Sinhala Transitive Verbs
Sinhala Transitive Verbs
Sinhala Transitive Verbs
Abstract
The Sinhala volitive/involitive contrast is characterized by verb stem
and subject case marking alternations, and broadly indicates the volitionality/non-volitionality of the subject, plus other co-varying features. While superficially a high/low transitivity split a` la Hopper
and Thompson (1980), we argue that the distinction actually emerges
from the interaction of just two factors: a realis/irrealis mode contrast
relating to expectations of certain event participants and an independent semantic case system (building on Inman 1993). Co-variation of
other semantic features including volitionality follows directly
from their interaction with semantic case and modality. Explaining
this transitivity split through the interaction of language-specific elements, our analysis refines recent Optimality Theoretic approaches to
transitivity (Malchukov 2005, 2006) by partly obviating the need for
1 Introduction
Prototype theories of transitivity (Hopper and Thompson 1980, Tsunoda
1981, 1985, Lazard 1998, 2003, Malchukov 2005, 2006, inter alia) maintain that transitivity is a gradient notion, wherein a clause may be more
or less transitive based on the degree to which it conforms to a transitive
prototype defined in terms of some set of distinct but co-varying semantic
features. Much work in this area has looked at so-called transitivity splits,
where two clauses that differ in one or more relevant semantic features also
differ by some overt grammatical distinction. However, certain questions regarding the nature of the systematic co-variation remain unexplained in the
literature: why should the semantic features that tend to vary across transitivity splits vary together, and why should they result in specific types of
grammatical splits? Using evidence from Colloquial Sinhala verb classes,
we address these questions, demonstrating that a careful spelling out of the
semantics of the relevant semantic and grammatical transitivity features in
particular languages can sharpen our predictions about co-variation.
Sinhala verbs fall into two stem classes, the volitive and involitive. Subjects of volitives are almost invariably nominative and subjects of involitives
occur in nominative, accusative, dative, or the postpositional case atiN. Volitives generally indicate volitional action and involitives non-volitional action (Gair 1970, Inman 1993). Examples are given in (1), where a transitive
volitive in (1a) contrasts with both a transitive involitive in (1b), where the
subject is marked by atiN (glossed POST), and an inchoative involitive with
2
a. Aruni Nimal-w@
giluwa.
Nimal-w@
giluna.
giluna.
Nimal-ACC/Nimal drown.INV.PST
Nimal drowned (accidentally).
Superficially, (1a) vs. (1b,c) represents a transitivity split since volitionality and number of participants (two of Hopper and Thompsons features)
systematically co-vary with the case marking and stem alternations. However, we argue that a careful examination of volitive and involitive semantics
reduces the contrast to just two cross-classifying properties of the language.
First, the stem alternation reflects a type of realis/irrealis contrast relating to
the intentions or expectations of certain participants in the event (building on
Inman 1993). This interacts significantly with other features that reference
intentions, including volitionality and ultimately actorhood, but not other
features, predicting when we see co-variation. Second, case-marking patterns follow from an independently motivated set of semantic (i.e. inherent,
non-structural) cases, with nominative (the default structural case) surfacing
to cover gaps in the paradigm. The categorical use of the nominative in the
volitive follows from the fact that all volitive stems have subjects that fall
into these gaps due to the types of events that volitive verbs describe.
3
HIGH TRANSITIVE
LOW TRANSITIVE
2 or more participants
1 participant
(A and O)
B. K INESIS
action
non-action
C. A SPECT
telic
atelic
D. P UNCTUALITY
punctual
non-punctual
E. VOLITIONALITY
volitional
non-volitional
F. A FFIRMATION
affirmative
negative
G. M ODE
realis
irrealis
H. AGENCY
A high in potency
A low in potency
I. A FFECTEDNESS
OF
O totally affected
O not affected
J. I NDIVIDUATION
OF
O highly individuated
O non-individuated
Hopper and Thompson further propose that when a clause overtly marks a
high/low transitivity feature, other features of the clause will also co-vary in
the same direction, their Transitivity Hypothesis (pp. 254-255, (9)):
(3)
T RANSITIVITY H YPOTHESIS : If two clauses (a) and (b) in a language differ in that (a) is higher in Transitivity according to any of
the features [in (2)], then, if a concomitant grammatical or semantic
difference appears elsewhere in the clause, that difference will also
show (a) to be higher in Transitivity.
