Castoriadis On Insignificance Dialogues
Castoriadis On Insignificance Dialogues
Castoriadis On Insignificance Dialogues
POSTSCRIPT ON
INSIGNIFICANCE
Dialogues with Cornelius
Castoriadis
Cornelius Castoriadis
2010032003
Contents
Acknowledgments
vii
Editors Introduction
ix
22
25
44
58
74
93
108
Index
111
vi
Acknowledgments
We would like to express our deep gratitude to all of those who have
contributed directly or indirectly to this project. First of all, we would
like to thank the Department of Philosophy at Villanova University,
and in particular the chair, John Carvalho, and the director of
graduate studies, Walter Brogan. We greatly appreciate the excellent
working conditions that allowed us to complete this project. We
would also like to thank Walter Brogan more specically for his role
as the editor of Epoch, the journal that accepted to publish our translation of the interview, No God, No Caesar, No Tribune! . . .
This book owes a special debt to Guillaume Zorgbibe, the director of
ditions du Sandre, and Pierre-Antoine Chardel, the director of the
book series Bibliothque de philosophie contemporaine. We would
like to thank the latter for bringing to our attention the interview entitled Breaking the Closure, which was originally published in one of
the books in his series: Cornelius Castoriadis: Rinventer lautonomie, ed.
Blaise Bachofen, Sion Elbaz, and Nicolas Poirier (Paris: ditions
du Sandre, 2008, 27389). We would like to express our sincere
gratitude to Guillaume Zorgbibe for granting us the translation rights.
We would also like to thank all of the friends and colleagues who
provided feedback on the editors introduction. It is a daunting task to
try to come to terms with the major facets of Castoriadis writings in
only a few pages, and we greatly appreciate the work of all of those
who took the time to read it. Arnaud Toms deserves particular
mention for his insightful comments and critical feedback, as well as
Suzi Adams, Nicolas Poirier, and Ingerid Straume.
Finally, this book would not have been possible without the diligent
work and support of the editorial staff at Continuum. We would like
vii
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
viii
Editors Introduction
Eros of Inquiry: An Aperu of Castoriadis
Life and Work
By Gabriel Rockhill
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
by four engaging discussions with a poet (Octavio Paz), a psychoanalyst (Jean-Luc Donnet), a biologist (Francisco Varela), a mathematician (Alain Connes), and a philosopher (Robert Legros).14 These
dialogues with representatives of so many different elds produce
far-reaching discussions that serve to introduce the broad and deep
concerns of a mode of critical thinking whose passion for knowledge
could not be reigned in by preestablished categories. In order to
introduce these discussions, I would like to provide a brief aperu of
Castoriadis key philosophical and ontological claims before examining, with a critical eye, the primary facets of his work discussed in
the dialogues: politics, art, psychoanalysis, and the philosophy of
science.15
HISTORICAL ONTOLOGY
Let us begin with one of Castoriadis most general claims: being is
creation.16 As he explains in Figures of the Thinkable, creation means,
above all, discontinuity, emergence of the radically new and stratication of what exists.17 Rather than the perpetual repetition of the
same fundamental elements or structures, being attests to the appearance of the unprecedented. This is, in part, because being is temporal,
or ratherin Castoriadis dauntless formulationbeing is time (and
not in the horizon of time).18 In short, creation, being, time go
together: being means to-be [tre signie -tre], time and creation
require one another.19
The imaginary and the imagination, Castoriadis writes, are the
mode of being that this vis formandi of Being in general takes in this
offspring of overall Being-being [ltre-tant global] that is humanity.20
The imaginary and the imagination are not simply reproductive or
combinatory faculties. The imaginary is an incessant and essentially
undetermined (social-historical and psychical) creation of gures/
forms/images, and the imagination is the capacity to give rise [faire
surgir] to something that is not the real. 21 Castoriadis tends to use
the vocabulary of the imagination to refer to the creative capacity of
the psyche, which he describes more specically as a radical imagination because it is neither determined nor reproductive but is
xiii
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
actually capable of producing reality. The terminology of the imaginary is commonly invoked to refer to the social imaginary and the
creative capacity of the anonymous collective.22 Castoriadis uses
these two poles of the vis formandi to dismantle the simplistic
opposition between individual and society, thereby demonstrating
that individuals are, and must be, social: There is no human
individual. There is a psyche that is socialized and, in this socialization, in the nal result, there is almost nothing individual in the true
sense of the term.23 Moreover, since society only exists qua
self-alteration, Castoriadis introduces the notion of the socialhistoricaldened as the self-creation [autocration] of society as
such and of the historical eld as suchto emphasize the extent to
which society and history are consubstantial in the creative production of social institutions:
The social makes itself and can only make itself as history; the
social makes itself as temporality; and it makes itself in every
instance as a specic mode of actual temporality, it establishes itself
[sinstitue] implicitly as a singular quality of temporality. [. . .] The
historical is this very thingthe self-alteration of this specic mode
of coexistence that is the social, and is nothing apart from this.
The historical makes itself and can only make itself as social;
the historical is, in an exemplary and pre-eminent manner,
the emergence of the institution and the emergence of another
institution [une autre institution].24
Castoriadis further divides the social imaginary into the instituting
social imaginary and the instituted social imaginary. The former refers
to the creation of social imaginary signications by the anonymous
collective and, more generally, the social-historical eld. Once these
are created, they solidify into the instituted social imaginary, which
guarantees the continuation of society and the perpetuation of
its forms. Every society is self-instituted, for Castoriadis, but most
societies attempt to guarantee their own proper institution by
instituting an extra-social origin of the social order itself. There
are two important ramications of this position. On the one hand,
it means that history is understood as creation and is therefore
undetermined (which does not mean that it is unconditioned):
xiv
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
xv
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
are not legally barred from participating in what the Greeks called
the ecclesia, the latter is almost exclusively dominated by private
interests:
On the factual level the essential features of public affairs are still
the private affair of various groups and clans that share effective
power, decisions are made behind closed doors, the little that is
brought onto the public stage is masked, prefabricated, and belated
to the point of irrelevancy.34
In short, the autonomous political project of democracy, as it was
once understood, has been gutted of its true content, leaving only the
abject carcass of pseudodemocratic oligarchy.
The demise of the project of autonomy at a political level is closely
tied to an overall crisis in social imaginary signications, that is, the
signications that determine the prevailing representations, affects,
and intentions of a society. The capitalist imaginary of unlimited
expansion of production and consumption has become the dominant,
and nearly exclusive, imaginary signication of contemporary society.35
The consumer, who is content to cast votes on the political marketplace every few years, has more or less entirely replaced the citizen,
once dened by Aristotle as one who shares in governing and being
governed.36 The unlimited world of endless consumption tends
to engulf all other social signications in a sinister abyss where
moneyor its avatars, such as media notoriety and poweris the
only value. Far from having the freedom naively presupposed by
the apologists of neoliberal ideology, the unchecked consumer is
plunged into a world of unbridled conformism and actually ends up
thinking and acting in strict accordance with what the institution calls
for. Heteronomy thereby establishes its hegemony in the heart of the
supposed freedom of unlimited consumerism. Moreover, the dominant
imaginary signication of unlimited expansion becomes a vortex in
which other signications disappear, leading to an overall atrophy of
the imagination and a retreat of creativity in all elds (philosophy, art,
science, etc.). Insignicance comes to saturate almost everything in a
determined world of blind narcissism and hedonism orchestrated by
the Eleatic fatalities of neoliberalism. And the project of autonomya
distinctive feature of the Westis relegated to the margins. Nevertheless, far from being a cynical and acquiescent condemnation of the
xvii
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
xxviii
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
xxix
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
CONCLUDING REMARKS
When driven by an intense eros of inquiry that knows no a priori
bounds, it is perhaps inevitable that you will occasionally falter.
In the case of Castoriadis, there are plenty of aspects of his work that
invite critical reection. Nevertheless, the breadth, depth, and
originality of his project need to be recognized in their own right. It
is extremely rare, particularly in an era of increasing academic specialization, that a single thinker spans the elds of philosophy, politics, psychoanalysis, art theory, economics, sociology, history, and
the philosophy of science. It is even more uncommon that he or she
do so while establishing a unique and expansive philosophical project that does not t comfortably within the dominant models and
intellectual fashions of the times. It is a testament to the intensity of
Castoriadis eros of inquiry that his passion for critical reection
broke through the strictures of his intellectual milieu in order to
establish a novel, unique and wide-ranging philosophical project.
His passion for independent elucidation should serve as an open
invitation to all of us to fervently pursue the tradition of radical
critique.
xxx
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
NOTES
1
3
4
9
10
The Castoriadis Reader, ed. and trans. David Ames Curtis. Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers Ltd, 1997, 362 / Fait et faire. Paris: ditions
du Seuil, 1997, 11 (translation slightly modied).
See Figures of the Thinkable, trans. Helen Arnold. Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 2007, 81 / Figures du pensable. Paris:
ditions du Seuil, 1999, 104.
On Socialisme ou barbarie, see The Castoriadis Reader, 139.
Since there is signicant uctuation in the biographical information available regarding Castoriadis, I have decided to rely on the
Association Castoriadis, whose members include many of his
close friends and family members: http://www.castoriadis.org/en/
readText.asp?textID=40. However, I decided to follow the bibliography provided by ditions du Seuil for the date of employment
at the OECD because 1945 (the date found on the Association Castoriadis website) seemed premature due to the fact that
Castoriadis had just arrived in Paris on a scholarship for a doctorat
dtat in philosophy (which he never nished).
The Imaginary Institution of Society, trans. Kathleen Blamey.
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1987, 74 / Linstitution imaginaire
de la socit. Paris: ditions du Seuil, 1975, 11011 (translation
slightly modied).
This rumored exchange is referred to in the Castoriadis obituary
on the website: http://www.agorainternational.org/about.html.
The Imaginary Institution of Society, 171 / Linstitution imaginaire de la
socit, 2567 (translation slightly modied).
It [structuralism] has nothing to say about the sets of elements it
manipulates, about the reasons for their being-such, about their
modications in time (ibid., 171/257). On the pseudo-scientic
ideology of structuralism, see World in Fragments: Writings on
Politics, Society, Psychoanalysis, and the Imagination, ed. and trans.
David Ames Curtis. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997,
51 / La monte de linsigniance. Paris: ditions du Seuil, 1996, 35.
Ibid., 501/34 (translation slightly modied).
The Castoriadis Reader, 398 / Fait et faire, 63. Also see the Agora
International Interview available at http://www.agorainternational.org/enccaiint.pdf.
xxxi
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
xxxii
See La monte de linsigniance, 902 and Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy: Essays in Political Philosophy, ed. David Ames Curtis. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1991, 14/Le monde morcel. Paris: ditions
du Seuil, 1990, 282.
See ibid., 1617/2856.
Ibid., 4/128 (translation slightly modied).
The interview with Legros was not part of the original French
publication and was rst printed in Cornelius Castoriadis: Rinventer
lautonomie, ed. Blaise Bachofen, Sion Elbaz, and Nicolas Poirier.
Paris: ditions du Sandre, series Bibliothque de philosophie
contemporaine, 2008, 27389. Since I wanted to add a discussion
with a philosopher, I am very grateful that ditions du Sandre let
us translate the conversation with Legros, which ts perfectly
within the purview of the book. Like the other interviews, it was a
lively oral exchange that took place on France Culture in the
1990s.
