(Brill S Studies in Intellectual History 187) Deborah Baumgold-Contract Theory in Historical Context-Brill Academic Publishers (2010) PDF
(Brill S Studies in Intellectual History 187) Deborah Baumgold-Contract Theory in Historical Context-Brill Academic Publishers (2010) PDF
(Brill S Studies in Intellectual History 187) Deborah Baumgold-Contract Theory in Historical Context-Brill Academic Publishers (2010) PDF
Brills Studies in
Intellectual History
General Editor
VOLUME 187
Contract Theory in
Historical Context
Essays on Grotius, Hobbes, and Locke
By
Deborah Baumgold
LEIDEN BOSTON
2010
Cover: King John signing the Magna Carta, England, 1215. 2010 Photos.com
This book is printed on acid-free paper.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data:
Baumgold, Deborah.
Contract theory in historical context : essays on Grotius, Hobbes, and Locke / by
Deborah Baumgold.
p. cm. (Brills studies in intellectual history)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-90-04-18425-1 (hardback : alk. paper) 1. Social contract. 2. Grotius, Hugo,
15831645. 3. Hobbes, Thomas, 15881679. 4. Locke, John, 16321704. I. Title.
II. Series.
JC336.B38 2010
320.11dc22
2010004394
ISSN 0920-8607
ISBN 978 90 04 18425 1
Copyright 2010 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands.
Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing,
IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission
from the publisher.
Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by
Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to
The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910,
Danvers, MA 01923, USA.
Fees are subject to change.
printed in the netherlands
CONTENTS
Preface .................................................................................................
Abbreviations .....................................................................................
ix
xvii
PART I
27
PART II
53
75
PART III
105
Chapter Six
135
viii
contents
AFTERWORD
169
Bibliography ........................................................................................
181
Index ....................................................................................................
189
PREFACE
The social contract is usually regarded as a quintessentially modern
political idea, which telegraphs the root modern principles of popular
sovereignty and governmental accountability to the people. By setting
classic contract theory in historical context, these essays present a
different view. Seventeenth-century contractarianism was a parochial
genre, they argue, that addressed problems which disappeared with the
advent of modern, electoral politics. A further theme is the parochial
nature of the texts; several essays relate Hobbess texts, in particular,
to the history of the book in the seventeenth century.
While my readings show the distance between classic social contract
theory and modern electoral politics, in doing so they illuminate
problems in the revival of contractarianism in the twentieth century.
The impulse to be skeptical of abstract, universal formulations of the
social contract, and instead to tie contract arguments to their contexts,
reflects a common critique of Rawlss initial formulation in A Theory
of Justice. As he would later acknowledge, the theory in fact builds
in his local horizon. The essays in Part I of the volume extend this
insight to Grotian, Hobbesian, and Lockean contract theories, making
the argument that they centrally address the ancien regime question
of the right to resist tyrants. Part II examines the logic of universalizing, philosophical contractarianism; these essays discuss the role of
historical facts in Hobbess political theory and the origin of modern contract theorys curious mix of voluntarist and nonvoluntarist
reasoning.
The first essay in the volume (Hobbess and Lockes Contract
Theories: Political not Metaphysical) introduces the major themes of
Parts I and IInamely, the subject, logic, and legacy of seventeenthcentury contract theory. Inspired by John Rawlss admission that his
twentieth-century contract theory builds in the horizon of modern
constitutional democracy, the essay critically examines two truisms
about seventeenth-century contract theory. The first is the stock view
that the English case is irrelevant to the logic of Leviathan and the
Second Treatise; the second, the Whiggish characterization of contract
theory as an important step in the development of democratic sovereignty. Regarding the first, I show how Hobbess and Lockes contract
preface
theories logically build in their local horizon, in the specific sense that
their political conclusions depend on introducing facts about hereditary monarchy. Second, I argue that the apparent continuity between
contract theory and modern representative democracy hides a deeper
discontinuity. Hobbesian and Lockean contract theories address an
issue peculiar to the ancien regimenamely, whether and when it
could be permissible to resist a legitimate ruler. This issue evaporated with the onset of electoral politics. Seventeenth-century contract
theory is therefore better regarded as a sophisticated approach to an
age-old issue that would soon disappear than as a stage on the road
to democracy. For reasons both of logic and substance, Hobbess and
Lockes social contracts are properly described as ancien-regime theories of politics.
The second essayPacifying Politics: Resistance, Violence, and
Accountability in Seventeenth-Century Contract Theorylooks at
another facet of these theorists preoccupation with the resistance
question: their concern with the reality of unpacified politics. Medieval and early-modern thinkers inhabited a world in which political
accountability customarily took violent forms, and it was this that gave
the resistance question its force. Working out the idea of a pacified
society was a principal problem for seventeenth-century social contract theory. Early in the century, Grotius De Jure Belli ac Pacis (1625)
defined the problem in terms that would be taken up in the subsequent theories of Hobbes and Locke. Grotius framed the idea that an
organized political society must be a pacifiedthat is, a civilsociety.
In similar vein, both Hobbes and Locke made a ban on the use of force
by private individuals the necessary and defining condition of political society. The Grotian problem inherited by Hobbes and Locke was
to specify the scope and limits of the requisite ban. Their opposing
constitutional positionsabsolutism combined with an individual
right of self-defense, in Hobbess case, versus Lockes defense of limited government and an extraordinary right of resistancerepresented
alternative solutions to the problem. Yet both were transitional figures
who envisioned pacified societies but nevertheless assumed the reality
of unpacified politics. Not until peaceful elections replaced violent
rebellion as the usual means of governmental transition would the
resistance question finally be resolved.
The essays in Part II critically examine the logic of universalistic
contract formulations. Hobbesian contract theory is commonly taken
to exemplify philosophical contractarianism, a genre devoted to gen-
preface
xi
erating abstract, universal principles, in contradistinction to a constitutional contractarian preoccupation with particular national histories
of compacts between ruler and ruled. When Hobbes Needed History
argues against the orthodox view that Hobbes never needed history.
To be sure, he intended to construct an ahistorical argument, and his
contract theory starts out this way in The Elements of Law. But political events forced him to make the argument more historical when they
brought to the fore the question, Who is sovereign?. So long as readers took for granted that England was a hereditary monarchy, Hobbes
did not need to ground his principles in historical detail. However,
when the success of the parliamentary cause dissolved that assumption, his political conclusions came logically to require the fact of the
Norman Conquest. This is made explicit in Leviathan, where Hobbes
appeals to the Conquest as the defining constitutional moment in English history. In conclusion, I argue that his historical arguments are the
strongest contractarian element in his theory because they combine
voluntarism with the idea of foundational constitutional decisions.
Voluntarist and nonvoluntarist dimensions of contract thinking are
the subject of the fourth essay, Hobbesian Absolutism and the Paradox in Modern Contractarianism. Hobbess defense of absolutism
involves the dual claims that consent is the foundation of legitimate
authority and that sovereignty is necessarily absolute. It is a paradoxical combination of claims: If absolute government is the product of
choice, how can it also be the sole possible constitution? While all of
Hobbess contractarian successors have rejected his preference for
absolutism, his dual claims have become commonplace. Since Hobbes,
contract thinkers routinely assert that people will choose their preferred constitution and that it is the only possible one. The essay examines the genesis of this paradoxical argumentation: Hobbess genius
lay in merging Grotiuss contractarian rationale with Bodins analytic
view that sovereignty must be absolute. The final section discusses
related criticisms of Rawlss contract theory, and shows that these
criticisms are also applicable to classic contract theory. Rawls inherited
a genre already flawed by the impulse to combine voluntarist with nonvoluntarist reasoning.
Part III turns from the subject and logic of classic contract theory
to the process of textual composition. The History of the Book is a
field that directs attention to the history and sociology of book and
manuscript production. Contributing to the field, the essays in this
section examine the process of composition of the three versions of
xii
preface
preface
xiii
xiv
preface
preface
xv
Chapter 6
The Difficulties of Hobbes Interpretation was originally published in
Political Theory 36/6 (Dec. 2008): 827855. 2008 Sage Publications.
Reprint authorized by Sage Publications.
ABBREVIATIONS
In the notes, abbreviations have been used for the following frequentlycited works.
SB
DJB
DC
EL(G)
EL(T)
LV
ST
Bodin, Jean Bodin. The Six Bookes of a Commonweale. Translated by R. Knolles and edited by Kenneth Douglas McRae.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1962. Reprint of
1606 ed. References cite the book, chapter, and page.
Grotius, Hugo. De Jure Belli Ac Pacis; Libri Tres. Translated
by Francis W. Kelsey. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1925. References cite the book, chapter, section, and page.
Hobbes, Thomas. De Cive: The English Version entitled in the
first edition Philosophicall Rudiments Concerning Government
and Society. Edited by Howard Warrender. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1983. References cite the chapter, section, and page.
Hobbes, Thomas. The Elements of Law Natural and Politic.
Edited by J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1994. References cite the chapter, section, and page.
Hobbes, Thomas. The Elements of Law: Natural & Politic.
Edited by Ferdinand Tnnies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1928. References cite the part, chapter, section,
and page.
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Edited by C. B. Macpherson.
London: Penguin Books/Pelican, 1968. References cite the
chapter and page.
Locke, John. The Second Treatise of Government, in Two
Treatises of Government. Edited by Peter Laslett. Revised edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960. Reprint.
New York: New American Library/Mentor, 1965. References
cite the section and page number.
PART I
CHAPTER ONE
1
John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical, Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 224.
2
John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 116.
3
Harro Hpfl and Martyn P. Thompson, The History of Contract as a Motif in
Political Thought, American Historical Review, 84 (1979): 941.
chapter one
subject,4 might not the same be the case for the theories of his great
predecessors? In Rawlsian language: Mightnt Hobbess and Lockes
contract theories be political rather than metaphysical in nature?
Granted, the standard view correspondsat least in partto the
authors intentions as well to the style of their arguments. Like the
Rawls of A Theory of Justice, Hobbes and Locke meant to be reasoning sub specie aeternitatis, as was characteristic of the natural-law tradition within which both worked (albeit in distinctsecular versus
theologicalvariants). My skeptical question concerns their grasp as
opposed to their reach. However much they intended to speak about
and to humanity, a constructivist view of philosophy suggests that
their achievement was necessarily more parochial.
To start with, it may be that the distinction between particular and
universalan argument for England versus an argument for humanitydid not strike them as self-evident in the way it does us. In terms
of intentions, they clearly meant their theories to run on two tracks.
Their universalistic arguments were meant to alter local politics,
which they conceptualized within the inherited frame of monarchy.5
If Hobbes and Locke aspired to universal philosophy, it is equally the
case that they saw themselves as reformers of an established order.
Hobbes wrote his political theory three times, starting in the late 1630s
in the waning days of Charles Is personal rule. The project began as
a brief for his patron, the prominent royalist Earl of Newcastle, in
the political debates surrounding the Short Parliament,6 and ended,
4
Whether justice as fairness can be extended to a general political conception for
different kinds of societies existing under different historical and social conditions, or
whether it can be extended to a general moral conception, or a significant part thereof,
are altogether separate questions. I avoid prejudging these larger questions one way or
another (Rawls, Justice as Fairness, 225).
5
Johann Sommerville holds a similar view of Hobbess theory: despite its veneer
of scientific detachment and its pretensions to universal validity, [it] was constructed
to support conclusions that were of the highest relevance to contemporary political
circumstances in England (Lofty science and local politics, in The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. T. Sorell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 247.
See also, Thomas Hobbes: Political Ideas in Historical Context (New York: St. Martins,
1992).
6
The first version, titled The Elements of Law, circulated in manuscript in 1640. It
was dedicated to William, Earl of Newcastle, with the explanation: Now (my Lord)
the principles fit for such a foundation [of a science of justice and policy], are those
which I have heretofore acquainted your Lordship withal in private discourse, and
which, by your command I have here put into method. . . . The ambition therefore of
this book, in seeking by your Lordships countenance to insinuate itself with those
whom the matter it containeth most nearly concerneth, is to be excused (Hobbes,
EL(T), The Epistle Dedicatory, pp. xviixviii). After his flight into exile, Hobbes
No more than Hobbes did Locke desire something other than a continuation of the monarchy, albeit a properly constituted monarchy.11
Intentions aside, the real issue raised by Rawlss admission concerns the logic of Hobbess and Lockes arguments. Is their parochial
English horizon built into the logic of their theories? The standard
interpretative view is that it is not. Even Peter Laslett, whose historical
quickly revamped the second, political section of the Elements into a Latin work, De
Cive, which appeared in a small edition in 1642 and in a second, larger edition in
1647.
7
Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 719: if a man consider that they
who submit, assist the Enemy but with part of their estates, whereas they that refuse,
assist him with the whole, there is no reason to call their Submission, or Composition an Assistance; but rather a Detriment to the Enemy. While the chapter endorses
the Engagement principle of a mutuall Relation between Protection and Obedience
(728), no mention is made of the Commonwealth.
8
Thomas Hobbes, The Autobiography of Thomas Hobbes, trans. B. Farrington,
in The Rationalist Annual, 1958, ed. H. Hawton (London: Watts & Co, 1957), 27.
9
Thomas Hobbes, Behemoth or the Long Parliament, ed. F. Tnnies, 2nd ed.
(London: Frank Cass, 1969), 204.
10
Locke, ST, 223, pp. 46263.
11
David Wootton (John Locke and Richard Ashcrafts Revolutionary Politics,
Political Studies 40 [1992]: 7998) and John Marshall (John Locke: Resistance, Religion and Responsibility [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994], 278) argue
that the Lockeanelective and contractarianversion of the ancient constitution was
a novelty of the 1680s.
chapter one
work reformed our understanding of the context of the Second Treatise, thought the English case irrelevant. As a political theorist, he
instructs in introducing the Second Treatise, Locke made no appeal
to history or tradition. Nothing in his book could be disproved by the
discovery of new evidence about what had happened in England in
1066, or 1215 or 1642.12 The first section of this essay will challenge
this standard view through a close examination of the logic leading to
Hobbess and Lockes main political conclusions. We will see how the
political conclusions of both theories depend, albeit in different ways,
on introducing facts about the historic English monarchy.
Taking seriously the parochial horizon of classic English contract
theory has the further consequence of calling into question the familiar
periodization of the genre. The social contract is customarily regarded
as a quintessentially modern political idea which telegraphs the root
modern principles of popular sovereignty and governmental accountability to the people. On this view, it hardly matters that the great
contract theories of the early-modern period were written in the context of an ancien-regime hereditary monarchy. That is not the world
to which they belong. Rejecting the principles that animated it, they
articulate ideasabout the source of legitimate authority and the relationship between ruler and ruledthat would come to be embodied in
the institutions of representative democracy of the coming age.
Jean Hampton substantiates the view, in game-theoretic terms, in
Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Lockean contract theory
and modern representative democracy share the root idea, she argues,
that rulers are hired by the people for reasons. Modern elections
simply normalize what was, in contract theory, an extraordinary right
to depose a legitimate government:
The contractarian will say that the ability of the people to make such
changes in who governs them, or in the terms of their governing, exist
in the meta political game of any state. But in modern democracies this
ability is incorporated into the political system such that it is subject to
rules of the object political game. That is, in these regimes there is an
attempt to define within the object game itself the meta political role that
people inevitably have on the social contract view.13
12
In the second section of the essay, I will argue, to the contrary, that
seventeenth-century contract theory is more accurately periodized as
an ancien-regime genre than as a modern one. Beneath the apparent
continuity between contract theory and modern representative democracy lurks a deeper discontinuity. Hobbess and Lockes contract theory address questions specific to the politics of hereditary monarchy,
namely the questions of whether and when it could be permissible
to resist a legitimate ruler. These questions evaporated with the onset
of electoral politics. Seventeenth-century contract theory is therefore
better regarded as a sophisticated approach to an age-old and soon-todisappear issue than as a stage on the road to democracy.
The Assumption of Hereditary Monarchy
It is certainly the case that Hobbess and Lockes contract logics do
not appear to be embedded in any specific political formation. Lockes
contractarian defense of the right of resistance presents this as a universal, inalienable right on the basis of several abstract arguments.
First, he makes indifferent authority the defining feature of civil society. It follows that absolute monarchy, in which subjects may not resist
their rulers, is indeed inconsistent with Civil Society, and so can be no
Form of Civil Government at all.14 Furthermore, he asserts that rational individuals would never consent to absolute government. To imagine they would is to suppose, in the oft-quoted metaphor, that Men
are so foolish that they take care to avoid what Mischiefs may be done
them by Pole-Cats, or Foxes, but are content, nay think it Safety, to be
devoured by Lions.15 Indeed, human beings are not actually free to
make a contract giving up the right of resistance, according to Lockean
theology: for Man not having such an Arbitrary Power over his own
Life, cannot give another Man such a Power over it.16
14
Locke, ST, 90, p. 369. He explains in the next section: For he being supposd
to have all, both Legislative and Executive Power in himself alone, there is no Judge
to be found, no Appeal lies open to any one, who may fairly, and indifferently, and
with Authority decide, and from whose decision relief and redress may be expected of
any Injury or Inconveniency, that may be suffered from the Prince or by his Order
(91, p. 370).
15
Locke, ST, 93, p. 372.
16
Locke, ST, 172, p. 429.
chapter one
Hobbes had tried to establish the reverse propositionthat unconditional sovereignty is a universal fact by virtue of the necessary structure of a social contract. He describes the contract as consisting in a
mutual promise, among incipient subjects, not to resist the will of the
sovereign, who cannot afterwards be held accountable by the people
because he was not a party to the contract.17 This is, Hobbes claims, a
logical, not merely stipulative, account of the nature of a social contract. Granting the nominalist assumption that the people as a corporate agent does not exist by nature, there simply cannot be a contract
between the sovereign and the people as a whole; there is no such
agent with whom an incipient sovereign could contract.18 Somewhat
harder to defend is the follow-up claim that accountability cannot be
justified via the idea of a contract between the sovereign and each individual subject. To do so, Hobbes introduces in Leviathan the idea that
each subject authorizes the sovereigns acts19 and defines authorization
as creating an identity between sovereign and subject that precludes
accountability.
He that complaineth of injury from his Soveraigne, complaineth of that
whereof he himselfe is Author; and therefore ought not to accuse any
man but himselfe; no nor himselfe of injury; because to do injury to ones
selfe, is impossible.20
17
18
19
20
granting in De Cive that this is the one thing alone I confesse in this
whole book not to be demonstrated, but only probably stated.21 Yet
the specification of a particular constitutionnamely, monarchy (or
aristocracy)turns out to be crucial to his defense of absolutism.
That defense is devoid of political force without the specification of a
monarchic constitution (or, conceivably, an aristocratic one).
This is evident in the logic of Hobbess account of sovereignty. In
democracy, the third possible form of government, the people reserve
sovereignty for themselves and therefore rulers are accountable:
If this power of the people were not dissolved, at the choosing of their
king for life, then is the people sovereign still, and the king a minister
thereof only. . . . And farther, though in the election of a king for his life,
the people grant him the exercise of their sovereignty for that time; yet
if they see cause, they may recall the same before that time.22
In principle, democracy is simply another form of absolute government. But in practice, a democracy with an executive agent is the same
thing as a monarchy holding only conditional sovereignty.
Therefore, in order to know the nature of the relationship between
ruler and ruled, and specifically to know whether or not rulers are
accountable, the location of sovereignty must be specified. The key
factual question is who controls governmental transitions. Monarchies
are either absolute or elective (meaning conditional) depending on
whether or not the people have reserved the right (and time and place)
to choose a new ruler at the death of the old.23 If it be known who
have the power to give the Soveraigntie after his death, it is known
also that the Soveraigntie was in them before.24 The effect is to make
hereditary succession (which he defines as meaning the sovereign
chooses his successor)25 the sole criterion of absolute monarchy:
21
10
chapter one
If . . . sovereignty is truly and indeed transferred, the estate or commonwealth is an absolute monarchy, wherein the monarch is at liberty, to
dispose as well of the succession, as of the possession.26
When Hobbes was first formulating his theory of politics, prior to the
Civil War, he and his readers would have taken for granted that the
specific government at issue was a hereditary monarchy. Making reservation of a popular right to choose the kings successor the necessary
condition of sovereign accountability only buttressed the assumption.
Since no one contended that the English people controlled succession
to the throne, Hobbess argument had transparent political force and
so the assumption of a monarchic constitution did not have to be
spelled out in the theory.
To the extent there was something unusual about Hobbess argument, it was the terms of his account of monarchic succession rather
than his constitutional assumption. His absolutist argument, privileging the kings will, contrasts with the traditional English subscription
to common- or natural-law views of succession.27 It is worth noticing
that both traditional accounts are incorporated into the Hobbesian
argument as subsidiary principles. Custom pertains, he says, in cases
in which the monarch fails to appoint an heir because silence is a
naturall signe of endorsement of custom. But when there is neither
testament nor pertinent custom, then it must be assumed that a ruler
wills the continuation of monarchy, and therefore natural principles
of preference (for children, first male, then female, then brothers, and
so forth) are to be followed.28 Presumably the point was to persuade
Englishmen that traditional ways of thinking about the matter actually
fit within his absolutist framework.
With the Civil War looming in the early 1640s, Hobbes took up a
new topic: the possibility of changing a government. The sitting of the
Long Parliament in November of 1640 soon led to debate over reform
of the constitution. In the spring, 1641, the Triennial Act passed, which
required the holding of a parliament every three years, and a variety
of other reform measures were enacted later the same year. Charles
26
11
Conceptually, all this adds to Hobbess contract logic is the supposition that some form of government exists, with incumbent ruler(s).
