Spiritual Titanism-Indian, Chinese, and Western Perspectives
Spiritual Titanism-Indian, Chinese, and Western Perspectives
Spiritual Titanism-Indian, Chinese, and Western Perspectives
SUNY Series in
Constructive Postmodern Thought
David Ray Giffin, editor
David Ray Griffin, editor, The Reenchantment of Science: Postmodern
Proposals
David Ray Giffin, editor, Spirituality and Society: Postmodern Visions
David Ray Giffin, God and Religion in the Postmodern World: Essays in
Postmodern Theology
David Ray Giffin, William A. Beardslee, and Joe Holland, Varieties of
Postmodern Theology
David Ray Giffin and Huston Smith, Primordial Truth and Postmodern
Theology
David Ray Giffin, editor, Sacred Interconnections: Postmodern Spirituality,
Political Economy, and Art
Robert Inchausti, The Ignorant Perfection of Ordinary People
David W. Orr, Ecological Literacy: Education and the Transition to a
Postmodern World
David Ray Griffin, John B. Cobb Jr., Marcus P. Ford, Pete A. Y. Gunter,
and Peter Ochs, Founders of Constructive Postmodern Philosophy:
Peirce, James, Bergson, Whitehead, and E. A. Hartshorne
David Ray Griffin and Richard A. Falk, editors, Postmodern Politics for a
Planet in Crisis: Policy, Process, and Presidential Vision
Steve Odin, The Social Self in Zen and American Pragmatism
Frederick Ferr, Being and Value: Toward a Constructive Postmodern
Metaphysics
Frederick Ferr, Knowing and Value: Toward a Constructive Postmodern
Epistemology
Sandra B. Lubarsky and David Ray Griffin, editors, Jewish Theology and
Process Thought
David Ray Griffin, Parapsychology, Philosophy, and Spirituality: A
Postmodern Exploration
Jay Earley, Transforming Human Culture: Social Evolution and the
Planetary Crisis
Daniel A. Dombrowski, Kazantzakis and God
E. M. Adams, A Society Fit for Human Beings
Jerry H. Gill, The Tacit Mode: Michael Polanyis Postmodern Philosophy
SPIRITUAL TITANISM
Nicholas F. Gier
Published by
State University of New York Press, Albany
2000 State University of New York
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner
whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may
be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by
any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape,
mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the
prior permission in writing of the publisher.
For information, address State University of New York Press,
State University Plaza, Albany, N.Y., 12246
Production by Diane Ganeles
Marketing by Fran Keneston
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Gier, Nicholas F., 1944
Spiritual titanism : Indian, Chinese, and Western perspectives /
Nicholas F. Gier.
p. cm. (SUNY series in constructive postmodern thought)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0791445275 (hardcover : alk. paper)
ISBN 0791445283 (pbk. : alk. paper)
1. ReligionPhilosophy. 2. Superman (Philosophical concept)
3. Philosophy, Comparative. 4. Religions. 5. Hinduism
Philosophy. I. Title. II. Series
BL51.G625 2000
291.2'13dc21
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
99-038494
The majestic aloofness of the perfected, balanced, absolutely selfcontained figure of the [Jaina] saint becomes emphasized in its triumphant isolation. The image of the released one seems to be
neither animate nor inanimate, but pervaded by a strange and timeless calm. It is human in shape and feature, yet as inhuman as an
icicle; . . . [the saint] stands supernally motionless, absolutely unconcerned about the worshipping, jubilant crowds that throng
around his feet.
Heinrich Zimmer, Philosophies of India
Contents
PREFACE
xi
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
xvii
INTRODUCTION
Introduction
The Titans: Superhuman and Superdivine
Uttaravada versus Avataravada
Summaries of the Chapters
Nietzsches bermensch Not a Titan
1
2
9
12
17
23
Introduction
Humanism and Superhumanism
Existentialism and Titanism
Christian Titanism and the Incarnation
Western Answers to Titanism
23
24
27
29
33
vii
39
39
40
45
48
51
54
56
viii
Contents
59
59
60
67
72
76
79
79
80
82
83
85
90
92
97
99
Introduction
Types of Indian Titanism
Yoga Titanism
The Purus.a Hymn and its Legacy
The Purus.a as Cosmic Yogi
Monism, Ecology, and Titanism
99
100
102
104
108
109
113
113
114
114
117
120
127
130
134
136
Contents
NTA AND
CHAPTER SEVEN: NEO-VEDA
AUROBINDOS SUPERMAN
Introduction
Ramakrishna: Kali s Child
Vivekanandas Manly Neo-Vedanta
Supermind, Superman, and Supernature
Conclusions
ix
139
139
140
145
148
155
157
Introduction
Buddhist Humanism
The Buddha Is Just the Buddha
The Buddha as Maha
purisa
The Cosmological Buddha of Mahayana
The Siddhas: Buddhas Lions
Zen, the Body, and Society
Conclusions
157
158
161
163
164
167
171
176
177
177
178
184
189
191
Introduction
Xunzi, Tian, and the Cosmic Triad
Is Xunzi a Technological Titan?
Machle: Xunzi Not a Titan
Neo-Confucianism and Titanism
Self, Body, and Society
191
192
195
199
201
205
207
Introduction
Purus.a and Panku
Immortality and the Immortals
Zhuangzi and Postmodernism
207
208
212
215
Contents
Zhuangzi and the Perfect Person
Zhuangzi and Nietzsche
The Triumph of the Confucian Sage
221
226
233
NOTES
237
SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY
283
INDEX
297
Preface
What matters most for India is not so much the salvation of the personality as the acquisition of absolute
freedom.
Mircea Eliade1
In the millennium to come we are meant to become
Gods on other planets. This is the great potential of our
Divinity.
Gopi Krishna2
The whole ascetic tradition . . . springs from that most
polluted of all sources, the Satanic sin of pride, the desire to be like gods. We are not gods, we are social irrational animals, designed to become rational, social
animals. . . .
R. C. Zaehner3
The idea for this book arose out of an insight I had about the use
of the term humanism by the Religious Right. The typical conservative Christian describes a humanist as one who attempts to move
God aside and to take Gods place. For such a Christian, humanism
is Titanism, a worldview in which human beings take on divine attributes and divine prerogatives. (The Religious Right is especially
keen on maintaining Gods right to set the laws of human conduct.)
As I show in chapter 1, some existentialists express a form of Titanism, but the Religious Rights blanket condemnation does a gross
injustice to more moderate forms of humanism, which include Christian humanists as diverse as Aquinas, Erasmus, the American
Founding Fathers, and C. S. Lewis.4 Over the twenty-five years that
I have taught Indian philosophy and religion, I have been struck by
xi
xii
Preface
Preface
xiii
xiv
Preface
Preface
xv
Acknowledgments
This project began in the early 1980s and in 1984 I had occasion
to speak with Wendy Doniger about the anthropomorphism of the
Purus.a hymn and her encouragement on the first draft of chapter 5
and frequent consultations on specific textual and linguistic matters
were greatly appreciated. Donigers thorough scholarship and creative insights have been a great inspiration to me.
I wish to thank the University of Idaho for granting me a sabbatical leave in 199293 to study in India, China, and Japan. During
the summer of 1992 the Department of Philosophy at the Chinese
University of Hong Kong was kind enough to provide me with library
privileges to research chapter 9. I am grateful to Chen Lai of Beijing
University and Tang Yi of Beijings Institute of World Religions for
helping me with Menciuss use of the word shen as discussed in chapter 9. I also thank Father Thomas Manninezhath for inviting me to
Dharmaram College, Bangalore, India, where in the fall of 1992 I
was a visiting scholar. In the winter and spring of 1993 Doshisha
University, Otani University, and the NCC Center for the Study of
Japanese Religion in Kyoto and the Nanzan Institute of Religion and
Culture in Nagoya kindly allowed me to use their excellent libraries.
While on leave in 1995 I was the guest of the Department of
Studies in Religion at the University of Queensland, where I consulted with their Asian specialistsN. Ross Reat and Rod Bucknelland was given access to their superb library. The last part of
1995 was spent in Bangalore where I worked in the library of United
Theological College. I am very grateful to the people in Brisbane and
Bangalore who aided me in my research.
P. S. Jaini of the University of California at Berkeley was particularly helpful in making comments on a draft of chapter 4. Graham Parkes of the University of Hawaii gave me encouragement in
my Nietzsche research. I owe a great deal to P. J. Ivanhoe of the University of Michigan, who read the last three chapters thoroughly and
who offered insightful suggestions. He and Paul Kjellberg of Whittier College are responsible for my new passion for Zhuangzi. I was
xvii
xviii
Acknowledgments
Acknowledgments
xix
The rapid spread of the term postmodern in recent years witnesses to a growing dissatisfaction with modernity and to an increasing sense that the modern age not only had a beginning but can
have an end as well. Whereas the word modern was almost always
used until quite recently as a word of praise and as a synonym for
contemporary, a growing sense is now evidenced that we can and
should leave modernity behindin fact, that we must if we are to
avoid destroying ourselves and most of the life on our planet.
Modernity, rather than being regarded as the norm for human
society toward which all history has been aiming and into which all
societies should be usheredforcibly if necessaryis instead increasingly seen as an aberration. A new respect for the wisdom of
traditional societies is growing as we realize that they have endured
for thousands of years and that, by contrast, the existence of modern
civilization for even another century seems doubtful. Likewise, modernism as a worldview is less and less seen as the Final Truth, in
comparison with which all divergent worldviews are automatically
regarded as superstitious. The modern worldview is increasingly
relativized to the status of one among many, useful for some purposes, inadequate for others.
Although there have been antimodern movements before, beginning perhaps near the outset of the nineteenth century with the
Romanticists and the Luddites, the rapidity with which the term
postmodern has become widespread in our time suggests that the antimodern sentiment is more extensive and intense than before, and
also that it includes the sense that modernity can be successfully
overcome only by going beyond it, not by attempting to return to a
premodern form of existence. Insofar as a common element is found
*The present version of this introduction is slightly different from the first
version, which was contained in the volumes that appeared prior to 2000.
My thanks to Catherine Keller and Edward Carlos Munn for helpful suggestions.
xxi
xxii
Series Introduction
*The fact that the thinkers and movements named here are said to have inspired the deconstructive type of postmodernism should not be taken, of
course, to imply that they have nothing in common with constructive postmodernists. For example, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Derrida, and Deleuze
share many points and concerns with Alfred North Whitehead, the chief inspiration behind the present series. Furthermore, the actual positions of the
founders of pragmatism, especially William James and Charles Peirce, are
much closer to Whiteheads philosophical positionsee the volume in this
series entitled The Founders of Constructive Postmodern Philosophy: Peirce,
James, Bergson, Whitehead, and Hartshornethan they are to Richard
Rortys so-called neopragmatism, which reflects many ideas from Rortys explicitly physicalistic period.
Series Introduction
xxiii
xxiv
Series Introduction
Series Introduction
xxv
xxvi
Series Introduction
Introduction
Introduction
It is truly ironic that the most famous gods of the worlds religionsGautama, Kr. s.n.a, and Jesusbegan their religious careers
as human beings. In his sermons Gautama Buddha made it clear
that he had come only to teach the Dharma and that his disciples
were not to worship him as a god or a savior. Although a few commentators choose to read divine attributes into the earliest reference, the Chandogya Upanis.ad describes Kr. s.n.a as a man, the son of
Vasudeva and Devaki .4 The Jesus of the Synoptic Gospels speaks of
himself as a good Jew would, making a clear distinction between
Spiritual Titanism
himself and God. Once he rebuked those who called him good, for no
one is good but God alone.5 An early and widespread Christology
was adoptionism, the view that Jesus was just a human being, approved and adopted by God at his baptism.
It is doubly ironic that Kr. s.n.a and Gautama actually became
higher than the Vedic gods: the Buddha is called God beyond the
gods (devati deva) and Kr. s.n.a becomes the highest expression of divinity, surpassing even Brahman itself. Already in some Upanis.ads
the divine person (purus.a) exceeds everything, including Brahman,
and Kr. s.n.a is the culmination of this Vedic personalism. In some
Christian sects, God the Father seems almost totally displaced by
the worship of Jesus. (During the Protestant Reformation this
heresy was called Jesuologie and some mainstream Protestants considered it a form of atheism.) At the World Congress of Religions in
1893, Swami Vivekananda defended the atheism of Buddhism and
Jainism by arguing that it is perfectly legitimate to evolve God out
of man. He then presented what appears to be the Buddhology
equivalent of Jesuologie: They have not seen the Father, but they
have seen the Son.6 We shall see shortly how Vivekanandas
Vedantist assumptions lead to an alternative interpretation of this
passage.
Introduction
ertion.)8 The Greek Titans were known for their boundless pride
(hubris) and for their violence (atasthale). Titanism is humanism
gone berserk; it is anthropocentricism and anthropomorphism
taken to their limits. The Titan insists that human experience is
the norm. Titans deliberately reverse the positions of humanity
and divinity; they take over divine prerogatives, and as a result of
their hubris, they lose sight of their proper place in the universe.
This book will define a deity as any being who is omniscient, omnipotent, infinite, and omnipresent. We maintain that a human
being is a spiritual Titan by claiming any or all of these attributes.
Even if there is no God, humans obviously delude themselves if
they believe that they can become divine in the sense of these attributes.
Following Zimmers lead, we will identify five types of Indian Titanism. The first is Asura Titanism, discussed in chapter 3, in which
the asuras (demons, antigods, or Titans) constantly battle the Hindu
gods. The second is Brahmin Titanism, in which the priests take
over the divine power of the sacrifice. The third is Gnostic Titanism,
in which humans contend that they have perfect knowledge. The
fourth is Yoga Titanism, in which yogis claim to have divine powers
by the practice of austerities. (Gnostic and Yoga Titanism are intimately linked in Jainism, where yogic discipline leads to absolute
knowledge. But they are separate in Sam
. khya-Yoga, where the practice leads to spiritual liberation but knowledge without content, and
in Puranic mythology where the practice of austerities leads to great
power not knowledge.) Finally, there is Bhakti Titanism, in which
humans such as Kr. s.n.a are bestowed with powers of universal redemption. The common thread throughout these five forms of Titanism is a determined attempt to acquire and to monopolize total
power.
Except for the violent asura-deva conflict, Indian Titanism has
expressed itself almost exclusively in an internal, spiritual way;
therefore, one can say that it is a rather benign form of extreme humanism. By contrast, the expressions of Western Titanism are primarily external, and with the aid of technology, a Titanistic spirit
can be said to inspire militarism, environmental pollution and
degradation, and the possible misuse of genetic engineering. If left
unchecked, Titanism might destroy or radically change life as we
know it on earth. Even though it is technological Titanism that poses
the real threat, it is essential to show that Indian Titans share some
of the same views as their Western counterparts, namely, anthropocentrism and autonomous selfhood. Some Indian views of self
Spiritual Titanism
Introduction
Spiritual Titanism
dared peril which he had not weighed; Prometheus devoted
himself to sorrows which he had foreknown. . . . The Satan of
Milton and the Prometheus of Aeschylus stand upon ground
as unequal as do the sublime of sin and the sublime of
virtue.16
Introduction
Spiritual Titanism
creature can exist without death.24 The great asura Mahis.a makes
the same request, but Brahma states that birth must be followed by
death, and death must be followed by birth; this is the eternal law of
nature.25 Even the Vedantist who unequivocally affirms an eternal
human essence realizes that this truth is expressed in a very particular way. They know the difference between the Upanis.adic truth I
am Brahman (as A tman) and the untruth and blasphemy of I am
Isvara, namely, the creator of the universe.26 The first expression is
the only way in which humans can claim immortality, while the second is a clear expression of spiritual Titanism.
The divinization of humanity and the origins of Indian Titanism
most likely have pre-Aryan roots in traditions we now know as
Sam
. khya, Yoga, and Jainism. It is by the perfection of yogic practices
that humans such as Divodasa are best able to challenge the preeminence of the gods. It is no coincidence that the Puran.ic writers
blame a Jaina monk for teaching Vena the blasphemy of making
himself divine.27 (The sages call Venas claim to divinity nonsensical.)28 Padmanabh S. Jaini observes that in the Vedic tradition divine attributes were imputed to humans only in a secondary sense,
and that one looks in vain for even one such reference [divine attributes in the primary sense] in the entire Brahmanical literature,
including the Upanis.ads.29 He also contends that the deification of
Mahavi ra and the Buddha was certainly a unique phenomenon in
the entire history of human civilization.30 Contrary to Jaini, I believe that we can find deification in the primary sense in the Upanis.ads, and one would also have to place Kr. s.n.a and Christ alongside
the Buddha and Mahavi ra.
In his book Presuppositions of Indian Philosophy Karl H. Potter
not only confirms my hypothesis about conceptual similarities between Indian anthropocentrism and the Greek Sophists homo mensura, but he also focuses on the hubris of the Indian yogis. Maintaining that Sam
. khya-Yoga is excessively anthropomorphic and
agreeing with Zimmer that asceticism is an expression of an extreme will for power,31 Potter states:
Indian philosophy does in fact elevate power, control or freedom to a supereminent position . . . the ultimate value . . . is
not morality but freedom . . . complete control over ones environmentsomething which includes self-control but also
includes control of others and even control of the physical
sources of power in the universe.32
Introduction
10
Spiritual Titanism
Introduction
11
12
Spiritual Titanism
Introduction
13
14
Spiritual Titanism
the divine man is replaced by a cosmic yogi, who, Titan-like, produces the universe by means of his own yogic powers. The desire to
become father of oneself is one of the general features of the psychology of Titanism, and the idea of a human being creating himself,
the universe, and the gods is the ultimate expression of extreme humanism. The male Titan also appears to be appropriating the creative power previously invested in the Goddess.
One could say that Titanism is predominantly a male problem.
It seems that, using Jungian terms, our animus leads us to overstep
boundaries (societal, natural, and spiritual) and our anima brings us
back into balance. Chapter 6 focuses on Sakta philosophy and analyzes this gender dynamic in the Indian context. In the later expressions of the Sam
. khya-Yoga dualism of purus.a (spirit person) and
prakr.ti (nature, matter) the former is represented as masculine and
the latter as feminine; indeed, prakr.ti is one of primary philosophical designations of the Hindu Goddess. The goal of yogic practice is
for each spirit to obtain final release from nature and to achieve par
excellence with Isvara the Lord, the only spirit not to have been entrapped in the material world.
One can observe several interesting and ironic implications in
Sam
. khya-Yoga philosophy. The yogic ideal involves a Titanistic effort to break all ties with nature, but the result is an entity who is totally isolated (there is no union with I svara), static, and impotent.
Dynamic power, interrelation, and the riches of experience lie with
nature and with her alone. This spirit-nature dualism was later infused into the Puran.ic literature, especially into the Sakta works,
where the power of male gods is female power (sakti). Furthermore,
many stories portray inactive male deities (e.g., the sleeping Vis.n.u),
whose duties are taken over by activist goddesses. In general it is the
Hindu Goddess who brings the Indian spiritual life back to earth,
back to the body, and back to ordinary human relations. Traditional
goddess theology, however, was always under the control of kings
and priests, so we will find that the Goddess does not always speak
with a feminine voice. Until recent times Indian kings call on her as
they went to war and the priests recited her scriptures only to males.
The only Indian writer who uses the words Titan and superman is Sri Aurobindo. He uses these words favorably and in his
works he outlines the evolution of a superrace of spiritual beings. Although in his attempt to distance himself from Nietzsche he misinterprets the idea of bermensch, Aurobindos own philosophy avoids
most of the liabilities of Titanism primarily because of his commitment to a social self and to the concept of feminine power. The bal-
Introduction
15
16
Spiritual Titanism
Introduction
17
18
Spiritual Titanism
called Thou Shalt, who rules over the camel, the first metamorphosis.
The lion takes every It was or it happened to me and transforms it
into a Thus I willed it and shall will it for eternity. Even though necessary and liberating, the lions work is ultimately negative and destructive. (The lion is called thief as well as predator and this might
provide a link to Prometheus stealing fire to create a new humanity.)
The lion opens up unlimited freedom and is thus effective in destroying old values; but because of his nihilism he is incapable of creating
new values. The Promethean No of the lion must be replaced by the
sacred Yes of the child, the third metamorphosis, which I believe is
Nietzsches answer to Titanism. The child, as Nietzsche says, is innocence and forgetting, a new beginning, a game [of creation], a selfpropelled wheel, a first movement, a sacred Yes.45
The Titan is a false bermensch, the superman of popular, but
distorted Nietzschean interpretation. The true bermensch knows
the meaning of the earth . . . I beseech you, my brothers, says
Zarathustra, remain faithful to the earth, and do not believe those
who speak to you of other worldly hopes. In former times the greatest sin was against God, but to sin against the earth is now the
most dreadful thing.46 The bergang of the bermensch is also an
Untergang; and she overcomes herself so that she is over herself,
not the world or other people. (Actually the play of bergang and
Untergang works out much better in a Daoist context, where the
sages overcoming always appears as underachieving and self-effacing.) Many of the metaphors of the bermensch are horizontal and
immanent, rather than vertical and transcendentfor instance,
Man is a rope, tied between beast and over mana rope over an
abyss.47 bermenschen never transcend their animal natures, because, as Graham Parkes observes: It is impossible to go over unless
the rope is held in tension; and if one casts off behind and loses the
connection back to ones animal past there will be nothing to prevent
a plunge into the abyss.48 bermenschen appear to be true ecological beings: in their Untergang humankind will prepare earth, animal, and plant for [them].49 The Overman is a person of the elements: he is the sense of the earth and also a sea so clean that it
will redeem a polluted humanity.50
Parkes proposes that we conceive of the Three Metamorphoses as
a dialectical triad of immersion, detachment, and reintegration.51A
person of the first stage is immersed in society and nature without
any clear delineation of self and other. People at this stage typically
take on the values that are given them, hence Nietzsches image of a
camel carrying the burdens of a herd morality. Persons in the second
Introduction
19
20
Spiritual Titanism
Introduction
21
the bermensch) must stress the point that all ideal human types
are culturally conditioned. One only needs to be reminded of two examples: Aristotles great souled man, a propertied male beaming
with pride, and with the Nazi interpretation of the bermensch. This
means that the lumpers would be hard-pressed, considering the
great variety of historical preferences, to agree on a single set of
virtues for the bermensch. Indeed, Nietzsches choice of ancient
warrior virtues is a source of constant irritation for even his most enthusiastic readers.
Magnus proposes that instead of seeing the bermensch as a
normative ideal, we should see it as a particular attitude toward life,
in which a person
would crave nothing more fervently than the eternal recurrence of each and every one of lifes moments. . . an bermensch cannot lie or imagine his life under erasure, edited,
emended in this way or that. Rather an bermensch must
love each and every moment of life unconditionally.58
Magnuss view of the Overman fits very nicely with a noncosmological interpretation of eternal recurrence, one that I have always
supported. Nietzsche did not want us to subscribe literally to a cosmology of eternal return; he only wanted us to live as if every moment of our lives would come back again. His pseudoscientific speculations notwithstanding, Nietzsche is using scare tactics; the terror
of eternal recurrence (Zarathustras most dreadful thought) is a psychological ploy to eliminate self-deception, to force us to love our
lives, and to get us to take full responsibility for ourselves. The most
that eternal return can mean psychologically is that we can expect to
be faced with many similar events in our lives and the sooner we remove the shackles of bad faith the better off we shall be. The most
that eternal return can mean cosmologically is that the universe has
no ultimate meaningin part or as a whole.
Whether we are lumpers or splitters we should all agree that the
bermensch is no Titan. (Even Magnuss suggestion that the bermensch is an inverted secular god equivalent does not mean that
the Overman takes on divine attributes.) This is not only clear in the
strong implication that the Overman is the child, but also in the
more indirect indication that all people, regardless of mental or
physical powers/appearances, can overcome themselves. Both the
Zhuangzi and Zarathustra play host to large numbers of strange
characters, many of them crippled and deformed. For Zhuangzi the
22
Spiritual Titanism
Titanism
in the West
Introduction
In American culture humanism has not been a term widely used
until the 1980s, when the Religious Right began to employ it to execrate everything that it is against. It used to be that all of Americas
ills were blamed on a Communist conspiracy, but now this has been
replaced with a humanist conspiracy. Humanists are being targeted as the one source of every evil, from homosexuality to oneworld government. This attack is truly incredible if one considers the
fact that humanism is one of the greatest achievements of Western
civilization. The humanism of Socrates has become the basis for ethical individualism; the humanism of the Greek Sophists gave law its
adversarial system and inspired Renaissance humanists to extend
education to the masses as well as to the aristocracy; the Christian
humanism of Aquinas and Erasmus helped temper negative views of
human nature found in the biblical tradition; and the humanism of
23
24
Spiritual Titanism
the Enlightenment gave us political rights, representative government, and free market economics.
Most of the distortion of the humanist tradition has come from
the Religious Right, but equal blame must go to some secular humanists who insist that only their views are true humanism. These
humanists, fundamentalists, and too many knowledgeable Christians continue to believe that all humanists are atheists. Humanists
are most often described as those who attempt to move God aside
and to take Gods place; in other words, the Religious Right conceives
of all humanists as Titans. Such a view simply does an injustice to
the Western humanist tradition, which, since Plato and Aristotle,
has been dominated by confirmed theists and moderate humanists.
Secular humanism has its origins in Protagoras and in his belief that
human beings are the measure of all things. This was definitely a
minority tradition until the Enlightenment, but even then theistic
humanists like the American Founding Fathers still prevailed. It
has only been during the last two centuries that secular humanism
has made any progress, culminating in our time with atheistic existentialism and other secular philosophies.
25
26
Spiritual Titanism
27
28
Spiritual Titanism
29
30
Spiritual Titanism
rogatives. In short, there is for Kant a little god, or Titan, in each one
of us. Kants moral rationalism can be seen as the fulfillment of Aristotles belief that reason is divine and that life according to it is divine in comparison with human life.19
Thinkers with any respect for logic must strongly disagree with
Sartres contention that there is no difference between being an absolute, temporally localized and being God.20 Sartre is obviously
contradicting himself: an absolute cannot be temporally localized.
Even if there were no God, this does not mean that we can take on
divine attributes. But if God exists, then the logic of divinity requires
that we acknowledge an ontological difference between Creator and
creature, between a necessary, infinite being and contingent, finite
beings. This is the thrust of the Hebraic principle in the Judeo-Christian (as well as in the Zoroastrian and Islamic) tradition. Jewish and
Christian thinkers might, therefore, contend that the lesson of the
Garden, the moral of the story of Job, and other examples of Gods
sovereign control offer the best defense against Titanism.
Even though the Bible warns against extreme humanismeven,
some might say, humanism in any formthis does not mean that
those who interpret biblical teachings were immune from Titanism. In
fact, in the Judeo-Christian tradition, it was only the Sadducees who
strictly adhered to the Hebraic principle. Along with the Pharisees, the
Sadducees rejected the Christian idea of Incarnation (to them a pagan
mixing of human and divine), but the Sadducees, unlike the Pharisees,
also eschewed the resurrection of the body and eternal life. In addition
to rejecting any idea of incarnation (the humanization of God), a truly
Hebraic theology must also avoid any divinization of humans by
granting them the divine attribute of immortality. Both concepts involve a clear violation of the Hebraic principle. In rejecting an immortal soul, the Sadducees were being loyal to a preexilic Hebrew tradition that the human soul was thoroughly mortal and corruptible.
Furthermore, references to bodily resurrection and to eternal life, except for a few obscure passages in the Psalms, do not appear until after
the Babylonian captivity. For the preexilic Hebrews, all human beings,
regardless of virtue or vice, went to Sheol, the Hebrew equivalent of
the Greek Hades. Walter Brueggemann finds the strongest biblical humanism in the Wisdom literature.21 Here Brueggemann discovers a
reaffirmation of the preexilic belief that being human is all there is
as contrasted with the orthodox doctrine that being human is just a
stage in our goal of becoming angels or gods.
At this point the intimate relationship between the two major
violations of the Hebraic principleour own divinization and the humanization of Godbecomes clear. In his De Incarnatione Athana-
31
sius proclaimed that the Logos became man so that we might become God.22 This is not just an erratic comment on Athanasius part,
because we can read in Thomist Etienne Gilson that by the grace of
the Incarnation, which made human nature divine, we can have
friendship with God because we can live with Him.23 Drawing on
Kirilovs point that the God-man is not the same as the man-god,
some might claim that the doctrine of Incarnation is a sort of reverse Titanism. (There is some truth in this contention, and that
will be discussed at the end of this section.) Incarnational theologies
might be yet another Promethean way to humble and to humiliate
Godto manipulate God for our own project of divinization. (The
subordination of God is particularly evident in the concept of keno sis,
in which God empties himself and takes on the form of a servant.)24
The humanization of God through incarnation could be just another
example of the vanity of our species. It becomes a vindication of
Xenophanes dictum that all creatures make gods in their own image.
The English debate on the Incarnation in the late 1970s offers
some evidence for this hypothesis. Michael Green, editor of The
Truth of God Incarnate and leading critic of the liberals of The Myth
of God Incarnate, quotes Michael Ramsey favorably: God is Christlike, and in him is no un-Christ-likeness at all.25 Christ is the New
Testament equivalent of the Hebrew Messiah, which was originally
the name for the future warrior-king who would destroy the enemies
of Israel and set up Gods kingdom on earth. Although Messiah
meant much more than this for most early Christians, it is nonetheless significant that contemporary evangelical Christians choose to
characterize the entire nature of God in terms of this human concept.
When Green demands a revelation of [God] that necessarily
corresponds to this real nature,26 he is essentially saying that Gods
real nature is somehow basically human. Confirming my point about
Xenophanes, Green argues that God deign[ed] to show me what he
was like in terms I could understand, the terms of a human life.27
Joining Green against the liberals in the incarnation debate, Brian
Hebblethwaite argues against John Hicks idea of multiple worldwide incarnations: For only one man can actually be God to us, if
God himself is one. . . . And the Son, we discover, is very God of very
God, Gods human face, reflecting Gods own glory, and bearing the
stamp of his nature.28 Are these conservative evangelical Christians
implicitly agreeing with Vivekananda that it is legitimate to evolve
God out of man?
Among the liberals it is Don Cupitt who best unveils the profound
mistakes of the literal incarnationists. Significantly, it is Cupitt who
best expresses the Hebraic principle in The Myth of God Incarnate.
32
Spiritual Titanism
Cupitt contends that a literal incarnation made it easy for the Church
to substitute a worship of Christ for the worship of God. This development was subtle, but deeply rooted, and broke through dramatically in
the Christocentrism of the Reformation. As Cupitt states:
Perhaps it was only when Christocentric religion finally toppled over into the absurdity of Christian Atheism that
some Christians began to realize that Feuerbach [and Xenophanes] might have been right after all; Chalcedonian Christology could be a remote ancestor of modern unbelief, by
beginning the process of shifting the focus of devotion from
God to man . . . . [Chalcedon led to] a cult of humanity. Similarly, it could not resist the giving of the title theotokos,
Mother of God, to Mary. The phrase Mother of God is prima
facie blasphemous.29
This is yet another aspect of the Christian project of humanizing God.
While American fundamentalists agree with these English evangelicals about a literal Incarnation, they violate the Hebraic principle in another way. Many in the Religious Right preempt Gods role
in the universe by making judgments for God. The most famous example of this, of course, is Jerry Falwells claim that God does not answer the prayers of Jews. More general, however, is the tendency for
fundamentalists to identify who the real Christians areusually
themselves. In his incisive Religious Right and Christian Faith,
Gabriel Fackre charges that fundamentalists who attempt to attain
Gods goals through political means are actually embracing a humanist ideology. Insofar as fundamentalists are attempting to do
Gods work for him in the world, they are just as humanist as the secularists they have railed against. Not unlike the ancient Gnostics,
the fundamentalists claim infallible knowledge in all things spiritual. This claim is obviously an expression of Gnostic Titanism, and
combined with the gnostic axiom of biblical inerrancy, it allows fundamentalists to profess to know what God exactly said and what God
actually wants us to do.
In the evangelical rationalism of Ronald H. Nash and Gordon H.
Clark, who resurrect the Logos doctrine of the early Church Fathers,
we find the claim that, insofar as the divine Logos is in the human
imago dei, we are able to think Gods thoughts after him.30 Especially
striking is the following motto by Stuart C. Hackett, another evangelical rationalist: I think, Therefore God is.31 Titanistic elements
in fundamentalism also appear among the creationists, who presume
to know, for example, that the search for extraterrestrial life is un-
33
necessary because they already know for sure that earthly life was
the only life that God planned for cosmic history.32
Before ending this section, we have to qualify, in a significant
way, the elements of Titanism that we have discovered in the JudeoChristian tradition. Religions of obedience stress other-power in
their belief in a transcendent, omnipotent God as sovereign ruler of
the universe, while gnostic religions focus on self-power and explicitly subordinate the role of the gods. In religions of obedience,
God saves us, but in religions of knowledge we save ourselves. A
major exception in the Asian tradition is Pure Land Buddhism. Shinran (11731262), Buddhisms Luther, radicalized a tradition that
had already placed emphasis on human depravity and reliance on
other-power rather than on self-power.33
Even though orthodox Christianity promises eternal life, it is
clear (despite theologians like Hackett who hold to a natural immortality)34 that the correct teaching should be a bestowed immortality. (Recall that Adam and Eve ate only from the knowledge tree,
and Yahweh removed them before they could eat of the Tree of Life.)
According to Christian doctrine, it takes a special act of God to restore the tarnished imago dei and to transform the mortal soul into
something fit for the divine presence. Gilson made this point clear:
Gods grace makes human nature divine.35 By contrast immortality
in Hinduism and Jainism is natural, an essential attribute of the
human soul. Therefore, the Titanistic elements of Christianity are
mitigated by the fact that the Hebraic principle, while substantially
compromised by the Incarnation, human immortality, and some
gnostic elements, is still intact. In short, God is still in control and
still makes the final decisions. (Recall that the yogi can roll up space
as it were a piece of leather, but only Yahweh can roll up the skies
like a scroll.)36 Therefore, there is no extreme humanism in Christianity (unless one agrees completely with Cupitts analysis of the Incarnation), but it is found in Hinduism, Jainism, and existentialism.
The yogi discovers his own divinity, Kirilov tries valiantly to make
himself God, but the Christian God bestows immortality by means of
divine grace and our obedience.
34
Spiritual Titanism
35
36
Spiritual Titanism
37
gods. And that is true only if you are willing to believe that entering
the ridiculous world of the gods is forever losing the purest of which
is feeling, and feeling on this earth.46
Dostoevsky also knows that we have to be true to the earth. In
Crime and Punishment Raskolnikovs Titanism is countered by the
childlike innocence and acceptance of Sonya, who, after hearing
Raskolnikovs confession, tells him to go to the Four Corners and to
kiss Mother Earth. Dostoevsky realizes, as Nietzsche did, that extreme humanism is ultimately destructive of every human value.
Late in the novel Raskolnikov has a dream, which Dostoevsky obviously designed as a warning:
He had dreamt in his illness that the whole world was condemned to fall victim to a terrible, unknown pestilence
which was moving on Europe out of the depths of Asia. All
were destined to perish, except a chosen few, a very few. . . .
People who were infected immediately became like men possessed and out of their minds. But never, never, had any men
thought themselves so wise and so unshakable in the truth
as those who were attacked. Never had they considered their
judgments, their scientific deductions, or their moral convictions and creeds more infallible. Whole communities, whole
cities and nations, were infected and went mad. All were full
of anxiety, and none could understand any other; each
thought he was the sole repository of truth and was tormented when he looked at the others, beat his breast, wrung
his hands, and wept. They did not know how or whom to
judge and could not agree what was evil and what good.
They did not know whom to condemn or whom to acquit.
Men killed one another in senseless rage. . . . In the whole
world only a few could save themselves, a chosen handful of
the pure, who were destined to found a new race of men and
a new life, and to renew and cleanse the earth; but nobody
had ever seen them anywhere, nobody had heard their voices
or their words.47
This nihilistic vision represents Dostoveskys acute perceptions of the
dangers of modernism. His diagnosis is, in short, that modernism
leads to Titanism, both spiritual and technological. (It is indeed incongruous that madmen making scientific deductions come out of
Asia, but it is consistent with Indian yogis who claim to be beyond
good and evil.) Dostoevskys answer, much like Solzhenitsyns, is a
38
Spiritual Titanism
call for a return to Mother Earth, Mother Russia, and the Russian Orthodox Churcha decidedly premodern solution to modernisms radical individualism and alienation. Keeping the dialogical
existentialists and process theists in mind and drawing on Hebrew and Buddhist sources, we will now turn to a consideration of
some postmodern solutions.