5
For example, they claim that in ergative languages, the contrast between
ERG-ABS vs. ABS-OBL (i.e. antipassive) case frames co-varies with several transitivity features as follows (Hopper and Thompson 1980: 268, (53)):
(4)
E RGATIVE
A NTIPASSIVE
Imperfective aspect
Total involvement of O
Partitive O
Definite O
Indefinite O
Kinetic/volitional V
Stative/involuntary V
Active participation of A
Passive participation of A
contact
pursuit
(motion)
perception/cognition
emotion
(sensation)
effective action
high transitivity
low transitivity
For example, NOM-ACC and ERG-ABS satisfy all constraints for effective
action verbs. But as we move down the O-hierarchy we see more marked
cases on O and conversely for A on the A-hierarchy. In addition, language
type plays a role: an additional Unmarked Case Constraint (UCC) requiring
one unmarked (nominative/absolutive) argument per clause produces different outputs for ergative and accusative languages, generating still more
complex patterns (see Malchukov 2005: 96-107 for a detailed discussion).
Though these updates to Hopper and Thompsons proposals greatly contribute to developing a testable theory of transitivity, a few problems remain.
First, as Tsunoda (1985) and Malchukov (2006) note, while the Transitivity Hypothesis in (3) allows for systematic co-variation, nothing inherent in
the hypothesis explains such variation (or predicts when it will occur). Why
should the features in (2) vary in the same direction when they co-vary?
For example, telicity, affectedness of O, and individuation of O are closely
related (see e.g. Tenny 1994, Krifka 1998, Beavers 2009) and thus intuitively are expected to co-vary (though not categorically; Lazard 2003: 175,
Beavers 2009). However, other features are clearly unrelated (e.g. agentivity
of A and affectedness of O) and intuitively should (and do) vary independently, contra (3). A suitable Transitivity Hypothesis should have a mechanism for calculating which semantic features co-vary and when.
Malchukov (2006: 333-334) partly addresses this by proposing that Hopper and Thompsons features can be ranked along a Transitivity Scale (a
one-dimensional semantic map) from those most likely to pertain to A, to
those most likely to pertain to V, to those most likely to pertain to O.
(6) Transitivity Scale
A-features
V-features
O-features
animacy|volitionality|kinesis|factivity|tense/aspect|affectedness|(O-)individuation
The emergent definitions of each feature allows us to make specific predictions about when we will get systematic co-variation between features and
when we will not. Furthermore, doing so we show that the semantic features
do not form a one-dimensional hierarchy, but rather a multi-dimensional
map. Likewise, the devices independently available for marking low transitivity have semantic content that also plays a role in predicting when we get
high/low transitive marking, regardless of the underlying clausal semantics.
gloss
volitive
involitive
volitive
involitive
wash
hood-a-n@wa
heed-e-n@wa
heed-u(w)-a
heed-un-a
suck
ur-a-n@wa
ir-e-n@wa
ir-u(w)-a
ir-un-a
make
had-a-n@wa
hd-e-n@wa
hd-u(w)-a
hd-un-a
open
ar-i-n@wa
r-e-n@wa
r-i(y)-a
r-un-a
10
nestomalt(-*w@) biuwwa.
elephant nestomalt
drink.PST
giluwa/mruwa.
d. Aliya
11
plate
eet hit@la
nemeyi.
The child broke the plate unintentionally. (Inman 1993: 98, (39))
Nonetheless, some volitives require volitionality, including the verb for murder, which is incompatible with a continuation denying volitionality:
(10) #Siri Gunee-w@
minimruwa,
eet hit@la
nemeyi.
a. Siri atiN
(#hit@la)
piNgaan@y@ kduna.
break.INV.PST
sadd@yak huna.
hear.INV.PST
c. Amma-t.@
(#hit@la)
wewuluna.
giluna/mruna.
giluna/mruna.
14
Our updated definition in (12) covers not just cases where the subject did not
intend to make P true, but also cases where the subject had no intentions at
all, thus permitting inanimate subjects with unaccusatives as in (14).
(14) PiNgaan@y@ mes@yen
plate
wtuna.
table.INST fall.INV.PST
maalu ageet.@
pihen@wa.
very.well cook.INV.PRS
given in (17), where B uses the volitive form of a verb for watch to claim
C participated in a certain watching event, and C counters with an involitive
use to deny that the event occurred (cp. sarcastic intonation in English).
