Analytic Approaches To Aesthetics (Oxford Bibliography)
Analytic Approaches To Aesthetics (Oxford Bibliography)
Analytic Approaches To Aesthetics (Oxford Bibliography)
Peter Lamarque
DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195396577-0004
Introduction
Aesthetics is broadly that branch of philosophy concerned with fundamental questions about the nature
of beauty, the nature of art, and the principles of art criticism. Some of these questions go back to the
ancient Greeks, but systematic study of the foundations of aesthetics did not begin until the 18th
century. Analytic philosophers turned their attention to this branch of the subject relatively late and in the
1940s and 50s tended to be scornful of what they found (John Passmore famously wrote of the
dreariness of aesthetics in 1951 in the journal Mind). However, in the fifty years up to the turn of the
21st century, and beyond that point, analytic approaches to aesthetics developed with considerable
sophistication and there is now a huge literature on all aspects of the subject under the broad heading of
analytic aesthetics. Other approaches exist, of course, notably that associated with Continental
philosophy, which is more historically oriented. The analytic approach is rooted in the analysis of
concepts (albeit increasingly informed by work in the empirical sciences) and tends to examine issues
about the nature of art and the aesthetic qualities of objects in an ahistorical manner, even if noting and
evaluating ideas from earlier periods. In the years since the early 1990s there has been a notable
growth in attention to the individual arts (music, painting, literature, film, etc.). Important developments in
the aesthetics of nature and the environment have also occurred.
Anthologies
There are several collections of papers that give a thorough overview of analytical work in aesthetics,
showing the range of topics covered and current thinking about them. Lamarque and Olsen
2003 collects influential papers on analytic aesthetics from its first flowering in the 1950s up to the
present day. Schaper 1983 includes some contributions from analytic philosophers, such as John
McDowell, not usually associated with aesthetics. Gaut and Lopes 2005 and Levinson 2003between
them give fairly comprehensive and even-handed coverage of topics and ideas currently being debated,
written by leading specialists. Kivy 2004 offers longer and more polemical articles again by leading
contemporary figures, each developing and defending a particular point of view.Kieran 2005 usefully
explores core debates using pairs of specially written papers taking different sides on current
issues. Feagin and Maynard 1997 and Neill and Ridley 1995 are large and popular anthologies that
include but extend beyond the analytic, both offering a broader context historically and in terms of
methodology.
Feagin, Susan, and Patrick Maynard, eds. Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1997.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A useful and imaginative selection of papers and extracts with a wide historical and cross-cultural
sweep.
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys, and Dominic McIver Lopes, eds. Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. 2d
ed. London: Routledge, 2005.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Parts II, III, and IV, on, respectively, aesthetic theory, issues and challenges, and the individual arts, are
detailed and accessible studies from an analytical point of view of key issues in aesthetics written by
prominent contemporary philosophers.
Find this resource:
Kieran, Matthew, ed. Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art.
Oxford: Blackwell, 2005.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Helpful format using pairs of commissioned articles taking different sides in current debates. Good for
seminar discussion, revealing where key disagreements lie.
Kivy, Peter, ed. The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics. Oxford: Blackwell, 2004.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A useful collection of eighteen commissioned articles by contemporary aestheticians. The articles
present an overview of an area but also offer sometimes polemical perspectives on their subjects.
Find this resource:
Lamarque, Peter, and Stein Haugom Olsen, eds. Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art:
The Analytic Tradition; an Anthology. Oxford: Blackwell, 2003.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A collection of forty-six papers representing some of the best and most influential work by analytic
philosophers in aesthetics from the 1950s to the present. Introductions to each section give a useful
overview.
Find this resource:
Levinson, Jerrold, ed. Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2003.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Forty-eight specially commissioned articles, at an introductory level, on a wide range of topics in current
aesthetics, under the headings Background, General Issues in Aesthetics, Aesthetic Issues of Specific
Art Forms, and Further Directions in Aesthetics.
Find this resource:
Neill, Alex, and Aaron Ridley, eds. The Philosophy of Art: Readings Ancient and Modern.
New York: McGraw-Hill, 1995.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A judicious wide-ranging selection of material from 20th-century analytical writing back to the ancient
Greeks and also including Hume, Kant, Nietzsche, Tolstoy, Freud, Collingwood, and Adorno, among
others.