29
This discussion is drawn from J. P. Kenyon, The Stuart Constitution 16031688:
Documents and Commentary (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 191
93, quoting (193) from Charles I, The kings Declaration showing the causes of the
late Dissolution, 10 March 1629.
30
Hobbes, DC, 6.20, p. 105.
31
Hobbes, LV, 18, p. 229.
12
chapter one
Nothing in the logic presupposes any particular constitution of government; however the new stipulation told readers they were not at
liberty to change the government they had inherited. So long as readers filled in the logic with the assumption that the state at issue had
traditionally been a hereditary monarchy, the implicit political import
remained clear.
As the Civil War progressed, however, the shared horizon dissolved
and abstract contract logic was no longer adequate for Hobbess political purposes: He needed to appeal to historical facts.32 By the late
1640s, he could no longer assume that his readers would presuppose
that England was or ought to be a hereditary monarchy. To justify
their cause in the Civil War, parliamentarians advanced the radical
claim that they were sovereign by virtue of representing the people.33
Answering their claim, Leviathan focuses on the concept of representation and asserts that representation is simply a facet of sovereignty.
Where there is already erected a Soveraign Power, there can be no
other Representative of the same people, but onely to certain particular
ends, by the Soveraign limited. Still, this abstract statement left open
the constitutional possibility that the so-called representatives really
were sovereign. And ruling out this possibility required Hobbes to
specify explicitly a manifest truth about the constitution at issue: in
a Monarchy, he that had the Soveraignty from a descent of 600 years,
was alone called Soveraign, had the title of Majesty from every one of
his Subjects, and was unquestionably taken by them for their King.34
Absent the Norman Conquest, in other words, England was not necessarily a hereditary monarchy, and if it was not a hereditary monarchy,
the king might be accountable to parliament or the people.
Without the fact of the Norman Conquest or, what comes to the
same thing, his readers supposition that he was treating a hereditary monarchy, Hobbess abstract contract logic could not answer the
question, Who is sovereign?. Answering this question is basic, within
Hobbesian logic, to answering the all-important question of whether
32
13
or not rulers are accountable to the people. He could initially formulate the theory entirely abstractly only because his audience would
import to reading it the assumption that the referent was a hereditary
monarchy. Once this could no longer be taken for granted, the supposition had to be expressly built into the argument through a historically explicit referent. Despite its philosophic appearance, this is
a constitutional contractarian defense of absolute monarchy in which
the institutional inheritance of specific polities [is] most relevant and
important.
In a curious, concluding twist, Hobbes would subsequently contradict himself and reject the historical story. In Leviathans Review and
Conclusion, he puts constitutional argument aside in favor of urging submission to the powers-that-be. Here, it is possession of power
that matters rather than its history:35 As if, he writes scornfully, the
Right of the Kings of England did depend on the goodnesse of the
cause of William the Conquerour, and upon their lineall, and directest
Descent from him.36 In context, the larger point is to urge the conquering regime to put the past out of mind37 because: For to the Justification of the Cause of a Conqueror, the Reproach of the Cause of the
Conquered, is for the most part necessary: but neither of them necessary for the Obligation of the Conquered. The argument eased the way
for the submission of royalists, though at the cost of obliterating differences between the regimes (to wit, there is scarce a Common-wealth
in the world, whose beginnings can in conscience be justified).38 This
clearly answers a different question from the constitutional arguments
that had preoccupied Hobbes during the long Civil War decade: no
longer was he concerned with how government should be structured
but, instead, simply with whether it should be obeyed.39
35
It is, Hobbes says, an erroneous opinion that they will all of them justifie the
War, by which their Power was at first gotten, and whereon (as they think) their Right
dependeth, and not on the Possession (Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion,
p. 721).
36
Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 721 (first emphasis mine).
37
Therefore I put down for one of the most effectuall seeds of the Death of any
State, that the Conquerors require not onely a Submission of mens actions to them for
the future, but also an Approbation of all their actions past (Hobbes, LV, A Review
and Conclusion, pp. 72122).
38
Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 722.
39
For a contrary view of the significance of the defense of de facto authority in the
Review and Conclusion, see Kinch Hoekstra, The de facto Turn in Hobbess Political Philosophy, in Leviathan After 350 Years, ed. T. Sorrell and L. Foisneau (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 2004).
14
chapter one
Lockean Political Logic
By contrast to Hobbess constitutional arguments, Lockes core political thesisthat tyrants may be resisteddoes not require any contingent constitutional assumptions. Under no legitimate constitution is
resistance ruled out of court, in principle, in Lockean theory. Grant
the definitional assertion that absolute monarchy is inconsistent with
civil society, or the complementary propositions that rational individuals would not and could not enter into an absolutist contract; and it
follows that the people always retain ultimate sovereignty and political authority is fiduciary in nature.40 Hence it is always the case that
rulerswhatever the form of governmentmay be resisted if they act
contrary to the trust reposed in them.
Yet no one doubts that the Second Treatise is enmeshed in its ancien
regime context. The generation since Lasletts pioneer work locating
the Second Treatise in the context of the Exclusion Crisis of 167983
has seen numerous commentaries detailing Lockes parochial horizonspolitical, religious, and intellectual. Richard Ashcraft extended
Lasletts work by making the case that Locke went beyond pamphleteering to participate actively in Whig conspiracies against Charles II
and James II;41 and John Dunn led the way in showing that the seeming modern liberalism of his thought is built on premodern, theological foundations.42 In addition, we also know that Locke drew on
familiar, inherited intellectual resources to conceptualize tyranny and
resistance. The work is summarily described by Quentin Skinner as
combining traditional private-law resistance theory with a secular
justification of resistance that had been developed by Huguenot thinkers in the 1570s.43 Echoing radical Calvinists of the previous century,
Locke holds that tyrants forfeit their authority and cease to be legitimate rulers; hence they may be opposed, as any other Man, who by
force invades the Right of another.44 In support of this private law
argument, the conclusion of the Second Treatise introduces the figure
40
15
Hence the question is not whether the Second Treatise is a work of its
time but, rather, whether the historical context is built into Lockes
arguments to any significant degree. Most scholars regard the local
references as merely illustrations and applications of an abstract theory
that can otherwise stand on its own, independent of the parochial context, and think that Locke used traditional materials to build a theory
that escapes its ancien-regime horizon.48 However, consider closely the
logic of Lockes account of the right of resistance. In the climactic chapter of the Second Treatise, he tells us that resistance is justified when
a government is dissolved from within, which happens either: when
the Legislative is altered, usually through the misuse of authority; or
the Legislative, or the Prince . . . act contrary to their Trust.49 These
dual grounds recall sixteenth-century Huguenot theory, which distinguished tyrants by usurpation, who seize power that is not lawfully
45
16
chapter one
Stipulating a constitution is a necessary step in the argument insofar as the concept, misuse of authority, requires a prior definition
of the parameters of authority. Only within some constitutional
frameworksuch as that of Englanddoes it become possible to lay
out specific grounds for rebellion. He proceeds to enumerate several
scenarios which made transparent, though implicit, reference to the
reigns of the last Stuarts. The legislative is altered when the king (1)
sets up his arbitrary will in place of the laws; (2) hinders the assembly from meeting or acting freely; (3) meddles with elections, or the
electors, contrary to the public interest; or (4) delivers the nation into
subjection to a foreign power.53
On its face, the second criterionviolating the peoples trustis the
point at which Lockes argument escapes from any contextual referent. His purpose in introducing the criterion is to license rebellion in
advance of settled tyranny:
50
Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 3067; see, also, Allen, History, 32021.
Locke, ST, 213, p. 456.
52
Locke, ST, 213, p. 456.
53
Locke, ST, 21417, pp. 45658. In a passage presumably inserted after the Glorious Revolution, he adds that such a Government may be dissolved if the prince
neglects and abandons his charge (219, p. 459).
51
17
To tell People they may provide for themselves, by erecting a new Legislative, when by Oppression, Artifice, or being delivered over to a Foreign
Power, their old one is gone, is only to tell them they may expect Relief,
when it is too late, and the evil is past Cure.
The people must have the right to act earlier, when rulers violate their
trust by endeavour[ing] to invade the Property of the Subject, and to
make themselves . . . Arbitrary Disposers of the Lives, Liberties, or Fortunes of the People.54 This turns out to be a legalistic argument, making reference to both natural and civil law. The claim that government
exists to protect subjects lives, liberties, and properties is originally
founded in natural law. But, Locke says, we cannot count on natural
law being applied and applied fairly; and, therefore, positive law is
required to fill in the content of individuals protection rights.
Men unite into Societies, that they may have the united strength of the
whole Society to secure and defend their Properties, and may have standing Rules to bound it, by which every one may know what is his.55
54
55
56
57
58
18
chapter one
59
John Dunn, for instance, observes that this [is] a theory of the restoration of
an existing degree of legality rather than a conceptually primitive doctrine of tyrannicide (Political Thought, 182). The specific political doctrine which emerged from
the work of 167981 and which made its publication such a natural gesture in 1690
was merely the dignifying of the legal order of the English polity (The politics of
Locke in England and America in the eighteenth century, in Political Obligation in
its historical context [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980], 60). See also
L. G. Schwoerer, The Right to Resist: Whig Resistance Theory, 1688 to 1694, in Political Discourse in Early Modern Britain, ed. N. Phillipson and Q. Skinner (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 251.
60
Kirstie McClure, Judging Rights: Lockean Politics and the Limits of Consent
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996), 17.
61
McClure, Judging Rights, 239.
62
An exception is James Tully, Placing the Two Treatises, in Political discourse
in early modern Britain, ed. N. Phillipson and Q. Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1993), who characterizes Locke as having a constitution-enforcing
conception of rights: the primary use of rights by Locke and republican-Whig writers
is to constrain or limit the king or parliament to act within a known and recognized
constitutional structure of lawfulness (261).
63
Locke, ST, 226, p. 464.
19
64
For similar arguments, see McClure, Judging Rights, 22829 and 238 (because
the experiential judgment that grounds its expression is a cognizance of civil injury,
its necessary frame of reference for existential civil agents must be a preexisting constitutional order).
65
Dunn, Political Thought, notes a related, though smaller, argument: The appropriate form of resistance varies to some extent with the constitution of societyin
England for instance it appears not to be legitimate to attack the monarch himself.
But its rationale is the same anywhere in the world and at any point in human history (179).
66
Perhaps the connection between the general and the particular was spelled out
in more detail in the lost middle section of the Second Treatise, which may have dealt
with English constitutional history (Laslett, Introduction, 66; and Julian H. Franklin,
John Locke and the Theory of Sovereignty, paperback ed. [Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1981], 122 n. 79).
20
chapter one
Resistance: An Ancien-Regime Problem
67
David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. E. C. Mossner (Harmondsworth,
Middlesex: Penguin/Pelican, 1969), 601.
21
This is a better way of thinking about resistance, Hume argues, for several reasons, negative and positive. Of the Original Contract is wellknown for criticizing the empirical falsity of the contract metaphor:
most people simply do not imagine that rulers title to authority and
subjects duty of allegiance are founded on consent.69 Furthermore,
interest underlies the very duty emphasized by the contractarians
that of promise-keepingas well as the duty of political allegiance.
The obligation to allegiance being of like force and authority with the
obligation to fidelity, we gain nothing by resolving the one into the
other. The general interests or necessities of society are sufficient to
establish both.70
68
22
chapter one
23
S. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic 17761787 (Chapel Hill, North Carolina: University of North Carolina Press, 1969), 352.
76
Jefferson, Declaration, 241.
77
Thomas Jefferson, Letter to James Madison, January 30, 1787, in The Political
Writings of Thomas Jefferson: Representative Selections, ed. E. Dumbauld (Indianapolis, Indiana: Bobbs-Merrill, 1955), 67. See also a letter to William S. Smith in the same
year in which Jefferson exclaims, God forbid we should ever be twenty years without
such a rebellion [Shays Rebellion] and declares, the tree of liberty must be refreshed
from time to time with the blood of patriots and tyrants (Letter to William S. Smith,
November 13, 1787, in Political Writings, 68, 69).
78
Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 728.
24
chapter one
the politics of those regimes. It was essentially the same question that
confronted Englishmen in the seventeenth century and Jefferson and
the colonists in the eighteenth: When is it permissible to remove an
established government with legitimate title to govern? In order to
answer this question, whether pro or con, reasons had to be given. The
edifice of contract theory provided a philosophically well-elaborated
way of arriving at good reasons for removing (or not removing) a bad
king with a good title, in Burkes phrase.79
Humes complaint about the contractarians casuistry of resistance
indicates why the genre would become anachronistic when the center
of British politics shifted from king to parliament and, in the colonies,
the constitution of the United States institutionalized a representative
national democracy. The signal fact about representative democracy
is that it largely eliminates the need to give reasons for removing rulers from power. The question When may legitimate rulers be turned
out of office? is only problematic in representative democracies when
the normal electoral mechanism fails.80 Hamptons notion that elections normalize the extraordinary right in contract theory to depose a
legitimate government is precisely and importantly wrong. Only in the
vaguest and most general sense does the electoral mechanism incorporate the contractarians meta game into normal politics. Rebellions
and elections are certainly two mechanisms whereby the people can
depose rulers. But the contractarians meta game is fundamentally
different from the normal game of representative democracies. Unlike
subjects of hereditary monarchs, precisely what citizens of modern
democracies do not need are reasons for throwing the bums out.81
79
Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday/Anchor, 1973), 35.
80
Indeed, the American device for dealing with that eventualityimpeachment
has itself been seen as an anachronistic inheritance from ancien-regime politics. During the furor over impeachment in the Clinton administration, the New York Times
noted that it had gone out of use in Britain by the end of the eighteenth century,
replaced by parliamentary confidence votes (A. Cowell, Impeachment: What a Royal
Pain, New York Times Week in Review, 7 Feb. 1999, p. 5).
81
Franklin, John Locke, makes a similar argument. In his view, the problem that
Locke (and Lawson) solved was the justification of resistance in a mixed constitution. The modern world, except for the United States, has dispensed with executives
who are constitutionally independent of the legislature, so the problem is now largely
irrelevant; and their solution is outdated even in the United States because elections
and impeachment now take the place of resistance. Hence, he concludes: Lockes
and Lawsons solution to the problem of removal is no longer required for a mixed
constitution (12324).
25
All Whig statements about resistance, Schwoerer observes, were derived from
some form of a theory of contract (Right to Resist, 238).
83
The House of Commons resolution, to which the Lords assented, stated That
King James the Second, having endeavoured to subvert the Constitution of the Kingdom, by breaking the Original Contract between king and people, and . . . having
violated the fundamental Laws, and having withdrawn himself out of this kingdom,
has abdicated the Government, and that the throne is thereby become vacant (T. P.
Slaughter, Abdicate and Contract in the Glorious Revolution, Historical Journal
24 [1981]: 330). For differing assessments of the significance of contractarian thinking
in the Convention debates, compare Slaughter with J. P. Kenyon, The Revolution of
1688: Resistance and Contract, in Historical Perspectives: Studies in English Thought
and Society, ed. N. McKendrick (London: Europa, 1974), esp. 4750.
26
chapter one
found, say, in Locke, Rousseau, and Kant. In order to do this we are not
to think of the original contract as one to enter a particular society or to
set up a particular form of government.84
84
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1971), 11.
85
See Rawls, Theory, 2729.
CHAPTER TWO
PACIFYING POLITICS:
RESISTANCE, VIOLENCE, AND ACCOUNTABILITY IN
SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY CONTRACT THEORY
The right to resist tyrants is one of the great resolved issues in political
philosophy. For half a millennium after Aquinas this was as contentious a matter as the right to abortion is now in the United States. Yet
the issue evaporated after the eighteenth century. The accountability
of governments to the people and, in the extreme, a popular right
of rebellion are political truisms across the world today. The Whiggish view that this marks the progress of liberty and the recession of
hidebound conservatism mistakes evaluation for explanation. Besides
which, it is dubious whether a secular decline in conservatism is a
conspicuous feature of modernity. Resistance ceased to be contentious
not because the world awakened to the correct view but because the
issues in question themselves changed.1
A key development, which has been paid more attention in historical
sociology than in histories of political thought, lies in shifting norms
about the use of violence in domestic politics. Inhabitants of longpacified modern societies assume that domestic political conflict will
not commonly take a violent turn and sharply distinguish the extraordinary right of rebellion from ordinary politics. By contrast, both sides
in medieval debates over the right of resistance took for granted that
the principles of conditional authority and accountable government
implied and legitimized violent conflict. This is evident, for example,
in the defense of resistance offered by the conciliarist Jean Gerson
(13631429). Writing at the time of the Great Schism in the Church,
Gerson maintained it is a mistake to claim that kings are free from
any obligations towards their subjects; if they act unjustly towards
their subjects, and if they continue in their evil behavior, then it is time
to apply that law of nature which prescribes that we may repel force
1
For the argument that doctrines must be understood in the context of the questions they are meant to answer, see R. G. Collingwood, An Autobiography (London:
Oxford University Press, paperback ed., 1970).
28
chapter two
with force.2 The same assumption that accountability implied political violence underpinned the classic case for nonresistance, which was
grounded on the Pauline statement in Romans XIII: the power that
is everywhere is ordained of God. Hence the fact that the rulers are
wicked and unjust does not excuse disorder and rebellion; outrage is
not to be resisted, but endured.3 In the absence of peaceful, electoral
mechanisms for holding rulers to account, it was realistic to suppose
that the only available responses to governmental malfeasance were
forcible resistance or passive endurance.
With the benefit of hindsight, it is apparent that the resistance
question conflated two, now largely separate, issues: the constitutional
relationship between ruler and ruled; and private warfare, meaning
the use of force without sovereign authority. The latter was a ubiquitous feature of medieval society, encompassing all manner of the
use of force by private individuals from vigilante justice to dueling to
political violence.4 The constitutional question of rulers accountability would cease to be an issue only with the achievement, in practice
and in theory, of a ban on private warfare, and particularly political
violence, in all but extraordinary circumstances. Only in the context
of a pacified society does the principle of governmental accountability
lose its fearsome aspect and become an unremarkable, uncontentious
feature of normal politics.
Working out the idea of a pacified society was a principal problem of seventeenth-century social contract theory. My purpose here
is to show, more specifically, that this was a shared preoccupation
of Hobbesian and Lockean contract theories. Despite their opposing
stands on resistance, Hobbes and Locke were in this significant respect
engaged in a common intellectual project. Furthermore, theirs was a
2
Jean Gerson, Ten Highly Useful Considerations for Princes and Governors (Antwerp, 1706), quoted in Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought,
vol. II, The Age of Reformation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 126
27.
3
The first and third quotations are from Martin Luther, Secular Authority: To
What Extent It Should Be Obeyed (1523), in Martin Luther: Selections from His Writings, ed. J. Dillenberger (Garden City, NY: Doubleday/Anchor, 1961), 366, 388. The
second is from Luther, Admonition to Peace (1524), quoted in Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 19.
4
Two enlightening discussions of private warfare in the medieval period are J. L.
Holzgrefe, The Origins of Modem International Relations Theory, Review of International Studies 15 (1989); and Robert Bartlett, Mortal Enmities: The Legal Aspect
of Hostility in the Middle Ages(manuscript, University of Chicago, n.d.).
pacifying politics
29
5
I am indebted to the work of Richard Tuck for this thesis and for much of my
understanding of Grotian theory. In the past decade, he and Knud Haakonssen have
done much to revive Grotiuss reputation as a seminal moral and political philosopher. De Jure Belli Ac Pacis, which has long been narrowly considered a founding treatise in modern international law, is now being recognized as a work that shaped two
centuries of moral and political philosophy. See Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their
Origin and Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); Grotius,
Carneades and Hobbes, Grotiana 4 (1983): 4362; The Modern School of Natural
Law, in The Languages of Political Theory in Early-Modern Europe, ed. A. Pagden
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987); and Haakonssen, Hugo Grotius and
the History of Political Thought, Political Theory 13 (1985): 23965.
6
Hobbes, DC, 6.13, p. 97. See also EL(T), II.1.5, p. 85: Where any subject hath
right by his own judgment and discretion to make use of his force; it is to be understood that every man hath the like, and consequently that there is no commonwealth
at all established.
7
Locke, ST, 89, p. 368.
30
chapter two
8
The Roman and canon law roots of private law doctrine and the development
of the doctrine by Lutheran and Calvinist thinkers are treated extensively in Skinner,
Foundations, vol. II, esp. 12427, 198204, 21724, 23435.
9
Quoted by Grotius, DJB, I.3.2, p. 91.
10
Grotius, DJB, Prolegomena, p. 21; see also I.1.2, p. 33.
11
Grotius rejects the distinction, which was central to Protestant resistance theory,
between subordinate officials and ordinary citizens. To his mind, it is erroneous to
pacifying politics
31
by him who has lawful authority to wage it)12 does not, for Grotius,
mark the division between illegitimate and legitimate violence. The
power to make war should be reserved to the king: but this, it must
be understood, refers to external war.13 The complementary assumptionthat private warfare can be legitimateframes Grotiuss consideration of popular sovereignty and governmental accountability: these
figure as concepts relevant to specifying when force may legitimately
be used by private individuals against the government.