(17) ((C is explaining why he left work late the night of his car accident))
A: i
parakku wela
why late
eheng giye?
wla blen@wa.
porn watch.INV.PRS
Yeah I look at porn when everyone leaves.
Additional examples are given in (18)-(19).
(18) ((A is surprised that B has cooked for himself))
A: Uyen@we-d@? Oyaa atiN
iwen@wa,
n.
pare
do.INV.PST
a. P is intended by x iff for all possible worlds in which xs intentions/expectations are realized x made P is true.
17
b. Volitive: vol P is true iff P is true and (by default) P was intended by the subject x.
Note that (21a) is not the negation of (12). First, intendedness (unlike unintendedness) requires not just that x expects P to be true, but expects to make
P true (e.g. if one expects to be forced to do something then one expects to
do it but does not intend to do it). Second, vacuous universal quantification
over an empty intention set allows inanimates, which lack intentions, to occur with volitives, a prediction borne out for natural forces and instruments:
(22)
a. Hul@N@ ham@n@wa.
wind
blow.VOL.PRS
break.VOL.PST
partial correlation: since the modality of volitives requires actorhood, patient subjects are precluded, correctly predicting that unaccusatives occur
exclusively in the involitive. Furthermore, our analysis also predicts that covariation should not be categorical when it does occur, although free variation is strictly limited. For example, volitives can be non-volitional, but only
if explicitly canceled in context, something not possible for all roots. Conversely, involitives can be volitional, but only if the speakers expectations
are taken into account instead, meaning that involitives are not a general way
of encoding volitionality. The overall picture of co-variation is as follows:
(24)
volitive stem
inolitive stem
(+realis+actor)
(-realis)
volitional
non-volitional
volitional
(canceled implicature)
(unexpected to subject)
non-volitional
This analysis makes predictions that differ from Malchukovs Transitivity Scale in 2. Malchukov puts mode (factivity), adjacent to tense/aspect
but separated from volitionality. Yet our discussion has shown that volitionality can be effectively reduced to a subtype of the mode once the semantics
of volitionality are better spelled out. This means that mode can be both an
A-related and V-related feature, depending on the specific modal operator
(indeed also supporting the Relevance Principle, since the feature is marked
on both elements via stem form and quirky case). But of course it need not
be; other modal operators may make no reference to A or O participants.
Likewise, the mode to actorhood connection (mediated through volitionality) is also unexpected in general, but predicted in this particular case.
More fundamentally, our analysis demonstrates that the relationships between features are not one-dimensional, but multi-dimensional, contingent
20
case, nominative, as the only possible subject case. Indeed, even among involitives there are gaps in the semantic case paradigm, predicting the presence of nominative and thus high transitive marking there as well.
Subjects marked by atiN occur exclusively with transitive caused changeof-state verbs (e.g. issenn@ lift; kdenn@ break, renn@ open; ellenn@
hang; hellenn@ shake; plenn@ split (as in wood); kr@kenn@ turn,
weelenn@ twine; see Wijayawardhana et al. 1991: 113-122), while dative subjects occur primarily with unergative verbs (e.g. n.d.enn@ cry; hinaawenn@ laugh; wewulenn@ shiver; numak renn@ yawn; nt.enn@
dance; widenn@ walk; Henadeerage 2002: 137-140). We could analyze
the distribution of atiN and dative structurally: atiN only occurs with transitives and dative only with intransitives (i.e. atiN indicates the presence of a
lower argument as in the analysis of ergative case by Wunderlich 1997).
However, this analysis is clearly insufficient, since (as discussed above)
unaccusative verbs are intransitive but do not take dative subjects. Furthermore, we also find dative subjects with some transitive involitive verbs, including performance verbs (kiy@wenn@, read, pwenn@ perform, kiyenn@
speak, say, recite), psych-verbs (dnenn@, feel; peenn@, see; henn@,
hear; teerenn@, understand), and verbs of receiving (lbenn@, receive):
(25)
a. Mat.@/*mam@
atiN
pot@ kiy@wewuna.
22
b. Lam@ya-t.@/*lam@ya atiN
child-DAT/child
sadd@yak huna.
POST noise
hear.INV.PST
atiN
tgi lbuna.
blow.INV.PRS
a. And@ree atiN
wli kwen@wa.
23
b. And@ree-t.@
wli kwen@wa.