Find this resource:
Schaper, Eva, ed. Pleasure, Preference, and Value: Studies in Philosophical Aesthetics.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A collection of commissioned papers by leading analytical philosophers, including John McDowell, Philip
Pettit, R. A. Sharpe, Anthony Savile, Ted Cohen, and Malcolm Budd. At times quite philosophically
demanding.
Find this resource:
Textbooks
There are plenty of general introductions to aesthetics, but not all are specifically focused on analytic
philosophy either in the topics discussed or in methodology. Carroll 1999 and Stecker 2005 are
especially helpful in exemplifying the use of analytical argument to clarify and assess theories about
art. Dickie 1997 is illuminating as a reflection on core themes of analytic aesthetics (also setting them in
their historical context), from an author who has made a major contribution to its development. Graham
2005 also sets the scene well, engaging with other approaches, for example, from Continental
philosophy. Lyas 1997 is a good introduction for beginners in philosophy, with engaging examples and
straightforward exposition. Townsend 1997 is more demanding but full of argument. Neill and Ridley
2007 uses a format that is highly effective for teaching: pairs of articles taking different sides in a debate.
Neill, Alex, and Aaron Ridley, eds. Arguing About Art: Contemporary Philosophical
Debates. 3d ed. London: Routledge, 2007.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Each of the three editions of this influential and useful textbook has contained different selections of
papers. Useful format of juxtaposing articles offering opposing points of view on a range of topics.
Find this resource:
Stecker, Robert. Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: An Introduction. Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield, 2005.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Especially helpful for displaying the analytical mode of argument in aesthetics; careful considerations
are given for and against a wide range of positions with useful summaries at the end of each chapter.
Find this resource:
Landmark Works
There are certain landmark works in the second half of the 20th century that stand out as especially
influential in the development of analytic approaches to aesthetics. Elton 1954 brought together papers
on aesthetics from prominent analytic philosophers; its polemical purpose was to show, in effect, how
aesthetics ought to be done. Beardsley 1958, a large and comprehensive work, illustrated that the
analytic approach need not be small-scale and piecemeal (as some of the contributors in Elton
1954 had suggested); it proposed that aesthetics should be metacriticism, a second-order study of the
principles of art criticism, but actually turned out to be more ambitious than that itself, with a wideranging account of how the arts fit into human life. Sibley 1959 turned attention to aesthetic concepts
applied to art and other objects (and significantly went beyond the 18th-century fixation with beauty
alone). Danto 1964 and Danto 1981 moved in a different direction, away from the aesthetic qualities of
art toward its social or institutional groundings, a move taken up in Dickie 1974 that offered the first fully
worked out institutional definition of art.Goodman 1968 introduced to aesthetics the rigorous style of a
prominent Harvard logician; no adequate theory of pictorial representation could fail to engage with its
controversial view of representation as a mode of denotation. Wollheim 1968 in a concise and readable
form addressed fundamental issues about the ontology of art and the form of life in which it gets its
meaning. Finally, the monumental Walton 1990, offering a unified account of many issues through the
idea of make-believe, is notable not just for its influence in aesthetics but for its impact in other areas
of philosophy (e.g., philosophy of mind and language).
Dickie, George. Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1974.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Presents Dickies original version of the institutional definition of art, which remains influential even
though he refined the theory in later writings.
Find this resource:
Wollheim, Richard. Art and Its Objects: An Introduction to Aesthetics. New York: Harper
and Row, 1968.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Influential reflections on the ontology of art and the role of seeing as in artistic representation by a
preeminent figure in analytic aesthetics. A second edition was published by Cambridge University Press
in 1980 with six supplementary essays developing its central themes.
Find this resource:
Defining Art
It is often thought, though not universally so, that giving a definition of art is a necessary first stage to
any adequate philosophy of art. Efforts in this endeavor are helpfully summarized in Adajian 2007 and,
at greater length, in Davies 1991, which attempts to categorize different kinds of definitions. Weitz
1956 famously argues that the very exercise is misguided, given the creative nature of art. Gaut 2000 is
a bridge between Weitzs anti-essentialism and those that propose full-scale definitions. Other
philosophical works, notably Dickie 1983 and Levinson 1979, have insisted that a definition is possible,
once formulated in the right terms. Carroll 2001 does not think a definition as such is possible, but
proposes an account of how we identify artworks, particularly those of a disputed kind, by means of
narratives connecting them to earlier works. Beardsley 1983offers a definition in terms of aesthetic
experience, although, as he recognizes, Beardsleys account does not readily fit conceptual art or other
kinds of avant-garde works. Carroll 2000 is a collection of papers showing contemporary philosophers
addressing the definitional issue and presenting a state-of-the-art survey of the different candidates on
offer.