Introduction
A major focus of this study is the concept of self and its relation
to others and to the universe. If we say that the primordial unity of
the Upanis.ads offers a premodern view of the self, and recognize the
Jaina-Sam
. khya-Yoga philosophies as anticipating modern selfhood,
then Buddhist and Chinese philosophy may have the potential of a
postmodern interpretation. (This means that the seeds for both modernism and its postmodernist critique were already present in the
Axial Age.) Many commentators have spoken of the Buddhas anticipation of postmodernism, and David J. Kalupahana is correct in
aligning him with constructive postmodernism rather than with
French deconstruction.4 The response of deconstruction to the autonomous self is to negate it completely, but constructive postmodernism seeks to reconstruct the self as relational and social. In their
innovative book Thinking Through Confucius, David L. Hall and Ro-
39
40
Spiritual Titanism
41
the rejection of science, technology, and a mechanistic cosmology. Ontologically the modern worldview is basically atomistic, both at the
physical and at the social level. The cosmos is simply the sum total
of its many inert and externally related parts, just as modern society
is simply the sum total of social atoms contingently related to other
social atoms. The modern state is simply the social atom writ large
on an international scale, acting as dysfunctionally as the social
atom does in smaller communities. The modernist view of time is
also linear, with one event happening one after the other, with no
other purpose than simply to keep on continuing that way. The modernist view of the sacred has been to reject it altogether, or to place
God in a transcendent realm far removed from the material world.
The latter solution is the way that some Christian theologians have
reconciled themselves with mechanistic science. The authors of The
Reenchantment of Science: Postmodern Proposals have argued that
this reconciliation began early on and that orthodox theologians
found mechanistic science an effective foil against a resurgent pantheism and panpsychism coming out of the Renaissance.7
Modernism also gave new meaning to what it means to be a subject, and the primary source of this innovation was the ego cogito of
Descartess Meditations. The pre-Cartesian meaning of subject (Gk.
hypokeimenon; Lat. subiectum) can still be seen in the subjects one
takes in school in or the subject of a sentence. In this ancient sense
all things are subjects, things with underlying [essential] kernels,
as the Greek literally says and as Greek metaphysics proposed. (As
opposed to substance metaphysics, the process view of pansubjectivism makes all individuals subjects of some sort of experience.)
After Cartesian doubt, however, there is only one subject of experience of which we are certainnamely, the human thinking subject.
All other things in the world, including persons and other sentient
beings, have now become objects of thought, not subjects in their own
right. Cartesian subjectivism, therefore, gave birth simultaneously
to modern objectivism as well. With the influence of the new mechanical cosmology, the stage was set for uniquely modern forms of
otherness and alienation.
By contrast the premodern vision of the world is one of totality,
unity, and above all, purpose. These values were celebrated in ritual
and myth, the effect of which was to sacralize the cycles of seasons
and the generations of animal and human procreation. The human
self, then, is an integral part of the sacred whole, which is greater
than and more valuable than its parts. And, as Mircea Eliade has
shown in Cosmos and History, premodern people sought to escape
42
Spiritual Titanism
the meaningless momentariness of history (Eliade called it the terror of history) by immersing themselves in an Eternal Now. Myth
and ritual facilitated the painful passage through personal and social crises, rationalized death and violence, and controlled the power
of sexuality. One could say that contemporary humankind is left to
cope with their crises with far less successful therapies or helpful
institutions.
In addition to the terror of history, many premodern people also
saw the body and senses as a hindrance to the spiritual life. This
view was later connected, as it was in Advaita Vedanta, with the
view that the natural world as a whole is illusory or at most only a
derivative reality. The alternative to Vedantist monism was a dualism of soul and body; and, in its most extreme forms, Manicheanism
and Gnosticism, one is presented with a fierce battle between our
spiritual natures and our animal natures. Interestingly, a mind-body
dualism characterizes some of modern thought, but it is formulated
in a much more subtle and sophisticated way. Most importantly,
matter is not considered the embodiment of evil.
It is important to observe that the doctrine of karma is modernist in assuming the concept of individual moral responsibility. It
is also significant that individual karma is most consistently expressed in the Jaina-Yoga-Sam
. khya philosophies that hold to the
modernist idea of autonomous selves. Individual moral responsibility becomes problematic only in the bhakti yoga of Hindu saviors forgiveness of human sins and in the distribution of the Boddhisattvas
excess merit. Some philosophers have struggled to make intelligible
the idea of collective karma,8 but the basic logic of karma dictates individual responsibility for individual acts and a corresponding individual resolution of guilt related to these acts.
A related contrast is the idea of premodern shame cultures
based on collective guilt and on the modern concept of guilt based on
personal moral responsibility. John Kekes has illustrated this distinction very well by an analysis of the story of Gyges and the Lydian
queen.9 Shame cultures are premodern and assume no distinction
between the inner and the outer, a realm of private as opposed to
public morality. Therefore, the only way for the queen to save her
honor was to make public the disgrace she experienced when the
king arranged for Gyges to see her naked. Kekes claims that shame
is a destructive emotion, because shame cultures are basically reactionary and do not allow constructive criticism of social norms or
proper resolution of conflicting personal feelings. In short, Kekes
concludes that there can be no moral progress if shame is central to
43
personal action. If Confucian yi (usually mistranslated as righteousness) is simply an internalized li (social norms), then Confucian
culture is a shame culture with exactly the same problems. A typical
modernist and also deconstructionist answer to this problem is to reject or to completely relativize moral standards. But if Hall and
Ames are correct in their interpretation of yi as a personal appropriation of li,10 we then might well see this as a constructive postmodern solution to the conflict between private and public morality. Such
an interpretation essentially makes yi the Confucian equivalent of
the act of personal appropriation that is present in Aristotles mean,
one that is objective but yet relative to us.11
Modern philosophy generally separates the outer from the inner,
the subject and the object, fact and value, the is and the ought, science and faith, politics and religion, the public from the private, and
theory from practice. Following Descartess insistence on a method of
reducing to simples and of focusing on clear and distinct ideas, modern humans have made great strides conceptually and theoretically.
The practical application of modernism has extended the rule of science and conceptual analysis to all areas of life: personal machines
of all sorts, a fully mechanized industry, and centralized bureaucratic administration. Critics of modernism observe that it is a great
irony that the modern state celebrates human rights but at the same
time its state organization has destroyed the basis for personal autonomy. It has also eroded the intimate ties of traditional community
life, and it has threatened the ecological balance of the entire planet.
.
Earlier it was suggested that Sankara represents premodern
thinking, but it is probably more accurate to say that, as opposed to
premodern views unaffected by modernist dichotomies and alienation, Sankaras absolute monism is in part a response to JainaSam
. kya-Yoga dualism. It is a significant fact that absolute monism
is not found in any premodernist worldview, which, in its search for
unity does not eliminate the individual completely and certainly
does not declare plurality an illusion. The uncompromising monism
.
found in Sankara and in his predecessor Gaud.apada is a comparatively late development, which could lead one to conclude that absolute monism represents a reflective and deliberate return to premodern unity with a vengeance, at least an intellectual vengeance.
.
It should also be acknowledged that both Gaud.apada and Sankara
may well have been influenced by Buddhist absolutists such as
Asvaghosa, who declared that the world of the birth-and-death soul
has no genuine reality.12 Therefore, illusionism may have had its
origins in Mahayana Buddhism not in Hinduism. Reacting against
44
Spiritual Titanism
45
experiments.15 In a chapter entitled The Reenchantment of Art: Reflections on the Two Postmodernisms, Suzi Gablick presents both
deconstructive and reconstructive examples of contemporary art and
finds that the latter movement is a continuation of the artistic revolution just described. Gablick states that
Reconstructionists . . . are trying to make the transition from
Eurocentric, patriarchal thinking and the dominator model
of culture to a more participatory aesthetics of interconnectedness, aimed toward social responsibility, psychospiritual
empowerment, deep ecological commitment, good human relations, and a new sense of the sacred. . . .16
This view of art reintegrates premodern elements but emphatically
rejects the modernist view of art for arts sake, which is yet another
result of the alienation of the private and public that we find in modern culture.
46
Spiritual Titanism
47
48
Spiritual Titanism
49
50
Spiritual Titanism
51
52
Spiritual Titanism
53
54
Spiritual Titanism
A revised prism analogy with many different soul prisms refracting their own perspectives gives us both the plurality and equality of souls that experience and justice require. Advaita Vedanta does
not do justice to the rich and dynamic diversity of life and the intrinsic value that ecological consciousness gives even to the smallest
species. In contrast to Advaita Vedanta, the prism no longer stands
for an ignorance that must be removed, but a window on reality
through which we perceive the world. Following Ramanuja, this
aperture of the soul remains for all incarnations and after liberation
as well. Finally, the revised analogy still confirms the validity of
mystical experiences: through spiritual exercise soul-prisms are able
to make themselves, momentarily, transparent to the One. In the
mystics some of Indras pearls sometimes become wondrously white
with the light of Brahman.
55
56
Spiritual Titanism
asks him about the nature of the Arhat: he must answer that the
Arhat is not a perfect being. Following this dialectical model of
karma, we interpret the resolution of the issue in this way: Arhat as
perfect being > no perfect being > reconstructed as Arhat as a being
without craving but living in a world of ordinary desires. There is
also a brilliant critique of the virtues (paramitas) as perfections, in
the way that Plato conceived them as Forms. Following Kalupahanas suggestion that we should see the perfection of virtues
morally rather than ontologically, we construct the following triad:
virtues as ontological perfections > no virtues as such > the virtues
reconstructed as perfected dispositions. Therefore, when Subhuti
hears the Buddha proclaim that the Tathagathas perfection of patience . . . is no perfection,36 we are not to take this to mean that the
Buddha does not have the virtue of patience. It is very clear from the
story of his appearance as Ks.anti that he was indeed a very patient
sage. The Buddha explains that if he had assumed a substantial concept of the self, he would also have had a perception of ill will at the
time. On our model this means that the Buddha, while deconstructing the idea of a substantial self and a corresponding notion of
perfect virtues, is reconstructing the virtue of patience on the basis
of a reconstructed process self.
Conclusions
Let us now summarize the view of self that we have presented in
the last two chapters. First, the self is dialogical not monological,
corresponding to the two types of existentialism discussed at the end
of chapter 1. Second, the self is constituted intersubjectively rather
than as the intrasubjective constitution of the Cartesian self. Third,
the self is somatic, that is, the body is constitutive of personal identity. The soul, as Merleau-Ponty, the Jainas, and the Confucians
have independently discovered, is also coextensive with the body.
This means, repeating Marcels language, that we are our bodies
rather than the modernist view that we own our bodies. Fourth,
the soul is not a social atom, analogous to the physical atom, moving
accidentally through social space. In this view society and community are simply abstractions; for the social atomist the only true realities are individuals. The constructive postmodern self, using
Whiteheads analogy of organism, is thoroughly social and relational.
If we are constituted just as much by others as we are by ourselves,
then society (and nature, too) is an interrelated whole rather than
57
the simple sum of existing individuals. Finally, the constructive postmodern self is not an enduring substance (either material or spiritual), but an ever-changing unity of personal events intimately
related to all other events. It is this process self that is offered as a
replacement for the autonomous selves of Western modernism, Jainism, and Sam
. khya-Yoga.
Prometheus East
Greek and Hindu Titans
Introduction
This chapter will investigate the phenomenon of Asura Titanism
and evaluate Indian mythological parallels to the story of Prometheus. The Sanskrit asura is usually translated as demon, but
sometimes as Titan or antigod. We shall see that demon is not
appropriate for the earliest Vedic use of the term, which, according to
W. H. Hale, could apply to gods, demons, and humans. The asuras
do, however, become the principal antagonists of the devas of Hindu
religion, especially as it is embodied in the Puran.as. We will usually
avoid calling the asuras demons, because although they are antagonists, they are sometimes more virtuous and superior in spiritual practice than the gods with whom they compete. Nevertheless,
the pejorative meaning of Asura and Titan eventually dominated
Greek and Indian mentalities. Just as Plato blamed evil on an ancient Titanic nature,4 so did later Indians blame it on ones asuric
nature.
59
60
Spiritual Titanism
The traditional theory about the origin of the Asuras is that they
parallel the Greek Titansthe older ancestors of the younger Olympian-like Devas. Greek Titanism, then, is a form of Asura Titanism,
where the main conflict is between two classes of mythical beings.
We also find that the Titans, especially Prometheus, turn out to be
more virtuous, at least in terms of his love for humanity, than the
Olympians. We will discover that the Puran.ic form of this Titanism
will be the weakest form of Hindu Titanism. The most troubling
forms are the ones in which human beings themselves take on divine
attributes and prerogatives. In addition to the fact that Prometheus
is an Asura and not a human being, we will also find other instructive differences between him and the spiritual Titans of the Indian
tradition. The chapter will begin with a discussion of Asura Titanism
in the Hindu tradition, will then turn to the human Titans of the
Puran.ic tradition, and will conclude with a comparative analysis of
the Prometheus myth.
Asura Titanism
One Vedic myth about the origin of evil indicates that it was a
combination of Prajapatis creative fiat and the spiritual geography
of the cosmos itself. When Prajapati created the gods they entered
the sky (divam); and this is why the gods are gods (devas).5 The
Asuras, on the other hand, entered the darkness of the underworld
and Prajapati pierced them with evil. As a result the Devas and the
Asuras became hateful fraternal enemie[s]. Prajapatis act of disapproval might be seen as simply a confirmation of the lower ( = less
good) domain that the Asuras had occupied. (In contrast the Greek
Titans are sent to the underworld by a deliberate act of Zeus.) A similar explanation, employing the gun.a theory of Sam
. khya, is found in
the Bha
gavata Pura
n.a. According to this account the gods are made
of sattva, the purest quality; the asuras are composed of the passion
of rajas; and the yaks.as and raks.asas are constituted by tamas, the
lowest, most impure quality. This gun.a determinism not only explains the behavior of these beings, but it also explains that why in
an age in which rajas is dominant, the great god Vis.n.u is inclined to
grant the wishes of the Asuras.6 As pure spirit (atman) Vis.n.u is devoid of gun.as and he cannot be partial to any being. It only appears
that he is partial because of the ascendency of one quality of any particular age. And even though Vis.n.u is the creator of time, it is time
not he that determines the dominant qualities of the ages.
Prometheus East
61
atapatha Bra
The S
hman.a has a very different view of the origin
of evil, one that parallels an Iranian myth. In this story Prajapati
creates the Devas and the Asuras as equals and gives them speech:
Both of them spoke the truth, and both of them spoke falsehood; and
as they spoke alike, they were alike. The gods gave up falsehood and
kept truth, and the demons gave up truth and kept falsehood.7 In
the Gathas of Zoroaster we find that Ahura Mazda creates two spirits, one who chose the good (Vohu Manah) and one who chose evil
(Angra Mainyu). Of these two spirits, the evil one chose to do the
worst thing, but the Most Holy Spirit, clothed in the most steadfast
heaven, joined himself unto Righteousness.8 We find yet another
view of the origin of evil in Greek philosophy when we analyze the
Prometheus myth in the last section of this chapter.
In the beginning the Devas and the Asuras shared the same loka
and feasted on the same divine food (soma). The Asuras were not yet
evil in any respect, because Varun.a is described as the wise sovereign (asura) king.9 This again reminds us that the ancient Iranians,
who once shared the same religious practices with the Indo-Aryans,
called their god the Wise Lord (ahura [ = asura] mazda) but called
their demons devas. The word yaks.a, used to describe a large category of demons, literally means honored ones. Their origins are
most likely pre-Aryan, making them older, in terms of Indian worship, than the Vedic gods. The pre-Aryan Jaina tradition, for example, regarded the yaks.asalong with raks.asas, bhutas, and
pisacasas deities, and contemporary Jainas regard them so to this
day. The Hindus of course consider all these beings to be demons, although usually in a lower class than the Asuras.
The traditional theory is sometimes called functional in the
sense that although the Devas and the Asuras share the same nature, the former usually function as divine beings while the latter
function as antigods. A. K. Coomaraswamy expresses the functional
theory like this: Although distinct and opposite in operation, [Devas
and Asuras] are in essence consubstantial, their distinction being a
matter not of essence but of orientation, revolution, or transformation. . . . The Titan is potentially an Angel, the Angel still by nature
a Titan.10 In one Vedic account, both Agni and Soma are former
Asuras, who are won over by Indra, king of the gods. The best example, however, is the great god Siva, who is known as the Slayer of Titans on the one hand but as the Lord of the demons (bhu
tas) on the
other. Indeed, all of the Asuras, except Prahlada, are Siva devotees.11
The Asura Andhaka and Sukra, the Asuras priest, are born of Sivas
body. His son Gan.esa is the head of a host of demons/demigods called
62
Spiritual Titanism
gan.as, and, according to one story, is the origin of evil in the world.12
In both Greek and Hindu mythology the Angels and Titans trade
places: Kr. s.n.a dispatches Asuras to heaven without even giving them
a choice, and Prometheus finally regains immortality and joins his
former enemies on Mt. Olympus. The functional theory explains why
the Asuras and the Devas form friendships such as the one between
Indra and Namuci. It also explains why Asuras such as Bali are capable of great virtue while the Devas can be devious and full of vice.
For example, the Devas betray the Asuras after requesting their cooperation in the churning of the cosmic ocean, and Indra turns on
Namuci and decapitates him.
The Buddhist view of the Asuras confirms the functional theory
just as well as does the Jaina tradition. In some Buddhist texts the
Asuras are known as the older devas, who originally dwelt in the
Tavatimsa Heaven. For example, Sakka refers to them as such in
the Sam
ya, and it is said that they lost their morality by at. yuttanika
tacking the Devas.13 The Bardo Thdol describes the Asuras as jealous, prideful, quarrelsome, and forever warring with the gods. One
Buddhist story tells of the Asura Rahu, who caused the eclipses of the
sun and moon by taking them into this mouth. One day the Buddha
made himself taller than Rahu, and with the Buddha towering over
him, he saw his Titanic folly and became a disciple.14 The Buddhist
Satan Mara is alternatively called an asura and yaks.a, and his battle with the Buddha could very well be seen as a battle of asura
against devati deva (god beyond god), a term used in Mahayana Buddhism. The Buddhist texts offer two interesting etymologies of asura.
The first simply takes the stem -sura to mean god and the a-privative
makes asura the antigod. The second is more fanciful: the stem -sura
refers to an intoxicant by which the Asuras once drank themselves
unconscious.15 By this account the term means teetotaler, because
they took a vow never to drink sura again.
In his thorough study of the Asuras, W. H. Hale qualifies the
functional theory by demonstrating that in the early Vedic period the
Asuras were not a separate class of gods/demons. Hale produces a
much better etymology of the word asura. Its roots are asu + ra and
its literal meaning is one who possesses asulife-power, connected
to both maya and brahman, the power of creation and the power of
the sacrifice respectively. Therefore, for the early literature Hale
translates the word as sovereign lord, and both gods and humans
took on this title by successfully exercising their powers. One is not
born with asuric power; rather, one must achieve it in an heroic act.
Indra as the slayer of Asuras most likely implies human, not di-
Prometheus East
63
64
Spiritual Titanism
of milk into butter and, in addition, often describes violent
attack.17
The churning of the cosmic ocean, the sages churning the wicked
king Vena, Indra churning the head of Namuci, and Vyasa using
fire sticks to churn out his son Suka are examples of these meanings
of manth. It is commonly assumed that the meaning of Prometheus
is forethinker (from manthno, to learn or to know) with his
bumbling brother Epimetheus as afterthinker, but the Indo-European root indicates meanings of churner or robber instead.18 Already we can see some interesting connections: Prometheus steals
fire from Zeus and the Asuras attempt to rob the gods of their divine
soma. It is also significant to note that Siva, Lord of the Bhu
tas, including the gan.as and pramathas, is also known as the fire god.
More figuratively, we have seen that the Asuras are related to the rajasgun.a, the quality of fiery passion.
According to the Harpers Dictionary of Hinduism the pramathas
(here the authors etymology is tormentor or smiter, focusing presumably on manth as to attack) are first mentioned in the Atharvaveda and are described as demons who are bearded, terrific, potbellied, hunch-backed and dwarfish and appear to be the same as
the gan.as.19 The gan.as are under the command of Gan.esa, hence one
of his names, Gan.apati. (Like the yaks.as Gan.esa also had a preAryan origin before being appropriated by the Siva cult.) Switching
playfully to the divine side, the gan.as are also called gan.adevata
s, attending not only to Siva and Gan.esa, but also to Indras court. If our
task is to find Hindu equivalents of the Greek Titans, we have certainly not found them in such minor beings as the gan.as or the pramathas. The ra
ks.asas, just as fearsome as the pramathas, fare no
better, because they are enemies of the human race, for instance,
Ramas enemy Ravan.a as the most powerful and famous.
Some of the most famous Asuras trace their lineage from Rambha. One day he and his brother Karambha were practicing austerities and Indra brutally murdered Karambha. So distressed was
Rambha that he decided to cut off his head and throw it into the sacrificial fire. Agni intervened, warned him that suicide was worse
than killing, and offered to grant him any wish that he desired.
Rambha said: Grant my desired boon that a son be born unto me,
who will destroy the forces of my enemy and who will conquer the
three worlds.20 The son requested was none other than Mahis.a, the
great Asura of the Durga myth, to which we shall return in chapter
6. Mahis.as son Rakta also won a victory over the Devas and ruled
Prometheus East
65
66
Spiritual Titanism
Prometheus East
67
pend on the sacrifice for their continued existence. In the Hindu tradition one should distinguish between a strong and a weak conception of immortality. The strong notion is contained in atman, a
perfect immutable being with no beginning or end. Doniger explains
the weak form in this way: The gods take the ambrosia from them
[the Asuras] and use it for the only immortality which is natural and
in order, even for the godsa full life-span.28 Even the high gods
Siva, Vis.n.u, and Brahma appear to be subject to weak immortality.
And only insofar as these godsusually only the first twoare later
identified with Brahman do they take on immortality in the strong
sense. We will see that the Goddess is also identified with Brahman,
but, if sakti is the only cosmic power, then the Goddess is ontologically supreme. Therefore, there is a third irony in Indian Titanism:
Hindu sages, Jaina saints, and Yoga adepts are claiming divine attributes that even the Vedic gods do not have.
68
Spiritual Titanism
presence of the Puran.ic equivalent of the Indo-Iranian theistic principle. (See supra, p. 7.) The gods condemned Vena and the r.s.is killed
Vena with some sacred kusa grass. The gods churned (manth) the
thigh of the dead Vena and produced Nis.ada, who carried the sins of
Vena into the Vindhya mountains.
Churned from Venas right hand, Pr. thu was big as a mountain,
shone on the earth as Indra in heaven,32 manifested divine signs,
and was omniscient and omnipresent. Under his wise and virtuous
rule, the earth enjoyed a Golden Age: there was great prosperity, religious practices flourished, and the gods received their soma. After
faithfully producing great abundance, the earth goddess Bhu
midevi
withdrew her fertility by taking all seeds into herself. Pr. thus new
subjects complained bitterly that the earth was becoming a great
desolation. Pr. thu pursued the goddess vigorously to the ends of the
universe, repeatedly impaling her with his arrows. (The story takes
the converse form of the Durgas pursuit of Mahis.a: Bhu
midevi takes
on various disguises, including that of an elephant, a buffalo, and a
cow.) Failing to find refuge in the gods, she had no choice but to confront Pr. thu and to ask him why he persecuted her so. Did he really
think that by killing her he could solve his problems? Furious at the
goddesss impudence, Pr. thu said that he would nourish and protect
his people by his yogic power alone. Finding this a bad idea, Bhumidevi said: Control your anger. I shall be full of food and will support these subjects.33 In the form of a cow she was milked for every
need and by every being in the universe. (In chap. 6 we shall investigate in some detail the claims of Yoga Titanism. We will also find
that Siva claims that he can rule exclusively by his yogic powers,
only to be castigated by Parvati for his ignorance, arrogance, and
presumption. We will also analyze the problem of the raging anger of
many Hindu Titans.) The writers of the Padma Puran.a display the
complete dominance of Pr. thu over Bhumidevi by making her his
adopted daughter and by naming her Pr. thvi .
In another story from the Mahabharata a different Pr. thu is a
Vasu, who along with Dyaus and other Vasus, stole the cow Nandini from a sage by the name of Vasis.t.ha. They did this so that the
cows magic milk would make a beautiful princess immortal. In
terms of our search for Prometheus equivalents in Indian mythology, Donigers comments are significant:
[Pr. thu] helps to steal this cow (as Prometheus steals the fire
from Zeus) in order to help a mortal defy the challenge of the
gods, to become free from age and diseasethe definitive
Prometheus East
69
70
Spiritual Titanism
Prometheus East
71
In his rejection of, and alienation from, the elements of the world,
Suka is a perfect candidate for the definition of Yoga Titanism discussed in chapter 5.
In addition to this epic account of Suka there are two Puran.ic
versions that offer similarities as well as some significant variations.
Common to the Maha
bharata and the Devi -Bhagavata is a visit to
King Janaka, famous for his status as a ji vanmukta (liberated while
embodied). Suka asks Janaka about the proper means of liberation
and the king responds with the traditional view of an orderly progression through the four stages of life (a
sramas). Suka has nothing
but loathing for the householders life, so he presses the king about
the necessity of committing himself to activities he detests. Realizing
Sukas advanced state of spiritual development, Janaka finally acknowledges that Suka is indeed an exception and that all he needs is
to recognize his perfected nature. Suka returns home to his father,
who reluctantly blesses his spiritual journey, ending in the self-apotheosis just described, which actually transcends all the a
sramas.
The Bhagavata Puran.a continues the theme of alienation from
the world but the jana yoga of the epic is replaced by bhakti yoga.
Although completely indifferent to, and immune from, the sensible
world, Suka still has love and compassion for all those still caught in
the web of Sam
. sara. The Devi -Bhagavata Puran.a, however, makes
significant changes to the story that are characteristic of its Sakta
(i.e., Goddess) orientation. This time Janaka does not make Suka an
exception and insists that he commit himself to the prescribed life
stages. Suka is able to hold his own in argument until Janaka observes that he is the one who is completely at ease in the world while
Suka is miserable and full of doubt. Suka returns home to his father,
marries a woman named Pi vari , and they have four sons and a
daughter. Like Janaka he, too, becomes one who is liberated while in
a body (ji vanmukta), but Suka attains this not so much because of
his yogic power but by virtue of his worship of Devi Maha Maya. The
Sakta Puran.as incorporated many Advaitin terms, but, as C.
Mackenzie Brown says, ma
ya
becomes radically revaluated, becoming more a means than an obstacle to liberation, a view reinforced by
the Tantric currents of the day.44 While the Devi -Bha
gavata version
of this story contains typical Sakta themesan affirmation of the
world through a coincidence of enjoyment (bhukti) and liberation
(mukti)Suka, always averse to any company, finally left his family and traveled to Mt. Kailasa.45 There he attained siddhi powers
and became like a second Sun. Although this apotheosis is not as
grand or as transcendent as the epic version that was just discussed,
72
Spiritual Titanism
this ending mitigates somewhat the effect of the general Sakta solution to the problems of Yoga Titanism that we explore in chapter 6.
Prometheus East
73
74
Spiritual Titanism
metheus was connected to the worship of the Goddess.49 Ovid relates that Athene provided the breath of life to animate the clay figures that Prometheus had formed as human beings.50 In one account
it is also Athene who helped Prometheus steal fire. It is significant
that in Prometheus Bound Prometheus called on the earth goddess
Gaia immediately after he was chained and also turned to her in the
end as the mountain collapses on him. Prometheus was also consoled
by a Chorus of the daughters of Oceanus, a Titan who reluctantly allowed them to come to Prometheus aid. (Prometheus married Hesione, one of Oceanus daughters, and her sisters remind Prometheus
of the times when he was gentle, humble, and far less angry.) Although male, Oceanus has deep feelings and moral qualities, and
paired with his wife Tethys, they together represent a Greek equivalent of prakr.ti, the dynamic material principle of Sam
. khya philosophy and later Goddess philosophy. The Greek attribution of primordial waters as male is unusual in world mythology; they are
generally female in other traditions, most notably Babylonian and
Hindu. Hesiods view that Oceanus and Tethys were children of Gaia
is a later one, but it returns us to the more universal view that a feminine material principleeither water or earthis the source of all
things. For Hesiod, Night is the dark side of the material principle,
called by Homer the subduer of gods and men,51 and it is so powerful that even Zeus stands in awe of her.
Zeus relationship with feminine forces is not one of alliance but
of conflict and domination. After the defeat of the original Titans, the
great Goddess Gaia produces one last antagonist for Zeus, the serpent-headed Typhon, a true god of chaos. With the thunderbolt that
the Cyclopes have given him, Zeus easily defeats Typhon, although
his maritime storms still remain to wreak havoc on earth. According
to the Pseudo-Apollodorus, Gaia makes one last attempt to defend
the old (dis)order: she sends the Giants, a race of fierce warriors,
whom she attempts to immunize with a potion of immortality. The
wily Zeus steals the potion before she can administer it, and Heracles wins the victory over the Giants. Zeus does not battle the Goddess directly, as Mahis.a engages Durga, but a basic conflict with
feminine power remains. Zeus supremacy over this power is symbolized in his decision to swallow his first wife Metis. By this act he
preempts the birthing process by having Metis child Athene issue
from his head rather than from her womb.52 (Another womb substitute is Zeus use of his thigh to give birth to Dionysos.) We have already seen that the Hindu Titan expropriates the creative powers of
the female and seeks to take all power unto himself. The converse is
Prometheus East
75
76
Spiritual Titanism
what Doniger calls the Doctrine of the Golden Extremes rather than
the Doctrine of the Golden Mean proposed by the Buddha and Aristotle.61 Even more than pride, the anger of the Hindu gods and the
sages was their fatal flaw, and the Buddha made the elimination of
anger the centerpiece of his moral psychology.
Prometheus is also intimately connected to what we have called
technological Titanism. The Greek titanos literally means the quicklime made from an earthly element and fire,62 and the Titans were
closely connected to the forge and to the art of smithing. Both Prometheus and Hephaistos were said to have been Kabeiroi, an ancient
race of men-gods who were great blacksmiths. The original Cyclopes
were probably bronze smiths, who, according to Robert Graves,63
were one-eyed because of the practice of covering one eye as protection at the forge. Therefore, the fire of Prometheus is not only the
cooking fire and the lighted torch, but the alchemical fire of the
smelter. Two fragments from Aeschylus now lost Prometheus plays
do thou guard thee well lest a bubble strike thy face; for it is bitter,
and deadly-scorching its vapors and like the goat, youll mourn for
your beard, you will64are clear allusions to the dangers of working
too close to molten metal. Although the connection is not made in the
Greek myths, the fact that smelting and mining are intimately connected leads, at least retrospectively in some minds, to protest a
major violation of the sanctity and integrity of Mother Earth. Until
the industrial age smelting and mining were relatively small scale,
so preindustrial peoples could not have predicted the catastrophic
implications of their powerful pyrotechnology.
Conclusions
In conclusion we can see that Prometheanism and technological
Titanism are clearly linked, but Prometheanism and the spiritual Titanism found in India have significant differences. First, Prometheus
is a god and not a mortal, so he cannot be accused of illegitimately
claiming divine attributes or coveting divine prerogatives. Second, although Prometheus does suffer from hubris and even from a touch of
insanity, he does not reject nature and the earth mother. This is true
only of Indian Titans not Prometheus, who has very close ties with
his grandmother Gaia. If bringing together Jungian anima and the
animus represents the overcoming of Titanism, then it is Prometheus, ironically, who embodies this reconciliation, a Greek Titan
rather than Zeus the chief Olympian. Third, Prometheus is not an as-
Prometheus East
77
cetic and he does not seek isolation from either nature or society; on
the contrary, he is fiercely committed to the flourishing of human
community and civilization.
Although they practiced austerities, the Hindu kings Divodasa
and Pr. thu also supported humankind and established kingdoms of
virtue. On this point the Devas and the Olympians share the same
distrust of humanity. There is a constant tension between the Devas
and human kings, because the more the latter establish virtue the
less inclined humans are to sacrifice to the gods. The social and
moral commitment of Divodasa and Pr. thu mitigate the effects of
their Yoga Titanism, whereas there appears to be little to qualify the
preference for isolation in other yogis and the sages, the latter usually allying themselves with the gods against humankind. Finally, it
is interesting to note that it is the Devas who can always count on
the Goddesss help, while it is Prometheus who is closest to her. Not
only does the yogi believe he can live without the human community,
but he, at least according to Sam
. khya-Yoga, also maintains that final
liberation depends on the complete elimination of the material principle and of the Goddess who embodies it.
Jaina Superhumanism
and Gnostic Titanism
[The Jinas] attained fullest self-realization and absolute perfection, bringing out to the full the divinity or
godhood inherent in man.
Jyoti Prasad Jain1
There is no deva but the Jina.
Medhavin2
Virtually no tradition other than Jainism has dared to
attach so cosmic an attribute [absolute knowledge] to a
human being.
Padmanabh S. Jaini3
Introduction
The previous chapter concluded that Asura Titanism is the weakest form of Indian Titanism. It is essentially nonexistent in Jainism
because the conflict between the Devas and the Asuras found in Hinduism is not present in Jaina mythology. As in the earliest Indo-Iranian traditions, the Devas and the Asuras are, for the Jainas, simply
different types of divine beings. In Jaina mythology the Devas are
.
portrayed as completely devoted to the Ti rthankaras (lit. ford-crossers)a typical Titanistic reversalso the Hindu tension between
the gods and humans is also virtually absent in Jainism. The Jainas
vigorously rejected the Vedic sacrifice and priestly prerogatives, so
Brahmin Titanism is obviously not an issue. One can, however, discern the existence of two other forms of Titanismnamely, the
.
Ti rthankara as perfect yogi and as perfect knower.
In this chapter we shall investigate possible Jaina contributions
to Yoga Titanism and to Gnostic Titanism. The next three sections
79
80
Spiritual Titanism
Jaina Superhumanism
81
82
Spiritual Titanism
the celestial and the terrestrial. The higher gods are found in the head
.
and the Ti rthankaras float free in the crown of the cosmic man. Jaina
ji vas are naturally self-moving, like Platos soul, and if not weighted
down by karmic matter, they will immediately shoot up to the top of
the universe. Crooked is the path of the evil soul, but straight upward
motion is perfect, in contrast with the Greeks circular motion.9
Jaina Superhumanism
83
that they have taken the place of God or the gods. The ritual called
paca-namaska
ra involves bowing to each of the five holy ones as a
supreme divinity (parames.t.hin): the Jinas, the Siddhas, the monastic leaders (a
ca
ryas), monastic preceptors (upa
dhya
ya), and all Jaina
sadhus in the world.14 This ritual is also simply called devapu
ja, and
here we see very clearly that these Jaina holy men have taken on the
divine name and divine worship. In fact, deva is commonly added to
.
the name of the Ti rthankaras, as in the Hindi Mahavi rdev. The most
dramatic expression of this direct substitution of man for God comes
from a sixteenth-century Jaina philosopher Medhavin, who responded
to the Muslim Firuz Khan of Nagpur by provocatively declaring:
There is no deva but the Jina.15
Other divine images, however, did appear in some Jaina temples
during the medieval period. There were statues of the snake god
Dharanendra and of his consort Padmavati , who, just as in the story
.
of the Buddha, protected Parsva (the twenty-third Ti rthankara) during his spiritual quest. These beings, generically called sasana.
devata
, are able to grant boons to pious supplicants.16 Each Ti rthankara is accompanied by two sasana-devatas, and five of the best
.
known are goddesses. The consort of the twenty-second Ti rthankara
Nemi is Ambika, whom we know from Hindu mythology as either
Sivas sister or as a form of Durga. Interestingly enough, the Sve.
tambara sect ranks a woman Malli as the nineteenth Ti rthankara,
and today the worship of the yaks.i Kushmandini Devi is an integral
part of the Jaina ritual at Sravanabelagola.
