which is usually viewed
as.given- !;lu'!; is actually a choice variable. I abstract from it here; for a more elaborate
analysis, see Barzel 1977.
I06
I07
Slavery
convince their future employers that they were more productive than they
actually were; since it was dif:ficult to ascertain their true productiveness,
their wages would consequently be bigher. Slaves, on the other hand,
would have done best to convince their owners that they were no good,
since little would then have been expected of them. s Slave owners, then,
had to spend resources to figure out how productive the slaves were and
how hard they could be driven, as w.ell as to actually supervise their ef
forts or oUtput..
. AssUriting lhat the supervision of effort is subject to diminishing mar
'ginal p(Qducclvty, intheir supenrision effQrt owners would have stopped
:short'!extracting the m,aximum output of whichslaves were capable.6
The difference between slaves' maximum output and their actual output
became the slaves' property in practice. As a rule, it carne not in the same
form as the product they produced for their owners, but, rather, in the
forrIi of reduced effort. Still, sIaves were able to convert some of this
, poteritial into m~terial goods.
Owners had -to choose between s"upervising their slaves' output, which
is cmparable to what employers have to d when the'free workers they
employ work by the piece, and sup.ervising their effort, which is compara
ble to what e!Ilployers must do when thyemployfree woiker's by the
hour. The latter re-quired continuous supervision, for whenever slaves
were not watched they had little incentive to perform. The former re
quired ovrseeing 9utput as. to .i!~i"quantiry, gUl!1iey, and, indirectly, its
effect on -bther productive inputS such as equipmenr. The supervision of
slaves' output also required'-utput quotas; left to their own devices,
slaves would have produced as little as they coufd. Moreover, quotas
could not have been set by simply observing past performance, since
slaves' incentive to produce little during the demonstration period would
have been strong indeed. Quotas were subject to error; toa high a quota
would have resulted in the destruction of slaves. Owners selected the
quota that would 'maximize their own -wealth and were expected to en
force the production of that quota but ,no more. This means that owners
left their slaves with the difference between the quota and the maximum
they could produce, a difference slaves could exploit. Given the two
methods of extracting output, owners could offer supervised sIaves the
option to work under the quota method, setting the quota to exceed the
supervised output. With this as an option, some slaves would have cho
Since slaves were the full-fledged legal property of their owners, ali the
::',:::::::::lnC'i5me:they:::cu:ld::generate.waslegally their.owners'. as welLqwners .
. who took anything from .their slaves vvere. simply taktig somethIig that,
was legally theirs to start with. Owners had the legal rght to take; they
also had the might. How, then, could slaves accumulate wealth, some
times to an extent that enabled them to purchase their own contracts?
Had both slaves' capabilities and the net output they produced been cost
lessly measurable, wealth-maxmizing slave owners would indeed have
extracted every last ounce of productveness from their slaves. Under
these conditions, which would have permitted owners to assume owner
shp in the most complete sense of the word, it is ironic that sIave status
itself would have been inconsequential. Had policing been costless, the
owner could have obtained the same income whle allowing tlie slave to
'operate asa.'free person; for instance, he could have done this by recev
ing an explicit'payment of the same value as that generated by the slave's
services withot requiring slave status. The free person, however, would
still have had to work exactly as a slave would in order to be able to
make his payment, or as a debtor would to pay off his or her debt. 4 This
is consistent with the Coase Theorem, which states that when rights are
clearly delineated - as they are here - resource allocation is independent
of the ownership pattem. In reality, the evaluaton of inputs and outputs
is costly, and policing is requred to induce effort. As we shall see, accu
mulation by slaves is thus possible.
When the net output of a free worker can be determined at low cost,
it is advantageous for him to operate independently, since this eliminates
the problem of incentive"Suchwasnotthecase'with'slaves; the labor
services slaves could provide be10nged to ther owners. Even when output
was easily measured, slaves would have gained from producing less and
thus hadto be induced to produce more. The distinction between sIaves'
and free workers' incentives became even more acute for tasks that free
workers performed by the hour. Fxee.workers would do best if they could
, 5,slaves had to be careful not to do toa good a job of deceiving their owners, snce
owners who
their slaves were nor worth their cost would have found rhem
4Had ali rights been well defined, which requires costless transacting,...not.. only,.......
would slave status have been rendered devoid of significance but forced slavery would
never have arisen in the first place, since one person would never have captured the
rights of others.
"::expeiliib'le;'"
.. .... .
6This statement applies to the average slave. SIaves who were mistakenly asked to
:il>. ITIore than they were capable of doing were in serious trouble, compared with
other'slaves, to the extent that they sometimes died of exhaustion,
Io8
r09
>I
Slavery
".
to
The legal ban on both forced and voluntary slaver,y i8 now.universal; in . :'
earlier eras, various restrictions were placed on baih practices. Voluntag- .
slavery was a contractual arrangemerrt into which neither party wold'
enter if she or he did not expect to gain from it, while under forced slav
ery it was owners who gained. Eventually all states abolished slavery,
most of them voluntarily. Needless to say, slaves had littIe direct influence
on the abolition decision. Issues of theft may have been partIy responsible
for the abolition decision. Because of theft, the institution of slavery, both
voluntaryand forced, mayentail costs that hnpinge on free persons, who
might consider them excessive.
. TWQJm:msof theft are associated with the institution of slavery. Al
ready mentioned is the fact that theft was the initial step in forced slavery.
The other form of theft occurred when slaves escaped; the escape tumed
what were to their owners valuabl~ assets into assets deprived of some
or all of their value. The loss that owners incurred due to abolition must
be weighed against the policing costs associated with theft.
Coercion of free people into becoming slaves has large1y been a conse
quence f raids.nd .. Qf.full~.fledge.d ...wars."among...nations..For..centuries.
West Africa was subject to raids alid ",s i:hemain source of slaves for
the American South, the Caribbeari,a.nq.- S9qth America. Since losers of
......SLAVES' CONSUMPTION
The sharp disparity between interests of the owners and those of slaves
was not confined to slaves' effort and its supervision; it also affected con
sumption practices. Owners could not drive their slaves hard unIess they
made sure that they were properly maintained - that the nutrition, medi
cai care, and other services si aves received werecommensurate with the
effort required of them. Correspondingly, as Fogel andEngetmanCI9?2:) '.
have shown, in the United States slaves received what by nineteenth
century standards appears to have been good medicaI care and a nutri
tious diet. 7 Owners, however, had little incentive to let their slaves con
sume food other than that induded in the least-cost diet, or to let them
consume other servjc~s beyond the lowest-cost ones required for mainte
nance. Slaves,Qn the other hand, were not necessarily harmed when their
7Fogel and Engerman, however, do not interpret their findings on nutrition the
way I do, nor do theY'systematically apply transaction cost notions to the analysis of
slavery.
IIO
.;.