Since the interviews are all from the 1990s, I have primarily
concentrated on Castoriadis later work, from approximately The
Imaginary Institution of Society (1975) until the end of his life. Moreover, for the purposes of writing a synoptic overview in the limited
space of this introduction, I have privileged a synchronic point of
view for purely heuristic reasons. In doing so, it is important to
highlight that it is by no means my intention to occlude the dynamism of Castoriadis project, which obviously changed in diverse
ways between 1975 and 1997.
Fait et faire, 253 (all translations, unless otherwise indicated, are
my own). The entire quote reads: being is creation, vis formandi:
not the creation of matter-energy, but the creation of forms.
Castoriadis also asserts that being is creation/destruction (Figures
of the Thinkable, 190/Figures du pensable, 223)
Ibid. (translation slightly modied).
Fait et faire, 258.
Domaines de lhomme. Paris: ditions du Seuil, 1986, 9.
World in Fragments, 184/Fait et faire, 116 (translation slightly
modied). For reasons of clarity, I have exceptionally translated
ltre as Being (in general) in order to distinguish it from ltant
(being in the sense of a specic entity or phenomenon).
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
xxxiii
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
xxxiv
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
xxxv
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
xxxvi
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
86
87
88
89
90
91
xxxviii
tionally. In fact, this is the state of almost all societies we know of,
almost everywhere, almost always (The Castoriadis Reader, 311/
Domaines de lhomme, 514).
Ibid., 268/3267 (translation slightly modied).
It is worth noting that Castoriadis has nonetheless suggested that
it is impossible to establish a hierarchy of the multiple socialhistorical worlds (see, for instance, Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy
66/Le monde morcel, 69).
As we saw above: Man is the only animal, capable of breaking the
closure in and through which every other living being is. (The
Castoriadis Reader, 314/Domaines de lhomme, 520). However, some
men have apparently not been capable of this, so they remain
within the closure of the animal world.
Castoriadis tends to downplay the central role of slavery and
imperialism in ancient Athens in favor of a relatively halcyon
image of autonomous democracy. On the centrality and importance of slavery, imperialism and various forms of rigid social
hierarchy in Athenian society, see Moses I. Finley, Ancient Slavery
and Modern Ideology. Princeton, NJ: Markus Wiener Publishers,
1998; Moses I. Finley, Democracy Ancient and Modern. New Brunswick and London: Rutgers University Press, 1985; Edmond Lvy,
La Grce au Ve sicle: De Clisthne Socrate. Paris: ditions du Seuil,
1997.
The Castoriadis Reader, 268/Domaines de lhomme, 327 (translation
slightly modied); ibid., 272/353.
See The Castoriadis Reader, 3978/Fait et faire, 63. In a revealing
discussion between Castoriadis and the Mouvement AntiUtilitariste dans les Sciences Sociales (MAUSS), Alain Caill
astutely underscores the tension in Castoriadis work between a
hyper-relativism in which all societies are recognized as equal
insofar as they are creations of the radical instituting imaginary
and an extreme form of universalism in which one cultural
dimension is unconditionally valorized over all others (Cornelius
Castoriadis, Enrique Escobar, Myrto Gondicas, Pascal Vernay,
Dmocratie et relativisme: Dbats avec le MAUSS. Paris: Mille et une
nuits, 2010, 51). In his response, Castoriadis distinguishes between
a philosophical point of view and a political point of view.
Philosophically and historically, he claims that we have to admit
EDITORS INTRODUCTION
92
93
94
xxxix
PART I
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
Translated by John V. Garner
Confronting diversionists [brouilleurs de pistes] and pseudocomplexity, which places hope wholly in the social imaginary,
Castoriadis was in search of a radicalness until the end. I am a
revolutionary in favor of radical changes, he said a few weeks before
his death3; I do not think that one can make the French capitalist
system work in a free, egalitarian, and just way as it [13] is. He was
a revolutionary who, through his life, went on to repeat, We do not
philosophize in order to save the Revolution but in order to save our
thought and our coherence.
But one cannot reduce Cornelius Castoriadis to a single register.
A philosopher and a sociologist, he also worked as an economist and
a psychoanalyst. A titan of thought, enormous, outside of norms,
said Edgar Morin. An encyclopedic thinker with a jubilation for living
and for ghtingcorporeal, spiritual, innite ghting, but constantly
movinghe leaves us with much to work with and so much work
to do . . .
Daniel Mermet
February 7, 1998
[14]
NOTES
1
Leon Trotsky (18791940) was a Bolshevik, and later an antiStalinist, whose version of Marxism emphasized Permanent Revolution. douard Balladur (1929) is a French right-wing politician
who served as Prime Minister from 19931995 and failed in a run
for President in 1995. TR
The numbers in brackets refer to the original pagination of the
French text: Post-scriptum sur linsigniance. Entretiens avec Daniel
Mermet suivi de Dialogue. La Tour dAigues: ditions de lAube, 2007.
TR
Cornelius Castoriadis died on December 26, 1997. Born in Greece,
he moved in 1945 to Paris where he created the now mythical
review Socialisme ou Barbarie. In 1968, with Edgar Morin and
Claude Lefort, he published May 68: The Rupture. In 1975, he published The Imaginary Institution of Society, his most important work.
3
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
CHAPTER ONE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
anything different, and I dont think they would do anything different if they returned to power. They are not statesmen [politiques], in
my opinion, but politicians [politiciens] in the sense of micro-politicians
[micropoliticiens], people on the hunt for votes by any means.
D.M.: Political marketing?
C.C.: Yes, its marketing. They have no program. Their aim is to stay
in power or to return to power, and for that theyre capable of anything. Clinton campaigned solely by following the pollsIf I say this,
is it going [17] to y?each time taking the winning option for public opinion. As they say: I am their leader, therefore Im led by them.
Whats fascinating in our age, as in all ages moreover, is the way
things conspire. There is an intrinsic link between this type of political
nullity, politics becoming worthless, and insignicance in other
domains, in the arts, in philosophy, or in literature. This is the spirit of
the times: without any conspiracy by some power that one could designate, everything conspires, in the sense of radiating in the same
direction, for the same results, that is to say, insignicance.
D.M.: How should politics be done?
C.C.: Politics is a strange profession, even the aforementioned politics.
Why? Because it presupposes two abilities that have no intrinsic relation. The rst is to come to power. If you dont come to power, you
can have the best ideas in the world, and its of no use. There is thus
an art of coming to power. The second ability is, once you come to
power, to do something with it, that is to say, to govern. [18] Napoleon knew how to govern; Clemenceau knew how to govern;
Churchill knew how to govern. These are people who arent of the
same political alignment as me, but what Im describing here is a historical type. Nothing guarantees that someone who knows how to
govern knows, for all that, how to come to power. In an absolute
monarchy, what did it mean to come to power? It meant to atter the
king, to be in the good graces of Madame de Pompadour.3 Today, in
our pseudo-democracy, to come to power means to be telegenic, to
sniff out public opinion. Once in power, what do you do? What
Mr. Chirac is currently doing: nothing. You swim downstream. As
needs be, you change hats because you recognize that in order to
come to power you told stories, and that these stories dont apply.
6
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
role as an oppositional force, these are some of the causes and some
of the symptoms of this rise of insignicance.
C.C.: But at present, were feeling the tremors of a revival of civic
activity. Here and there, were nonetheless starting to understand that
the crisis is not an inevitable outcome of modernity to which we
must submit, adapt, for fear of archaism. Thus the problem of the
role of citizens is raised and the aptitude of each person to exercise
rights and democratic duties with the aimsweet and [27] beautiful
utopiaof getting out of generalized conformism.
D.M.: Your colleague and accomplice, Edgar Morin, talks about the
generalist and the specialist. Politics requires both: the generalist who
knows next to nothing about a little of everything, and
the specialist who knows everything about a single thing but not the
rest. How is a good citizen made?
C.C.: This dilemma has been posed since Plato. Plato said that the
philosophers, who are above the specialists, must rule. In Platos theory, they have a view of everything. The other alternative was Athenian democracy. What were the Athenians up to? Indeed, something
very interesting. Its the Greeks who invented elections. Its an
historically attested fact. Perhaps they were wrong, but they invented
elections! Who was being elected in Athens? The magistrates werent
being elected. The magistrates were being appointed by drawing lots
or by rotation. For Aristotle, remember, a citizen is someone who is
capable of governing and being governed. Everyone is capable of governing, so lots are drawn. Why? Because politics is not the business of
specialists. There is no science of [28] politics. There is opinion, the
doxa of the Greeks; theres no episteme.7 Id like to point out, moreover,
that the idea that there arent specialists of politics and that all opinions are of equal worth is the only reasonable justication for the
principle of the majority. Thus, for the Greeks, the people decide and
the magistrates are chosen by drawing lots or appointed by rotation.
There are specialized activities because the Athenians werent crazy.
Indeed, they did rather signicant things; they made the Parthenon,
etc. For these specialized activitiesthe setting up of shipyards, the
construction of temples, the waging of warspecialists are necessary.
Therefore, such specialists are elected. Thats what an election is
because election means election of the best. And what is the election
11
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
of the best based on? Well, thats where the education of the people
comes in, since they are led to choose. A rst election takes place,
a mistake is made, its noticed, for example that Pericles is a deplorable strategist; well, then, he is not reelected, or hes even dismissed.
But the postulate according to which doxa, opinion, is equally shared,
is of course an entirely theoretical postulate. For this postulate to have
a bit of substance, doxa most be cultivated. And [29] how can a doxa
concerning the government be cultivated? Well, through governing.
So democracythis is whats importantis a matter of educating citizens, something that does not exist at all today.
Recently, a magazine published a statistic indicating that 60 percent
of congressmen admit that they dont understand anything about the
economy, congressmen, in France, who are going to make decisions,
who are making decisions all of the time! They vote on the budget,
they increase or decrease taxes, etc. In truth, these congressmen, just
like cabinet members, are slaves to their specialized advisors. They
have their experts, but they also have their prejudices or preferences.
And if you closely follow how a government, a large bureaucracy,
functionsas I have done in other circumstancesyou see that those
who are in charge trust the experts, but they choose experts who
share their opinions. You will always nd an economist who will tell
you, yes, yes, this must be done, or a military expert who will tell
you, yes, nuclear armament is necessary or nuclear armament is
not necessary: anything and everything. This is an utterly insipid
game, and this is how we are currently being governed. Hence the
dilemma of Morin and Plato: [30] specialists or generalists. Specialists
in the service of people, that is the question, not in the service of a
few politicians. And people learning to govern by governing.
D.M.: You said education, and you say, this is not the case today.
More generally, what mode of education do you envisage? What
mode of distributing knowledge?
C.C.: There are many things that would need to be changed before
we could talk about truly educational activity at the political level.
The principle education in politics is active participation in affairs,
which implies a transformation of institutions that encourages this
participation and that makes it possible, whereas contemporary institutions repel, distance, dissuade people from participating in affairs.
12
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
true speeches are. This is what doesnt exist in a social projection [projection sociale], if I might say.
D.M.: With whom do you want to struggle? And against whom and
against what?
C.C.: I want to struggle along with practically everyone, with the
entire population, or almost, and against the system, and therefore
against the 3 percent, the 5 percent of people who are really [35]
staunch and un-educatable defenders of the system. This is the division, in my opinion. I believe that currently everyone in society
apart from 3 or 5 percenthas a personal and fundamental interest in
things changing.
D.M.: But what would you say to the younger generation?
