Essay 1 Autopoeisis
Essay 1 Autopoeisis
Essay 1 Autopoeisis
Autopoiesis and a
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
CREA, CNRSEcole Polytechnique,
Paris, France.
Biology of Intentionality
1.1
Francisco J. Varela
Introduction
As everybody here knows, autopoiesis is a neologism, introduced in 1971 by H. Maturana and myself to designate the organization of a minimal living
system. The term became emblematic of a view of
the relation between an organism and its medium,
where its self constituting and autonomous aspects
are put at the center of the stage. From 1971, until
now much has happened to reinforce this perspective. Some of the developments have to do with the
notion of autopoiesis itself in relation to the cellular
organization and the origin of life. Much more has
to do with the autonomy and self-organizing qualities of the organism in relation with its cognitive
activity. Thus in contrast to the dominant cognitivist, symbol-processing views of the 70s today we
witness in cognitive science a renaissance of the concern for the embeddedness of the cognitive agent,
natural or artificial. This comes up in various labels
as nouvelle-AI (Brooks 1991c), the symbol grounding problem (Harnad 1991), autonomous agents in
artificial life (Varela & Bourgine 1992), or situated
functionality (Agree 1988), to cite just a few selfexplanatory labels used recently.
Any of these developments could merit a full talk;
obviously I cannot do that here. My intention
rather, profiting from the position of opening this
gathering, is to try to indicate some fundamental
or foundational issues of the relation between autopoiesis and perception. Whence the title of my
talk: a biology of intentionality. Since the crisis of
classical cognitive science has thrown open the issue
of intentionality, in my eyes autopoiesis provides a
natural entry into a view of intentionalty that is
seminal in answering the major obstacles that have
been addressed recently. Ill came back to that at
the end. Let me begin at the beginning.
1.2
1.2.1
Cognition and
Minimal Living Systems
Autopoiesis as the
skeletal bio-logic
The bacterial cell is the simplest of living systems because it possesses the capacity to produce,
through a network of chemical processes, all the
chemical components which lead to the constitution
of a distinct, bounded unit. To avoid being trivial, the attribute living in the foregoing description
must address the process that allows such constitution, not the materialities that go into it, or an
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
1.2.2
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
points here is that we gain by seeing the continuity between this fundamental level of self and the
other regional selves, including the neural and linguistic where we would not hesitate to use the word
cognitive. I suppose others would prefer to introduce the word information instead. Well, there
are reasons why I believe this even more problematic. Although it is clear that we describe an X
that perturbs from the organisms exteriority, X is
not information. In fact, for the organism only is
a that, a something, a basic stuff to in-form from
its own perspective. In physical terms there is stuff,
but it is for nobody. Once there is bodyeven in
this minimal formit becomes in-formed for a self,
in the reciprocal dialectics I have just explicated.
Such in-formation is never a phantom signification
or information bits, waiting to be harvested by a
system. It is a presentation, an occasion for coupling, and it is in this entre-deux that signification
arises (Varela 1979, 1988; Castoriadis 1987).
Thus the term cognitive has two constitutive dimensions: first its coupling dimension, that is, a link
with its environment allowing for its continuity as
individual entity; secondby stretching language, I
admitits imaginary dimension, that is, the surplus
of significance a physical interaction acquires due to
the perspective provided by the global action of the
organism.
1.3
Perception-action and
basic neuro-logic
1.3.1
In the previous Section, I have presented the fundamental interlock between identity and cognition
as it appears for a minimal organism. In this Section I want to show how the more traditional level
of cognitive properties, involving the brains of multicellular animals, is in some important sense the
continuation of the very same basic process.
The shift from minimal cellularity to organism
with nervous system is swift, and skips the complexity of the various manners in which multicellular organisms arise and evolve (Margulis & Schwartz
1988; Buss 1987; Bonner 1988). This is a transition
in units of selection, and one that implicates the somatic balance of differentiated populations of cells
in an adult organism, as well as crafty development
pathways to establish a bodily structure. As Buss
has stated recently: The evolution of development
is the generation of a somatic ecology that mediates
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
mal molecular self. I am claiming that contemporary neuroscienceslike cell biology for the case of
the living organizationgives enough elements to
conceive of the basic organization for a cognitive
self in terms of the operational (not interactional!)
closure of the nervous system (Maturana & Varela
1980; Varela 1979). I speak of closure to highlight the self-referential quality of the interneuron
network and of the perceptuo-motor surfaces whose
correlations it subserves. The qualification operational emphasizes that closure is used in its mathematical sense of recursivity, and not in the sense
of closedness or isolation from interaction, which
would be, of course, nonsense. More specifically,
the nervous system is organized by the operational
closure of a network of reciprocally related modular
sub-networks giving rise to ensembles of coherent
activity such that:
(i) they continuously mediate invariant patterns of
sensory-motor correlation of the sensory and effector surfaces;
(ii) give rise to a behavior for the total organism
as a mobile unit in space.
The operational closure of the nervous system
then brings forth a specific mode of coherence, which
is embedded in the organism. This coherence is a
cognitive self : a unit of perception/motion in space,
sensory-motor invariances mediated through the interneuron network. The passage to cognition happens at the level of a behavioral entity, and not, as
in the basic cellular self, as a spatially bounded entity. The key in this cognitive process is the nervous
system through its neuro-logic. In other words the
cognitive self is the manner in which the organism,
through its own self-produced activity, becomes a
distinct entity in space, but always coupled to its
corresponding environment from which it remains
nevertheless distinct. A distinct coherent self which,
by the very same process of constituting itself, configures an external world of perception and action.