Breaking from the theistic horizons of medieval thinking on the
subject, Grotius meant to devise a natural law theory that would
have a degree of validity even if we should concede . . . that there is
no God, or that the affairs of men are of no concern to Him.14 For
a substitute, he turned, in neo-Stoic fashion, to principles of nature
and named self-preservation as the first principle and right reason,
whose object is moral goodness, as the second. These are principles
that govern the use of force generally. War is lawful, he stipulates,
when its end and aim is the preservation of life and limb and when
it does not conflict with the purpose of society, which is to safeguard
individuals rights.15
On this basis, Grotius at the outset in De Jure Belli Ac Pacis conceives
the question of the legitimacy of private warfare as a problem requiring
balancing the right of self-defense with social utility. On the one hand,
the root principle of self-preservation licenses (some instances of )
private warfare: private wars in some cases may be waged lawfully
because the use of force to ward off injury is not in conflict with
the law of nature.16 How far, on the other hand, is the exercise of
the natural right of self-defense consistent with the requirements of
organized society? To attack this key question, Grotius starts with the
relatively straightforward case of criminal violence. Arguing against
the view that the establishment of public tribunals overrides the right
hold that the latter may not resist tyranny but the former have a right and duty to do
so (DJB, I.4.6, p. 146).
12
Grotius, DJB, I.3.1, p. 91. The classificatory scheme also includes mixed warfare: that which is on one side public, on the other side private.
13
Grotius, DJB, I.4.13, p. 158; see also I.3.4, p. 97.
14
Grotius, DJB, Prolegomena, p. 13. Cf. Haakonssen, Hugo Grotius, 24849,
who argues that this proposition drew on traditional scholastic philosophy and was
not, in other words, a novel thought.
15
Grotius, DJB, I.2.12, 45, pp. 5153.
16
Grotius, DJB, I.3.1, p. 91. See also II.1.16, p. 184, and, generally, II.1.37, pp.
17275.
32
chapter two
of self-defense,17 he observes that even within organized political systems individuals retain the right to use defensive force in situations
of extreme and imminent peril: By the laws of all peoples known to
us the person who in peril of his life has by means of arms defended
himself against an assailant is adjudged innocent.18
Private warfare in the form of political resistance was a more complex matter, which Grotius could more clearly define than resolve. His
insight lay in seeing that the issue was one of means as well as ends:
that is, it concerns the admissibility of violence in civil society as well
as the constitutional and moral relationship between ruler and ruled.
Thus, in the first instance, Grotius defines resistance as an analytic
issue concerning the necessary attributes of a state.19 While by nature
all men have the right of resisting in order to ward off injury, this
cannot be taken to license a promiscuous right of resistance:20
As civil society was instituted in order to maintain public tranquillity,
the state forthwith acquires over us and our possessions a greater right,
to the extent necessary to accomplish this end. The state, therefore, in
the interest of public peace and order, can limit that common right of
resistance. That such was the purpose of the state we cannot doubt, since
it could not in any other way achieve its end. If, in fact, the right of resistance should remain without restraint, there will no longer be a state,
only a non-social horde.21
17
Cf., e.g., The Trew Law of Free Monarchies (1598), in which James I rebuts the
private law brief for resistance by arguing that private citizens in organized societies
may not use violence to defend themselves: if it be not lawful to a private man to
revenge his private injury upon his private adversary (since God has only given the
sword to the magistrate) how much less is it lawful to the people, or any part of them
(who all are but private men, the authority being always with the magistrate, as 1 have
already proved), to take upon them the use of the sword, whom to it belongs not,
against the public magistrate, whom to only it belongs. In David Wootton, ed., Divine
Right and Democracy (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1986), 101.
18
Grotius, DJB, I.3.2, p. 92.
19
Grotius also reproduces the traditional, Ciceronian definition of a state as a
complete association of free men, joined together for the enjoyment of rights and
for their common interest (DJB, I.1.14, p. 44).
20
The latter phrase is taken from the translation of the passage in Barbeyracs 1738
edition, as quoted by Tuck, Natural Rights Theories, 7879. In this version, the conclusion reads, if that promiscuous Right of Resistance should be allowed, there would be
no longer a State, but a Multitude without Union.
21
Grotius, DJB, I.4.2, p. 139. See also I.4.4, p. 143: Now beyond doubt the most
important element in public affairs is the constituted order of bearing rule and
rendering obedience. . . . This truly cannot coexist with individual licence to offer
resistance.
pacifying politics
33
22
34
chapter two
the strong analytic proposition, which Hobbes will defend, that sovereignty is necessarily unconditional. It is also possible, Grotius held, for
there to be a historical contract between ruler and ruled providing for
governmental accountability, retained popular rights, and therefore a
right of resistance:
If rulers [are] responsible to the people, whether such power was conferred at the beginning or under a later arrangement, [then] if such rulers transgress against the laws and the state, not only can they be resisted
by force, but, in case of necessity, they can be punished with death.27
For he who alienates his own right can by agreement limit the right
transferred.28
On its face, this last contractarian argument contradicts the previous analytic proposition that a promiscuous right of resistance is
per se incompatible with civil society. Either nonresistance is a constitutive attribute of organized political society or it is a circumstantial
norm, varying between states. Furthermore, both analytic and contractarian lines of argument fit uneasily with the third pertinent Grotian
conceptthe natural right of self-defense. To say that extreme and
imminent peril licenses defensive violence, in the case of individuals
and of nations, cuts away at the analytic proposition that a promiscuous right of resistance is inimical to civil society and runs counter
to the contractarian argument that nations may consent to absolute
subjection.29
We can see, with the perspective of hindsight, that Grotiuss mistake
lay in conflating several different issues under the single heading of the
resistance question. The apparent inconsistencies between his arguments disappear if their several topics are distinguished. Whereas the
plainly to transfer to him the legal right to govern, retaining no vestige of that right for
itself? The influence of this line of argument on British political thinking throughout
the seventeenth century is discussed by Tuck, Natural Rights Theories.
27
Grotius, DJB, I.3.8, p. 156.
28
Grotius, DJB, I.4.14, p. 159. This follows the stipulation: If in the conferring of
authority it has been stated that in a particular case the king can be resisted, . . . some
natural freedom of action . . . has been reserved and exempted from the exercise of
royal power.
29
In De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo (1672), Samuel Pufendorf attempted
to reconcile the natural right and contractarian Grotian arguments by distinguishing between defensive resistance when a prince has become an enemy and forcible
resistance to rulers who have not ruled in accordance with [the peoples] desires.
The former but not the latter is permissible even in nations that have entered into an
absolutist contract. De Jure Naturae . . ., trans. C. H. Oldfather and W. A. Oldfather
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1934), bk. VII, ch. 8, 6, p. 1110.
pacifying politics
35
36
chapter two
30
The just quoted passage from Hobbes, DC, 5.7, p. 88, echoes EL(T), I.19.10, p. 81.
Deborah Baumgold, Hobbess Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), chs. 23.
32
It is worth notice that Hobbess formulation of the concept of authorization also
has Grotian roots. Cf. LV, 17, p. 227: every one [is] to owne, and acknowledge himselfe to be Author of whatsoever he that so beareth their Person, shall Act, or cause
to be Acted; and Grotius, DJB, I.4.4, p. 141: Under subjection the Apostle includes
the necessity of nonresistance. . . . For the acts to which we have given our authorization we make our own.
33
This interpretation is cogently argued by Hanna Pitkin, Hobbess Concept of
RepresentationII, American Political Science Review 58 (1964): 90914. See also
David Gauthier, The Logic of Leviathan: The Moral and Political Theory of Thomas
Hobbes (Oxford: Clarendon, 1969), ch. 4; and Raymond Polin, Politique et Philosophie
chez Thomas Hobbes (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1953), ch. 10.
34
Hobbes, DC, 5.7, p. 88; see EL(T), I.19.10, p. 81.
31
pacifying politics
37
35
38
chapter two
involves contrasting a primitive natural right of war with the narrower right of self-defense retained by individuals in civil society. As
long as there is no caution had from the invasion of others, Hobbes
explains in De Cive, there remains to every man that same primitive
Right of selfe-defence, by such means as either he can or will make use
of (that is) a Right to all things, or the Right of warre.38 This juridical assumption, he expressly stipulates, is a necessary condition of the
state of nature being a state of war:
Seeing then to the offensiveness of mans nature one to another, there
is added a right of every man to every thing whereby one man invadeth
with right, and another with right resisteth; and men live thereby in
perpetual diffidence, and study how to preoccupate each other; the estate
of men in this natural liberty is the estate of war.39
It follows, then, that the first precept of natural law is that every man
divest himself of the right he hath to all things by nature.40
By the time he wrote De Cive, Hobbes had seen that divestiture
of the right to all things is consistent with retention of a right of
self-defense and is the basis for the states monopoly on the right to
punish. One of the principal revisions of the theory between the first
and second versions is the insertion, in the discussion of possible contracts, of the caveat: no man is obligd by any Contracts whatsoever
not to resist him who shall offer to kill, wound, or any other way hurt
his Body. When a man is arrivd to this degree of fear, we cannot
expect but he will provide for himself either by flight, or fight. Neither
is it necessary, Hobbes continues, that subjects should promise the
sovereign, If I doe it not, though you should offer to kill me, I will
not resist.41 Civil society does not require individuals to renounce the
right of resistance in self-defense; it merely requires renunciation of
the aggressive right to kill, which becomes a state monopoly.42
38
Hobbes, DC, 5.1, p. 85. See also EL(T), II.1.5, p. 85 (the passage is quoted in note
6 above).
39
Hobbes, EL(T), I.14.11, pp. 5556 (emphasis added). The idea that natural right is
a main cause of war in the state of nature is discussed by Franois Tricaud, Hobbess
Conception of the State of Nature from 1640 to 1651: Evolution and Ambiguities, in
Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes, ed. G. A. J. Rogers and A. Ryan (Oxford: Clarendon,
1988), 11417.
40
Hobbes, EL(T), I.15.2, p. 58.
41
Hobbes, DC, 2.18, pp. 5859.
42
Pufendorf adopted the distinction in De Jure Naturae: the right of war which
accompanies a natural state is taken away from individuals in a commonwealth;
pacifying politics
39
For in the meer state of nature, if you have a mind to kill, that state it
selfe affords you a Right. . . . But in a Civill State, where the Right of life,
and death, and of all corporall punishment is with the Supreme; that
same Right of killing cannot be granted to any private person.43
Next, Hobbes develops the distinction between defensive and aggressive violence as a matter of defending oneself versus defending others:
Neither need the Supreme himselfe contract with any man patiently
to yeeld to his punishment, but onely this, that no man offer to defend
others from him.44 This formulation closes the private law loophole for rebellion in Grotian theory arising from the stipulation that
extreme and imminent peril overrides the law of nonresistance in
the cases of both criminal attack and tyranny. By distinguishing selfdefense from defending others, Hobbes separates the two casespermissible self-defense and impermissible political resistance.45 Thus, in
discussing the liberty of subjects in Leviathan, he makes a point of
noting that men who have resisted the Soveraign Power unjustly
nonetheless are entitled to bear arms subsequently in self-defense.46
What Hobbes has done, in effect, is to limit the purchase of the right
of self-preservation by defining the right more narrowly and literally
40
chapter two
than had Grotius. It is specifically a right of self-defense, and Hobbesian nominalism rules out conceiving of a corporate or national self to
be protected from tyrannous government. For these reasons, political
resistance is not an exercise of the private sword that is covered by the
right of self-defense.
Subtracting Hobbess medieval equation of conditional sovereignty
with a license for private warfare, his position in De Cive comes down
to the proposition that civil society requires a state monopoly on the
right to kill and ban on the use of the private sword except for individual self-defense. To transform this fairly unexceptional view, which
is compatible with a range of political constitutions, into a brief for
absolutism requires introducing further empirical assumptions. Logically, the following brief for absolutism is a contingent argument and
not an integral part of the nonresistance contract logic. First, as we
have seen, the brief for unconditional sovereignty requires conflating
resistance to established government with private warfare and therefore excludes the empirical possibility of nonviolent political conflict.
Second, to support the principle of unified sovereignty, Hobbes introduces the contingent proposition that limited and divided sovereignty
produces private warfare: In every commonwealth where particular
men are deprived of their right to protect themselves, there resideth
an absolute sovereignty.47 Proponents of limited monarchy deceive
themselves, he explains, in thinking they have made a commonwealth, in which it is unlawful for any private man to make use of his
own sword for his security.48 Similarly, the division of sovereignty
either worketh no effect, to the taking away of simple subjection, or
introduceth war; wherein the private sword hath place again.49 In
sum, conditional sovereignty and divided sovereignty license private
warfare because they institutionalize political conflict; absolutism is
therefore the only political constitution that will support civil society.
It is a parochial, medieval brief, which rests on the supposition that
political conflict will escalate into armed conflict.
Indeed, there is a curious discrepancy between the nonresistance
social contract and this defense of absolutism, which is indicative of
Hobbess transitional position in the history of ideas. The contract
47
48
49
pacifying politics
41
codifies the modern norm banning private warfare, whereas his arguments for absolutism presuppose precisely the absence of this norm.
Thus, on the one hand, Hobbes envisions a civil or pacified society,
but, on the other, he assumes the reality of uncivil, violent politics.
The Lockean Solution
Force, or a declared design of force upon the Person
of another, where there is no common Superior on
Earth to appeal to for relief, is the State of War.
Locke, Second Treatise of Government, 19
Starting with the very suppositions about violence, civil society, and
governmental accountability that underpinned Grotian and Hobbesian absolutism, Locke produced the definitive modern brief for the
right of resistance, popular sovereignty, and the accountability of
government to the people. To stand late medieval absolutism on its
head, we will see, he conceptualized the right of rebellion in a way
that defused and tamed the resistance question. But the lineaments of
modern, pacified politics are only incompletely sketched in the Second
Treatise. Locke, like Hobbes, is a transitional figure, who envisions
pacified society, yet by and large continues to associate governmental
accountability with violent political conflict.
Two root assumptions that Locke held in common with Grotius
and Hobbes were that the use of force by private individuals is inimical to civil society and that the principle of governmental accountability licenses violent conflict and rebellion. As I noted at the outset,
his definition of political or civil society echoes Hobbess in making
renunciation by private individuals of the right to use force the defining feature of civil society:
There, and there only is Political Society, where every one of the Members hath quitted this natural Power, resignd it up into the hands of the
Community in all cases that exclude him not from appealing for Protection to the Law established by it.50
50
Locke, ST, 87, p. 367. See also 89, pp. 36869, and 171, p. 428.
42
chapter two
From the insecurity of the state of nature, it follows for Locke that
renunciation of the right of punishment and creation of a state monopoly on that right are the foundation of civil society and government:
Tis this makes them so willingly give up every one his single power
of punishing to be exercised by such alone as shall be appointed to it
amongst them; and by such Rules as the Community, or those authorised by them to that purpose, shall agree on. And in this we have the
original right and rise of both the Legislative and Executive Power, as well
as of the Governments and Societies themselves.54
Yet Locke also, famously, defends the right of the people to remove
a tyrannous government that violates the trust of the people. Where
Hobbes translated the Grotian absolutist contract from a contingent
into a necessary proposition, Locke universalizes the Grotian accountability contract: rulers are always, not merely sometimes, responsible
to the people.
The Legislative being only a Fiduciary Power to act for certain ends,
there remains still in the People a Supream Power to remove or alter
51
Locke, ST, 171, p. 428. The idea that individuals in the state of nature possess the
right to use the sword to enforce natural law was developed by Jacques Almain in an
early sixteenth-century conciliarist tract: see Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 11819.
52
Locke, ST, 20, p. 322.
53
Hobbes, LV, 13, pp. 18485.
54
Locke, ST, 127, p. 397.
pacifying politics
43
the Legislative, when they find the Legislative act contrary to the trust
reposed in them.55
The Grotian-Hobbesian absolutist contract is untenable for two reasons. As Gods creatures, we are not at liberty to consent to slavery
or to absolute subjection, and self-preservation is, therefore, a Fundamental, Sacred, and unalterable Law.56 To arrive at the conclusion
that tyrannous governments may be forcibly resisted, Locke only needs
to add (following Grotius but contra Hobbes) the private law principle
that the inalienable right of self-preservation applies to societies as well
as to individuals.57
Nonetheless, he agrees with Grotius and with Hobbes that the right
of rebellion is antithetical to political society: this Power of the People to defend themselves against tyrannous government can never
take place till the Government be dissolved.58 At this crucial point
in the argument, Locke reverses and advances on the arguments of
his absolutist predecessors by conceptualizing the right of rebellion
as an extraordinary right, which comes into force only in the special
circumstances of a state of War:59
Whenever the Legislators endeavour to take away, and destroy the
Property of the People, or to reduce them to Slavery under Arbitrary
Power, they put themselves into a state of War with the People, who
are thereupon absolved from any farther Obedience, and are left to the
common Refuge, which God hath provided for all Men, against Force
and Violence.60
55
44
chapter two
The introduction of the technical concept of a state of war, as a juridical condition distinct from civil society and from the state of nature,
was a simple and brilliant conceptual move. It effectively defused the
resistance issue by distinguishing the right of rebellion from private
warfare. The right of rebellion does not violate the ban on private warfare that defines civil society because it is an extraordinary right that
obtains only when tyrannous rulers have themselves subverted civil
society.61
The idea of a state of war was a natural extension of private law
resistance doctrine and, in effect, renders that doctrine compatible with
the absolutists position that resistance is inconsistent with civil society. Before Locke, other private law thinkers had described tyrants as
rebelling against the people,62 and this was a stock argument of radical
Whigs in the early 1680s.63 From this point it was a short step to define
the resistance situation as a special juridical circumstance. Nor was
Locke alone in using the idea of a state of war.64 In a 1657 diatribe
against Cromwell, Killing Noe Murder, for example, Edward Sexby had
characterized a usurper as being in a state of war with every man;
therefore everything is lawful against him that is lawful against an
open enemy, whom every private man has a right to kill.65
61
Locke, ST, 226, p. 464: For when Men by entering into Society and Civil Government, have excluded force, and introduced Laws for the preservation of Property,
Peace, and Unity amongst themselves; those who set up force in opposition to the
Laws, do Rebellare, that is, bring back again the state of War, and are properly Rebels.
See also 227, p. 464, and 212, pp. 45556.
62
Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 2012, discusses Luthers use of the argument in a
Warning to His Dear German People (1531): tyrants are the real rebels, since they are
nothing but assassins and traitors, refusing to submit to government and law, and
are thus much closer to the name and quality which is termed rebellion than those
whom they accuse of being in rebellion against their supposed authority.
63
Ashcraft, Revolutionary Politics, 19597, 392405; and Revolutionary Politics
and Lockes Two Treatises of Government, Political Theory 8 (1980): 46974.
64
Ashcraft (Revolutionary Politics, 444; see also Revolutionary Politics, 236)
claims the concept, along with other key Lockean terms, first appears in James Tyrells
Patriarcha non monarcha (1681). He also quotes the use of the phrase in a 1682 tract
by Robert Ferguson: whensoever laws cease to be a security unto men, they will be
sorely tempted to apprehend themselves cast into a state of war, and justified in having recourse to the best means they can for their shelter and defense (Revolutionary
Politics, 322).
65
William Allen [Edward Sexby], Killing Noe Murder: Briefly Discourst in Three
Quaestions (1657), in Wootton, ed., Divine Right, 37475. My thanks to Alan Houston
for bringing this point to my attention.
pacifying politics
45
66
67
68
69
46
chapter two
If violence is inimical to civil society and if civil society requires conditional political authority, it follows that there needs to be an ordinary,
institutionalized, and nonviolent process of holding governments to
account: in short, civil society requires peaceful electoral politics. This
final step in the development of the idea of pacified politics is only intimated in the Second Treatise. It is suggested by the statement that parliamentary sovereignty is the one form of government consistent with
civil society: the People . . . could never be safe nor at rest, nor think
themselves in Civil Society, till the Legislature was placed in collective
Bodies of Men, call them Senate, Parliament, or what you please.74 Yet
70
Locke, ST, 90, p. 369; see also 94, pp. 37274, and 174, p. 421. Cf. Hobbes,
who argues from the absence of an authority to adjudicate conflicts between ruler and
ruled to the absurdity of conditional sovereignty: there is in this case, no Judge to
decide the controversie: it returns therefore to the Sword again; and every man recovereth the right of Protecting himselfe by his own strength, contrary to the designe they
had in the Institution (LV, 18, pp. 23031).
71
Locke, ST, 137, p. 405; see also 93, p. 372.
72
Locke, ST, 228, p. 465.
73
Locke, ST, 230, pp. 46667.
74
Locke, ST, 94, p. 373. It is worth noticing, however, that Locke bases the statement on the principle that rulers must be subject to law, rather than on the requirements of civil society: By [this] means every single person became subject, equally
with other the meanest Men, to those Laws, which he himself, as part of the Legislative had established.
pacifying politics
47
Locke expressly grants that popular consent may underwrite hereditary monarchy as well as elective monarchy in which authority is
held for life.75 Rebellion being the sole mechanism of governmental
accountability in these latter forms of government, it cannot be said to
be a Lockean principle that a legitimate political society must have an
electoral political system (and a peaceful electoral system at that).76
At the most, what can be said is that Locke preferred parliamentary sovereignty,77 that he counted it among the tyrannous acts that
dissolve government for a prince to interfere with parliamentary
elections,78 and, arguably, that he conceived of electoral politics and
violent rebellion as alternative mechanisms for holding government
to account. Richard Ashcraft has made the case that radical Whigs
in the period, including Locke, presupposed the electoral alternative
and came to espouse rebellion only after the failure of parliamentary
efforts to exclude the Duke of York from the throne.79 Perhaps this is
Lockes meaning in an elusive remark at the conclusion of the Second
Treatise:
If any Men find themselves aggrieved . . . who so proper to Judge as
the Body of the People. . .? But if the Prince, or whoever they be in the
Administration, decline that way of Determination, the Appeal then lies
no where but to Heaven.80
75
48
chapter two
81
Mark A. Kishlansky, Parliamentary Selection: Social and Political Choice in Early
Modern England (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), esp. 18283, 198
99, and 22630.
pacifying politics
49
82
J. H. Plumb, The Origins of Political Stability: England 16751725 (Boston:
Houghton Mifflin, 1967), xviii; see also 105.