1i;,; :
~~1 ,";~{i.~::m~,!trra(:'H~:,!::\S!:;~'~:!:'; i~;"~. ~~? . ~'~~.~.~ ~:;;: ~~,:.;-? :,~~,~~: -~: -;);.}.;? <::.~)
Slavery
wars and raids were not the winners' counnymen, one would not expect
states to outlaw that source of slavery. However, raids in which free per
sons are captured and turned into slaves against their will can also occur
within a country. Free persons will take steps privately to protect them
selves against enslavement; they will also use the state to enhance their
rights. The most obvious use of the state machinery is to make enslave
ment of one's countrymen a crime. A more extreme step is to prohibit
slaveryaltogether. 8 Enslaved persons would have found it exceedingly
.. difficult.todemonstrate that they were forced into slavery in a society
'tht p~ITJ:tted slavery. The returns !rom suchtheft, then, are higher
where shlvery is perm:i~tedthanthey re where slavety is prohibited'X:on::'
versely; the threat to free persons of being turned into slaves is relatively
low in countries that prohibit slavery,9 The fear free people have of being
turned into slaves may partially explain the ban on slavery?O
A different kind of cost arises in the case of escaping slaves. It seems
to be generally true that certain costs of protecting property from theft
. are assumed by the.state. In Chapter 8; I suggest as a general proposition
that activitk:s will be banned if the police protection they require is very
costly. If, as compared with the private value of slavery to slave owners,
the cost to the polce of rec()v(!r.illge!)~aped slaves was excessiy.~,J,hlVery
. would be bnned~'
....
The higher the dange.r to a country's residen'ts 'ofbdiiii'forcedhito
slavery, and the higher the cost of.recovering escaped slaves, the more
liklyt is th~t slavei:y will.be prohibjted. For a long time in the American
Soutb, being a slave and being black were almost synonymous. l l Free
people: nearlYa.Jl of thm white,-did not have to fear becoming enslaved,
and escaped slaves could readily be identified and captured. As the popu
lation of free blacks grew, however, the distinction between a free persoii
and a slave became more difficult to establish. 12 Consequently the costs
of slavery increased, and the net gain from the institution declined. 13 If
slavery were legalized in our own society, the distinction between free
people and slaves would be more difficult to establish and the problems
of the forced enslavement of free people and of capturing escaped slaves
would become even more acute than they were in the Old South. It is not
surprising, then, that in many societies slavery was severely restricted and
that it is now universally prohibited.
.
The demise of indentured servi rude may have been due to forces simi
lar .W .~hQ~(!.t.httt..te.4..tg.m"'..c!..e.J..11.i~e..(J..f.~h'!.ye..l:Y.~ ..At.Jt.~.~f.l.::e.p~jf.l,-.!p.e popula
8Consistent with this view is the observation that raids to acquire si aves dedined
after the colonization of Africa. Enhancement of property rights within colonies in
creased the colonies' value to<the colonizers.
9 Isolated cases of slavery are nevertheless reported in the press.
.
10 According to' Jewish law, Jews were allowed to keep other Jews as slaves. The
law required, however, that ali Jewish slaves be freed by the onset of every Sabbatical
year."lf during a Sabbatical year one spotted a Jewish slave, it was c1ear it was iIIegal.
This constraint on slavery reduced the gain frommegally enslaving other Jewish indi
viduais, and it is consistent with the hypothesis presented in this study.
11 The identification of sIaves with a particular people is the apparent source of the
term "slave." To the Slavs the term "Slav" apparently meant "person." Most of the
Slavs present in andent Rome were slves, and the Romans used the term meant for
.Q.t:Ie.to.identifyHthe..other... HH ....................................H................H.... :....::..:.. :.. H.. HH H........ .
tin:ift.A:ffierka WaS'sparS';"aiid'sefvahts;'tlest'ffiif'GfmanY;'Were
easify distinguished from "free people. Ovei time, the population grew'
and diversified,making escape easier and perhaps also making the en
slavement of free people easier, thus lowering the net benefit of the insti
tution to the originally free population.
By the end of the nineteenth century, slavery had largely been abol
ished, perhaps because the costs of policing the institution exceeded its
rewards. 14 The current prohibition of slavery implies that each individual
is the owner of the capital asset embedded in himself or herself. The
abolition of slavery was accompanied by the transfer of such capital
assets from the previous slave owners to the'slaves themselves. The prohi
....... bition .orslavery .also. entails .additional.r.estrictions.on contracting: Essen
tialIy, when workers contract for the supply of their own labor services,
only short-term contracts aJ;"e legally enforceable. These additional re
strictions may also reflect the attempt to make the theft of people more
costly.
CONCLUSION
Even though forced slaves seem to have been stripped of any rights, in
practice ownership over them was not complete. Owners had to spend
resources on supervising the work effort and consumption pattern of
their slaves and on preventing their escape. Such efforts were subject to
increasing costs, and attempts to economize on these costs included
granting slaves various rights. In some cases slaves' 'output'ratherthan .
their effort was supervised. The attempt to lower the cost of supervision
then included granting slaves the right to part of the output or of their
own time. These slaves, though legally ther masters' property, were able
to accumulate wealth and occasionalIy to buy their own contracts.
13 Some slaves woo .were, in fact, freed by their owners chose to reta in the legat
status of slave, presumably to retain the owners' protection and to reduce the chance
of being forced back into sIavery.
14The insttution resurfaced under a new guise in the nineteenth century, with the
importaton of hinese workers, a newly distinct set of people, for railroad construc
tion. Like its predecessor, it did not last longo
II3
Wealth-maximizing constraints
on prQper.ty, rights
",
" , '
-o
''I T
4..........
RESTRICTIONS ON OWNERS
-..,
3The manufacturers retain ownership of income streams that have only zero or
nega tive values. They are the residual c1aimants, i.e., responsible for those nega tive
income streams. Payments to the manufacturers for these potential services come
ahead of time, when the original transactions are concluded.
'being"stolen;ownership':ls.neverentirely"secure~'Thefrcan,take'many"
II6
II7
Two distinct legal doctrines govem the use of water in the United States.
In the eastem states, the prevailing system, originating in English com
mon law, is riparian, permitting landowners reasonable use of water
from rivers that run by their properties. Water is relativ.ely abundant in
that region (as it is in England), and so naturally the rights to it are rather
loosely defined. 6 In contrast, many of the western states are arid, and the
prevailing system is appropriative, granting individuais more complete
4Lueck (X989) suggests that the state restriction on trade in game-animal products
may be explained by the attempt to reduce poachiJ:lg.
5This section relies heavily on Miller (I985).
6CRose(x99 0 ) analyzes changes within the riparian system brought about primarily
by the emergence of large-scale use of water for power for which previous rights were
not well defined.
. ....
Il:8
... ',',',
,'. :.','
'/.~.> .''':'.~.'",'
i,,' i,',
flow. 9
the water foc a specific purpose, for example, to irrigate an orchard. The
" h er-pnonty
" ' h o ldecs are alI owe d to d o. PeopIe Wlt
. h n'ghts to Wlt
. h
the h 19
draw watec from a stream who are restricted to a specific use have rights
that are delineated moce narrowly, and are consequently less valuable,
.than tli~y 'Wlli~d be"in the absence of the restrction. As a result of the
iest:riction; ht;wever, the rights ()f thosepeoplewith Iower .prioritiesand
the rights !;ti the two groups c;ombined are more:deady delineated. In
.other words, whereas the rights of people with high priorities are attenu
ated, the rights of those with lower priorities are thereby enhanced. The
more dearly rights in general are delineated, the more they are valued,
since If;SS is expected to be spent on their capture.