The contemporary Jaina philosopher Vija Bhuvanbhanusuri confirms the fact that some Jainas still believe that the gods can bestow
grace.17 Surprisingly enough, he also appears to commit himself to
what I have called the Indo-Iranian theistic principle. Bhuvanbhanusuri cautions those who take attributions of divinity to humans (e.g.,
he is like a deity) as actually meaning that the man is divine, because deva is used only for gods not mortals.18 On the same page,
however, Bhuvanbhanusuri reaffirms the general Jaina position that
.
the Ti rthankaras are divine. This inconsistency could be resolved by
maintaining that mere mortals are transformed into deities at liberation, but as we shall see presently, this is not the Jaina view at all.
84
Spiritual Titanism
natures; rather, the Jinas simply discover their own divinity. God is
not an indwelling presence, as in Christian mysticism, but human
essence is literally divine essence. As we have seen, the Jainas believe in Uttaravada (the ascendence of man to Godhood)19 rather
than Avataravada, which they impute to Hinduism and Christianity.
Prem Suman Jain states that a person has infinite powers and that
the individual is capable of reaching such divine heights because
the pure form of the self is itself divine and therefore relies on its
own efforts.20 This appears indeed to be an extreme humanism and
a supreme form of spiritual Titanism.
Jyoti Prasad Jain uses the phrase man is the measure of all
things as a way of describing the Jainas humanistic belief that
human beings are in control of their own destiny.21 The Greek homo
mensura can also be used to describe the extreme anthropomorphism and anthropocentrism of Jaina humanism. As we have seen,
the cosmos for some Jainas is human-shaped and the human realm,
where true spiritual deliverance is found, is the center of the cosmos.
Krishna Prem and Madhava Ashish express the Hindu version of
this: The divine purpose cannot be effected except through its highest creation, Man. . . . Man is indeed the measure of all things. . . .
Other than this, divinity has no aim. . . . Here at last is Man, to
whose evolution the totality of universal power has contributed.22
Homo mensura, the watchword of Western humanism, is more cosmic and comprehensive here in Jainism and Hinduism than it ever
was in Greek Sophism.
The interpretation of the word OM (sounded as three letters:
AUM) becomes radically anthropomorphic in Jainism. First, the
Vedic reading was geographic with the three letters representing
earth, the atmosphere, and the heavens. This view appears to efface
the human place and to emphasize the cosmic source and meaning of
the word. Second, the Ma
ndukya Upanis.ad added a fourth element
to represent the silence between the sounding of the sacred word.
While this Upanis.ad maintains the macrocosmic origin of OMthis
syllable is this whole world23 and contains all of timeit also offers
a microcosmic interpretation as well. The letter A stands for the
waking state; the letter U symbolizes what we would now call rapideye-movement sleep; the M expresses deep sleep; and the silence
stood for the trance state of the liberated yogi. The interpretation
was also intimately connected to the human body in that the speaking started at the back of the mouth (A), moved through the middle
(U) and closed with the pursed lips of the M. Further intensifying the
anthropomorphizing of AUM, the Jainas made the three letters rep-
Jaina Superhumanism
85
86
Spiritual Titanism
Jaina Superhumanism
87
.
we had his ESP powers. For Asanga and Vasubandhu, however, the
true Buddha-mind has none of these qualities. Assuming that the extent of Buddha awareness is universal, the Mahayana scholastics
debated the question of whether there were any limits to it. They
agreed that such objects as a barren womans son and an eternal
self were not possible objects of Buddha awareness. They also rejected the notion that the Buddha-mind was only potentially aware,
because this would require that intention and volition would be necessary for the actualization process. To this significant break with
the Pali accounts, there came another change, at least insofar as
knowing the Dharma was the focus of the Buddhas omniscience.
.
Asanga and his associates affirmed that the prefix sarva- means all
actual states of affairs and rejected the lesser alternative of all
knowledge that has salvific importance.
In a thorough and insightful discussion Paul J. Griffiths demonstrates how radically the Buddha-mind is totally free of intentions
and constructions. Using Thomas Nagels famous article What Is It
Like to Be a Bat? Griffiths demonstrates that the Buddha-mind is
much more inaccessible than a bats mind.35 Indeed, nothing in true
Buddha awareness corresponds to any awareness that we can experience or imagine. (Just as in the Christian via negativa, the use of
terms becomes equivocal rather than univocal.) In the case of the bat
we can at least imagine the types of perceptions and mental states
it might have. In the case of the Buddha-mind, however, we might as
well imagine what it is like to be a rock. This point is not as facetious
as it might first appear, because a common image for the Buddha
mind is a completely still lake perfectly reflecting its surroundings.
According to Mohist logic, the lake and its surroundings are not analogues; rather, they are parallel to the Buddha mind and to its contents. The terms of parallel arguments have similar syntactic structuresthey are much more like mathematical ratioswhereas the
terms of analogical arguments have different syntactic structures.36
Any comparison between our minds and inanimate objects would be
analogical, but for the Buddha-mind, it being more inanimate than
anything mental we know, it is parallel.
The content of the Buddha-mind is not the result of sensation
or intention, so it is, strictly speaking, uncaused and has always
and necessarily existed. This also means that it is eternal and unchanging, a claim that appears to undermine the doctrine of impermanence. The Mahayana scholastics attempt to reconcile this by
saying that the Buddha-mind has eternal and unchanging awareness of all reals without exception in all modes of appearance
88
Spiritual Titanism
Jaina Superhumanism
89
Buddha had to reject the Jaina idea of an independent, pure knowledge as impossible. Both the skandha psychology and the process ontology of no-substance/no-self precludes anything at all similar to
Jaina omniscience. The Buddha constantly disabused people of the
idea that he possessed the same knowledge as Mahavi ra did. His
most emphatic denial was spoken in the presence of King Pasenadi of
Kosala: There is neither a recluse nor a Brahman who at one and the
same time can know all, can see allthis situation does not exist.40
Jaina and Mahayana scholastic positions are obviously docetic
theories of the saints nature, just as docetic as the early Christian
fathers attempt to explain Christs nature. All three religions ascribe
divine attributes to their saviors while at the same time trying to
preserve their humanity, that is, their ability to function in a body
and to relate to other people in the world. All three present us with
the notion of perfect beings appearing to use sense organs and their
bodies, but in fact they were not really doing so. It seems clear that
both Jainas and Mahayanists undermine their saviors humanity as
badly as Christian theologians did.
Pali Buddhist views on omniscience are made especially clear in
a conversation the Buddha once had with a prominent disciple. In
the Maha
parinibba
na suttana Sariputra greets the Buddha and proclaims that no one is greater or wiser than [he], especially with regard to omniscience.41 The Buddha asks his disciple if he had
personally known all these religious teachers. Sariputra is embarrassed and has to answer no. The Buddha further chides him for
not realizing that one would have to be omniscient in order to recognize omniscience in another. Nathan Katz aptly summarizes the
Buddhas reasoning: he does not want anyone to be hailed as omniscient, be it Mahavi ra or himself, because for Buddhism a highly serious human disease is the tendency to claim, despite the lack of
grounds for such claiming, an expression of the craving for speculation.42 To avoid confusion Katz suggests that we view the Buddhas
knowledge claims under the rubric of tivijja rather than sabbaa.
When Vacchagotta imputed Jaina omniscience to him, the Buddha
categorically rejected it and instead claimed a threefold knowledge
(tivijja): namely, former lives, the karma of others, and his complete
escape from rebirth.43
The limited nature of the Buddhas claims in the Pali scriptures
militate strongly against the hypothesis that he was a Gnostic Titan.
It should be mentioned that Nagarjuna refines Buddhist dialectic so
masterfully that it protects his Madhyamaka school from any hint of
Gnostic Titanism. Kalupahana finds it significant that nowhere in
90
Spiritual Titanism
the Karika does Nagarjuna refer to omniscience.44 Indeed, the ultimate effect of Nagarjunas dialectic is the realization that the negation of knowledge is the means to liberation. Nagarjunas concept of
su
nyata
, however, is not at all nihilistic; rather, it simply means that
u
no one thing is self-contained or self-sufficient. S
nyata is relative
nonbeing while at the same time it is relative being as well; all
things are interdependent and relative to one another. Sunyata
means that there are no substanceseither physical (matter) or
mental (soul or a
tman). Nagarjunas doctrine destroys the very idea
of autonomous selves, the foundational idea for all Titanistic philosophies. We shall have occasion to disconfirm the general thesis of a
Buddhist Titanism in chapter 8.
Aneka
ntava
da and Gnostic Titanism
Let us now look at aspects of Jainism that might mitigate the
charges of Jaina Titanism in the previous sections. With regard
to Gnostic Titanism one could offer the Jaina epistemology of anekantavada. This famous doctrine of many-sidednesscontrasted
with the one-sided (ekanta) views of Vedanta and Sam
. khyais dramatically expressed in the story of the partial knowledge that five
blind men have of an elephant. It is clear, however, that the omniscient Jinas are no longer blind, because they now know all aspects
of all things at once. Even at the fourth level of a fourteen-stage spiritual practice, the Jaina monk is like a person born blind who sees
the world for the first time on the sudden acquisition of eyesight,
so the soul now sees the truth.45 The epistemological mode of
anekantavada is no longer operational, because at this stage, as
P. S. Jaini states, the monk has an absolutely undistorted view of
reality.46
Jaina writings are filled with incredible knowledge claims, and
it appears that all of us are able to get a taste of the saints perfect
knowledge. The author of the Gommat.sa
ra Ji va-Kanda, for example,
presumes to tell us the exact number of hell beings or celestial beings and many other precise calculations. He also categorically
states that every six months 608 souls leave the nigoda realm. In the
same time, at the top of the universe, exactly the same number of
souls are liberated.47 In his commentary J. L. Jaini attempts to enhance the accuracy of this knowledge by presenting many of the calculations in elaborate algebraic formulations. For example, Jaini is
able to calculate that at any one instant there can be a maximum of
Jaina Superhumanism
91
898,502 vibratory omniscients in the cosmos.48 (The presence of vibration means that the soul is still being affected by the body and
.
the senses, so that a Ti rthankara is a nonvibratory omniscient.)
Such claims of precise knowledge and the Jainas taxonomic exuberance (found in other Indian treatises as well) tends to close philosophical discourse rather than open it up. One would think that the
doctrine of many-sidedness would lead to the latter rather than to
the former. The ramifications of this Gnostic Titanism are not salutary: the imputation of perfect knowledge to Mahavi ra leads to excessive knowledge claims on the part of his followers.
A possible Jaina response to the foregoing is that anekantava
da
is the condition of the vast majority of Jainas and that this limitation
instills humility and encourages an epistemological tolerance that
makes Gnostic Titanism impossible in practice. Furthermore, the
complete knowledge that the Jina has of the world is ultimately irrelevant. The most important aspect of kevala-jana is self-knowledgeseeing that our inner natures are divinerather than any
knowledge about the world. World knowledge is not used, as it is in
technological Titanism, for domination and exploitation.
With regard to epistemological tolerance the Jainas could use
Gandhis words very profitably. In a response to queries about apparent inconsistenciesfor instance, holding to advaita and dvaita
at the same timeGandhi answered that he believed in the Jaina
view of many-sidedness, and that his aneka
ntava
da is the result of
49
the twin doctrine of satya and ahim
sa
.
If
one
thinks of Gandhis
.
view of relative truth and how this would preclude one thinking
ill of others with differing beliefs, then the alliance with Jaina
aneka
ntava
da is a natural one. In the same passage Gandhi continues: Formerly I used to resent the ignorance of my opponents. Today
I can love them because I am gifted with the eye to see myself as others see me and vice versa.
Surprisingly, P. S. Jaini offers a strong disclaimer on the point of
epistemological tolerance: This practice [anekantavada] probably
does not really increase tolerance of others views; nevertheless it
has generated a very well-informed (if not always valid) sort of criticism.50 In a very sympathetic appraisal of Jainism, Christopher
Key Chapple describes Jainism as a friendly form of religious fundamentalism, in which Jainas are firmly committed to their own
views and have no intention of ever changing them. At the same time
anekantavada allows them to be tolerant of other views, which are
seen as incomplete rather than incorrect.51 The Jainas resistance
to accepting other views is most likely the principal reason why Jain-
92
Spiritual Titanism
ism survived in India, whereas Buddhisms demise was partially because Buddhists allowed too much syncretism with Hinduism.
Another Jaina response might be to call our attention to the fact
that aneka
ntava
da is primarily a logical, not an epistemological doctrine. Anekantavada lays out seven logical possibilities with regard
to a things existence and to its expressibility: (1) from one standpoint, my computer exists; yet (2) it did not exist before it was produced nor will it exist after it is destroyed; but now we can see that
(3) because my computer presently exists but will cease to be, we can
say that it both exists and does not exist; (4) if (3) holds, then it is impossible to express everything definite about my computer; therefore, we must conclude that (5) things are existent and expressible;
(6) nonexistent and inexpressible; or (7) existent, nonexistent, and
inexpressible.52 These logical possibilities exist independent of
whether one is omniscient or not, and can be immediately recognized
by any rational person.
The foregoing appears to be an answer to our charge that the
Jaina saints are exempt from aneka
ntava
da. But is this actually so?
The doctrine of many-sidedness makes every truth provisional, but
does the omniscient saint know only provisional truths? Is Jaina omniscience simply the sum total of all partial truths? No, it is in fact
very different from this. As we have seen, Jaina omniscience literally
means having total and complete knowledge of all things in all of
their possible modes. This is the very opposite of aneka
ntava
da. The
other point to observe is that our division between the logical and the
epistemological is quite artificial. Not only can we not really separate the two, but there is also, at least for most ancient philosophers,
a necessary connection to metaphysics. Even one as skeptical as the
Buddha held that truth, knowledge, and reality are all interrelated.
We are, after all, speaking about being and nonbeing, not simply affirmation and negation.
Jaina Superhumanism
93
all creatures and regard[ing] them as ones own self. . . .53 Compared
to Hinduism and Buddhism, where there is a hierarchy of consideration (viz., higher-minded creatures have priority over the lower),54
Jainism attempts to enforce a strict egalitarianism regarding the objects of injurious action. Simply put, every life unit (ji va) has equal
value. Therefore, Jaina ahim
. sa is based on the equality and universal kinship of all souls.
This egalitarianism is a great Jaina achievement, but the philosophical formulation is questionable. First, every Jain ji va, just as
every Sam
. khya purus.a, is distinct and separate from every other, so
a Jaina cannot, strictly speaking, regard another self as her own
self. Second, sympathy and reciprocity, along with equality, must be
necessary conditions for ahim
. True sympathy and reciprocity are
. sa
possible only in a system of internal relations. Jaina spiritual atomism, insofar as it pertains to personal salvation, is based on external
relations, that is, the possibility of the soul to become completely independent from everything else in the cosmos. A Jaina may, theoretically, be able to recognize another soul as equal; but it is difficult to
see, given the insistence on the isolation of the liberated soul, how
souls can be truly sympathetic (feeling with is the literal meaning)
with one another. In Buddhism, on the other hand, we find that relatedness and interdependence are the very essence of reality, so
that there is a near perfect match between ontology and ethics. Unfortunately, the Jainas theoretical Titanism is at odds with the practice of its most treasured virtue.
A contemporary Jaina philosopher reaffirms the theory of absolute independence and its relation to ahim
. sa. N. D. Bhargava argues that ahim
sa
must
be
totally
unconditional
and unrelational,
.
that its practice is successful only by disengaging from the world of
give-and-take. Bhargava contends that such a world, based as it is
on possession and domination, is necessarily violent. In their practice of ahim
. sa Jaina saints cannot depend upon the existence of others or the action of others, because nonviolent action is independent
of society. Bhargava states that the world of relationship is a world
of attachment and aversion. But nonviolence is possible and possible
only without interrelationship, because interrelationship is dependent on others and cannot be natural.55 The ultimate implication of
Bhargavas view is a reductio ad absurdum: liberated Jaina saints
are the only ones who can practice nonviolence, but their isolated
lokas are the only places in the universe where such practice is not
necessaryindeed, it has no meaning at all there. Saints in the
world, going from town to town for food and teaching, are still pre-
94
Spiritual Titanism
. sa
is not worth anything at all. In my own work I have argued that nonviolence is at most an enabling virtue, a necessary means to the
substantial virtue of love and compassion.58
Coupled with the equality of the souls is the Jaina doctrine of
panzooism, which conceives of ji vas of one sort or another inhabiting every part of the universe. Even though the Upanis.ads and
Vedantist philosophy frequently indicate that all things have a
tman,
Hindu beliefs about an intermediate state for the departed soul are
not consistent with this view. After death the soul wanders in the atmosphere for some time before falling in raindrops to earth. There it
becomes part of the plants that human beings ingest, so that individual souls finally make their way to a males testes. The Jainas reject this view as incoherent and have instead committed themselves
to a doctrine of instantaneous reincarnation. Their argument is simple: if everything is ensouled, then the atman cannot displace any
living air bodies, water bodies, or earth bodies; nor can it compete
with any plant ji va.59 Again we see the Jainas firm commitment to
the equality, integrity, and value of all souls.
Part and parcel of the Jainasview of instantaneous reincarnation
is their rejection of the souls omnipresence, a view found in Vedanta,
Nyaya, and Sam
. khya-Yoga. (This position, however, appears to conflict with Nathmal Tatias description of the Jinas soul filling up,
Titan-like, the entire cosmos.)60 The omnipresence of every soul not
Jaina Superhumanism
95
96
Spiritual Titanism
Jaina Superhumanism
97
Conclusions
On a practical level the Jainas are to be commended for their
fierce commitment to the ideal of nonviolence and to their success in
helping to eliminate animal sacrifice and to diminish cruelty to animals and meat eating in India. With their ethics of minimal impact
on the environment and their panzooism, the Jainas could be hailed
as the worlds first ecologists. (The ancient Zoroastrians, with their
protection of fire, water, earth, and air, are perhaps runners-up for
this honor.) On the theoretical side, however, we must conclude that
Jainism does constitute a form of spiritual Titanism. This of course
is one of its most benign forms and Jaina monks are no obvious no
threat to other humans and the environment. Practically, the Jainas
have been able to meld self and world rather successfully. Philosophically, however, their strict dualism, substance metaphysics, extreme anthropocentrism, and hyperbolic knowledge claims remain
fundamental problems.
Hindu
Titanism
Deep in the tiny atom of the psyche lies hidden a tremendous force which will lead the psyche to the point of
omniscience, omnipotence, and omnipresence if this
force is released properly, systematically, and chronologically.
Rammurti S. Mishra1
In the beginning was yoga, and no longer the sacrifice.
The Absolute is that of the yogi. . . . Yoga thus becomes
the supreme value, and the Absolute is that of the yogi.
. . . The starting point for everything, the ground zero of
cosmogony, thus takes the form of a projection of the
yogi into the absolute.
Madeleine Biardeau2
Enough of this asceticism, my son. By your dharma you
have conquered all worlds, now you should protect the
world, for there is no other dharma like that.
Brahma to Divodasa3
Introduction
Chapter 3 demonstrated why Asura Titanism is the weakest
form of Hindu Titanism, and chapter 4 presented the evidence for
Yoga and Gnostic Titanism in Jainism. The first section of this chapter will continue the discussion of these two types as well as Brahmin and Bhakti Titanism. The second section discusses the Yoga
Titanism of Sam
. khya-Yoga philosophy. The third section analyzes
the Purus.a hymn of the R. gveda, which serves as the prototype for divinized humanity in the Indian tradition from the Vedas to the Pu-
99
100
Spiritual Titanism
ran.as. The fourth section shows how Purus.a becomes a cosmic yogi
in the Puran.as. The final section takes issue with claims that Vedantist monism is the best grounds for ecological ethics and that this
monism is the best answer to Indian Titanism.
Hindu Titanism
101
102
Spiritual Titanism
around, laughing, playing, taking his pleasure with women, chariots, or friends and remembering no more that excrescence [which
was] his body.12
Yoga Titanism
The Kanphata yogis claim that their sect existed before creation,
and that their guru Gorakhnaih had Brahma, Vis.n.u, and Siva as his
first disciples.13 Practicing austerities could generate power equal to,
or superior to, that of the gods. An angry glance of an ascetic, for example, could reduce any being to ashes. Kapila, the reputed father of
the Sam
. khya system, was said to have incinerated sixty thousand of
King Bhagi rathas ancestors. Called the God of Sam
. khya or even
Isvara himself, Kapila was known also as the mind-born son of
Brahma, present at the beginning of each cycle of creation with perfect knowledge and disposition.14 Another aspect of tapas that frustrated the gods was the fact that the ascetic was usually immune
from sexual temptation, the most successful strategy that the gods
had always used against their antagonists. The story of Gautamas
rejection of Maras daughters and Divodasas steadfastness in the face
of the sixty-four yoginis Siva sent to seduce him are good examples.
(Divodasa was finally defeated by Vis.n.u and his associates disguised
as Buddhist missionaries.) Again, contrary to Greek myth, it is the
gods, not the Titans, who are prone to deception.
As we have already seen, the Sam
. khya-Yoga philosophy contains a strict dualism between the soul (purus.a) and matter (prakr.ti). As opposed to the pantheism of Vedanta in general and of the
absolute monism of Advaita Vedanta in particular, Sam
. khya-Yoga
claims that individual souls are real, eternal substances and that
matter is equally real, even in its inactive and nondifferentiated
state. Contrary to popular views, the yogi does not unite with any divine reality, not even with I svara the Lord. Purus.a souls are selfcontained and self-sufficient substances, so they are by nature
similar to the autonomous selves of Western philosophy.
As would be expected the gods have a subordinate role in
Sam
. khya-Yoga, and Mircea Eliade gives the reason for their inferior
position: It is only through experiences that one acquires freedom.
Therefore, the gods (videha, disincarnate)who have no experience because they have no bodieshave a condition of existence inferior to the human condition, and as such they cannot attain to total
deliverance.15 Again we see the Titanistic insistence that human ex-
Hindu Titanism
103
104
Spiritual Titanism
dous force which will lead the psyche to the point of omniscience, omnipotence, and omnipresence if this force is released properly, systematically, and chronologically.19 Mishra has essentially confirmed
our thesis about Yoga Titanism, but he does not realize that the attributes he ascribes to the yogi are actually not compatible with the
purus.a nature. If prakr.ti is the only source of power, as Sam
. khyaYoga teaches, then the liberated yogi is completely impotent not omnipotent. If power is relational and socially constructed, as more and
more commentators on this issue realize, then the free and independent yogi can have no power. Furthermore, the purus.a is not omniscient as the Christian God isknowing everything past, present,
and futurebut more like Aristotles God, a being knowing only its
own perfect nature. Finally, the yogi cannot properly claim omnipresence, because he must contend with the infinite number of individual
spirits who have a claim on the same spiritual space. (As we saw in
the last chapter, the Jainas solve this by saying that the soul takes on
the bodily shape of its last incarnation.) The purus.as are totally isolated and inactive, completely cut off from everything else, including
the Lord Isvara, who inspired the purus.as to become like him in the
first place. The lives of spiritual Titans are exceedingly solitary experiences. The purus.a is like the perfectly pure and victorious Jaina
saint, but is also absolutely alone.20
Hindu Titanism
105
measure of his greatness, but greater yet is (primal) Man: All beings
form a quarter of him, three-quarters are the immortal in heaven.23
The Titanistic subordination of the world and the gods culminates in
the declaration that Indra is born from the Purus.as mouth.
The Purus.a hymn is reworked in the Atharva-veda, where the
demotion of the gods is well advanced. As builders of the Primal
Man, it is easy to imagine them as Lilliputians swarming around the
giant body, erecting scaffolding and fashioning the breast and neck
of Man.24 But these godlings are not the real creators, for we learn
that it is Brahman, the single God [who] put sacrifice in Man.25 The
reference to Brahman, however, is self-reflexive, for Brahman [as]
Man [acquires] this fire,26 so the Primal Man is creator of himself.
The identity of Purus.a and Brahman is clear, when we are given an
interesting, but probably bogus, etymology of purus.a:
Brought forth above, brought forth athwart,
All cardinal points did Man pervade,
[Yes, Man] who Brahmans city (pur) knows,
By which he is called Man (purus.a).27
Brahmans city is radiant . . . yellow, gold, compassed with glory
round aboutjust as the Purus.a is always describedand the Creator Brahma has entered in.28
In the Br.hadaran.yaka Upanis.ad we find the purus.a motif refashioned once again: In the beginning this [universe] was the Self
alone,in the likeness of a man (purus.a).29 In this same brahmana
we also see the post-Vedic tension between the sacrifice, which the
gods desperately need, and the Upanis.adic discovery of the A tman
within, which makes the sacrifice unnecessary. Whoso thus knows
that he is Brahman, becomes this whole [universe]. Even the gods
have not the power to cause him to un-Be, for he becomes their own
self. . . .30 In a word (viz., atman), the gods are being converted to
Brahmanism against their will! Here is their complaint:
Just as many animals are of use to man, so is each single
man of use to the gods. To be robbed of even a single animal
is disagreeable. How much more to be robbed of many! And
so the [gods] are not at all pleased that men should know
this.31
tman=
The gods pleas are in vain, for the new religion of Purus.a=A
Brahman, and the immediate divine power that it promises, is solidly
106
Spiritual Titanism
Hindu Titanism
107
108
Spiritual Titanism
forms, where the savior is a yogi or gnostic who has turned from selfish isolation to compassion for all creatures. On this interpretation,
Kr. s.n.a would be an example of a reverse avataralike Jesus and
Gautama (mortals made highest God)who take on, in the imagination of their devotees, the salvation of both humans and gods
alike. This transformation of Yoga Titanism into Bhakti Titanism is
most evident in Mahayana Buddhism.
In this section we have covered the development of the Purus.a
motif from the R. gveda through the Upanis.ads to the Bhagavad-gi ta
.
We have seen that there is a clear transformation of the Purus.a as a
sacrificial victim to a Titan of the universe, a view already implied in
the R. gveda. We need to acknowledge, however, that the Sam
. khya
purus.a is far less masculine than the Vedic purus.a. The former, as
we have seen, is impotent and passive as opposed to the active
prakr.ti. In the Sam
. khya system, as C. Mackenzie Brown explains,
the Paursic (manly) character of the cosmic [Vedic] Purus.a loses
any heroic, aggressive tendencies, becoming absorbed in the image of
the quiescent witness.54 We have also noted that in the Gi ta
Kr. s.n.a
elevates himself as the ultimate Purus.a, higher even than Brahman,
and takes a position equivalent to that of I svara the Lord. In the
next section we will discover that the theme of the Great Yogi continues in Puran.ic cosmogony as well.
The Purus.a as Cosmic Yogi
Hindu accounts of the fall of human beings generally describe
the gods as very anxious about the implications of such a great increase of evil in the world. The logic of Vedic religion is clear: wicked
people would sacrifice less, thus the gods would have less power. But
even more threatening to the gods (and to the priests who cultivated
them) is the existence of human ascetics. Doniger observes that a
priest might legitimately emulate the gods, but an ascetic should
not. An ambitious priest was like a god; an ambitious ascetic was like
a demon.55 The power of performing austerities (tapas) was one that
the gods could not keep to themselves, as they did the soma sacrifice.
Asuras and humans, therefore, had equal access to this powerful
means of gaining merit and liberation.
The reformulation of the Purus.a hymn in the Puran.as demonstrates the power and significance of Yoga Titanism. Here the divinized male person is given the highest titlepurus.ottamaand he
is also called maha
yogin. Madeleine Biardeau contends that this iden-
Hindu Titanism
109
110
Spiritual Titanism
fact that the Vedic tradition deified basic natural elements and made
mountains and rivers into goddesses. He also mentions the organic,
holistic worldview, based on internal rather than external relations,
which is contained within Hinduism. By homologizing the cosmos to
the human form, the Hindu sages, according to Kinsley, have given
the cosmos great value. Using the Purus.a hymn as an example of
this organic view, Kinsley does not realize that purus.a as human
form preempts both heaven and earth. The latter cannot possibly
have the intrinsic value that they do in Chinese philosophy. The ecological vision of organic harmony can come only from a worldview in
which each member of the cosmic triad has its own independence
and integrity. Even in Sam
. khya-Yoga, where prakr.ti does have its
own nature, it devolves, once human purus.as are free from it, into an
inactive, valueless mass.
Referring to some of the same passages that we have used to
support Hindu Titanism, Kinsley admits that such hymns might be
taken as evidence of spiritual megalomania, delusions of grandeur.
However, in the context of Hindu philosophical thought, particularly
in the context of the monistic vision of reality, it is clear that they
represent redefinitions of I and me.62 If Kinsley means the absolute monism of Advaita Vedanta, then the holistic and pluralistic
web of existence we witness with our five senses is not such a rich
fabric at all, but an undifferentiated One. Organic holism loses all of
its conceptual power for ecology if it is interpreted in terms of pure
nondualism.63 Ramanujas panentheismjust like American process
theologyis a much better philosophical model. There is a significant contrast between seeing the cosmos as a dreamlike appearance
.
(Sankara) and the cosmos as the very body of the Godhead (Ramanuja).64 The ultimate effect is that absolute monism desacralizes the
universe, while panentheism resacralizes it. If by monistic vision of
reality Kinsley means general Upanis.adic monism, then he must
acknowledge the undeniable presence of Sam
. khyas influence in the
Upanis.ads and in the Gi ta. If the passages are interpreted from this
perspectiveindividual selves are plural, real, and supremethen
it is difficult to avoid Kinsleys diagnosis of spiritual megalomania.
The passages that we have examined from the Upanis.ads and Gi ta
are not cosmocentric and not even theocentric if Purus.a is a deified
yogi.
In a provocative article criticizing the use of Advaita Vedanta for
environmental ethics, Lance E. Nelson contends that Advaita Vedanta achieves its nonduality exclusively not inclusively such that
disunity rather than unity with the world is the result. (John White
Hindu Titanism
111
The Yogi
and the Goddess
Without you [Radha], I [Kr. s.n.a] am inert and am always powerless. You have all powers [sakti] as your
own form; come into my presence.
Brahmavaivarta Puran.a1
You should consider who you are, and who nature is. . . .
How could you transcend nature? What you hear, what
you eat, what you seeits all Nature. How could you
be beyond Nature?
Paravati to Siva, Skanda Pura
n.a2
Prologue: The Dancing Goddess
In the beginning there were disembodied spirits suspended in
space, unmoving and fixed in trance. Enter a dancing Goddess, creating solid ground wherever she steps. Her dynamic gestures cause
the spirits to stir and gradually, one by one, they begin to dance with
the Goddess. As they dance, they take on bodies, and they, too, begin
to feel ground beneath their moving feet. Only one spirit, Isvara the
Lord, remains fixed and undisturbed. The cosmic dance continues
and becomes more complex, creative, and frenzied. Isvara, however,
begins to call the spirits back to their original state. He exhorts them
to give up their embodied lives, which to him are sinful and degrading. One by one, the spirits disengage from the Goddess, throw off
their bodies, and return to their static state of complete autonomy
and isolation. Without dancing partners the Goddess also falls into
inactivity. The cosmic dance is finished and the evolution of the
world ceases.3
113
114
Spiritual Titanism
Introduction
This chapter entertains the thesis that Indian goddess worship
serves to balance masculine views of individual autonomy and separation from the body and nature. As we have seen, Yoga Titanism
emphasizes personal isolation and is similar to Western Titanism in
that respect. The first section contrasts the passive and inert views
of the material principle (primarily found in Greek thought) with the
dynamic and creative views of Hinduism. The second section traces
the philosophical origins of Sakta theology with a focus on some
basic problems of Sam
. khyas purus.a-prakr.ti dualism. The third section demonstrates the fact that Puran.ic writers appropriated the
Sam
. khya principle of prakr.ti and the Vedantist concept of maya to
establish a powerful goddess ontology, one that overcomes the alienation from nature and from other selves found in Sam
. khya-Yoga philosophy. Hindu Tantrics used the concept of sakti to produce the
same results. The fourth section draws on Stanley N. Kurtzs psychoanalytic study of Hindu goddesses and presents his reasons why
goddess worship survived in the Indian subcontinent. The fifth section contains a critique of Kurtzs view and confirms a suspicion that
traditional Sakta theology does not actually express a genuine female voice. If this is so, then this mitigates somewhat the thesis that
Sakta theology is an answer to Titanism. Finally, some encouraging
manifestations of Sakta theology among contemporary Indian women
are discussed.
115
116
Spiritual Titanism
The co-option and exploitation of the creative energies of the female have a long history in Europe. Hesiods Theogony still preserves the idea of primordial chaos and Gaia the earth goddess as
the source of all things, but the power of the Greek Goddess was
gradually coopted by male deities, starting with Zeus and his selfcreated daughter, as well as with priests and philosophers. Although
there is an egalitarian human creation story in Gen. 1:26, in Gen. 2
Eve is made out of Adams rib and the mother of all the living becomes his subordinate. We now know that many ancient Hebrews
worshiped goddesses along with Yahweh, but this practice was of
course never condoned by the priests or prophets. The last trace of
the feminine in Hebrew scripture, a figure called Sophia (Yahwehs
helpmate in Prov. 8:30), was replaced, except for the Gnostic sects, by
the masculine Logos by Philo of Alexandria. For Philo the cosmos becomes the mind-born creation of God, whose Logos makes the world
out of absolute nothing, not the feminine chaos implied in Gen. 1:1.
The final banishment of the Goddess of watery chaos is implied in
the declaration in Revelation that in the new heaven and new earth
. . . the sea [is] no more (21:1). In the new creation, the writer is
telling us, the irrational goddesses will not bother us anymore.
In pre-Socratic philosophy the idea of phusis (Lat. natura), although not identified as female, was a creative and dynamic material
principle. This idea was replaced by inert atoms or by Aristotles hule,
both passive and inactive material principles. Aristotles idea that the
female womb was simply a receptacle for self-contained male seed
joined similar views of human reproduction in the ancient world. The
father essentially recreates himself in the womb of the passive mother.
There are, however, some significant exceptions to this view. While
most Buddhists affirmed the passive role of the female, both the
Jainas and the Tantrics thought that the menstrual blood served a
purpose in human conception.10 In the Jewish tradition there is a fascinating parallel to the Tantric idea of white and red semen:
There are three partners in man . . . his father supplies the
semen of the white substance out of which are formed the
childs bones, sinews, nails, and the white of his eyes. His
mother supplies the semen of the red substance out of which
is formed his skin, flesh, hair and black of his eye. God gives
him the soul and breath, beauty of features, eyesight, hearing, speech, understanding, and discernment.11
Although sexist and theocentric, this Jewish view does give an active
role to the female in the formation of the fetus. The Western esoteric
117
tradition preserved the coequal partnership of male and female principles until, as Carolyn Merchant has shown,12 witch-hunts and mechanistic science virtually eliminated the idea of dynamic nature
and the feminine symbolism attached to it.
rika
contains a vivid metaphor of prakr.ti as a se.
ductive dancer who entices all the inactive purus.as (save one Isvara,
who remains free and detached) to join in her creation of the world.
The fall into the created world can be reversed only by breaking
away from prakr.ti using the spiritual discipline of Isvarathe ma-
118
Spiritual Titanism
ha
yoginas a model for liberation. Successful yogic liberation would
leave prakr.ti without any dance partners and she then returns to an
undifferentiated mass. Says the indifferent one [purus.a], I have
seen her; the other [prakr.ti] ceases, saying I have been seen.16 (As
we shall see, the bashful prakr.ti, whose action reflects the ideal
Hindu wife, is dramatically transformed in the Sakta tradition.)