Thus the dative in (25b) can be assimilated under a more general use of the
dative for experiencer subjects. Dative also independently marks possessors,
including both possessor subjects and indirect objects (the stative volitive in
(29a) being a very rare example of a non-volitional, quirky subject volitive,
which we treat as a lexical exception):
(29)
exists.VOL.PRS
24
b. Eyaa mat@
mee sumaane salli dunna.
Thus the dative in (25c) can also be subsumed under a more general use
of the dative. Indeed, these two datives may be collapsible, as argued by
Mohanan and Mohanan (1990) based on data from Malayalam, where experiencers may be expressed as the goal argument of a light deictic motion
verb with the stimulus as a theme (cp. English happiness came to him). Thus
a single notion of goal may underlie both uses of the dative: either the goal
of a physical object or the goal of a mental/physical sensation.
However, this analysis does not obviously explain why dative also marks
subjects of unergatives or subjects of performance verbs such as those meaning read, perform, and recite. Before we offer a tentative solution to
this, we first argue that these two uses of the dative are not distinct. As
suggested by Tenny (1994), and then argued (in different ways) by Beavers
(2009) and Rappaport Hovav (2008), performance verbs are not standard
agent/patient transitive verbs on par with verbs meaning break or cool.
Rather, these verbs take direct objects that measure out the event by the subjects progress through the object the subject moves through the book
in (25a), much in the same way that the subject moves along the path object
in John hiked the trail. Evidence for this comes from the fact that performance objects pattern like path objects in terms of measure phrases: in both
cases V DO halfway means roughly V half of DO, an equivalence that does
not maintain for most change-of-state verbs:
(30)
a. John hiked half of the trail John hiked the trail halfway.
25
This is again explained if performance verbs are analyzed as abstract motion verbs, where the subject progresses through the direct object, which in
turn measures out the event (see Beavers 2009 for a detailed analysis). On
this analysis, performance verbs are abstract unergative verbs, and thus the
dative is subsumable under the same analysis as more canonical unergatives.
With this reduction, we argue that the subject role for involitive unergatives is that of involuntary actor. Evidence comes from a comparison with
the semantics of atiN, which we suggest marks involuntary causers. It is a
crucial difference between clauses that take atiN and those that take dative
that the former have causative semantics, i.e. in standard event decompositional terms we can say that causative events have the structure in (32a) and
unergatives have the structure in (32b) (following the notation of Rappaport
Hovav and Levin 1998: 108 for expository convenience).
26
(32)
(x, y individuals)
b. [ x ACT (y) ]
(x, y individuals)
(negated cause)
ii. The vase did not break, though John hit it. (negated result)
iii. John neither acted nor did the vase break.
b. John did not run/read the book.
(both negated)
(no ambiguity)
Crucially, clauses that take atiN subjects show ambiguity under negation, but
those that take dative do not, as in (34), supporting our analysis.
(34)
a. Eyaa atiN
piNgaan@y@ kdune
n.
break.INV.PST NEG
(negated cause)
ii. The plate did not break, though she hit it. (negated result)
iii. She neither acted nor did the plate break.
b. Mat.@
pot@ kiy@wewune
(both negated)
27
(no ambiguity)
Further evidence for the contrast between clauses with atiN subjects and
those with dative subjects comes from verbs that show an alternation. As
noted above, the verb meaning eat in (27) allows either atiN or dative; with
the former the subject intended to do something, though not to eat sand,
while in the latter case the subject had no intentions at all. Crucially, with
eat verbs the subject is both an actor and a causer: the subject works his way
through the sand in (27) like a motion verb (Ramchand 2008) and simultaneously the sand comes to be affected (eaten) by the action of the subject
like an agent/patient verb (Beavers 2009). This event type is schematized
in (35) (again borrowing for convenience the notation for accomplishments
with associated actions of Rappaport Hovav and Levin 1998: 108).
(35) [ [ x ACT ] CAUSE [ y BECOME < EATEN > ] ] (x, y individuals)
If dative marks involuntary actors and atiN marks involuntary causers, the
dual nature of the subjects role explains the alternation and the semantic
contrast. If the action is intentional but the causation is not, the subject is
an involuntary causer, yielding atiN. Alternatively, if the action itself is unintended, the subject is an involuntary actor and dative is licensed. Thus
the semantic contrast reflects the variable scope of the involitive operator,
providing further motivation for the contrast in the two cases.