Two obsrved practjces lend support to the hypothesis that the state
imposed restriction on water use is intended to ncrease the value of wa
tet.rights. ::rbe first regards the inter-organization transfer ofwater. Mu
tual ditch companies and irrigation districts are permitted to use water
in a way that seems to evade the regulation of wtertransfer:Thesetga
nizations of neighbors are pennitted to combine the water rights of their .
members. The restriction on transfers within each organization is
.avoided, enabling mem~rs. toimproy~_the aliQcation. of water among
themselves. Provided that ihe pattem f water se is nt ltered, the re
tum- quantity (and quality). of the--~ater is likewise- n~t altered. The
greater flexibility available to these organizations, then, does not signifi
cantly impinge on the rights of others. Aliowing water transfer within
ditchcompanies and withn irrigation districts is therefore consistent
with the explanation that the purpose of the more general constraint on
transfers is to enhance tJ:te clear delineation of rights.
The se~ond practice concems the distinct Jorm' of the constraint on
wate,.. use that is applied in Ne~ Mexico. 11.1. tnat state waterrightli are
defined in terms of consumption, that is, the ne!" amountof water re
tained by the owner. Among the western states, New Mexico is one of
the most arid, and it consequently values its water highly; so it is not
surprisipg that it finds the costs of the added measurement that cqnsump
Before I776, allland in the colonial United States had been initially de
clared to be the property of the British crown. Bridsh authorities em
ployed vacious methods ..o.disp.ensing.Jand,...including."granting ..lt ...to...........
. s tatesftradini :companle~;aiid i.ndlvi.dua1SwhoCiossedthAtlaiidc~'The" . . ..
tiansfet of power in I776 was accompanied bya change in the land
release policy. The federal govemment of the United States adopted a
more unified policy of managing its land holdings, one element of which
was to discourage "preempton" - the priority right of the illegal settlers,
or squatters, to buy the land OR which they had settled.
Until the Louisiana Purchase in I803, most U.S. government-owned
land was in the thirteen original states, and market sales of govemment
land were routine. During the nineteenth century the U.S. government
took possession of vast amounts of land in the West. Abundant as the
la:nd"was, the govemment made a concerted effort to prevent its becom
ingcommonproperty. Asthepopulation grew;thegovernmentcontinued
to sellland in some areas. In others the govemment periodically released
for settlement blocks of land that were not handled in a conventional .
commercial fashion. The govemment could have auctioned off these par
cels of land or set a price, or a price structure, at which to sell whatever
acreage buyernvanted to purchase. Instead, passing various acts, the best
known of_ which is the Homestead Act of I862, the government either
set a price substantially below the market price or charged no price at
ali. At the same time it imposed severe constraints that those claiming
land had to satisfy before they could gain the right to seU the land.
A possible explanation for these govemment restrictons is that they
were imposed in order to induce settlers' self-protection against raids
where such protecton was cheaper than direct pr.otection by the state._
Had all unsettled land been placed in the public domain or made avail
able for sale, so that anyone could have settled in any unoccupied area,
the cost to the state of protecting settlers would have been high. Such
could have exceecleef the
costs, particularly in isolated or hostile areas,
.
net value of the newly settled areas to thelr owners. On the other hand,
'9B'
.
h
I
f
h' .
f
ecause It IS eaSIer to measure t e vo ume o water r an It IS to measure some o
its.other attributes, it is relatively easy to see that a reduction by one owner of the
10]ohnson, Gisser, and Werner (I9 8I ) di~uss water rights in New Mexico in a
amo.unt of.~at~r returned to th~ stteam will not reduce the amount of water avaiJable
t?):li,~r::p..rl?rBltY,{)~~<;:S ..~~~.l1:.f"t~e.!_~r.eI~.()r:;.atfe~far:t~er.d.?:~I::lS!r,el'I~I:n.-. td!J.~r.>:t.llae)()~~f~$imilar vein. In a study of water rights in four western states, Gsser (I 995) elabo~ates
prlonty.u~rs .. ut a reuuCUon In tue qua Ity o returne water Wl . ten. t? re ur:;e ~ne
on the analysis I offer here. He demonstrates a strong trend toward a c1earer dehnea
~~~er quahty. av.a~lable to .al! those downstream, regardless ~f thelr pnontJ:. Thls.lmton of rights to water in New Mexico 'and a fitful trend in Arizona, California, and
phe!> tba~,. prlOntles remammg constant, the value of the nght to water in a glven
'Ti
s
stniam is likely to decline the farther downstream it is.
exa "
I20
I2I
such cost dediried as the density of settlers in the area increased. Simi
larly, these costs dedined if the new area abutted previously settled areas.
Whereas the governrnent routinely seemed to take upon itseff the pro
tection of its people and their property, the govemment as the owner of
the land could relatively easily withhold protection from areas it chose
protect such people. Because the govemment w~s tli oWrie.rf the land,:
posed by the 1862 act, are consistent with.the hypothesis that their func
tions were most likely to contest settlemeni by whites; not in areas where
such a threat was absent. A central feature of homesteading was for the
a family and to restrct each settler to one such unit. 12 A less obvious but
equally important feature was the attempt to ensure that the land would
actually be densely occupied. This may help explain not only tbeJow
pecuniary price (zero in I862) of the land13 but also the'federal govem
land became so valuable that a large fraction of the units open for home
l11n the first edition of this book I considered only self-protection. The more general
121n later acts applying to the more arid land farther west, the unit was increased
W'up'Uf6"4<:)"'actes;'
13Settlers, however, could preempt the land for $I.2.5 per acre after six months'
residence.
4
1 This argument paralIels Cheung's (I977) regarding:the phenomenon of owners
"underpricing" the better movie theater seats in order to get those seats fully (or
IS Ali homesteads in each newly opened area were 'released by the government under
diii same set of constraints even though they were not llequally valued. Allocation
~:r~~~;v:~uc~~:~~:tb~~: h:riI~Ftei;rl~<:6id:;f~~~r~littis~fii~~'~:k'th~;:d'!th;........
gun; henc the term "Sooner, Conversely, the.l,?west-value homesteads remained
undaimed. The Graduation Act of r854 provided for progressive price reductions for
such unclaimed land.
.
this section 19 are strctly those between private parties. In I984 - and
firm (seemingly Cars and Concepts, Inc.) to turn its automobiles into
auto bodies from Chrysler and then performed the conversion. By pur
chasing the auto bodies, the conversion firm presumably became the
strained, First, the contract between the two firms stipulated that only
16The size of the individual holding and the consolidation of holdings presented
particularly acute problems where the land was used for grazing, which requires large
blocks of land.
17 Allen (I99 I ) elaborates on the hypothesis that the purpose of the Homestead Act
was to reduce the cost of protection by government. He ingeniously exploits differ
fcom the 1860s to the I930S to test the hypothess, which his results conclusively
support.
I 2
....................
"'crea:rd:'a'separ'ate':departmen:t:or:divislon::to"ma~e::convern6fes;In1:hat
12 4
ping the parts or continuing to store them and to make them available
to Paccar.