Purus.as not only attain complete separation from nature, but also
from Isvara as well. There is no union with ultimate reality as in Upanis.adic monism: With the cessation of prakr.ti . . . the purus.a . . . attains isolation (kaivalya) which is both certain and final.17
Kathleen M. Erndl acknowledges the influence of both Sam
. khya
and Vedanta on Sakta theology, but argues that the latter differs
from them in its relentless exaltation of the material world. It is more
thoroughly world-affirming than either of them.18 We have seen
that Sam
. khyas prakr.ti is more dynamic and creative than Greek
ideas of matter, but Erndl notes that Sam
. khya ultimately joins the
Greek and Christian project of devaluing matter, and in turn of devaluing the female. (Even though prakr.ti is the active power, the figurative language of the Sam
. khya literature always subordinates it to
purus.a, usually as a servant/wife to master/husband.) As we have
seen, prakr.ti will, according to the original view, return to an inactive,
undifferentiated mass, and the purus.as will be free of its interference
and distractions. In contrast to the near universal myth of the clash
of sky father gods with earth or water goddesses, Sam
. khya dualism
contains little conflict or tension. Indeed, enlightened souls discover
that natures intellectual and spiritual qualities (sattvagun.a) are
their ultimate means of escape from her. The Sa
m
rika
is rich
. khya-ka
in powerful figures of speech: As the unknowing milk functions for
the sake of the nourishment of the calf; so the prakr. ti functions for
the sake of the release of the purus.a.19
With regard to Vedantist influence on the S akta movement,
both Erndl and Mackenzie Brown recognize that goddess philosophy generally avoids the strict nondualism of the Advaitins. In
their enthusiasm for the goddess to preempt all previous ontological states, S akta writers sometimes call Devi nirgun. a Brahman
(transcending all qualities) as well as sagun.a Brahman (containing
all qualities). Making the Goddess free of qualities does not mean
that the phenomenal world then becomes an illusion, as it does in
Advaita Vedanta. (As an example, only one major commentary on
the Devi -Mahatmya, the one by Nagoji Bhatta, describes the Goddess as static nirgun.a Brahman. Another commentary by Advaitin
Bhaskararaya emphasizes the fact that the Goddess as nirgun.a
119
120
Spiritual Titanism
argue that isolation and possession actually diminishes any constructive use of personal power. John B. Cobb and David R. Griffin,
two process philosophers, state that the persuasive power to open
the future and give freedom [to others] is a greater power than the
supposed power of absolute control. . . .26
121
inal with this text. The author(s) obviously know that traditionally
Indras consort is Saci ; Vis.n.us wife is Laks.mi ; and Sivas mate is
Sati , Uma, or Parvati . But they deliberately coin feminized versions
of the male namesAindri for Indra, Vais.n.avi for Vis.n.u, and Mahaswari for Sivaso as to dissociate these feminine divinities from
any previous mythological connections. The authors very much wish
to stress the fact that these are not just wives of male deities; rather,
they are very much their own power, or more precisely, Devi s sakti.
One critical moment in the narrative of the Devi -Mahatmya
may be cause for some qualification to the current thesis. Knowing
that Mahis.asura cannot be defeated by man or beast, all the male
gods combine their own energy (tejas) to create the Goddess. The
passage, in Coburns translation, is as follows:
Then from Vis.n.us face, which was filled with rage,
Came forth a great fiery splendor (tejas),
(and also from the faces) of Brahma and Siva.
And from the bodies of the other gods, Indra and the others,
Came forth a great fiery splendor,
and it became unified in one place.
An exceedingly fiery mass like a flaming mountain
Did the gods see there, filling the firmament with flames.
That peerless splendor, born from the bodies of all the gods,
Unified and pervading the triple world with its lustre, became a woman.31
The fact that Devi is produced from the gods tejas appears to mitigate the thesis that Devi is a cosmic power truly her own. Coburn
has captured the meaning of tejas nicely by combining the ideas of
brilliance and luminosity, and it has been variously defined as fiery
splendour, glory, fiery destructive power, energy.32 Tejas can also
mean virile semen, which relates it to another word for male
powervi rya, meaning manliness, heroism; male seed. For example, Agnis fiery seed (tejas), which later becomes Sivas, the incredibly hot semen that cannot be contained by anything except the god.
dess Ganga (as Parvati s substitute womb), gives rise to the war-god
Skanda.
Interestingly enough, especially for those used to Judeo-Christian ideas of divinity, tejas is not a necessary attribute, that is, it is
not inherent in the nature of the gods themselves. This explains why
the devas and the asuras both need soma or amr.ta to keep themselves energized, and that is the reason why the Manusmr.ti fre-
122
Spiritual Titanism
quently refers to tejas origin as the Veda and the rituals it contains.33
In the same text the derivative nature of tejas is seen in the phrase
the brilliant energy of ultimate reality (brahma
).34 Tejas is not only
an attribute of the gods and antigods, but it is also found in the
Manus, sages, priests, kings, and ordinary men. The priest takes on
a physical form of brilliant energy (tejas) and attains the supreme
condition . . .; the king is made from particles of these lords and
gods, therefore he surpasses all living beings in brilliant energy
(tejas).35 Tejas ebbs and flows, as can be seen in the man who breaks
a vow of chastity, sheds his semen, and loses his tejas back to the
gods.36 Also significant is the case of the man who loses his tejas by
having sex with a menstruating woman, and the priest who loses his
vitality by looking at a woman putting on her eye make-up, rubbing
oil on herself, undressed, or giving birth.37 Even in their misogyny
the author(s) of the Manusmr.ti give a backhanded compliment to the
power of woman.
The verbal root sak gives rise to at least three words in the Vedas: Sakra (powerful one), a name for Indra; saci (personalized as
Indras consort Saci ); and sakti. The latter two words have the general meaning of ability, power, capacity, but until the Sakta
Puran.as they were not yet related to any notion of cosmic power as
feminine. Returning to the Devi -Mahatmya let us look at a crucial
passage: Whatever and wherever anything exists. . . . O you who
have everything as your very soul, of all that, you are the power
(sakti). . . .38 We can see that the first Sakta theologians have drawn
on the Vedic sakti to make a full-blown deity, separate from, and now
fundamental to, the existence of all gods and goddesses. As Coburn
phrases it: rather than being quasi-independent of its possessor
(the Vedic view), sakti now is not something that a deity has, but
something that the Goddess is. . . .39 Sakti is something Devi has as
a necessary attribute and, panentheistically, something that everything else in the universe has by virtue of Devi s omnipresence.
Phrased metaphysically, sakti is always a substance, not an attribute, while the reverse is true of tejas, where even in Indian
physics fire (tejas) is just one of the attributes, along with air and
water, of a basic substance (bhu
ta).
Sakta theology appears to have broken the vicious cycle of the
Vedic maxim, explained superbly by Brian K. Smith (supra, p. 100),
that one gains power only at anothers expense. The Vedic power
game, as with most patriarchal concepts of power, is a zero-sum
game. Those who control the sacrifice, either by hook or by crook
(with the gods dominating in the crook department), control tejas.
123
So the result is constant battles between gods and antigods, gods and
ascetics, priests and kings. The Sakta view is different: even though
Mahis.a loses his tejasDevi teases him to show his womanish nature40he still presumably has his own sakti, for this is a power that
all beings have by virtue of their very existence.
If Devi has her own ontological status as supreme prakr.ti and
sakti, then we are compelled to read her creation out of the gods
tejas much differently than one might initially. In the context of
Sakta ontology, it must mean that the gods were simply able to make
her appear, or, as we shall see, to add attributes to a preexisting primordial power. It might also mean that the gods are now assigning,
as a sign of deference (they give her all their weapons), their brilliance to Devi and become dim in the same way that Siva becomes
inert when Kali dances upon him. Significant also is the fact that
Devi calls on a gods sakti, not his tejas, to join in her fight against
Mahis.a. Equally significant is the fact that when Mahis.a complains
about being ganged up on by so many goddesses, Devi draws all the
saktis into herself and finishes the battle alone. Finally, even though
the text refers back to the creation out of the gods tejasborn from
the bodies of the gods41the very next verse states that the Goddess
was born from the body of Gauri (=Parvati ), which essentially
means that she is born out of herself, because, as Coburn sees it,
Gauri as a supreme form of the Goddess.42 Or to see the question
even more fundamentally the author(s) clarifies Devi s birth: She
is said to be born in the world, even though she is eternal.43
Our interpretation is confirmed by looking at the same event as
portrayed in the Devi -Bhagavata Puran.a. Just as in the Devi -Mahatmya, the Goddess, here called Mahalaks.mi , appears out of the
gods tejas. However, in the detailed description that follows, it is
clear that the gods are simply adding attributes to, or enhancing preexisting attributes of, a primordial deity. If Devi is nothing but the
sum total of the gods fiery energy, then the following statement
makes no sense: Even Brahma, Vis.n.u, Mahes.a, and Indra are never
competent enough to describe her form properly.44 The Goddess is
constant, she is always existent; . . . She assumes different forms for
the fulfillment of the devas ends. . . .45 In a clear allusion to
Sam
. khya, the author(s) describes Devi as the actor and the gods as
mere spectators. The Devi comes out of that mass of celestial
light,46 which suggests that she comes out on her own stage with the
gods tejas as its lighting.
The Devi -Bha
gavata Pura
n.a combines Vedanta, Sam
. khya, and
Tantra in a marvelous synthesis. Devi is first and foremost Nirgun.a
124
Spiritual Titanism
125
126
Spiritual Titanism
gods warn that the world cannot live without love and that it will be
ruined as a result of his rash act. Siva refuses to see the logic of this
version of Parvati s argumentthat isolated purus.as are empty and
impotent without the life-giving qualities of prakr.ti. Siva repeats his
warning that desire is the cause of the downfall of all beings, including
the gods. As a rejoinder, the gods, never known for their philosophical
acumen, present a very subtle and effective argument. They remind
Siva that the universe was created by desire: Indeed, the whole of it
is in the form of ka
ma. That ka
ma is not killed.54 The gods then lay
the philosophical noose around the great gods neck: It is from ka
ma
that the fierce krodha (anger) takes origin. You yourself have been won
over by krodha.55 This response makes Siva even more angry and he
becomes desirous of burning (everything) with his third eye.
iva, Wendy
In her Asceticism and Eroticism in the Mythology of S
Doniger presents a thorough analysis of the Siva-Kama-Parvati relationship, and one of the most helpful references she found was a
Buddhist poem, which reveals succinctly the fundamental problem
of Hindu asceticism:
Love and anger both are states
hostile to self-control
What then did Siva hope to gain
by slaying Love in anger?56
The anger of the gods and sages, and the alacrity by which they incinerate their opponents, represents a fatal flaw in their spiritual
discipline. Rather than find a Golden Mean as the Buddha or Aristotle recommend, the Hindus are notorious for pursuing, as Doniger
suggests,57 the Golden Extremes of excessive eroticism on the one
hand and excessive asceticism on the otherboth filled with the
pride and hubris of a Titan.
The Skanda Pura
n.a presents Parvati (here called Girija) as the
mother of the universe: it was she who created the three worlds
along with Brahma and others. Making use of the qualities of rajas,
sattva, and tamas, she caused the origin, sustenance, and annihilation (of the worlds).58 Parvati s plan for the seduction of Siva does
not follow Buddhist lines; rather, it is eminently Hinduthoroughly
excessive and thoroughly dialectical. (Her tapas is so great that it
dialectically coincides with the heat of her desire to become Sivas
mate.) Parvati s penance produces a fire so great that it threatens
the triple worlds. This leads to yet another embassy of the gods to
Siva, in this case led by Vis.n.u. This time Siva relents, predicting that
127
Parvati will bring Kama back to life. He still, however, warns about
the dangers of desire, but at least now he concedes the winning point
in the previous debate: It is from it (ka
ma) that anger is produced.59
Siva concedes much more in the scene in which the two lovers
become engaged. While earlier praised as the father, mother, and
lord of all the worlds, Siva now proclaims Parvati to be the creatrix
of the universe by means of her maya and her prakr.ti. The translator G. V. Tagare finds it odd that Siva launches into a detailed exposition of Sam
. khya cosmogony (with a bit of Vedanta mixed in), but it
is both natural and particularly conducive to the thesis of this chapter. Siva admits that Parvati as prakr.ti is capable of action continuously, while he as the purus.a is totally inactive. (This gives Siva
the lame excuse that it must be Parvati who actually proposes marriage!) The crucial passage is the following: The being devoid of
gun.a has become enveloped by gun.a
s. . . . The independent one has
become dependent. O goddess, a great thing has been achieved by
you.60 The great Goddess has persuaded a great, but reluctant Yogi
that he must merge with prakr.ti, which amounts to a total transformation of the Sam
. khya philosophy. The alleged independence of the
isolated purus.a has been replaced by an interdependent relational
self. Kama has indeed been reborn, namely, in the sakti of the androgyne that is Siva-Parvati the Ardhanari svara. By means of a
grand coincidentia oppositorum they have both reached a double
goal: the fire of yogic tapas and the fire of ka
ma. In Sakta theology the
possibility of both mukti and bukti has been combined in one deity.
128
Spiritual Titanism
explain the demise of the Goddess in Europe and her continued presence in India, this theory has very negative implications for the Indian psyche. The Indian males unresolved relation and therefore
unhealthy attachment to his mother is reflected in his societys continued celebration of the Goddess, whose two traditional forms represent the bad, terrifying mother on the one hand (Kali and Durga)
and the nurturing domesticated wife-mother on the other (Parvati ,
Laks.mi , and Sarasvati ) on the other. Therefore, while the typical
Western male frees himself from this ambivalent mother image and
becomes an autonomous individual, the Indian male remains trapped
in the Oedipal phase and suffers a lack of ego identity and selfesteem. The traditional psychoanalytic image of the Indian male is
of a young boy, spoiled by an overindulgent mother, suddenly thrust
into a male community that terrifies him and that offers him no constructive way of coping with the transition. Kurtz summarizes this
position:
[Traditional] analysts give us a Hindu child locked in the
mothers embrace. In this traditional account, the mothers
indulgent presence surrounds the child until around the age
of five when the fathers discipline intervenes traumatically.
This juxtaposition of prolonged indulgence and sudden frustration is said to mark the Hindu adult with a hidden yearning for the idyllic past, a time when child and mother were
one.61
In contrast the Western male does not remain locked in the mothers
embrace; rather, he forms a successful relation with both his biological and spiritual father and leaves his mother and the Goddess
behind. Cosmic power then is coopted by the male and masculinized,
as we saw in the language of the defense intellectuals.
Kurtz tries to demonstrate how the evidence of Santos.i Ma dissolves the traditional distinction between unmarried goddesses of
terror and destruction on the one hand and married goddesses of domestic virtue on the other. In the movie about Santos.i Ma, a daughter of the elephant god Gan.esa and hence a granddaughter of Parvati , she is portrayed as a benevolent virgin who is abused, both
verbally and physically, by the married goddesses. Even before the
rise of Santos.i Ma, there were enough discrepancies in the traditional model to bring it into question. For example, the ferocious,
blood-drinking Kali standing on the body of her husband Siva is a
striking counterexample to this model. (The fact that Siva eventu-
129
ally pacifies her does not entirely explain away the anomaly.) The
traditional model has also been undermined by Lynn Bennetts field
studies in Nepal, which show a tension between dangerous wives,
especially when the young Hindu wife first enters her husbands
family, and benevolent unmarried sisters.62
In his investigation of Santos.i Ma, Kurtz was frustrated by the
tendency of his respondents to redefine her in terms of the other goddesses, especially Durga. His failure to discover the specific sociological origins of a new goddess led him to an even greater discovery:
in India all goddesses are ultimately one. There are not two types of
goddess, one malevolent and the other benevolent, but rather one
Goddess who appears diverse because the typical Hindu child, growing up in an extended family, experiences a wide variety of women. A
mother, heretofore perceived as completely benevolent, can now appear as malevolent when she gives the child over to another female
family member for care. The child will forgive her mother when she
returns safely to her, but will still continue to mistrust her and other
women in the extended family. In an intricate new schema to explain
the Hindu goddesses, Kurtz provides for a malevolent-benevolent
range for all the goddesses as psychological projections of sisters,
daughters, aunts, wives, mothers, or mothers-in-law.
Kurtz believes that many observers have misperceived the Indian mother as a smother mother, a term more appropriate for the
isolated mother of Western nuclear families. Kurtz shows that the
Indian mother, like mothers in other non-Western societies, does not
show inordinate affection for her children. The conclusion that Kurtz
draws is that the Indian child, far from being less able to cope in the
wider world, is better equipped psychologically and emotionally to
face the deepest issues of human life. This is especially true if this
psychological development is continually reinforced by hearing and
incorporating the stories of Hindu mythology. While the Western individual is left alone to resolve the basic issues of separation, sex, violence, and death, Hindu mythology provides the Indian with a
public form of psychotherapy that is free and readily available.
Finally, to correct the misapplication of Freudian models to Indian culture, Kurtz claims that Indian males pass through a Durga
complex rather than an Oedipus complex. The Durga complex resolves pre-Oedipal tensions between the child and his mothers in
the formation of an ego of the whole, a social, relational self that
gives the child a sense that he is whole and good in so far as he contains and is contained by the group.63 On this account the isolated
Western self or yogic purus.a is the pathology, not the norm. (We need
130
Spiritual Titanism
131
132
Spiritual Titanism
protect a Hindu males genitals and semen and help him get a good
wife. Therefore, it looks as if the Devi myth contains far more unresolved pre-Oedipal conflicts than Kurtz would like to admit. After
all, Durga is the kings goddess, and her cult is administered by him
and by his priests. In the not too distant past these same men went
to war with her blessings, and Hindu militants called on her before
they destroyed the mosque in Adhyohya in December 1992. If Durga
is the leader of armies, then she is not so different from Yahweh the
Warrior, Lord of Hosts (=armies).
These observations raise some problems for my thesis that Goddess worship serves as an answer to Hindu Titanism. If Durga is primarily a projection of male desires to control the world, then Kurtz
and I are in trouble. If Durga is nothing but a female Titan, then my
thesis is rejected, not supported. In this view the Goddess represents
an uneasy fusion of the stereotypical compassionate mother and aggressive male-warrior. (Devotees are never lovers of Devi , as they
are of Kr. s.n.a, but are children in her maternal embrace.) The maternal role is virtually absent in the Devi -Mahatmya, and the words
tejas and vi rya (virile, heroic power) appear frequently.70 But even in
the Devi -Bhagavata, where the maternal role is strong, anger, violence, and aggression are also present. Here her battle with Mahis.a
is portrayed as a contest between a real man (the Goddess) and a
eunuch-demon, who has, as Doniger translates it, no balls.71 Devi
reminds the demons that she has manliness (paurus.a) as her inherent nature, obviously referring to her purus.a nature.72 Although
the final goal of the authors of the Devi -Bha
gavata is to present the
Goddess as beyond gender, it is still significant to note that in her
cosmic manifestation (visvarupa) she appears in a male form complete with male genitals.
It is also intriguing to note that one Indian artist has portrayed
Indira Gandhi not as Si ta, nor Sarasvati , but as Durga riding on her
tiger.73 This particular deification of Indira Gandhi brings us back to
one of the central themes of Hindu Titanism: the apotheosis of individual human beings. This divinization of human beings was usually
focused on the male priest or on the male yogi, but could, especially
as Sakta theology became popular, also be embodied in a woman as
well. Both the humanization and feminization of God is seen in Vasudeva S. Agrawalas view where Brahman is both eternal man and
eternal woman.74 If Titanism is defining divinity in terms of humanity, here is a possible source for both male and female Titans in the
Hindu tradition.
133
134
Spiritual Titanism
Conclusions
Westerners in search of a Goddess in eclipse for nearly two thousand years have the principal advantage of starting fresh. Most
women and men are in control of their own research and of the reconstruction of the myths they wish to live by. They are free to draw
inspiration from a vast cross-cultural reservoir of spiritual resources. If they perceive that ancient Goddess worship has been compromised by too much male interference, then they can choose from
myths selectively or create new ones of their own. Cynthia Humess
field research in Uttar Pradesh indicates that more Hindu women
are now willing to reform their own tradition. Humes agrees that
there is a fundamental residue of sexism and patriarchal subversion
in traditional Devi worship: [I]ronically, men may more closely express divinity than females, even when the Divine is viewed ultimately as the Goddess, for men are not permeated with evils as
women are. . . .78 Nevertheless, Humes has observed significant innovations. At the Vindhyachal temple near Mirzapur many women,
having learned Sanskrit in school, are now reciting the Devi Mahatmya by themselves. Other women sing praises to the Goddess
in the vernacular, and one of the most famous singers is called guru
by her own husband. Other women are channeling for the Goddess,
or in a substantial break from tradition, are creating modern dances
for her.
In the area of ecology one example is worthy of mention. In her
book Staying Alive: Women, Ecology, and Development Vandana
Shiva draws on the principles of Goddess philosophy and critiques
the standard model of economic development in her own Indian subcontinent. She calls it maldevelopment and claims that it is the
product of a partriarchal view of the world. Shiva describes this philosophy as one that
ruptures the cooperative unity of masculine and feminine,
and places man, shorn of the feminine principle, above nature and women, and separated from both. . . . Nature and
women are turned into passive objects, to be used and exploited for the uncontrolled and uncontrollable desires of
alienated man.79
Shivas operative word for feminine power is prakr.ti, and she believes that Indias women (and the men who work with them in ecologically sound occupations) are the current embodiment of the
135
Goddess dynamic, healing power. Shiva and the brave women she
writes about are using Sakta theology to fight their battles over the
forests, water, and food of India.
Before we discuss one last contemporary example, let us briefly
look at one positive female model from the Mahabharata, one that
serves as a balance to Durga the warrior. This is the story of Draupadi , common wife of the Pandava brothers and a goddess in her own
right, at least in the Tamil tradition.80 In the Mahabharata Kr. s.n.a is
not, contrary to his popular reputation, a god of peace and compassion, but a warrior-god who leads his own clan and his relatives into
total destruction. One essential part of Kr. s.n.as plan is that Yudhishthira, the eldest and most pacifist of the Pandava brothers,
should lose a game of dice, which leads to the humiliation of Draupadi and to the exile of his brothers. In response Draupadi dares to
condemn Kr. s.n.a:
As a man splits log with log, stone with stone, iron with
ironthings that [of themselves] can neither move nor
thinkso does the Lord God, the Self-subsistent, the primal
Grandsire, hurt one creature by means of another, establishing for himself an alibi. Joining things together only to disjoin them again the Lord acts at his own good pleasure,
playing with his creatures as children play with dolls. He
does not treat his creatures as a father or a mother would
but acts in raging anger; and since he acts so, others follow
his example.81
Although Draupadi is not exactly an innocent agent in the high
drama of this grand epic, her indictment of God is as severe as Jobs.
Yudhishthira is shocked at his wifes blasphemy and defends Kr. s.n.a
in ways very similar to Jobs friends. Finally, Gandhari , wife of the
Kuru king Dhritarashtra, also curses Kr. s.n.a for the destruction that
he has wrought, and predicts that his tribe will also be destroyed and
that he will fall, Achilles-like, to the arrow of a hunter.82
Finally, let us feature Mallika Sarabhai, a Gujarati dancer and
actress, most famous for her role as Draupadi in Peter Brooks
Maha
bha
rata. In a recent interview in the Deccan Herald, Sarabhai
tells how she fought for a rewriting of Draupadi s character. As she
explains: Despite researching the Mahabharata for eleven years,
they are white Anglo-Saxon men. To them, the whole concept of
women as Shakti was unknown.83 Since then she has gone on to
choreograph and stage Shakti and Sitas Daughters, both powerful
136
Spiritual Titanism
137
tinues and becomes more complex, creative, and frenzied. The spirits call to Isvara and encourage him to join them, but he resists saying that what they are doing is sinful and degrading. The dancing
beings persist in their attempt to get the great Yogi to join the cosmic
dance, and finally, but reluctantly, he agrees. His steps are awkward
at first, but gradually he, too, is dancing eagerly like the rest of
them. At times it appears as if the Goddess and the Yogi are a single,
united body. The Goddess is well pleased and the cosmos continues
and all embodied beings are blessed beyond measure.
Neo-Vedanta and
Aurobindos Superman
Introduction
Both Ramakrishna and Aurobindo were considered avata
ras, incarnations of the divine. Ramakrishnas divine nature (as Vis.n.u) was
confirmed by several prominent Bengali holy men, and one of Aurobindos followers has called him the author of the universe.5 As
this divine status was self-attested as well as proclaimed by their disciples, it would seem that they are indeed very good candidates for
spiritual Titanism. We shall see, however, that there are some important mitigating factors, most notably Tantric elements in which
139
140
Spiritual Titanism
141
142
Spiritual Titanism
a mature manner. He remained Kali s child, never her lover (nor any
other womans), and poured his sexual energies into intense emotional and physical relationships with his boy disciples.
It is a great irony that what Kripal takes to be a personally devastating encounterthe apprenticeship with Totapurithe orthodox followers interpret as the philosophical turning point of Ramakrishnas life. Vivekananda and others maintain that Totapuri
taught him that there was something higher and more ultimate
than the Mother, namely, the nirgun.a Brahman of Advaita Vedanta.
It is true that Ramakrishna quickly absorbed the teaching and he
amazed his guru in experiencing nonduality in such a short time. Kripal, however, demonstrates very convincingly that it was Totapuri who
was converted to Sakta theology rather than Ramakrishna being
transformed into an Advaitin. Even The Gospel of Ramakrishna
records Totapuris attempt to drown himself in the Ganges only to be
saved by a vision of the Mother.11
In one crucial passage Ramakrishna refers to a sword of gnosis
by which he was able to cut the world of name and form from the
formless Absolute and to attain samadhi in the latter. Presumably,
Ramakrishna was then able to leave the world of prakr.ti behind.
Kripal argues that this was only a temporary division, and that his
dialectic, like Aurobindos, was always both-and synthetic rather
than the neither/nor of the Advaitin neti, neti. As Kripal states:
Moreover, within this dialectic, the goddess of the Many always is
given preference over the god of the One. . . . In the end, her truths
are more ultimate, more psychologically true, more mystically satisfying than those of . . . Vedanta.12 One specific psychological truth
mentioned here is the I-Thou experience of the bhakta-sakta, which
requires a social, relational self not the totally dissolved self of the
Advaitin. In a direct reference to the life of Kr. s.n.a,13 Ramakrishna
definitely sides with Kr.s.n.as Gopi s, who even though they had an experience of the formless one, much preferred the I-Thou experience
with their Lord.
Let us return to Ramakrishnas divine status and try to gain
some clarification about these allegations. Ramakrishnas father
Kshudiram was passionately devout and managed to accomplish
several major pilgrimages during this lifetime. During a trip to
Gaya in 1835 Vis.n.u appeared to him in a dream and declared that he
would be born as his son. At the same time Ramakrishnas mother
Chandra Devi also experienced an amazing dream: It was as if a luminous god entered my bed and lay down.14 Later, in broad daylight
at the Siva temple, she claimed that she was impregnated by a di-
143
vine light that emanated from Sivas great limb. From the very beginning Ramakrishnas life was marked by the interplay of the erotic
and the divine and by the powerful Bengali mixture of Vaishnava devotionalism and Siva-Sakta sensualism.
After he was installed as the priest at Dakshineswar, he began
having bizarre experiences, which both he and his associates
thought was some severe mental disorder. As we have already seen,
it was the Brahman.i who declared that Ramakrishna was not insane
but was in fact an incarnation of Vis.n.u. This claim was confirmed by
two local spiritual leaders: Vaishnavacharan, an eminent Tantric
teacher, and Pundit Gauri. Ever refusing to make an issue of it or to
exploit it in any way, Ramakrishna was very nonchalant and modest
about these attestations. He never, however, denied the truth of
them and never rejected the implication that he was in a great line
of men-godsfrom Kr. s.n.a, Buddha, Christ, and down to Caitanya.
In many sayings Ramakrishna was inclined to speak of the incarnation of God in every person, good or evil. Ramakrishnas own
interpretation of Narayan.a, a name for Vis.n.u, was man (nara) is in
his essence God.15 This doctrine appears to take on a very specific
application after he dislocated his arm while embracing the Lord
Jagannath in the erotic state.16 After this incident Ramakrishna
committed himself almost exclusively to a view of total divine immanence in which social relations and the body took on new emphasis and value. Furthermore, as Kripal demonstrates, Ramakrishnas
sayings about this crucial event are intimately connected to explicit
exclamations of love for his male disciples: I love them, I see
Narayan.a in them.17 Therefore, this statement and others (You
have assumed a body; therefore enjoy God through His human
forms)18 have an undeniable homoerotic ring to them. Ramakrishna
admitted that God manifests herself to a greater degree in puresouled devotees,19 namely, his young male disciples. By turning
from the Spirit-form of God to particular human forms,20 Ramakrishna may have been finally embracing a Tantric practice that he
previously rejected. In Vaishnavacharans Tantric community one
was obliged to choose a ritual sex partner as ones own deity and
then to delight in God. If Kripal is correct, Ramakrishnas view of
incarnation and human divinity is quite distant from the grand cosmic theories of divinization that we have found in other forms of
Indian Titanism. Not only is the hubris and social isolation eliminated, but we now see that the act of celebrating God in the form of
young boys is more emotional and psychological than theological and
philosophical.
144
Spiritual Titanism
145
the rose garden only after full immersion in the world of experience.
A full dialectic of the sacred in which the pure is synthesized with
the impurein which infantile sexuality is replaced (but not lost) in
genital sexualityis not present in Ramakrishna. He is fully cognizant that such a commitment would involve a fall that he was not
willing to experience:
The Child is a very pure state. In the Tantras there is talk
about the left-handed practice with a woman, but this is not
good. It leads to a fall. . . . I performed the worship of the sixteen-year-old girl in the child state. I saw that her breasts
were Mothers breasts, that her vagina was Mothers vagina.
This is the child statethe last word in mystical practice.25
Ramakrishna, however, is emphatic about the fact that the purity of
the child (and his boy disciples) should never be sullied by the impurities of the world; and in insisting that this is the ultimate in spiritual practice, he precludes the full operation of the dialectic of the
sacred. In Norman O. Browns neo-Freudian vision, Loves Body is
not possible without full immersion in the world. The mature lover
rediscovers the polymorphous sexual body in a process of returning
to Eliots garden and knowing it for the first time. Eliots development may be seen as fulfilling the threefold dialectic of premodern >
modern > constructive postmodern, while Ramakrishnas position
may be interpreted as one stuck in premodern notions of innocence
and totality.
146
Spiritual Titanism
Isvara is not only the Creator but includes all the sensible world as
well (sagun.a Brahman), and he reminds us that this is the not the
God with which we are identical:
There is one thing to be remembered: that the assertionI
am Godcannot be made with regard to the sense-world. If
you say in the sense-world that you are God, what is to prevent your doing wrong? So the affirmation of your divinity
applies only to the noumenal.27
We are God only in the sense that our essence is nirgun.a Brahman
.
tman. (This is also San
or A
karas position, because, as we have seen,
147
ferred the Puran.as and the Tantras, while the former liked the Gi ta
and the Upanis.ads, rejecting the Puran.as as superstitious and the
Tantras as obscene and poison to the mind. Vivekananda completely
reverses the Tantric position of Kali over Siva. According to Kripal,
he brags that, in the end, Siva reclaimed his rightful dominance
over Sakti and made her a servant, and that Kr. s.n.a left the women of
Vrindavana to become a mighty king in a distant city.30 Therefore,
Vivekananda rejects both the possibility of becoming either Kali s
child or lover, and returns the yogi to the nay-saying lion stage. He
was in fact called Narendra the Lion, who wished to preach the
virtues of spiritual manliness and renunciation.31
There is, however, evidence that shows Vivekananda much more
favorably inclined to Sakta thought. It is not true that the Goddess
completely recede into the background, because Vivekananda writes
poems in honor of her, with one on Kali that enthusiastically celebrates her destructive power.32 While in the United States he taught
classes on Mother worship, one in which he said that
Mother is the first manifestation of power and is considered
a higher idea than the father. With the name of Mother
comes the idea of Shakti, Divine Energy and Omnipotence.
. . . She is the sum total of the energy of the universe. . . .
Power is power everywhere, whether in the form of evil or as
Saviour of the world. . . . The first idea connoted by it
[Mother worship] is that of energyI am the power that is in
all beings.33
Vivekananda also believed that Mother worship was the best way to
solve the problem of evil and to express the idea of nonduality.34 Most
of Vivekanandas principal Western contacts were women and he
spoke often about womens rights. (Significantly, however, he focused
on the traditional view of chastity as the highest virtue.) In February of 1899 Vivekananda encouraged Nivedita (Margaret Noble), one
of his most celebrated disciples, to deliver a speech on Kali , and he
took strong exception to the critical remarks about this made by Mahendralal Sarkar, Ramakrishnas doctor.35
Vivekanandas article Modern India, published in a Bengali
journal Udbodhan in March of 1899, ends with this prayer to Devi : O
Thou Lord of Gauri, O Thou Mother of the Universe, vouchsafe manliness unto me! O Thou Mother of Strength, take away my weakness,
take away my unmanliness, and make me a Man!36 This prayer reminds one of ancient Hindu kings who called on Durga before they
148
Spiritual Titanism
went into war, and it is yet another example of the Goddess being exploited for specific male purposes. Vivekananda was obsessed with
the idea of strength and virility, and he appropriates the idea of sakti
for this purpose. In this passage he focuses on ojas, another term for
virility and equivalent to tejas: This ojas is the real man and in
human beings alone is it possible for this storage of ojas to be accomplished.37 As in traditional yoga practice all sexual energy must be
converted to ojas, and only by this means can men become God.
Therefore, Vivekanandas philosophy is, on balance, much more a
manly neo-Vedanta rather than a feminist Sakta philosophy.
149
stopped] short of the supreme effort to turn the body into a perfect
image of the Divine. . . .42 Aurobindo always speaks of the descent
of the divine not humans ascending to Godhood, but it is still not
clear where he stands on Avataravada versus Uttaravada. One reading would be that Rama and Kr. s.n.a are avataras but that he is a
ji vanmukta who has corrected and expanded the work of earlier
yogis. This means that the Superman is not an avatara but, as L.
Thomas ONeill phrases it, a man integrally transformed into divinity. A superman is the divine man and not the divine as man. . . .
the Avatar[a] comes to lead evolution whereas the superman is the
summit of evolution.43
Even though the ji vanmukta attains liberation while in the
body, the body and nature as a whole are not completely transformed
as they should be. As Aurobindo states: For its perfect solution
would be the material immortality of a fully organized mind-supporting animal body,44 which he claims would lead to a practical
omnipotence. Claims of human immortality and omnipotence are of
course primary facets of spiritual Titanism, but this claim of bodily
immortality presents further problems. Philosophers have long debated the intelligibility of human immortality without a body, but
the claim of somatic immortality exacerbates those logical problems
even more. Without attempting to solve them, Aurobindo alludes to
those very problems: To discover and realize the immortal life in a
body subjected to death and constant mutation,this is offered to us
as the manifestation of God in Matter and the goal of Nature in her
terrestrial evolution.45 The Platonic and traditional Indian assumption of the souls clean break with the finite world appears to be a far
stronger philosophical basis from which to argue for the souls immortality. This book is committed to an embodied self, one that recognizes its limits within the body and the world. Aurobindos
both-and, synthetic dialectic may work for some issuesmost
promisingly with regard to the reconciliation of sat (being) and asat
(relative nonbeing)but it cannot resolve the logical contradiction of
an immortalized mortal.46
The Gnostic Titanism we found in Jainism also appears in Aurobindo and in the Mother, the latter claiming that even after only
one experience of the Divine we shall know everything, and even
more.47 The Mother may mean only that we know the unity of Divine and of other general attributes. But if the claim is anything like
the Jaina position, then we definitely have a case of Gnostic Titanism. In The Life Divine Aurobindo speaks of a race of gnostic beingsomnipotent and omniscientwho not only embody a universal
150
Spiritual Titanism
151
152
Spiritual Titanism
153
154
Spiritual Titanism
to an extension and even to an outburst of the same divine
self-consciousness in other individual souls. . . .67
Although he confuses the Buddhas vow to preach with the Bodhisattvas vow of total self-surrender, Aurobindo acknowledges that
this principle finds its best expression in the Bodhisattvas decision
not to enter Nirvan.a until all sentient beings are saved. Aurobindos
Integral Yoga, however, extends even beyond sentient beings, for all
of nature will be redeemed. Even in Mahayana Buddhism the Bodhisattva and his community of saints will exit nature as we know it.
In contrast, as ONeil phrases it, the Superman is liberated in nature, not from it.68 Such a view obviously has significant ecological
implications.
Along with Aurobindos concept of social self comes an emphasis
on the affective dimensions of the human person. He recognizes the
fact that the use of pure reason is necessary to reach the heights of
metaphysical knowledge, but this knowledge does not fully satisfy
the demand of our integral being.69 An Integral Yoga requires a complete view of the human being as well as the involvement of all nature. Pure reason produces the abstract philosophy necessary to
guide life, but it is the passions that really drive human action. It is
not our intellectual ideas that govern our action, but our nature and
temperamentor, as the Greeks would have said, thumos and not
nous.70 As a result Aurobindos works are filled with references to
joy, delight, and bliss: The joy of being to others; for their joy will be
part of his own joy of existence. To be occupied with the good of all beings, to make the joy and grief of other ones own.71 For Aurobindo
gnostic being is replaced by bliss being, such that the heart supersedes the mind in universal beauty and harmony.72
Aurobindos commitment to Vedantist philosophy allows him to
counter the individualism and anthropocentrism found in the JainaSam
. khya-Yoga traditions. In this regard he retells the Mahabharata
story of the Asura Virochana and Indra to explain the correct way to
see the relationship of self and God. Virochana looked at himself in
the mirror and concluded that he was God. He gave full rein to the
sense of individuality in himself which he mistook for the deity.