1.3.2
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
mentation of some high-level algorithm. Neural networks even in their fine detail are not like a machine
language, since there is simply no transition between
such elemental operational atoms with a semantics
and the larger emergent level where behavior occurs. If there were, the classical computer wisdom
would immediately apply: ignore the hardware since
it adds nothing of significance to the actual computation (other than constraints of time and space). In
contrast, in distributed, network models these details are precisely what makes a global effect possible, and why they mark a sharp break with tradition
in AI. Naturally this reinforces the parallel conclusions that apply to natural neural networks in the
brain, as we discussed before.
I have raised this point to caution the reader
against the force of many years of dominance of
computationalism, and the consequent tendency to
identify the cognitive self with some computer program or high level computational description. This
will not do. The cognitive self is its own implementation: its history and its action are of one piece.
Now this demands that we clarify now the second
aspect of the self to be addressed: its mode of relation with the environment.
1.3.3
11
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
However this coupling is possible only if the encounters are embraced from the perspective of the system
itself. This amounts, quite specifically, to elaborating a surplus signification relative to this perspective. Whatever is encountered must be valued one
way or anotherlike, dislike, ignoreand acted on
some way or anotherattraction, rejection, neutrality. This basic assessment is inseparable from the
way in which the coupling event encounters a functioning perceptuo-motor unit, and it gives rise to
an intention (I am tempted to say desire), that
unique quality of living cognition (Dennett 1987).
Phrased in other terms, the nature of the environment for a cognitive self acquires a curious status:
it is that which lends itself (es lehnt sich an. . . ) to
a surplus of significance. Like jazz improvisation,
environment provides the excuse for the neural
music from the perspective of the cognitive system involved. At the same time, the organism cannot live without this constant coupling and the constantly emerging regularities; without the possibility
of coupled activity the system would become a mere
solipsistic ghost.
For instance, light and reflectance (among many
other macrophysical parameters such as edges and
textures, but let us simplify for the arguments
sake), lend themselves to a wide variety of color
spaces, depending on the nervous system involved
in that encounter. During their respective evolutionary paths, teleost fishes, birds, mammals, and
insects have brought forth various different color
spaces not only with quite distinct behavioral significance, but with different dimensionalities so that
it is not a matter of more or less resolution of colors (Thompson et al. 1992). Color is demonstrably not a property that is to be recovered from
the environmental information in some unique
way. Color is a dimension that shows up only in
the phylogenetic dialogue between an environment
and the history of an active autonomous self which
partly defines what counts as an environment. Light
and reflectances provide a mode of coupling, a perturbation which triggers, which gives an occasion
for the enormous in-formative capacity of neural
networks for constituting sensori-motor correlations
and hence to put into action their capacity for imagining and presenting. It is only after all this has
happened, after a mode of coupling becomes regular and repetitive, like colors in oursand others
worlds, that we observers, for ease of language, say
color corresponds to or represents an aspect of the
world.
A dramatic recent example of this surplus significance and the dazzling performance of the brain as
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
Brooks (1987, p. 1)
When the synthesis of intelligent behavior is approached in such an incremental manner, with strict
adherence to the sensory-motor viability of an agent,
the notion that the world is a source of information
to be represented simply disappears. The autonomy of the cognitive self comes fully in focus. Thus
in Brookss proposal his minimal creatures join together various activities through a rule of cohabitation between them. This is homologous to an
evolutionary pathway through which modular subnetworks intertwined with each other in the brain.
The expected result are more truly intelligent autonomous sense-giving devices, rather than brittle
informational processors which depend on a pregiven environment or an optimal plan.
It is interesting to note that in this paper Brooks
also traces the origin of what he describes as the
deception of AI to the tendency in AI (and in
the rest of cognitive science as well) to abstraction,
i.e., for factoring out situated perception and motor
skills. As I have argued here (and as Brooks argues
for his own reasons), such abstraction misses the
essence of cognitive intelligence, which resides only
in its embodiment. It is as if one could separate
cognitive problems in two parts: that which can be
solved through abstraction and that which cannot
be. The second is typically perception-action and
motor skills of agents in unspecified environments.
When approached from this self-situated perspective there is no place where perception could deliver a representation of the world in the traditional
sense. The world shows up through the enactment
of the perceptuo-motor regularities. Just as there
is no central representation there is no central system. Each activity layer connects perception to action directly. It is only the observer of the Creature
who imputes a central representation or central control. The creature itself has none: it is a collection
of competing behaviors. Out of the local chaos of
their interactions there emerges, in the eye of the
observer, a coherent pattern of behavior (Brooks
1986, p. 11).
To conclude, the two main points that I have been
trying to bring into full view in this Section devoted to the cognitive self are as follows. First, I
have tried to spell out the nature of its identity as a
body in motion-and-space through the operational
1.4
Organisms double
dialectics
13
Biology of Intentionality
Francisco J. Varela
These two terms are truly in a relation of codefinition. On the one hand the global level cannot exist without the network level since it comes
forth through it. On the other hand the dynamical
level cannot not exist and operate as such without
it being contained and lodged into an encompassing
unity which makes it possible.
Second, a dialectics of knowledge establishes a
world of cognitive significance for this identity. This
can only arise from the perspective provided by this
identity, which adds a surplus of significance to the
interactions of the environment proper to the constituting parts.
The key point, then, is that the organism brings
forth and specifies its own domain of problems
and actions to be solved; this cognitive domain
Acknowledgments
The financial support of CNRS, Fondation de France
(Chaire Scientifique) and the Prince Trust Fund is
gratefully acknowledged.
14