4. For parts Paccar ordered back from Sajac, Paccar would pay 90 per
2.
since the InternaI Revenue Servce (IRS) had stipulated a few years earlier
that firms such as Paccar could not write off the cost of parts they did
not actually sell. By selling the parts to Saiac at just a fraction of the
accounting cost of these parts, Paccar was able to write these parts off.
to Sajac, claiming that the transactiQn did not constitut a sale because a
the list ensured that Paccar would remain the true owner of the parts.
Granted that the tax' incentive induced the arrangement at least in part,
The view that commodities are made up of many attributes and that it .
is sometimes advantageous not to have a single persbn orasingle Hrm.
own all of them suggests that there is no definitive answer to the IR..S
challenge.21 Paccar did remain the owler of some attributes of'the pa'itS;
but Sajac became the owner of others, namely, the storage attributes.
Sajac's gains came primarily from lowering the costs of storage and from
selling the parts back to Paccar, Sajac apparently made efforts in both
respects: It maintained facilities for low-cost, long-term storage, and it
devoted resources - essentially making sales pitches t0 bring to the'
attention of Paccar's replacement-parts division the availability of vari
ous parts it was storing even though it appeared that Paccar continued
tObwntheparts.
It seems that Paccar's main objectives in restricting Sajac to selling the
parts back were to maintain its own reputation and to prevent Sajac from
taking a ride on the Paccar brand nam by selling truck drivers low
quality parts bearing Paccar's name: Paccar could have protected its
brand name by storing the parts direct1y.or by renting space from Sajac
in whichto store the parts, thereby retaining control of their quality. In
neither case wouMtheincentivesfor'e:ffici~t"$torage hllvebeenasstrong....
21The court, however, ruled for the IRS.
12 5
as they were in the actuaI case, where the reward, on the margin, be
longed entirely to the fum in charge of the storage.
than one person is a major source of side effects b~ause the own~r of a
subset of a commodity's attributes can relatively easlly consume wIthOUt
charge some of the attributes belonging to oth~rs. It i~ toa expell;sive,
Vertical relationships
however, to price and police alI the effects assocIated wIth transactl0ns.
.
One method of reducing the costs of the attempted capture by some peoThe relationships betwe~n Paccar and .the storage finn and betw~en
pIe of others' rights is to impose constraints on the for~er: One farmer
Chrysle: and .the converSlon firm shed hght on the problem of ve~cal
might be able to capture another farmer's water by sWltchmg t~ a ~rop
integratlOn. Llke other firms, both Paccar and ChrysIer are onIy parnally .
that returns Iess of the withdrawn water to the stream. The Iatter s nghts
vertically integrated. In our daily lives""e.ar.~,~c:>~~<:l:~c:>::o~se.J::Yi~g:,~,igl:1I;)!:::::::""::Cn:b'e"pr6teCted:;:hwever."bynot allowing the former to use water to
.integrated !J:ms22 that wefail,tQ'Qskwhy every individu.al do~snot. operirrigate ne~ crops. Such resttictions serve to ma~e rights clearer, thereby
ate as an mdependent one-person fum. The precedmg dIscusslOn of
enhancing them even though they may superficIally appear to attenuate
therelationship betweeI). me two pairs of firms points to some of the
them.
.
As the costs associated with a restriction rise, new methods of pro
' gains resulting from operating independently. When people assume ownership, they also assume responsiblity for their own behavior. On the
tecting rights are expected to emerge. When the value of a new crop or
other hand, when people work as others' employees, or when other proof the water itself increases, I expect that protection of the rights of
duction factors are rented out, .shirking is to be expecte~. When two indelower-priority owners of water rights will be enhanced th~ough the use
pendent fums perform operatl0ns that would otherWlse have been perof a more expensive and more accurate method of measurmg the water
formed within a single firm, however, a market exchange is required. As
used by high-priority owners. The more accurate metering of the actual
I previously argued, any exchange consumes resources, and effecting fuU
use of the water itself should permit the relaxation of indirect constraints
'alienation is often expensive:'Correspondingly, most exchanges involve
on the use of water such as the choice of which crops to grow, and
only subsets ofthe'attributes'ofthegoodsinvolved;In'the'caseofthe'
"'i:he'gr~~t:i~g"to own;rs ofwater rights greater freedom in trading those
truck~parts storage, Sajac, which bo~ght.the p~rts, seems to have operrights.
.
. .
ated mdependently of Paccar, but ItS operatlOns were severely conThe restrictions on water use and the restrlctlOns on homesteaders
strained. Nevertheless, these operations were much less constrained than
have been government-imposed. The framework in which they were dis
cussed is the same as the framework for the private restrictions Chrysler
they would have been had they been carried out within Paccar. Sajac was
more of a residual claimant to the stO'ge operations th~n a ~acca: diviand Paccar imposed on their exchange partners. In e~c~ ?f t?es~ ~ases I
sion would have been. PresumabLy the costs of .the partlal'ali~natl0n of
assume that every decision is ultimately made by maXImlzmg mdlv~duals.
the parts first from Paccar and then back to It - were relatlvely low;
In none of the cases are marginal costs expected to be equated wIth the
theref~re Sajac, the s~orage firm, assu~ed responsibility for the s~orage
corresponding marginal valuations. In each case, however, f?rces. indl:
ope(atlon. The costhness of tra~sfernn~ other spare-f.>arts attnbutes
ing toward such equalization are assumed to be present. ThlS pomt wlII
seems to be the reason Paccar restncted SaJac to return of the parts rather
be elaborated on briefly in the next chapter.
than,aII.ow:ing it to dispense them without constraint.23
CONCLUSION
22 A supermarket, for instance, is a firm that seUs a huge array ofpfoducts and
whose emplQyee:s perform ,a wide variety of vertical (as weU as horizontal) operations.
"""23The"amblgti'igdng wnO the true owner of the parts was, and consequently
the nature of Paccar's scope of operations, ilIustrates Cheung's (19,8,3) observation
conceming tne difficulty of determining what a firm actually is, and points to the
advantage of concentrating on contracts.
I26
': ,,;'
~,;,.~:,
;':'. ,~:,:i~~B;;~~',X.;'y,,",
""~,,,
..\,'
",~;.;
<'. :"/
;'~T
:.
>'
:'
','~,'
a non-market economy.
ALLOCATION BY VOTING
viduais who use markets retain controI of how they use their wealth,
demonstrate that they value some of these constraints even though they
Voting is used not only in the public sector but also in many profit
seeking settings, including shafeholder corporations (mostly to elect of
ficers) and in condominiums (to make an array of'01'el'ating decisions).
The origins of organizations such as corporations and condominiums, in
which voting is used, lie in the operations of entrepreneurs. In the case of
cortdominiums, for example, developers typically erect the housing units
and related structures and complete other prepanltory work before sell
, ingthe units to individual buyers. Developers do not have to seU housing
units as condominiums. Another option, one that maintains the owner
occupier tax advantage, is to seU the units to individual buyers, who op
erate independendy of one another. It is presumed that developers will
generally choose the method of sale that promises the largest difference
between the aggregate selling price of their units and the costs they incur.
In fact, condominium developers are offering buyers packages that
consst of both the physical structures and the rules that-will govern some
....aspectsc,ofthe.prospl'!ctive owners' future behavior - rules that include
1 As Wing Suen ponted out to me, the irony is compounded
the championing of
the use of prces in socialist systems by such eminent economists as Lerner and Lange.