Indra looked in the mirror, but he was still not clear on the matter.
He returned to the Devas priest Br. haspati and found out that he
was God only because all things were God, since nothing existed but
the One. If he was the one God, so was his enemy, the very feelings
of separateness and enmity were not permanent reality but transient phenomena.73 This story demonstrates yet another way to dis-
155
Conclusions
One is struck by some affinities between Aurobindos vision and
that of Buddhism, a connection he himself acknowledged. From the
standpoint of constructive postmodernism, the conceptual framework of this study, Buddhist philosophy is still preferred over Aurobindos neo-Vedanta. Even though his dynamic Sakti is a clear
.
advance over Sankaras static Brahman, Aurobindo is still wedded to
a substance metaphysics, one that prefers permanence over impermanence.74 Furthermore, Aurobindo maintains that the goal of evolution is already prefigured in its beginning: This teleology does not
bring in any factor which does not belong to the totality; it proposes
only the realisation of the totality in the part.75 This is definitely a
premodern totalism rather than a modern version of evolution. This
makes Aurobindo very different from Whitehead and other emergent
evolutionists, who believe that real novelty comes into the world.76
Aurobindos solutions to the problems of the One and the Many and
the self and others also have a ring of premodernism. (The apparent
fusion of human will with the All-Will is especially problematic.)
Therefore, we will now turn to Buddhism and Chinese philosophy as
the most appropriate ancient precursors of constructive postmodernism and as the most promising answers to spiritual Titanism.
Buddhism, Humanism,
and Titanism
Introduction
In this chapter we shall investigate the hypothesis that some aspects of Buddhism represent a form of Titanism. At the end of chapter 2 we saw how the Buddhas philosophy might be conceived as an
anticipation of constructive postmodernism. We have also seen that
Nagarjunas masterful dialectic undermines any unwarranted knowledge claims as well as thoroughly refuting any notion of a substantial self, Buddha, or world. Pure Land Buddhism avoids extreme
humanism in the same way that Christianity does, namely, by denying the basis for humanism in the first place. Shinrans rejection of
self-power in favor of the other power of the Amitabha Buddha
undercuts the axiom that humans can establish virtue or liberate
themselves under their own power. On this point Pure Land Buddhism joins the Abrahamic religions and leaves the gnostic religions
of Asia.
157
158
Spiritual Titanism
Buddhist Humanism
In an unpublished paper entitled Buddhism and Chinese Humanism, David J. Kalupahana contends that it is Buddhism, not
Confucianism, which should be promoted as the true humanism of
Asia. He claims that Gautamas rejection of transcendental knowledge, his declaration of moral freedom in the midst of karmic determinants, and his refusal to go beyond immediate experience all
converge with major elements of Western humanism. Based on
knowledge gained from experience and induction, a Buddhist, says
Kalupahana, can use an evaluative knowledge called anumana, a
mode of moral reflection that allows her to complete the eightfold
159
160
Spiritual Titanism
tic philosophy, then none of the classical Asian philosophies, including Confucianism, qualifies as such. Ironically, contemporary Western humanists cannot consistently hold to this criterion of freedom
either. The Humanist Pantheon, comprised of historical humanists
chosen by the editors of Free Inquiry, is filled with determinists such
as Lucretius, Epictetus, Spinoza, Hume, Mill, and Freud.6 Their
Academy of Humanism also contains the sociobiologist Edward O.
Wilson and other prominent scientists who subscribe to the theory of
universal determinism. It is clear that ancient and contemporary humanists support moral and social freedom, but do not agree on the
issue of free will and an internal self-determining agent. Furthermore, we have seen that too much emphasis on self-determination
can lead to Titanism.
Spiritual goals are present in both Buddhism and Confucianism,
so again we must reject the proposals of those who insist that true
humanism must be thoroughly secular. In chapter 10 we shall see
how Confucian humanism recognizes a finely tuned balance between
humans, heaven, and earth. Although it is more anthropocentric
than Confucianism, early Buddhist humanism never exaggerates
the human position as much as Sam
. khya, Jainism, or technological
Titanism. Without falling into Titanism Buddhists agreed with the
Jainas that human beings can achieve liberation under their own
power and with their own effortswithout divine aid, prayer, or sacrifice. With all these qualifications in mind, Kalupahanas thesis
that Pali Buddhism contains a very enlightened form of humanism7 is a very well supported.
Japans Soka Gakkai is one of the current Mahayana schools
that continues the tradition of Buddhist humanism. Their leader,
Daisaku Ikeda, although a controversial political figure, has written
a very fine biography of the Buddha that strongly emphasizes the
humanity of the Buddha,8 and thus avoids the docetism that characterizes many other Mahayana schools. Ikeda follows the medieval
monk Nichiren, whom he paraphrases as saying: The Buddha is an
ordinary human being; ordinary human beings are the Buddha.9
The interpretation of the second phrase is essential to formulating
Buddhist humanism correctly. If it means that all of us have the potential to understand the Four Noble Truths and to overcome craving in our lives, then we have done justice to Pali Buddhist philosophy. If it means that all of us somehow possess a Buddha-nature
metaphysically equivalent to the dharmakaya, the cosmic body of
the Buddha, then we have strayed from Buddhist humanism. The
monism of this position, namely, the implication that all individuals
161
are essentially one, undermines a central tenet of humanism: the individual integrity of each human being. The individualism of humanism has been seen as its greatest flaw, and it certainly is if the
individual is conceived as a social atom externally related to other
isolated selves. But if the individual is interpreted as the relational
and social self of Buddhism and Confucianism, then we have an idea
of self that avoids the two extremes of monistic dissolution and social
atomism. This means that any Titanism found in Mahayana Buddhism will be mitigated considerably, as it is in Vedanta, by monistic
tendencies that merge all selves into one; and this point is maintained even in those Mahayana schools that are consistently nonsubstantialist in their monism. (In other words, the self can dissolve
just as well into sunyata as it can into a divine substance.) On the
other hand, Titanism is exacerbated in the spiritual atomism of
Jainism and Sam
. khya-Yoga.
The Buddha Is just the Buddha
In the Pali scriptures there is a famous exchange between the
Buddha and a brahmin named Dona that seems to imply that the
Buddha was a spiritual Titan. Dona asked the Buddha what sort of
being he was, and Gautama answered that he was he was neither a
god nor a gandhabba (heavenly being) nor a yakkha (demon) nor a
human.10 The apparent meaning of this statement is that the Buddha was not a member of any of the six realms of existence, that is,
those for hellish beings, animals, hungry ghosts, humans, asuras,
and gods. For some Mahayana Buddhists this passage is positive
proof that the Buddha definitely claimed to have a transcendental
existence and could legitimately be called a god beyond the gods (devati deva).
Of all the realms of existence the deva-loka is an especially difficult one to leave: the gods are enjoying blessedness, but they are accruing karma because of their indulgence in heavenly bliss. This
view is found in a wide variety of Buddhist schools. In the Bardo Thdol it is clear that being a god does not mean that one is liberated. A
commentator on this famous text describes divine existence as a
realm of pride, complete self-absorption, and intoxication with the
existence of the ego.11 In Buddhaghosas eschatology, the gods are
expelled from their realm by a cycle of cosmic destruction that forces
them to take on human incarnations.12 This preference for human
existence, the embodied existence where true enlightenment can
162
Spiritual Titanism
163
164
Spiritual Titanism
cept was based on the Purus.a hymn.18 This hymn, which was analyzed in chapter 5, describes the Purus.a as creating the universe out
of his body, something the early Buddhist texts do not maintain. Furthermore, in the Purus.a hymn there is no mention of any prediction
of personality . . . from physiognomical characteristics,19 even
though this was part of pre-Buddhist Indian tradition. None of the
Hindu gods are said to have the laks.an.a, so they are not, at this
stage in the history of Buddhism, signs of a divine being. Therefore,
the attribution of the laks.an.a to the Buddha indicates an elevation
of his humanity not a transformation into divinity. In other words,
early Buddhists were drawing on physical marks that distinguished
superior human beings and not attributes generally given to the
gods. Wimalaratana sums up his argument this way: . . . The marks
belong neither to Vis.n.u, Narayana, or Siva in their origin, nor are
they signs of deification. Possession of these attributes does not invalidate the Buddhas humanity in any way. Yet it indicates that in
him humanity has become perfected.20 The fact that Rama was said
to have the same long arms as the Buddha is a minor exception to
this rule. The Hindu deities also used the power of the third eye
(urna), but from the Buddhas urna came rays of compassion and
wisdom, not destruction.
165
166
Spiritual Titanism
167
168
Spiritual Titanism
169
of the body is seen in the fact that the rupa skandha is associated
with the Vairocana Buddha, the Buddha at the very center of the Tibetan mandala.
Let us now look at the eighty-four Siddhas, whose gurus initiated them by means of the Hevajra Tantra. The powers of siddhi
were recognized and practiced by the earliest Buddhist monks. Here
is a description from a Pali text:
[The monk] becomes many or having become many, becomes
one again; he becomes visible or invisible; he goes feeling no
obstruction to the further side of a wall or rampart or hill as
if through air; he penetrates up and down through solid
ground as if through water; he walks on water without
breaking through as if on solid ground; he travels crosslegged in the sky like the birds on the wind; even the sun and
the moon, so potent, so mighty though they be, he touches
and feels with his hand; he reaches in the very body even up
to the heaven of Brahman.42
The Buddha himself practiced siddhi powers. He and his disciples
were said to have flown to Sri Lanka for missionary work; and the famous thousand Buddha art motif comes from a incident in which the
Buddha, in order to avoid capture, became many [i.e., 1,000] [but]
one again. The Buddha, however, was persistent in his warning
that siddhis could easily corrupt their practitioners and that they
alone could not promote liberation from the cycles of rebirth. Even
the Buddhist Tantrics held that the yogi who remained attached to
the minor siddhis could not be saved, for only the higher siddhis,
developed by compassionate outreach, could do that. As Robinson
states: By allowing himself to be beguiled by lesser powers, the siddha prevents himself from taking that one step further to total liberation.43 To place this within our Nietzschean heuristic, one could
say that the yogi of the minor siddhis is still trapped in the lion
stage, where the freedom and pride of having power over ordinary
constraints prevent one from further spiritual development.
We will generally focus on those Siddhas whose lives offer evidence against the charge of spiritual Titanism. First, however, let us
look at a Siddha who expresses the greatest temptation of yogic powers. There is the story of Kan.h.apa who deluded himself into believing that he was more powerful than his guru. In a fit of anger he
killed a young girl with his yogic powers. For his crime he was rebuked by the girls people: Those who call themselves Buddhists
170
Spiritual Titanism
171
ra.
Such
a
doctrine
allows Buddhist Tantrism and other
.
Mahayanist schools to validate the body and all of its affections. As
N. N. Bhattacharyya states: Liberation is not of the soul. It is of
[the] body which can be attained within the span of a human life.47
It is therefore significant that, after a life of love and compassion,
most of the Siddhas leave earth with their bodies intact. Buddhist
Tantrism has overcome one of the main failings of Yoga Titanism: its
mind-body dualism and its attendant antisocial isolationism. In his
praise of the two sister Siddhas, Kan.h.apa explains that to remain
merely in your own tranquility is the inferior way. You should work
for the benefit of living beings.48
172
Spiritual Titanism
able transform the old mental self into a new body-mind. The practice of zazen forces the mind to stop thinking and this state of nomind will allow monks to reunite with their body and nature as
whole. As Arifuku Ko gaku phrases it: It is nothing other than the
human beings becoming through the body a thing of nature.50
Kogaku finds that Dogens doctrine of body-mind compares very
favorably to Nietzsches idea of the body as a great reason. Like
Dogen Zarathustra proposes that the small reason they call spirit
should be a servant to the body, for I am body entirely, and nothing
beside; and soul is only a word for something about the body.51 In a
general way Ko gaku conceives the practice of zazen as the formation of an overhuman (bermenschlich) body by means of the human body.52 In a bold inversion of the Cartesian method, Nietzsche
persuasively justifies the somatic approach: the body is by far the
richer phenomenon, affording clearer observation and it is therefore methodologically permissible to take the richer phenomenon as
a key to the understanding of the poorer.53 (Given the fact that the
Japanese mi can mean both self and body, one should add that
the East Asian languages are far richer in their ability to express
these basic truths.) Kogaku concludes his insightful article with the
observation that both Dogen and Nietzsche extend the notion of body
into nature, so that the whole earth is the true body of the Buddha
and that Zarathustras motto Be true to the earth is also an expression of the bermenschs new body-self.
Moving from the Soto Zen to Rinzai Zen, we will, with the aid of
Graham Parkes, continue the comparative analysis of Zen and Nietzsche. Parkess focus is on the cultivation of the emotions, and he
wishes to destroy the stereotypical view of the Nietzschean bermensch overflowing with unbridled Dionysiac passion and . . . the
serene Zen master sitting in dispassionate contemplation, unperturbed by a single affect.54 Contrary to popular conception, Nietzsche is just as critical of an undisciplined life of passion as any
Indian ascetic. Taking the Rinzai monk Hakuin as his point of comparison, Parkes proceeds to argue that both he and Nietzsche have
a very similar program of spiritualizing the emotions. Hakuin warns
that a person who fanatically avoids the object of the senses and
dreads the eight winds that stimulate the passions . . . never will be
able to achieve the Buddha Way.55 Parkes speculates that Daoist influencethe idea that the sage has ordinary emotions but is not ensnared by themmay well have led to the positive view of the
passions that we find in Rinzai or Linji Chan, as the southern school
of instant enlightenment is called in China.
173
174
Spiritual Titanism
ously not a Daoist or Zennist means, but the end of spiritualizing the
passions is the same.
With the foregoing in mind we should not be surprised to learn
that it was a Linji monk who added the last two pictures to the famous Ten Oxherding Pictures. Earlier versions of these poignant
metaphors of the spiritual life consisted of five, six, or eight blackand-white ink drawings ending with a totally white circle. A Linji
monk by the name of Guoan Shiyuan (ca. 1150) added a ninth drawing Returning to the Origin (a natural landscape with no humans)
and a tenth Entering the Marketplace with Helping Hands (showing the pilgrim engaging a Buddha). The obvious point of these last
pictures is the one that the Siddha Kan.h.apa just made: To remain
merely in your own tranquility is the inferior way. You should work
for the benefit of living beings. In other words, one is not to remain
in the nonduality of sunyata, but is to returned purified and transformed for action in the world.
The transitional quality of the eighth picture can be seen in
terms of Han dynasty bronze mirrors, which had mountains, trees,
and wild animals engraved on their backs. In addition to the Zen
idea of the enlightened self as a perfectly polished mirror reflecting
nature as it is, these bronze mirrors offer an equally powerful Daoist
notion of looking through the mirror at the true nature of reality.62
This is an introspective look that turns out to have an exterospective
result; or, better yet, we have proved that there is no insurmountable
gap between the inner and the outer. Notice that neither metaphor
assumes that reality is an undifferentiated unity. Finally, the tenth
ox-herding picture takes us from the many wonders of nature to the
plurality of social relationsa plurality in an organic natural and
social whole, but a plurality nonetheless.
Let us now look at Ueda Shizuterus interpretation of the Ten
Oxherding Pictures. Ueda believes that they reveal a threefold negative dialectic, one that has similarities to the dialectic of constructive postmodernism discussed in chapter 2. The first seven drawings
represent the first thesis of the dialectic: a self struggling for enlightenment within the framework of a substance metaphysics. The
eighth picture of the void represents sunyata (as in all interpretations), which empties the self of all substantiality; and this represents the first negation of the dialectic. Steve Odin then explains
the rest:
Ueda emphasizes that this Zen Buddhist Nothingness that
desubstantializes the ego-self must not be adhered to as a
175
Nothingness but must itself be emptied through a deeper realization of the Nothingness of Nothingness. The ninth and
tenth stages depict the true self in the locus of absolute
Nothingness, the middle way of emptiness between eternalism and nihilism.63
The concept of absolute Nothingness is very obscure and problematic. Parmenides seems to be correct in his argument that absolute
nonbeing (ouk on) is unthinkable, whereas in The Sophist Plato proposed that relative nonbeing (me on), produced by the Form of Difference, is eminently intelligible.64 The same result can be achieved
less obscurely by the triadic formulas that were presented in chapter
2. Mapping it on to the Ten Oxherding Pictures we would have the
substantial self (1-7) > no substantial self (8) > relational process self
(910). This would follow the general triadic model of metaphysics,
deconstruction, and constructive postmodernism.
In his monumental work The Social Self in Zen and American
Pragmatism (published in this same Constructive Postmodern
Thought series), Steven Odin has studied in great detail the social
turn in twentieth-century Japanese philosophy. As he explains:
Whereas earlier Japanese models of selfhood tended to articulate human nature in negative terms as muga (Sk. ana
tman)
or no-self, the models formulated by 20th Century Japanese
thinkers have underscored the dialectical relation between
the individual and social aspects of personhood.65
The Japanese word for person (ningen) serves this philosophical purpose just as well as the Chinese word ren, which has the same fully
relational meaning. (See chap. 9 for a more in-depth discussion on
ren.) Ningen is composed of two Chinese characters, one meaning individual and the other meaning society. Developing a ningen model
of selfhood, Watsuji Tetsuro contends that even Heideggers Mitsein
has not overcome the anthropocentric bias of Western philosophy.
Building on Watsuji and others of the Kyoto school Odin makes a
thorough and convincing case for substantial parallels between twentieth-century Zen philosophy and American pragmatism. Rejecting at
least a half dozen previous interpretations of su
nyata
in Zen philosophy, he settles on the choice of social for su
nya and sociality for
su
nyata
. Focusing his study on George Herbert Mead, Odin discovers
that both Mead and Zen have thus converged upon the same fundamental insight: that the self and all events are a function of reality.66
176
Spiritual Titanism
Using also Dorinne Kondos work Crafting Selves, Odin offers a model
for self creation that follows our dialectic of reconstruction: people
learn to deconstruct their separate ego selves and to reconstruct new
contextual selves which are relationally defined as social, decentered,
multiple, fluid, open, shifting, and ever-changing.67 Vigorously rejecting deconstructive postmodernism, Odin retains all the value of
postmodernism without the negatives of the French deconstructionists: While [they] shatter all self-identity into a multiple play of differences with no unity, Mead instead shows how the multiple self
arises by taking on the social roles of others in the community at the
Me pole while having a source of unity and individuality at the I
pole.68 In chapters 9 and 10 we shall see that Confucianism provides
a similar view of the constitution of selfhood.
Conclusions
Let us now conclude with a summary of our discoveries. The
Buddhas Middle Way and his rejection of all cravingyogic as well
as sensualrepresents one of the most effective responses to Indian
Titanism. Although the Buddha adopted many of the techniques of
the yogis, he did not accept their ontology of self nor their specific
spiritual goals. Therefore, there is no evidence for any Yoga Titanism. In chapter 4 Gnostic Titanism was also eliminated when we
discovered that the Buddhas knowledge claims were so qualified
that the term omniscience is probably inappropriate. We also found
that the Pali Buddhist use of the term maha
purisa is not connected
with the Purus.a hymn of the R. gveda, one of the primary sources for
Hindu Titanism. In the early texts maha
purisa means perfect man,
but it does not mean that the Buddha was God. We did find, however,
some evidence of Buddhist Titanism in the Mahavastu, the concept
of Svayambhu, the trikaya doctrine, the appropriation of the visvaru
pa concept in the cosmological Buddha, and Tantric Deity Yoga.
The Siddhas remarkable feats, on the other hand, were overshadowed by an emphasis on their playfulness and on their ultimate commitment to compassion and social outreach. Finally, we have presented Zen, with its commitment to the body and a social self, as the
most compelling Buddhist answer to spiritual Titanism.
On the Deification
of Confucius
Introduction
Except for a miraculous birth story, Confucius was not elevated
in the same way as Jesus, Kr. s.n.a, or Gautama. The deification of
Jesus and Gautama happened fairly soon after their deaths, but the
glorification of Confucius by Chinese culture did not happen for five
hundred years. An analysis of the ways in which Confucius was regarded by Chinese culture reveals instructive differences between
177
178
Spiritual Titanism
him and the other saviors. Mahayana Buddhist and orthodox Christian philosophers rejected many popular notions about their respective saviors, but most accepted them as gods. For the purposes of our
thesis, it is significant that most Confucian philosophers never
viewed Confucius as a deity. Furthermore, popular notions of Confucius as a perfect sage differ very much from the modes of deification
we have seen so far. In summary terms, Confucius was not divinized
as a savior; rather, he was canonized as the saint of the literati.
In this chapter we will investigate the development of ideas
about the nature of Confucius person. First, we will review the relevant historical facts about how he was regarded in Chinese culture
and politics. Second, we will analyze two crucial texts that some
claim support the divinity of the sage. Here we will take issue with
recent attempts by Roger T. Ames, David L. Hall, and Edward
Machle to deify Confucius and the Confucian sage in general. Finally, we will propose Confucianism as one of the most constructive
Asian answers to spiritual Titanism.
179
180
Spiritual Titanism
by kowtowing to Confucius at the temple in Lu.12 In 1012 C.E. Chenzong bestowed on him the title Most Perfect Sage.
It was not until the reigns of Renzong and Shenzong (10231086
C.E.) that neo-Confucian influence was powerful enough to moderate
the excesses of the cult. In 1074 C.E. some officials proposed that Confucius be called di (God), but the Confucians of the Hanlin Academy
and the Board of Rites rejected the proposal. The official reason
given was that di was not a title that Zhou officials ever used for nobility, but John K. Shryock suspects that the real reason was [that]
the idea of divinity associated with the word . . . would have been obnoxious to the neo-Confucians.13 As an obvious but instructive contrast, just think of the undisputed doctrine of Christs divinity in the
medieval church.
The Mongol emperors mandated that the spirit tablets of Zhuxi
and of other neo-Confucian masters be placed alongside those of Yen
Hui, Zengzi, Zisi, and Mencius. (Other Confucian scholars were installed, and sometimes removed, over the centuries, with two added
as recent as 1919.) In his detailed description of the Confucian temple at Anjing, Shryock hesitates to translate the word shen as god(s)
for the reason that the Chinese could not possibly have considered
all these men, including Confucius, as gods. Significantly, the word
di is used to describe Guangong, the god of war, and currently the
most popular god in Hong Kong. Shryock concludes that the positions of Confucius and Guangong are different. The former is usually
considered as the perfect man, while the latter is a god in full standing.14 Reflecting this distinction in recent centuries, Confucian temples have been called wen miao, rendered most appropriately as
civil temple, not sacred temple. As Laurence G. Thompson states:
The entire complex was thus a memorial hall rather than a palace
of gods.15
In 1530 C.E. further attempts to discourage the deification of Confucius were made. It was decided that Confucius would no longer be
called prince and that the buildings erected in his honor would not be
called temples, but simply halls. (Under the Manchus, however, the
title prince was not only restored, but also applied to Confucius ancestors.) Furthermore, images of Confucius and his disciples, installed under Buddhist influence during the reign of Xuanzong
(712756 C.E.), were replaced by spirit tablets. Because of this switch,
the Jesuits, who arrived at the end of the sixteenth century, had no
reason to call Confucianism an idolatrous religion.
The coming of the Jesuits offers some significant insights about
how the Ming Chinese viewed Jesus vis--vis Confucius. It is obvious
181
182
Spiritual Titanism
183
184
Spiritual Titanism
perior because it eliminates divine authority, for a ren daojiao society would be ruled by a human king not by a divine one.25 What we
see in Yuans rejection of a Confucian religion and Kangs quasiscientific humanism is essentially a fulfillment of the Confucian
view of, as Herbert Fingarette so aptly phrased it in a book title, the
secular as sacred. On such a view, where the idea of a transcendent
deity is not functional, the word deification has no meaning at all.
185
obviously figurative nature of this passage; and (2) they do not read
the passage in its own context or in the context of traditional and
contemporary commentary. On the first point, Hall and Ames overlook the nature of the texts language. Just as we are not to believe
that the sage is actually an abysshe is only deep and unfathomable as an abysswe are not to think that the sage is literally
Heaven. Charles Mullers translation does not even hint at the sages
divinity: So sincere is his ren, so unfathomable is his depth, so vast
is his spaciousness.31
On the second point, chap. 31 describes the sage in human, not in
divine terms: Only the perfect sage . . . has quickness of apprehension, intelligence, insight, and wisdom, which enable him to rule all
men. . . . All embracing and extensive as Heaven and deep and unceasingly springing as an abyss! He appears and all people respect
him, speaks and all people believe him, acts and all people are
pleased with him. . . . Therefore we say that he is a counterpart of
Heaven. The attributes of the entire passage are elevated and exaggerated, but they are not to be taken as divine. Furthermore, we see
the source of the similes with Heaven and the abyss. Finally, we see
that the sage is the counterpart of Heaven, not identical to Heaven.
This passage reinforces the Chinese view of the Cosmic Triad, in
which each member maintains its own place, role, and integrity.
Tu Wei-ming, even though cited favorably by Hall and Ames, offers a less monistic, less pantheistic view of the cosmic triad of
Heaven, Earth, and human beings. For Tu human beings constitute
a trinity with Heaven and Earth, in which they form a coincidence
with Heaven, but they maintain a conceptual separation within
an unbreakable organismic continuum.32 This has to be the correct
view of the Cosmic Triad. Coincidence and conceptual separation
clearly do not indicate identity of any kind. Hall and Ames even
quote Tus warning that the Doctrine of the Mean does not mean to
suggest that Confucius is, in a sense, being deified.33 Nevertheless,
Hall and Ames, going against the texts and the tradition, claim that
the fact is, however, that Confucius is deified, or rather deifies himself.34 Ironically, Hall and Ames fight gallantly against the Christian idea of transcendence all throughout their book; but then, by
raising the issue of deification, which makes sense only within a
view of divine transcendence (or human transcendence in the case of
Yoga Titanism), they undercut their otherwise innovative reinterpretation of Confucius.
Hall and Amess deification of Confucius is especially baffling
because they argue persuasively that tian should be defined in a
186
Spiritual Titanism
187
ification of Confucius with the same fervor that the Jews have rejected
the divinity of Jesus, and we should do the same.
Edward Machles innovative rereading of Xunzi (discussed in
the next chapter) is also marred by his view that the sage is a supernatural being: The sages may thus justly be considered gods
and greater gods than most, since a sage is equal to Tian and
Earth.40 Machle claims that such an apotheosis of human into
godhead is, of course, no great problem for Chinese culture,41 but in
the previous section we have seen that there was a general waxing
and waning of the elevation of Confucius and of the other sages.
Most important, however, is that the philosophers themselves, except for Kang Youwei, Chen Huan Chang, and Yen Fu early in this
century, resisted the deification of Confucius. Not one of the medieval Confucian scholars, as we shall see in the next chapter, supported such a notion. Buddhist and Christian philosophers appeared
to have no problem with the deification of their respective figures,
but Confucian philosophers obviously did. On this issue especially it
is important to keep Chinese popular culture and religion separate
from Confucian philosophy.
Machle shows that previous commentators have underplayed
the use of the words shen and shenming in the text of the Xunzi. As
a result they end up overemphasizing Xunzis naturalism. The shen
or divinity of Tian is shown only indirectly in the cycles of the
heavens and the seasons. As the Xunzi states: It is to be called shen
because though we do not see its workings, we see its effectiveness.42 As we shall see, this is how Machle is able to distinguish between Tian and nature: Tian is the invisible spiritual force behind
nature. As there is no plural in Chinese, shen can be seen as both the
singular divinity Tian and the plurality of its spiritual effects. Not
seeing the actual workings, we see the effects, and for this reason
[the agents] are properly called spirits (shen).43 But surely we are
not to call these spiritual effects either God or gods. If we are to use
the word God, we should reserve it exclusively for Tian, which according to Machle is at the top of the cosmic hierarchy, as perfect
yang and as preeminent shen.44
As in the Hebrew uses of ruah (spirit) and nephesh (lit. breath),
the Chinese soul can also be called shen, this time human spirit not
a divine being. (Machle correctly relates this usage to the Greek psyche.) Therefore, Xunzi has no problem celebrating departed shen, but
he does reject superstitions about ghosts (gui). It is clear that in stating that the natural effects of Tian, including the actions of the sage,
188
Spiritual Titanism
are shen, Xunzi is in no way saying that they are divine beings. This
conclusion is consistent with Machles insistence, in a dispute with
Robert Eno,45 that Tian and the sage kings must be seen as distinct
beings. This criticism also applies to Halls and Amess monistic tendencies to identify or merge Tian and the sage.
The parallel to the Hebrews and the Greeks is instructive: neither human nephesh nor psyche can be called a divine being. A Christian parallel is also appropriate: Confucians are born with the shen of
Tian in the same way that Christians are created in the image of God.
Tian gives humans mind (xin), sensibilities, and feelings, and the
Christian God bestows reason, conscience, and righteousness, but the
resultant beings are not gods, even if they are saints or sages. (The
Christians are closer to Mencius on the presence of conscience in the
human soul.) Sages then become host[s] of a divine manifestation
(shenming)46 so they can do Tians work on earth. (Consistent with
Confucian humanism, they do this by learning, not by original divine
endowment or by grace.) But in neither Christianity nor Confucianism
does the knowledge of God-Tian result in becoming God, especially
since, in both traditions, complete knowledge of God is impossible.
A grammatical analysis of the Xunzi also supports my position,
and Machle himself supplies the data. In Xunzis usage of shen, it is
often more adjectival in force (eight times) or part of an adjectival or
adverbial phrase (eight times); twice, as a noun, it refers to ones
vital functionings. The rest of the time it clearly indicates supernatural beings or forces. . . .47 We have already discussed Menciuss use
of shen as a predicate adjective, so we should use the meanings wonderful, marvelous, miraculousnot divinefor the adjectival uses
that Machle finds in the Xunzi.
If Tians natural effects are shen, then that means that its effects and the sages actions are spiritual, just as Tian in us or the
image of God might be called our spiritual natures. Therefore, the
claim that the sage is the equal of Tian and Earth is not to say that
she is same as Heaven; rather, it means that each of the members of
the cosmic triad are equally valuable, although Heaven and Earth
can claim supremacy in the fact that they both produce human beings. On the other hand, Heaven and Earth cannot be truly fulfilled
without the sage. Tian-and-Earth produce the junzi . . . (who) is the
general manager (ling) of the myriad things.48 Even Xunzis perfect man (zhi ren) does not compete with Tian by encroaching on
Tians province.49
Although we can understand his reasons for using the first two
terms, we must reject as misleading Machles characterization of the
189
190
Spiritual Titanism
of any special divine nature. The lives of the sages are, like nature,
expansive and productive, and this is a key to understanding a crucial text in the Analects: It is the person who extends the Dao, not
Dao that extends the person.57 As we have seen, this passage sums
up succinctly the nature of Confucian humanism.
Without ever approaching anything like the Christian idea of
transcendence, Confucian philosophers nevertheless recognize a
qualitative difference between humans and the divine. Therefore,
Confucian thinkers do not humanize God nor do they divinize
human beings. Even the ancient sage kings, although great, were
not considered gods. Confucius, himself humble about his own
achievements, clearly recognized the necessity of balance, of accepting limitations, and of concentrating on an earthly moral life. Even
though they are mediators between heaven and earth, the Confucian
sages are still rooted firmly in the earth, in their physical selves, and
in the body of society.
Confucius offers the best answer to spiritual Titanism for the
following reasons: (1) he rejects the distinction between theory and
practice as well as the bifurcation of heart and mind; (2) he believes
that the main purpose of knowledge is not for power or control, but
for edification and pure joy; (3) he has no concept of rational autonomy, a dominant idea in Western humanism, but operates with a relational, social self; and (4) he proposes an aesthetic, rather than
rational, ordering of human lives. Like an artist, the Confucian sage
seeks harmony among human selves and attunement with natural
things. This contrasts significantly with mere agreement, or what is
worse, with bureaucratic enforcement of rules and short-sighted exploitation of the environment. Like an expert performer, the Confucian participates in the holy rites of li and is thereby humanized, not
divinized, by them.
10
Xunzi and
Neoconfucianism
Introduction
In this chapter we will expand the argument that Confucian
philosophy offers the most constructive answer to Titanism. In the
first section we will analyze Xunzis view of the Cosmic Triad, drawing on the recent contributions of Edward Machle. The deification
of the sage is a sure sign of Titanism, but Xunzis perfect man
(zhi ren) does not compete with Tian by encroaching on Tians
province. However, the traditional reading of Xunzi as a thoroughgoing naturalist and prototechnologist appears to undermine the
thesis that Xunzi offers an answer to Titanism. In the second section, we discuss the traditional interpretation, and in the third,
Machles answer to this view is presented. In the final section we
show how the neo-Confucian philosophers generally avoid Titanisms mistakes. We will also show that some elements of twentiethcentury Western philosophy are consonant with the Confucian view
of human nature and reality in general. This will constitute an extension of the earlier discussion of the self and of constructive postmodernism.
191
192
Spiritual Titanism
193
tsit Chan tends to merge Heaven and Nature by stating that Tian
operates with constant regularity, Machle subtly separates Tian
and Natures regularities with that fact that Tian maintains constant routines for the heavenly bodies; and he comments that Tian
is thus distinguishable from nature both by its primacy and its functions. . . .4 Machle of course agrees that Tians providence is general rather than specific, so Tian does not favor one person or
society over another. Even though the barbarians may have their
customs, Xunzi maintains that only the Chinese have Li, the correct
rules of human behavior. (We will now follow Machles convention of
leaving li as the Chinese logos in italics and always indicating the
ritual li as Li.) This is due, however, to the keen perception of Chinese sages and not to any special action on the part of Tian.
Xunzi believes that Tian rules only in the higher levels of the cosmic hierarchy and that humans should always expect irregularities
in their immediate lives and environment. Separating those that
might be signs of Tian (eclipses and falling stars) from those that are
not (floods, drought, etc.) is an important duty of the sage and of the
wise administrator. Only the superstitious person thinks that the latter are acts of divine retribution. As for the falling of stars and the
groaning of trees, they are but [passing] changes in Tian and Earth,
mutations of yin and yang or deviant emergents among things. It is
appropriate to think them weird, but dreading them is an error.5
Returning now to the ideal balance in the Cosmic Triad, Xunzi
tells that we are not to compete with Heaven, for each member of
the triad has its own distinct role to play. Heaven has its seasons,
Earth has its wealth [resources], and man has his government [culture]. This is how they are able to form a triad (can).6 Machles
translation of the last sentence draws on another use of can as describing the alignment of the three stars in Orions belt. Here, then,
is Machles translation of this passage: Tian has its season, Earth
has its productiveness, and [the] man has [an ability] to set things
in order. It is this situation that constitutes their potential to be
harmoniously aligned.7 Machle inserts the definite article before
man to emphasize the hierarchical thinking that pervades all of
Confucianism. It is not just any person who can align himself with
Heaven and Earth; it is only the sage, the perfect man. Only he
who understands the distinctive functions of Heaven . . . may be
called a perfect man (zhi ren).8
The literal meaning of zhi ren, according to Machle, is he who
has arrived or the ultimate man. (Zhuangzis zhi ren, most likely
the source of Xunzis use of the term, will be discussed in chap. 11.)