PART II
CHAPTER THREE
1
Harro Hpfl and Martyn P. Thompson, The History of Contract as a Motif in
Political Thought, American Historical Review, 84 (1979): 941.
2
Hobbes, LV, 19, pp. 24041. Behemoth, Hobbess post-Restoration history of
the Civil War, opens with the same assertion that the government of England was
monarchical . . . by right of a descent continued above six hundred years (Behemoth
or The Long Parliament, ed. F. Tnnies and intro. M. M. Goldsmith, 2nd ed. [London:
Frank Cass, 1969], 1).
54
chapter three
Such references are usually regarded as merely an illustrative application of the theory. They tie down the abstract social contract story in
English history, but are otherwise ad hoc and of no theoretical consequence.3 Such dismissal slights the possibility that Hobbess political
analysis might rest, at least to some degree, on the constitutional fact
of an actual compact.4
No one has ever doubted that he, along with everyone else, presupposed England to be a hereditary monarchy. When Hobbes initially
framed his theory of politics, prior to the outbreak of the Civil War,
the supposition did not need defense. But Parliamentarians subsequent claims to a share in sovereignty, or the entirety of it, changed
the agenda. These claims could not entirely be rebutted with abstract
contractarian argument: to do that, Hobbes had to introduce a Grotian account of English constitutional history. To the extent the theory
came to require this historical dimension, it became less an explanation of the structure of sovereignty everywhere and always, and more
a contingent account of the constitution of a particular nation-state.
Hobbess Problem
Prior to the Civil War, when Hobbes was composing the first version
of his political theory, The Elements of Law (1640), no one dreamt that
the location of sovereignty in England could be a contentious matter. England was a hereditary monarchy. The pertinent question was
whether or not sovereignty was absolute.5 Hobbes set himself to answer
3
J. G. A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law: A Reissue with
a Retrospect (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 165; Quentin Skinner,
History and Ideology in the English Revolution, Historical Journal 8 (1965): 161,
168, 178.
4
David Gauthier asserts that a full contractarian understanding of political institutions and practices requires more than a hypothetical constitution: it requires a
constitutional fact (Constituting Democracy, The Lindley Lecture, University of
Kansas, 1989, 21 n. 17).
5
Hobbes so described the pertinent issue in retrospective autobiographical remarks
on the composition of The Elements of Law. When the Parliament sat, that began
in April 1640, and was dissolved in May following, and in which many points of the
regal power, which were necessary for the peace of the kingdom, and the safety of
his Majestys person, were disputed and denied, Mr. Hobbes wrote a little treatise in
English, wherein he did set forth and demonstrate, that the said power and rights were
inseparably annexed to the sovereignty; which sovereignty they did not then deny to
55
that question with a nonhistorical contract argument about the necessary structure of sovereignty everywhere and always. In effect, it was
an effort to wed two extant defenses of absolutism: Bodins assertion
that sovereignty is necessarily absolute and Grotiuss contractarian
argument that it is possible to consent to slavery and absolutism.
For the doctrine of the desirability and, indeed, necessity of absolute sovereignty, Bodins Rpublique (1576, and in English translation, 1606) was a standard authority in early-Stuart England.6 Bodin
famously held that sovereign authority is the defining characteristic of
a state,7 and that sovereignty is both unconditional and unified. Sovereignty is the greatest power to command, meaning the sovereign is
bound only by natural and divine law and accountable only to God.8
He saw divided sovereignty as impossible by definition, and undesirable in any case.9
The Elements of Law invokes Bodin as an authority on absolutism.
It was rare for Hobbes even to mention writers with whom he agreed,
yet here he goes so far as to quote the Rpublique. The subject is the
impossibility of divided sovereignty: if there were a commonwealth,
wherein the rights of sovereignty were divided, we must confess with
Bodin, Lib. II chap. I. De Republica, that they are not rightly to be
called commonwealths, but the corruption of commonwealths.10 In
addition, Hobbes reproduces a related Bodinian distinction between
(unified) sovereignty and (divided) administration;11 and paraphrases
be in the King; but it seems understood not, or would not understand that inseparability (Considerations upon the Reputation, Loyalty, Manners, and Religion, of
Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury,
ed. Sir William Molesworth, vol. IV [London: J. Bohn, 1840], 414).
6
Bodins influence on English political thought is detailed by J. H. M. Salmon, The
French Religious Wars in English Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959);
and George L. Mosse, The Struggle for Sovereignty in England (New York: Octagon,
1968), ch. 2.
7
A commonweale is a lawfull gouernment of many families, and of that which
vnto them in common belongeth, with a puissant soueraigntie (Bodin, SB, I.1, p. 1).
8
Bodin, SB, I.8, pp. 8489.
9
Wherefore such states as wherein the rights of soueraigntie are diuided, are not
rightly to bee called Commonweales, but rather the corruption of Commonweales
and, anyway, divided authority leads to endlesse sturres and quarrels, for the superioritie (Bodin, SB, II.1, p. 194).
10
Hobbes, EL(T), II.8.7, p. 137. The relevant passage in the Republique is quoted
in the previous note.
11
Hobbes, EL(T), II.1.17, p. 90. In this discussion, Hobbes cites the examples Bodin
had given of Rome and Venice (SB, II.1, pp. 18890; see also II.7, pp. 24950).
56
chapter three
Hobbes must shortly have realized that this last point marked a crucial
disagreement with Bodin:16 the notion of a mutual contract between
ruler and ruled, carrying obligations on both sides, was inconsistent
with a full-fledged defense of absolutism.17
12
For if one part should have power to make the laws for all, they would by their
laws, at their pleasure, forbid others to make peace or war, to levy taxes, or to yield
fealty and homage without their leave (Hobbes, EL(T), II.8.7, p. 137). Bodin had written, the nobilitie which should haue the power to make the lawes for all . . . would by
their lawes at their pleasure forbid others to make peace or warre, or to leuie taxes, or
to yeeld fealtie and homage without their leaue (SB, II.1, p. 194).
13
Hobbes, EL(T), II.8.6, p. 136.
14
In return for the faith and obeisance he receiueth, the sovereign oweth iustice,
counsell, aid, and protection (Bodin, SB, I.6, p. 58; see also IV.6, p. 500).
15
Bodin, SB, I.8, p. 93.
16
In the parallel passage in the next version of Hobbess theory, De Cive (1642), the
distinction between law and covenant is omitted (DC, 12.4, pp. 14849).
17
Still, one can hear echoes of Bodin in the central principle of Hobbess Engagement remarks in the conclusion of Leviathan: the mutuall Relation between Protection and Obedience (LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 728). Cf. Bodins description
of the contract between ruler and ruled quoted in note 14 above. Thus it can be argued
that Hobbes ended up reproducingnot avoidingthe contradiction in Bodinian
57
In De Jure Belli Ac Pacis (1625), Grotius offered a contract argument more promising to absolutist theory.18 The argument is framed
to rebut the opinion that sovereignty always resides in the people and
rulers are therefore always accountable to their subjects. Grotiuss
answer is that individuals and peoples are radically free to consent to
slavery and to absolutism:
To every man it is permitted to enslave himself to any one he pleases for
private ownership . . . Why, then, would it not be permitted to a people
having legal competence to submit itself to some one person, or to several persons, in such a way as plainly to transfer to him the legal right
to govern, retaining no vestige of that right for itself? And you should
not say that such a presumption is not admissible; for we are not trying
to ascertain what the presumption should be in case of doubt, but what
can legally be done.19
theory between the principle of unconditional sovereignty and the notion that ruler
and ruled have mutual obligations.
18
Regarding Grotiuss influence on Hobbes, see the work of Richard Tuck, especially Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1979); and Philosophy and Government 15721651 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 304.
19
Grotius, DJB, I.3.8, p. 103.
20
Grotius, DJB, I.3.8, p. 104.
21
He is not a thoroughgoing contractarian, however. Public authority can be
acquired through war, quite independently of any other source (Grotius, DJB, I.3.8,
p. 105). This seems to exhaust the possibilities: The right to rule . . . cannot come into
existence except by consent or by punishment (II.22.13, p. 552). See note 25 below.
22
Grotius, DJB, I.3.8, p. 104.
58
chapter three
Grotius carries through by noting that conditional and divided sovereignty are possible contract choices.23 Equally, it is a matter of constitutional choice whether or not a people retains authority to change the
structure of government.
The will of the people, either at the very establishment of the sovereignty,
or in connexion with a later act, may be such as to confer a right which
for the future is not dependent on such will.24
23
For he who alienates his own right can by agreement limit the right transferred
(Grotius, DJB, I.4.14, p. 159). See also I.3.17, p. 124: Against such a state of divided
sovereigntyhaving, as it were, two headsobjections in great number are urged
by many. But, as we have also said above, in matters of government there is nothing
which from every point of view is quite free from disadvantages; and a legal provision
is to be judged not by what this or that man considers best, but by what accords with
the will of him with whom the provision originated.
24
Grotius, DJB, II.4.14, pp. 22930.
25
There are other, pertinent noncontractarian lines of argument in De Jure Belli Ac
Pacis (see note 21 above). With respect to the right of resistance, in particular, Grotius
sometimes takes the position that renunciation of the right is a defining characteristic
of civil society. I survey his arguments on the subject in chapter two.
26
Grotius, DJB, I.3.12 and .13, pp. 115 and 119 (emphasis omitted).
27
For example, Hobbes, LV, 5, pp. 11012 and 11516; 9, pp. 14748. His discovery
of Euclid is reported in Aubreys Brief Lives (ed. Oliver Lawson Dick, paperback ed.
[Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962], 150).
59
60
chapter three
61
The idea of a tie between each subject and the sovereign is the basis for
a newauthorizationversion of the political covenant in Leviathan.
This covenant consists in the mutual assertion, among incipient subjects, I Authorise and give up my Right of Governing my selfe, to this
Man, or to this Assembly of men, on this condition, that thou give up
they Right to him, and Authorise all his Actions in like manner.37 The
formulation has four specific implications. First, it provides a further
ground for the claim that rulers cannot be accountable to the people:
because every Subject is by this Institution Author of all the Actions, and
Judgments of the Soveraigne Instituted; it followes, that whatsoever he
doth, it can be no injury to any of his Subjects; nor ought he to be by
any of them accused of Injustice.38
36
62
chapter three
necessity of nonresistance. . . . For the acts to which we have given our authorization
we make our own (DJB, I.4.4, p. 141).
39
Hobbes, LV, 18, p. 229.
40
Hobbes, LV, 18, p. 232.
41
Cf. Glenn Burgess, Contexts for the Writing and Publication of Hobbess Leviathan, History of Political Thought 11 (1990): 68790.
42
Henry Parker, Observations upon some of his Majesties late Answers and Expresses
(London, 1642): In this Policy is comprised the whole art of Soveraignty . . . where
Parliaments superintend all, and in all extraordinary cases, especially betwixt the King
and Kingdom, do the faithfull Offices of Umpirage, all things remain in . . . harmony
(42); Parliament is to be accounted by the vertue of representation, as the whole
body of the State (45). Parker sometimes goes further and identifies Parliament with
63
If the point wasnt clear enough for his readers, Hobbes spells out its
application to England. It is here that the earlier-quoted reference to
the Norman Conquest appears. Although it is absurd to think that in
a monarchy the peoples deputies are their absolute Representative,
Hobbes admits that this is a commonly accepted view:
In a Monarchy, he that had the Soveraignty from a descent of 600 years,
was alone called Soveraign, had the title of Majesty from every one of
his Subjects, and was unquestionably taken by them for their King; was
notwithstanding never considered as their Representative; that name
without contradiction passing for the title of those men, which at his
command were sent up by the people to carry their Petitions, and give
him (if he permitted it) their advise.
the nation: the whole Kingdome is not properly the Author as the essence it selfe of
Parliaments (5).
43
Hobbes, LV, 16, p. 220.
44
Hobbes, LV, 22, p. 275.
45
Hobbes, LV, 19, p. 241.
64
chapter three
46
Hobbes, EL(T), II.1.3, pp. 845; DC, 7.1, pp. 1067; LV, 19, p. 239.
65
47
66
chapter three
end of his life, contributing to the Exclusion Crisis the opinion that a
king cannot be compelled to disinherit his heir.52
Naturally, Hobbess discussions of succession focus on hereditary
monarchy, although the issue arises under other forms of government.53 He defines hereditary descent to mean that sovereigns choose
their successor,54 though as a supplemental principle something
akin to fundamental law obtains.55 To prevent civil war, they have a
natural-law duty to name an heir.56 If they fail to do this, the same
natural law (to procure peace) dictates the supposition that the ruler
intended the monarchy to continue.57 The precise rules for determining succession in such cases may be matters of custom or, failing that,
the presumption of naturall affection.58
The inclusion of rules of succession in the generic social contract
story indicates that, from the beginning, Hobbes saw the importance of
the question Who is sovereign? and conceived the answer in historical terms. Political events made the question more salient when he was
composing Leviathan than it had earlier been. But that works assertion that Englands present form of government and sitting dynasty
were inheritances, via the principle of hereditary descent, from the
Norman Conquest was fully consistent with the account he had always
given of the way in which a contract creating absolute monarchy came
to bind future generations.
Not only is the Norman Conquest interpretation of Englands constitution consistent with the contract story which Hobbes had always
52
Quentin Skinner, Hobbes on Sovereignty: An Unknown Discussion, Political
Studies 13 (1965): 218.
53
Hobbes, LV, 19, pp. 24748.
54
E.g., Hobbes, LV, 19, p. 249.
55
Regarding the idea of fundamental law, see Hobbes, LV, 26, p. 334.
56
Hobbes, DC, 7.16, p. 113; LV, 19, pp. 24748.
57
Curiously, though, when the principle of sovereign control comes into conflict
with societys interest in a peaceful succession, Hobbes opts for the former: If a Monarch shall relinquish the Soveraignty, both for himself, and his heires; His Subjects
returne to the absolute Libertie of Nature; because, though Nature may declare who
are his Sons, and who are the nerest of his Kin; yet it dependeth on his own will . . . who
shall be his Heyr. If therefore he will have no Heyre, there is no Soveraignty, nor
Subjection (LV, 21, p. 273).
58
Hobbes, LV, 19, p. 250. Cf. EL(T), II.4.14, pp. 1067, and DC, 9.1219,
pp. 12628. In his post-Restoration Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student
of the Common Laws of England, Hobbes details the rules governing the natural
descent of sovereignty in England, saying these go back to the Saxons and remain
the law of the land (English Works, vol. VI [1840], 15253).
67
Hobbes traces the legal order and property arrangements back to the
Norman Conquest, as well. Laws, he declares in the Dialogue . . . of the
Common Laws, are commands or prohibitions, which ought to be
obeyed, because assented to by submission made to the Conqueror
here in England.60 Similarly, subjects estates derive from the initial
distribution of land by William, who at the Conquest won possession
of all the land of England.61 That distribution is also the basis of subjects duty to serve the king in war, since William had given away his
lands in return for past and future military service: whereby, when
[Charles I] sent men unto them with commission to make use of their
service, they were obliged to appear with arms.62
The most striking aspect of these historical contractarian comments
on the English constitution is the assertion that title to the throne is
inherited from William the Conqueror.63 The assertion underwrites
distinctions between sovereign right and power, rightful and usurped
power, and between the legitimacy of government and citizens obligation to obey. After the Restoration, Hobbes would emphasize the
59
68
chapter three
distinction between sovereign right and power in Behemoth, concluding the work with the observation: I have seen in this revolution a
circular motion of the sovereign power through two usurpers, father
and son, from the late King to this his son.64 To the question who
had the supreme power? after the dissolution of the Long Parliament in 1653, he replied: If by power you mean the right to govern,
nobody here had it. If you mean the supreme strength, it was clearly
in Cromwell.65
Even when the Stuarts were out of power, Hobbes had been prepared to distinguish sovereign right from citizens obligation to obey
de facto rulers. Behemoths defense of their title to the English throne
is prefigured in a discussion in Leviathan of the dissolution of government and the state:
though the Right of a Soveraign Monarch cannot be extinguished by
the act of another [i.e. through international or civil war]; yet the Obligation of the members may. For he that wants protection, may seek it
anywhere; and when he hath it, is obliged (without fraudulent pretence
of having submitted himselfe out of fear,) to protect his Protection as
long as he is able.66
64
69
After the Restoration, Hobbes would insist that this was the view he
had always held. He retrospectively described his Interregnum arguments in favor of Engagement with the new regime as narrowly concerning what point of time it is, that a subject becomes obliged to
obey an unjust conqueror.68 Yet the post-Restoration claim has never
been taken especially seriously, by Hobbess contemporaries or by later
readers.69 He became known, instead, for defending de facto authority
and taking an antifoundational view of sovereignty.
Mocking the Norman Conquest
The historicity of Hobbess contract arguments has been obscured by
his about-face in Leviathans Review and Conclusion. There, counseling allegiance to the postregicide government, he abjures historical commitments and embraces de facto authority. With the issue of
deposition moot, the salient topic was now conquest: this (to define it)
is the Acquiring of the Right of Soveraignty by Victory. Which Right,
is acquired, in the peoples Submission, by which they contract with
the Victor, promising Obedience, for Life and Liberty.70 On the key
point of indefeasible sovereign right, Hobbes had contradicted himself. Either sovereign right is contingent on others actsconquerors
victory and subjects submissionor it is not.
As if to telegraph the contrast between this new stance and the
account of sovereignty he had developed in connection with Leviathans authorization covenant, Hobbes goes on to mock the opinion
that the Norman Conquest has authority over present political arrangements. Neither the justness of the Conquerors cause nor the artificial
68
Hobbes, Considerations, 4212. In the same passage, Hobbes also plays up
the stipulation that a subject must protect his Protection. The latter explains away
his stance on Engagement as a justification for the actions only of royalists, but not a
justification of the actions of the Kings enemies (see Burgess, Contexts, 67879).
69
Contemporary readings of Hobbism have been detailed by Quentin Skinner in
a series of classic articles. See, in addition to the works cited previously, Hobbess
Leviathan, Historical Journal 7 (1964): 32133; and The Ideological Context of
Hobbess Political Thought, Historical Journal 9 (1966): 286317.
70
Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 721. Cf. The Elements of Law, where
Hobbes mentions only that subjects obligation transfers to the conqueror (II.2.15,
p. 98); and De Cive, If the Kingdome fall into the power of the enemy, so as there can
no more opposition be made against them, we must understand that he, who before
had the Supreme Authority, hath now lost it (DC, 7.18, p. 116). See also the passage
in De Cive quoted below in the conclusion in which Hobbes treats the possibility that
subjects may choose not to consent to the conquerors authority.
70
chapter three
71
71
without a King or House of Lords.74 To endorse a republic with parliamentary sovereignty was something he could never bring himself
to do.)75
Conclusion
Which is the real Hobbes? Is he better characterized as a philosophical contractarian, a historical contractarian, or an antifoundational
defender of the powers-that-be? The first, to be sure, corresponds to
his methodological intentions and aspirations. Yet the impulse to formulate a universalistic and contractarian defense of absolutism failed
when political events forced him to confront the issue of deposition.
He eventually had to recognize that the political force of his theoretical arguments depended on introducing contingent, historical facts
about the English constitution.
Furthermore, Leviathans appeal to the English constitution is consistent with Hobbess earlier discussions of rules of succession, which
give a historical coloration to his philosophical-contract story. These
historical themes have been obscured by Hobbess more influential
Engagement remarks in the conclusion of Leviathan. Yet it is instructive, in this regard, to perform a thought experiment. Imagine that
Charles I won the Civil War so that Hobbes never had occasion to
write the Review and Conclusion. This counterfactual is the right
frame for reading the body of the work, since the main lines of his
thinking were laid down well before the defeat of the Stuarts. Absent
the confusion introduced by his well-known Engagement remarks, we
can see the continuity between Hobbess Civil War political theory and
post-Restoration writings; see that he made historical-contractarian
arguments throughout; and appreciate the ways in which English history became more prominent in his thinking over time.
If Hobbes was in some respects a historical contractarian, there
is also ground for concluding that this Grotian line of argument is
the strongest contractarian element in his theory. Among his several
74
Samuel Rawson Gardiner, ed., The Constitutional Documents of the Puritan Revolution, 16251660, 3rd ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1906), 391.
75
After the Restoration, however, Hobbes was quite ready to state that Parliament
had held supreme power in the period of the Engagement Controversy (Behemoth,
15455; Dialogue, 1718).
72
chapter three
accounts of the relationship between ruler and ruled, this story is the
only one that incorporates two defining features of contractarianismvoluntarism (i.e. the idea that political legitimacy issues from
the assent of individuals)76 and the idea of a constitutional compact.
