Benoit Guillete A Travers de Reel PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

ISSN

1751-8229

Volume Eight, Number Two

Translation of Book Review: Recension dA travers le reel:


Entretiens avec
Fabien Tarby.
Book review originally published in French as : Recension
dAutour de Slavoj iek: Psychanalyse, Marxisme,
Idealisme Allemand; in International Journal of iek
Studies: Volume 5, Number 3.
Original author of book review: Benot Guillette, Universit
du Qubec Montral.
Review translated from the original French by
Jonathan Ferguson, Kings College London

This book presents the interviews Fabien Tarby (a specialist in the philosophy of Alain
Badiou) had with Slavoj iek (a longtime friend of Alain Badiou). Concision and
clarity are two of the qualities that distinguish ieks answers to Tarby. iek has
managed, in this book, to provide an excellent synthesis of his thought. The book is
divided into ten chapters and, it seems to me, expounds all the themes and theses
dear to iek. The themes of contingency and negativity are particularly well
discussed: both themes reappear in several chapters.

The first two chapters are concerned with psychoanalysis. In the first, iek mainly
focuses on his ideas on contingency in relation to psychoanalysis. According to iek,
it is necessary to reject the psychoanalytic approach of CG Jung because Jung does
not understand the importance that Freud attributed to contingency. In the second
chapter, Zizek clarifies what it is that he rejects and what it is he accepts from the
work of Lacan. The Lacan iek rejects is the one for whom the purpose of a
psychoanalytic cure is to enable the patient (the analysed) to keep their distance from
The Real. One can find that Lacan in The Ethics of Psychoanalysis (Lthique de la
psychanalyse) and in his teaching of the final six or seven years. The Lacan that iek
accepts is that found in Lenvers de la psychanalyse,1 in Encore 2 and especially in La
Logique du fantasme.3

The third chapter focuses on Hegel. According to iek, Hegel is a thinker of


contingency since the Hegelian necessity is always retroactive. iek even goes so
far as to say that Hegel would have found Marx rather too idealistic, for presuming to
know the objective tendency of history. iek thinks that in order to get an accurate
idea of the (dialectical) philosophy of Hegel, we must pay close attention to what he

writes concerning three themes: the cunning of reason, negativity and the
contingency of necessity.

As regards the cunning of reason, Hegel mentions the assassination of Caesar, in


order to show the contingency of necessity. Regarding negativity, Hegel mentions the
recurrence of wars to demonstrate that there is a surplus negativity that can never be
mastered or resolved (Aufhebung) by dialectics. According to iek, the negativity
that one finds in German idealism can only be understood in light of the death drive,
as the compulsion to repeat. Finally, as regards the contingency of necessity, Hegel
mentions the essential role of a monarch at the head of a modern
rational/non-totalitarian State to show that the dialectical mastery or resolution of
transcendence always supports itself by an empirical residue, a radically contingent
surplus.

The fourth chapter is rather long (in comparison to the other chapters of the book) and
focuses on the philosophy of Alain Badiou. iek mainly focuses on explaining the
disagreements he has with his friend Badiou about Hegel, Marx and Lacan. iek
regrets that Badiou does not notice the contingency of necessity in Hegel. He also
regrets that if one follows Badiou "You can understand Marx whatever way you like"
(p.97), as Badiou ascribes but little importance to the economy. Finally, iek regrets
that Badiou, by not taking seriously the Lacanian (death) drive, does not see that it is
pointless to reduce human beings to the status of mere animals or unsophisticated
hedonists, intent on maximizing their pleasures.

The fifth chapter focuses on science and religion. The ikian critique of Badiou
continues on the terrain of science. According to iek, science recognizes (contra
Badiou) the contingency of all the axioms derived from mathematics. Then Zizek
takes the side of Niels Bohr against Werner Heisenberg, asserting that quantum
mechanics is not just concerned with uncertainty of an epistemological order, but also,
in particular, the indeterminacy of an ontological order. Discussing religion, iek
expounds his thesis that one cannot be an atheist except through the Christian
experience. To be an atheist, it is not enough not to believe in God, it is also
necessary that there is nothing that believes on our behalf, and that our faith is in
nothing objectified. In other words, God, the Big Other, must Himself stop believing
that He exists. It is only when when Jesus, on the cross, cries out, "My God! Why hast
thou forsaken me? that God loses faith in himself. Before that, in the book of Job,
God recognized that He Himself was insane. And already in Judaism, the prohibition
of making an image of God points towards the belief that God does not exist outside
of the direct relationships we have with others (our neighbor). Christianity pushed this
belief further to its logical conclusion, even though the institutions of Christianity have
attempted to stifle the subversive force of this insight.