C.C.: If youre putting it as a question of organization, I would say that
there is no answer. Currently, this is also the question. One of my
friends from the journal Socialisme ou Barbarie, Daniel Mothwho is
still my friendwrote this extraordinary phrase: Even the Roman
Empire, in disappearing, left behind it ruins; the workers movement,
in disappearing, only left refuse behind. How do we get organized
now? The question is how can we get organized? This question runs
into the same obstacle, that is to say that people are not active enough
at present to do something like that. In order to take up an organization of this kind, its necessary to be ready to sacrice more than one
hour Saturday night. This implies a rather signicant undertaking,
and very few people are currently disposed to do this. This is why I
describe the era since 1960 [36] as an era of privatization. People have
withdrawn into their little milieu, the nuclear family, not even the
extensive family. In May 1968, we used to say subway-work-sleep,
now its subway-work-TV-sleep.
D.M.: And no work? Can work be erased?
C.C.: Subway-work-TV-sleep and unemployment ofce.
D.M.: And the intense fear of losing ones job! The panic is widespread, as its: I dont have it anymore or Im not going to have it
anymore.
C.C.: Yes, absolutely.
15
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
C.C.: No, not forbid in the repressive sense, but know that there are
things we cannot do, or that we must not even try to do, or that we
must not desire. Take, for example, the environment. We live in a free
society on this marvelous planet that were in the process of destroying. And as I utter this phrase, I have in mind the wonders of the
planet. Im thinking for example of the Aegean Sea, of snow-capped
mountains, Im thinking of the view of the Pacic from a spot in Australia, Im thinking of Bali, of the Indies, of the French countryside
[39] that were in the process of demolishing and deserting. So many
wonders are on the way to being demolished. I think that we should
be the gardeners of the planet. We ought to cultivate it, cultivate it as
it is and for itself, and nd our life, our place relative to this. Here we
have an enormous task. And all of this could take up a large part of
peoples free time, people liberated from work that is stupid, productive, repetitive, etc. Now this is clearly very far not only from the
current system but from the dominant imagination of today. The
imaginary of our age is the imaginary of unlimited expansion, it is the
accumulation of junk: a TV in every bedroom, a microcomputer in
every bedroom . . . this is what we must destroy. The system relies on
this imaginary that is here and that functions.
D.M.: What youre continually talking about here is freedom?
C.C.: Yes.
D.M.: Difcult freedom?
C.C.: Oh yes! Freedom is very difcult. [40]
D.M.: Difcult democracy?
C.C.: Difcult democracy due to freedom, and difcult freedom due
to democracy, yes, absolutely, because it is very easy to let oneself go:
man is a lazy animal, it has been said. Here again, I return to my
ancestors. Theres a marvelous phrase from Thucydides: it is necessary to choose: rest or be free. I think its Pericles who says this to the
Athenians: if you want to be free, you have to work. You cannot
rest. You cannot sit down in front of the TV. You are not free when
youre in front of the TV. You believe youre free in zapping like an
imbecile, but you arent free; its a false freedom. Freedom is not only
Buridans ass choosing between two piles of hay. Freedom is activity.
17
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
And its an activity that at the same time is self-limiting, that is to say,
that knows that it can do anything but that it mustnt do everything.
Thats the great problem, for me, of democracy and of individualism.
D.M.: Freedom is made up of limits? Philosophizing is establishing
limits?
C.C.: No, freedom is activity, the activity that knows how to set its
own proper limits. [41] Philosophizing is thought. It is the type of
thought that knows how to recognize that there are things we dont
know and will never know . . .
NOTES
1
18
7
8
10
11
19
PART II
DIALOGUES
The four Dialogues that are the subject of this little book, with
Alain Connes (mathematician), Jean-Luc Donnet (psychoanalyst),
Octavio Paz (poet), and Francisco Varela (biologist), are a modest
testimony not simply to the passionate curiosity of Cornelius Castoriadis for all domains of knowledge, but above all to his philosophical determination to think all of what is thinkable.1 It is a unique
testimony, however, since these interviews were at rst radio broadcasts, with the constraints and the limitsbut also with the enthusiasm, polemical vigor, afnity, and friendshipthat this implies.
From time to time, thought drifts onto adventurous and precipitous
paths, leaving itself open, in a way, to the test of the interlocutor.
Several notes were added that will perhaps aid the reader to enhance
his or her own course. But the transcription of the recordings was
limited to a simple work of placement into a format, never seeking
to smooth out the bumps, the approximations, much less the
provocations.
It was Alain Finkielkraut who, in his broadcast Rejoinders (France
Culture) from July 6, 1996, invited Octavio Paz and Cornelius Castoriadis, long-time friends for that matter, to have a dialogue concerning
the theme Facing Modernity. As for the three other interviews, they
are taken with the good graces of . . . Cornelius Castoriadis, and
broadcast on [46] April 20 on France Culture. Several months before,
Katharina von Bulow had proposed that he choose the persons with
22
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
NOTES
1
24
CHAPTER TWO
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
O.P.: Everywhere!
C.C.: Everywhere, certainly, but what there is, is a sort of historical
Niagara. There is no conspiracy, but everything conspires [conspire] in
the sense that everything radiates [respire] together, everything
radiates in the same direction: the corruption that has become
systematic; the autonomization of techno-scientic evolution that
no one controls; the market, of course, the tendency of the economy;
the fact that we no longer worry about knowing if what we produce
serves whatever purpose it may be but solely about knowing if it can
be sold (and not even about this, because if we produce it, we will
make sure, by way of advertising, that it can be sold). Were
acquainted with all of these phenomena. That is, we have, all at
once, a kind of faceless inhuman power, an explosion of its institutional bearers, and even a servility of these institutional bearers to
this historical tendency. [54]
O.P.: I would like to add something. Yes, there is no one in charge.
This is not a class as Marx wanted it to be. Its not a group; its not a
tyrant. These are impersonal forces. Thus, we nd ourselves confronting impersonal forces, nearly autonomous mechanisms; and, at the
same time, what is confronting them is general passivity. Now, in my
opinion, the disconcerting problem is not that of technology (in the
end, I am not really against technology, why?). No, I think that the
disturbing thing, the phenomenon that must preoccupy us, is the
phenomenon of general passivity. Here, I seeand perhaps Cornelius
Castoriadis is in agreement with methat one of the factors, perhaps
the decisive factor, was the great revolutionary failure of the twentieth century. At the end of the century, after the fall of communism,
we nd ourselves in a kind of historical pause, a kind of void. There is
no historical project, and, at the same time, there is the acceptance of
this situation, which, on the one hand, destroys values, and, on the
other hand, transforms society into a society of consumption.
A.F.: You are certainly in agreement with that assessment, Cornelius
Castoriadis . . .
C.C.: Yes, of course.
A.F.: It is the historical failure that explains the passivity?
28
C.C.: No, I think there is more than that, in one sense. I think that
what Octavio Paz is mentioning is a [55] fundamental factor. There
is this disappointment, this fantastic disillusionment regarding the
transformation of the hopes of a large part of humanity, the
intellectuals, the workers, and the ordinary people . . . Hopes are
transformed into a totalitarian machine of extermination and
oppression or, with social-democracy in the West, into a simple
agency of accommodation to the existent order, small reforms, etc.
Well, thats one thing. The second thing is that there was, nevertheless, an extraordinary adaptation of the regimethat is, of capitalismto a new situation that translates, for example, directly into
the society of consumption. This is to say that, starting from a certain
moment, we understood what we had to do. Octavio Paz cites
Fourier, saying that we have to manufacture, for peoples consumption, indestructible products (Im not talking about vegetables or
fabrics but about other products). But what is precisely characteristic
of modern production is what economists have called incorporated
obsolescence. That is, products are manufactured in order to be used
up very rapidly; all consumers know it. And what is the logic of this
story? One of my friendsa worker in automobile distributionsaid,
in 1954, that a Rolls-Royce was becoming less expensive than a
Renault 4CV. Everyone laughed, but he was right. A Rolls-Royce
lasts almost indenitely and it offers a lot more services because you
dont have to repair it, while the Renault 4CV was something to
throw away after 3 or 5 years. But that goes hand in hand with the
fact that, effectively, in the current social and economic conditions,
you can buy Renault 4CVs [56] with the politics of credit, monthly
installments. Its a small price and so they sell, while the Rolls-Royce
doesnt sell.
O.P.: Im wondering if the passivity isnt also explained by the
amelioration of the material living conditions of society. In this sense,
capitalism won favor because it was able to offer better, less expensive
products to the masses.
A.F.: To that end, I would like to simply illustrate what you are saying
through a joke that was common in Poland during the totalitarian
period. A customer goes into a shop, he asks for a cut of meat, and
they say to him: Oh no, mister, here there is no sh, there is no
29
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
meat; thats the other side! So, its a joke concerning the shortage
that effectively made it such that the capitalist system was able to
present itself asand to be relatively (vis-a-vis a system where
nothing functioned)a system where things function. One world of
shortage, one world of abundance. Now, must this be creditedor
not, and to what degreeto its account?
C.C.: That is not the problem, to credit it to its account or not.
We must say rst that this had all the more impact since Marxist ideology propagated the idea that capitalism can only condemn people to
misery. But that was refuted day after day by the facts. Capitalism did
not evolve spontaneously; there were the workers struggles, there
were the unions, there were pressures, strikes, etc. But, [57] at a
certain point in time, it accommodated itself to all of that. I would like
to add one thing, and we should, for that matter, be careful here, without making prophecies or renewing apocalyptic predictions: maybe
this period of capitalism has already begun to be behind us. What we
are seeing currently in the industrialized countriesin particular in
Europe, less in the United Statesis a crisis of a new type, one with
this creation of exclusion, with an extraordinary unemployment level,
with globalization that obligates the old industrial countries to enter
into phases where there are no longer jobs for people. And all of this
is, nevertheless, still the futurewell, sureits not the future, its the
present, but I do not want to make predictions . . .
O.P.: But perhaps it isnt necessary to focus on these questions at the
theoretical, or rather the technical, level. It is clear that the economy
of the totalitarian countries was an economy of shortage and that the
economy of capitalism is an economy of abundance.
C.C.: Of relative abundance, yes.
O.P.: Of abundance for the majority, for the majority in the developed
countries. If you are speaking about my country, its the opposite.
The majority is poor and even sometimes miserable. But we are
speaking right now of the most developed, most advanced sort of
country. Now, the question arises of knowing how abundance (Marx
was thinking of abundance) produced negative fruits, from the
spiritual point of view, for the [58] population of the countries of the
West and detrimental fruits for the underdeveloped countries. And
30
that is, for me, one of the great contemporary historical mysteries:
how abundance, in producing conformity, neutered individuals,
transformed people in masses, into satised masses without will and
without direction.
C.C.: It transformed them into totally private or privatized individuals,
as I have been saying for a long time (this has been one of the themes
of my reection since 1960). But I do not believe that it is necessary
to incriminate abundance as such. I believe that it is necessary to
incriminate the mentality that makes the economy the center of
everything. In Marxs work, it was the center of everything because
the capitalist economy was not going to be able to give people what
they were waiting for; only the communists were able to provide it,
communism such as he thought of it. For people in current society,
its the same idea: whats important is the economy, consumption.
But, in fact, the crisis of the current society concerns the signications
that hold this society together, what one calls values or what one
could also call norms. It is not due to the diffusion of material
abundance; it exists in a certain parallel way. What does the crisis
stem from? On the one hand, it stems from what you mentioned,
from the fall of revolutionary ideologies and, on the other hand, from
the very profound crisis of the ideology of progress. For people in the
nineteenth centuryfor the big liberals or the progressivists
progress was not only a question of the accumulation of wealth. [59]
John Stuart Mill thought that progress was going to give people freedom, democracy, happiness, a better morality. But, today, no one, not
even the incense-bearers for the current system, dare to say that
theres nothing to do but let progress do its work and we will all be
happy or better off. That is not true; everyone knows that perhaps we
will have a better television and then thats all.