Regarding the first, consider his apparently contractarian defenses
of the principle of unconditional sovereigntyi.e. the nonresistance
and authorization covenants. As we have seen, both covenant formulations actually rest on logical analyses of corporate agency and
the necessary relationship between ruler and ruled. At base, Hobbes
argues that unconditional sovereignty is a necessary (rather than chosen) feature of political relationships. Unified sovereignty is defended
with a similar, definitional claim that this is also a necessary feature
of sovereignty, along with the prudential generalization that divided
sovereignty is a bad thing. Only the latter is potentially a voluntarist
argument. But he was unwilling to follow Grotius and to grant that
assent alone, not the merits of unified versus divided sovereignty, is
the sole relevant criterion.77 Thus in none of Hobbess several defenses
of unconditional and unified sovereignty is the political covenant more
than illustrative: the basic reasoning is (variously) logical, definitional,
or prudential.
The antihistorical model of Leviathans Review and Conclusion,
tying obligation to protection, is voluntarist but not contractarian.
This is a voluntarist model, as the preceding defenses of unconditional
and unified sovereignty are not, because it plainly rests the legitimacy
of a conquerors regime on the assent of subjects.78 The possibility that
assent might not be given is canvassed in De Cive: if in a Democraticall, or Aristocraticall Government some one Citizen should, by force,
possesse himself of the Supreme Power, if he gain the consent of all the
Citizens, he becomes a legitimate Monarch; if not, he is an Enemy not
76
Patrick Riley, How Coherent is the Social Contract Tradition?, Journal of the
History of Ideas 34 (1973): 543.
77
The Grotian position is quoted in note 23 above.
78
It should be noted, though, that the Review and Conclusion includes the possibility of giving merely tacit consent, which Hobbes defines as living openly under the
protection of a conqueror (LV, pp. 72021). It can be argued that this diminishes the
force of consent in the argument. In some of his previous discussions of conquest,
the concept of consent is stripped of any effective force when Hobbes describes consent as hinging on the conquerors choice. It is the conqueror who decides whether to
treat the vanquished as though they have given consent by allowing them liberty, to
keep them in bonds as nonconsenting slaves, or to kill them (EL(T), II.3.34, p. 100;
DC, 8.25, pp. 11819).
73
Elucidated on Hobbesian principles, it implies the argument that England has an absolutist constitution because subjects transferred sovereignty to William the Conqueror and did not reserve the right or the
occasion to hold the monarchy accountable. Had circumstances and
choices been different at the founding, by implication, English rulers might be accountable to the people and England might not be a
monarchy at all. In this constitutional argument, absolutism is a contingent, not a logical, feature of (English) government. Furthermore,
by contrast to Leviathans Review and Conclusion, the argument is
foundational rather than utilitarian. Legitimate authority is seen here
to derive from a constitutional compact and subsequent adherence
to rules of monarchic succession, not from subjects interest in being
protected.
Is it perverse to conclude that when Hobbes needed history he was
at his best as a contractarian thinker?
79
CHAPTER FOUR
76
chapter four
on the illogic of so doing. Williamss foil is Patrick Rileys classic on the subject, Will
and Political Legitimacy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982), which
emphasizes the voluntarism of the tradition and praises Kant, in contrast, for transforming the social contract into an Idea.
2
Bodins influence on English political thought is detailed by J. H. M. Salmon, The
French Religious Wars in English Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959);
and George L. Mosse, The Struggle for Sovereignty in England (New York: Octagon,
1968), ch. 2. Regarding Grotius, see citations in subsequent notes.
3
Salmon, French Religious Wars, 11314 (quotation, 113 n. 30). See, too, Alain
de Benoist, What is Sovereignty?, Telos 116 (1999): 99118: The problem with
sovereignty is differently posed with Thomas Hobbes (15881679). While, in Bodins
theory, the idea of absolute sovereignty is oriented explicitly against feudal power, which
implies granting the prince authority independent of his subjects consent . . . Hobbes
was the first to invoke a social contract (104). David Parker makes a similar argument: Law, Society and the State in the Thought of Jean Bodin, History of Political
Thought 2 (1981): 25385.
hobbesian absolutism
77
Already the foundations are fully laid for Hobbess later construction
of that great Leviathan as a mortal God to whom we owe under the
immortal God our peace and defence.4
4
Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, vol. II, The Age of
Reformation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 287.
5
Richard Tuck, Grotius, Carneades and Hobbes, Grotiana 4 (1983): 59. See also
Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, paperback ed., 1981), chs. 36; Optics and Sceptics: The Philosophical Foundations of Hobbess Political Thought in Conscience and Casuistry in Early
Modern Europe, ed. E. Leites (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 23563;
Philosophy and Government 15721651 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1993), 305; and Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 2022.
6
Perez Zagorin, Hobbes Without Grotius, History of Political Thought 21
(2000):1640. See also Hobbes on Our Mind, Journal of the History of Ideas 51
(1990): 31735.
7
Johann P. Sommerville, Selden, Grotius, and the Seventeenth-Century Intellectual Revolution in Moral and Political Theory in Rhetoric and Law in Early Modern
Europe, ed. V. Kahn and L. Hutson (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2001), 320.
See also Tom Sorell, Hobbes Without Doubt, History of Philosophy Quarterly 10
(1993): 12135.
78
chapter four
While Hobbes does not appeal to Grotiuss authority in a similar manner, nor do we have direct evidence that he read De Jure Belli ac Pacis or
other writings, we know there was a copy of De Jure Belli in the library
8
M. M. Goldsmith, Hobbess Mortal God: Is there a Fallacy in Hobbess Theory
of Sovereignty, History of Political Thought 1 (1980): 3740.
9
Hobbes, EL(G), 27.7, pp. 16667.
10
Bodin, SB, II. I, p. 194.
11
Hobbes, EL(G), 27.7, p. 167.
hobbesian absolutism
79
12
Noel Malcolm, Hobbes, Thomas (15881679), Oxford Dictionary of National
Biography (Oxford: Oxford University Press, online edition, 2006) [http://www
.oxforddnb.com/view/article/13400, accessed 28 Nov 2007].
13
The relationship between Grotius, Selden, and Hobbes is debated by Richard
Tuck and Johann Sommerville. See Tuck, Natural Rights Theories, ch. 4; Grotius
and Selden in The Cambridge History of Political Thought 14501700, ed. J. H.
Burns (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 499529; and Philosophy and
Government, chs. 67. Cf. Sommerville, Selden, Grotius, 320 and 33537.
14
Thomas Hobbes, The Correspondence of Thomas Hobbes, ed. Noel Malcolm
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), vol. I, Letters 17 and 18, pp. 30 and 32.
15
Noel Malcolm, Biographical Register to Hobbess Correspondents in Correspondence, vol. II, 88788.
16
See Tuck, Hobbes, 2023; and chapter five of the present volume.
17
Hobbes, EL(G), 1.1, p. 21.
18
E.g., Seyla Benhabib, The Methodological Illusions of Modern Political Theory,
Neue Hefte fr Philosophie 21 (1982): 4774.
80
chapter four
19
Harro Hpfl and Martyn P. Thompson, The History of Contract as a Motif in
Political Thought, American Historical Review 84 (1979): 93233. See also J. G. A.
Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law (New York: Norton, 1967),
esp. ch. 9; and J. W. Gough, The Social Contract: A Critical Study of its Development
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936), chs. 67.
20
Pocock, Ancient Constitution, 16.
21
Hpfl and Thompson, History of Contract, 93233.
22
Hpfl and Thompson, History of Contract, 942; Pocock, Ancient Constitution,
22931.
23
Quoted in Thomas P. Slaughter, Abdicate and Contract in the Glorious Revolution, Historical Journal 24 (1981): 330.
24
Hpfl and Thompson, History of Contract, 941.
25
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract, trans. Maurice Cranston (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968), bk I, ch. 4.
hobbesian absolutism
81
Grotiuss contract argument was basically an abstraction from historical contractarianism, which was a genre of first-order claims about
historical contracts rather than second-order reflection on historical
argumentation.29 Stepping away from particular national histories
of contracts, he advanced two general propositions: (1) legitimate
authority is founded on consent;30 and (2) a variety of constitutional
26
82
chapter four
31
Annabel Brett, Natural Right and Civil Community: The Civil Philosophy of
Hugo Grotius, The Historical Journal 45 (2002): 41, 48.
32
Pocock, Ancient Constitution. Consistent with his radical account of permissible
contracts, Grotius held that a people could give up the right to alter constitutional
arrangements in the future; however, being a merely permissive statement, this left the
opposite possibility open in principle. See the discussion in Book II, chapter four of De
Jure Belli ac Pacis. However, in the conclusion of the 1610 work on his own country,
he had sounded like a typical historical contractarian: we owe much to our ancestors,
who have accepted a form of government, which was excellent in itself, and ideal for
our character and ambitions, from the original founders . . . It is now our duty . . . firmly
to defend this form of government, which is urged by reason, approved by experience,
and recommended by antiquity (Grotius, Antiquity, 115).
hobbesian absolutism
83
84
chapter four
argument for which he was best known. Thus, for instance, the passage
claiming that sovereignty is a unity, nevertheless continues with an
attempted explanation of how both divided and conditional rule are
possible.39 Grotius makes an attempt to reconcile these positions by
distinguishing sovereignty from the possession of sovereignty,
Up to this point we have tried to show that the sovereignty must in
itself be distinguished from the absolute possession of it. So true is this
distinction that in the majority of cases the sovereignty is not held absolutely.40
Yet it is not clear what this might mean. Rather than concentrate on
his effort to combine contractarianism with a definitional position
inherited from Bodin, let us turn instead to see how Bodin had originally worked out the universalistic claim that sovereignty must be
absolute.
Bodinian Absolutism
Bodins Six Bookes of a Commonweale interjected into the development of political thought in the early-modern period the strenuous
claims that personalized sovereignty is unconditional and perpetual.41
Soueraigntie is the most high, absolute, and perpetuall power ouer
the citisens and subiects in a Commonweale; the prince or people
themselues, in whome the Soueraigntie resteth, are to giue account
vnto none, but to the immortall God alone.42 With the further identification of legislative authority as the key mark of sovereignty, this
translated into the proposition that sovereign power centrally consists
in giuing laws vnto the subiects in generall, without their consent,
39
Grotius, DJB, I.3.17, p. 123: nevertheless a division is sometimes made into parts
designated as potential . . . and subjective. . . Thus, while the sovereignty of Rome was
a unity, yet it often happened that one emperor administered the East, another the
West, or even three emperors governed the whole empire in three divisions.
So, again, it may happen that a people, when choosing a king, may reserve to itself
certain powers but may confer the others on the king absolutely.
40
Grotius, DJB, I.3.14, p. 120.
41
Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 284301.
42
Bodin, SB, I.8, pp. 84, 86. Also, p. 85: Soueraigntie is not limited either in power,
charge, or time certaine.
hobbesian absolutism
85
while the sovereign is not subiect to any law (meaning human law,
whereas divine and natural law govern all).43
Softening the assertion of unconditional sovereignty were a number
of qualifications. Bodin saw rulers and subjects as having mutual ties:
for the faith and obeisance he receiueth, the sovereign oweth iustice, counsell, aid, and protection.44 In the same vein, he distinguished
contracts between ruler and ruled, which reciprocally bindeth both
parties from mere laws.45 So, too, fundamental laws such as the Salic
law in France were binding on sovereigns, and their successors could
annul violations.46 In addition, he held that absolute monarchs could
not tax without the consent of representative assemblies of their subjects, except in emergencies.47 In fact, Bodin preferred to accent the
limits he placed on sovereign power rather than its broad scope. In
the preface to the second edition of the Rpublique, he protested the
charge that the theory gives too much power to one man by drawing
attention to its inclusion of various limitations on sovereign authority.48 In addition, the work classifies monarchies into three kinds,
based on the criterion of the conduct of government: there is lawful or royal monarchy, in which the prince obeys the laws of nature
and respects subjects liberty and property; lordly monarchy, in
which the prince is absolute master over subjects goods and persons;
and tyrannical monarchy, in which the prince violates natural law
and abuses his subjects and their property. Bodin maintained that
most European monarchies were lawfulas opposed to lordlyin
character.49
43
Bodin, SB, I.8, pp. 8889, 98 (quotations on pp. 98 and 88). Indeed, Bodin held
that princes are more straitly bound than their subiects by the law of God and
nature: For God taketh a straiter account of princes than of others (104).
44
Bodin, SB, I.6, p. 58; see also IV.6, p. 500.
45
Bodin, SB, I.8, p. 93. Hobbes mentions this distinction, though it makes no sense
in his own theory, just prior to the paraphrasing from the Rpublique that was quoted
in the introduction (EL(G), 27.6, p. 166).
46
Bodin, SB, I.8, p. 95.
47
Bodin, SB, I.8, pp. 9697. See Martin Wolfe, Jean Bodin on Taxes: The
Sovereignty-Taxes Paradox, Political Science Quarterly 83 (1968): 26884; Julian H.
Franklin, Bodin and Locke on Consent to Taxation: A Brief Note and Observation,
History of Political Thought 7 (1986): 8991; and Franklin, Jean Bodin, 8792.
48
Bodin, SB, p. A71. See Julian H. Franklin, Sovereignty and the Mixed Constitution: Bodin and His Critics, in Cambridge History, ed. Burns, 3069; Franklin, Jean
Bodin, ch. 5; Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 293300.
49
Bodin, SB, II.2, pp. 2001.
86
chapter four
However, the key point is that none of the limits Bodin placed on
sovereign power were enforceable. His admission of various qualifications and limits therefore functioned less to counteract his absolutist assertions than, as Julian Franklin recognized, to undermine
traditionally recognized limits: The Rpublique would help to show
how all medieval checks on royal power could be deprived of binding
force.50
Secondly, absolutism referred to unified control of the major rights
of sovereigntyor, in other words, opposition to a mixed constitution.
Just as with regard to unconditional sovereignty, Bodin framed unified sovereignty as a necessary proposition: the soueraigntie is alwaies
indiuisible and incommunicable.51 But this argument turns out to be
more empirical than the treatment of unconditional sovereignty and
therefore less clearly universal. In the passage from the Six Bookes that
Hobbes picked up and used in The Elements of Law, Bodin starts off
by suggesting a necessary political dynamic for legislative authority to
lead to de facto control of all powers: if the nobility should have the
power to make laws, they would forbid others to make peace or war
without their leave.52 He continues by shifting to the different proposition that unified sovereignty would be the eventual outcome of divided
sovereignty, although divided sovereignty is possible temporarily.
Whereby it commeth to passe, that where the rights of soueraigntie are
diuided betwixt the prince and his subiects: in that confusion of the state,
there is still endlesse sturres and quarrels, for the superioritie, vntill that
some one, some few, or all together haue got the soueraigntie.
50
hobbesian absolutism
87
54
Bodin, SB, I.6, p. 49. Preston King, The Ideology of Order: A Comparative Analysis of Jean Bodin and Thomas Hobbes (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1974), 29: Bodin
broadly assumes that most organisations (most particularly the family and the state)
can only enjoy a unity through the establishment and sharing of a single individual
as head (a father or a sovereign). He is not absolutely consistent in this view, and
that is why I resort to formulae of the kind he is largely inclined to believe. See also
Franklin, Jean Bodin, 23.
55
Bodin, SB, II.5, p. 221.
56
Bodin, SB, II.2, p. 199. With regard specifically to the distinction between sovereignty and the form of government, Bodin proclaimed that this was his discovery and
pointed to its analytic utility: But here happily some man will say, that none but my
selfe is of this opinion . . . True it is that I cannot denie the same; yet this distinction
neuerthelesse seemeth vnto me more than necessarie, for the good vnderstanding of
the state of euery commonweal; if a man will not cast himselfe headlong into an infinite labyrinth of errours (II.7, pp. 24950).
57
Bodin, SB, II.1, p. 190. Turning next to Venice, he argues that it was an aristocracy and not, as many thought, a mixed constitution. In Book Six, Bodin advocates
combining monarchic sovereignty with mixed government (VI.6, p. 755).
58
Goldsmith, Hobbess Mortal God, 42; Franklin, Jean Bodin, 23.
88
chapter four
hobbesian absolutism
89
90
chapter four
hobbesian absolutism
91
rational choice.71 The state-of-nature deduction generates, in Leviathan, the famous proposition that
The only way to erect such a Common Power, as may be able to defend
them from the invasion of Forraigners, and the injuries of one another . . .
is, to conferre all their power and strength upon one Man, or upon one
Assembly of men.72
71
Grotius and Hobbes differed on the question of the extent of the necessary submission. Grotius opened up a small window for resistance in cases of extreme peril
(I do not doubt that to human law also there can be applied what love under such
circumstances would commend [DJB, I.4.3, p. 149]), while Hobbes allowed, more
strongly, for an unalienated right of self-defense against violence (DC, 2.18, p. 58; LV,
14, pp. 192 and 199). See Tuck, Natural Rights Theories, 7781, 12225.
72
Hobbes, LV, 17, p. 227.
73
Hobbes, EL(G), 20.19, p. 117.
74
Hobbes, EL(G), 19.7, p. 106.
92
chapter four
Of course such abrogation would formally require the consent of literally every subject who had consented in the first place; however,
Hobbes acknowledges, this is not something that most people understand. So, he replies,
there is another tye also toward him who commands; for each Citizen
compacting with his fellow, sayes thus, I conveigh my Right on this Party,
upon condition that you passe yours to the same.
75
76
77
78
hobbesian absolutism
93
Therefore,
the government is upheld by a double obligation from the Citizens, first
that which is due to their fellow citizens, next that which they owe to
their Prince. Wherefore no subjects how many soever they be, can with
any Right despoyle him who bears the chiefe Rule, of his authority.79
This idea of a direct tie between ruler and ruled becomes, in Leviathan,
a second account of the political covenantthe authorization account.
Here the covenant promise adds the concept of authorization to the
Grotian language of renouncing the right of governing: every man
should say to every man, I Authorise and give up my Right of Governing my selfe, to this Man, or to this Assembly of men. 80
Although the universalizing, prescriptive case for absolutism is
carried over in Leviathans famous description of a horrific state of
nature and the motivation which this creates for submitting to strong
government, that substantive argument is now accompanied by two
fully developed logical accounts of the necessity of absolute sovereignty. At the start of the chapter on sovereign right, before turning
as he had in the earlier versions to enumerate specific rights of sovereignty, Hobbes inserts a complete logical proof for unconditional
sovereignty. First, because the sovereign is not a party to the political
covenant, he cannot be accused of breaking promises to his subjects81
(keeping covenants having previously been defined as the sole basis for
defining injustice).82 Why, next, is a contract between ruler and ruled
impossible? The answer is twofold: it is impossible for the sovereign
to contract either with the people as a whole or with each individual.
Prior to the institution of the state, first, no such thing as a corporate
agentthe peopleis in existence: With the whole, as one party, it
is impossible; because as yet they are not one Person. Secondly, the
79
94
chapter four
83
hobbesian absolutism
95
If there had not first been an opinion received of the greatest part of England, that these Powers were divided between the King, and the Lords,
and the House of Commons, the people had never been divided, and
fallen into this Civill Warre.86
That is, elite division leads to civil war when rival elites mobilize ordinary people and transform political conflict into civil war. This empirical hypothesis yields a prescription of the need for popular acceptance
of the unification of sovereignty: there be few now (in England,) that
do not see, that these Rights are inseparable, and will be so generally
acknowledged, at the next return of Peace.88 So it seems that divided
sovereignty represents confusion rather than a genuine possibility.89
In the end, though, like Bodin, Hobbes papers over any discrepancy
between empirical reasoning and a strong analytic claim for the necessity of unified sovereignty by simply defining away the possibility of
divided government. To wit, regarding mixt Monarchy . . . the truth is,
that it is not one independent Common-wealth, but three independent
Factions.90
86
96
chapter four
Paradoxical Contractarianism: From Hobbes to Rawls
Philosophical contractarianism, created by the amalgamation of Grotian and Bodinian briefs for absolutism, is contract theory shorn of
contingency. Only by eliminating the permissive quality of historical contractarianism did contract reasoning become a philosophical genre. Where permissive contract reasoning mandated historical
investigation of the kinds of contracts actually made by real peoples,
the transformed genre directed attention to questions about human
nature, morality, and rationality. But philosophical interest was purchased at the cost of advancing the paradoxical position that human
beings would choose to have the relationship with their rulers that
must exist between them. In the Hobbesian example, human beings
would choose absolute government in order to avoid a horrific state
of nature (and the danger of civil war); and an understanding of the
logic of the social contract shows this to be the necessary structure of
the relationship between ruler and ruled. While later contract thinkers
would reject Hobbess constitutional doctrine, his legacy lay in modeling contract reasoning without contingency.91
Broadly speaking, the outcome was the displacement of politics
and contingency from the center to the periphery of contract theorizing and, ultimately, the depoliticization of the genre.92 The distinction Bodin had drawn between the form of sovereignty, which is not
contingent, and the form of government, which is, left a subsidiary
space for variety and choice. In the Elements, Hobbes reproduced
this distinction;93 while dropping it from De Cive and Leviathan, he
nonetheless continued to recognize the possibility of various forms
of government and admitted that he had not demonstrated but only
probably stated a preference for monarchy.94 Locke and Rousseau
would combine a definitive contract, derived from propositions about
human nature, with acknowledgement of variety in possible forms of
91
Rosamond Rhodes reads Hobbesian and Rawlsian moral philosophy in similar fashion as making assent the linchpin of obligation: Obligation and Assent in
Hobbess Moral Philosophy, Hobbes Studies 15 (2000): 4567; and Reading Rawls
and Hearing Hobbes, Philosophical Forum 33 (2002): 393412.
92
B. Honig, Rawls on Politics and Punishment, Political Research Quarterly 46
(1993): 99125.
