Lyotard - Can Thought Go On Without A Body (From Materialities of Communication)
Lyotard - Can Thought Go On Without A Body (From Materialities of Communication)
Lyotard - Can Thought Go On Without A Body (From Materialities of Communication)
COMMUNICATION
EDITED BY
William Whobrey
STANFORD,
CALIFORNIA
1994
'EAN-FRANOIS LYOTARD
Can Thought Go on
Without a Body?
He
You philosophers ask questions without answers, questions that
have to remain unanswered to deserve being called philosophical.
According to you answered questions are only technical matters.
That's what they were to begin with. They were mistaken for
philosophical questions. You turn to other questions that seem
completely impossible to answer: which by definition resist every
attempt at conquest by the understanding. Or what amounts to the
same thing: you declare that if the first questions were answered,
that's because they were badly formulated. And you grant your
selves the privilege of continuing to regard as unresolved, that is, as
well formulated, questions that technical science believes it an
swered but in truth only inadequately dealt with. For you solutions
are just illusions, failures to maintain the integrity due to being-or
some such thing. Long live patience. You'll hold out forever with
your incredulity. But don't be surprised if all the same, through
your irresolution, you end up wearing out your reader.
But that's not the question. While we talk, the sun is getting
older. It will explode in 4.5 billion years. It's just a little beyond the
halfway point of its expected lifetime. It's like a man in his early
forties with a life expectancy of eighty. With the sun's death your
insoluble questions will be done with too. It's possible they'll stay
unanswered right up to the end, flawlessly formulated, though
Thought Without
Body?
287
now both grounds for raising such questions as well as the place to
do this will no longer exist. You explain: it's impossible to think an
end, pure and simple, of anything at all, since the end's a limit and
to think it you have to be on both sides of that limit. So what's
finished or finite has to be perpetuated in our thought if it's to be
thought of as finished. Now this is true of limits belonging to
thought. But after the sun's death there won't be a thought to know
that its death took place.
That, in my view, is the sole serious question to face humanity
today. In comparison everything else seems insignificant. Wars,
conflicts, political tension, shifts in opinion, philosophical debates,
even passions-everything's dead already if this infinite reserve
from which you now draw energy to defer answers, if in short
thought as quest, dies out with the sun. Maybe death isn't the
word. But the inevitable explosion to come, the one that's always
forgotten in your intellectual ploys, can be seen in a certain way as
coming before the fact to render these ploys posthumous-make
them futile. I'm talking about what's X'd out of your writings
matter. Matter taken as an arrangement of energy created, de
stroyed, and re-created over and over again, endlessly. On the
corpuscular and/ or cosmic scale I mean. I am not talking about the
f.lllliliar, reassuring terrestrial world or the reasuring transcendent
immanence of thought to its objects, analogous to the way the eye
transcends what's visible or habitlls its situs. In 4.5 billion years there
,\"ill arrive the demise of your phenomenology and your utopian
politics, and there'll be no one there to toll the death knell or hear it.
It will be too late to understand that your passionate, endless
questioning always depended on a "life of the mind" that will have
been nothing else than a covert form of earthly life. A form of life
that was spiritual because human, human because earthly-com
ing from the earth of the most living of living things. Thought bor
rows a horizon and orientation, the limitless limit and the end
without end it assumes, from the corporeal, sensory, emotional,
and cognitive experience of a quite sophisticated but definitely
earthly existence-to which it's indebted as well.
With the disappearance of earth, thought will have stopped
leaving that disappearance absolutely unthought of It's the hori
zon itself that will be abolished and, with its disappearance, your
transcendence in immanence as well. If, as a limit, death really is
288
Jean-Franfois Lyotard
what escapes and is deferred and as a result what thought has to deal
with, right from the beginning-this death is still only the life of
our minds. But the death of the sun is a death of mind, because it is
the death of death as the life of the mind. There's no sublation or
deferral if nothing survives. This annihilation is totally different
from the one you harangue us about talking about "our" death, a
death that is part of the fate of living creatures who think. Annihila
tion in any case is too subjective. It will involve a change in the
condition of matter: that is, in the form that energies take. This
change is enough to render null and void your anticipation of a
world after the explosion. Political science-fiction novels depict the
cold desert of our human wrld after nuclear war. The solar explo
sion won't be due to human war. It won't leave behind it a devas
tated human world, dehumanized, but with nonetheless at least a
single survivor, someone to tell the story of what's left, write it
down. Dehumanized still implies human-a dead human, but con
ceivable: because dead in human terms, still capable of being sub
lated in thought. But in what remains after the solar explosion,
there won't be any humanness, there won't be living creatures,
there won't be intelligent, sensitive, sentient earthlings to bear
witness to it, since they and their earthly horizon will have been
consumed.