194
Spiritual Titanism
This suggests parallels to both Buddhism and Hinduism. The Buddha is called the Tatagathaliterally the one who has arrived at
Nirvan.a with nothing else to do or will. Pali Buddhism agrees with
Confucianism that this perfect person (Pali uttamapurisa) is in no
way a deity. The second translation of zhi ren as ultimate person
can be contrasted to Kr. s.n.a as uttamapurus.a, a superman superior
even to Brahman the Godhead. The Pali uttamapurisa is simply a
perfected human being rather than a Vedic cosmic man (purus.a). As
we have seen, this Hindu Titan does not appear in Buddhism until
the Buddha is called maha
purus.a in the Maha
vastu.9
The sage models himself on Heaven, which performs its office
without any action or effort. The emperor also follows the sages lead:
he is to center himself on the pole star, face south, do nothing, and let
his ministers run the state.10 This is where Daoist wu wei and Confucian sagehood converge in stark contrast to Western and Indian
forms of extreme humanism, where the Titan, by a supreme act of
willpower, overcomes the constraints of body and natural environment and attempts to isolate himself from both. Machle reminds us
that for the Chinese an assertion of will reveals an imperfect state
rather than the ideal: Where we hold will to be one of the perfections of a person, the Chinese idea would suggest that it is rather a
mark of an imperfection, either in the person or in his or her situation, an imperfection that requires will or effort to deal with.11 This
means that Tian also has no will and this fact has allowed Westerners and even many Chinese to mistranslate Tian as nature. This
negative view of the will also strengthens the position of Chinese
philosophy (including Chinese Buddhism) as an answer to Titanism.
As we shall see in chap. 11, Nietzsches will to power is a natural impulse rather than an intentional will, a fact that establishes a close
affinity between him and the Chinese.
Xunzi believes that people should order their lives on natural
harmonies and regularities, but, contrary to Mencius and the neoConfucians, he says that they should not deliberate or devote any
effort to the deep and invisible processes of Heavens hidden
spirit. This would constitute hubris on their part and tend to upset
the balance of the Cosmic Triad. Xunzis caution here is completely
compatible with Confucius own diffidence about all things spiritual
and his exhortations that we should concentrate on human affairs.
Therefore, the superior person (junzi), one step lower than the sage
(sheng ren) or the perfect person (zhi ren), is content with knowing
Heavens distinctive functions, but remains ignorant and silent about
the inner secrets of Heaven. The superior man is serious about what
195
lies in himself and does not desire what comes from Heaven. The inferior man neglects what is in himself and desires what comes from
Heaven [i.e., a misdirected desire for good fortune].12 True Confucian
humanists stay within themselves and their society and do not aspire
to Heaven or have Nietzsches otherworldly hopes.
196
Spiritual Titanism
197
Confucians separate the cognitive and affective parts of the soul just
as Xunzi does, yet they generally maintain a balanced view of the Cosmic Triad and do not recommend the exploitation of nature. But even
with some separation of mind, feelings, and senses, we must remind
ourselves that Confucian philosophy never entertained a complete
subject/object split, which led to the egocentric predicament and to
other serious problems associated with modern Western philosophy.16
Some might say that the solution to the problem lies in Xunzis
difference with Mencius. By rejecting the Mencian view that Heaven
is in everyone of us, Xunzi literally cuts the heart out of Confucian
philosophy. The result is that he is unable to express the essential interrelation of the partners of the Cosmic Triad. Just as important as
the integrity of each is the holistic view of their interpenetration, a
pervasive theme, as we shall see, in neo-Confucianism. On this view,
Heaven and Earth, for Xunzi, are not internally, but externally related to one another and to human beings. This would explain why
in this passage both Heaven and Earth are described as primarily
objects for human use. Thom H. Fang is a supporter of this view:
[Xunzi] was the only one who seemed to be fed up with the
value-centric conception of Heaven. Just for this reason, he
wanted to set up the supremacy of man apart from unnecessary complication with Nature, which is nothing more than
a neutral order with physical energies in store for human
utilization.17
Without mentioning Xunzi specifically, the neo-Confucian Zhangzai,
centuries later, diagnosed this problem succinctly:
When the Way of Heaven and the nature of man function separately, there cannot be sincerity. When there is a difference
between the knowledge obtained by following Heaven and
that obtained by following man, there cannot be perfect enlightenment. . . . And when the nature of man and the Way of
Heaven are united in harmony, they will be preserved and
abide in sincerity.18
Xunzis critics would argue that he overreacted to Mencius by strictly
separating the elements of the Cosmic Triad. As a result he did not
fully appreciate the moral and aesthetic powers of Heaven and Earth
nor did he completely understand their interactive harmonies. Returning to the poetic lines just quoted, we should, contrary to Xunzis
198
Spiritual Titanism
apparent advice to regulate it, simply admire Heaven as great; instead of genetic engineering, we should allow species to multiply by
themselves; we should stand in awe of Heaven and Earth rather
than exploiting them for our own use. The cosmic trinity can be sustained, as the Doctrine of the Mean says, only if human beings assist
in the transforming and nourishing process of Heaven and Earth.19
In order to avoid the anthropomorphism he found in Mencius,
Xunzis critics claim that he still preserves an anthropocentrism that
leads him to treat Heaven and Earth more like objects rather than
subjects in their own right. This is contrary to the Confucian tradition, as Tu Wei-ming maintains:
Confucian humanism is therefore fundamentally different
from anthropocentrism because it professes the unity of man
and Heaven rather than the imposition of the human will on
nature. In fact, the anthropocentric assumption that man is
put on earth to pursue knowledge and, as knowledge expands, so does mans domination over earth, is quite different from the Confucian perception of the pursuit of knowledge as an integral part of ones self-cultivation.20
Note that, technological exploitation aside, the spiritual Titans of
India might be said to have the same agenda. Earth and our bodies
are viewed as not ends in themselves, but as means to a liberation
that exceeds even the realm of the gods. Neither Heaven, especially
in Buddhaghosas doctrine of celestial destruction where the gods are
forced into the human realm,21 nor Earth can maintain their integrity or value in such a view.
Benjamin Schwartz sums up this traditional view of Xunzi by
claiming that he represents a paradigm of the positivist-technological orientation and is the best Chinese example of the scientific
humanism of Europe.22 Since Xunzi lacks an appreciation of basic
theoretical investigation, he is more like Francis Bacon than Galileo
Galilei. There is more than a hint of Bacons knowledge is power in
the Chan translation of Xunzis poetic lines. Tu Wei-Ming essentially
agrees with this assessment of Xunzi, but he does add an important
caveat at the end of this insightful passage:
To be sure, the belief that knowledge implies power is not totally absent in the Confucian tradition. Xunzi, for example,
strongly advocates the position that since culture is manmade, the human transformation of nature is not only nec-
199
200
Spiritual Titanism
201
202
Spiritual Titanism
203
204
Spiritual Titanism
205
206
Spiritual Titanism
especially important contributions here with his notion that the self
is essentially coextensive with the body. (This means, as we have
mentioned previously, that the body is constitutive of personal identity, most powerfully so in affective dimensions of human experience.) The self is fully embodied, not only in the immediate physical
sense, but in the wider world as well. For the Confucian moral learning is literally an education of the entire body. Ritual, music, and the
martial arts harmonize both body and soul such that they become attuned to the laws of Heaven and Earth. In Christian theology the
image of God is a spiritual gift separate from the body, but for the
Confucian ones heavenly endowment is expressed, as Tu Wei-ming
observes, in organic terms such as physical form (xing) or a bodily
design brought about by germination of moral seeds.48 Mencius
calls the original heart the great body and it is what animates and
cultivates the physical form (the small body). The result is a veritable fusion of the inner and the outer such that the virtues, while
rooted in [the] heart, are also manifested clearly in the face, limbs,
and back.49 This means that sages literally image the virtue in
their bodies. Is this perhaps the ethical implication of Wittgensteins
famous statement that meaning is a physiognomy?50 In contrast to
some recent interpretations, I maintain that Wittgenstein joins the
dialogical existentialists and Whitehead in a constructive postmodernism that merges nicely with both Confucianism and Buddhism.51
11
Laozi, Zhuangzi,
and Nietzsche
Daoism protests not so much against gods who transcend the world as against humans masquerading as
gods.
Ellen Chen1
There are two limiting cases, the child and the saint,
where this pawning of ones liberty . . . does not take
place.
Gabriel Marcel2
La vrit sort de la bouche des enfants et des fous.
Old French saying
Time spent laughing is time spent with the gods.
Japanese proverb
Introduction
It should be an uncontroversial thesis that the wu wei of Daoism
stands as the very opposite of the overassertive claims of spiritual
Titanism. Affirming the same integrated self as Zen Buddhism and
Confucianism, Daoism rejects the dualism of matter and spirit that
one finds in Jainism, Sam
. khya-Yoga, and the Abrahamic religions.
We shall find, however, that, as opposed to the social self of Confucianism, Zhuangzis philosophy appears to join Yoga Titanism in affirming an antisocial self, which although living in the world, remains
disengaged from it. On the other hand, Laozis Daoism expresses a
distinct preference for the feminine, which, as we have seen in Sakta
theology, offers a necessary corrective to typical male ideas of isolation and autonomy. We have observed that spiritual Titanism can be
207
208
Spiritual Titanism
found not only in the deification of humans beings, but also in the
closely related claim of human immortality. Religious Daoism makes
claims in the latter area and also transforms Laozi into a cosmic
man, and the Zhuangzi also appears to deify the sage. These three
issues, plus the question of postmodernism and Nietzsches relation
to Zhuangzi, will be discussed in this final chapter.
The first section will compare and contrast the Vedic Purus.a and
the Chinese cosmic man Panku. We shall discover that the Chinese
myth has its own origins; and if there was Indo-Iranian influence, it
was late and it could have made the Panku myth more anthropocentric. The second section deals with the concept of personal immortality and the immortals in religious Daoism and the basis that some
commentators see for this idea in the Daodejing. The third section
discusses Zhuangzis alleged anticipation of postmodernism. We will
side with those commentators who see significant differences between him and the French deconstructionists. In the fourth section
we shall analyze Zhuangzis concepts of the perfect person (zhi ren)
and the true person (zhen ren). The descriptions of these remarkable
characters might at first glance lead us to call them Titans, but we
will argue that this would be a mistaken interpretation. In the fifth
section we will look at some similarities between Zhuangzi and Nietzsche, but we will also find some important differences. (In a word, Nietzsche is ultimately more Tantric than he is Daoist.) Nevertheless,
the comparative analysis with Daoism allows us to get a better idea
of the childlike spontaneity and freedom that Nietzsche attributes to
his bermensch. In the concluding section we return to the Confucian
sage as the most satisfactory answer to the spiritual Titanism.
209
Schipper does admit that some texts indicate that an Old Lord
(Laojun) transforms the mothers womb, but he says that jun doesnt
necessarily mean male, because the mythological use of the word
usually indicates a goddess not a god. But Schipper does allow the
interpretation that the Old Lord is Laozi himself before his conception, so it could be that this story is not entirely different from the
Indian model of the savior becoming the father of himself. If Schipper is correct, however, this is completely consistent with the Daoist
(except for Zhuangzi) preference for the feminine and for the soft
virtues. This preference did not lead to any appreciable change in
womens inequality or lack of power, but it did produce at least two
notable advances for Chinese women, one specific and temporary
and the other more general and significant. First, in the second century C.E. religious Daoists throughout China instituted a practice of
having equal numbers of male and female masters at their temples.
Second, Schipper points out that China was the only ancient society
where women were in control of the sexual education of their husbands.4
An imperial inscription of 165 C.E. indicates that Laozi had been
elevated to the highest possible cosmic level: he is declared to be coeternal with the sun, moon, and the stars. If Kr. s.n.a and the Buddha
could take on the visvaru
pa of the Purus.a, then it was only natural
that religious Daoists would also identify Laozi with Panku, the cosmic man:
[Laozis] left eye became the sun; his right eye, the moon; his
head became mount Kunlun; his beard, the planets and constellations; his bones, dragons; his flesh, four-footed creatures; his intestines, snakes; his stomach, the sea; his fingers, the Five Peaks; his hair, trees and grasses [etc.]. . . .5
The Daoist philosophical texts, on the other hand, do not contain
any evidence of the cosmicization of the sage. As we shall see, the
Daoist sages, rather than becoming Panku, return to a state resembling primordial chaos (hundun). It is an act of merging and
not one of anthropomorphic projection. Therefore, just as we have
seen with regard to Confucius, the deification and cosmicization of
Laozi happened in the religious tradition and not in the philosophical texts.
The Chinese myth of the cosmic man Panku appears to have
some similarities with the Purus.a hymn of the R. gveda, particularly
with regard to the theme of dismemberment:
210
Spiritual Titanism
After the death of Panku, his breath became the wind and
clouds, his voice the thunder, his left and right eyes the sun
and moon, his four limbs and the five bodies (fingers) the
four quarters of the earth and five great mountains, his
blood the rivers, his muscles and veins the strata of earth,
his flesh the soil, his hair and beard the constellations, his
skin and body-hair the plants and trees, his teeth and bone
the metals and stones, his marrow gold and precious stones,
and his sweat the rain.6
The most striking difference between the two myths is that no living
beings or artifacts come directly from the Chinese giants body,
whereas creations from the Purus.as body include such things as
gods, animals, scripture, and humans arranged according to caste.
More important is the fact that in the Chinese view Heaven and
Earth already exist, having both arisen out of chaos (hundun), and it
is Pankus job to open up a space between the two so that a natural
and cultural world can evolve. In the Purus.a hymn the cosmic man
encompasses the entire universe: he is three quarters Heaven and
one quarter Earth. Only in the later versions of the Chinese myth
does Panku also create Heaven and Earth, and this more anthropocentric version could have been the result of a Chinese adaptation
of the Purus.a theme as the cosmological body of Buddha. Therefore,
in the original Chinese view the balance of the Cosmic Triad is preserved whereas the integrity of Heaven and Earth is compromised in
both the Purus.a hymn and in the later Chinese version.
The Panku myth is intimately connected to a totemic dog-deity
named Panhu, who was worshiped by the Man tribes in South
China. Besides their linguistic affinity, the two are also closely connected with primordial chaos (hundun) and, alternatively, creation
out of a calabash gourd (hulu) or cosmic egg. (Prajapati and Purus.a
are also said to have come out of a golden embryo [hiran.yagarbha].)
The connection to Panhu may explain why Panku has animal as well
as human characteristics: two horns projected from his head, and
two tusks from his upper jaw. His body was thickly covered with
hair.7 Although the Indian tradition has its share of theriomorphic
deities, all are of Puran.ic and therefore late derivation. (The intriguing exception of course is the horned figure of the Harrapans
whom some take to be a proto-Siva.) No such animal characteristics
are attached to the Purus.ahence a more anthropomorphic figure
and who, as we have seen, becomes identified as a cosmic yogi in the
211
Puran.as. Therefore, scholars are justified in holding to an independent Chinese origin of the Panku myth.
It is also important to note the pivotal role that a goddess plays
in the Panku and Panhu myths. Just as a feminine principle Viraj is
present in the Purus.a hymn so does Panku appear to be androgynous, combining both the yin and the yang. The principal goddess is
called Nugua and her origins, like Panhus, are theriomorphic: she is
most closely associated with snakes, snails, and frogs. She is most
often paired with Fuxi the ox-tamer and is credited with repairing
the damage of the Great Deluge. She is also associated with a time
in China when people knew their mothers rather than their fathers, and also significant is the masculinization of Nugua in later
patriarchal ages.8 After the Great Deluge she is said to have given
birth to a son, a queer thing called hundun with no anus or urinary
opening. After pondering the matter for a while, Nugua and her husband decided to cut up their child and the pieces became the people
of the world.
Whereas the Daodejing frequently speaks of origins in the Mother
and the feminine, the primordial ground of the Zhuangzi appears to
be gender neutral. (In several passages Zhuangzi reverses the traditional qualities of the yin and the yang;9 but, if this is a deliberate
privileging of the feminine, it does not at all effect the general antisocial attitude of his sage.) While the dismemberment of Panku gives
us the natural world, the boring of Hundun in the Zhuangzi (end of
chap. 7) produces, as it does in the Nugua story, the human world.
This elegant and concise parable tells the story of three emperors:
Shu of the South Sea (symbolizing yin), Hu of the North Sea (representing yang), and Hundun of the Center. Shu and Hu met Hundun
in the Center and their host treated them very graciously. Wanting
to repay Hundun for his hospitality and noticing that Hundun did
not have the seven human orfices, Shu and Hu proceeded to create
an opening for Hundun on each successive day. Their kindness was
very ill conceived and Hundun died on the seventh day. Max Kaltenmark captures the Daoist moral of this story: An untimely zeal [of
Hu and Shu] would wish to make it [Hundun] like everybody else,
and initiate it into civilized life by giving it the sense organs that destroy its unity. The myth is a perfect symbol of the Founding Kings
original sin.10
For the Daoist true kindness and reciprocity need no acknowledgment; indeed, Shu and Hus gesture, just like any human moral
response, is always bound to have elements of self-interest and in-
212
Spiritual Titanism
213
Ellen Chen rejects this interpretation as inconsistent with the selfeffacing Dao and Daoists who are supposed to model the Dao. Instead she takes her lead from Wangbis commentary, which reads:
Whoever dies, but whose Dao by which he lived does not perish,
completes his longevity. The body is gone, but the Dao still exists.16
People are immortal only insofar as they are one with the Dao.
Furthermore, the phrases immortal Dao or eternal Dao may also
be misleading, giving the false impression of Indian or Christian
ideas of immutable spiritual substance. The character chang very
often qualifies the Dao, and the rendering eternal should be replaced by something like constant or steady. For example, in
chap. 16 Wing-tsit Chan proposes that one becomes everlasting by
being in accord with an eternal Dao, while Michael LaFargue says
that one lasts very long following the steady Dao.17
Other passages in the Daodejing also allude to a human state
that may appear deathless or eternal, but we should call these people balanced and invulnerable rather than immortal or eternal. Those
who are immune to weapons and to the attacks of wild animals because they have no death spot18 have stayed, as the first stanza implies, in tune with the Dao. Proposing a life-death dialectic, the poet
tells us that the thirteen body parts (four limbs and nine orifices)
are both life-givers and death-bringers. (The myth of piercing the
Hundun is obviously in the background here.) Thus, those who have
lived life . . . lavishly have dissipated their de, but those who have
preserved their dethe abundant de of the childwill not die prematurely. Like the Hundun, people should stop the apertures, close
the doors,19 and then they can save their life (shen). With accumulated de people can, just like Nietzsches bermenschen, become all
overcoming and have long life and enduring vision.20
The immortals (xian) of religious Daoism should be interpreted
much in the same way as these sages from the Daodejing. They are
more fantastic and eccentric, more like Zhuangzis fabulous characters, but there are fundamental similarities. There are innumerable
immortals, so we will touch on only some of the most notable. At the
time of his story Zhongli Chuan was six hundred years old and a master of the art of inner alchemy. He inducted Lu Dungbin as a fellow
immortal by a simple test of character. Zhongli required that Lu do
many good deeds, and he offered him some false gold to expedite the
process of helping poor people become rich. Lu refused to use alchemy
to achieve his goal, proved that he had a good heart, and immediately
entered into Zhonglis instruction. The immortals, however, were not
paragons of conventional virtue, for Lu seduced a maiden Ho Xiengu
214
Spiritual Titanism
(White Peony) and his powerful semen made her one of the immortals. Lan Caiho was a musician of indeterminate sex, who exclaimed
Im pregnant all year long and who could mediate easily between
the yin and the yang; Cao Guojin was a drunken geomancer; Zhang
Guolao was a former minister who rode a mule backward; and every
night Li Tieguai returned to a gourd to sleep, reenacting the Daoist
return to the Hundun. In addition to their eccentric behavior the immortals are known primarily, just as the Buddhist Siddhas are, for
their humanitarian aid to the poor and oppressed.21
The translation of xian as immortal is misleading (Victor Mair
would rather call them transcendents), because these beings are not
gods even in the sense of the popular Chinese religion. The character
xian is composed of two glyphshuman being and mountainand if
we use these as a guide to the meaning of xian we would get people of
the mountains or even human mountain. Phonologically, xian is related to such meanings as to change, to evolve, and to dance,
which provides another link to the self-transforming sages of philosophical Daoism. Although they are known to help the harvests in the
plains, they do not themselves eat grains. They also protect the
land,22 perhaps an indirect recognition of the importance of mountain
watersheds. (Zhuangzis shen ren keeps creatures free from plagues
and makes the grain ripen every year.)23 In contrast to the gods of the
cities, who command formal worship and sacrifice, the immortals are
not bound by religious rite, philosophical doctrine, or political administration. This is entirely consistent with their natures, which are
completely free and spontaneous, providing the people of the plains
with symbols of personal liberation, play, and boundless joy.
We now take an abrupt comparative leap to the immortals of
Herman Hesses Steppenwolf. (Actually, as a devoted Nietzschean
Hesses place in this chapter is very appropriate.) At the beginning of
the novel the protagonist Harry Haller is trapped in a dualistic wolfman persona, which is gradually replaced with a view of the onion
self, a thousand layered self that Hesse drew either from Asian or
Nietzschean sources (or both). Hesses immortals symbolize the free
self-transformation that is possible if one embraces this idea of the
soul. Harry encounters Goethe in a dream and he chides this immortal for taking himself so seriously and for betraying the spirit of
Romanticism. Harry contrasts Goethe to Mozart, who did not make
pretensions in his own life to the enduring and the orderly and to exalted dignity as you did. He did not think himself so important! He
sang his divine melodies and died [young].24 (The movie Amadeus
portrays Mozart exactly in this way.) Goethes response is a veritable
215
216
Spiritual Titanism
217
ing into question. These procedures lead to the creation of texts that
are extremely playful and also very obscure.
If the basis for clear distinction and differentiation is subverted,
then judgments about true/false or good/evil are ultimately groundless. Skepticism about knowledge claims and moral relativism, so argues the deconstructionist, follow necessarily. Zhuangzi, however,
has another solution. Behind the infinite play of signifiers, there is
the Dao, and Zhuangzi never rejects its existence and never denies
that conforming to the Dao is what we ought to do. Whereas it is arguable whether Nagarjuna accepts or rejects an ultimate reality
the subtlety of his dialectic is consummatethe text of the Zhuangzi
is unequivocal about the existence of the Dao and our access to it
through illumination. The sage . . . opens things up to the light of
Heaven.33 Wherever we walk, how can the Way be absent? he
says, and its linguistic equivalent is whatever the standpoint, how
can saying be unallowable?34 The literal meaning of dao, after all, is
track or road, and any road is walkable and even rough ones are
at least climbable. Therefore, the Way is walkable, and if we are
careful with our language, it is talkable, too. At least the figurative
language of the Daodejing and the Zhuangzi is acceptable talk about
the Dao. At most, by another interpretation of this passage, we can
say that all language gets at the Dao (words and things could not
exist without it), but only partially and only indirectly. Zhuangzi
never gives up on words, for he even wants to have a word with the
man who has forgotten words.35 Berksons image of someone turning on the lights in a dark room full of people groping around with
flashlights is a brilliant analogy to explain Zhuangzis idea of illumination and to show that he ultimately parts company with French
deconstruction.36 Derrida believes that we are producing ever increasing polyvalent meanings, while Zhuangzi believes that the sage
discovers a univocal, transcendent meaning of the Dao whose worldly
meanings are irreducibly polyvalent.
Returning to the comparison between Zhuangzi and Nagarjuna,
Loys claim that both philosophers point to a nondual reality beyond
language may not be correct. While Kalupahanas rejection of the
traditional absolutist interpretation of Nagarjuna is still much in
dispute (it is enough to confirm Kalupahanas point that this was
certainly not the Buddhas view), we should side with Berksons view
that what the sage discovers is the equality of all perspectives, not
their complete identity. The monistic interpretation is supported by
passages such as the one at the beginning of chap. 4: The Way
doesnt want things mixed with it. When it becomes a mixture, it be-
218
Spiritual Titanism
comes many ways; with many ways, there is a bustle; and where
there is a lot of bustle, there is troubletrouble that has no remedy!37 This passage expresses the odd implication that competing
linguistic and cultural worlds are completely alien to the Dao, which,
if the Dao is the source of all perspectives, cannot be correct. In any
case the passage does not imply that these worlds are illusory; their
existence and the trouble they cause are very real. Furthermore, this
passage once again supports the Dao as the norm, a view that undermines a deconstructionist interpretation of Zhuangzi.
That Zhuangzis vision is more pluralistic than monistic is supported by many texts. Heaven blows on the ten thousand things in
a different way, so that each can be itselfall take what they want
for themselves. . . .38 Ordinary people forget who the great piper is
and claim absolute truth for their own perspectives, whereas the
sage acknowledges the relative truth of all of them. (Here the gap between Derrida and Zhuangzi is greatest: Derrida recognizes the relative truth of all perspectives, but would never commit himself to an
ontological source for them.) As Berkson states: Each individual is
unique and sounds different (will have a different viewpoint and nature), but underlying all is the sound of Heaven; behind all of the differences, there is an all-encompassing, underlying Dao.39
Knowledge is indeed possibleit is, in Kwang-ming Wus incredibly
playful translation, huge and it widens, widenswhile perspectival knowledge is small and it is picky, picky; huge words burn,
burn; small words chat, chat.40
If the Dao exists and if we are exhorted to conform to its norms,
then Zhuangzi is not the skeptic or relativist that many have taken
him to be. Recently a number of scholars have constructed cogent
arguments against both of these claims. Philip J. Ivanhoe looks at
Zhuangzi from the standpoints of four types on skepticism: sense,
ethical, epistemological, and language skepticism, and concludes
that Zhuangzi can only be called a language skeptic and a qualified
epistemological skeptic.41 (Great Understanding as intuitive knowledge of the Dao is available to the sage or to the knack master.) As
we have just seen, being skeptical about discursive speech to capture the Dao does not undermine either Zhuangzis commitment to
the Dao nor his belief that there is a correct way to follow it. Paul
Kjellberg argues that Zhuangzis skepticism is very much like the
Greeks; it is a therapeutic method designed to effect an epoch, a
suspension of judgment about conventions that distort reality and
confine the human spirit. With regard to relativism, it holds only
among various language games and not the Heavens eye perspec-
219
tive of the sage, similar to the birds eye (guan) view of the Daodejing.42
If Zhuangzi is not a desconstructive postmodernist, can he be
construed as a constructive postmodernist? Daoism joins Buddhism
in offering a basic process philosophy that informs much of contemporary constructive postmodernism. One might say, however, that
the Dao represents a premodern totality from which all things arise,
to which all things must conform, and to which all things must eventually return. The fact that the Daoist sage must model the Hundun,
a primordial unity without openings, appears distinctively premodern. Apremodernist interpretation of Daoism is much better grounded
in the Daodejing, but it probably does not do justice to Zhuangzis
philosophical brilliance and innovation. As we have just seen,
Zhuangzis view of reality is not simply monistic, but a rather sophisticated idea of plural linguistic worlds.
Paul Kjellberg takes a view opposite to Loy by locating languages
difficulty not in the fact that its constant categorizing fails in the
face of an undifferentiated reality; rather, it fails because reality is
far more subtly differentiated than we can ever imagine or language
could ever express. (The Tao of Physics notwithstanding, contemporary physics appears to confirm this as well as todays forms of
process pluralism.) If ultimate reality were totally unstructured,
then Zhuangzis knack masters, who most commentators see as on
par with the sage, could not possibly operate. We must assume that
the natural veins (tian li, like veins of jade says Fung Yulan)43 that
Cook Ding follow are very real and, by analogy, mark off real divisions of the Dao, divisions that ordinary conventions and language
always obscure. According to A. C. Grahams translation of tian li,
Cook Ding is following Heavens structuring, just as Woodcarver
Qing matches Heaven with Heaven, and just as Platos dialectical
butcher is following the logos.44 If Dao has a logos, then Zhuangzi is
definitely not a deconsturctionist. Finally, we should remember that
Lord Wenhui acknowledges the moral implications of Cook Dings
skill. He praises him not for his butchering expertise, but because
the amazing cook teaches Wenhui how to nurture life.45
David L. Hall offers a pluralist interpretation of Daoism that
might go too far. Hall shows that contemporary postmodernism is
driven by perceptions of difference, and he is correct in his assumption that Derridas diffrance is related to Heideggers principle of
the ontological Differenz between Being and beings. From my own
work on Heideggers Differenz, I have concluded that Being is best
interpreted in terms of Kants transcendental conditions for the pos-
220
Spiritual Titanism
221
222
Spiritual Titanism
ified; and (2) what are we to make of their fantastic trips? Let us look
at five translations of the phrase zhi ren shen:
Burton Watson: The Perfect Man is godlike.
Wing-tsit Chan: The perfect man is a spiritual being.
A. C. Graham: The utmost man is daemonic.
Fung Yulan: The perfect man is mysterious.
Kwang-ming Wu: The ultimately arrived man is spiritfilled.51
Following our analysis of Mencius use of shen in chap. 9, we note once
again that shen is standing as a predicate adjective and its meaning
then should be wonderful, marvelous, miraculous. Linking the sage
with the knackmasters, Wu agrees with this line of thinking: the zhi
ren is daemonically marvelous, skillful, versatile.52 Noting three interrelated meanings of shen, Wu proposes a cosmic sense in which qi
and shen are functionally equivalent, a psychological meaning of
human vitality (the Greek pysche), and a special instance in which
the sage or the knackmaster, because of their openness to the Dao, receive an extra charge of cosmic shen. They become veritable geniuses
in their chosen tasks. As Wu states: This is almost like the Socratic
daemon, though without its nagging foreboding, forbidding connotations.53 We can safely conclude that the zhi ren are not divine beings
as we have defined them in the introduction; they are not godlike
but they are definitely spirit-filled. Although Xunzis sage becomes
a zhi ren because of his virtuous actions, his idea of shenming, as a divine enhancement, is comparable to Wus third meaning of shen.
Now, how are we to take the descriptions of the incredible journeys of the zhi ren? Are they just part of what Lee Yearly calls Zhuangzis rhetoric of exaggeration; or shall we see them as examples of
the incredible hubris of the Indian yogis, who also flew through the
heavens and claimed the power of a thousand gods? One hypothesis
could be that these heavenly journeys are descriptions of shamanistic visions, but Zhuangzi always condemns the shaman and elevates
his zhi ren instead. For example, the shaman considers pigs inauspicious, but the perfect person finds them auspicious. However, the
fact that Daoist sages considers them so does not necessarily mean
that they would find any other animal inauspicious. Instead, they
would reject completely the conventional distinction between the
two. We should, however, not dismiss outright the possibility that
shamanism was the origin of these fantastic images.54 Robert Eno
phrases the issue this way:
223
224
Spiritual Titanism
225
226
Spiritual Titanism
227
228
Spiritual Titanism
one had as a child. (Those who live in the mountains do not eat the
five grains, a diet that dissipates de rather than preserves it.) The
way of the sage is also crooked like a mountain path rather than
straight like a city street, a moral code, or a Mohist argument. In
chapter 4 of the Zhuangzi the madman of Chu yells out to Confucius:
Leave off, leave offthis teaching men virtue! Dangerous, dangerousto mark off the ground and run! Fool, fooldont spoil my walking! I walk a crooked waydont step on my feet.79 Zarathustra also
says that all good things approach their goal crookedly . . . all good
things laugh.80 One of the higher men says that Zarathustra is evidence for the truth that the sage walks on the most crooked ways.81
In one of Nietzsches most powerful parablesThe Vision and
the Riddlewe find Zarathustra walking a mountain path with a
crippled dwarf riding on his shoulder. Our initial impression of the
dwarf is a negative one: he is the spirit of gravity and he is
Zarathustras devil and archenemy. He is half dwarf, half mole,
making lame, dripping lead into [Zarathustras] ear.82 Earlier in the
book Zarathustra says that his devil is a serious and solemn spirit
of gravity; and this spirit is opposed to his dancing god and to his
newly found power to fly. Zarathustras powers are very similar to
Zhuangzis zhi ren: Now I am light, now I fly, . . . now a god dances
through me.83 (Zarathustras bright flame and his power to fly is the
Nietzschean equivalent of the spiritual enhancement [shenming] of
the Daoist sage.) The spirit of gravity also orders that our children
be taught self-loathing so that they then become camels of slave
moralityloaded down with too many alien grave words and values.84 The person who has discovered herself says: This is my good
and evil, but the mole and dwarf, representing the spirit of gravity, counters with moral universalism: Good for all, evil for all.85
Returning to The Vision and the Riddle, Zarathustra finally
challenges the dwarf: Stop, dwarf! It is I or you! But I am the
stronger of us two: you do not know my abysmal thought. That you
could not bear!86 Zarathustra then presents the dwarf with a vision
of eternal recurrence, but, curiously and surprisingly, the dwarf is
not only able to bear this terrible truth but he also appears to know
all about it and its implications. Speaking like a Daoist sage he declares: All that is straight lies. . . . All truth is crooked; time itself is
a circle.87 (Laurence Lamperts cannot possibly be correct in claiming that the dwarf is somehow the spirit of rationalism.88 The rationalist prefers a straight idea of truth and a linear view of time.) In
The Joyful Wisdom it is a demon who brings the news of eternal recurrence, but those strong enough to accept the message will declare:
229
You are a god, and never have I heard anything more godly.89
Zarathustras devil-dwarf may have a more positive role to play than
we first thought.
Earlier in the story the dwarf offers other sagely advise: O Zarathustra . . . you philosophers stone! You threw yourself up high,
but every stone that is thrown must fall.90 Is it possible that
Zarathustra by climbing too high and by presuming to fly needs to be
reminded by this alter ego dwarf of his own motto Be true to the
earth? Commentators have identified several alter egos in Zarathustra, so it is quite possible that the dwarf is yet another one of
Zarathustras multiple selves. We should always remember that all
overcoming is self-overcoming, and that even Overmen will have
overdragons who are worthy of them.91 Zarathustra goes on to advise the higher men that they should not fear the devil, and that they
should not be so obtuse as to call the Overman a devil, as surely the
people of the plains will do.
Could it be that the dwarf is a symbol of Zarathustras most
abysmal thought that he has always carried?92 After all, the motto
What goes up must come down is simply the vertical version of
What goes around comes around. Earlier in The Way of the Creator Zarathustra warned his brothers that lusting for the
heights is so many convulsions of the ambitious.93 The dwarf s
point is confirmed in the section The Spirit of Gravity, which reminds us that even when humans learn to fly the boundary stones
themselves will fly up into the air before [them], and [they] will rebaptize the earththe light one.94 Even those who fly should remain true to the earth; for all those who fly, Johnathan Livingston
Seagull and Zhuangzis Peng bird notwithstanding, will eventually
have to make a landing.
The Vision and the Riddle ends with a shocking scene where
Zarathustra comes upon a shepherd with a snake in his throat. The
snakethe heaviest and the blackestcould symbolize the choking effects of the slave morality, and, as my students have suggested,
the snakes head, which Zarathustra exhorts the shepherd to bite off,
could represent the Christian God himself. At the passionate urging
of Zarathustra, the shepherd does decapitate the snake and is immediately transformed: No longer shepherd, no longer humanone
changed, radiant, laughing . . . a laughter that was no human laughter.95 After the death of God, there is only eternal recurrence, and
this cosmic laughter of Hesses immortals is the only proper emotional response to such a meaningless existence. As Graham Parkes
says: laughter [is] an often necessary concomitant of insight into the
230
Spiritual Titanism
231
Zhuangzis sage-cripples? Recall that the hesitant and fearful tightrope walker in the town of Motley Cow is called lamefoot by the
jester, who taunts the man for his lack of courage and knocks him
off the rope. (Zarathustra promises to give the mortally wounded
man a proper burial but leaves his body in the crook of a tree!)106
Nevertheless, as with all things Nietzschean, we must interpret the
dwarf dialectically not dualistically. The latter view, expressed by
Lampert, sees the confrontation between Zarathustra and the dwarf
in a Manichean way: To club the Dwarf to death is to club to death
the whole rational, Socratic tradition, . . .107 which is seen as an evil
that must be completely destroyed. We have already objected to seeing the dwarf as a rationalist, and we now must question whether
the dwarf s disappearance actually means that he has been annihilated. Nietzsche hated dualism just as much as he did rationalism,
so the best solution is that the dwarf dissolves into the dialectical
unity/difference that is Zarathustras character.
One way to see this dialectical interpretation is the Tantric one,
expressed most appropriately in the Hevajra Tantra: whatever
demon should appear before him is an integral part of himself.108
The eschatological pilgrims in the Bardo Thdol are told to take the
wrathful deities that threaten them as simply psychological projections of their own evil deeds. (Even in dualistic Zoroastrianism the
soul sees his good and evil deeds projected as a lovely maiden and an
ugly hag, respectively.)109 As Zarathustra is beyond good and evil, the
dwarf is an alter ego projection of his most abysmal thoughts; or he
is, as suggested earlier, a counter to his attempts to climb ever higher
and to ignore the truth of What goes up must come down.