93
Hobbes, EL(G), 20.17, p. 116.
94
Hobbes, DC, The Authors Preface to the Reader, p. 37 (emphasis omitted).
hobbesian absolutism
97
or, i.e., a constitution of the English sort.95 Rousseau, of course, combines the claim that sovereignty must be democratic with a consideration of alternative forms of government, in which connection he
allows (in a passage often confusing to students) that If there were
a nation of Gods, it would govern itself democratically. A government so perfect is not suited to men.96 Yet these prudential discussions and particular specifications are appendages to their hegemonic
pronouncements on the nature of the relationship between ruler and
ruled. They contrast, to cite an obvious example, with Machiavellis
awareness of contingency in the relationship between ruler and ruled,
and his consequent preoccupation with understanding the politics of
different governmental forms.
The consignment of traditional political topics and sensibility to the
secondary topic of differences between forms of government opened
the way to more thoroughgoingand deliberatedepoliticization of
the genre. In the opening of A Theory of Justice, Rawls explains that his
transformation of contract theorizing into a genre of moral philosophy is accomplished by turning away from traditional concerns with
the constitution of particular social and governmental arrangements.97
Critics charge that his turn away from politicsseen as the realm of
contingency, plurality, conflict, and negotiationruns even deeper
in his theory: by eliminating the stuff of politics, he created a profoundly, and not only topically, antipolitical theory.98 It would be an
error, though, to target critique exclusively at Rawlss twentieth-century revival of contract thinking: it is just as pertinent to early-modern
philosophical contractarianism as it is to A Theory of Justice.99 Rawls
95
98
chapter four
inherited a genre100 already flawed by the impulse to combine voluntarist with nonvoluntarist reasoning. By way of conclusion, I want to
focus on three related criticisms of Rawlss contract argumentsthey
dissolve into (1) truth claims; into (2) cognitive, justificatory argument;
and even into (3) disciplining argumentand explore the salience of
these criticisms to classic philosophical contractarianism.
Michael Sandel lays out the tension between voluntarism and truth
claims in Rawlss theory, a tension that generates rivalmore versus
less voluntaristinterpretations of his position. Is it Rawlss view that
anything could be chosen in the original position and the outcome
would be fair? Or, as Sandel thinks, is it simply that, given their situation, the parties are guaranteed to choose the right principles?101
Notice that Rousseaus concept of the general will suffered from the
same ambiguity. If the general will simply represents community
consensus, anything will qualify so long as citizens reason in publicspirited fashion. On a less voluntarist reading, general will decisionmaking is a procedure for arriving at the right policy (although in
Rousseaus theory, unlike Rawlss, the procedure does not guarantee
the outcome). And here, too, textual evidence supports the less voluntarist interpretation. Rousseau distinguishes community consensus
from the always rightfuli.e., objectively correctgeneral will:
It follows from what I have argued that the general will is always rightful and always tends to the public good; but it does not follow that the
decisions of the people are always equally right.102
hobbesian absolutism
99
about human nature and, behind that, physical premises. The goal was
exactly to delimit choice, as is clear in the introduction to the political covenant in Leviathan. There, he makes the strong claim that the
only way to create political power adequate for defense against foreign invasion and civil warthe initial conditionis to conferre all
their power and strength on a sovereign.
Rawlss critics argue, furthermore, that (1) he eliminates plural perspectives and selves, and therefore the theory articulates the reasoning
of a single, rational deliberator;104 and that (2) his contract is of a
cognitive rather than voluntarist sort. The first critique resonates with
the present-day school of rational-choice interpretations of Hobbism,
which sees in his account of the state of nature a precursor to the
prisoners dilemma and other game-theoretic problems.105 The school
finds it a virtue that Hobbism can be constructed as an account of the
deliberations of a (singular) rational actor in an insecure situation.
The elimination of plurality leads, next, into an argument about the
nature of the contract itself. Sandel and others think that Rawlss contract is finally more cognitive than voluntarist in nature:
104
Sidney S. Alexander (1974) Social Evaluation Through Notional Choice, The
Quarterly Journal of Economics 88 (1974): 597624. Rawls himself seems to have
come out on both sides of this line of argument. In A Theory of Justice, he granted,
since the differences among the parties are unknown to them . . . each is convinced
by the same arguments. Therefore, we can view the choice in the original position
from the standpoint of one person selected at random (Theory, 139). In response to
criticism on this score, he responded by identifying two essential contract elements
in the theory: publicity and finality. The contract device is required, first, because
reaching a unanimous agreement without a binding vote is not the same thing as
everyones arriving at the same choice, or forming the same intention. That it is an
undertaking people are giving may similarly affect everyones deliberations so that
the agreement that results is different from the choice everyone would otherwise have
made. Furthermore, if we make an agreement, we have to accept the outcome; and
therefore to give an undertaking in good faith, we must not only intend to honor it
but with reason believe that we can do so. Thus the contract condition is a significant
further constraint (John Rawls, Reply to Alexander and Musgrave, The Quarterly
Journal of Economics 88 [1974]: 651). For a full discussion of the issues, on which I
rely, see Jean Hampton, Contracts and Choices: Does Rawls Have a Social Contract
Theory?, The Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 31619. Hampton sides with Alexander
and argues that the requirements of publicity and finality make for a weak form of
contractarianism, at best, and in fact do not require a contract at all. See, too, Sandel,
Liberalism, 13132.
105
Jean Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986); Gregory S. Kavka, Hobbesian Moral and Political
Theory. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986); Joe E. Hicks, Philosophers
Contracts and the Law, Ethics 85 (1974): 1837.
100
chapter four
The philosophical considerations by which Rawls would persuade us set
out from the contractarian tradition. The well-ordered society he recommends comes as close as a society can to being a voluntary scheme
(13). But what begins as an ethic of choice and consent ends, however
unwittingly, as an ethic of insight and self-understanding. In the final
passage of the book, the language of choosing and willing is displaced by
the language of seeing and perceiving, as the voluntarist image of Kant
gives way to the cognitive image of Spinoza.106
106
107
108
109
hobbesian absolutism
101
political second Part, are recast from the earlier versions with a new
focus on dangerous doctrines and public instruction.110
Bonnie Honig suggests that the depoliticizing effect of Rawlss theory extends beyond substituting understanding for choice into disciplining the will itself. Two features of the argument point in this
direction: repeatability and an appeal to introspection. By contrast to a
voluntarist contract, which could go otherwise, Rawlss agreement will
never go otherwise and therefore, she speculates, perhaps the point is
something beyond identification of the principles of justice.
Perhaps Rawls counts on the original position to issue not only in an
intersubjective agreement among selves but also (repeatedly) in an intrasubjective ordering of the self according to the dictates of Rawlsian rationality and justice.
Repeatability is, at base, what Hobbes achieved with his transformation of Grotian contractarianism. This is simply another way of framing the essence of the paradoxical reasoning that he inaugurated: we
can only choose what is, in fact, the necessary structure of political
authority. Moreover, recall the claim with which Leviathans introduction famously concludes: When I shall have set down my own reading orderly, and perspicuously, the pains left another, will be onely
to consider, if he also find not the same in himself.112 Might Honigs
diagnosis of the specter of discipline behind the facade of choice not
be accurate to Hobbism and the genre of social contract thinking he
founded?
110
Compare Hobbes, LV, 29, pp. 36568, and 30, pp. 37685, with EL(G), 27 and
28, and with DC, 12 and 13.
111
Honig, Rawls, 10910. In similar vein, Hampton, Contracts and Choices,
concluded: Therefore, understanding the deliberation in the original position as carried out by a single deliberator following the dictates of practical reason, rather than
understanding it as carried out by many parties trying to forge a contract, is a far better way of showing how Rawls thinks a state organized according to the two principles
is something to which we would voluntarily consent, its constraints and obligations
recognized by us as self-imposed (33738).
112
Hobbes, LV, The Introduction, p. 81.
PART III
CHAPTER FIVE
1
Thomas Hobbes, Considerations upon the Reputation, Loyalty, Manners, and
Religion, of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes
of Malmesbury, ed. Sir William Molesworth, Vol. IV (London: J. Bohn, 1840), 414.
2
Ferdinand Tnnies, The Editors Preface, in EL(T), ixx; and George Croom
Robertson, Hobbes, cheap ed. (Philadelphia, n.d.), 501.
3
Robertson, Hobbes, 52.
4
Richard Tuck, Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 19, 24.
5
Noel Malcolm, A Summary Biography of Hobbes, in The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 41 n.
52, 28, 27.
106
chapter five
Attention to the text itself can help resolve the puzzle. Looking
closely at the organization of the work, we will see that Robertsons
suspicion was largely, but not entirely, on target. The bulk of the Elements appears to have been composed deliberately and systematically,
and therefore was probably completed before the political crisis of the
spring of 1640. However, the organization breaks down in later chapters. There are six chapters at the end of the work that depart from the
prior manuscript, in form or content, in ways that suggest they may
have been hurriedly written. A significant example is the odd claim, in
the second chapter of Part II, that democracy is the original form of
all government. It was hardly a position one would have expected to
find in a work defending absolute monarchy, especially a work written
in the context of the pre-War controversies between parliamentarians
and the king over their respective powers. Hobbes, in fact, would jettison democracy first from the revised theory presented in Leviathan,
presumably due to the arguments unfortunate implication that England had once upon a time had a popular government.6 The textual
evidence, we will see, indicates that democracy first was an argument
cobbled together to bring an ongoing project to a hasty conclusion.
This and other evidence suggest that Hobbess memory of writing the
Elements during the Short Parliament was accurate but incomplete,
shorthand for a more complicatedand plausibleprocess of composition. It appears that The Elements of Law was largely, but not entirely,
drafted by the spring of 1640, at which time the calling of the Short
Parliament led Hobbes to finish it in short order.
Focusing on the puzzle of the composition of the Elements introduces a more general issue in Hobbes studies. The process of compositionof all three major textsis a side of Hobbess political
arguments that merits more consideration. Quite foreign to our image
of an independent author producing a single, finished text, authorship
for Hobbes was complicated by patronage and exile, as well as by his
own peculiar way of writing. These led him to produce three, progressively longer, versions of a single project over the span of something
like fifteen years, and in two languages and countries. The substance
of Hobbess political theory cannot help but have been affected by its
process of compositionin the Elements, to be discussed here, and
later in De Cive and Leviathan.
6
A. P. Martinich, Hobbes: A Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999), 156.
107
7
Malcolm, Summary Biography, 2627; and Tuck, Hobbes, 20. Cf. Robertson,
Hobbes, 4852.
8
For a similar view, see E. G. Jacoby, Thomas Hobbes in Europe, Journal of
European Studies, 4 (1974): 63.
108
chapter five
More specifically, Hobbes was pondering and discussing with Mersenne the idea that our perceptions are the product of motions coming
from external objects and affecting the brain.10 The idea is framed in
the Elements thus: image or colour is but an apparition unto us of
that motion . . . which the object worketh in the brain.11 He explains,
further, that
conceptions or apparitions are nothing really, but motion in some internal substance of the head; which motion not stopping there, but proceeding to the heart, of necessity must there either help or hinder that
motion which is called vital.12
This denies the traditional, Aristotelian view that the qualities we perceive are inherent to external objects: the subject wherein colour and
image are inherent, is not the object or thing seen . . . that is nothing
without us really which we call an image or colour.13 Hobbes touched
on the idea in correspondence to Newcastle in 163614 and would later
recall pondering it, and the mechanical view of nature from which
109
15
Thomas Hobbes, The Verse Life, in EL(G), 257: Whether on Horse, in Coach,
or Ship, still I/Was most Intent on my Philosophy./One only thing ith World seemd
true to me,/. . ./One only True Thing, the Basis of all/Those Things whereby we any
Thing do call./. . ./To Matter, Motion, I my self apply, The continuation of the passage
is quoted below on p. 112.
16
For an excellent account of this, see Tuck, Hobbes, 1519.
17
The claim appears in the dedication to a 1646 work on optics: That which I have
written . . . is grounded especially upon that wch about 16 yeares since I affirmed to your
Lopp at Welback, that light is a fancy in the minde, caused by motion in the braine,
which motion againe is caused by the motion of ye parts of such bodies as we call lucid:
such as are the sunne and ye fixed stars, and such as here on earth is fire. Thomas
Hobbes, To the Right Honourable the Marquis of Newcastle [dedication to A minute or first draught of the Optiques, 1646], in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of
Malmesbury, ed. Sir William Molesworth, Vol. VII (London: J. Bohn, 1845), 468.
18
John Aubrey, Thomas Hobbes, in Aubreys Brief Lives, ed. Oliver Lawson Dick
(Ann Arbor, 1962), 150; and Hobbes, Prose Life, 24647.
19
Johann P. Sommerville, Thomas Hobbes: Political Ideas in Historical Context
(New York: St. Martins Press, 1992), 14.
20
Hobbes, EL(T), p. xvii. See also I.13.34, pp. 5051, where he defines the mathematici as those who employ the geometrical method.
110
chapter five
21
111
Logica, ex. T.H.25 Nonetheless, although Digby seems to be referring to a different work, the method he discusses is on display in The
Elements of Law. The work is framed in deductive fashion as a series
of definitions of basic concepts, which appear in black gothic script in
the manuscript.
In the political realm, Hobbess return home coincided with the
growth of the Ship Money controversy.26 Ship Money was a tax levied
by Charles I without parliamentary consultation or approval, which
was challenged in court in 1637 in Hampdens Case over the refusal of
a subject to pay. Although the judges supported the King, the case fed
growing disenchantment with his regime, and it is surely unlikely that
Hobbes was ignoring these events. In the preface to the second edition of De Cive (1647) he explained why he was to publish on politics
shortly thereafter:
my Country some few yeares before the civill Warres did rage, was
boyling hot with questions concerning the rights of Dominion, and the
obedience due from Subjects . . . And was the cause which (all those other
matters deferrd) ripend, and pluckt from me this third part.27
Hobbes may well have specifically had in mind the Ship Money controversy, which directly concerned the rights of Dominion, and the
obedience due from Subjects.28
The passage makes reference to his plan for a three-part series of
works on body, man, and citizen. I was studying Philosophie for my
minde sake, he explains:
I had gathered together its first Elements in all kinds, and having digested
them into three Sections by degrees, I thought to have written them so as
in the first I would have treated of a body, and its generall properties; in
25
Jean Jacquot and Harold Whitmore Jones, Introduction to Critique du De
Mundo de Thomas White, by Thomas Hobbes (Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin,
1973), 16. Malcolm concurs in the identification (Hobbes, Correspondence, 49 n. 2).
26
Robertson, Hobbes, 48; Tuck, Hobbes, 2324; Sommerville, Thomas Hobbes, 17.
Sommerville relates Hobbess arguments to the immediate political context in Lofty
Science and Local Politics, in The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 24673.
27
Hobbes, DC, The Authors Preface to the Reader, pp. 3536 (emphasis omitted).
28
Tuck, Hobbes, comments, these must have been the questions to which Hobbes
was referringthe argument of the Elements of Law is particularly well judged as a
contribution to the Ship Money debate, on the Kings side (24).
112
chapter five
the second of man and his speciall faculties, and affections; in the third,
of civill government and the duties of Subjects. . .29
There is some dispute among scholars whether the plan actually predated the Elements; most think so, although Ferdinand Tnnies, who
edited the 1928 edition of the work, disagreed.30
Within the work, the internal outline laid out in the first paragraph
corresponds to the second and third sections of the plan, to which is
added a final section on law:
The true and perspicuous explication of the elements of laws, natural
and politic, which is my present scope, dependeth upon the knowledge
of what is human nature, what is a body politic, and what it is we call
a law.31
29
113
35
Harold Love, Scribal Publication in Seventeenth-Century England (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1993), 210.
36
J. C. A. Gaskin, A Note on the Texts, in EL(G), xlvii.
37
Martin Dzelzainis, Edward Hyde and Thomas Hobbess Elements of Law, Natural and Politic, The Historical Journal 32 (1989): 30317, notes evidence that Hobbes
edited the work after this date, altering whichever copy was available (313).
38
Sommerville, Thomas Hobbes, 172 n. 42; see also Martinich, Hobbes, 122.
39
Hobbes, Considerations, 414.
114
chapter five
Scribal publication could also be attractive as a means of avoiding censorship,44 which may have been a Hobbesian consideration, although
the work includes less of the controversial religious material than
would appear in the subsequent versions.
The Elements was written, Hobbes also records in the dedication, at
Newcastles behest: Now (my Lord) the principles . . . are those which
I have heretofore acquainted your Lordship withal in private discourse, and which by your command I have here put into method.45
Scribal publication served patrons desire for advancement as well as
authors.46 Newcastle was associated with the absolutist faction of Laud
and Strafford, and we can suppose that the work was meant to support
their cause at court as well as strengthen Newcastles position with
the King while also, last but not least, improving Hobbess standing
with Newcastle. As a link in a chain of patronage and dependence,47
production of the Elements can be compared to the effort, not long
before, by the Earl of Devonshire to have Hobbes elected to the Short
Parliament.48 Like that unsuccessful political initiative, the literary act
40
Love, Scribal Publication, 47, citing J. W. Saunders, The Stigma of Print: A Note
on the Social Bases of Tudor Poetry, in Essays in Criticism, vol. I (1951).
41
Love, Scribal Publication, 177: [S]cribal publication [w]as a means by which
ideologically charged texts could be distributed through the governing class, or various interest-groups within that class, without their coming to the knowledge of the
governed.
42
Hobbes, EL(T), p. xviii.
43
Love, Scribal Publication, 184.
44
Love, Scribal Publication, 185.
45
Hobbes, EL(T), xvii.
46
Love, Scribal Publication, 192.
47
Love, Scribal Publication, 179.
48
See Malcolms notes to the Correspondence, Vol. I, p. 171, n. 2.
115
grew out of Hobbess material position and the practice of patronage in mid-seventeenth-century England; therefore production of the
Elements is better understood as a social act rather than, as we might
assume, the work of an academic working in isolation.49
The Text
If there is little autobiographical evidence from the 1630s bearing
directly on the composition of the Elements, the work itself is unusually
revealing. Its layout is worth considering, to begin with. The bulk of
the workfour-fifths of the chapters, to be preciseis fleshed out on
a skeleton of defined terms, which appear highlighted in black gothic
script in the manuscript. This method of exposition corresponds to
the geometrical methodof proceeding by way of axiomatic definitionsto which Digbys 1637 letter alluded. In chapter six of the work,
Hobbes explains the method thus:
The first principle of knowledge therefore is, that we have such and such
conceptions; the second, that we have thus and thus named the things
whereof they are conceptions; the third is, that we have joined those
names in such manner, as to make true propositions; the fourth and
last is, that we have joined those propositions in such manner as they
be concluding. And by these four steps the conclusion is known and
evident, and the truth of the conclusion said to be known.50
49
See Lisa Sarasohn, Was Leviathan a Patronage Artifact?, History of Political
Thought 21 (2000): 60631.
50
Hobbes, EL(T), I.6.4, p. 20. See, also, I.13.3, pp. 5051: they proceed from most
low and humble principles, evident even to the meanest capacity; going on slowly,
and with most scrupulous ratiocination (viz.) from the imposition of names they infer
the truth of their first propositions; and from two of the first, a third; . . . and so on,
according to the steps of science.
51
Hobbes, EL(T), p. xv (chapter title).
116
chapter five
of what is human nature, what is a body politic, and what it is we call
a law.52
Chapter one proceeds to diagram the several natural faculties, distinguishing and cataloguing faculties of body versus faculties of mind, and
concluding with a discussion of cognitive powers. In continuation, the
next chapter (on the cause of Sense) opens, Having declared what I
mean by the word conception . . . I come to the conceptions themselves,
to show their difference, their causes, and the manner of their production.53 Hobbes then proceeds to highlight, define, and explain the
concepts Sense and Object of sense. Filling out the mental map,
chapter three considers various other sorts of mental images, distinct
from present perceptions, such as Phantasy or Imagination, Sleep,
Dreams, Fiction, Phantasms, and Remembrance.54
The layout would seem to evidence the slow composition process
that Hobbes described, retrospectively, in De Cives preface.55 It also
brings to mind Aubreys account of the way in which Leviathan was
composed:
He walked much and contemplated, and he had in the head of his cane a
pen and ink-horn, carried always a notebook in his pocket, and as soon
as a thought darted, he presently entered it into his book, or otherwise
he might perhaps have lost it.
Having previously outlined the work, he knew where an idea would fit:
He had drawn the design of the book into chapters, etc. so he knew
whereabouts it would come in.56 Likely as not, this had been Hobbess
way of working for some time, so the scaffolding of highlighted definitions may represent the initial outline of the Elements, which he subsequently filled in with argumentation.
The scaffolding breaks down and disappears from the last chapters of the work. Highlighted definitions are absent from Part II,
Chapters 2 and 5 (comparing the origin and the incommodities of the
several forms of government); 7 (on religious authority); 8 and 9 (on
the causes of rebellion and the duties of rulers); and 10 (on law) (see
52
117
Appendix 1). This may indicate that these final chapters were drafted
hurriedly and without benefit of a prior outline.
It is also noteworthy, and possibly indicative of a hasty completion,
that there is but one final chapter on the nature and kinds of laws.57
When outlining the work, Hobbes seems to have envisaged that the
topic would form a more substantial theme of the manuscript, which
was titled, after all, The Elements of Law. Recall the initial outline, in
the first paragraph, in which law figures as a major subject; this is
echoed in the outline that opens Part II. Civil law continues to be
announced as a major theme: In this part . . . shall be considered, the
nature of a body politic, and the laws thereof, otherwise called civil
laws.58 Assuming the chapters were being written in order, this suggests that Part I had been completed prior to the calling of the Short
Parliament and that Hobbes had begun Part II, still anticipating that
law would be a major theme.