12 9
to
4The fact that transacting is costly and needs facilitating suggests that cash is not
as neutral as it is often thought to be. If, for example, blood sellers were paid in non
transferable tuition vouchers, it seeInshigl1lyl*~Iy..~h.-at...tll.e!r.a.c.ti()l1,?finfected addicts
"""amongsellers"woilloeS'malIertlin 'ir was with cash as the means of payrr/ent.
5Kessel identified various methods of screening out individuais who are Iikely to be
carriers. These methods, however, are costly. Sellers of blood were generally not
screened, whch implies that the cost of screening must have been toa high.
I3 I
C&:,~.':;";~'"_'=~"~.:'L>.";z{So2l~:t:,::~~:;~~L~.,;c;,,;B~i:,~~i:;.:2;;:~:~~;:;~~~~~~~~~~:ifi~;~l:i8E!~~
know or suspect that they are carriers are aware that their donation will
prises, and some government enterprises may actually seem to operate in
do harm. They are simply expected not to donate.
that way. Even when profit maximization is the stated objective of the
af course, cash markets are not used by accident; they ~co?omize on
govemment enterprise, however, the identity of the residual claimants
some of the costs of effecting exchange. The use of donors m heu of cash
remains unclear.
markets incurs costs that are absent from cash markets. For insta~e,
The difficulty of identifying such individuaIs and the common claim
volunteers are not generalIy the lowest-cost suppliers of the commodlty
that government is generally wasteful and inefficient both suggest to
or service they donate. The costs and gains of using markets as compare~
many that private-property rights are absent from government opera
with other allocation methods, such as charity, differ across commodltions. Indeed, former communist countries claim to have abolished.
ties. Given the difficulty of testing for the presence ofhepati~is and the .
. private-property rights, at least with regard to the mean~ '?f l":rduction:~ .
HN virusthatcauses.:AIDS:,;:blaod:is:.:one:commodityJor:whl'Ch::the::ad.:.:::::::::::::..lshal1rgue that private propertjr rights must exist m'a functioni+ig econ
vntagesf non-market over market allocation are evident. .
omy? I shall also argue 'that the notion that govemment is .inefficient
The cash-market sellers' ability tpgain by knowingly passmg off lowcannot be correct. After some general comments on.individual maximiza
quality specimens as high in quality .is common to many co~odities
tion, I shall try to determine what can be inferred from the sheer existence
besides blood. Nevertheless, charity is not expected to be used m all such
of a government-run enterprise, using a city bus syst~m as the example. I
shall then consider the meaning of an arbitrary detail of its operations _
cases. The precise nature of the quality problem is likely to differ from
one commodity to another; and each should generate its own charitable
the activities of bus drivers - and move on to more general aspects of the _
response. Mechanisms other than charity may be more effective in securoperation of such a system. I shall not inquire directly into what the
ing the desired quality for some of these commodities.
proper areas for government activity are; rather, I am using a propertyAlthough a donor's motive for c~oosing o~e .charity over ~nother
rights approach to offer a glimpse into the way a gov~rnment.fun~tions.
seems to be a matter of taste, one slmple pre.dlctlOn c~n be d~r~ved: .lt
The assumption of individual maxirp.ization is heavdy e~lOlted m ~cQseems reasonable to assume that, like other actlOns, charlta~.leJpv1Il&.wtll
nomics literature that features an analysis of profit-seeking enterpnses
expariWherithe'gairistgeiieiatesbeco~e'rigei:6 On. the issue .of
and private consumption. I wish to examine the implications of individ
blood, it is predicted that in the span of time after the dlscovery that
ual maximization for government operations. Because government.s are
'.
blood could be infected with the HIV virus but before effective tests for
run by people, government activity ultimately results from the interac
it were devised, the amount of blood donated relative to that sold for
tions of maximizing individuais. Contrary to the implied assertion by
ALLOCATION BY GOVERNMENT
from which no one else gains, such an occurrence is inconsistent with
maximizing. Whoever takes any kind of action must expect to gain from
The government of every country plays an important role in economic
it; indeed, the perceived net gain must always be the largest one available.
activity, and some governmertts' roles are enormous. Ali governments
An action that appears to others to have been wastefu! must, neverthe
engage in non-business activities, such as conducting foreign affairs and
less,
have been e:xpt:(;tedt()gellerate a gain to the person who underto~k
operating the courts, and virtually alI also engag~, to varying degrees, in
Ti:. Moreovr~sch a person must not have believed he or she could gam
more businesslike activities, often conducting operations that in some
more by acting differently. The resources under consideratiQn are ulti
other countries are run privately, usually for profit. It is occasionally ar
mately alIocated to a particular use by whoever is in cOlltrol of them.
gued that governments should seek profits when they manage their enterThe logic behind the allocation is straightforward. $uch resources have
6This account does not offer an explanation as to why people give to charity, and
alternative uses, each with its own valuation. The ability of potential
<
it does not attempt to predict when people wOllld give more or less. It does, however,
shed light on the social value of induc:ing sllch a mode of behavior. To make the
7In the aftermath of the breakdown of Eastern European commllnism, many of the
functionaries of these regimes who contnl:ledto-(')pe:t'ate.jn-theiTold-in~i'tu.tions-actu"
ally landed on their feet. This implies that these individuais hd sllbstni:ial economic
rghts.
signment of property rights. Here the drivers acquire the right to a wage,
constraints, however, other potential users of the resources that appear"
lower the perceived net gain from an action to the individuaIs who have
higher the potential benefits of an actiori, the more the beneficiaries are
without it. Drivers have at least some rights over themselves; they con
abl~.to~id.!()~ it; "ability," however, II1~YlJ(!difficult to translate into an
trol, that is, they own the rights to, the levei of effort, and theyexchange
ctual bid.
. .
tem must gain from forming the contracts that induce the drivers to per
ownership :}nd government activity. Because maximizing people will act
form busing services. Smilarly, the mere fact that drivers are given routes
only when they expect to gain from their actions, one must be able to
these owners also owned the rights to the terminology. Ir is ironic, ar least in rerms of....
the rhetoric, that communist states had a hard time keeping resources such as air and
rivers from getting imo the public domain (the ultimate in collective ownership!). As
a result, the value of these resources was reduced to a levei much lower than the one
they occupy in capitalist states.
I35
beca use the individual would reap the difference between the gains and
the cost. Moreover, such a service would be expanded until, on the mar
gin, the cost equaled the gain.
In a poltical system, given the way such systems usually operate, the
effect of demand forces is less direct, but it is definitely not absent. The
system of rewards in government seldom compensates individuais for the
full private gains they generate. An operator in the poltical realm unable
to claim :1:00 percent of the residual would stop short of the levei of
service a private operator would reach. Although the same forces that
bridge gaps created by price contro~~..t.e.~<:f.~<>,pJ:e:yentgapsbetweenmi~::.
ginal valuations and marginal costs from growing ever larger, a full
fIedged residual claimant is less handicapped than one who has only a
partial clairn; the full-fIedged daimant will consequently produce what
appears to be a more effident outcome.