O.P.: Yes, which is to say that we are all facing a historical project that
is fully tried and tested; its progress. But Castoriadis said some things
that are slightly different. The rst, which touched me profoundly, is
that we have reduced (modern society has reduced) the meaning of
all values to their economic value. So, in order to renew society, it will
be necessary to undertake a critique. The remedies are not solely of an
economic character; they have a character that is more profound,
moral, or spiritual, whatever you want to call it.
31
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
32
the universal revolt: it came from a lot of countries, France, the United
States, Germany, my country . . .
C.C.: Mexico . . .
O.P.: Yes. And, for all that, the demands were not economic in
character, nor even social, but, rather, moral in character. And the
predecessors, the prophets (vague prophets) of the movement were
rather poets. Sometimes, in listening to our students or in reading the
inscriptions on the walls, I thought of William Blake, of Andr Breton,
of a lot of poets from the nineteenth centurythe romanticsand
from the twentieth century who were rebelling as Baudelaire had
done. They were not making denunciations in the name of a class,
nor in the name of an economy. What was in play was something
completely different: the position, the place of the human person in
society, I would say. I think that modern society eliminated values,
the very center of the creativity that is the human person. Castoriadis
spoke about the individual; I would like to substitute the word person
for the word individual. [62]
A.F.: I would like to dwell properly for one second on May 1968 and
on the uneasiness regarding the movement that might be the bearer
of this awakening or of this exit from nihilism. Because this movement itself ought to remain ambiguous or ambivalent for us. Certainly,
there has arisen an attempt to get out of economism, a severe and
beautiful critique of the values of consumption. But the fact remains
that one of the most severe symptoms of the spiritual crisis that you
are both describing is the crisis of education, the crisis of transmission
(moreover, you speak about this, Cornelius Castoriadis, in your book).
And here, nevertheless, the movement of 1968 is also somewhat
responsible, given that it had a way of presenting pedagogical mastery
as a form of oppressive mastery; the master who teaches and the
master who oppresses were somewhat identied with each other.
And it is true that, today, the disappearance of culture or the humanities in instruction, in the name of protability, is all the more easily
achieved since this culture was delegitimated in the name of the
revolution. Therefore, even this movement cannot be greeted or
commemorated in a uniquely emphatic way.
33
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
A.F.: Excuse me. I would like to say that this cult of youth, in my
opinion, is interesting, and it extends far beyond the case of France.
Youth was being afrmed very strongly in 1968 with a kind of
potential for revolt. But this conformism, about which both of you
tend to agree, is surely exemplied by the cult of youth.
C.C.: It is one of its manifestations.
A.F.: Another manifestation that seems interesting to me is, as Pguy6
said, this way of having a foot in all camps [toucher tous les guichets].
That is, the more one is in the middlethe more one is really in the
norm, the current norm, the norm of current affairs and of the
media the more one presents oneself as marginal, as subversive.
Gay Pride7 can be described like this. You know, the large demonstration that took place several days ago. It was celebrated by all of the
newspapers; it completely took on the appearance of radical
subversion. . . . It seems to me that this is one of the modalities of
contemporary conformism. [65]
C.C.: Sure, but there are several things here. There is the fact that,
from the moment when the systems producers and vendors
discovered that there was, as they say, an enormous youth market, it
ceased to be simply a subversive value or a revolutionary value. And
then, on the other hand, there is one fact that neither the classical
revolutionaries, the reformers, nor the democrats really ever comprehended, realized, or predicted: the fantastic capacity of contemporary society to absorb everything. This is to say that everything
becomes a means for the system. If there were today, for example, an
Antonin Artaudthere are no more of them, but if there were one
it would be a spectacular curiosity if we were to provide funding for
him. So, either he would commit suicide, put himself away in a
psychiatric hospital, or he would, himself as well, become someone
who would end up on television.
O.P.: A television star! I think that we agree in saying that we are
living throughI would not say a crisis (Krisis) because it is a very
exaggerated wordbut we are living in a kind of empty space where
the great hope of the classical liberalisms with the idea of progress and
the hopes of Marxism are dened as a serious historical failure. The
important thing in my opinion will be to see how we can remake
35
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
C.C.: This is why I do not restrict myself to speaking of an autonomous society. I say: an autonomous society where there are autonomous individuals, and I stress the fact that the two are inseparable.
Because those whom you call personswell, in France the word
would not see a big success because it has Christian connotations,
personalists. . . . I know very well that you are not using it in that
sense, but . . . [68]
O.P.: No, but I am not afraid of . . .
C.C.: For good reason, me neither.
O.P.: Because Christianity forms a part of our heritage.
C.C.: Of course, of course. But, in the end, I prefer to speak of
autonomous individuals (or, if you wish, of autonomous personalities). And we can reproach our contemporary society precisely
for killing personality, individuals, the true individuality of people.
Now, if we want to move on to something different, for me, this is
what strikes me as a problem (and here we are facing the abyss):
basically, what does this require? It requires a new historical
creation with new signications, new values, a new type of human
being, all of which has, more or less, to be done at the same time,
transcending, by denition, all possibility of foresight and of
forward planning.
A.F.: A new historical creation that would be a radical alternative . . .
C.C.: Absolutely.
A.F.: Is it necessary to think in terms of a radical alternative . . . ?
[69]
O.P.: If we think in terms of a radical alternative, we are thinking in
terms of creation . . . ?
C.C.: Yes.
O.P.: But there it is; Im a bit indecisive concerning the word creation.
If the word person has Christian echoes, the word creation has even
more theological tonalities (laughs). It confronts us with the idea of a
creator God who takes the world and makes it emerge from nothing.
Historical creation must base itself on already existing givens. We cannot do something purely unheard-of. In each period of history,
37
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
historical creations are not simply combinations, but also transformations of preexisting elements. Thats why the theory of evolution
seems particularly fertile to me. Thanks to it, we are able, without
betraying the rationality of the universe, to arrive at this strange
being, at this strange appearance in the history of the universe, which
is the human mind.
C.C.: Here, there would be an entire philosophical discussion that
I will abstain from approaching now because it would lead us too far
aeld. In any case, I agree with you in saying that there is, in effect, a
theological past behind this word creation; but we are not obliged to
adopt it, any more than you adopt the theological past that is there
behind the word person. I would say, simply, that when the polis, the
Greek city, emerges, when modernity emerges, etc., theres no God
behind it. Its a creation of men; and it is not a simple [70] reprisal of
elements that were in existence. There is a new form that is not limited to combination. When you write a poem, you use the words of
the language, but what you are doing is not a combination of these
words. Its a new form that you impose on them, through their linkage, through a sense [esprit] that pervades a poem. This is your creative side [ct createur] qua poet.
O.P.: Yes, but you are already speaking of a philosophical denition of
the word creation in saying that it is not like a combination
(but if it is not a combination, what is it?). But that is not what is
important. The interesting idea, in my opinion, is that creation is only
comprehensible as transformation, a transformation that can be
radical, like the transformation from animal to man.
C.C.: . . . For example.
A.F.: But perhaps one can make another objection to the utilization
of this term creation, specically for this period we live in. Each of
you spoke of the failure of a certain hopefulness, and of the consequences that this failure was able to have, in terms of passivity. But
is there not, is it not necessary to take into account, quite simply, a
failure of or a critique of the principle of hope11? And here
Im making reference to the book of Hans Jonas, The Imperative of
Responsibility12 basically [71] the modern program (or paradigm)
was always founded on the surpassing of the given toward something
38
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
NOTES
1
42
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
43
CHAPTER THREE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
a transition into the sexual act, for example, the cure is dead. There is
no difculty here; the experiences are there and the consequences for
the patient are very serious, thats for sure. And this can no longer be
a psychoanalytic cure.
K.v.B.: Could you specify why?
C.C.: It is precisely because the analyst is a distant, if not impersonal,
authority that he represents a projection surface onto which the
patient can project all his phantasms, the good as well as the bad. He
is the all powerful object. To cite a phrase of Lacan that deserves to be
preserved, he is the subject supposed to know!5 And one sees this
with patients. But at the same time, perhaps, inasmuch as he deprives
the patient of certain satisfactions, notably erotic, he can be a very bad
gure, the foil. In this sense, in both cases, there is, in the transfer, a
certain repetition of the infantile relation. But there is also, of course,
something else. Once the cure is nished, what [87] happens? What
one observes is that a completed cure goes through the transfer
solution. That is to say, the subject drops the analyst, and in a way
that is almost inhuman.
J.-L.D.: I have a comparison in mind. Not long ago, I did some
research on childbirth without [postpartum] sadness, and I went on
nights to observe deliveries. I found myself wrapped up in the drama
that it can be, in the crisis. And the women were turning to me. I
found myself to be positioned to help them psychologically and
sometimes it created a link with an extreme intensity. However, once
the baby was there, it was as if I no longer existed. The deliverers
know well about this. Obviously, the analytic cure, which Freud compared on occasion to a gestation, certainly poses more complex problems. Cornelius stressed well the fact that what ruins all curative
projects whenever there is a transition to the sexual act is precisely
that the transfer is no longer analyzable. And the wager of the cure is
that the transfer is analyzable and that, being analyzed, it dissolves
sufciently according to the needs. I quote that for you, and it is a
formula that matters a lot for me because it permits one to get out of
theoretical schemas. And this is translated through the fact that,
whenever one meets his or her patients, for example in analytic
societies, one avoids establishing immediate relations with them, one
50
honors, in some sense, temporal distances in a way that lets the transfer disappear little by little in life. [88]
C.C.: If I may put a word in, this is a problem that has a particular
importance, but not for the analysis of subjects in general. Because,
either the analysis obtains and the transfer is analyzable, for
better or worse, sufciently according to needs, or else one does not
manage to analyze it and one ends up with interminable cures,
because the patient cannot handle being removed from this link and
because the analyst does not know how to help him remove himself
from it. But there, where it becomes seriousand this is one of the
problems of he psychoanalytic institutionthis distancing, in effect,
becomes a lot more difcult if the patient does an analysis in order to
become an analyst himself, in which case the investment of the
analyst as subject supposed to know acquires a double depth: it is
not only the emotional ties, but it is what allowed me to become an
analyst . . .
K.v.B.: We are coming back to childbirth . . .
C.C.: Yes, my being an analyst depends upon him; thus a tie is
created. And if the analyst who was the analyst of this patient
does not know how to do this, he can create entirely intolerable situations that disturb life in analytic societies.
K.v.B.: Doesnt the subject always need a tutelary reference
exterior to himself? Can one lay down a law for oneself?
J.-L.D.: This is just the founding ambiguity that Freud detects within
the agency that he is led to free up [89] as the Superego (ideal). The
differentiation Ego/Superego within the Ego conveys, primarily and
simultaneously, the genesis of the Superego, starting from the outside, through the internalization of the parental authority, and the
perpetuation of the conditions (dependency, need for love, threat of
loss) of this infantile origin through the internalization itself.