Democracy First
Turning from form to content, let us focus, first, on the two chapters
in Part II that compare various forms of governmentChapter 2, Of
the three sorts of Commonwealth, and Chapter 5, The incommodities of several sorts of Government compared.59 The topic of the first
is the way in which the several forms of government are instituted; the
second treats their conveniences, and inconveniences.60 Chapter 2
is the locale for the curious claim that all governments are initially
democracies. This is so, Hobbes explains, because the other forms of
government require nomination of rulers and prior agreement on
majority rule:
The first in order of time of these three sorts is democracy, and it must
be so of necessity, because an aristocracy and a monarchy, require nomination of persons agreed upon; which agreement in a great multitude
of men must consist in the consent of the major part; and where the
57
Note that this is among the chapters from which highlighted definitions are
absent.
58
Hobbes, EL(T), II.1.1, p. 83.
59
Capitalization in the chapter titles follows Harley 4235.
60
Hobbes, EL(T), II.5.1, p. 107.
118
chapter five
votes of the major part involve the votes of the rest, there is actually a
democracy.61
61
Hobbes, EL(T), II.2.1, p. 92. Cf. DC, 7.5, p. 109: Those who met together with
intention to erect a City, were almost in the very act of meeting a Democraty.
62
Here, and throughout the chapter, this discussion has been corrected. The original treated incorrectly the passage in De Cive quoted in the previous note.
63
Hobbes, EL(T), I.19.7, p. 80: The covenant is said to consist in every man
oblig[ing] himself to a single or collective ruler; and, if the latter is the case, then
also they covenant, that every man shall hold that for the command of the whole
council, which is the command of the greater part of those men.
64
Hobbes, EL(T), II.1.3, pp. 8485.
119
65
66
120
chapter five
By contrast, Leviathan makes explicit that the only parties to the covenant are the incipient subjects:
Because the Right of bearing the Person of them all, is given to him they
make Soveraigne, by Covenant onely of one to another, and not of him
to any of them; there can happen no breach of Covenant on the part of
the Soveraigne; and consequently none of his Subjects, by any pretence
of forfeiture, can be freed from his Subjection.69
In fact, the process of improving the defense of unconditional sovereignty began soon after completion of the Elements. The first edition
of De Cive, which was finished in November 1641, introduces this
important specification that the covenant takes place between subjects
only.70 Hobbess haste to revise the argument is still more evidence of
his dissatisfaction with the defense of unconditional sovereignty in the
Elements and, therefore, the likelihood that these discussions had been
drafted under pressure of time.
67
121
Bodin
It may well be that the defense of absolutism was the major uncompleted piece of the manuscript prior to the calling of the Short Parliament. Recall that when Hobbes described writing a little treatise
during the Parliament, he specifically characterized it as a defense of
absolute sovereignty, which was intended to set forth and demonstrate, that the said power and rights were inseparably annexed to
the sovereignty. There is a second anomalous chapter on absolutism
in Part II that also bears evidence of being hastily composedthis is
Chapter 8, on the causes of rebellion.
Unusual for Hobbes, the chapter appeals to authorityin this case,
the authority of Bodin, who was a standard source in mid-seventeenthcentury England for the defense of absolutism.71 Most unusually,
Hobbes cites and actually paraphrases Bodins argument regarding the
impossibility of divided sovereignty:
if there were a commonwealth, wherein the rights of sovereignty were
divided, we must confess with Bodin, Lib. II. chap. I. De Republica, that
they are not rightly to be called commonwealths, but the corruption of
commonwealths.
(Bodin had written, the nobilitie which should haue the power to
make the lawes for all . . . would by their lawes at their pleasure forbid
others to make peace or warre, or to leuie taxes, or to yeeld fealtie and
homage without their leaue.)73
Bodin is not named in connection with several further points in the
chapter, but these are Bodinian arguments that run counter to mature
Hobbism. In the paragraph preceding the quotation from the Rpublique, there is a curious rebuttal of the view that rulers are subject
71
122
chapter five
But within Hobbess theoretical framework, use of the Bodinian distinction simply made no sense.
In Chapter 8, also, Hobbes endorses Aristotles view that liberty is
the peculiar characteristic of democracies:
And Aristotle saith well (lib. 6, cap. 2 of his Politics), The ground or
intention of a democracy, is liberty . . . For men ordinarily say this: that no
man can partake of liberty, but only in a popular commonwealth.76
74
Hobbes, EL(T), II.8.6, p. 136: this error seemeth to proceed from this, that men
ordinarily understand not aright, what is meant by this word law, confounding law
and covenant, as if they signified the same thing.
75
Bodin, SB, I.8, p. 93. See also I.6, p. 58: In return for the faith and obeisance
he receiueth, the sovereign oweth iustice, counsell, aid, and protection; and IV.6,
p. 500.
76
Hobbes, EL(T), II.8.3, p. 134.
77
Hobbes, LV, 29, p. 369: From the same books, they that live under a Monarch
conceive an opinion, that the Subjects in a Popular Common-wealth enjoy Liberty;
but that in a Monarchy they are all Slaves. I say, they that live under a Monarch conceive such an opinion; not they that live under a Popular Government: for they find
no such matter.
78
Bodin, SB, II.7, p. 250. Hobbes is likely to have come across this passage because
it immediately follows a discussion of the impossibility of divided sovereignty.
123
One may surmise that Hobbes was led to make such mistakes, as well
as to defer to Bodins authority in the first instance, by a need to complete a defense of absolutism that was not, in fact, fully worked out in
his mind. In order to finish the job in a hurry, he seems to have been
writing with an open copy of the Rpublique close at hand.
Chronology of Composition
The evidence is not sufficient to distinguish with certainty which
chapters were composed during the Short Parliament, but does permit
reconstructing the range of possibilities. These are detailed in Table 1.
Table 1: Hypothesized Chronology of the Composition of The Elements of Law
Period of Composition
Pre-Short Parliament
Pre-Short Parliament
Part 1.
Part 2.
1.
Short Parliament
Pre-Short Parliament
Pre-Short Parliament
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
Short Parliament
?
8.
9.
Short Parliament
10.
124
chapter five
79
80
81
125
82
126
chapter five
he will himselfe, for the preservation of his own Nature. Just two
paragraphs down, however, he introduces a more expansiveand
contradictorydefinition: Right, consisteth in liberty to do, or to
forbeare . . . so that Law, and Right, differ as much, as Obligation, and
Liberty.84 If right and law are opposites, then natural right should
not include the natural-law limitation of self-preservation, as it does
according to the first definition. Scholars have treated the apparent
inconsistency as a substantive problem in need of interpretation.85 Yet
the substantive problem may be simply another artifact of Hobbess
process of writing and thus illustrate, again, how that process could
frustrate his ambitions of rigor.
Like other early modern thinkers, Hobbes rewrote and progressively
expanded his political theory over the course of roughly fifteen years.
This little MS treatise, Aubrey said of The Elements of Law, grew
to be his book De Cive, and at last grew there to be the so formidable
Leviathan.86 Hobbes may well have learned this process of composition from Bacon, for whom he early on served as a secretary.87 Bacon
produced thirteen editions of the Essayes between 1597 and 1625, and
expanded the work from ten essays in the original to fifty-eight in a
volume three times longer.88 Hobbess way of writing turned the process of expansion into yet another opportunity for introducing inconsistencies,89 since he seems to have been content, oftentimes, to layer
argument on top of argument. Commenting on this tendency, Glenn
Burgess has suggested (with the works new authorization argument
specifically in mind):
84
127
In this vein, consider those rival definitions of natural right in Leviathan, whose evolution can be traced back through the Elements and
De Cive. In the first treatise, the parallel passage has the point of defining natural law, which Hobbes identifies with reason;91 but the section expands in the next two versions to cover natural right as well.
In De Cive, answering objections to the idea of natural law, Hobbes
introduces a definition of RIGHTnamely that which is not done
against Reason.92 This becomes, with revision, the second definition of
natural right in Leviathan (liberty to do, or to forbeare); but Hobbes
confuses matters by further introducing a definition of the specific
concept, right of nature, that builds in self-preservation. Here, again,
is a case in which expansion generated inconsistency.
Of course expansion could also be an occasion for Hobbes to remove
inconsistencies and improve the logic of his arguments. This possibility is illustrated in the evolution of the democracy first argument.
Apparently aware that democracy first fit poorly with the rest of the
theory in the Elements, Hobbes jettisoned the claim from Leviathan.
In this instance, expansion served rather than frustrated his desire
for rigor.
The overall impact of his method of writing, and of revising and
expanding the treatises, can be measured only by building up case-bycase investigations of anomalies in his arguments.93 Leviathan stands
in need of a textual archeology that traces its layers of sedimentation in the development of chapters and arguments from the Elements through De Cive to the masterpiece. This work will, I suspect,
90 .
Glenn Burgess, Contexts for the Writing and Publication of Hobbess Leviathan, History of Political Thought 11 (1990): 690. (However I disagree with Burgesss
characterization of the three strata in Leviathanaboriginal democracy; authorization and representation; and, lastly, the de facto defense of Engagementsince it
appears to me that the first is not part of the work. My suspicion is that Hobbess composition process is more complex than Burgesss schema suggests.) See also Jacquot
et Jones, Introduction, 79: louvrage ne rsulte pas dune rdaction continue, mais
dune juxtaposition, dans un certain ordre, de pages crites divers moments.
91
Hobbes, EL(T), I.15.1, p. 58: There can therefore be no other law of nature than
reason, nor no other precepts of natural law, than those which declare unto us the
ways of peace.
92
Hobbes, DC, II.1, p. 52.
93
My thanks to Iain Hampsher-Monk for suggesting these concluding points.
128
chapter five
129
Appendix 1
Outline of Chapter Topics and Definitions in The
Elements of Law*
Part I. Concerning men as persons natura
1. The general division of mans natural faculties
.1: The true and perspicuous explication of the elements of laws, natural
and politic, which is my present scope, dependeth upon the knowledge
of what is human nature, what is a body politic, and what it is we call a
law (p. 1).
2. The cause of sense
.1: Having declared what I mean by the word conception . . . I come to the
conceptions themselves, to show their difference, their causes, and the
manner of their production (p. 2).
Sense and Object of sense
3. Of imagination and the kinds thereof
Phantasy or Imagination; Sleep; Dreams; Fiction; Phantasms; Remembrance
4. Of the several kinds of discursion of the mind
.1: The succession of conceptions in the mind (p. 10).
Discursion; Ranging; Sagacity; Reminiscence; Experience; Expectation
or Presumption of the future; Conjecture; Signs; Prudence
5. Of names, reasoning, and discourse of the tongue
.1: Seeing the succession of conceptions in the mind are caused (as hath
been said before) by the succession they had one to another when they
were produced by the senses; . . . man . . . hath imagined and devised to set
up a visible or other sensible mark . . . [to] bring to his mind the thought
he had when he set it up (pp. 1314).
Mark; Name or Appellation; Positive; Privative; Universal; Singular;
Equivocal; Understanding; Affirmation or Negation; True or Truth;
False; Syllogism; Ratiocination
6. Of knowlege, opinion, and belief
Science; Sapience; Supposed; Think; Opinion; Belief; Conscience
7. Of delight and pain; good and evil
.1: In the eighth section of the second chapter is shewed, how conceptions
or apparitions are . . . motion in some internal substance of the head;
which motion not stopping there, but proceeding to the heart, of necessity must there either help or hinder that motion which is called vital;
when it helpeth, it is called Delight . . . (p. 21).
Pain; Hatred; Appetite; Aversion; Fear; Good; Evil; Goodness; Badness;
Pulchritudo; Turpitudo; End; Fruition; Profitable; Use; Vain; Felicity;
Sensual; Joy; Grief
8. Of the pleasures of the sense; of honour
.1: Having in the first section of the precedent chapter presupposed that motion and agitation of the brain which we call conception, to be continued
to the heart, and there to be called passion; I have thereby obliged myself,
130
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
chapter five
as far forth as I can, to search out and declare, from what conception
proceedeth every one of those passions which we commonly take
notice of (p. 24).
Honour; Honorable; Worth; Reverence
Of the passions of the mind
Glory; Aspiring; False Glory; Vain Glory; Humility; Dejection; Shame;
Courage; Anger; Revengefulness; Repentance; Hope; Despair; Diffidence;
Trust; Pity; Hardness of heart; Indignation; Emulation; Envy; Laughter;
Weeping; Lust; Love; Charity; Admiration; Curiosity; Magnanimity;
Pusillanimity
Of the differences between men in their discerning faculty and the cause
.1: Having shewed in the precedent chapters, that the imagination of men
proceedeth from the action of external objects upon the brain . . . and
that the passions proceed from the alteration there made, and continued to the heart: it is consequent in the next place . . . to declare what
other causes may produce such odds, and excess of capacity, as we
daily observe in one man above another (p. 37).
Dulness; Fancy; Judgment; Wit; Levity; Gravity; Stolidity; Indocibility;
Madness
What imaginations and passions men have, at the names of things
supernatural
.1: Hitherto of the knowledge of things natural, and of the passions that
arise naturally from them. Now forasmuch as we give names not only
to things natural, but also to supernatural; and by all names we ought
to have some meaning and conception: it followeth in the next place, to
consider what thoughts and imaginations of the mind we have, when
we take into our mouths the most blessed name of GOD (p. 41).
How by deliberation from passions proceed mens actions
.1: It hath been declared already, how external objects cause conceptions,
and conceptions appetite and fear, which are the first unperceived
beginnings of our actions . . . This alternate succession of appetite and
fear . . . is that we call Deliberation (p. 47).
Will; Voluntary Actions; Involuntary or Mixed; Consent; Contention;
Battle; mutual Aid; Union; Intention
How by language men work upon each others minds
.1: Having spoken of the powers and acts of the mind . . . considered in every man by himself, without relation to others; it will fall fitly into this
chapter, to speak of the effects of the same powers one upon another
(p. 49).
Teaching; Learn; Persuasion; Controversy; Consent; Counselling;
Promise; Threatening; Commanding; Law; Instigation; Appeasing
Of the estate and right of nature
.1: In the precedent chapters hath been set forth the whole nature of man,
consisting in the powers natural of his body and mind, and may all be
comprehended in these four: strength of body, experience, reason, and
passion (p. 53).
.2: In this chapter it will be expedient to consider in what estate of security this our nature hath placed us (pp. 5354).
Right; War; Peace
131
132
chapter five
6. That subjects are not bound to follow their private judgments in controversies of religion
.1: Having showed that in all commonwealths whatsoever, the necessity of peace and government requireth, that there be existent some
power . . . by the name of the power sovereign, to which it is not lawful
for any member of the same commonwealth to disobey; there occurreth now a difficulty, which, if it be not removed, . . . maketh it unlawful for a man to put himself under the command of such absolute
sovereignty as is required thereto (p. 113).
Fundamental; Superstruction
7. That subjects are not bound to follow the judgment of any authority in
controversies of religion which is not dependent on the sovereign power
.1: In the former chapter have been removed those difficulties opposing
our obedience to human authority, which arise from misunderstanding of our Saviors title and laws . . . Now they who differ not amongst
themselves concerning his title and laws, may nevertheless have different opinions concerning his magistrates, and the authority he hath
given them (p. 126).
8. Of the causes of rebellion
.1: Hitherto of the causes why, and the manner how, men have made
commonwealths. In this chapter I shall show briefly, by what causes,
and in what manner, they be again destroyed (p. 133).
9. Of the duty of them that have sovereign power
.1: Having hitherto set forth how a body politic is made, and how it may
be destroyed, this place requireth to say something concerning the
preservation of the same (p. 142).
10. Of the nature and kinds of laws
.1: Thus far concerning the Nature of Man, and the constitution and
properties of a Body Politic. There remaineth only for the last chapter,
to speak of the nature and sorts of law (p. 147).
.10: And thus much concerning the elements and general grounds of
laws natural and politic (p. 151).
* Highlighting of key terms follows the Harley 4235 manuscript.
133
Appendix 2
Comparison of Chapters on the Several Forms of
Government in The Elements of Law and Leviathan
Elements of Law (Part II)
Ch. 2. Of the three sorts of
commonwealth
(ch. 1, 3)*
(ch. 1, 1516)
19: democracy first;
derivation of other
forms of government
2: no contract between
ruler and ruled
3: sovereign cannot
injure subjects
910: absolute vs. elective
kingdoms
11: people = multitude;
civil person
1216: discharge of
subjection
Ch. 5. The incommodities of
several sorts of government
compared
1: benefits (peace &
preservation) same for
sovereign and subjects
2: conveniences and
inconveniences
to ruler and to ruled
3: inconveniences to subjects in
each form of government:
4: assembly debate
excites passions
56: since there are more rulers in
aristocracy and democracy
than in monarchy, there is
more corruption potential
7: law more constant in
monarchy
Leviathan
Ch. 19. Severall Kinds of
Common-wealth by Institution, and . . . Succession
12: definitions of three kinds of
government; names for
bad forms
3: England, a monarchy for 600
years; danger of
subordinate representatives
(ch. 18, 4)
(ch. 18, 6)
1013: absolute vs. elective
kingdoms
(ch. 16, 1, 13)
(ch. 21, 2125)
134
chapter five
(ch. 4, 1117)
7: disagreements in
assemblies may lead to
civil war
9: in dangerous times,
assembly governments need
dictators
(temporary monarchs)
1423: succession
Note:
This essay uses the 1928 Tnnies edition of The Elements of Law (Cambridge University
Press) as well as the original manuscript, Harley 4235 (1640), British Library. Quotations (using modernized spelling) are taken from the Tnnies edition, although in a
few cases (which are indicated in notes) capitalization or emphasis follows the Harley
manuscript.
CHAPTER SIX
1
See, e.g., Robert Darnton, What is the History of Books?, in Books and Society
in History, ed. Kenneth E. Carpenter (New York: R. R. Bowker, 1983), 326; and D. F.
McKenzie, Bibliography and the Sociology of Texts (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1999).
2
G. A. J. Rogers and Karl Schuhmann, Introduction to Thomas Hobbes Leviathan
(Bristol: Thoemmes Continuum, 2003).
3
Thomas Hobbes, Lviathan: trait de la matire, de la forme et du pouvoir de la
rpublique ecclsiastique et civile, trans. Franois Tricaud (Paris: ditions Sirey, 1971).
4
Tom Sorell and Luc Foisneau, eds., Leviathan After 350 Years (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 2004).
136
chapter six
hobbes interpretation
137
138
chapter six
10
Rogers and Schuhmann, Introduction 1921. Thomas Hobbes, Critique du De
Mundo de Thomas White, ed. Jean Jacquot et Harold Whitmore Jones (Paris: Librairie
Philosophique J. Vrin, 1973).
11
E.g., Jeffrey R. Collins, The Allegiance of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 82.
12
Noel Malcolm, A Summary Biography of Hobbes, in The Cambridge Companion
to Hobbes ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 28. Many
share this view, including: Quentin Skinner, Introduction: Hobbess Life in Philosophy, Visions of Politics, vol. 3 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 9, 11;
and M. M. Goldsmith, Hobbess Ambiguous Politics, History of Political Thought
11 (1990), 639.
hobbes interpretation
139
13
Rogers and Schuhmann, Introduction, 45. They see some similarities between
the accounts of human nature in Leviathan and the Elements but little in common
between their political sections (p. 19). However, compare Karl Schuhmann, Skinners Hobbes, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6 (1998): 121.
14
Hobbes, LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 728.
15
Lodi Nauta, Hobbes on Religon and the Church between The Elements of Law
and Leviathan: A Dramatic Change of Direction? Journal of the History of Ideas 63
(2002): 577. See, also, Hobbes the Pessimist?, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 10 (2002): 3154.
140
chapter six
16
hobbes interpretation
141
19
142
chapter six
20
Harold Love, Scribal Publication in Seventeenth-Century England (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), 5254.
21
Michael Kiernan, General Introduction and Textual Introduction to The
Essayes or Counsels, Civill and Morall, by Francis Bacon (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1985). Aubrey reports that Bacon dictated to a secretary while walking (Aubreys Brief Lives, 150), so it is conceivable that Hobbes modeled his way of
working on observation of Bacons practice.
22
John N. King, On Editing Foxes Book of Martyrs, Medieval & Renaissance
Texts & Studies 188 (1998), 53.
23
Thomas C. Faulkner, Robert Burtons Sources and Late Topical Revision in The
Anatomy of Melancholy, Medieval & Renaissance Texts & Studies 188 (1998): 23.
24
Aubrey, Aubreys Brief Lives, 150; Hobbes, Prose Life, 24647; and Malcolm,
Summary Biography, 21 and n. 34.