Why would an operator not be allowed to daim :IOO percent of the
residual? MQre generally, why are individuais not always allowed free
rein to become residual daimants? Prohibitions mustperform real func
tins. The superior who has constrained the operator presumably has the
power to impose constraints. 12 Returning to the example of suburban
. busser:vice:Thesuperi:or may have had.no.interest in increasing the oper
ator's wealth but could still have been able to increase his or her own
. wealth by selling the righ~t~~~~~~'th~'~~b~~b:Iii~d~rto'aiiswer"i:he '
questiono regarding the absence of a full-fIedged residual daimant, one
nrust also-ask what prevented the superior from selling the right to the
opeJ:ator or, even better, to the highest bidder. I conjecture that the an
swer lies in the fact that the seller's wealth depends.not only on the pecu
niary price but ais o on features of the buyer a?d of the exchanged pr~J2: .. _
erty.
In general, maximizers may choose not to seU an asset or a franchise
to the highest bidder. There are many reasons for this reluctance, ali of
which may be viewed as resulting from the presence of side effects. For
instance, manufacturers sometimes pay their salespeople a commission
. ora salary insi:(iiid of selling them the merchandise outright. By not grant
ing salespeople full residual-daimant status, manufacturers ensure that
11S
non-market economies a
11 d"
.
d"
. .
their incentive for capturing wealth from other salespeople is tempered.
ome,
,.
re ca e
comman
economles; a command
"
b
eC~)flomy IS ~ne In
WhlCh the planner imp?ses an.utput targetalong with the control
~n a?other case,persons w hO ~annot fu ~ Iy gu~rantee t helr
acUons m~y e
pnce. Imposmg as the term may sound, It will be obeyed only if it sets low targets.
llldllled to take unduly large nsks. The lllcentlve to undertake excesslvely
risky projects where some of the risk is borne by third parties is reduced
Because mputs are neve: uniform, and beqluse of random fluctuations, the output
ta~get asth<:mcommander
set must,
as a filie,
short
ut. Other
'f h d " k
II
d to become f u Ii -fied ge d resl'd ua I .
wIse
the case ofwIII
slave
the comma
d fali 'lI
. of Imaximum
b out.Ph'
I te. eclslon ma ers are not a owe
bl'
rvJ>
n er WI mcur osses y pUnIS mg those
I .
-
lll1:a .e to ?bey the.,,Qmm.t!d..b.e.c.a.us~jUs.:.excessiv.e...If..o.urputjs,costly:, to..measure",. , .......... , .....~.,a.I~~:?~:. ,..... ...... :,..,:.. ........ . . ; .
~hl.rklllg wlth r.egard tO,the target ou~put may :ls,? ccr. The quantity supplied, then,
One reason resldual-dalmant nghts are not granted may apply pnmar
clear the market and from allocations that simply seemed arbitrary. Gov
emment enterprises were affected by such policies in various ways. How
would the operations of the bus~system repair shop have been run under
such conditions? Presumably, from time to time the repair shop would
have been hampered by a shortage of parts. As Iong as buses were run
ning, we must condude that individuais in the repair shop were being
rewarded for getting the buses to work and that the rewards were larger
when the repair-shop services were better. Repair-shop personnel would
have gained by having parts on hand, and conseql;lently.should nave been
willing to spend resources in order.to secuie them'-They might, for in
stance, have aitempted to trade wn rhe repai,r !moI? ~f another city's bus
system or with a truck repair shop. Alternativly, they might have 'offered
a special reward to the parts producers for furnishng extra. parts. Such
producers, as is generally true under price controls, would not have been
likely to produce at full potential ~or the controlled-price segment of the
market. They might readily have been induced to expand output, how
ever, if the reward had exceeded the controI price. l l
The details of sum operations cannot be.determined by an armchair
economist, but maximizing behavior implies i:hat the discrepancies be
tween marginal valuation and marginal costs must generate forces to
ward their elminatidn. Indeed, as was shown in the discuss!on of price
controIs in Chapter 2, once the added adjustment of transaction costs is
accounted for, the discrepancies must be elminated entirely. This attain
ment of equilibrium simply follows from maximiztion. Th equilibri'um:# ..
itself, however, is likely to differ from equilibria reached under diffe~nt
sets of constraints. Given the government-imposed restrictions, the ad;
justment costs may be so high that the final output may lag drastically
behind the corresponding market outcome.
The advantages of allowing residual claimants to operate in an econ
omy are dear. In the context of new opportunities for the bus system.L ..
suppose it is discovered that the residents of a new'suburb'are willng to
pay more for bus service than this service would cost. If an individual
were in charge of deciding whether or not to start service, and if- he or
shewerealsothe sole daimant to the residual, service would be provided
~s expected
to lllcrease lf the reward IS larger;
wiII n o t be f or th commg
. I'f'It
1&
&imply commanded.
. _an.mcrease
..
.
..
. here
.'
. authonty;
.
12 For slmphclty,
the supenor
IS assumed to possess the ultlmate
people intermediate in the hierarchy are ignored.
I3 6
:I37
IO
costs, whereas the second type arises in the process of cieatirig monopo
. occur, in part, at the expense of others;thus,. they also seem to have the
right to harm other people. Yet such rights are not exercised indiscrimi
:nateIy,andItlsworthwhileto'de"teiiriinetneCi:irist:nces"ii"ndec"whith" .
.....................I:3.l).................. - ..................
............................................... .
I39
I4
The existence of theft makes the distinction between economic and legaJ
rights clear; it also highlights the notion that economic rights are never
absolute. Thieves lack legal rights over the goods they steal. Nevertheless,
they are able to consume the goods, to exdude others from using them,
to derive incme from them, and to alienate them. Each of these capabili
ties is an attrbute of ownership. The lack of legal rights may reduce the
value of these capabilties, but it does not nullify them.
The fact that thieves have rights over stolen property implies that the
current owners of property that might possibly be stolen do not have full
rights over "their" property. Owners cannot be certain of the future use
of such properties. The economic rights they do have depend, in part, on
the protectloneHorti:radebYthestate. iliseighcii also depend on the
measures owners take to protect themselves from theft: The more they
are willing to spend, the more secure their rights are expected to become.
The dfort they make, however, is not expected to deter all theft. For
instance, fences around orchards are not made to be totally insurmount
able; the cost of making them insurmountable exceeds the gain. Here,
too, individuaIs choose to leave some rights inthe public domain. When
the probability that thieves will steal o.ne's apples is"po"S"iivii'tneri'rie:
has only partial ownership over the apples.