We now ask what independent evidence there is for these analyses. For
datives, we tentatively suggest that an involuntary actor is essentially an experiencer, albeit an experiencer of a physical sensation of performing an
action rather than a psychological or static physical sensation. The explanation for the lack of dative inanimate involuntary actors may follow from
this fact (since inanimates cannot be experiencers), or from a restriction of
dative to actors that are truly non-volitional, requiring that they have inten28
tions (i.e. unlike the involitive operator more generally, inanimates are not
exempt from computing intentions if dative).
For atiN we propose that its distribution derives from its etymology: it
is synchronically identical to the instrumental form of at@ hand, i.e. it is
superficially identical to the expression by hand. However, there is evidence that it has grammaticalized into a substantive postposition (Gair 1970:
73) that heads a PP that is the subject of the involitive clause. First, the
[ DP atiN ] phrase is a constituent, as can be shown by constituency tests.
For example, while scrambling is possible in Sinhala, as shown in (36a-c),
atiN cannot be scrambled away from the DP it marks, as shown in (36d,e).
(36)
a. Siri atiN
piNgaan@y@ [email protected]
binduna.
accidentally broke.INV.PST
wiweec@nee keruna.
criticism
do.INV.PST
Siri-w@
The Sinhala instrumental case shows the same two uses, suggesting it also
30
kaewwa.
piruwa.
I water glass
This in turn explains the restriction that atiN always occur with transitive
causation verbs: the causal intermediacy requires the presence of some other
entity in the clause that is acted upon, which requires the presence of a lower
argument, effectively replicating the Wunderlich (1997) analysis of ergative
case noted above. The only aspect of causal intermediacy not preserved is
the requirement of an external causer, though this may have been lost in
grammaticalization since atiN is not referential on its own.
Likewise, the exclusive use of atiN in involitive clauses may also derive
from its erstwhile instrumental status. Instruments are by definition unwitting, so that we might expect atiN to only occur in non-volitional clauses.
However, as noted above, doxastic and ironic uses with atiN are volitional,
suggesting that non-volitionality is not a synchronic component of its meaning. Nonetheless, it is plausible that this component of instrumentality has
grammaticalized into a restriction that atiN only occur with involitives. Thus,
while postpositional atiN is not attested outside of involitive clauses, its distribution may have an independent diachronic semantic explanation.
We can thus sweep non-nominative subjects of transitive and unergative
verbs under two semantic cases:
31
(40)
We turn next to intransitives, and argue that semantics also determines the
subject cases there, although at least one case may indeed be a default case.
a. Aruni-ge
drown.INV.PST/die.INV.PST
nominative subject is compatible with a context in which there was no external causer, but not an accusative subject. Similarly, the emphatic/reflexive
clitic -m@ (which conveys a by himself/herself reading) is only compatible
with nominative subjects as shown in (43).6
(42)
a. Amma lissuna,
3SG-ACC
n.
push.CAUS.PST NEG
Mother fell, but nobody pushed her.
b. #Amma-w@
lissuna,
3SG-ACC
n.
push.CAUS.PST NEG
Mother fell, but nobody pushed her.
(43)
a. Shameela-m@
hir@wuna/lissuna.
Shameela-REFL get.stuck.INV.PST/slip.INV.PST
Shameela got herself stuck/slipped on her own.
b. #Shameela-w@-m@
(reflexive)
hir@wuna/lissuna.
Shameela-ACC-REFL get.stuck.INV.PST/slip.INV.PST
Shameela got herself stuck/slipped on her own.
(#reflexive)
Beavers and Zubair argue that ECOS unaccusatives are derived from transitive causative volitive verbs by a process of causer suppression that may
result in two possible interpretations the suppressed causer is interpreted
reflexively as co-identified with the patient argument, or it is existentially
bound and is interpreted as distinct from the patient. These two meanings
33
are represented in (44b,c) respectively. ICOS verbs we assume are noncausative and reflect only inchoative semantics as in (44a).
(44)
a.
b.
(ICOS)
(Refl. ECOS)
and arises due to gaps in the paradigm: the arguments that take nominative
are unable to bear any of the semantic cases discussed above.
Among involitives, unaccusative subjects cannot be marked by atiN since
there is no causal precedence, nor dative because they are not involuntary
actors, recipients/goals, or experiencers. If there is external causation accusative is possible, but minus that there is no semantic case left. Likewise,
inanimate actors such as natural forces cannot be marked dative since they
have no intentions, nor atiN or accusative due to lack of causally subsequent/prior entities. In all cases, default nominative is all that is left.
