Ignorantia Juris Non Excusat
Ignorantia Juris Non Excusat
Ignorantia Juris Non Excusat
- A
STUDY OF THE LAW RELATING TO MISTAKES
Ankit Majmudar*
Nandan Kamath*
INTRODUCTION
The functions of criminal law are two fold in nature. Primarily, it aims at
the imposition of corrective measures to prevent the occurrence of criminal acts.
Subsidiarily it aims at correction in relation to the mental state of the person or
persons responsible for the criminal act. If the aim of criminal law were only the
former, it would serve to punish the act itself, irrespective of whether it was done
unconsciously, negligently or intentionally. However, the law aims at punishing
those respon~ible for the act, and responsibility appears to imply a certain mental
state - in this context, a guilty mind. The maxim "actus non fadt reum nisi
mensit rea" has acquired an imposing presence in criminal jurisprudence. It is
by virtue of this maxim that the idea of mistake as an excuse has come to be
accepted.
The general principle is that a person is presumed to know and intend the
natural consequences of his act and is, therefore, held responsible for it. However,
there are certain exceptions to this general rule, wherein a person may be excused
of his crime.
The absence of mens rea is one such excuse. The excuse of mistake is based
on the ground that a person who is mistaken or ignorant about the existence of a
fact cannot form the requisite intention to constitute the crime and is therefore
not responsible in law for his deeds. This has been incorporated in the common
law principle "ignorantia facit doth excusat, ignorantia juris non excusat"
(ignorance of fact excuses, ignorance of law does not excuse).1
The long application of this principle is apparent from the seventeenth
century case of R. v. Levett,2 where an accused was acquitted on this ground.
After this, there has been considerable development in the law relating to mistake,
in spite of which incoherence continues regarding the exact scope of this defence.
Added to this, the jurisprudence and statutes behind this defence continue to
vary from country to country, making it vital to examine the comparative position
in various countries. The principal issues that surround the question of mistake
as a defence relate to the presence of any additional requirements or qualifications
*
III Year B.A., LL.B. (Hons.), National Law School of India University
79 ER 1064, where the accused killed a woman, who was hiding behind a curtain in his house,
mistakenl y believing her to be a burglar.
Vol. 10]
11
Juris Excuse?
absence
of
UNDER INDIAN
LAW
The defence of mistake in Indian law falls under the category of general
exceptions to criminal liability in the Indian Penal Code. Specifically, it is
incorporated in Ss. 76-79 of the Code. The justification for exemption on the
ground of mistake of fact, as mentioned earlier, is the principle that such a mistake
would negative the requisite intention. Thus, a bona fide belief of the existence
of facts which, if true, would have made the act innocent in law, is an excuse.
However, mistake of law is not a defence, because every man is presumed to
know the law and is to be held responsible in case of its breach.3
Thus, S.76 deals with persons who consider themselves bound to perform
certain acts, and as long as this belief is founded on a mistake of fact and not a
mistake of law, such an act is not an offence. S.79 deals with acts that a person
considers himself justified in performing because of a mistake of fact and not a
mistake of law.4 The distinction between the two sections lies in the difference
between legal compulsion and legal justification.
Courts in India, following
English decisions, have acknowledged mistake of fact as a defence in the c.,se of
bigamy and other statutory offences.5 Further, in Keso Sahu v. Saligram,6 it was
held that to bring a case under S. 79, it was sufficient to show to a reasonable
extent that the belief as to the fact was in good faith.
The defence of mistake of law is of no value in India. This is made clear by
its specific exclusion in S.76 as well as S.79. The justification for this is that the
3
4
State of Maharashtra
v.
In Raj Kapoorv. Laxman (1980) 2 SCC 175, it was held that "if the act was done by one who by
reason of a mistake of fact in good faith believes himself to be justified by law in doing it, then the
exception operates, and the bona fide belief, although mistaken, eliminates the~ulpability. If the
offender can irrefutably establish that he entertained a mistake of fact and in good faith believed
that he was justified by law in committing the act, then the weapon of S.79 demolishes the
prosecution."
5 In Kohu M.K. [smail v. Mohammed K. Umma, AIR 1959 Ker 151, the accused was charged with
bigamy under S.494 of the IPC for contracting a second marriage during the continuanc,e of the first
marriage. She was acquitted on the grounds that she honestly and on reasonable grounds believed
that she had obtained a divorce from the complainant, although the divorce was unauthorised.