Private-protection methods are as varied as are commodities them
14 1 '
selves. Owners 'of apple 'orchards may empl'oY guards to reduce theft;
ence between. total c'onsumers' valuati'on and t'otal inn'ovat'ors' C'osts.
they may place trees farther fr'om their property b'oundaries than they
Each of the potential patterns of activity leading t'o a particular innova~
would in the absence of theft; and they may grow less valuable apples
tion will generate its own net present value. The highest value will be
that are less appealing to thieves. Indeed, landowners might grow entirely
generated by the innovative activity that satis6.es two conditions: that it
be free of duplication and that it be undertaken at the time that yields
different crops if theft became a serious problem. 4 Those owners who
wish to employ others t'o tend their orchards may fear employee theft.
the highest consumer valuation net of innovating costs. One market force
Changing a contract's form is expected to change the incentive to steal.
mat tends to bring about the realizati'on of these conditions is competi~
If, fot example, an 'owner forms a fixed-rent contract with a worker to
ti'on am'ong innovators in recruiting customers f'or their particular inno~
tend the orcharcl>.tlle:PfJ~mr~Il~'Wrk!;;,;~thdtsimplydjsappear:s;'::::,::.::::::::,,::yti9.!lspefore expending resources on the actual inn'ovatio~..5 lri order,
"'The'notiornhat theft is a manifestation of the imperfect delineation of
to attract potential customers away from competing inrtovators, not nly
theater owners relinquish to the public domain, two relate to the differ.
tion, but the winning nnovator will also be the one who performs the.
ence in value among seats. The first relinquished attribute is the differ
innovation activity dosest to the time that maximizes its net present
ence in value between the better and the inferior seats within a price class
value; only then can the bid for customers dominate that of competitors.
of seats. People can capture the difference in value by arriving early and
When the cost of recruiting cust'omers, whether directly or indirctly, is
occupying the better seats. To the extent that policing is imperfect, a sec
low, customers have, in practice, the rights to the gain from the irnova
ond attribute that is partially relinquished is the difference in value across
tion. As in the case of predatory practices, the easier the advance con- .
. '
price classes. Where seats are sold in several price classes, as is common
tracting, the better the delineation of rights.
Innovators who possess unique talents do not need to cede to custom
o~tside the United States, buyers of lower-priced tickets can cpture the
diffrnce to the extent that they are not prevented from occupying
ers al1 the potential gains the innovations.generate. Such inno.vators may
... higher-pricedseats; The'state'tklsparththeefteiiiiitffort onlyiri
encounter another problem, however. Every customer may try to obtain
the latter case, sinc6 jumping seats constitutes a legal infraction, whereas
a bargain by offering the lowest royalty payment. Since the innovators'
marginal cost of serving extra consumers is zero, the}'" may be willing to
selecting a certain seat within a price dass obviously does noto The eco
nomic logic of the two types of capture, however, is the same.
relinquish ground rather than lose customers. IndividuaIs' incentive fur
bargaining under these conditions implies that the difference between the
maximum consumers' vaIuation and the marginal cost lies, in thepublic
domain.
The potentiaI loss from such bargaining can, however, be low~
- PROPERTY RIGHTS" TO 'INNOVATIONS
ered if the parties can be compelled not to bargain. Therefore, if the op
In contrast to other areas in economics, the importance of property rights
tion of selling the use of the innovation to different consumers at different
considerations to innovations has been widely recognized by economists;
prices can be eliminated, either privateIy or through legal prohibition of
nevertheless, some major rights issues remain unresolved. One such issue
price discrimination, then the innovator's rights over the innovation will
concerns the economic rights innovators can expect to have over their
be partially restored. Maximizing sellers will equate their constrained
innovations. When a uniquely talented individual develops an innova
""marginaLre.venue.totheir(zero).marginal cost and will price accordingIy.
tion, it seems plausible that such an individual will b' ~ble to obtain the
The superimposed uniformity of prices -r()yalty rates in this context
rights to it, since he or she will control the 6.eld. On the other hand, if
delineates rights, and their determination is free of direct capture costs.
many individuais are able to develop the same innovation at a similar
This arrangement is not entirely free of cost, however, because when a
cost, it may appear that none has a right to it and that, in their competi
single price is prescribed, the welfare triangle that couid have been
tion for the gain from the innovation, its economic value will be dissi
avoided under price discrimination is relinquished to i:I1e,pubIic domain.
pated; nevertheless, in this case rights ma}' also be weU defined,
A useful measure of the net present value of an innovation is the differ
5yu (19 81 ) discusses at length methods'used"fr"'suttf'fecfuti~g;"Detse;"(968r"
4Reportedly some avocado orchards in.the San Diego area have been abandoned
beca use of increased theft.
I4 2
was the first to consider a:dvance contracting for selling commodities whose produc
tion is subject to deelining costs.
. ,
'.
. ,
WildIife, by its very nature, s fleeting. How can one establish rights to
it?6 It would be simple to let one person own the entire habitat of a
wildlife stock such as a herd of deer. Some large hunting ranches in the
United States do contan the entire habtats of several wild animaIs, and
some African game preserves are home to whole herds of many different
species. Seemingly, the reason these ranches re so large is to encompass
endre habitats. Likewise, many primtive sodeties seem to have owned
the entire habitat of wildlife stock tliey hunted or flshed.
A wild'ife stock that oc;cupies and traverses a land area is only one of
several attributes of the land; the others include the capacity for growing
wheat; yielding mineraIs and groundwater; and offering sceruc' vantage
.. points, as well as providing habitat for wildIfe. Each implies a distinct
parcel sjze and shape for optimal use. Wildlife stocks themselves are di
"erse, varying greatly both in vaIue (pests being negativelr..Y.<:i1lle<:iLat:ld ..
Ticlij;-sl'ze..onhe..ti-ltoryi:heyoccupy;Weretransactlo'costs zero - nd
'~The'dis(;,ussion
145
II
PeopIe have discretio.n cver hcw to. delineate rights, and as part of their
maximizaticn effcrt they do. sc to whatever degree they desre. Rights are
never perfectly delineated, hcwever, beca use the fact that ccmmcdities
ru;:e not unfcrm and are e:x:pensive to. measure makes perfect delineadon
prchibtively cO!rl:Iy. Nevertheless, since 'pecpIe do. what they deem
"best," rights may be sad'tc be always weU delineated.
Thcse prcperti~s 'that'pecpIe chcse.nct.tc delineate are in the publie
dcmain. $uch properties indude much of the wcrld's oceaDS;they.also...
indude the cccI air in air-ccnditicned shcpping maUs, which is not
ch~rged fcr.cn the margin. Properties in. the pubIic dcmain can be aug
..nented or diminished.:'Asthe values cf t:ommcdities and cf commcdity
change, people's deciscns regarding whaf to. leave in, what to. relinquish,
and what to. redaim frcm the public domain change ccrrespcndingly.
The public dcmain is ubiquitcus; innumerable ccmmodity attributes
are placed in it. Any service nct fuUy charged fcr on the margin is at least
partly relinquished tC.the public domain. Owners cculd charge fcr such
services; but the extra returns cften do. nct justify the extra ccsts. Fcr
instance, ccncert-hall cwners relnquish to. the public dcmain the differ
ential in valuaiicn amcng' equaUy priced seats. When the value of
ccncert-hall seats falls - which might happen when the hall is used by a
lccal chcir rather than a famcus cpera star - seats are expected to be
priced in lesser detai!. The differences in value amcng seats that were
formerly differential1y priced are relinquishedto the public domain. Pa
trons are expected to. daim that differential through the expenditure cf
rescurces. Resource cwners attempt to.. maximize the net values of their
rescurces: They attempt to. crganize their actions sc that, eteris paribus,
'they'riiiriii:i:ii:~'tlielo'sse!drompladnfttrlbuteshl'thep'bcdomaii .......
Barzel 1987.
