100% found this document useful (1 vote)
873 views7 pages

Probability Theorem Proofs

(1) The document outlines the axioms of probability as defined by Kolmogorov, including that the probability of any event A must be greater than or equal to 0, the probability of the entire sample space S must equal 1, and the probability of mutually exclusive events sums to the probability of their union. (2) It also discusses the rules of Boolean algebra as they relate to probability, such as the commutative and associative laws for union and intersection. (3) Several theorems are then proved, including that the probability of the complementary event Ac equals 1 minus the probability of A, the probability of the null event is 0, and a formula for the probability of the union of two events A and
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
873 views7 pages

Probability Theorem Proofs

(1) The document outlines the axioms of probability as defined by Kolmogorov, including that the probability of any event A must be greater than or equal to 0, the probability of the entire sample space S must equal 1, and the probability of mutually exclusive events sums to the probability of their union. (2) It also discusses the rules of Boolean algebra as they relate to probability, such as the commutative and associative laws for union and intersection. (3) Several theorems are then proved, including that the probability of the complementary event Ac equals 1 minus the probability of A, the probability of the null event is 0, and a formula for the probability of the union of two events A and
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 7

AXIOMATIC PROBABILITY AND POINT SETS

The axioms of Kolmogorov. Let S denote an event set with a probability measure P
defined over it, such that probability of any event A S is given by P (A). Then, the
probability measure obeys the following axioms:
(1) P (A) 0,
(2) P (S) = 1,
(3) If {A1 , A2 , . . . Aj , . . .} is a sequence of mutually exclusive events such that Ai Aj =
for all i, j, then P (A1 A2 Aj ) = P (A1 ) + P (A2 ) + + P (Aj ) + .
The axioms are supplemented by two definitions:
(4) The conditional probability of A given B is defined by
P (A|B) =

P (A B)
,
P (B)

(5) The events A, B are said to be statistically independent if


P (A B) = P (A)P (B).
This set of axioms was provided by Kolmogorov in 1936.
1

The rules of Boolean Algebra. The binary operations of union and intersection are
roughly analogous, respectively, to the arithmetic operations of addition + and multiplication
, and they obey a similar set of laws which have the status of axioms:
Commutative law:
Associative law:
Distributive law:
Idempotency law:

A B = B A,
A B = B A,

(A B) C = A (B C),
(A B) C = A (B C),

A (B C) = (A B) (A C),
A (B C) = (A B) (A C),
A A = A,
A A = A.

De Morgans Rules concerning complementation are also essential:


(A B)c = Ac B c

and

(A B)c = Ac B c .

Amongst other useful results are those concerning the null set and the universl set S:
(i) A Ac = S,
(ii) A Ac = ,
(iii) A S = S,

(iv) A S = A,
(v) A = A,
(vi) A = .
2

LEMMA: the probability of the complementary event. If A and Ac are complementary events, then
P (Ac ) = 1 P (A).
Proof. There are
Therefore, by Axiom 3,

A Ac = S

and

A Ac = ,

P (A Ac ) = P (A) + P (Ac ) = 1,

since P (A Ac ) = P (S) = 1, whence P (Ac ) = 1 P (A).

LEMMA: the probability of the null event. The probability of the null event is
P () = 0.
Proof. Axiom 3 implies that
P (S ) = P (S) + P (),
since S and are disjoint sets by definition, i.e. S = . But also S = S, so
P (S ) = P (S) = 1,
where the second equality is from Axiom 2. Therefore,
P (S ) = P (S) + P () = P (S) = 1,
so P () = 0.
3

THEOREM: independence and the complementary event. If A, B are statistically


independent such that P (A B) = P (A)P (B), then A, B c are also statistically independent
such that P (A B c ) = P (A)P (B c ).
Proof. Consider
A = A (B B c ) = (A B) (A B c ).
The final expression denotes the union of disjoint sets, so there is
P (A) = P (A B) + P (A B c ).
Since, by assumption, there is P (A B) = P (A)P (B), it follows that
P (A B c ) = P (A) P (A B) = P (A) P (A)P (B)
= P (A){1 P (B)} = P (A)P (B c ).

THEOREM: the union of of events. The probability that either A or B will happen or
that both will happen is the probability of A happening plus the probability of B happening
less the probability of the joint occurrence of A and B:
P (A B) = P (A) + P (B) P (A B)
Proof. There is A (B Ac ) = (A B) (A Ac ) = A B, which is to say that A B can
be expressed as the union of two disjoint sets. Therefore, according to axiom 3, there is
P (A B) = P (A) + P (B Ac ).
But B = B (A Ac ) = (B A) (B Ac ) is also the union of two disjoint sets, so there
is also
P (B) = P (B A) + P (B Ac ) = P (B Ac ) = P (B) P (B A).
Substituting the latter expression into the one above gives
P (A B) = P (A) + P (B) P (A B).

BAYES THEOREM
Observe that the formula for conditional probability implies that
whence we

P (A B) = P (A|B)P (B) = P (B|A)P (A),


P (A|B) =

P (B|A)P (A)
.
P (B)

Consider a set = {H1 , H2 , . . . , Hn }, wherein Hi Hj = ; i 6= j, which comprises all possible


explanations of an event E. The evidence of E will cast some light upon the likelihoods of
the hypotheses. The posterior likelihood of an hypothesis Hi in the light of the event E is
P (E|Hi )P (Hi )
, where
P (E)
X
X
P (E) =
P (E Hi ) =
P (E|Hi )P (Hi ).

P (Hi |E) =

We use the following terminology:


P (Hi ) is the prior likelihood of the ith hypothesis Hi ,
P (Hi |E) is the posterior likelihood of the ith hypothesis,

P (E|Hi ) is the conditional probability of the event E under the hypothesis Hi ,


P (E) is the unconditional probability of the event E.
6

A Bayesian Problem. The dawn train collects any milk churns that were left on the
platform of Worplesham station on weekdays. Churns are left on three of the five days. A
man arrives at the station not knowing the exact time and thinking that there is a fifty-fifty
chance that he has missed the train. Then he notices that there are no milk churns on the
platform. How should he reassess the chances that he has missed the train?
Answer: Let T be the event that the train has already passed and let N be the event of
there being no milk churns on the platform when I arrive. We have
P (T |N ) =

P (N |T )P (T )
P (N )

with
P (N ) = P (N |T )P (T ) + P (N |T c )P (T c ).
We take
P (N |T ) = 1,
Then

P (T ) = P (T c ) =

1
2

and P (N |T c ) =

1 2 1
7
P (N ) = 1. + . =
2 5 2
10
1 10
5
and P (T |N ) = 1. .
= .
2 7
7

2
.
5

You might also like