6 1977 Cri LJ 1725 (Ori).
12
The Student Advocate
[1998
OF MISTAKE
Law Commission of India, 42nd Report, 1971, pp. 83-85. Thus in State of Maharashtra v. M.l/.
George. AIR 1965 SC 722, the Supreme Court, while refusing to accept a plea of ignorance of a
Reserve Bank notification, the Court held that for an Indian law to operate and be effective within
the
the country.
territory of India, it is not necessary that it should either be published, or be made known outside
<}
In l/arbhajan Singh v. State of Punjab, AIR 1961 Punj 215. the court held that "under S. 105, if an
accused person claims the benefit of exceptions, the burden of proving his plea that his case falls
under the exceptions lies on the accused. Where the burden of an issue lies upon the accused, he is
not required to discharge that burden by leading evidence to prove his case beyond a reasonable
preponderance
probabilities.
doubt ... In suchof cases,
law treats the onus as discharged if the accused succeeds in proving a
Hidayatullah
and Manohar
10 Gaya Din, (1934) 9 Luck 517. Again, in Damodar Shenoi v. Public Prosecutor, 1989 Cri LJ
II Id.
2398,
it was held that the accused would also have to show that there was no malice on his part.
Vol. 10]
13
mistakes that result out of a misconception of facts as they exist, and those because
of a mistake in the existing legal position. However, a more appropriate
classification has been made by George Fletcher,13 who classifies them on the
basis of legal outcomes. Thus, by his method, there are three kinds of mistakes:
Mistakes barring liability altogether.14
Mistakes barring liability only if the making of the mistake is free from
culpability. 15
The mistake might have no effect on the outcome of the case.16
It is in third category that, at present, mistakes of law would appear to fall.
Mens rea can be loosely translated as guilty mindY It can occur in a number
of forms, such as intention, knowledge, negligence, etc. Any offence, if it is not
a strict liability offence, requires a certain mental element. This mental element
forms the mens rea of the offence. The evidence of a genuine mistake of fact,
therefore, which, if the facts existed as the offender believed them to, would
make his act innocent, would, on principle, negative the mens rea and result in
acquittal.18 A mistake of fact which negates an intention to cause a consequence
prohibited by law is a defence because a person must intend to cause all the
consequences which he has in fact caused if he is to be held criminally responsible
for causing these consequences.19 As regards a mistake of law, it is submitted
that the present position not allowing it as a defence requires reconsideration.
The same principle applies as in the case of mistake of fact, i.e. the person did
not intend the consequences to occur, in terms of the fact that he did not wish to
breach the law. It is therefore submitted that at least a reasonable mistake of law
should be allowed as a defence.
In common law, the law in this regard has been laid down by the decision
of D.P.P. v. Morgan,2 which made it clear that where the offence required
intention or recklessness as part of its ingredients, a mistake of fact which
13 Fletcher,
Rethinking
14 The first bases itself on the presumption that every offence requires a certainmellS rea. TIllis in the
Indian context, murder requires an intention to cause death. If there exist a mistake which obviates
such intention, a person cannot be punished for it.
15 In tbe second category, would fallmistakes such as those, which exempt the person only if they are
reasonable. Thus, if we consider S. 304A of the IPC, it would require the accused to have made a
mistake, which does not seem to be negligent. Only then can he claim exemption from culpability.
16 As regards the third kind of mistake, this kind has no exculpatory
defence arises. whether the mistake is reasonable or not.
176(1972-73).
18 Crim LQ 78 (1975-76).
of a
14
[1998
precludes both states of mind will excuse, irrespective of whether tbe mistake is
reasonable or not.
As regards mistake of law, it is submitted that here it would be appropriate
to use reasonableness as a Criterion. Thus, a person who had used all reasonable
means to ascertain the law, and had still remained under a misconception, is
certainly less culpable than an offender who, without any semblance of care,
perfonns actions without ascertaining their legality. Such a limited use of mistake
of law would serve the purpose. As regards the lndian law, tbe position reflected
in the IPC (that of requiring mistakes to be perfonned in good faith) is ideal.
This enables a compromise between reasonableness and reckless mistakes.