But the work proper to the psychic space of this differentiation
permits the Ego to autonomize itself (to subtract itself from the
authority of the Superego, according to Freud) by de-personalizing
it. But the impulsive alimentation [lalimentation pulsionnelle] of the
Superego (notably in aggression) makes it such that its regression and
51
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
C.C.: Lets leave aside the extreme cases; lets say that well be in his
bosom. Who has a bosom? Its the mommy, is it not? Therefore, I do
not accept that idea. And I would like to say something more. It is true
that this is a very hard problem in reality. Like Jean-Luc said, meaning
is the activity of the creation of meaning, and for me moreover, it is a
whole reinterpretation of the philosophical idea of truth that goes into
it. Because truth is not correspondence, is not adequation; it is the
constant effort to break the closure in which we exist, and to think
something other, and to think not only quantitatively, but more profoundly, to think better. This movement is truth. That is why there are
great philosophies that are true, even if they are false, and other philosophies that may be correct and have no interest.
J.-L.D.: Thats the retying of ties.
C.C.: It is, in effect, the retying of ties. What is the phrase from Freud
to Schur at the moment when he asks him to make the fatal injection?
It makes no sense any more. Now, up until then, for Freud, his life
made sense. Why? Because he could work and think. And when he is
taken by an incessant pain, he is in a state of incapacity and he says
that it makes no sense any more.
But, to nish, must we rely upon a radical, ultimate, or positivist
nationalism in order to accept the possibility of an autonomy for individuals? I will take a case, which is not crystal clear, [95] but which
generates thought all the same: ancient Greece and, in particular, the
democratic city. In the democratic city, there is a religion, but this
religion is a civil affair. Its the civil religion, as Rousseau said. There is
no belief in the immortality of the soul. The rst funeral inscriptions
where one sees the hope of another life and where, in a certain way,
one prays to the gods to be favorable to the departed, date from after
the end of the fth century, that is, in a phase of decadence. Until
then, either there was no immortality or there was what Achilles
said to Ulysses when he was visited by him in the land of the dead:
I would prefer to be the slave of a poor peasant on the earth than to
be king of all the underworld.10 Death is worse than life; there is no
hope. This does not prevent the Greeks from creating, in particular,
a democracy where it is clear that the law is laid down by the people.
For sure, this is not pure as an example because there is the rest of
religiosity, a religiosity that doesnt have the same character. We see it
55
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
in contemporary society. Even if there was not a total de-Christianization with the French Revolution, modern democracies established
themselves on the principle of the secular.
J.-L.D.: I want to return to the ethic, to the specicity of the
psychoanalytic position, which manifests itself fully only in practice,
and which experiences inevitable interferences from the moment
that there is a theorization effort (but the cure is never an application of the theory). This specicity follows from a capacity to listen
that privileges, above all, [96] psychic evenementality in its processural ux, in its contextuality, in its dynamic. This privilege conferred
upon the primary processes transfers the representational contents to
the second plane insofar as they can be appreciated in their validity
from the viewpoint of the secondary processes, and from an ordinary
line of argumentation.
Utilized in applied psychoanalysis, this privilege permits one to
interpret the ensemble of the human minds major constructions
(religions, metaphysics) and even scientic systems, without placing
oneself on the terrain of their validation. All these systems can, in
effect, appear as projections in the external world of certain endoperceptions of psychic functioning, and can therefore contribute to
its knowledge. This is why, echoing back to the choice of the term
meta-psychology, I proposed to speak of the meta operation.
It seems important to me, at least initially, to situate well the
specicity of this approach. It could not aim to reduce these
systems, any more than the other productions of civilization for that
matter, because it in no way purports to substitute itself for them.
Even if, in the last instance, it proves untenable, this point of view
corresponds, for psychoanalysis, to a refusal to produce a conception
of the world.
Thus, when Freud, in Moses and Monotheism,11 speaks of Christianity
as a regression to polytheism and, at the same time, guratively as
a progression in the confession of the fathers murder (a rewarded
confession!), he is referring to psychic functioning; regression or
progression do not take on normative value. However, [97] within his
logic itself, it is indispensable to him to assert the material-historical
reality of the murder of the dominant male in the primitive hoard.
There is a need to construct a mythscientic perhapsin order to
approach the unknown.
56
NOTES
1
7
8
10
11
CHAPTER FOUR
KATHARINA VON BULOW: First of all, I would like to ask Francisco Varela
how he discovered Cornelius Castoriadis, why he became interested in
him, how he was useful to him in his own works . . . ?
FRANCISCO VARELA: Weve known each other for many years, more
than 15 years, certainly. And the connections between our works are
of various sorts and have evolved and changed historically. In the
beginning, I believe that what interested me in reading his work1
and, in parallel, what Cornelius found in my writingsis that we
were each reecting on the question of autonomy. For me, this was
more from the position of living things, since I am a biologist and, for
him, from the position of the imaginary and the social. However,
these are problematics, each of which obviously refers to the other.
K.v.B.: And the psychoanalytic aspect as well?
F.V.: It was not the psychoanalyst that I read, but rather the theorist
of society and the thinker of the imaginary. For me, that is not the
same thing. [100]
K.v.B.: And from your position, Cornelius, what interested you in the
work of Francisco Varela?
58
59
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
What does this mean, briey, for our listeners? I can say a bit
about it; you will correct me if I have badly understood you. In any
case, as for me, I [102] now use the notion of closure a lot.6 Which is
to say that, for a for-itself, a psychic subject or a living being or a
society, there is creation of a proper world (Eignewelt, one would say
in German), and nothing can enter into this proper world if it is not
transformed according to the principles of this world. Thats easy
enough to comprehend. Lets take the example of the living being: it
is sensitive to a certain category of exterior shocks, but these shocks
are never presented to it as they are. Thus, higher living beings
have a perception of colors but, to use a radical albeit entirely correct
expression, the world of the physicist does not have colors; it has
wavelengths. Color is a quality that shows up with certain categories
of living beings, those which do not perceive luminous vibrations as
such, like electromagnetic vibrations, but perceive blue, red, etc.
Furthermoreand this is a point that Francisco has himself stressed
as well not only is there this transformation of what Freud very
rightly called masses of energy, masses of matter in motion, into
qualities for the subject, but there is evidently also the fact that there
is never a term for term correspondence. This means, for example,
that perception of color is always a function of a perceptual context
and, I would also add, always a subjective one, but thats another
story. . . . So, we have this [example]. And the same thing is true in
the psychic system. This is my domain rather than that of Francisco,
but lets take an extreme case, if you will. A paranoiac will interpret
all motion as aiming to destroy him or to persecute him. For example,
this microphone that you are holding [103] in front of me is at this
moment emitting fragrances that aim squarely at derailing my
nervous system. . . . He makes everything come back into his system
of interpretation. It is the same for a society, where this closure
[clture] appears more explicitly in closed [ferme]for example
primitive or traditionalsocieties. For a genuine Hebraic mindset, an
event as catastrophic as the Holocaust will be interpreted as a supplementary test inicted on the Jewish people and on it alone, which
proves its election. The Holocaust is going to enter into the system of
interpretation that is the proper world of this imaginary Jewish
universe. It is with these ideas, above all, that I came together with
Francisco and that I even used him. . . .
60
F.V.: We should recall, here, the Cerisy Colloquium on selforganization. . . .7 For me, the motivation for this type of reection
was in no way coming from the psychoanalytic, or the social-thinker,
side of Castoriadis. On the subject of autonomy, I remained a biologist.
Why? Because, originally, this investigation on autopoiesiswhich
means, literally, self-construction, self-production . . .
C.C.: . . . or self-creation . . .
F.V.: . . . or self-creation, yes. Thats a Greek neologism invented in
order to designate what Cornelius was just speaking about. Now,
there was, thus, back when we were [104] working on this theme,
the will to be in opposition to what was, toward the 1970s, the dominant way of thinking. It envisioned in the living being a system that
was pretty much a collector of information, capturing information,
the shocks coming from outside in order to impose on them a certain
unitary manipulation. This model, founded on the metaphor of the
computer, seemed to us to be entirely unsatisfactory. But it is necessary to understand well that we were, at the time, really going against
the current and were more or less isolated. Today . . .
C.C.: . . . are we not still, more or less?
F.V.: In my opinion, it has evolved enormously, and this model of
thinking the living beingthis outrageous representationalismnevertheless has a much more weakened existence now. Thus, we forged
this concept of self-production or self-creation or autopoiesis in order
to express this fact founded on the very biology of the organism, on
biochemistry and cellular life. Why? Becauseand this is the second
important point for meit is a gesture that is at the origin, at the very
root of life. It is not even necessary to think it at the level of mammals,
of humans, or of social beings. Life, qua self-constituting process,
already contains this distinctness of a for-itself, as Cornelius would
say, the source offromwhich the imaginary emerges, capable of
giving sense to what is only masses of physical objects. This rootedness of sense in the origin of life is the novelty of this concept of
autonomy, or autopoiesis. Whence came its popularity, at least its success, I think, [105] in the following years. And what I was just sayingthat there is an excess of the imaginary that comes from this
self-construction of the living beingthis is something that I learned
61
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
from reading Cornelius. And I would never have dared to speak of the
imaginary in the origin of life if I had not had use of this kind of continuity between biological phenomena of the origin of life and the
social domain. I am clearly saying continuity; I am not saying
identity.
K.v.B: In your book, Francisco Varela,8 you talk about philosophy
right from the start. You bring up the importance of phenomenology.
You mention Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty in order to point
out that they at least placed in the body the beginning of their
philosophy, the beginning of their reection on perception, the imaginary, the constitution of the subject, etc. But for you, what is not
pertinent in philosophy is precisely that what is at stake therein is a
process that falls under biology, therefore a science, and that
everything we have thought about mind, the soul, psychoanalysis,
etc., seems to be called into question by this scientic approach.
F.V.: By no means! What I am trying to say in my book is, in a certain
way, the opposite, but in the following sense. Alreadyas a rst side
pointI wrote The Embodied Mind nearly 20 years after that theorization of [106] autopoiesis. Many things happened in the meantime,
and you cannot pass right over the whole evolution of my work. But,
above all, what is the fundamental goal of this reection in The Embodied Mind? It is to raise a question that seems to me still to be very badly
thought out in the sciences that concern themselves with thought or
cognitive and mental phenomena. And, here, Im envisioning the
neurosciences, linguistics, what one calls, roughly speaking, the
cognitive sciences.9 The open question is the abyss that exists between
the mechanisms proposed by the sciences and the incarnate, lived
experience [vcu incarn] of every individual. Short of clarifying the
transition and the complication of these two poles, every effort at a
common reection on the autonomy of the living being and the social
can only remain a dead letter. It is here that phenomenology, in the
Merleau-Pontian tradition, is greatly helpful.
C.C.: I am totally in agreement with what you have just said.
I would simply like to bring to the fore a certain number of points.
And, rst, what is striking when one looks at the tendency that we
called cognitivism, and even connectionism, is thatI am brutal, as
62
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
interacts, though we are not able to simply say that everything interacts with everything, because there is the localizable, there are partial
sets [des ensembles par parties]. . . . And what also characterizes the
social imaginary as well as the radical imaginary of the subject and
the theoretical imaginary is, in the cognitive domain for example, the
capacity to create new axioms, in the most abstract sense of the term
(not necessarily in the mathematical sense), from new bases. All of a
sudden, a new base is created, which, precisely, because it is of this
sort, is not foundable. It is perhaps justiable if it is an issue of a
rational system, but it is not foundable because it is a creation. And a
creation is neither deducible nor producible. It is the real sense of the
new. If it is deducible and producible, it is not new, it exists potentially
in the anterior system.
F.V.: Absolutely, of course.
C.C.: And this, therefore, is the genuine question. The idea that one
can simulate creation seems to me to be contradictory in the terms.