Carroll, Nol, ed. Theories of Art Today. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2000.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Twelve essays by prominent contemporary philosophers on different aspects of the definitional issue. A
helpful overview and key text in analytic aesthetics.
Find this resource:
Carroll, Nol. Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art. In Beyond Aesthetics:
Philosophical Essays. By Nol Carroll, 100117. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,
2001.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Defends the idea of identifying artespecially avant-garde artby means of historical narratives that
connect contested works to art history in a way that discloses that the mutations in question are part of
the evolving species of art.
Find this resource:
Davies, Stephen. Definitions of Art. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A wide-ranging critical assessment of different approaches to the definition of art, notably in terms of
functional and procedural theories. Clearly written in nontechnical terms.
Find this resource:
Dickie, George. The New Institutional Theory of Art. Proceedings of the 8th
International Wittgenstein Symposium 10 (1983): 5764.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A succinct statement of the revised version of Dickies influential institutional definition. Shows clearly
what the institutional theory seeks to achieve. Reprinted in Lamarque and Olsen 2003.
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys. Art as a Cluster Concept. In Theories of Art Today. Edited by Nol
Carroll, 2544. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2000.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A version of family resemblance views, arguing that among a cluster of putative features of art, no one
is necessary but all, or a subclass, are sufficient.
Find this resource:
Weitz, Morris. The Role of Theory in Aesthetics. Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism 15 (1956): 2735.
DOI: 10.2307/427491Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Highly influential statement of anti-essentialism, rejecting the attempt to define art, on the grounds that
art is an open concept. Reprinted in Lamarque and Olsen 2003.
Find this resource:
Ontology of Art
The ontology of art raises questions about what kind of thing works of art are, to what ontological
category they belong. A simple and standard view is that there is no single category to which all works
belong but that some works, such as paintings, carved sculptures, and buildings, are particulars (e.g.,
physical objects), whereas other works, such as poems, symphonies, and dramas, are abstract entities
of some kind, allowing for multiple instantiations. Wollheim 1980 importantly explains the latter class by
invoking the distinction between types and tokens; thus, a poem or a symphony is a type, of which
individual copies or performances are tokens. Wolterstorff 1980 offers a variant of this theory, referring
not to types but to norm-kinds. Other philosophers place artworks into a single category. Thus, Currie
1989 sees all works as types, that is, types of action, the action of discovering a structure through a
heuristic path. Davies 2004 takes a similar line, although identifying works with token performances
(art-making). Margolis 1980 sees works of art as emergent entities never identical to their physical
embodiment. Rohrbaugh 2005 offers a detailed survey and assessment of these and other ideas,
and Thomasson 2004 provides judicious comments on how one might arbitrate in the debates.
Thomasson, Amie L. The Ontology of Art. In The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics. Edited
by Peter Kivy, 7892. Oxford: Blackwell, 2004.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Helpful and accessible survey of the key issues, with reflections on the constraints on any adequate
ontological theory.
Find this resource:
Wollheim, Richard. Art and Its Objects. 2d ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1980.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Important work by a prominent philosopher. Uses the type-token distinction to explain the relation
between certain kinds of works and individual copies or performances.
Find this resource:
Zemach, Eddy. Real Beauty. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A thorough-going but technically difficult defense of aesthetic realism.
Find this resource:
Iseminger, Gary, ed. Intention and Interpretation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
1992.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
An important collection of essays on the intention debate in aesthetics, including arguments for and
against actual intentionalism and hypothetical intentionalism.
Find this resource:
Livingston, Paisley. Art and Intention: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2007.
Margolis, Joseph, and Tom Rockmore, eds. The Philosophy of Interpretation. Oxford:
Blackwell, 2000.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Commissioned papers on different aspects of interpretation, offering a broad perspective on the
principal issues.