DISTINCTIONS
BETWEEN
MISTAKES
Considerable controversy bas, of late, erupted over this area. The distinction
between mistakes of fact and law lie primarily in their capacity as defences; As a
result, tbere are often attempts to project a certain mistake as one of fact and not
of law.21 In Thomas v. The King,22 it was held that "a mistake as to the existence
of a compound event consisting of law and fact is in general one of fact and not
one of law". This is also supported by Glanville Williams.23 However, in R. v.
Cunningham,22a it was held that an accused who speeds cannot claim a defence
of having misread the speed limit sign, as this was a mistake of law. It is submitted
that this decision goes against the views expressed earlier.
The solution to this quandary lies in allowing a reasonable mistake of law
as a defence. This would remove the necessity of distinguishing between mistakes
of fact and law, for, in both the cases, if the mistake is reasonable, the defence
exists. In tbe alternative, a much wider interpretation must be given to mistakes
of fact so as to incorporate cases of mixed mistakes.
THE COMPARATIVE
POSITIONS
ABROAD
Common lAw
The land mark decision of D.P.P. v. Morgan24 settled the law in tbis regard.
A mistake, whether reasonable or not, will excuse criminal liability if it precludes
the requisite state of mind. In case the law requires negligence alone, then only
21
Thus, in R v. Prue, R v. Basil, (1979) 46 CCC (2ed) 257, the court held that lack of knowledge as
to the suspension of licenses constituted a defence to the charge, mens rea being an essential part of
the offence. The majority held the mistake to be one of fact.
22
22a[1957]
2 All ER 412.
23
Glanville Williams, Criminal Law - The Second Part 568 (1961), where the author states that if a
mistake contains any element of mistake of fact, then it must be governed by the rules as to mistake
of fact and is none the Jess a defence on that ground because accompanied by an interwoven mistake
oflaw.
24
Vol. 10]
15
16
[1998
clear that the factor that removes mens rea is not merely the absence of knowledge
of facts, but a mistaken belief which precludes the very presence of such a mental
element; Le., it is a positive affirmation of the absence of mens rea. Proudman
introduced a further aspect regarding mistake in the context of strict liability
offences. "A statute which appears to impose strict responsibility may nevertheless
be understood as allowing the defence that the accused held an honest and
reasonable belief in the existence of circumstances that would make innocent the
act with which he or she was charged."
In other words, mistake of fact has been recognised as a defence in even
strict liability cases. It is submitted that this is the correct position. The presence
of a mistake of fact negates the question of the accused intending to commit the
act mentioned in the statute. Therefore, such an interpretation is in conformity
with the rationale behind strict liability.
MISTAKE
AND STRICT
LIABILITY
Strict liability crimes have been defined33 as crimes which do not require
intention, recklessness or even negli~ence as to one or more elements in the
offences. Thus in regard to a certain element in the actus reus, no mens rea need
be proved.34 If a certain element of an offence is described as falling within the
ambit of strict liability, a reasonable mistake as to that particular fact is not a
defence. A mistake as to other circumstances may well allow a defence. This was
illustrated in R. v. Prince,35 where the accused was convicted under s.20 of the
Sexual Offences Act, 1956, although he had made a reasonable mistake about
the age of the girl he was taking. However, a substantial mental element was
required - this was demonstrated when the majority stated that the accused must
have intended to take the girl out of possession of the guardian - L e., the mental
element of intent. If a mistake had been made as to that particular element, it
would have served as a defence.
Thus, an offence of strict liability only partially does away with the mental
element. Again, in State of Maharashtra v. M.H. George,36 the Supreme Court
stated that the accused was guilty because he intended to bring a particular item
into India.
One of the prominent arguments brought forward by some authorities37
regarding the justification for dismissal of mistake as a defence in strict liability
offences, is that wrongdoers take the risk of their act turning out worse then they
Vol. 10]
Juris Excuse?
17
expect. Thus, in U.S. v. Feola,38 the Court reasoned that an offender takes the
victim as he finds him and is correspondingly liable, even if circumstances of
which he was ignorant, make his act more serious than he intended. In Prince,
Bramwell, J, stated that the accused had committed a wrong by taking a girl of
such tender years out of the possession of her father. The trouble with this
argument is that it ignores the requirement of proportionality of punishment. Its
application would cause a person who commits a statutory offence with full mens
rea to be punished as much as one who by virtue of a mistake of fact committed
a magnified offence, although his intent might have been to commit a much
smaller offence.