Assume that the ground, Husserl's
clouds of heat and matter. Considered as matter, the earth isn't at all
originary since it's subject to changes in its condition-change
from further away or closer, changes coming from matter and
energy and from the laws governing Earth's transformation. The
289
Ponty spoke of the chiasmus of the eye and the horizon, a fluid in
which mind floats. The solar explosion, the mere thought of that
explosion, should awaken you from this euphoria. Look here: you
try to think of the event in its
that" before any quiddity, don't you? Well, you'll grant that the
explosion of the sun is the
apres rnoi Ie
thc disaster. This and this alone is what's at stake today in technical
and scientific research in every field from dietetics, neurophysiol-
290
Jean-Fran(ois Lyotard
storage capacity for its memory that's greater than those of other
living things. Most of all: it's equipped with a symbolic system
that's both arbitrary (in semantics and syntax), letting it be less
dependent on an immediate environment, and also "recursive"
(Hofstadter), allowing it to take into account (above and beyond
raw data) the way it has of processing such data. That is, itself.
Hence, the way it has of processing as information its own rules j,
turn and of inferring other ways of processing information. A hu
man, in short, is a living organization that is not only complex but.
so to speak, replex. It can grasp itself as a medium (as in medicine)
or as an organ (as in goal-directed activity) or as an object (as in
thought-I mean aesthetic as well as speculative thought). It can
even abstract itself from itself and take into account only its rules oi
processing, as in logic and mathematics. The opposite limit of this
symbolic recursiveness resides in the necessity by which it is bound
(whatever its meta-level of operation) at the same time to maintain
regulations that guarantee its survival in any environment whatso
ever. Isn't that exactly what constitutes the basis of your transcen
dence in immanence? Now, until the present time, this environ
ment has been terrestrial. The survival of a thinking-organization
requires exchanges with that environment such that the human
Thought Without
Body?
291
hody can perpetuate itself there. This is equally true of the quintes
sential meta-function-philosophical thought. To think, at the very
least you have to breathe, eat, and so on. You are still under an
obligation to "earn a living."
The body might be considered the hardware of the complex
technical device that is human thought. If this body is not properly
functioning, the ever so complex operations, the meta-regulations
to the third or fourth power, the controlled deregulations of which
you philosophers are so fond, are impossible. Your philosophy of
the endless end, of immortal death, of interminable difference, of
the undecidable, is an expression, perhaps the expression par excel
['lice, of meta-regulation itself. It's as if it took itself into account as
meta. Which is all well and good. But don't forget-this faculty of
being able to change levels referentially derives solely from the
symbolic and recursive power of language. Now language is sim
ply the most complex form of the (living and dead) "memories"
that regulate all living things and make them technical objects
better adjusted to their surroundings than mechanical ensembles.
In other words your philosophy is possible only because the mate
rial ensemble called "man" is endowed with very sophisticated
software. But also, this software, human language, is dependent on
C0t1-
Jean-Fran(ois Lyotard
292
293
in it just as the eye does in the field of the visible. In France, this
analogy was already central to Wallon's work, for example, and
also to Merleau-Ponty's. It is "well known." Nonetheless it has to
be stressed that this analogy isn't extrinsic, but intrinsic. In its
procedures it doesn't only describe a thought analogous to an
experience of perception. It also describes a thought that proceeds
analogically and only analogically-not logically. A thought in
which therefore procedures of the type ''just as . . . so likewise . . . "
or "as if . . . then" or again "as p is to q, so r is to s" are privileged
compared to digital procedures of the type "if . . . then . . . " and "p
is not non-p." Now these are the paradoxical operations that con
stitute the experience of a body, of an "actual" or phenomenologi
cal body in its space-time continuum of sensibility and perception.
Which is why it's appropriate to take the body as model in the
manufacture and programming of artificial intelligence if it's in
tended that artificial intelligence not be limited to the ability to
reason logically.
294
Jean-Franfois Lyotard
It's obvious from this objection that what makes thought and
the body inseparable isn' t just that the latter is the indispensable
hardware for the former, a material prerequisite of its existence. It's
that each of them is analogous to the other in its relationship with
its respective (sensible, symbolic) environment: the relationship
being analogical in both cases. In this description there are convinc
ing grounds for not supporting the hypothesis (once suggested by
Hilary Putnam) of a principle of the "separability" of intelligence, a
principle through which he believed he could legitimate an attempt
to create artificial intelligence.