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys. Art and Knowledge. In Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Edited by Jerrold
Levinson, 436450. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A critical analysis of pro- and anti-cognitivist arguments, defending a pro-cognitivist stance.
Find this resource:
Kieran, Matthew, and Dominic Lopes, eds. Knowing Art: Essays in Aesthetics and
Epistemology. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer, 2007.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A useful collection of papers covering literature and the visual arts and assessing the claims made for
arts cognitive potential.
Find this resource:
Nussbaum, Martha. Loves Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1990.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A selection of Nussbaums essays sharing the general theme that literature can enrich human moral
sensibility and educate the emotions.
Values of Art
Philosophers ask how the values of art relate to other values and also what criteria are available for
making judgments about individual works. The question of whether artistic value can be a subject of
objective reasoning is also prominent. Lamarque 2009 offers general observations about these issues,
and Budd 1995 gives a sophisticated survey of competing theories as well as developing a novel
account. Goldman 1995 also proposes its own subtle view of aesthetic and artistic value. Savile
1982 explains and defends the test of time as a criterion of value. Sibley 2001examines the role of
reasons in aesthetic judgments, but Goldman 2006 argues that such judgments are not subject to
general principles. Gaut 2007 tackles a much debated issue, advancing the case for the relevance of
ethical values in some assessments of aesthetic value.
Budd, Malcolm. Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry, and Music. London: Penguin, 1995.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Important but philosophically demanding book, partly a critical analysis of principal views, partly the
presentation of a specific thesis, defining value in art in terms of the intrinsic values of certain
experiences of art.
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys. Art, Emotion, and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A rigorous and sustained argument for the view that aesthetic evaluations of art can partially rest on
moral evaluations.
Find this resource:
Savile, Anthony. The Test of Time: An Essay in Philosophical Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1982.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A fascinating and richly argued defense of the idea of the test of time as a criterion for artistic value.
Find this resource:
A nuanced discussion of Monroe Beardsleys view that there are general criteria for aesthetic
evaluations, putting forth a limited case for such criteria.
Find this resource:
Music
Prominent issues in the philosophy of music concern musical expressiveness, music and meaning, and
the ontology of music. For an excellent and opinionated overview of the field, the best starting point
is Scruton 1997. Kivy 1993 is a collection of papers by Peter Kivy, a major contributor to all aspects of
the subject. Budd 1985 explores theories of emotion in music in a mostly critical vein but is a good
foundation for subsequent work. Davies 1994 examines meaning in music, usefully identifying the main
issues. Levinson 1980 initiated a large and continuing literature on the ontology of music, notably on the
consequences of taking musical works to be abstract entities.Dodd 2007 is a full-length challenge to
Levinson, even rejecting the view that musical works are strictly created (rather than discovered).
Budd, Malcolm. Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A rigorous analytical study of prominent theories of how music relates to the emotions. Budds criticisms
leave many of these theories in tatters.
Find this resource:
Davies, Stephen. Musical Meaning and Expression. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
1994.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A thorough examination of arguments for and against the view that music is a kind of language.
Find this resource:
Dodd, Julian. Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2007.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A lively but controversial defense of the Platonist idea that musical works are abstract, eternal types, the
tokens of which gain their identity entirely through certain sorts of audible properties.
Find this resource:
Kivy, Peter. The Fine Art of Repetition: Essays in the Philosophy of Music. Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Kivy is a leading analytical philosopher of music and this contains many of his most influential papers,
for example, on musical Platonism, opera, and music and emotion.
Find this resource:
Levinson, Jerrold. What a Musical Work Is. Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 528.
DOI: 10.2307/2025596Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A highly influential essay on musical ontology, sometimes technical in content, arguing that musical
works are abstract entities but also genuinely created, not just discovered. Reprinted in
Levinsons Music, Art, and Metaphysics (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1990).
Find this resource:
Scruton, Roger. The Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Covers all aspects of the philosophy of music in a clear, readable style; written by a prominent
philosopher with a profound knowledge and love of music.