Currently, our friend Henri Atlan, for example, is talking about
networks of connected automatons by saying that there is an
aleatory emergence of meaning. I do not dispute to what extent this
is true or not, but I would say that [114] positive scientists, when all
is said and done, are no longer able to do anything except call aleatory
that which is a creation. Since a creation, by denition, is neither
deducible nor producible, it is perceived as something that appears in
a radically aleatory fashion. What is false in this idea is that the word
aleatory has mathematical meaningor, otherwise, it is simply a
wordonly for a predetermined set of possibles. Yet, precisely, what
is proper to creation is to bring about possibles which did not exist
beforehand. The rst living cell that emerges creates, in a sense,
possibilities of life, which only existed beforehand in an entirely
empty and sophistical way.
F.V.: I am perfectly in agreement that the profound question is truly
this one. Up to what point can one think creation, at least make
a description of it? But where I am no longer in agreement with
Cornelius is with respect to what he quite rightly calls identitarian
logic. And, as he knows very well, here we are touching on a profound
debate, a point of great profundity, at the core of the sciences and
67
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
forms that being has created, from the galaxies to the owers and to
the symphonies of musicians, is reducible, can be brought back to
diverse combinations of a form or of several very simple forms (which
is the case with the neuro-psychologist Jean-Pierre Changeux, for
example, in France) and, on the other hand, the idea that being is
creation, that the propriety of being is to make surface new forms.
Now, in what sense does this have a link with politics? I think, quite
simply, that this latter philosophical option liberates us to think politics. It liberates us from social determinisms, from the idea that one
could never do otherwise, that history will never be able to get out of
this circle where it rolls around constantly: oppression, a bit of freedom, re-oppression, etc. It afrms that nothing, in knowledge, is
opposed to the idea that we can one day create a society in which
autonomous human beings can collectively govern themselves in
autonomy. From this point of view, it is not a deduction from philosophy to politics, but it is nevertheless a [122] certain complementarity.
And here, I believe that Francisco will probably agree.
F.V.: I agree, entirely even. But grant me that you reect at the social
level more explicitly than I do. And the possibly deducible relation
between what I do at the level of the living being and mathematics
and politics is less direct. I therefore place more condence in my
intuition as a citizen than in my intuition as a scientist for my political
engagements. Even if these are, of course, things multiply linked
together.14 But such as you phrased your question, I had the impression that you expected something like nalized product from me,
which would have found its place, so to speak, in some sort of utopia,
ideality. And I obviously have nothing of the sort to propose to you.
[123]
NOTES
1
72
6
7
10
11
12
13
14
73
CHAPTER FIVE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
A.C.: In fact, they are already confronted with this problem. The
diverse categories of elementary particles are of a nite number, but if
one looks at their possible states, those are of an innite number.
C.C.: That is true. Now, there is a bifurcation that immediately appears
here, since you spoke about physics, which opens two paths. A rst
one, which I would like to eliminate immediately, is that of reductionism. It begins from an observation of evidence: our brain, with
which we do mathematics, among other things, is a physical object
and, in particular, a living object, a biological object. And here is
where the biologists come in to afrm: mathematics is in the brain,
end of story. But, as for me, I do not manage to comprehend how the
innite is within the brain! The innite is precisely an ideality created
by the human imagination, for the functioning of which the brain is
a necessary condition, but by no means sufcient. And we too often
forget that distinction.
The other path leads to what an American physicist, Wigner, has
called the [136] unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics when
one applies it to he real world.7 An enormous problem! In your book
with Changeux, you make a very important remark to which I adhere
entirely, to the effect that physics is not reducible to mathematics.
Likewise, mathematics is not reducible to physics. There are whole
branches of mathematics . . .
A.C.: Of course, like arithmetics, for example . . .
C.C.: . . . yes which do not have physical reality, including the
primary numbers of course, but also the space of innite dimension. . . .
They become tools but do not have physical reality. Thus, there is, in
mathematical language, a non-empty intersection between the physical universe and the mathematical universe; there is a part wherein
they cross over, and within that part, the effectiveness of mathematics
is really diabolical. And, then, there is a part of physics (perhaps it is
the most essential part, in a sense) which is outside of the rest, just as
there is a part of mathematics which is also outside of the rest and is
just as essential. And this is, in my eyes, a very strong argument
against all reductionisms.
A.C.: Absolutely. Moreover, with respect to the human brain, the
materialist point of view is very limited, not only because, of course,
82
the brain is a material, nite object, but, above all, because it purports
to comprehend what matter is, because it is [137] mistaken and shams
us. Certainly, as long as one takes interest in biological phenomena at
the level of the molecule, one can, in effect, have an approximately
valid idea of what one is dealing with. But as soon as one changes
levels in order to be concerned with the elementary particles of quantum mechanics, this very notion of matter, of the material world,
becomes evanescent. Nevertheless, this really is the essential question
that is necessary for us to face: what is external reality? And one can
take the same argument that localizes mathematics in the brain,
paraphrase it for external reality, and end up at exactly the same
conclusion, which is that external reality exists only in the brain. That
hardly advances us.
For me, external realityeverything that is outside of usis essentially, and rst, an inexhaustible source of information and, secondly,
something not able to be bypassed [quelque chose dincontournable], in
a certain way. Yet, mathematical realitywhen one is talking about
the primary numbers, the innity of primary numbershas exactly
the characteristics of being a source of information that is, on the one
hand, unpredictable, unfailing, and, on the other hand, not able to be
bypassed, inevitable. Such is the primary experience that one gets
with mathematics; it is impossible both to capture it all at once and to
bypass the bulk of information that it represents. If someone, one day,
comes along with a very powerful computer and says, I produced the
greatest primary number, we know that he is mistaken because we
have the demonstration of the innitude of primary numbers. [138]
C.C.: Which is, moreover, an admirable demonstration already present in Euclid, and which a normally intelligent, ten-year-old child
must be able to comprehend.
A.C.: But which absolutely would not work on a computer, since you
take the numbers, you take the product of all the preceding numbers,
and you tag on one; and it is something absolutely impossible to do
with a machine. But thats how it is: mathematics is a reality that is
truly unable to be bypassed, perfectly well-dened, and an inexhaustible source of information. While external reality, even in a somewhat
intuitive sense of the material world that surrounds us, is something
that is much more difcult to dene and perceive. Because, whatever
83
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
the passage of time. Just a few words on this. In contemporary physics, we make time one of the coordinates of space-time, and we thus
believe we understand what it is. But, in fact, there is a total illusion
here. Physics does not explain and never says why time passes, why
time ows. It is a coordinate, but the coordinates of space do not ow.
Time, it ows. For as long as we have not reected in a sufciently
precise way on this owing of time, the Darwinian explanation will
remain a vicious circle. Species disappear because time passes; but
why does time pass? What does this passage of time signify? What
does our perception of this passage signify?
On this essential problem of the relations between the physical
world, the material world, and this access to the innite, this space of
transcendence that makes for the originality of the human soul,
I admit that I have a rather radical view. I trust only in things that
exist independently of time, in order thus to assign to the sole mathematical reality this independence, this atemporality. This allows us to
ensure its existence independently of our comprehension of the owing of time. And I place in it the founding stone upon which to construct my conception of reality. Now, take the question of integration
with the interior of the reality of the physical universe that we know
about, that of the big bang, of the temporality that characterizes us
and that characterizes the universe we live in. And by working on this
problem, by discussing it with physicists [141], I ended up more or
less at the conclusion that the owing of time has nothing to do with
a coordinate in space-time, has nothing to do with this somewhat
naive model that we have of space-time and of physics, but, in fact, it
had something to do with thermodynamics. In a paradoxical, provocative way, I will say that if time passes, it is because we are bathing
in 3 Kelvin rays, this fossil ray that stems from the big bang. For me,
time passes because we are incapable of experiencing [connatre] the
microscopic distributions of what is happening in the universe that
surrounds us, and because this lack of information, this kind of macroscopic perception that we have of it, makes it such that gradually
our body is destroyed, our genetic precision erodes. And in order to
struggle against it, we are disposed of only this discrete phenomenon,
which is the transmission of life, the transmission to other generations of this sort of bible contained in our genetic information, which,
because it is discrete and rigid, will be very difcult to diminish and,
85
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
on the contrary, will be able to ght and thrive against this owing of
time about which we can do nothing because it is due to destruction,
to friction, and to our incapacity to experience [connatre] all the
details of the microscopic world that surrounds us.
C.C.: I would like to come back to some of the subjects that you just
mentioned and, rst, to what you said about Darwin and Darwinism,
which is entirely correct but insufcient. The core of the question is
that there is no Darwinian explanation [142], there is only a grandiose tautology: survival only to those that are suitable for survivable.
A.C.: But we agree!
C.C.: Now, the essential question is twofold: rst, why are there
different living beings? Secondly, and above all, why do these differences go in the direction of a growing complexication of the living
being? Here, Darwin had no response. He relied upon examples that
had very little value: variations within a species, etc. Then, with mutations, they found not a response, but a stone that was missing for
making the fact of evolution comprehensible: there is evolution
because there is mutation. But these mutations are aleatory, come
about by chance, and the enigma reappears: how is it that aleatory
mutations so oftennot always because some of them that are deadly
and impair the being that carries themproduce coherent forms,
capable of living and even of being the seat of new mutations that will
lead further along on the scale of complexity? On this issue, modern
neo-Darwinism has no response in my view. They speak, here again,
of the aleatory, but in my mind this aleatorynot the trivial aleatory
of the dice throw or of the card one pullsis a pseudonym that deterministic and positivistic scientists give to the fact of creation. Because
its an either/or: either something is a production starting from what
exists, and one can explain it, say how it was manufactured, or it is
not. And determinism calls aleatory that which it cannot explain, that
is to say, the fact of creation.
A.C.: We are entirely in agreement here.
C.C.: And there is the growing complexication, about which
Stephen Jay Gould tried to give an explanation. It starts with a zerocomplexity. A rst living form appears, which obviously cannot come
86
from this side of zero. If, thus, it goes somewhere, it will be toward
complexity, and after a million years there will be very complex
forms. . . . But thermodynamics does not authorize such a reasoning,
which teaches us that there are many chances for these forms to lose
complexity rather than to continue to become more complex. What
they do not see here is that life is a creation, and a permanent
creation of new forms, and that the human species is such a creation
with that which characterizes it in particular, namely, the creative
imagination.
Before coming to the famous question of the universality of mathematics, just a word on what Alain Connes said about time just now.
I do not believe that thermodynamics can explain time to us. The
great problem that it faces up to is obviously the arrow of time, why
there is before and after, why it ows. But, here again, it is necessary
to distinguish two times.
A.C.: Absolutely. [144]
C.C.: There is a time that I will call ensemblist-identitarian, or
algorithmic, for which thermodynamics is valuable. But if this time
were alone, there would have been several initial forms that would
have degraded themselves at the end of about fteen million years.
Yet, what we observe is that there is always the emergence of new
forms. There is thus another time, which is not the simple time of
deterioration but the time of creation, that I call poetic time, because
poiesis means creation. And the true before/after is marked under this.
Do you agree?
A.C.: Entirely. Certainly, this would necessitate a lot more explanation, but lets say that I was speaking here of the owing of time in the
naive sense of the term. And it is quite evident that it would be necessary to make the distinction between at least three or four forms of
time. . . .
K.v.B.: If one reads the absolutely superb pages of St. Augustine or
other great philosophers on time, one observes that what gave them
the greatest fear is the time that ows, deterioration, death, forgetting. . . .
A.C. & C.C.: Obviously, thats the big issue!
87
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
order to respond to this anguish of death. There is an eternity somewhere, elsewhere, and in this eternity we personally participate. And
there is an innite, which is not only like the innite number of innities in mathematics, but which is a person, who is good, who loves
us, etc. And it was for centuries that this worked.