151
'< '. :;,';:<:;'~::~~:~:','>:: .: .. \~>~\::;,~~d::~.'! ~.,_:;~;~'<"'.:R\f!;~::i,5!,~:jt~~;'H~;Uf .'~!':';~'>!;-':,.' '.;,~. <. ",.~: ,';' .'!';',1:";':":"~':.' '!.:
; .. '
::~ ~::~:;-'~
c:;, ",
","-,,-,,~~,~~~~:::.::..~.:>:.
;",;.
In
'.
1:5 2
I53
Barzel, Yoram. 1994. "The Capture ofWealm by Monopolists and the Protection
of PropertyRights." IntemationalReview of Law and Economia 14: 29 2
References
49
Barzel, Yoram, and Tim Sass. 1990. "The Allocation of Resources' by Voting."
Quarterly Journal of Econo1?'tics lOS: 745-7 1
Bean, Richard N., and Robert P. Thomas. 1974. "The profits of the Slave Trade:
The Fishers of Men." journal of Economic History 34, no. 4: 885-9 1 4.
Cheung, Steven N. S. 1969. A Theory of Share Tenancy. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Cheung, Steven N. S. 1974. "A Theory of Price ControI." journal of Law and
Economics 17, no. I: 53-72.
Cheung, Steven N. S. 1977. "Why Are Better Seats 'Underpriced'?" Economic
. . ' . . ..
Inquiry 15, no. 3: 5 I 3-2.2. .
Cheung, Steven N. S. 1983. "T\1e. Contractual Nit1.iJ;e of me Firm:~ journal of
Law and Economics 2., no. I: 1-22..
'.,
.
Coase, Ronald H. 1937. "The Nature of th Firm." Economica 4, no. 3: 3 86
Akerlof, George. 1970, "The Market for 'Lemons': Quality Uncertainty and the
Market Mechanism." Quarterly journal of Economics 84: 488-50.
4 0 S
Alchian, Armen A. 1965. "Some Economics of Property Rights." Il Politico 30,
Coase, Ronald H. 1960. "The Problem of Social Cost." journal of Law and
Alchian, Armen A., and William R. AlIen. 1977. Exchange and Production, 2nd
Dam, Kenneth W. 1965. "Oil and.Gas Licensing and me North Sea." Journal f
Alchian, Armen A., and Harold Demsetz. 1972. "Production, Information Costs,
Deacon, Robert T., andJon Sonstelie. 1985. "Rationing by Waiting and the Value
154
155
Keterences
Hart, Oliver, and John M60re. 1990. "Property 'Rights and the Nature of the
Firm." Journal ofPolitical Economy 48, no. 6: III9-58.
Holmstrom, Bengt R., and Paul Milgrom. 199I. "Multitask Principal-Agent
Analysis: Incentive Contracts, Asset Ownership and Job Design." }ournal of
Iaw, Economics and Organization 7: 24-52.
Holmstrom, Bengt R., and Paul Milgrom. 199+ "The Finn as ao Incentive Sys
tem." American Economic Review 84, no. 4: 972-9I.
Jensen, Michael C., and William H. Meckling. 1976. "Theory of the Firm: Mana
gerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure." Joumal ofFinanciai
Economics 3, no. 3: 305-60.
'
Johnson, Ronald N., Micha Gisser, and Michal Werner. 1981. "The Definition
of Surface Water Right and Transferability." Joumal of Iaw and Economics
24, no. 2: 273-88.
.
::::::,::::::::KIl..!;!:iJ~~p4,P,,;I;98I. The Economics and Po/itics of Oil Pria Regulfltion: Fedral,
Policy in the Post~Embargo Era. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press; .
Kessel, Reuben A. 1974. "Transfused Bl09d, Serum Hepatitis, and the Coa'se
Theorem." Joumal of Iaw and Economics 17; no. 2: 265-9' .
Klein, Benjamin, Robert G. Crawford, and Armen A. Alchian. 1978. "Appropri
able Rents, Vertical Integration, and the Competitive Contracting Process."
Journal of Iaw and Economics n, no. 2: 297-326.
.
Knight, Frank H., 192I. Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Knight, Frank H. 1924. "Some Fallacies in the Interpretation of SociaJ Cost."
Quarterly Journal of Economics 38, no. 7: 582-606.
.
Krueger, Anne O. 1974. "The Poltica I Economy of the Rent-Seeklng Society....
American EconomicReview 66, no. 3: 291-303.
,
Landes, William M. 197I. "An Economic Analy~is of the Courts." JOlfmal of
Iaw and Economics 14, no. I: 61-108.
Libecap, Gary D. 1989. Contracting for Property Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lueck, Dean. 1989. "The Economic Nature of Wildlife Law." fournal of Legal
Studies 18, no. 2: 291-324.
Milgrom, Paul, and John Roberts. 1990. "The Economics of Modem 'Manufac
turing: Technology Strategy and Organization." American Economic Review
80, no. 3: 511-28.
Miller, Kathleen A. 1985. "The Right to Use vs. the Right to SeU: Water Rights
in the Western United States." Ph.D. diss., University ofWashington.
North, Douglass C. 198I. Structure and Change in Economic History. New
York: Norton.
'
Ostrom, Elinor. 1990. Governing th Common: The Evolution of lnstittions
for Collective Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
PosIlel,r'f.Richl'~~~lA.~ "J:9..7,5,~ ,~Ihe,Soc.i~.1 qs.t of Monopoly and Regulation." Jour
na o Po itica Economy 83, no. 4: 807-27.
Posner, Richard A. 1992. Economic Analysis of Iaw. 4th ed., .Boston: Litde,
Brown.
Priest, George L. 1980. "Selective Characteristics of Litigation." Journfll afLegal
Studies 9, no. I: 399-42I.
Priest, George L., and Benjamin Klein. 1984. "The Selection of Disputes for Liti
'
gation." JouriilfLegal Studies q, no. I: I-56.
Rockoff, Hugh. 1984. Drastic Measures: A 8#t.QrY...gLW.QgfUl/nd.P..r..k,?'CQntmls, ..
in the United States. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
'
15 6
'.
157
lndex
'.
.'
ad valorem tax, 34
agency theory, 14
Akerlof,. George, I 5n '
Alchian, Armen A., 3, 4n, 6n, 14,
65n, 75-6, 93n, 12.4n
Allen,.Douglas W., 3n, 4n;33n, 43n,
46n, 12.2.n, 12.3n
Allen, George c., 56n
Allen, William R., 3, 4n, 93n
allocation by government; 132,.,.8'
Anderson, Terry L., 119n
"'.....
....
......................
. 143n
donated bloQd,..I3,q-2.
Eggertsson, Thrinn, 13 n
Ellckson, Robert c., 3, 90n
84, 144
Gisser, Micha, 12.1n
108, 146
Goldberg, Victor P.,67n
I2.4 n
Hart, Oliver, 75-6
159
lndex
lndex
Hill, P.J., lI9n
. Hobbes, Thomas, 86-8
HoImstrom, Bengt R., 40n, 75-6
homesteading, x2x-3
wildlife, 145-7
Williamson, Olver E., 140, 65 n , 67 n ,
75-6
Yu,Ben T., 143 n
quasi rents, 14
,.