In the sixth chapter (which is relatively short), iek speaks of the strengths and
weaknesses he sees in the works of Deleuze and Derrida. As regards Deleuze, iek
values the books he wrote alone, including Logique du Sens,4 but criticises the books
he wrote with Flix Guattari. iek prefers the Deleuze of the sterility of sense to the
Deleuze of the productivity of sense. In relation to Derrida, iek is suspicious of the
mechanical side of Derridas analyses, and of his subjective position of a philosopher
who is too sure of himself. But iek appreciates Derridas concept of diffrance

because he considers it to be closely related both to Hegelian mastery5 and the


Freudian death drive.

In the subsequent chapter, iek and Tarby talk about politics. iek gives three
main reasons why he is Eurocentric: 1) The breakaway from the mythical universe
achieved by Ancient Greek philosophy; 2) the Christian religion; and 3) the French
Revolution. iek is concerned to convince us that the task of the Left is to press a
certain terror into the service of equality. Only this terror can open up a social space
where equality is one of the conceivable choices. And, according iek, it is precisely
when one takes upon oneself the negativity inherent to the death drive, that one can
obtain that equality.

Chapter eight is relatively short; iek talks about the recent history of
region in which lives: the Balkans. After telling us he does not know why he and his
Slovenian friends have chosen to focus on6 Lacan over all the other theorists who
make their mark on them in their youth, he gives a typically Lacanian explanation of
the problems in the Balkans: The Balkans have been caught in the Western dream,
and when we are caught in the act of desiring the other, were fucked.

The last two chapters focus on cinema. When it comes to his writings on
film, iek has the audacity to say that one must only ascribe importance to what he
has written on the cinema as an art, and as an art different from other arts. iek
therefore disparages what has written about cinema for the purposes of illustrating
some philosophical arguments, together with what he has written for the purposes of
mapping out the ideological coordinates of our time. iek appears particularly proud

to have shown that cinema, thanks mainly to particular camera moves, is the only art
that makes possible, without regard to the narrative content, the expression of
unconscious forms and circulation of libidinal (pre-ontological) objects.

In the last chapter, iek explains why there are more films than novels
about vampires, why the undead are not vampires, why the double8 horrifying with
German idealism and why he does not lets himself be fooled by werewolves. Finally,
he argues that consummate art8 is what subjectifies and gives a voice to an
impossible Real.

In this book, iek has presented his main ideas by comparing them to those of the
most influential French philosophers, without humouring them on account of their
friendship. However, this is not the first time he has been severely critical of his peers.
Rather, what specifically distinguishes this book is how iek sets out its ideas in a
simple and concise manner. And iek seems all the more outrageous for exposing
his ideas succinctly. This leads me to conclude that we can find a place "across the
Real"9 when we dare to express ourselves succinctly; by contrast, interminable
discussions themselves place themselves "athwart the Real;10 that is to say, they can
mask or repress this outrageous Real.

References
iek (2010), A travers le reel : Entretiens avec Fabien Tarby, Nouvelles Editions
Lignes, 221 pages.

Notes
1.

Other Side of Psychoanalysis.

2.

Also rendered in English as Encore. [Translators note].

3.

The Logic of Fantasy.

4.

The Logic of Sense.

5.

Relve.

6.

Privilgier. [Translators note].

7.

Sosie. [Translators note].

8.

Lart suprme.

9.

travers le rel. This and the following en travers du rel are a pun on the title

[Translators note].
[Translators note].

[Translators note].

[Translators note].

of the book under review.


10.

[Translators note].

[Translators note].

En travers du reel. The reader must bear in mind, in order to understand this

pun, that athwart and en travers de mean both across and obstructing/opposing,
while travers de merely means across, without the connotation of
obstructing/opposing. [Translators note].

You might also like