Among volitives, animate subjects of unergatives may not be dative
since its inherent non-volitionality clashes with the interpretative principles
governing volitives. Inanimate subjects are ruled out for dative a priori. Accusative may not mark subjects of volitives since no volitive takes a patient
subject (as discussed in 4), and atiN is (as argued above) restricted to involitive clauses and thus also never occurs with volitives. Thus again default
nominative is the only case left. Note that it is possible to have quirky subjects in the volitive; as shown in (29a) dative possessor subjects are possible.
Thus the only explanation is that nominative fills in the gaps where other
cases fail, and there are more such gaps with volitive verbs than involitives.
3 and 5.1-5.2 emerge through the interaction of three factors: verb class,
the modal operators associated with the two stem types, and the system
of specific semantic cases found in the language. In terms of Malchukov
(2005), FaithRole (overtly indicate thematic roles) is presumably ranked
highly in Sinhala, explaining why we get quirky cases at all. However, were
we to focus just on Malchukovs constraints, we might expect some volitives
with quirky subjects, and likewise no nominative subjects in involitives. We
could overcome this by saying TransDef (prefer unmarked frames) is ranked
more highly just for volitive stems, but this would not explain nominative
subjects with involitives. On our analysis, no reranking is necessary: even
with FaithRole ranked highly across the board, if there is no case for a given
thematic role, then nominative is all that is left (i.e. FaithRole is vacuously
satisfied). However, it is only by examining the semantics of particular cases
in detail that this conclusion emerges, adding an additional level of explanation beyond Malchukovs broader constraints on surface forms.
6 Conclusion
We have argued that the Sinhala volitive/involitive contrast is a high/low
transitivity split that reduces to two factors: a stem alternation indicating
a realis/irrealis distinction that has significant interaction with volitionality
and actorhood, and a system of semantic cases. In contrast to Malchukovs
one-dimensional Transitivity Scale, our analysis indicates that semantic features form a multi-dimensional map. The crucial factor is the way particular
semantic features are independently defined, so that mode not normally
considered an A-related feature happens to be an A-related feature here.
36
References
Beavers, J. 2009. On affectedness. Unpublished ms., The University of
Texas at Austin.
Beavers, J. and C. Zubair. 2009. Anticausatives in Sinhala: Involitivity and
causer suppression. Unpublished ms., The University of Texas at Austin
and Georgetown University.
Brandt, P. 2006. Receiving and perceiving datives (cipients): a view from
German. In Datives and other cases: between argument structure and
event structure, D. P. Hole, W. Abraham, and A. Meinunger (eds.), 103
139. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Croft, W. 1991. Syntactic Categories and Grammatical Relations: The
Cognitive Organization of Information. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Curnow, T. J. 2003. Nonvolitionality expressed through evidentials. Studies
37
Endnotes
1
We would like to thank Patrick Brandt, Marco Garcia, Andrej Malchukov, and an
anonymous reviewer for their very useful comments on an earlier draft. Thanks also to
Andrew Koontz-Garboden, John Peterson, Farzan Zaheed, Bettina Zeisler, and audiences
at the Transitivity Workshop at Cologne and the 2008 LSA Annual Meeting for their feedback. We would also like to thank our informants. Any errors or omissions are our own.
2
There are of course other modalities in Sinhala (e.g. future tense) that vary indepen-
dently; we refer here just to the specific modality associated with (in)volitive-marking.
3
There is some evidence of this in other languages as well. Brandt (2006) notes a paral-
lel situation with German cipient-datives in too-comparatives similar to The soup is too hot
(to me). Brandt argues that the predicate expressing too hotness generates a presupposition
that there is some other index (world) in which this state of affairs does not obtain, and this
index is associated with the dative-marked participant, which he analyzes as a predicate
internal subject of sorts. Thus again computing possible worlds results in A-marking.
5
The difference between (26) and the volitive variant in (22a) is that the involitive typ-
ically conveys a meaning that the blowing is unexpected/unexplained to the speaker, i.e. a
doxastic use. To simply say that the wind blows, the volitive is the preferred form. This is as
expected on our approach. Since the subject has an empty intention set, the non-volitional
reading of the involitive means the same as the volitive. In this case we would expect the
unmarked volitive to be preferred, leaving the involitive for uses that do not code subject
intentions, such as the doxastic. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out us.
6
never occurs with inanimate objects and only optionally occurs with animates. However,
(42)-(43) show that overtly accusative subjects have a different reading from overtly nominative ones, suggesting that when marking subjects these cases are not in free variation.
41