STRICT
LIABILITY
AND MISTAKES
OF LAW
It is now well settled that ignorance of the law is not an excuse. As a result,
there is occasioned an occurrence of strict liability, in that whenever there is a
mistake as to law, regardless of culpability, the offender is punished. The issue
was examined in Hopkins v. State39 where a person was convicted for an offence
although he had been advised by the Attorney General that his actions did not
constitute an offence. The question is wheth~r it is just to convict a person who
acts reasonably and yet suffers from a mistake of law. Maintaining a policy that
every person is presumed to know the law, may be appropriate for natural offences
like murder, rape, etc. but with regard to areas where laws are complex and
subject to change such a presumption would not be just.
It has been argued40 that in the absence of the presumption, ignorance of
the law '!Vouldbe encouraged and it is in the larger interests of justice must be
sacrificed. Such an argument, however, detracts from the principle of not
punishing any innocent person, even if guilty ones may escape. The utilitarian
principle advocated by Justice Holmes would go against this. Moreover, these
arguments ignore the fact that no culpability can be attached to a person who has
made a reasonable mistake of law. Law seeks to punish those who are accountable
for their offences but in the case of a person who has made a reasonable mistake
of law, the person can no longer be held liable.
In view of the above, it is submitted that the imposition of strict liability, in
the context of mistake of law, especially those which are reasonable, is not
justified.
MISTAKE
INDUCED
18
(1998
Nancy Kaster, Mistake of Law and the Defence of Officially Induced Error 28 Crim LQ 308
(1985-86).
42
43
44
(1984) 43 CR (3d) 39. The court laid down the following conditions: The actor must advert to his
legal position; The actor must seek advice from an offici?l; The official must be one who is in volved
in the administration of the law in question; The official must give erroneous advice; The erroneous
advice must be apparently reasonable; The error of law must arise out of the erroneous advice; The
actor must act in good faith and without reason to believe that the advice is erroneous; The actor's
error of law must be apparently reasonable; The actor must, while seeking advice, act in good faith
and take reasonable care to give accurate information to the official whose advice he solicits.
45
46
A.J.L. Ashworth,
Vol.
to]
Juris Excuse?
19
behaved perfectly and in accordance with rules. Punishment in these cases would
be pointless and against all principles of justice.
CONCLUSION
It is clear from the above discussion, that the present jurisprudence relating
to mistake tends to give a great deal more importance to a mistake of fact than to
a mistake of law. This is to the extent that a mistake of fact, whether reasonable
or not, acts as an excuse, while a mistake of law does not amount to one under
any circumstances. While the rationale behind this seems to be, simply, that
every man is expected to know the law, it is submitted that such an assumption is
too broad. The reason for which mistake as a defence is simply that it does away
with the mens rea necessary for the offence. However, it is submitted that the
same is applicable to a mistake of law as well. There too, the offender does not
intend to commit the offence. The maxim "ignorantia juris non excusat" should
not operate when the person does not even know that his actions constitute an
offence.
No doubt, doing away entirely with the ongoing presumption of every man
knowing the law would act as an incentive to develop ignorance; however, if a
person has used all possible means to ascertain the law, and still operates under
a mistake of law, it would be manifest injustice to punish him. He cannot be held
responsible for not knowing the law. It is in these cases that mistake of law must
operate as a defence. If an unreasonable mistake of fact is accepted as a defence,
it is implicit that the person is being excused for his stupidity and/or negligence.
In the case of a reasonable mistake of law, a person has fulfilled the criteria
demanded by law, i.e. he has behaved like a reasonable man. Nor does he have
any culpable mental element. It is submitted that the focus must always be whether
the mental element of the accused corresponds to the mental element envisaged
by the offence. If it matches, as must the actus reus, then no doubt he is liable,
and must be punished, But if it does not, then irrespective of whether it is a
mistake of fact or law, it must exonerate the accused.
An unreasonable mistake of law, however, need not be an excuse. This is
not because the guilty mind is present, but because, if a person is reckless or
negligent in determining what the law is, he cannot claim this as an excuse to
commit the crime.
In conclusion, therefore, the recommended position is as follows. In the
Indian context, any mistake of fact, in order to operate as an exculpation, must
conform to the requirement of good faith. Mistakes of law, however, must be
allowed as a defence only if reasonable. The above arrangement, it is submitted,
would best serve the ends of justice.