Yet another dialectical reading rests on the recognition that the
cripple, the monster, the fool, the madman, and the child are all allies in the spiritual instruction of the convention-bound and the unenlightened. (Truth comes from the mouth of babes and fools, as
the French say.) In his analysis of the deformed and monstrous in
the Zhuangzi, Robert E. Allinson states: The higher realization . . .
is [that] monsters . . . are our greatest blessing and without them we
could neither progress in a spiritual direction nor would we have a
constant reminder and embodiment of that progress.110 As with the
Daoist and Hesses immortals, the monster, the fool, and the childs
greatest value is their spontaneity and freedom; and as such they
can speak the truth when societys conventions have either obscured
it or prohibited its proclamation. (In taking her jesters advise the
queen was allowed to go against convention and tradition.) Allinson
sees the effect of this liberating speech and behavior very incisively:
232
Spiritual Titanism
In the clear-cut separation between form and content (monster and true speech), there is the greatest chance for the
cancellation of the analytical judgment at the same moment
as the engagement of the receptive, intuitive function. . . .
The acceptance of the monster as a brother takes social and
philosophical courage.111
233
of innocence and experience, she responds that she has simply heard
(not learned) the Dao.115
234
Spiritual Titanism
of Mencius view comes with his notion that we must carefully tend
and fertilize the moral sprouts that we are given at birth. The
Daoists countered Confucian self-cultivation with the image of the
uncarved block (pu) and the infant who has yet to smile, or the person who conforms most closely to the Hundun.
In an article on Nietzsche and Rinzai Zen discussed in chapter
8, Parkes proposes that Nietzsches self-cultivation is not assertive
at all but corresponds more closely with the Rinzai and Daoist idea
of discovering a natural human core, a homo natura who is not carved
out of stone but simply freed from cultures petrifications.121 He goes
on to suggest that Nietzsche also has his own version of Daoist illumination (ming) in which all things are seen simply as they really
are. If Nietzsches homo natura is like the Daoist pu, then it would be
unnecessary for him to say that it needs to be perfected. There is
only an image in Nietzsches ugly stone, one that needs to be actively
sculpted and formed. And if Nietzsche does indeed believe in something like the Daoist ming (we should be wary of the truth of this hypothesis), then he is not the deconstructive postmodernist that many
have taken him to be.
Even Parkes has to conclude that despite the basic similarities
among the Rinzai monk, the Daoist sage, and Zarathustrathe
spiritualizing of the emotions is fundamentalhe admits to a striking difference in the modi operandi.122 Parkes sees the Rinzai monk
as engaged with his fellow monks and the world while Nietzsche
was much more solitary, even more so than the antisocial Daoist
sage. (Nietzsche also places much more emphasis on pain, suffering,
despair, and tragedy, while the Daoist sage is immune to these.) The
Zen monk and Daoist sage will be indistinguishable from the herd,
while the bermensch will be a new aristocrat, a master of the
earth and a master over all men.123 Finally, as Roger Ames sees it,
the many de ideally blend and harmonize, while the many wills to
power in Nietzsche compete with one another. Ames cites two illustrative texts, one that points out the equivalent Nietzschean de
ontology and the other that demonstrates the difference with Daoism:
Every center of force adopts a perspective toward the entire
remainder, i.e., its own particular valuation, mode of action,
and mode of resistance . . . life itself is essentially appropriation, injury, overpowering of what is alien and the weaker;
suppression, hardness, imposition of ones own forms, incorporation and at least, at its mildest, exploitation.124
235
236
Spiritual Titanism
would call yi centrifugal Sinngebung and yi* would be the centripetal forces of the social, historical, and cultural world.) By enlarging themselves the sages can also enlarge others, and by doing
this they can extend the Dao and form a trinity with Heaven and
Earth.134 Even with such achievements, Confucian sages still remain earth-bound humans with limitations, for even Yao and Shun
had found it difficult to accomplish ren.135 In the Doctrine of the
Mean, where sages are especially elevated, the author(s) admits that
there is something which even the sage does not know . . . [and] is
not able to put into practice.136 The Chinese sages are definitely not
Titans. Titans assert their self-sufficiency and egoistic wills; they
stand as solitary rebels against society and nature; and they claim
knowledge of things that they cannot possibly know. Chinas sages,
on the other hand, are corporate personalities; they claim to know
little; they blend in and harmonize; they find joy in nature; and they
preserve their childlike hearts.
Notes
Preface
1. Mircea Eliade, Patanjali and Yoga, trans. Charles L. Markmann
(New York: Schocken, 1975), p. 50.
2. Empirical Research into the Phenomenon of Kundalini (New Delhi:
Kundalini Research Association International, n.d.), p. 13.
3. R. C. Zaehner, Our Savage God (London: Collins, 1974), p. 263.
4. See C. S. Lewiss affirmation of humanism in The Abolition of Man
(New York: Macmillan, 1947), p. 30; Nicholas F. Gier, Religious Liberalism
and the Founding Fathers, in Two Centuries of Philosophy in America, ed.
Peter Caws (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), pp. 2245; and Gier, God, Reason,
and the Evangelicals (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1987),
chap. 9.
5. Edward Said, Orientalism (New York: Pantheon, 1978), p. 3.
6. Ibid., p. 204.
7. See, for example, Bhiku Parekh, Gandhis Political Philosophy (London: Macmillan, 1989).
8. Quoted in David E. Shaner, The Japanese Experience of Nature,
in Nature in Asian Traditions of Thought, eds. J. B. Callicott and R. T. Ames
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1989), p. 181.
9. M. K. Gandhi, Harijan 7 (August 19, 1939), p. 237.
10. See my article The Color of Sin/The Color of Skin: Ancient Color
Blindness and the Philosophical Origins of Modern Racism, Journal of Religious Thought 46:1 (Summer-Fall 1989), pp. 4252. One could counter that
the Indian caste system is evidence against this thesis, but this system was
racist only in its original form. As intermarriage between Aryan and nonAryan did eventually occur on a wide scale, an Aryan apartheid never developed and the caste system became a source of social, not racial, discrimination.
11. For an argument that Wittgenstein does not go the way of French
deconstruction, see my review of Gertrude Conways book Wittgenstein on
237
238
Notes
Introduction
1. Karl H. Potter, Presuppositions of Indias Philosophies (Westport,
CT: Greenwood, 1963), p. 3.
2. Heinrich Zimmer, Philosophies of India, ed. Joseph Campell
(Cleveland, OH: World Publishing, 1956), p. 232.
3. Quoted in Freeman Dyson, The Race Is Over, New York Review of
Books (March 6, 1997), p. 4.
4. Chandogya Upanis.ad 3.17.6.
5. Mark 10:18.
6. Swami Vivekanandas Speeches and Writings (Madras, India: G. A.
Natesan, 6th ed., 1922), p. 47.
7. Zimmer, Philosophies of India, pp. 23132.
8. Hesoid, Works & Days and Theogony, trans. Stanley Lombardo (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1993); Theogony 209.
9. From the Prometheus fragment of 1816, quoted in Joseph C.
McLelland, Prometheus Rebound: The Irony of Atheism (Waterloo, Ontario:
Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1988), p. 112. I am indebted to McLelland
for several references on the use of the Prometheus myth in Western culture.
10. Percy Bysshe Shelley, Prometheus Unbound, ed. L. J. Zillman
(Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1959), p. 121.
11. Quoted in McLelland, Prometheus Rebound, p. 116.
12. Prometheus, trans. Michael Hamburger, in Goethes Collected
Works: Selected Poems, ed. Christopher Middleton (New York: Suhrkamp,
1983), vol. 1, p. 29.
13. Ibid., p. 31.
Notes
239
240
Notes
man, simply because Brahman is impersonal and the Gi tas God is definitely personal (Edgerton, trans., The Bhagavad Gi ta [New York: Harper,
1944), p. 139.
27. An unnamed Jaina monk comes to Vena and declares: I am most
adored by the gods. . . . [my faith is] Arhats are the gods . . . [and] the best
worship is that of a Jaina mendicant. Vena learns quickly from his new
teacher: I alone am the highest (form of) religion; I alone deserve to be worshipped; I am eternal; . . . I am the ancient, very holy, Jaina religion
(Padma Puran.a 2.37.13, 17, 20; 2.38.18; trans. N. A. Deshpande in Ancient
Indian Tradition and Mythology, vol. 41, pp. 1038, 1043.)
28. Ibid., 2.28.35, vol. 41, p. 1003.
29. Padmanabh S. Jaini, On the Sarvajatva (Omniscience) of Mahavi ra and the Buddha, in Buddhist Studies in Honour of I. B. Horner, eds. L.
Cousins et al. (Dordrecht, Netherlands: Reidel, 1974), p. 72.
30. Ibid.
31. Potter, Presuppositions of Indias Philosophies, p. 153; Zimmer,
Philosophies of India, p. 400fn.
32. Potter, Presuppositions of Indias Philosophies, p. 3.
33. S. K. Maitra, The Gitas Conception of Freedom as Compared to
Kant, in Radhakrishnan: Comparative Studies in Philosophy, eds. W. R.
Inge et al. (New York: Humanities Press, 1951), pp. 34861.
34. Potter, Presuppositions of Indias Philosophies, p. 95. One reader
has condemned Potters remarks as Orientialist, but it seems that this is
the reverse of what has usually be taken to be the Orientalist bias. EuroAmericans have viewed Asian peoples as passive and impotent, not as power
hungry individuals. The Orientalist sees Asians as different and Other, not
in terms of the common humanity that Potter and I do.
35. The Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda (Calcutta: Advaita
Ashrama, 1970), vol. 8, p. 190. On this same page he also states: He that
hath seen the son hath seen the Father, and without seeing the Son, you
cannot see the Father.
36. Vivekananda, Karma-Yoga and Bhakti-Yoga (New York: Ramakrishna-Vivekananda Center, rev. ed., 1973), p. 148.
37. Lance E. Nelson, Living Liberation in San.kara and Classical Advaita, in Living Liberation in Hindu Thought, eds. A. O. Fort and P. Y.
Mumme (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996), p. 39.
38. In the Tantric Saivism of Kashmir there is a focus on physicality involving an alchemical transmutation leading to the divinization of the body
itself (Paul E. Muller-Ortega, Aspects of Ji vanmukti in the Tantric Saivism
Notes
241
242
Notes
53. Parkes, Wandering Dance, p. 246.
54. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 198.
55. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York:
Random House, 1974), 109, p. 169.
56. Bernd Magnus, Nietzsches Philosophy in 1888: The Will to Power
and the bermensch, Journal of the History of Philosophy 24:1 (1986), p.
93.
57. Ibid., p. 83.
58. Ibid., p. 95.
59. Nietzsche, Portable Nietzsche, pp. 24950.
60. Ibid., p. 143.
Notes
243
244
Notes
firms my own conviction that those who continue today to affirm a strong
doctrine of the incarnation risk destroying belief in God (Incarnation and
Myth, pp. 4445).
30. See Ronald H. Nash, The Word of God and the Mind of Man (Grand
Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1982); and Gordon H. Clark, In Defense of Theology
(Milford, MI: Mott Media, 1984). For a discussion of the term evangelical rationalism see my book God, Reason, and the Evangelicals (Lanham, MD:
University Press of America, 1987); chap. 1.
31. Stuart C. Hackett, Personal Immortality and Human Nature: A
Philosophical Case, a paper presented at the Advanced Seminar on Eschatology and the Second Coming, New Ecumenical Research Association, San
Juan, Puerto Rico, February, 1984.
32. Acts and Facts (August 1976), p. 4.
33. See Alfred Bloom, Shinrans Gospel of Pure Grace (Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1965).
34. Hackett, Personal Immortality and Human Nature.
35. Gilson, Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas.
veta
36. S
stavara Upanis.ad 6.20; Isa. 34:3.
37. John B. Cobb and David R. Griffin, Process Theology: An Introductory Exposition (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1976), p. 8.
38. See my article Three Types of Divine Power, Process Studies 20:4
(Winter 1991), pp. 22132.
39. Gabriel Marcel, Being and Having, trans. Katharine Farrer (London: Dacre Press, 1949), p. 174.
40. Quoted in John W. Yolton, John Locke: Problems and Perspectives
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), p. 6.
41. Sartre, Existentialism and Human Emotions, p. 36.
42. Ibid., p. 38.
43. Sartre, An Interview (1970), reprinted in Robert C. Solomon, Phenomenology and Existentialism (New York: Harper, 1972), p. 51118.
44. Camus, Carnets II, January, 1942-March, 1951 (Paris: Gallimard,
1964), p. 42.
45. Camus, The Myth of Sisyphus, trans. Justin OBrien (New York:
Vintage Books, 1955), p. 91.
46. Ibid., p. 47.
47. Dostoevsky, Crime and Punishment, trans. Jessie Coulson (New
York: Norton, 1964), pp. 52324.
Notes
245
246
Notes
Notes
247
248
Notes
4. Plato, Laws 701c.
Notes
249
250
Notes
39. Tagare, Kurma-Purana, p. 173 fn.
40. Bhagavata Pura
n.a 8.17.19 (Tagare), vol. 9, p. 1086.
41. Maha
bra
rata 12.311, trans. Doniger, Echoes of the Maha
bra
rata,
in Puran.a Perennis, ed. Doniger (Albany: SUNY Press, 1993), p. 40.
42. Devi -Bha
gavata Pura
n.a 1.14; Vijnanananda trans., p. 47.
43. Mahabrarata 12.319, trans. by Doniger in Echoes of the Mahabrarata, p. 48.
44. C. Mackenzie Brown, Modes of Perfected Living in the Mahabha
rata and the Pura
n.as, in Living Liberation in Hindu Thought, eds. A. O.
Fort and P. Y. Mumme (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996), p. 170.
45. Devi -Bha
gavata Pura
n.a 1.19; Vijnanananda trans., p. 72.
46. Aeschylus, Three Greek Plays: Prometheus Bound, Agamemnon, the
Trojan Women, trans. Edith Hamilton (New York: Norton, 1937), pp. 30, 123.
47. See Don Handelman and David D. Shulman, God Inside and Out:
ivas Game of Dice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), p. 56.
S
48. C. Kernyi, Prometheus: Archetypal Image of Human Existence,
trans. Ralph Manheim (New York: Pantheon, 1963), p. 45. I am indebted to
Kernyi for both references and insights.
49. Ibid., p. 61. Kernyis comment is curious in light of the fact that Titans and Titanesses (in seven pairs) were intimately connected to a sevenday week, thirteen-month lunar calender. See Robert Graves, Greek Myths,
vol. 1, pp. 2729.
50. Ovid, Metamorphoses iii.
51. Homer, Iliad 14.258.
52. Impregnation by swallowing is common in ancient mythology. The
precedent for the reproductive mechanics of this story about Zeus may be
the Hittite account of Kumarbi (=Kronos) who bites off and swallows the penis of Anu (=Uranus) and gives birth to a Zeus-like storm god. See G. S. Kirk
and J. E. Raven, The Presocratic Philosophers (London: Cambridge University Press, 1957), p. 36.
53. See the Kathamr.ta 5.68; cited in Jeffrey J. Kripal, Kali s Child
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), p. 276.
54. Hesoid, Works & Days and Theogony, trans. Stanley Lombardo (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1993); Theogony, 89798.
55. Ibid., 93233.
56. Aeschylus, Prometheus Bound, trans. Philip Vellacott (London: Penguin Books, 1961), 376.
Notes
251
252
Notes
also developed a caste system, but the presence of Brahmin Jainas did not
prevent Jainas from performing their own worship at Jaina temples.
12. Hemacandra, Yogasastra 2.45; cited in Paul Dundas, The Jains
(London: Routledge, 1992), p. 201.
13. Jyoti Prasad Jain, Essence of Jainism, p. 11.
14. Jaini, Jaina Path of Purification, pp. 16263.
ra
ra
15. Medhavin, S
vaka
ca
ra Dharma-samgraha-S
vakacara.
16. See P. S. Jaini, Jaina Path of Puridication, p. 194.
17. Bhuvanbhanusuri, Essentials of Bhagavan Mahavi rs Philosophy,
pp. 120, 122. The author also states that one can eliminate sin by venerating Mahavi ra (p. 71).
18. Ibid., p. 121.
19. See Devendra Muni, Jaina Religion and Philosophy: An Introduction, trans. Kewal Krishan Mitall (Daipur, India: Sri Tarak Guru Jain Granthalya, 1985), p. 10.
20. Prem Suman Jain, The Ethics of Jainism, in World Religions and
Global Ethics, ed. S. Cromwell Crawford (New York: Paragon House, 1989),
p. 71. Jyoti Prasad Jain uses the language of transformation, but it is clear
that this is not a metaphysical change: This transformation of man into god
is the realistic end of religious pursuit in Jainism for a sincere aspirant of
the Truth. . . . Each soul, when completely free from karmic influences, becomes itself and transforms into divinity.. . . Each liberated soul is a full
and perfect divinity in itself and by itself (Essence of Jainism, pp. 8, 10).
21. Jyoti Prasad Jain, Essence of Jainism, p. 8.
22. Krishna Prem and Madhava Ashish, Man: The Measure of All
Things (Wheaton, IL: Theosophical Publishing House, 1969), pp. 18788,
336. The Sam
. khya tradition also makes humankind the end of all evolution:
From Brahma down to a stock, the creation is for sake of Purus.a, till there
be discrimination (Sam
. khya-pravacana-sutra 3.47, trans. Nandall Sinha,
The Sam
. khya Philosophy, in Sacred Books of the Hindus, ed. B. D. Basu
[New York: AMS Press, 1974], vol. 11, p. 324).
23. Ma
ndu
kya Upanis.ad 1.1, trans. R. E. Hume, The Thirteen Princpal
Upanishads (London: Oxford University Press, 2nd ed. rev., 1931).
24. See Jaini, Jaina Path of Purification, pp. 16264.
25. Quoted in Sartre, Existentialism and Human Emotions, pp. 2930.
26. See Bhuvanbhanusuri, Essentials of Bhagava
n Maha
vi rs Philosophy, p. 35. The Lord [Mahavi ra] had appeared here only to destroy his internal enemy namely . . . illusion (p. 45).
Notes
253
254
Notes
45. Nathmal Tatias commentary on the Tattvartha Sutra, p. 281. Tatia acknowledges that the saints omniscience is a major exception to
anekantavada (p. xvii).
46. See P. S. Jaini, Jaina Path of Purification, p. 142.
47. Sri Nemichara Siddhanta Chakravarti, Gommat.sa
ra Ji va-Kanda,
trans. J. L. Jaini in Sacred Books of the Jainas, vol. 5, p. 289.
48. Ibid., p. 308.
49. Gandhi, Young India 8 (January 21, 1926), p. 30.
50. P. S. Jaini, The Jaina Path in Purification, p. 96.
51. Christopher Key Chapple, Nonviolence to Animals, Earth, and Self
in Asian Traditions (Albany: SUNY Press, 1993), chap. 5.
52. See the Tattva
rtha Sutra 5.31, pp. 13940.
53. Quoted in Kotturan, Ahim
. sa, p. 13. No matter whether he is Svetambara, or Digambara, a Buddhist or follower of any other creed, one who
looks on all creatures as his own self, attains salvation (quoted in ibid., p. 12).
54. See A. Siddhatissa, Buddhist Ethics: Essence of Buddhism (London: Allen & Unwin, 1970), p. 88; Bhagavada Puran.a 3.29.2832. Jainism
does allow that if one cannot uphold the vow of noninjury to immobile beings, then one must at least maintain it for mobile beings.
55. N. D. Bhargava, Some Chief Characteristics of the Jain Concept of
Nonviolence, in Contribution of Jainism to Indian Culture, p. 124.
56. For more discussion see my article Gandhi, Ahimsa, and the Self,
Gandhi Marg 15:1(April-June 1993), pp. 2438.
57. Ibid., p. 122. To be fair, Bhargava does insist that the use of the
negative formulation does not mean that we should not love, but his rejection of interrelationship does not give strong motivation to do so.
58. See my article The Virtue of Non-Violence: A Buddhist Perspective, Seikyo Times (February 1994), pp. 2836.
59. See P. S. Jaini, Karma and the Problem of Rebirth in Jainism, pp.
219ff.
60. See Tatias translation of the Tattvartha Sutra, p. 285.
61. Ibid., 5.16, p. 127.
62. Ibid., p. 219.
63. Bhuvanbhanusuri, Essentials of Bhagavan Mahavi rs Philosophy,
pp. 23, 22.
64. Ibid., p. 22.
Notes
255
65. J. L. Jaini enthusiastically supports the radical dualism of Kundakundacharya in this passage: God versus Satan becomes Pure Soul versus Matter. God is Pure Soul. Satan is Pure Matter, the tempter, seducer, deluder and Jailor of the Soul (Samayasara, in Sacred Books of the Jainas,
vol. 8, p. 43).
66. See the Gommat.sa
ra Ji va-Kanda, Sacred Books of the Jainas, vol.
5, p. 144.
67. A. Chakravartinayanar, A philosophical introduction to Pacha
stika
yasa
ra, in Sacred Books of the Jainas, vol. 3, p. xxix.
256
Notes
11. See, for example, the Katha Upanis.ad 3.11.
12. Chandogya Upanis.ad 8.12.3. Chapple uses this passage as a concluding vision of a very different dialectical process. In a concise and brilliant interpretation of the Mahabharata he sees the self-division of Vyasa as
an emanation of being (sat) out of nonbeing (asat) and a return to that undifferentiated source (Nonviolence to Animals, Earth, and Self in Asian Traditions, p. 82). In the context of the religion of Kr. s.n.a I would see this vision
as holistic but with the differentiation of personal interaction.
13. See Eliade, Yoga: Freedom, and Immortality (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2nd ed. 1969), p. 307.
14. See Gerald J. Larson, The Philosophy of Sam
. khya, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, vol. 4, p. 627n8.
15. Eliade, Patanjali and Yoga, pp. 5354.
16. Eliade, Yoga: Freedom, and Immortality, p. 98.
17. The Sam
. khya-karika, trans. Gerald Larson, Classical Sam
. khya
(New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2nd ed., 1979), 17.
18. Sam
. khya-pravacana-sutra 3.47, trans. Nandall Sinha, The Sam
.khya Philosophy in Sacred Books of the Hindus, ed. B. D. Basu (New York:
AMS Press, 1974), vol. 11, p. 324. I have given Eliades alternative translations (Patanjali and Yoga, p. 20).
19. Mishra, Yoga Sutras, p. vi.
20. Tattva
rtha Su
tra 10.1, p. 253.
21. See Vasudeva S. Agrawala, Purus.a-Sukta, Dr. Mirashi Felicitation Volume (Nagpur, India: Vidarbha Samshodhan Mandal, 1965), pp. 7, 8.
22. See Raimondo Panikkar, The Vedic Experience (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977), p. 73; and Chapple, Nonviolence to Animals,
Earth, and Self in Asian Traditions, p. 50. I would reverse the following observation by Chapple: The human order is seen as an extension of and utterly reliant on the natural order (p. 52).
23. R. geda 10.90.2.
24. Atharva-veda 10.2.4.
25. Ibid., v. 14.
26. Ibid., v. 21.
27. Ibid., v. 28.
28. Ibid., v. 33. Now that Golden Person who is seen within the sun
has a golden beard and golden hair. He is exceedingly brilliant, all, even to
the fingernail tips. . . . His name is High. He is raised high above all evils.
Verily, he who knows this rises high above all evils. . . . He is the lord of the
Notes
257
worlds which are beyond yonder sun, and also of the gods desires. Chandogya Upanis.ad 1.6.68. Cited from Robert E. Hume, The Thirteen Principal
Upanishads (London: Oxford University Press, 2nd ed. revised, 1930).
29. Br.hada
ran.yaka Upanis.ad 1.4.1.
30. Ibid., v. 10.
31. Ibid.
32. Ibid., 2.1.2 (Hume).
veta
33. S
svata
ra Upanis.ad 3.8, 9.
34. Ibid., 6.11.
35. Mun.d. aka 2.1.2; Chandogya 4.15.5; 5.10.1; Br.hadaran.yaka 1.12.
veta
36. S
svata
ra Upanis.ad 6.11.
37. Maitri Upanis.ad 2.7.
38. Ibid., 6.21, 22.
39. Kausi taki 1.5, 6.
40. Taittiri ya 1.6; 2.8.
41. Maitri 4.4.
veta
42. S
svata
ra 6.20.
43. Taittiri ya 3.5.
44. Bhagavad-gi ta
15.15, 18.
45. Ibid., 11.13; 10.2; 11.52.
46. Ibid., 14.3, 27.
47. The Bhagavad-gi ta, commentary and trans. R. C. Zaehner (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1973), p. 368.
48. Chandogya Upanis.ad 8.12.3.
49. Ibid., p. 367.
50. See Robert S. Minor, An Exegetical Commentary of the Bhagavadgi ta (New Delhi: Heritage Publishers, 1982), p. 429. Minor also does the
best job of sorting out the three different uses of purus.a in these verses.
51. Doniger OFlaherty, Origins of Evil in Hindu Mythology, pp. 78ff.
52. Ibid., p. 82.
53. Chandogya 3.17.6
54. C. Mackenzie Brown, The Triumph of the Goddess (Albany: SUNY
Press, 1990), pp. 12829.
258
Notes
55. Ibid., p. 89.
56. Biardeau, Puranic Cosmogony, vol. 2, p. 818.
57. Ibid., p. 819.
Notes
259
260
Notes
point in his praise for Durga: Through maya, you assume manhood (purusatva), and thorough ma
ya you are Prakr. ti herself / You are beyond both,
eternal, supporting the Supreme Brahman / O Goddess, you have the form
of a woman; you are the excellent Purus.a; and you are a eunuch (quoted in
ibid., p. 136).
16. The Sa
m
rika, Larson trans, 66.
. khya-ka
17. Ibid., 68.
18. Kathleen M. Erndl, Victory to the Mother (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 31.
19. Sam
rika
, 57.
. khya-ka
20. See Thomas B. Coburn, Encountering the Goddess (Albany: SUNY
Press, 1991), pp. 134, 145. This book contains a complete translation of the
Devi -Ma
ha
tmya and this will be the translation cited in the next section.
21. Brown, God as Mother, p. 128.
22. Aldous Huxley, After Many a Summer Dies the Swan (London: Chatto
and Windus, 1939), p. 175.
23. Maitri Upanis.ad 4.4.
24. Catherine Keller, Warriors, Women, and the Nuclear Complex, in
Sacred Interconnections: Postmodern Spirituality, Political Economy, and
Art, ed. David R. Griffin (Albany. SUNY Press, 1990), p. 72.
25. See my article Three Types of Divine Power, Process Studies 20:4
(Winter 1991), pp. 22132.
26. Cobb and Griffin, Process Theology, p. 119.
27. Devi -Ma
ha
tmya 1.59; 4.6; 11.10.
28. Brahmavaivarta Pura
n.a, Rakr.ti-Khanda 55.87; Pintchman trans.,
p. 164.
29. Kr. s.n.adasa Kaviraja, Caitanya-carita
mr.ta 1.4.83; cited in Edward
C. Dimock Jr., Li la, History of Religions 29:2 (November 1989), p. 162.
akti of All: the Vision of the
30. Thomas B. Coburn, Consort of None, S
Devi -Mahatmya, in The Divine Consort: Radha and the Goddess of India
(New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1984).
31. Devi -Ma
ha
tmya 2.912.
32. See Doniger OFlaherty, Asceticism and Eroticism in the Mythology
iva, p. 325.
of S
33. The Laws of Manu, Doniger trans., 4.186; 11.122, 247.
34. Ibid., 7.14.
Notes
261
262
Notes
58. Skanda Pura
n.a 1.1.21.62.
59. Ibid., 1.1.22.26.
60. Ibid., 1.1.22.9596.
61. Stanley N. Kurtz, All Mothers Are One (New York: Columbia University Press, 1992), p. 31.
62. Lynn Bennett, Dangerous Wives and Sacred Sisters (New York: Columbia University Press, 1983).
63. Kurtz, All Mothers Are One, p. 143.
64. Ibid., p. 93.
65. Ibid., p. 174.
66. Devi -Bha
gavata Puran.a 1.15; Vijnanananda trans., pp. 5253.
67. A. K. Ramanujan, On Folk Mythologies and Folk Puran.as, in
Pura
n.a Perennis, p. 107.
68. Bennett, Dangerous Wives and Sacred Sisters, p. 278.
69. Coburn, Encountering the Goddess, p. 222 fn. Coburn is drawing on
Cynthia Humess field research in Uttar Pradesh.
70. See the Devi -Ma
ha
tmya 3.38; see also Skanda Pura
n.a 1.3.1.10.68.
71. Devi -Bha
gavata 5.10.3234; Doniger OFlaherty, Women, Androgynes, and Other Mythical Beasts, p. 82.
72. Brown, however, reminds us that the Sam
. khya purus.a is far less masculine than the Vedic purus.a. The former, as we have seen, is impotent and passive as opposed to the active prakr.ti. In the Sam
. khya system, as Brown explains, the Paursic (manly) character of the cosmic [Vedic] Purus.a loses any
heroic, aggressive tendencies, becoming absorbed in the image of the quiescent
witness. On the other hand, the feminine traits of Prakr.ti, at least as they appear in the Devi -Bha
gavata, are primarily maternal and nonerotic, lenient
rather than lustful. As Prakr.ti and Purus.a fuse in the higher nature of the
Devi , she combines the ideal of the dispassionate witness and the compassionate mother (Triumph of the Goddess, pp. 12829). Brown also observes that
there is an important contrast between the Goddess as primarily a warrior in
the Devi -Ma
ha
tyma and her more maternal role in the Devi -Bha
gavata.
73. Susan S. Wadley, Women and the Hindu Tradition, in Women in India: Two Perspectives, eds. Doranne Jacobson and Susan S. Wadley (Columbia,
MO: South Asia Books, 1977), p. 132; cited in Tracy Pintchman, The Rise of the
Goddess in the Hindu Tradition (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994), p. 211.
74. Vasudeva S. Agrawala, The Glorification of the Great Goddess (Varanasi, India: All-India Kashirag Trust, 1963), pp. 3, 4; cited in Coburn, Encountering the Goddess, p. 157.
Notes
263
75. Miranda Shaw, Passionate Enlightenment: Women in Tantric Buddhism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994), p. 33.
76. Rita M. Gross, Buddhism after Patriarchy? in After Patriarchy, p.
33.
77. Shaw, Passionate Enlightenment, p. 11.
78. Cynthia Humes, Glorifying the Great Goddess or Great Woman?
Hindu Womens Experience in Ritual Recitation of the Devi -Ma
ha
tmya, in
Women and Goddess Traditions, eds. Karen L. King and Karen Torjesen,
(Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1997), p. 52.
79. Vandana Shiva, Staying Alive: Women, Ecology, and Development
(London: Zed Books, 1988), p. 6.
80. Alf Hiltebeitel has argued that a Tamil goddess cult of Draupadi is
really the original basis of the Maha
bha
rata (The Cult of Draupadi I [Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1988]).
81. Maha
bharata 3.31.347, trans. R. C. Zaehner, Concordant Discord
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), p. 177.
82. Maha
bharata 11.25.401 in ibid., p. 183.
83. Aditi De, Draupadis Daughter, Deccan Herald (December 17,
1995), Articulations sec., p. 1.
264
Notes
7. Sri Aurobindo Birth Centenary Library (Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust, 1970), vol. 12, p. 44.
8. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 416.
9. Wendy Doniger OFhaherty, foreword in Edward C. Dimock Jr., The
Place of the Hidden Moon (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), p.
xiii; cited in Kripal, Ka
li s Child, p. 117.
10. Kripal, Ka
li s Child, p. 118.
11. The Gospel of Ramakrishna, p. 31. The many passages that do appear to support the illusory nature of the world and a formless Brahman
must be seen as a sign of deference to the many disciples who came from the
Brahmo Samaj.
12. Kripal, Ka
lis Child, p. 146.
13. See ibid., p. 191.
ri sri ra
14. S
makr.s.n.a-Li la
prasan.ga 1.4.7; trans. Kripal, p. 55.
15. Cited in Kripal, Ka
lis Child, p. 227.
16. Katha
mr.ta 4.227 (Kripal).
17. Ibid., 4.143.
18. Gospel of Ramakrishna, p. 432; Katha
mar.ta 5.122.
19. Gospel of Ramakrishna, p. 405.
20. Ibid., p. 432.
21. Kripal, p. 138.
22. Ibid., pp. 14042.
23. Katha
mar.ta 4.36.
24. Gospel of Ramakrishna (condensed version), p. 326.
25. Kathamr.ta 2.62;5.14041 (Kripal); see Gospel of Ramakrishna, p.
701.
.
26. Upadesasa
hasri 2.3.1; 2.10.8; cited in Nelson, Sankara and Classical Advaita, in Living Liberation in Hindu Thought, p. 39.
27. Vivekananda, On the Vedanta Philosophy, in Complete Works,
vol. 5, p. 282.
28. Kripal, Kalis Child, p. 26. Phrases cited from the Li laprasan.ga
5.12.3.11.
29. Quoted in Narasingha P. Sil, Vivekanadas Ramakr. s.n.a: An Untold
Story of Mythmaking and Propaganda, Numen 40 (1993), p. 46; quoted in
Kripal, Ka
lis Child, p. 26.
Notes
265
30. Kripal, Ka
lis Child, p. 27. He cites the Katha
mr.ta (4.296) as evidence.
31. Ibid., p. 26. Narendra was a lion among men (Li laprasan.ga 5.12.
3.11).
32. Vivekananda, Complete Works, vol. 4, p. 384; vol. 5, p. 439. He was
surprised that the temple priests allowed him to worship the Mother to
[his] hearts content, even though he had allegedly been spiritually polluted
by traveling Europe and America (vol. 7, p. 239).
33. Ibid., vol. 7, p. 26; vol. 6, p. 147.
34. Ibid., vol. 6, pp. 14550; vol. 8, p. 253.
35. See Dhar, Vendanta and the Bengal Renaissance, p. 126.
36. Vivekananda, Modern India, in Complete Works, vol. 4, p. 480.
37. Ibid., vol. 8, p. 46.
38. Aurobindo, Mind of Light, p. 106
39. L. Thomas ONeil, Toward the Life Divine: Sri Aurobindos Vision
(New Delhi: Manohar, 1979), p. 20. Anthropomorphism is an imaged recognition of the truth that man is what he is because God is what He is and that
there is one soul and body of things, humanity even in its incompleteness
the most complete manifestation yet achieved here and divinity the perfection of what in man is imperfect. That he sees himself everywhere and worships that as a God is also true (Life Divine, p. 699).
40. Quoted in A. K. Sarkar, Sri Aurobindos Vision of the Supermind
(New Delhi: South Asian Publishers, 1989), p. 23.
41. Aurobindo, Synthesis of Yoga, p. 591.
42. Haridas Chaudhuri, Sri Aurobindos Vision of Supermanhood, Sri
Aurobindo Circle No. 1 (Bombay: Bazar Printing Press, 1944), p. 71; cited in
ONeil, Toward the Life Divine, p. 76.
43. ONeill, Toward the Life Divine, p. 75.
44. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 2.
45. Ibid.
46. See Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 34; see also Nicholas F. Gier, Dialectic:
East and West, Indian Philosophical Quarterly 10 (January 1983), pp. 20718.
47. Collected Works of the Mother, vol. 10, p. 34.
48. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 980.
49. Aurobindo, Birth Centenary Library, vol. 18, p. 71.
50. Aurobindo, The Superman (Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram, 1991), p. 6. First published as three separate essays in 1915.
266
Notes
51. Ibid., p. 1.
52. Ibid., p. 2.
53. Ibid., p. 15.
54. Nietzsche, Thus Spake Zarathustra, in The Portable Nietzsche, p.
124.
55. Aurobindo, Arya (August 15, 1915), p. 9.
56. P. B. Saint-Hilaire, The Future Evolution of Man (Pondicherry, India: All India Press, 1963), p. 148.
57. Aurobindo, The Mother (Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram,
1928), p. 2. Francis Bacon claimed that science does not merely exert a gentle guidance over natures course; [it has] the power to conquer and subdue
her, to shake her to her foundations (The Works of Bacon, eds. J. Sedding
et al. [Stuttgart: F. F. Verlag, 1963], vol. 5, p. 506.
58. P. Nallaswami, Sivajana Siddiyar 3.2.77; cited in R. C. Zaehner,
Evolution in Religion: A Study in Sri Aurobindo and Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), p. 104.