As for this experience of eternity, of atemporality, mathematics opens
it up for us, for sure, but so do great works of art, for example. Once
again, the St. Matthew Passion was created in Leipzig, in such and such a
year, by an individual who had 20 children. . . . But all of that is totally
non-pertinent to the meaning and the musical content of the St.
Matthew Passion. Man creates and has access to a world of idealitiesof
the imperceptible, certainlywhich are nevertheless immanent, and
which he manages to let into his proper world. Mathematics is an
excellent manifestation of it, but so is art and even great thinking.
[147]
Just one more word on matter, about which you were very correctly
saying that it became evanescent with modern physics. But there is
more: the categories themselves of our ordinary perception became
evanescent with it, for example, the separability in quanta, or
identity. And I am not talking about causality. Physics thus makes us
discover strata of being that are different from the habitual stratum
in which we live, and this is one of the reasons for the fascination
that it exerts.
Last point before coming to the question of intemporality. I was
very happy to observe our agreement on that. One does not work on
mathematics solely with ones brain in the trivial sense. The psyche,
the human soul, can do nothing if there is not simultaneously
representation, desire, or affect. One does mathematics because one
desires to do mathematics and because doing mathematics procures
pleasure.
A.C.: Absolutely. And also because one is attracted by a mystery. . . .
C.C.: Yes, but this is the case with all three at once; the fascination
exerts the question of meaning. But, in the end, the whole human
being is implicated. And this remains a reason why I do not believe a
machine will ever be able to think. I do not see a machine becoming
passionate for the demonstration of the innitude of the primary
numbers. Why would that interest it?
89
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
NOTES
1
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
3
4
5
92
CHAPTER SIX
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
societies and other societies does not belong to the nature of thingsto
a physisbut to a nomos, which is to say to an institution, convention,
social law. This yields histories, for example in Herodotus, that
ridicule the customs of the Greeks by depicting the king of the
Persians who displays to the Greeks the [274] funeral customs of the
Indians and to the Indians the customs of the Greeks. For each of
these two peoples, the customs of the others are a pure and simple
abomination. But the break also, and above all, takes form starting
from the moment when the philosophers began to demolish the
mythological traditions and to search for a principle of truth and of
reection within their own activity of thinking. And also, this break
immediately extends itself into the sphere of politics with democracy,
the question of the law, the question of justice. Certainly, the putting
into question of the law as falling under physis remainsin particular
in the plane of politicslimited in Greece (with slavery, the status of
women, etc). But it was reborn in modern times. It is not at all a copy.
It is something else. It is a new departure that enacts itself in Europe,
which, starting from a certain moment, is reinspired by the Greeks.
It culminates there, as we know, in the Enlightenment, with the
French Revolution, simultaneously with the will for a self-institution
of society (we make our laws) and for an autonomy of human reection, of knowledge. Religion is a private affair; the Scriptures contain,
perhaps, a revelation or do not contain it, but even this revelation
must pass through the lter of reason. This is already Descartes trying
to demonstrate the existence of God, it is Kant, etc. Yet it continued,
lasting for a certain amount of time. The question that is being
posed today is this one: the rise of another tendency, which is very
important, which manifests itself in modern timesthis is the tendency toward the rational mastery of the world and, in particular, the
placing of the economy at the center of everything, the expansion of
productive forces (it is in this sense that Marx participated in the
capitalist universe), and something that is translated to the level of
concrete individuals (who cannot each be a capitalist or an entrepreneur) as a ight behind a purportedly ever more elevated level of
lifeto what extent is the development of this tendency in the process of eliminating the value of autonomy?
What I mean to say, here, is that we were wrong, lately, to speak
of individualism or of narcissism. Individualism [275] is an empty
94
formulation behind which there is a content. Individuals do not valorize the individual as individual; they valorize a content, and this
content is a certain life of that individual. And this life is what we are
accustomed to call the society of consumption.
A.F.: Robert Legros, what is the meaning for you of this formulation
about the rupture of closure?
ROBERT LEGROS: If you will, I will begin with what Cornelius Castoriadis just said by saying that, in our modernity, there are, at bottom,
two antagonistic projects: on the one hand, the project of autonomy,
and, on the other hand, the project of mastery linked to the idea of
individualism. Yet, it seems to me, for my part (and this is a disputed
subject that could incite a discussion) that these two projects are not
so independent; and the search for autonomy can be (I am not saying
must be) at the origin of this society of consumptions search for mastery. But to introduce this debate, Ill go back, thus, to the expression
the rupture of closure, since my book, in effect, claims to be a reection on the meaning of this rupture. The question is: in what sense is
there a rupture? Let us immediately highlight that if there should not
have been the possibility of rupture, what we do as philosophers, our
very interrogation would lose all meaning. To introduce this question,
I would like to begin in the way that Kant presents the problem,
which brings us back to asking about the way the problem is presented in the Enlightenment.4 Kant says this to us: manand it is this
denition which is expressed, in his eyes, by the Enlightenmentis
naturally superior. Which signies that he is originally autonomous,
or, to retrieve an expression of Fichte, only man is originally nothing. Which means that man is a being who does not have a nature,
who, on the one hand, is not destined to imitate an ideal nature and
who, on the other hand, is not reducible to immediate inclinations
[276] that would be natural. And it is precisely because he is nothing,
because he has no nature, that he is autonomous. This is, Kant tells
us, what man originally is: he is naturally superior, thus autonomous by nature, thus naturally without nature. But, Kant adds as
well, throughout human history, man believed that he was not
superior, that he was inferior, which is to say, in sum, that throughout
history, man accepted the principle of heteronomy rather than that of
autonomy. And, in addition, throughout history, men basked in a
95
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
certain state of inferiority, and this state of inferiority, says Kant, has
thus become almost a nature, which signies, basically (which
rejoins a theme often developed by Castoriadis), that the principle of
heteronomy naturalizes attitudes. It naturalizes attitudes rst in the
sense that it makes them (nearly) spontaneously inferior, submissive.
It is through a certain spontaneity that individuals come to submit
themselves, and thus the attitude is natural (or naturalized) in the
sense that it has something spontaneous. The principle of heteronomy equally naturalizes attitudes in the sense that the principles
that command the attitudes are outside of what could be decided
upon by them, that they pertain to physis. Norms are not decided by
us, they are transcendent, pertain to physis and not to nomos. And,
nally, the attitude is naturalized to the extent that the meaning of
things appears as natural, familiar; it is self-evident. What does Kant
draw as a conclusion? He draws as a conclusion that since man is
nothing by nature, naturalization is an illusion and that, as a consequence, that which pertains to the properly human is the extraction
from naturalization. What interested me is the objection that the
romantics make to this idea from Kant. This seems to me quite strong.
It consists in saying, if man is nothing by nature, one thus cannot
even say that autonomy is original. What is necessary to say is that
naturalization is original, meaning that man becomes human through
his inscription in a particular humanity, which has its norms, which
has its practices [usages], which has its customs. In other words, [277]
man is rst of all naturalized and it is thanks to this naturalization that
he has an opportunity to be human, that is, to singularize himself, to
autonomize himself, to invent himself.
The argument seems strong to me, but the conclusion drawn by
the romantics from this argument seems to me to be false. If naturalization is original, say the romantics, then (here is the conclusion that is abusively drawn in my eyes) the extraction from
nature is a dehumanization. This means that the fact of wanting to
autonomize oneself, of wanting to make oneself independent of the
tradition, culminates in an abstract humanism, in a humanism that
dehumanizes, in the end, since abstract man is no longer anything.
How would abstracted man (from all tradition, from all culture) be
something if man is nothing by nature? And if abstract man is
nothing, has nothing human left, mustnt we understand that the
96
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
because, from the biological point of view, man, like all living species,
does not seek to indenitely expand the object and the dimensions of
consumption. He would have a level of consumption that would
saturate him and then it would end. The madness of the consumption
of the modern world stems from the purest imaginary; it has nothing
natural about it, it is a historical artifact. What is more, this masks
something else, which is much more important. I do not want to get
into the question of the universality of man. But, in the end, what the
inspection of history and of ethnology reveals to us is not the universality of man qua consumer. It is the universality of man qua creator,
qua producer of imaginary identities, of religions, of signications, of
values, of norms, etc. Yet, evidently, the difculties start here because
his productions are different. The question is, where can one recognize oneself, and to what extent can this rupture of closurewhich
opened itself with Greece, which is so amplied in the Westto what
extent can this opening allow for another type of universality in
which human creativity frees itself [se dgage], and at the same time
maintain the criteria that permit it to eliminate that which, in this
creativity, can just as well surface as monstrous? For the monstrousness engendered by our creativity, this also exists. The second thing
that I would like to say is that it is incontestable that, in the modern
era (and already in the ancient era, but in another way than for the
modern era), the project of autonomy and the [282] project of an
indenite expansion of a so-called mastery have contaminated each
other. The most agrant case being that of the revolutionary movement, which, under the grip of Marxism, supposed that there was
nothing to do but realize the mastery over nature in order to hand
over autonomy to man, which is a total illusion. As for me, I think, on
the contrary, that today, that which we need is not a mastery, but a
control of this desire for mastery, a self-limitation. Autonomy means
self-limitation. We need to eliminate this madness of expansion
without limit; we need an ideal of frugal life, of a management of
the resources of the planet with due care and attention [de bons pres
de familles]. If the two projects have contaminated each other, it is
necessary to know how to begin, and this beginning is obviously
not easy. No one is proposing stopping scientic research under the
pretext that it can bring out very dangerous things; but there are,
nevertheless, very dangerous zones: the passage from research
100
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
historical debt and we pay this debt through pushing further along
this tradition of freedom, this exigency of freedom, through transmitting it to new generations. [285]
A.F.: Before Robert Legros responds, I will provide you with several
impressions concerning the relation that we have today with the
tradition and with creation. What strikes me is that the richness of the
heritage [patrimoine] and the vitality of contemporary art are gloried
from now on in the language of consumption. I am thinking here of
an edition of the Nouvel Observateur, which celebrates what it calls the
the feast of culture. To speak of culture, its proliferation, its variety,
and the taste of the public for it, they are speaking spontaneously in
culinary terms. Everything is eaten today, even culture. The society of
consumption knows no limit. The highest and the most rewarding
activities are brought down to the pleasure of feeding oneself.
R.L.: Isnt it here alone that man understand himself as universal and
abstract being who can establish a museum-touristic relation to the
tradition and a relation of consumption with tradition? To throw the
question back out, we could return to Kant and start, this time, no
longer from the text on the Aufklrung but from what Kant calls
genius. Because what Kant calls genius is no longer the subject in the
sense of the conscious and voluntary subject but a being that is
transcended by what it does. It is at once transcended by the meaning
of what it elaborates and overwhelmed by the questions that arise
from what it creates. The artist creates and is even so much the
creator that he does not himself will the origin of what he does. He
wants to give expression to something that transcends him. This could
lead one to think that it is not because we have knowledge that we
are in a society that self-institutes itself, it is not because we would
have this knowledge that we would be more creative [plus createur].
Doesnt creation (or, lets say, in order to generalize, invention, the
faculty to start off, to singularize oneself, to render oneself autonomous) go hand in hand with a certain absence of lucidity? Doesnt
the greatest lucidity, namely that we know ourselves creators of our
norms, go hand in hand with a certain sterility? Isnt there the danger
in contemporary art of producing only to express creation? The art of
a traditional society is [286] certainly a lot less lucid since it does not
recognize itself as art and believes that applied norms are norms that
103
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
result from physis and have nothing to do with nomos. But wasnt it
sometimes more inventive than an art that claims to be entirely lucid
with respect to its own origin?