Find this resource:
Pictorial Art
A large amount has been written by philosophers on the nature of depiction, how two-dimensional
pictures can represent objects, real or fictional. The simple idea that pictures represent by resembling
their subject matter has come in for serious criticism, not least in Goodman 1976, although Hopkins
1999 gives a sophisticated reappraisal. Goodman 1976 rejects resemblance in favor of denotation,
and Wollheim 1998 explains representation in terms of a special kind of perception, seeing in,
whereas Lopes 1996 focuses on the relation between representation and interpretation. Walton
2008 famously appeals to games of make-believe in the perception of pictures and argues for the
transparency of photography. Scruton 1983 controversially argues that photographs are not
representations at all. Dutton 1983 is a fascinating collection of papers on forgery that in different ways
reveal important aspects of pictures and why they are valued.
Dutton, Denis, ed. The Forgers Art: Forgery and the Philosophy of Art. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1983.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
An important and engaging collection of essays, including extracts from Nelson GoodmansLanguages
of Art, in which he distinguishes arts that are autographic (i.e., forgeable) from the allographic (i.e.,
nonforgeable).
Find this resource:
Lopes, Dominic McIver. Understanding Pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A thoughtful and original study of many aspects of pictorial representation, including what it is to
recognize an object in a picture.
Find this resource:
Walton, Kendall L. Marvelous Images: On Values and the Arts. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2008.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A handy selection of Waltons papers in aesthetics, including six important contributions on pictures and
photography.
Find this resource:
Literature
For a good overview of topics in the philosophy of literature, see Davies 2007, Lamarque 2009,
and John and Lopes 2004. Olsen 1987 positions literary aesthetics in relation to literary theory and
takes a polemical stand in favor of an institutional view of literature. Lamarque and Olsen 1994 is a
lengthy treatment of the issue of how fiction and literature relate to truth. Searle 1979 is an important
paper on the logic of fiction, applying speech act theory, and Radford 1975 offers an entertaining and
extensively debated argument that it is irrational to respond emotionally to fictional characters.
John, Eileen, and Dominic M. Lopes, eds. Philosophy of Literature: Contemporary and
Classic Readings; an Anthology. Oxford: Blackwell, 2004.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
An accessible collection of forty-five essays and extracts, by prominent philosophers, covering all
aspects of the philosophy of literature.
Find this resource:
Lamarque, Peter, and Stein Haugom Olsen. Truth, Fiction, and Literature: A
Philosophical Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A detailed examination of the role of truth in relation to literature, arguing that truth is not a primary
literary value.
Find this resource:
Olsen, Stein Haugom. The End of Literary Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1987.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A collection of Olsens papers on literary aesthetics, showing pioneering work in the analytic tradition.
Find this resource:
Radford, Colin. How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina? Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society 69 (1975): 6780.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
An entertaining and controversial paper arguing that although it is quite natural, it is also irrational to
become emotionally involved with characters we know to be fictional. Reprinted in Lamarque and Olsen
2003.
Find this resource:
Searle, John. The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse. In Expression and Meaning.
By John Searle, 5875. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1979.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Applies speech act theory to fiction, arguing that fiction writers pretend to perform illocutionary acts,
without intended deception.
Find this resource:
Carroll, Nol. A Philosophy of Mass Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A magisterial treatment of a complex and controversial subject, the status and value of popular arts. It
takes on much current theorizing, for example, in cultural studies, and presents a compelling alternative
using the methods of analytic philosophy.
Find this resource:
Sparshott, Francis. Dance: Bodies in Motion, Bodies at Rest. In The Blackwell Guide
to Aesthetics. Edited by Peter Kivy, 276290. Oxford: Blackwell, 2004.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Sketches in a readable manner a framework for a philosophy of dance and the sorts of questions that
arise.
Find this resource:
Berleant, Arnold, and Allen Carlson, eds. The Aesthetics of Natural Environments.
Peterborough, ON: Broadview, 2004.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A useful and accessible collection of essays, old and new, on all aspects of this branch of aesthetics.
Find this resource:
Budd, Malcolm. The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2002.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
A collection of Budds own influential papers on the aesthetics of nature. Sometimes demanding in their
analytical style but always rewarding.
Find this resource:
Carlson, Allen. Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art, and
Architecture. London: Routledge, 2000.
Save Citation Export Citation E-mail Citation
Carlson is one of the foremost aestheticians writing on the aesthetics of nature. This book consolidates
his own influential position and reflects judiciously on current debates in the subject.
Find this resource: