Debating Humanity. Towards A Philosophical Sociology: Daniel Chernilo
Debating Humanity. Towards A Philosophical Sociology: Daniel Chernilo
Debating Humanity. Towards A Philosophical Sociology: Daniel Chernilo
Towards a
Philosophical sociology
Daniel Chernilo
ABLE OF CONTENTS
Introduction
Chapter 1. The humanism debate revisited. Sartre,
Heidegger, Derrida
Chapter 2. Self-transcendence. Hannah Arendt
Chapter 3. Adaptation. Talcott Parsons
Chapter 4. Responsibility. Hans Jonas
Chapter 5. Language. Jrgen Habermas
Chapter 6. Moral goods. Charles Taylor
Chapter 7. Reflexivity. Margaret Archer
Chapter 8. Reproduction of life. Luc Boltanski
Chapter 9. Back to Philosophical Anthropology? Hans
Blumenberg
References
Introduction
This book introduces the idea philosophical sociology as a research
programme that explores the various anthropological dimensions
through which both sociology and philosophy have defined notions
the human, human beings, humanity and indeed human nature
over the past 60 or so years. I contend that these notions have
mostly remained implicit in contemporary debates; at the very least,
that they have not been fully articulated out. The project of a
philosophical sociology is built on three main pillars:
(1) The anthropological features that define us as human beings are
to a large extent independent from, but cannot be realised in full
outside, social life. The core of this book then looks at seven of
these properties (as they have been discussed by a particular writer
over the past 60 or so years): self-transcendence (Hannah Arendt),
adaptation (Talcott Parsons), responsibility (Hans Jonas), language
(Jrgen Habermas), moral goods (Charles Taylor), reflexivity
(Margaret Archer) and the reproduction of life (Luc Boltanski).
(2) Substantively, this matters because our conceptions of the
human ultimately underpin our normative notions in social life.
Normative ideas in society depend on the human capacity to reflect
on what makes us human and mobilise the ways in which we
imagine the kind of beings that we would like to become. Normative
ideas are therefore irreducible to the material or sociocultural
positions that humans occupy in society.
(3) Given that in contemporary societies humans themselves are
ultimate arbiters of what is right and wrong, our shared
anthropological features as members of the human species remain
the best option to justify normative arguments. These
anthropological traits define us as members of the same species not
only create the conditions for social life to unfold but they are also
the basis from which ideas of justice, self, dignity and the good life
emerge. A universalistic principle of humanity is to be preferred over
particularistic conceptions of race, culture, identity, and indeed
class.
Sociology and Philosophy
The notion of philosophical sociology indicates also a preference for
a conception of sociology that cannot be realised without a close
and careful relationship with philosophy. Whilst the early
institutionalisation of sociology was unquestionably driven by an
effort of differentiation from philosophy (Manent 1998), it is wrong
to construe this as sociologys rejection or neglect of philosophy
networks are real because they are well constructed, only networks
are viable because they speak various languages, only networks
allow unstable components to become scientific, artistic, or
economic. A genuine ontological plurality fails to emerge because
all is now subordinated to an endless flow of networks; all we can
learn and experience we learn and experience because it has
successfully become real as a network: As collectives, we are all
brothers (1993: 114)
The second issue refers directly to the question of the status of the
human in Latours work. The problem here can be introduced in the
same way as above: either do human exist but we have never
understood them (in a milder form: modern Western metaphysics
has fundamentally misconstrued them) or they dont exist and are
indeed central to the difficulties we have in understanding the
world. Similar to what happens to the argument on the
differentiation of various domains, one is also reminded here of
Niklas Luhmanns (2012) argument that individuals are external to
society. But what for Luhmann counted above all as a requirement
of methodological consistency (and even in that softer case it
remained always a constant source of epistemological and
normative headaches), Latour has again pushed as question of
ontology. But it is one thing to accept that the traditional volitional,
dispositional, affective and indeed moral connotations of the human
are in need of permanent redefinition a perfectly reasonable claim
that I fully endorse and quite another to uphold the full
reversibility that Latour favours: humans are visible only if and when
they are part of a network. My point is simple banal even and
suggests that the very terms with which Latour himself justifies his
intellectual enquiry do require a strong and in fact highly
conventional conception of the human. In We Have Never Been
Humans, for instance, he is concerned with such questions as global
warming and the atomic bomb (Latour 1993) and in An
Anthropology of the Moderns he speaks at length about the revival
of fundamentalism, poverty, misogyny and colonialism as well as
ubiquitous ecological dangers (Latour 2013: 142-56, 268-91).
But because these are only understandable as normative motifs he
has to affirm in practice what rhetorically denies: there wes and
theys that ultimately care for these problems are, of course,
human beings.7 Can there be anything more modern that Latours
dissatisfaction with modernitys own self-descriptions? His work
belongs to the decidedly modern genre in which modernity is in
permanent need of full reconsideration: it is a thoroughly modern
attempt to account for the modern dissatisfaction with the modern
7 There is, even, a humanist plea that humans have not counted enough
throughout human history: humans have always counted less than the vast
population of divinities and lesser transcendental entities that give us life (Latour
2004: 456).