C.C.: You are posing very important and complex questions. There is,
notably, the question of contemporary art or alleged contemporary
art, which must, perhaps, be set apart. But I would not say at all that
we can make general the idea that the work of geniusas Kant says,
of the great work of artnecessarily consists of an enormous portion
of non-lucidity in the habitual sense. Here, again, it is necessary to be
understood [sentendre]. It consists of an enormous share of creation
that is, of the radical imaginary, of something that arisesand at
the same time it is never a great work of art (this Kant knew very
well, everyone knows it well), if in this imagination, in this arising, a
fantastic quantity of logic and lucidity is not combined. We should not
believe that Chopin, applying himself to piano in order to improvise,
did just whatever. In his ngers, there are entire volumes of arithmetic and in his head as well. Otherwise, he would not improvise as
he improvises. It is evident. Its a separate question.
There are two questions here. I think that modern art is not a victim
of its lucidity but of its will to create the new for the new. When
I speak of self-institution, I do not at all mean [sentendre] that we
regather all the citizens every morning saying, thats it, were changing the laws because these are the laws of yesterday. . . . No, I understand simply that it is not necessary to have, each time, a revolution
in order to change the laws, whatever they are. It can be that the laws
are tacitly ratied, if not indenitely during long periods of time, quite
simply because they are good, because no one is thinking of others
that are better. Lets take the example of philosophy. Is it that, if there
is a philosopher who has original ideas, lucidity prevents him from
being original? I think this is false. I think that lucidity is an essential
ingredient so that [287] he is precisely able to get started between
what is original and what is not or simply doesnt hold. I think, therefore, that it is necessary to distinguish the domains. And it is above all
necessary to understand one thing. An autonomous society, a society
that gives itself its laws and knows that it gives itself its laws, such a
society can exist only with autonomous individuals. These are two
sides of the same coin. Without autonomous individuals there is no
104
POSTSCRIPT ON INSIGNIFICANCE
we have been able to create, that is the prerequisite for all true
democracy. And this is why democracy is the most difcult and most
tragic regime of all.
R.L.: We are indeed aware [conscience] of the mortality of our works
and of meaning, but with the consciousness, as well, that we are not
the masters of the meaning that we make or create, with the
consciousness that we make or create meaning only through being
overcome by it and by being led to the innite questions that it
provokes.
NOTES
1
2
3
107
108
109
Index
111
INDEX
boundary 64, 70
brain 75, 824, 89
break xviii, xxiii, xxv, xxvi,
xxix, xxxvii n88, 40, 55,
93107 see also rupture
bureaucracy x, 12
calculation 63, 70, 768
calculus 756
capitalism xvii, 3, 9, 10, 16, 27,
29, 30, 31, 90, 94
Castoriadis, Cornelius ixxxxix,
1, 23, 223
catastrophe, theory of 69
Cerisy Colloquium 61
Changeux, Jean-Pierre 23, 72,
74, 75, 76, 82, 90
chaos xviiixx, xxii, xxxiii n37,
xxxiv n45, xxxvi n78
see also abyss
Christianity xxii, 37, 39, 53, 54,
56, 88
Churchs thesis 75
closure xii, xxii, xxv, xxix,
xxxvii n88, xxxix n93,
55, 5960, 93107
cognition xxxvii n85, 59, 625,
67
cognitive science 64
cognitivism 62
Cohn-Bendit, Daniel xxxviii
n91, 23, 24n2
communism 2, 8, 28, 31
computer 17, 61, 63, 66, 76, 79,
83 see also robot, machine
condition
necessary 69, 82
of existence xvi, 70
of possibility 68
sufcient 69, 82
112
INDEX
crisis
of autonomy xxviii
of education 33
of production 9, 34
of signication xii, xvii, 11,
305
of value 34
critique x, xii, xiii, xxv, xxix,
xxx, 10, 14, 31, 33, 38,
978
Darwinism 846
deconstruction xii
deduction
vs. creation 67
defunctionalization xxv
democracy xvxvii, xx, xxix,
xxxvii n89, 67, 1012,
1718, 26, 29, 31, 41, 55,
69, 94, 1012, 107
Athenian 112, 41
pseudo-democracy 67
representative 7, 10
true 7, 10, 107
Descartes, Ren 40, 94, 101
desire xxxxi, xxix, xxxiv n57,
2, 14, 1617, 19n8, 46,
49, 534, 634, 66, 71,
89, 981, 105
for autonomy 989, 100, 101,
105
determination xiii, xiv xvii,
xxiv, xxvixxvii, xxxv
n66, 7, 22, 47, 668
see also creation,
indetermination
determinism xvxvi, 45, 47, 72,
84, 86
differential equation 80
discontinuity xiii
INDEX
evolution
of society 8, 14
of the sciences xxiii, 28
theory of 36, 38, 86
see also Darwinism
exhaustion, method of 79
Fermats theorem 63, 65
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 95
Finkielkraut, Alain 223,
2542, 93107
rst natural stratum xxiv
for-itself xxiv, 591, 89
formalization xxiv, 66, 68, 74,
76
forms
creation of new xiii, xv, xviii,
xxxii n16, xxxiii n17, 38,
42, 49, 69, 72, 75, 867
institutional 52
perpetuation of xiv
social-historical xv, 98
Foucault, Michel xvi
France 7, 9, 12, 27, 33, 345, 37
France Culture xxxi n14, 223,
93
freedom xvii, 1718, 31, 41, 44,
49, 72, 1023
French Revolution 7, 56, 94
Freud, Sigmund xxxxi, 457,
507
functionalism xi, xxiv, xxv
genius xix, 1036
global xiii, 68, 6970
see also local
globalization 30
God xii, xv, 14, 368, 401,
525, 94
Gould, Stephen Jay 86
114
Greece
Ancient x, xvxxviii, xxix,
xxxv n75, xxxviii n91,
11, 38, 39, 55, 69, 934,
100, 102
contemporary ix, 3, 25, 61, 65
Greek democracy 1112, 41
Greek resistance 5
happiness 31, 41
Hegel, G. W. F. xxii
Heidegger, Martin xii, 62
Heraclitus 45, 57n3
Herodotus 94
heteronomy xvii, xxvixxviii,
957 see also autonomy,
society
history xxviii, xxii, xxvxxx,
xxxv n75, xxxviii n91,
13, 16, 27, 369, 49, 53,
59, 64, 66, 70, 71, 72, 78,
95, 97102, 106
of humanity xxviixxviii, 97
laws of 36
of mathematics 78
of philosophy xxv, xxxv n75,
97
philosophic xxxviii n91
religion of 53
see also Thucydides
Holocaust 60
hope 389, 55
humanism 96
Husserl, Edmund 62
identitarian see ensemblistidentitarian dimension
identity xx, xxiv, 62, 89
ideology
liberal xvii, 10, 13
INDEX
Marxism as 30, 53
of progress 10, 31, 53
of pseudo-science xxxi
illusion 54, 85, 96, 100
imaginary x, xiii, xiv, xv, xvi,
xvii, xviii, xx, xxi, xxvi,
xxxvii n80, xxxviii n91,
3, 17, 458, 54, 5864,
7980, 100, 104
instituting xxvi, xxxviii n91,
59
radical xxvi, 46, 54, 67, 104
social xivxv, xviixviii,
xxxvii n80, 3, 67
imagination xiii, xv, xviixviii,
xxixxii, xxivxxvii,
xxxiv n57, xxxvi n80, 17,
45, 478, 66, 75, 7780,
82, 87, 104
creative xviii, xxvi, xxxvi
n80, 75, 77, 87
radical xiii, xxi, xxii, xxiv,
xxxiv n57, 45
immanence 53, 54, 89
indetermination xiiixiv, xxiv,
xxvixxvii, xxxv, 47
individual x, xiv, xvi, xixxxii,
xxvi, xxxix n94, 16, 27,
31, 33, 36, 37, 41, 48, 52,
53, 55, 59, 62, 88, 89,
946, 989,
1045, 106
individualism xx, 18, 26, 945
innity, of primary
numbers 823, 89
inherited thought xi, xxiii, xxvi,
34, 47
insignicance xii, xvi, xvii, 2,
56, 11, 256, 32
integral 81
INDEX
limit (Contd)
self-limitation xii, 168, 100
limit, to a machines
capacity 75, 79
limit, to philosophy x, xii, xv,
xxv, 94
see also unlimited
limits, theory of 79, 81
linguistics 62
living being xxiv, xxv, xxxvii
n88, 40, 5962, 65, 72,
80, 86 see also for-itself
local 67, 6970, 83, 84, 88
see also global
machine 29, 63, 65, 66, 746,
78, 83, 89 see also
computer, robot
magma xxi, xxiv, xxvi, xxxv
n67, 66 see also
ensemblist-identitarian
dimension
Maoism 1314
market xvii, 9, 268, 34, 35
Marx, Karl 9, 28, 30, 31, 40, 45,
59, 94
Marxism x, xi, xvi, 3n1, 9,
28, 301, 35, 45, 53,
70, 100
mastery see rational mastery,
project of
materialism 36, 80, 825
mathematics xiii, xxiv, 59,
669, 72, 7491
and innity 83, 89
and philosophy 78
and physics 77, 82, 88
and pleasure 89
and reality 77
as creation 75, 82, 84, 91
116
INDEX
phenomenology xi
philosophy ixxiii, xv, xvii,
xviii, xxv, xxx, xxxv
n75, 6, 46, 47, 62, 78,
97, 104
and democracy xv, xx, 69
and mathematics 78
and myth 94, 102
and poetry 42
and politics 712
and science xviii, xxiii, 84
continental xxv
Western xv, xxvi, xxix, xxxv
n75, 25
physics 40, 71, 77, 812,
845, 8991
elementary particles 81
mathematics and 77
matter xxxii n16, 60,
83, 89
Newtonian xxiii, 28
Plato 11, 12, 71, 84
pleasure xxxxi, 457, 507,
89, 102, 103
pleasure principle 54
mathematical 89
poetry xxxvi n80, 42
poiesis xxii, 87
see also autopoiesis
polis 38, 69
politics xiii, xvi, xxix, xxx, 2, 6,
11, 13, 36, 40, 53,
712, 94
education in 12
specialists and
generalists 1112
totalitarian 25
possibility
conditions of xxvii, 36, 68
non-determined xxvii, 67
117
INDEX
possibility (Contd)
non-existing 67
of articial intelligence
637
of creation 68, 95
primary numbers see numbers
private xvii, 94
privatization 31
production xiv, xvi, xix, 34, 61,
86
capitalist xvii, 94, 29
vs. creation 67, 86
progress xxiii, 10, 26, 31, 35,
39, 45, 53
ideology of 31, 53
mythology of 53
scientic xxiii, 84
progressivism xii
Proust, Marcel 16, 81
psyche xiiixiv, xxxxii, xxiv,
456, 80, 89
see also soul, for-itself
psychic monad see monad
psychoanalysis x, xiii, xx,
xxii, xxx, 3, 16, 22, 23,
4457, 58, 613, 66
analyst as authority 50
analyst-practitioner 44, 45,
502
analytical institution 51
and politics 52
cure xxii, 47, 50
perspective of 56
purpose of xx, xxii,
44, 48
transfer xxi, 47, 4951,
56
psychosis 467
public sphere xvixvii
Pythagorean Theorem 90
118
INDEX
INDEX