59. Aurobindo, Mother, pp. 3637.
60. Ibid., p. 35.
61. Ibid., p. 1.
62. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 922.
63. Aurobindo, Birth Centenary Library, vol. 19, p. 960.
64. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 1067.
65. Aurobindo, Superman, p. 16.
66. Ibid., p. 15.
67. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 40.
68. ONeil, Toward the Life Divine, p. 76.
69. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 61.
70. Aurobindo, Superman, p. 12.
71. Aurobindo, Life Divine, p. 976.
72. Ibid., p. 991.
73. Aurobindo, Notes on the Mahabharat (Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram, 1956), p. 57.
74. World-existence is the ecstatic dance of Siva which multiplies the
body of . . . God numberlessly to the view: it leaves that white substance pre-
Notes
267
cisely where and what it was, ever is and ever will be. . . . (Aurobindo, Life
Divine, p. 78).
75. Aurobindo, Sri Aurobindo Birth Centenary Library, vol. 19, p. 834.
76. It is not true to say, as Whitehead does, that God goes on evolving
with the evolution of the world, but evolution only exhibits different facets of
the multiple nature of God (S. K. Maitra, The Meeting of East and West in
Sri Aurobindos Philosophy [Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Press,
ri Aurobindos Vision of the Supermind for
1956], p. 431). See also Sarkars S
more Whitehead-Aurobindo comparative work. Unfortunately, both of these
studies contain major errors in interpretating Whiteheads philosophy.
268
Notes
olulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1976), p. 112. See also his History of Buddhist Philosophy, pp. 12223.
14. Anguttara-nika
ya 4.6.36; Book of Gradual Sayings, vol. 2, p. 44.
15. The Lakkhan.a Suttanta in Dialogues of the Buddha, trans. T. W.
and C. A. F. Rhys David (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1921), part 1, p.
139.
16. Bellanwila Wimalaratana, AStudy of the Concept of the Maha
purisa
in Buddhist Literature and Iconography (University of Lancaster diss., 1980),
pp. 27475.
17. Brahma
yusutta in the Majjhima Nika
ya II,137; Middle Length Sayings, vol. 2, p. 322.
18. See Rhys Davids introduction to the Lakkhan.a Suttanta, pp. 135
36.
19. Wimalaratana, Study of the Concept of the Mahapurisa in Buddhist Literature and Iconography, p. 267.
20. Ibid., p. 269.
21. Cited in Angela F. Howard, The Imagery of the Cosmological Buddha (Leiden, Netherlands: Brill, 1986), frontispiece in Chinese with translation. The concept of a superior form of the divinity, as opposed to the common
form, may have been a Buddhist borrowing from Hindu thought (p. 58).
22. Ibid., p. 61.
23. J. R. Haldar, Early Buddhist Mythology (New Delhi: Manohar, 1977),
p. 131.
24. See Wimalaratana, Study of the Concept of the Mahapurisa in
Buddhist Literature and Iconography, p. 59.
25. The Maha
vastu, trans. J. J. Jones (London: Routledge Kegan Paul,
1976), vol. 2, pp. 38.
26. Questions of Milinda, trans. I. B. Horner (London: Luzar, 1969),
vol. 1, p. 219.
27. Wimalaratana, Study of the Concept of the Mahapurisa in Buddhist Literature and Iconography, p. 56.
28. Maha
vastu, vol. 2, pp. 1921.
29. Mahamati, the food for my Sravakas, Pratyekabuddhas, and Bodhisattvas is the Dharma and not flesh-food; how much more the Tathagatha!
The Tathagatha is the Dharmakaya, Mahamati; he abides in the Dharma as
food; he is not a body feeding on flesh. . . . (The Lankavatara Su
tra, trans.
D. T. Suzuki [London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1932], p. 219).
30. Majjhima-Nika
ya II, 6; Middle Length Sayings, vol. 2, p. 207.
Notes
269
270
Notes
52. Ko gaku, Problem of the Body in Nietzsche and Do gen, in Nietzsche and Asian Thought, p. 219.
53. Quoted in ibid., p. 221.
54. Graham Parkes, Nietzsche and Zen Master Hakuin on the Roles
of Emotion and Passion, in Emotions in Asian Thought, eds. Roger Ames
and Joel Marks (Albany: SUNY Press, 1995), p. 213.
55. Quoted in ibid., p. 223. No primary citation given.
56. The Platform Scripture of the Sixth Patriarch, ed. and trans. Philip
B. Yampolsky (New York: Columbia University Press, 1967), 29, p. 150.
57. Ibid. 26, p. 148.
58. Nietzsche, Human All-Too-Human, trans. Paul V. Cohn, The Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche, ed. Oscar Levy (New York: Russell & Russell, 1964), vol. 7, p. 225.
59. Portable Nietzsche, p. 511. I have added to Grahams original points
on this passage.
60. Ibid., p. 519.
61. The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale
(New York: Vintage Books, 1968), 384.
62. See Kristofer Schipper, The Taoist Body, trans. Karen C. Duval
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), p. 172.
63. Steven Odin, The Social Self in Zen and American Pragmatism (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996), p. 97.
64. It is Paul Tillich, not Plato, who makes this specific distinction between ouk on and me on. See his book Systematic Theology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), vol. 1, p. 188.
65. Odin, Social Self in Zen and American Pragmatism, p. 33.
66. Ibid., p. 24.
67. Ibid., p. 61.
68. Ibid., p. 266.
Notes
271
3. Julia Ching, Who Were the Ancient Sages? in Julia Ching and R.
W. L. Guisso, eds., Sages and Filial Sons (Hong Kong: Chinese University
of Hong Kong Press, 1991), p. 17.
4. See D. Howard Smith, Confucius (New York: Scribners, 1973), p.
124.
5. Quoted in ibid., p. 176.
6. Fung Yu-lan, A History of Chinese Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1953), vol. 2, p. 168.
7. E. H. Parker, Studies in Chinese Religion (London: Chapman and
Hall, 1910), p. 221.
8. Granet, Religion of the Chinese People, pp. 11011.
9. Wu Chengen, Monkey, trans. Arthur Waley (New York: John Day,
1943), pp. 78.
10. See ibid., p. 284.
11. Anne D. Birdwhistell, Transition to Neo-Confucianism (Palo Alto,
CA: Stanford University Press, 1989), p. 168. In her excellent study of sagehood, Julia Ching states: The word sage clearly refers to a great and superior being: not necessarily a god, but a human being whose understanding
and virtue may be described as god-like. Ching adds that there were deity
symbols in the sage-king tradition, but these were demythologized by Confucian philosophers. See Ching, Who Were the Ancient Sages, in Sages and
Filial Sons, p. 17.
12. See Raymond Dawson, Imperial China (London: Hutchinson, 1972),
p. 141.
13. John K. Shryock, The Origin and Development of the State Cult of
Confucius (New York: Century Co., 1932), p. 155.
14. Shryock, The Temples of Anking and their Cults (New York: AMS
Press, 1973), p. 55.
15. See Thompson, Chinese Religion, p. 78.
16. See John D. Young, Confucianism and Christianity: The First Encounter (Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1983); and Jacques Gernet, China and the Christian Impact: A Conflict of Cultures, trans. Janet
Lloyd (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
17. See Shyrock, Temples of Anking and Their Cults, p. 57.
18. Translated by Young, Confucianism and Christianity, p. 121.
19. Quoted in K. L. Reichelt, Religion in Chinese Garment, trans. Joseph
Tetlie (London: Lutterworth Press, 1951), p. 55.
272
Notes
20. Ibid., p. 56. Another version of this benediction contains the phrase
the efficacy of the Master matches that of Heaven and Earth, but this is
the only allusion that might imply that Confucius has divine powers.
21. E. T. Williams, The State Religion of China During the Manchu
Dynasty, Journal of the North China Branch, Royal Asiatic Society 44
(1913), p. 151; quoted in ibid., p. 75.
22. Quoted in Friedrich Starr, Confucianism: Ethics, Philosophy, Religion (New York: Covici Friede, 1930), p. 232.
23. Quoted in ibid., pp. 23334.
24. Kang Yu-wei, Confucius as a Reformer 2.12, quoted in Fung Yulan, History of Chinese Philosophy, vol. 2, p. 678.
25. Chu Chai and Winberg Chai, eds., Confucianism (Woodbury, NY:
Barons Educational Series, 1973), p. 162.
26. David L. Hall and Roger T. Ames, Thinking Through Confucius (Albany: SUNY Press, 1987), pp. 24243.
27. A Chinese-English Dictionary (Beijing: Commercial Press, 1980), p.
608. I am grateful to Chen Lai of Beijing University and Tang Yi of Beijings
Institute of World Religions for making me aware of this mistranslation.
28. Yang Buojun, Mengze Yi Zhu (Mencius Annotated and Translated
into Modern Chinese) (Beijing: Zhong Hua Press, 1984), p. 417. This means
that every translator of 7b25 that I consulted has missed this predicative
meaning of shen. Lionel Giles: A sage who is beyond our comprehension
may be called a divine man; James Ware: What remains unknown despite
the fact that one is a sage is called divine; Wing-Tsit Chan: When a sage is
beyond our knowledge, he is called a man of spirit; and D. C. Lau: To be
sage and to transcend the understanding is called divine.
29. Tu Wei-ming, Confucian Thought: Selfhood as Creative Transformation (Albany: SUNY Press, 1985), p. 152. Tu calls on the authority of
Zhuxi on this point. Tu also uses another unidentified translation of this
passage that does not deify the sage: He whose sageliness is beyond our
comprehension is called spiritual (p. 96).
30. Doctrine of the Mean, chap. 32 (Chan).
31. Charles Muller, The Doctrine of the Mean at www.acmuller.gol.com/
contao/docofmean.htm.
32. Tu Wei-Ming, Confucian Thought, p. 129. In his commentary on the
Doctrine of the Mean, Tu makes it clear that this godlike creativity of Confucius must not conceived as the demonstration of some superhuman quality inherent in his nature. Far from being superhuman, what Confucius was
able to manifest can be characterized as a refinement of his humanity
Notes
273
274
Notes
Notes
275
17. Thom H. Fang, The World and the Individual in Chinese Metaphysics, in The Chinese Mind, p. 242.
18. Source Book, p. 507.
19. Doctrine of the Mean 22 (Chan).
20. Tu Wei-Ming, Confucian Thought, p. 75.
21. Buddhaghosa, Path of Purity, pp. 480ff.
22. Benjamin Schwartz, The World of Thought in Ancient China (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 310. Schwartz qualifies Xunzis
utilitarianism as a method dictated primarily by the exigencies of his period.
Under better conditions, argues Schwartz, Xunzi would agree with Confucius and Mencius that the virtuous person should be internally motivated
rather than be guided by external reward or punishment. Xunzi is especially
emphatic about pursuing music and the holy rites as ends in themselves.
23. Tu Wei-ming, Confucian Thought, p. 75.
24. Source Book, p. 134.
25. Machle, Nature and Heaven in The Xunzi, p. 127.
26. Ibid., pp. 14849.
27. Analects 2:12.
28. See Platos Protagoras 333.
29. See chapter 9 of the Xunzi.
30. Xunzi, chap. 21; Machle trans., p. 151.
31. Mencius 7a13.
32. See, for example, Sallie McFague, Models of God: Theology for an
Ecological, Nuclear Age (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1987).
33. See Cheng Hao, Source Book, p. 525; and Doctrine of the Mean, 33.
34. Tu Wei-ming, Confucian Thought, p. 132.
35. Ibid.
36. Mencius 5a5.
37. Ibid.
38. Tu Wei-ming, Centrality and Commonality, pp. 9, 102. Also curious
is Tus comment that the Greek homo mensura is not humanistic enough (p.
102), presumably implying that Heaven ought to be humanized as well as
Earth. Tus phraseology is better when he states that the human project is
Heavens self-consciousness in its own ultimate transformation (p. 108).
39. Ibid., p. 84.
276
Notes
40. Zhuxi (Chu hsi), Source Book, pp. 59394.
41. Wang Yang-Ming, Source Book, pp. 656, 673.
42. Lu Xiangshan (Lu Hsiang-Shan), Source Book, p. 575.
43. Wang Yang-ming, Source Book, p. 685.
44. Ibid., pp. 69091.
45. Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, 1178a67.
46. Hall and Ames, Thinking Through Confucius, p. 153.
47. Analects 6.23.
48. Tu Wei-ming, Confucian Thought, pp. 23, 70. Most of the insights
in this paragraph come from this outstanding book.
49. Mencius 7a21.
50. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M.
Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958), 568.
51. See my article Wittgenstein and Deconstruction (unpublished)
and also my book Wittgenstein and Phenomenology.
Notes
277
11. Watson, Complete works of Chuang Tzu, p. 87; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 89.
12. Watson, Complete works of Chuang Tzu, p. 122.
13. Ibid., p. 124.
14. Henry Wei, trans., The Guiding Light of Lao Tzu (Wheaton, IL: Theosophical Publishing House, 1982), p. 170.
15. Chen, Tao Te Ching, p. 137.
16. Ibid. Fung Yulan claims that Zhuangzis position is the same as the
Daodejing. The Dao continues to exist but ones xin ceases when the body
dies. See Fung Yulan, A Taoist Classic: Chuang-tzu (Beijing: Foreign Languages Press, 1989), p. 62.
17. Wing-tsit Chan, The Way of Lao-tzu (Indianapolis, IN: Library of
Liberal Arts, 1963), p. 128; Michael LaFargue, The Tao of the Tao Te Ching
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), p. 62.
18. Daodejing, chap. 50 (LaFargue).
19. Ibid.
20. Daodejing, chap. 59 (Chen).
21. I am indebted to Schipper, Taoist Body (pp. 16067) for this material on the immortals.
22. Ibid., p. 172.
23. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 46; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 33.
24. Herman Hesse, Steppenwolf, trans. Basil Creighton (New York:
Bantam Books, 1969), p. 110. Nietzsche believes that Goethe was the bermensch of the eighteenth century: A kind of self-overcoming on the part of
that century. He bore its strongest instincts within himself. . . . What he
wanted was totality; he fought the mutual extraneousness of reason, senses,
feeling, and will . . . he disciplined himself to wholeness, he created himself
(Portable Nietzsche, p. 554).
25. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 86; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 89.
26. David Loy, Zhuangzi and Nagarjuna on the Truth of No Truth in
Essays on Skepticism, Relativism, and Ethics in the Zhuangzi, eds. P. J.
Ivanhoe and Paul Kjellberg (Albany: SUNY Press, 1995), pp. 5067.
27. Daodejing, chap. 40 (Chan).
28. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 179.
278
Notes
29. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, pp. 32, 40; Graham, Chuang-tzu, pp. 45, 53.
30. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 43; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 57.
31. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 47; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 59.
32. Mark Berkson, Language: The Guest of RealityZhuangzi and
Derrida on Language, Reality, and Skillfulness in Essay in Skepticism, Relativism, and Ethics in the Zhuangzi, p. 110.
33. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 52; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 40.
34. Ibid.
35. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 302; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 190.
36. Berkson, Language, p. 108.
37. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 54; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 66.
38. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 37; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 49.
39. Berkson, Language, p. 108.
40. Kwang-ming Wu, The Butterfly as Companion: Meditations on the
First Three Chapters of the Chuang-tzu (Albany: SUNY Press, 1990), p.
136: Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 37; Graham, Chuang-tzu, p.
50.
41. Philip J. Ivanhoe, Zhuangzi on Skepticism, Skill, and the Ineffable
Dao, Journal of the American Academy of Religion 51:4 (Winter, 1993), pp.
63954.
42. This is Chens suggested translation of guan in chapter 1. The character guan is composed of two radicals bird and eye (Tao Te Ching, p. 54).
43. Yulan, Taoist Classic: Chuang-tzu, p. 59.
44. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 64; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 51; Plato, Protagoras 333.
45. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 64; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 51.
46. David L. Hall, To Be or Not to Be: The Postmodern Self and the
Wu-forms of Daoism, in Self as Person in Asian Theory and Practice, ed.
Roger T. Ames (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994), p. 224.
Notes
279
280
Notes
65. Parkes, Nietzsche and Zen Master Hakuin on the Roles of Emotion and Passion, in Emotions in Asian Thought, p. 227.
66. Nietzsche, Will to Power, 691.
67. Ibid., 692.
68. Ames, Nietzsches Will to Power and Chinese Virtuality (De): A
Comparative Study, in Nietzsche and Asian Thought, pp. 13050.
69. Portable Nietzsche, p. 307.
70. Herbert Fingarette, ConfuciusSecular as Sacred (New York:
Harper Torchbooks, 1972), chap. 2.
71. Ames, Nietzsches Will to Power and Chinese Virtuality (De), p.
133.
72. Portable Nietzsche, p. 199.
73. Ibid., p. 480.
74. Nietzsche, Will to Power, 490.
75. Portable Nietzsche, p. 520.
76. Ibid., p. 143.
77. Ibid., p. 176.
78. See Girardot, Myth and Meaning in Early Taoism, p. 189.
79. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 66; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 75. This must be a reference to marking off straight boundaries for
fields and roads.
80. Portable Nietzsche, p. 406.
81. Ibid., p. 427.
82. Ibid., p. 268. Zarathustra says: I am the enemy of the spirit of
gravity (p. 304).
83. Ibid., p. 153.
84. Ibid., p. 305.
85. Ibid., p. 306.
86. Ibid., p. 269.
87. Ibid., p. 270. In his mountain home at least having something riding on his back is seen in a postive light (p. 295).
88. Laurence Lampert, Nietzsches Teaching: An Interpretation of Thus
Spake Zarathustra (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), p. 165.
89. Nietzsche, The Joyful Wisdom in The Complete Works of Friedrich
Notes
281
Nietzsche, ed. Oscar Levy (New York: Russell & Russell, 1964), vol. 10, 341,
pp. 27071.
90. Ibid., p. 268.
91. Ibid., p. 256.
92. Ibid., p. 274.
93. Ibid., p. 175.
94. Ibid., p. 304.
95. Ibid., p. 268.
96. Parkes, The Wandering Dance: Chuang Tzu and Zarathustra,
Philosophy East and West 33:3 (July 1983), p. 236.
97. Nietzsche, Will to Power, 1040.
98. Portable Nietzsche, p. 438.
99. Ibid., p. 143.
100. Daodejing, chap. 41 (Chen). Giving the inferior person this much
credit goes against the usual interpretation of the first stanza of this chapter, but I am grateful to Ivanhoe for supporting me in this reading.
101. Quoted in Griffiths, On Being Buddha, p. 73.
102. Portable Nietzsche, p. 294.
103. Gospel of Ramakrishna (condensed ed.), p. 279.
104. Ibid., p. 351.
105. Portable Nietzsche, p. 305.
106. This might after all be a proper burial for a Zoroastrian, who exposed their dead in high places so that their bones could be picked clean for
later disposal.
107. Lampert, Nietzsches Teaching, p. 164.
108. Hevajra Tantra, excerpted in World of the Buddha, p. 308.
109. See R. C. Zaehner, The Teachings of the Magi (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1976), p. 134.
110. Robert E. Allinson, Chuang-tzu for Spiritual Transformation (Albany: SUNY Press, 1989), p. 51.
111. Ibid., p. 56.
112. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, pp. 723; Graham, Chuang-tzu, pp. 7980.
113. Parkes, Wandering Dance, p. 246.
282
Notes
114. Vicki Noble, Motherpeace (New York: Harper, 1983), p. 25.
115. Watson, Complete Works of Chuang Tzu, p. 82; Graham, Chuangtzu, p. 87.
116. Book of Songs #55 (Karlgren).
117. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 98; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 97.
118. Portable Nietzsche, p. 199.
119. Parkes, Composing the Soul, pp. 16364.
120. Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals 2.17.
121. Parkes, Nietzsche and Zen Master Hakuin on the Roles of Emotion and Passion, in Emotions in Asian Thought, p. 217.
122. Ibid., p. 228.
123. Nietzsche, Will to Power, 958.
124. Ames, Nietzsches Will to Power and Chinese Virtuality, pp.
14647; The Will to Power, 567; Beyond Good and Evil, p. 259.
125. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 89; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 86.
126. Chen Guying, Zhuang Zi and Nietzsche: Plays of Perspectives,
in Nietzsche and Asian Thought, p. 129.
127. Nietzsche, Joyful Wisdom, 354, pp. 296300.
128. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 89; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, pp. 8687.
129. See Essays in Skepticism, Relativism, and Ethics in the Zhuangzi, pp. 2078.
130. Ivanhoe, Zhuangzi on Skepticism, Skill, and the Ineffable Dao,
p. 652 fn. 46.
131. Tu, Confucian Thought, p. 14
132. Graham, Chuang-tzu, p. 89; Watson, Complete Works of Chuang
Tzu, p. 86.
133. Hall and Ames, Thinking Through Confucius, p. 96.
134. Analects 15:29 (Ames); Doctrine of the Mean, chap. 22 (Chan).
135. Analects 6:30.
136. Doctrine of the Mean, chap. 12 (Chan).
Selected
Bibliography
283
284
Selected Bibliography
Selected Bibliography
285
286
Selected Bibliography
Selected Bibliography
287
288
Selected Bibliography
Hume, Robert E. The Thirteen Principal Upanishads, 2nd ed. London: Oxford University Press, Revised, 1930.
Humes, Cynthia. Glorifying the Great Goddess or Great Woman? Hindu
Womens Experience in Ritual Recitation of the Devi -Mahatmya. In
Women and Goddess Traditions, eds. Karen L. King and Karen Torjesen. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1997, pp. 3963.
Ivanhoe, Philip J. Zhuangzi on Skepticism, Skill, and the Ineffable Dao.
Journal of the American Academy of Religion 51:4 (Winter 1993), pp.
63954 .
. Human Nature and Moral Understanding in Xunzi. International
Philosophical Quarterly 34:2 (June 1994), pp. 16775.
Jain, Prem Suman. The Ethics of Jainism. In World Religions and Global
Ethics, ed. S. Cromwell Crawford. New York: Paragon House, 1989,
pp. 6588.
Jain, Jyoti Prasad. The Essence of Jainism. Varanasi: Shuchita Publications, n.d.
Jaini, Padmanabh S. On the Sarvajatva (Omniscience) of Mahavi ra and
the Buddha. In Buddhist Studies in Honour of I. B. Horner, eds. L.
Cousins et al. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Reidel, 1974, pp. 7190.
. The Jaina Path of Purification. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1979.
. Karma and the Problem of Rebirth in Jainism. In Karma and Rebirth in Classical Indian Tradition, ed. Doniger OFlaherty. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1980, pp. 21738.
Kalpasu
tra, trans. K. C. Lalwani. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1979.
Kaltenmark, Max. Lao Tzu and Taoism, trans. Roger Greaves. Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1969.
Kalupahana, David J. Buddhist Philosophy: A Historical Analysis. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1976.
. Na
ga
rjuna: Philosophy of the Middle Way. Albany: SUNY Press, 1986.
. A History of Buddhist Philosophy: Continuities and Discontinuities.
Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1992.
Katz, Nathan. Buddhist Images of Human Perfection. New Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 1980.
Keller, Catherine. Warriors, Women, and the Nuclear Complex. In Sacred
Interconnections: Postmodern Spirituality, Political Economy, and
Art, pp. 6382.
Kernyi, C. Prometheus: Archetypal Image of Human Existence, trans. Ralph
Manheim. New York: Pantheon Books, 1963.
Selected Bibliography
289
290
Selected Bibliography
The Maha
vastu, trans. by J. J. Jones. London: Routledge Kegan & Paul, 1976.
Maitra, S. K. The Meeting of East and West in Sri Aurobindos Philosophy.
Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Press, 1956.
McLelland Joseph C. Prometheus Rebound: The Irony of Atheism. Waterloo,
Ontario: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1988.
Mei, W. P. The Basis of Social, Ethical, and Spiritual Values in Chinese Philosophy. In The Chinese Mind, ed. Charles A. Moore. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1967, pp. 32329.
Minor, Robert S. An Exegetical Commentary of the Bhagavad-gi ta. New
Delhi: Heritage Publishers, 1982.
Mishra, Rammurti S. Yoga Sutras: The Textbook of Yoga Psychology. New
York: Doubleday Anchor, 1973.
The Mother. The Collected Works of the Mother. Pondicherry, India: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust, 1979.
Muller-Ortega, Paul E. Aspects of Ji vanmukti in the Tantric Saivism of
Kashmir. In Living Liberation in Hindu Thought, pp. 187218.
Myokyo-ni. Gentling the Bull. London: Zen Centre, n.d.
Mythologies, eds. Yves Bonnefoy et al. and trans. Wendy Doniger et al. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1991.
Nature in Asian Traditions of Thought, eds. J. B. Callicott and R. T. Ames.
Albany: SUNY Press, 1989.
Nelson, Lance E. Reverence for Nature or the Irrelevance of Nature? Advaita Vedanta and Ecological Concern. Journal of Dharma 16:3
(July-September 1991), pp. 282301.
.
. Living Liberation in Sankara and Classical Advaita. In Living Liberation in Hindu Thought, pp. 1762.
Nietzsche and Asian Thought, ed. Graham Parkes. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1991.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spake Zarathustra. In The Portable Nietzsche,
trans. and ed. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Viking, 1954.
. The Joyful Wisdom, trans. Thomas Common. In The Complete Works
of Friedrich Nietzsche, ed. Oscar Levy. New York: Russell & Russell,
1964, vol. 10.
. The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale.
New York: Vintage Books, 1968.
Odin, Steven. Process Metaphysics and Hua-Yen Buddhism. Albany: SUNY
Press, 1982.
Selected Bibliography
291
292
Selected Bibliography
The Sacred Books of the Jainas, ed. J. L. Jaini. New York: AMS Press, 1974.
Sacred Interconnections: Postmodern Spirituality, Political Economy, and
Art, ed. David R. Griffin. Albany: SUNY Press, 1990.
Said, Edward. Orientalism. New York: Pantheon, 1978.
Saint-Halaire, P. B. The Future Evolution of Man. Pondicherry, India: All
India Press, 1963.
Sarkar, A. K. Sri Aurobindos Vision of the Supermind. New Delhi: South
Asian Publishers, 1989.
Schipper, Kristofer. The Taoist Body, trans. Karen C. Duval. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993.
Schwartz, Benjamin. The World of Thought in Ancient China. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1985.
Sethna, K. D. The Spirituality of the Future. East Brunswick, NJ: Association of University Presses, 1981.
Shaw, Miranda. Passionate Enlightenment: Women in Tantric Buddhism.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994.
Shiva, Vandana. Staying Alive: Women, Ecology, and Development. London:
Zed Books, 1988.
Shyrock, John K. The Origin and Development of the State Cult of Confucius.
New York: Century, 1932.
Smith, Brian K. Eaters, Food, and Social Hierarchy in Ancient India. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 58:2 (Summer 1990), pp.
177206.
A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy, trans. and ed. Wing-tsit Chan. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963.
Sri Mad Devi Bhagavatam (Devi -Bha
gavata Pura
n. a), trans. Swami Vijnanananda. New Delhi: Manogarlal, 192123.
Stutley, Margaret and James Stutley. Harpers Dictionary of Hinduism. New
York: Harper, 1977.
Sugunasiri, Suwanda H. J. The Whole Body, Not Heart, as Seat of Consciousness: The Buddhas View. Philosophy East & West 45:3 (July
1995), pp. 40930.
Thompson, Laurence G. Chinese Religion: An Introduction, 3d ed. Belmont,
CA: Wadsworth, 1979.
The Tibetan Book of the Dead, trans. Francesca Fremantle and Chgyam
Trungpa. Boulder, CO: Shambhala Publications, 1975.
Selected Bibliography
293
Tiwari, J. N. Goddess Cults in Ancient India. New Delhi: Sundeep Prakashan, 1985.
Tsong-Karpa. Tantra in Tibet. London: Allen & Unwin, 1977.
Tu, Wei-ming. Confucian Thought: Selfhood as Creative Transformation. Albany: SUNY Press, 1985.
. Centrality and Commonality: An Essay on Confucian Religiousness.
Albany: SUNY Press, 1989.
Umasvati. Tattvartha Sutra (That Which Is), trans. Nathmal Tatia. New
York: HarperCollins Publishers, 1994.
Vajracchedika Prajaparamita, trans. Edward Conze. Rome: Serie Orientale Roma, 1957.
Valantasis, Richard. Constructions of Power in Asceticism. Journal of the
American Academy of Religion 63:4 (Summer 1995), pp. 775821.
Vivekananda, Swami. Speeches and Writings, 6th ed. Madras: G. A. Natesan,
1922.
.The Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda. Calcutta: Advaita
Ashrama, 1970.
. Karma-Yoga and Bhakti-Yoga. New York: Ramakrishna-Vivekananda
Center, rev. ed., 1973.
White, John D. God and the World from the Viewpoint of Advaita Vedanta:
A Critical Assessment. International Philosophical Quarterly 30:2
(June 1981), pp. 18593.
Williams, Paul. Mahayana Buddhism: Doctrinal Foundations. London:
Routledge, 1989.
Wimalaratana, Bellanwila. A Study of the Concept of the Mahapurisa in
Buddhist Literature and Iconography. University of Lancaster dissertation, 1990.
Wu, Kwang-ming. The Butterfly as Companion: Meditations on the First
Three Chapters of the Chuang-tzu. Albany: SUNY Press, 1990.
Young, John D. Confucianism and Christianity: The First Encounter. Hong
Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1983.
Zaehner, R. C. Hindu Scriptures. London: J. M. Dent & Sons, 1956.
Zimmer Heinrich. Philosophies of India, ed. Joseph Campbell. Cleveland:
World Publishing, 1956.
Note on
Supporting Center
This series is published under the auspices of the Center for Process
Studies, a research organization affiliated with the Claremont School
of Theology and Glaremond Graduate University. It was founded in
1973 by John B. Cobb Jr., Founding Director, and David Ray Griffin,
Executive Director; Mary Elizabeth Moore and Marjorie Schocki are
now also Codirectors. It encourages research and reflection on the
process philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead, Charles Hartshorne,
and related thinkers, and on the application and testing of this viewpoint in all areas of thought and practice. The center sponsors conferences, welcomes visiting scholars to use its library, and publishes
a scholarly journal. Process Studies, and a newsletter, Process Perspectives. Located at 1325 North College, Claremond, CA 91711, it
gratefully accepts (tax-deductible) contribuations to support its work.
295
Index
(Note: Chinese characters have been transliterated using the Pin Yin system. The Wade-Giles transliteration is given in parentheses.)
Abrahamic religions, 7, 157, 182, 186,
202, 207
advaita, 5154, 91
Advaita Vedanta, 11, 40, 42, 46, 50,
5154, 102, 110, 118, 119, 140, 142,
144, 152, 258
Aeschylus, 6, 28, 76
ahim
. a, 51, 91, 9294, 97, 170, 254
American Founding Fathers, xi, 24
Ames, Roger T., 40, 43, 178, 18486,
188, 205, 226, 234, 245
Analects, v, 25, 184, 186, 190, 205, 215
anatman, 47, 89
anekantavada, 80, 9092, 96, 254
anthropocentrism, xiv, 3, 7, 8, 10, 16, 81,
84, 97, 103, 150, 160, 162, 191, 198,
203, 208, 209
anthropomorphism, 7, 8, 10, 16, 25, 26,
81, 84, 111, 148, 198, 202, 204, 209,
210, 243, 265
Aquinas, Thomas, xi, 23, 29
Aristotle, 12, 20, 21, 43, 54, 76, 82, 97,
104, 116, 126, 205
.
Asanga, 87, 167
As vaghosa, 43
asuras, 3, 8, 5967, 72, 75, 79, 100, 101,
108, 111, 115, 121, 150, 154, 158,
161, 164
Asura Titanism, 3, 5977, 79, 99, 158
Athanasius, 23, 3031
Athene, 5, 74, 115
atman, xv, 8, 48, 50, 5154, 60, 67, 90,
94, 96, 103, 104, 117, 146, 201, 255
Aurobindo, 14, 139, 140, 141, 148155,
263, 267
297
298
Index
Index
Hinduism, xiii, 12, 13, 15, 25, 33, 43, 50,
61, 66, 84, 92, 93, 94, 96, 99, 101,
108, 109, 114, 115, 119, 126, 127,
129, 131, 132, 147, 159, 162, 163,
164, 192, 194, 201, 212
holistic, 35, 110, 197, 256
homo mensura, 26, 84, 275
Hua-yen Buddism, 5253
hubris, 3, 12, 13, 72, 114, 143, 168, 203,
222, 269
humanism, xi, 3, 12, 2326, 84, 157,
177, 183, 194, 224
Buddhist, 25, 158161
Confucian, 25, 160, 190, 198
Christian, xi, 23
scientific, 16, 184
secular, 24, 26, 159
superhumanism, 1, 2426, 80
theistic, 24, 3334
Hume, David, 47, 48, 160
hundun, 16, 209, 210, 21112, 219, 230,
232, 234, 235, 279
immortality, 16, 30, 33, 67, 69, 100, 104,
106, 149, 208, 21215
immutability, 13, 67, 96, 227
Indo-Iranian theistic principle, 7, 68, 83
incarnation, 9, 10, 16, 2933, 104, 143,
148, 161, 244
Indra, 7, 62, 68, 121, 122, 123, 154
Islam, 12, 13, 83
I s vara, 8, 11, 14, 70, 102, 103, 104, 107,
108, 111, 113, 117, 118, 13637, 145,
146, 151
Jaini, Padmanabh S., 8, 86, 90, 91, 95
Jainism, xii, xiii, xiv, 2, 4, 9, 10, 13,
1517, 19, 25, 33, 39, 40, 42, 43, 46,
49, 50, 51, 53, 55, 56, 57, 61, 66, 67,
7997, 103, 104, 111, 116, 149, 159,
160, 161, 162, 168, 204, 207, 220,
240, 252, 254
Jalandhara, 65, 249
James, William, xiv, 48
Jesus, 1, 2, 8, 16, 27, 89, 108, 177, 180,
187, 243
ji va, xiii, xv, 4647, 48, 50, 82, 86, 93,
96, 133
ji vanmuktra, 11, 71, 111, 145, 148, 149,
241
299
300
Index
Index
Raskolnikov, 27, 36, 37
reason, 26, 29, 205, 227, 246
Religious Right, xi, 23, 24, 32
ren (jen), 12, 16, 175, 185, 186, 203, 205,
215, 235, 236
R.gveda, 5, 13, 63, 99, 108, 176, 209, 255
r. is.is, 68, 69, 104
Said, Edward, xii
Sam
. khya, xii, xiii, 8, 17, 50, 60, 74, 90,
95, 96, 101, 102, 103, 106, 108, 109,
110, 111, 113, 117, 118, 119, 120,
123, 125, 127, 140, 151, 153, 160,
241, 252, 262
Sa m
. khya-Yoga, 4, 17, 19, 39, 40, 42, 43,
4647, 49, 50, 51, 57, 77, 86, 94, 96,
99, 101, 102, 103, 106, 110, 153,
154, 161, 168, 192, 204, 207, 220,
259
Sartre, Jean Paul, 12, 23, 2829, 30, 34,
35, 49, 233
Sarvastivadins, 44, 54, 86
Satan, 56, 39, 62, 255
Sautranikas, 44, 54, 241
self, 3957, 106, 133, 140, 167, 176, 191,
220
autonomous, xv, 12, 15, 17, 28, 3435,
42, 57, 103, 119, 153, 190, 205, 207
Buddhist, 4748
Hebrew, 4546, 47
process, 55, 56, 175
relational, xv, 15, 39, 3435, 55, 56,
140, 142, 153, 175, 176, 205, 220
social, xv 14, 15, 17, 50, 140, 142, 143,
153, 175, 176, 205, 220
substantial, 55, 57, 157, 168, 17475,
246
akta philosophy/theology, 14, 71, 74,
S
103, 109, 113137, 140, 142, 146,
148, 151, 152, 167, 207, 259
sakti, 14, 66, 67, 70, 73, 113137, 140,
147, 148, 151, 152, 153, 155
an.kara, 11, 40, 43, 46, 5154, 101, 110,
S
111, 145, 146, 155, 245
shamanism, 22223, 279
shen, 16, 180, 184, 18788, 213, 22223,
224, 227, 228, 272, 273
sheng, 194, 221
Siddhas, 167171, 176, 214
siddhi, 71, 82, 83, 84, 169
301
302
Index