She
Now that's something to leave us satisfied as philosophers. At least
something to assuage a part of our anxiety. A field of perception has
limits, but these limits are always beyond reach. While a visual
object is presenting one side to the eye, there are always other sides,
still unseen. A direct, focused vision is always surrounded by a
curved area where visibility is held in reserve yet isn't absent.
This disjunction is inclusive. And I'm not speaking of a memory
brought into play by even the simplest sight. Continuing vision
preserves along with it what was seen an instant before from
another angle. It anticipates what will be seen shortly. These syn
theses result in identifications of objects, identifications that never
are completed, syntheses that a subsequent sighting can always
unsettle or undo. And the eye, in this experience, is indeed always
in search of a recognition, as the mind is of a complete description
of an object it is trying to think of: without, however, a viewer's
ever being able to say he recognizes an object perfectly since the
field of presentation is absolutely unique every time, and since
when vision actually sees, it can't ever forget that there's always
more to be seen once the object is "identified." Perceptual "recogni
tion" never satisfies the logical demand for complete description.
In any serious discussion of analogy it's this experience that IS
meant, this blur, this uncertainty, this faith in the inexhaustibility of
the perceivable, and not just a mode of transfer of the data onto
an inscription-surface not originally its own. Similarly, writing
plunges into the field of phrases, moving forward by means of
adumbrations, groping toward what it "means" and never un-
Thought Without
Body?
295
aware, when it stops, that it's only suspending its exploration for a
moment (a moment that. might last a lifetime) and that there re
mains, beyond the writing that has stopped, an infinity of words,
phrases, and meanings in a latent state, held in abeyance, with as
many things "to be said" as at the beginning. Real "analogy"
requires a thinking or representing machine to be
in its datajust as
the eye is in the visual field or writing is in language (in the broad
sense). It isn't enough for these machines to simulate the results of
vision or of writing fairly well. It's a matter (to use the attractively
appropriate locution) of "giving body" to the artificial thought of
which they are capable. And it's that body, both "natural" and
artificial, that will have to be carried far from earth before its
destruction if we want the thought that survives the solar explosion
to be something more than a poor binarized ghost of what it was
beforehand.
From this point of view we should indeed have grounds not to
give up on techno-science. I have no idea whether such a "pro
gram" is achievable. Is it even consistent to claim to be program
ming an experience that defies, if not programming, then at least
the program-as does the vision of the painter or writing? It's up to
you to give it a try. After all, the problem's an urgent one for you.
It's the problem of;l comprehension of ordinary language by your
machines. A problem you encounter especially in the area of termi
nlltlser interface. In that interface subsists the contact of your
artificial intelligence with the naive kind of intelligence borne by
so-called "natural" languages and immersed in them.
But another question bothers me. Is it really another question?
Thinking and suffering overlap. Words, phrases in the act of writ
ing, the latent nuances and timbres at the horizon of a painting or a
musical composition as it's being created (you've said this your
selves) all lend themselves to us for the occasion and yet slip
through our fingers. And even inscribed on a page or canvas, they
"say" something other than what we "meant" because they're
older than the present intent, overloaded with possibilities of
meaning-that is, connected with other words, phrases, shades of
meaning, timbres. By means of which precisely they constitute a
field, a "world," the "brave" human world you were speaking
ahout, but one that's probably more like an opaqueness of very
distant horizons that exist only so that we'll "brave" them. If
296
Jean-Fran{ois Lyotard
habitus, or arrange
ments of the body. It's at this cost, said Glenn and Andreas (and you
can imagine how '1uickly I agreed, helped out by Dogen, Diderot,
and Kleist), that a brush encounters the "right" shapes, that a voice
and a theatrical gesture are endowed with the "right" tone and
look. This soliciting of emptiness, this evacuation-very much
the opposite of overweening, selective, identificatory activity
doesn't take place without some suffering. I won't claim that the
grace Kleist talked about (a grace of stroke, tone, or volume) has to
be merited: that would be presumptuous of me. But it has to be
called forth, evoked. The body and the mind have to be free of
burdens for grace to touch us. That doesn't happen without suffer
ing. An enjoyment of what we possessed is now lost.
Here again, you will note, there's a necessity for physical expe
rience and a recourse to exemplary cases of bodily ascesis to under
stand and make understood a type of emptying of the mind, an
emptying that is required if the mind is to think. This obviously ha
nothing to do with
mutatis mutandis
Durcharbeitung . In which-though I won't labor the
point-the pain and the cost of the work of thought can be seen.
This kind of thinking has little to do with combining symbols in
accordance with a set of rules. Even though the act of combining,
as it seeks out and waits for its rule, can have quite a lot to do with
thought.
Thought Without
Body?
297
298
Jean-Fran{ois Lyotard
'
299
300
Jean-Fran{ois Lyotard
analogoll