25
Sir Kenelm Digby to Hobbes, from Paris, 17[/27] January, 1637, Letter 25 in
Thomas Hobbes, The Correspondence, vol. I, ed. Noel Malcolm (Oxford: Clarendon,
1994), 4243.
hobbes interpretation
143
It is clear, at least, that the geometrical model was in play. The first
principle of knowledge, Hobbes explains in the work:
is, that we have such and such conceptions; the second, that we have
thus and thus named the things whereof they are conceptions; the third
is, that we have joined those names in such manner, as to make true
propositions; the fourth and last is, that we have joined those propositions in such manner as they be concluding. And by these four steps the
conclusion is known and evident, and the truth of the conclusion said
to be known.29
Following through on this idea of science, most of the text is constructed around a scaffolding of defined terms, which are highlighted
in black gothic script and linked with transitions sign-posting the
progress of the argument.30 However, the method breaks down in the
last chapters of the work, where the scaffolding of highlighted terms is
26
144
chapter six
hobbes interpretation
145
itself with those whom the matter it containeth most nearly concerneth,37 such as, possibly, the King and his closest advisers, Laud and
Strafford.38 In addition, the traditional stigma of print in court circles
might have made manuscript publication a better choice than print for
Newcastle and Hobbes.39
De Cive
In late 1640, Hobbes fled into exile in Paris, where he took up connections with a circle of scientists and philosophers associated with Marin
Mersenne, a French monk whom he had met on a mid-1630s trip to
the Continent. By November of the following year, only a year and a
half after the appearance of the Elements, he had completed the next in
his trio of political-theory texts, the first edition of De Cive. Although
it came out in print, in Latin, it was hardly more public a work than
the Elements: the edition was small and semianonymous, signed only
with Hobbess initials. Patronage played a role in this publication, as
it had in the case of the Elements. Where Newcastle had directed the
production of that first work, now Mersenne took on the role. It was
he who arranged for the publication of De Cive, and he subsequently
circulated the work for comments.40
By early 1646, Hobbes had completed a second edition of De Cive.
Published in Amsterdam early the following year, it gave the first fully
publiclarge and signedpresentation of Hobbess political theory.
It was an enlargement of the first edition with the addition of a new
preface and annotations in the text answering criticisms of the work.41
Hobbes prepared it by recording the additions and notes on a copy of
the first edition, from which the second was then printed.42 Once again,
patronage mattered. Samuel Sorbire, a member of Mersennes circle,
37
146
chapter six
hobbes interpretation
147
his new audience, it was surely faster to start with an existing manuscript than to begin entirely afresh. Subsequently, the process of serial
composition itself became a complicating factor for his plan of a unified, deductive science, since the process of continual authorial revision and expansion of the texts only invited disorder.
Leviathan
Hobbes seems to have viewed the second edition of De Cive as the
definitive statement of his moral theory, explaining in a 1646 letter
that he aimed to achieve in metaphysics and physics (on which he
was then working) what I hope I have achieved in moral theory.48
Indeed, the edition made his reputation on the Continent, and in the
eighteenth century would be more influential than Leviathan.49 Why,
then, did he go on to produce Leviathan? It unfortunately is a question
lacking a clear answer; we know remarkably little about whyor even
whenLeviathan was composed. This is an area in which the paucity
and uncertain reliability of the autobiographical materials particularly
matter.
Today, most scholars follow Schuhmann in dating the composition
to a single yearthe winter 1649/50 through the winter of 1650/51or
an approximation thereof.50 This is less than certain, however, because
Hobbess autobiographies indicate that he started the work in 1646,
during the period in which he was mathematics tutor to the Prince
of Wales and prior to a major illness in 1647.51 After the illness, we
know that he was absorbed for several years in the scientific section of
the tripartite project.52 But in 1649, he seems to have taken up politics
148
chapter six
hobbes interpretation
149
Hobbess rapid completion of both the Elements and De Cive. He cannot have had time to render all the pieces that went into the work
consistent with one another.
There was to be one more political-theory text: a Latin translation,
by Hobbes, of Leviathan, which was published in 1668. Once again,
there is disagreement over when it was actually composed and the
disagreement bears on understanding the composition of his political
theory. Franois Tricaud, in the introduction to his 1971 French translation, argues that there was a Latin proto-Leviathan which predated
the English version and was therefore intermediary between De Cive
and that work.58 Tricaud draws on earlier work by Zbigniew Lubienski
and F. C. Hood, but his thesis is disputed by Schuhmann and Rogers,
who stress the inferiority of the translations Latin to that in Hobbess
earlier Latin works.59
George Croom Robertson observed in his classic 1886 commentary
that in truth, the whole of [Hobbess] political doctrine . . . has little
appearance of having been thought out from the fundamental principles of his philosophy.60 It is clear that political crisis, Civil War, exile,
as well as patrons demands and directions, all pulled against Hobbess
philosophic aspirations. If we knew the complete story, filled in with
lost information about Leviathan, the narrative would no doubt be
even more complicated.
Three Texts or One (or Two)?
The conventional view, which is implicitly assumed in the preceding
discussion, is that the three political treatises are related in the way
that Aubrey said they were: This little MS. treatise [the Elements]
grew to be his Booke De Cive, and at last grew there to be the so
formidable LEVIATHAN.61 However, as I noted in the introduction,
58
Franois Tricaud, Introduction de Traducteur, in Lviathan by Thomas Hobbes
(Paris: ditions Sirey, 1971), xixxxix.
59
Rogers and Schuhmann, Introduction, 2301. On the comparison of the English and Latin versions, see also Skinner, Life, 2931. For examples of additions
and revisions to the Latin Leviathan that run counter to Tricauds thesis, see R. W.
Serjeantson, Hobbes, the Universities, and the History of Philosophy, in The Philosopher in Early Modern Europe, ed. Conal Condren, Stephen Gaukroger and Dan
Hunter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 13637.
60
Robertson, Hobbes, 57; see, also, 38.
61
Aubrey, Aubreys Brief Lives, 151.
150
chapter six
62
Thomas Hobbes, Considerations upon the Reputation, Loyalty, Manners, and
Religion, of Thomas Hobbes, English Works, vol. IV (1840), 414.
63
Thomas Hobbes, The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity, and Chance,
English Works, vol. V (1841), 453. For the continuity between Leviathan and De Cive,
see also the Prose Life, 250; Considerations, 426; and LV, A Review and Conclusion, p. 727. Hobbess friend, Robert Payne, reported in May 1651 that Much of
his de Cive is translated into Leviathan (Robert Payne Gilbert Sheldon, in Schuhmann, Chronique, 123). By contrast, however, the passage from the second edition of
De Cive quoted earlier, in the section on the work, seems to assimilate the Elements
to De Cive: there, Hobbes mentions writing his political work some few yeares before
the civill Warres did rage, which on its face refers farther back than the November
41 first edition of De Cive.
64
John Aubrey, The Brief Life, in EL(G), 235.
hobbes interpretation
151
production. His references to the later works carefully specify that they
were books. For instance, after describing the little treatise, he goes
on to report that, later: Being at Paris, he wrote and published his
book De Cive, in Latin; and subsequently, he wrote and published his
Leviathan.65 In similar vein, his Verse Life notes, I published . . . My
Book de Cive.66 Thus he seems to have drawn a modern distinction
between manuscript and print production, and counted only the latter
as publication. This implies that the Elements was a different sort of
work, not that it was an unconnected one. Perhaps Hobbes regarded it
as a draft of De Cive, which his patron had wanted to have circulated,
precipitously, in the spring of 1640.
Hobbes further contributed to confusion about the relationship
between the texts by a tendency to characterize Leviathan in terms of
its new material, in particular the expanded treatment of ecclesiology
and theology. His Prose Life (in which he refers to himself in the
third person) explains:
In that work he described the right of kings in both spiritual and temporal terms, using both reason and the authority of sacred scripture . . . He
hoped that this work might convince his countrymen, especially those
who had rejected the episcopacy, of its truth. He also wished at the same
time to deal with theological matters in the text.67
65
152
chapter six
I present illustrative comparisons of both sorts. For macro comparisons, Appendices I and II provide annotated outlines of the chapter
organizations of the Elements, De Cive, and Leviathan. Appendix I
shows the relationship between the first twelve chapters of Leviathan
and chapters two through thirteen of The Elements of Law; these are
chapters on human nature and knowledge that do not appear in De
Cive. Overall, it shows substantial, but hardly complete, continuity in
organization. A major change is the transformation of a section in the
Elements (Of the Faculties Motive), covering three chapters (79),
into a single omnibus chapter in Leviathan on the passions, which
included moving some material elsewhere. There are also changes in
chapter contents, which do not show up at this level of abstraction.
For instance, the consolidation of the treatment of the passions in
chapter six of Leviathan is accompanied by extensive reorganization
and revision in the list of specific passions. Also, curiously, the title of
chapter eight of that work, Of the Vertues, commonly called Intellectuall, and their contrary Defects, is accurate to the organization of
the parallel chapter in the Elements (ten), which counterposes virtues
and their opposing defects; however this format is not actually used
in the Leviathan chapter. Chapters eleven of Leviathan and thirteen in
the Elements have the same topicnamely, social relationshipsbut
different titles and different material.
Appendix II outlines comparison of all three works, starting where
De Cive picks up with the state of nature chapter. This appendix
emphasizes illustrative parallels so as to show the substantial continuity between the works, while also noting some instances of reorganization. Like Appendix I, changes in chapter contents do not appear at
this level of abstraction. The most obvious change overall is of course
the great expansion in the treatment of religious topics in Leviathan,
which begins on a modest scale in De Cive. There is also Leviathans
added chapter on authorization (16) and the Review and Conclusion,
with its much-debated endorsement of de facto authority. Less often
remarked, but clearly important to the subject matter, is the addition
of the seven chapters in Part II that treat the art of ruling, subjects
liberty, and criminal justice.
Next, by way of illustrating how the process of serial composition played out at the level of specific arguments, Table 1 presents a
micro comparison of the parallel chapters on the state of nature; it
charts significant changes and developments through the three versions. The most notable change is the transfer of discussion of natural
hobbes interpretation
153
De Cive
Leviathan
Ch. 13. Of the Naturall
Condition of Mankind . . .
12: deduction of
the natural state of
war: If now to this
naturall proclivity
of men, to hurt each
other . . . You adde,
the right of all
to all
68
154
chapter six
right from this to the following chapter in Leviathan, which has the
effect of deleting natural right from the logical deduction that a state
of nature would be a state of war. The table also shows how the arguments progressively evolved through the several versions, with several
additions in Leviathan originating in annotations to the second edition of De Cive.
Hobbess Way of Writing
We know that the texts evolved in this sort of way due to Hobbess
way of writing, which consisted, as Aubrey recorded about Leviathan,
in jotting down notes as he walked and subsequently fitting them into
an existing outline. Although Aubreys report specifically refers to
Leviathan, the method is also evident in De Cive, most obviously in
the insertion of annotations in the second edition. It further complicated matters that Hobbess framework was unstable: while inserting
points and arguments, he also very often engaged in moving existing
ones around. Altogether, the technique produced a distinctive kind of
work, which has been described as a juxtaposition, in a certain order,
of pages written at different times rather than a coherent, continuously composed treatise.69
The unit is frequently a topical block of several paragraphs, which
expand and/or otherwise change shape and content between the several works. The treatment of madness in the Elements and Leviathan
is illustrative. Chapter 10 in the first work, concerning differences
between men in their discerning faculty, has three paragraphs on
the subject, first defining it (9: some imagination of such predominance above all the rest, that we have no passion but from it)70 and
then offering examples (1011). Leviathan, chapter 8 (on intellectual
virtues and defects), opens discussion of madness with a parallel definition (16: stronger, and more vehement Passions for any thing)
and attributes it to great vaine-Glory . . . or great Dejection of mind,
as had the Elements.71 But, while chapter 10 of the Elements concludes
after the third paragraph on madness, in Leviathan Hobbes expands
69
hobbes interpretation
155
72
156
chapter six
Table 2: Comparison of the Three Covenant Passages
De Cive
Leviathan
7: The making of
union consisteth in
this, that every man by
covenant oblige himself
to some one and the
same man, or so some
one and the same
council, by them all
named and determined,
to do those actions,
which the said man or
council shall command
them to do; and to do
no action which he or
they shall forbid, or
command them not
to do.
7: This submission
of the wils of all those
men to the will of one
man, or one Counsell,
is then made, when
each one of them
obligeth himself by
contract to every one
of the rest, not to
resist the will of that
one man, or counsell,
to which he hath
submitted himselfe.
of the relationship between ruler and ruled: in De Cives version subjects have merely not to interfere with government, whereas Leviathan
actively implicates them in its actions. Thus the addition complicates
Hobbess defense of absolutism, since side-by-side in Leviathan now
stand the early no contract/nonresistance formulation and the later
authorization logic. It is a major example of the way in which his writing process could turn developmental inconsistencies between works
into internal inconsistencies within, in particular, Leviathan.
Such layers of argumentation have created interpretive disputes
about even the most essential aspects of Hobbism. Recall the debates
concerning religion and de facto authority that I briefly noted at the
start, and consider the extent to which they turn on textual issues.
Parts III and IV of Leviathan have received sustained attention over
the past several decadesattention that extends, in fact, even into
questioning the usual emphasis on Hobbess secular political topics.
Religion, Jeffrey Collins claims in The Allegiance of Thomas Hobbes,
was more than a discrete subject in Leviathan: conventional scholarship on Hobbes has failed . . . to grasp the fundamentally religious
hobbes interpretation
157
Much hinges on his definition of the relevant corpus. The substantive thesis crumbles if one rejects Collinss view of the relationship
between the core political-theory texts: if the three are related as a
single project, in which religion is originally treated as a minor topic,
then it cannot be accurate to characterize Leviathan as a fundamentally religious work.
Collinss thesis addresses an interpretive thicket initiated by a series
of articles by Richard Tuck on Hobbesian ecclesiology. Tuck portrayed
De Cive, not the Elements, as aberrant. He contrasted chapter seventeen of De Civein which Hobbes states that the sovereign is obligd
as a Christian . . . to interpret the Holy Scriptures by Clergy-men lawfully ordaind80with Leviathans assertion that the sovereign possesses complete ecclesiastical authority. From this, he concluded that
Hobbes must himself have believed that to a great extent [Leviathan]
had superceded De Cive.81 But, in turn, Glenn Burgess and Johann
78
Collins, Allegiance, 4. A similar claim was made by A. P. Martinich, The Two
Gods of Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on Religion and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1992).
79
Collins, Allegiance, 6162, see too 69.
80
Hobbes, DC, 17.28, p. 249.
81
Richard Tuck, Warrenders De Cive, Political Studies 33 (1985): 3134 (quotation appears on p. 313; emphasis mine); and Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1989), 2731, 7374, 8391.
158
chapter six
hobbes interpretation
159
texts are related and continuous, which as I have said is widely held.
Yet the evidence suggests we need to think about continuity in a new
way. Nauta and Hoekstra, much as they otherwise differ, accept the
common equation of continuity with consistency and discontinuity
with inconsistency. (Nauta writes, There is no fundamental reversal
or new direction in Hobbess position, but rather a development and
an extension of a line of thinking which is already clearly visible in
the earlier works.86 For his part, Hoekstras purpose in identifying a
thematic doctrine of doctrines is to reveal an underlying consistency
beneath the twists and turns over time in Hobbess argumentation.)
However, Hobbess method of writing actually pulled in a different
direction. His habit of inserting new material into existing discussions
made inconsistency as much or more likely a concomitant of continuity as consistency. Think, for instance, of the evolution of the covenant
passages. They are clearly continuous insofar as Hobbes kept adding
new material to old, but the process resulted in rivalinconsistent
versions of the covenant logic in Leviathan. In his case, continuity
bred inconsistency and contradiction as much as the opposite.
Conclusion
Attention to compositional process cannot, on its own, resolve Hobbisms puzzles, but it can clarify interpretive disputes and make us wary
about the selective use of textual evidence. To frame its import more
specifically, recall the critical queries set out at the end of the introduction. How, to start with the least critical, should understanding
Hobbess compositional process affect evaluation of interpretations?
Can it help us distinguish a better from a worse interpretation? The
process of serial composition makes textual plausibility an important
criterion of interpretation. Interpreters need to be careful, in the first
instance, that claims about and characterizations of Hobbess political
theory are plausible in terms of the facts of composition and chronology. For example, a strong claim that Hobbess political theory is
fundamentally religious is implausible, given the sparing treatment of
religion in the Elements. Although a necessary condition of good interpretation, textual plausibility cannot be a sufficient condition since it is
86
160
chapter six
87
hobbes interpretation
161
Latin Leviathan, De Corpore and De Homine. The closest approximations are marginal references in some editions, narrative comparisons,
and charts showing chapter comparisons.89 But these are difficult to
follow or offer inadequate information, which leaves scholars needing to work out comparisons again and again in ad hoc fashion. A
multiple-text edition would facilitate our analysis of the evolution of
particular arguments and support systematic overviews of the larger
sweep of changes through the multiple texts.
On a continuum of textual difficulty, Hobbess political theory
stands at the farther extreme away from the simpler texts produced by
present-day compositional practices. He complicated the early-modern process of serial composition by the way in which he went about
inserting new material and moving old around. Still, the standards
that can help us make sense of the impact of process on his political
theorytextual plausibility, specificity, and the need for textual archaeologyare more generally applicable. Interpretations ought always
to be textually plausible, specific, and to take into account developments in an authors thinking. Otherwise, as Gadamer taught us,
we risk eliminating the horizon of the text from the interpretive
enterprise.90
89
Warrenders editions of the English and Latin De Cives give marginal references
to parallels in the Elements and Leviathan; Rogers and Schuhmann, Introduction,
and Schuhmann, Leviathan and De Cive, provide narrative comparisons; Gaskins
edition of the Elements charts chapter comparisons with De Corpore as well as the two
other political works.
90
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. ed. by Garrett Barden and John
Cumming (London: Sheed & Ward, 1975).
162
chapter six
Appendix I
Chapter Parallels, Leviathan 112 and
The Elements of Law, 213*
1. Sense
2. Cause of Sense
2. Imagination
3. Imagination . . .
4. Speech
6. Knowledge . . .
1 & 4. definition of science
6. Passions
[10. Of Power, Worth, Dignity,
Honour]
: Faculties Motive
7. Delight and Pain; Good and Evil
8. Pleasures of the Sense; Honour
9. Passions of the Mind
[6.68]
9. Knowledge
[6. Knowledge . . .]
[8.5. honour]
12. . . . by Deliberation proceed
Actions
12. Of Religion
hobbes interpretation
163
Appendix II
Outline of The Elements of Law, Chapters 1429, De Cive,
Chapters 118, and Leviathan, Chapters 1331, 3943,
including illustrative parallels*
The Elements of Law
De Cive
Leviathan
Part I (cont.)
Liberty
Part I (cont.)
2. Law of Nature
concerning contracts
3. Other Lawes of
nature
12: perform
covenants
13: acknowledge
equality
1: perform covenants
Empire
5. First Originall, of
civill government
17. Definition of a
Commonwealth
7. Three kindes of
Government
164
chapter six
Appendix II (cont.)
The Elements of Law
De Cive
[Ch. 21.1216:
discharge of subjection]
24. Incommodities of
10. Comparison of
Several Government[s] the three kinds of
government
Leviathan
11. Scripture
[20. 1617]
concerning the right of
government
2225, 2728: Subject
Systems; Public
Ministers; Nutrition
and Procreation of
a Commonwealth;
Counsell; Crimes;
Punishments and
Rewards
[Ch. 26 appears below.]
2526. Decision[s]
[on] Religion Depend
on the Sovereign
Power
27. Causes of Rebellion 12. Causes which
dissolve all civill
government
29. Nature/Kinds of
Laws
hobbes interpretation
165
Appendix II (cont.)
The Elements of Law
De Cive
Leviathan
Religion
1517. Gods
government by nature;
old Covenant; new
Covenant
17.1921: nature of a
Church
AFTERWORD
CHAPTER SEVEN
1
For a history of the term absolutist, beginning with its usage by Hegels successor at the University of Berlin, see Istvan Hont, Jealousy of Trade: International
Competition and the Nation-State in Historical Perspective (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press/Belknap, 2005), 45960. See also Nicholas Henshall, The Myth
of Absolutism: Change & Continuity in Early Modern European Monarchy (London:
Longman, 1992), ch. 1.
170
chapter seven
2
As the editors of the volume, Monarchisms in the Age of Enlightenment, point
out, classic republicanism included a monarchic element (Hans Blom, John Christian
Laursen and Luisa Simonutti, ed., Monarchisms in the Age of Enlightenment: Liberty,
Patriotism, and the Common Good [Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007], 6).
3
Cf. Noel Malcolm, Reason of State, Propaganda, and the Thirty Years War: An
Unknown Translation by Thomas Hobbes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), ch. 6, esp.
11819, and Istvan Hont, Jealousy of Trade, chs. 1 and 7.
4
See Preston King, The Ideology of Order: A Comparative Analysis of Jean Bodin
and Thomas Hobbes (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1974), for a definition of absolutism in terms of movement towards centralization as opposed to its accomplishment,
8384.
5
It has seemed so to Quentin Skinner: [T]wo main traditions of absolutist political philosophy had become established by the close of the sixteenth century. One
of these was the providentialist tradition, later associated in particular with Filmer in
England and Bossuet in France. The other was the more rationalist tradition stemming
from Bodin and the neo-Thomists, and reaching its climax in the natural-law systems
afterword
171
contract theory, they do not. While essays in this volume have noted
two other typical features of early-modern contract theoriesnamely,
a tendency to combine voluntarist and nonvoluntarist claims (chapter
four) and a preoccupation with the subject of resistance (chapters one
and two), in other respectsvisions of the best form of government
most notablycontract theories were all over the board. As well as
using different philosophical styles and idioms, Bodin, Grotius, and
Hobbes also disagreed about forms of government. What they shared,
instead, was an understanding of the state, its tasks and place in human
life.6 Conceptualized as the basis of a tradition, this understanding
provides a context in which to locate and compare their discussions
of local political issues and events, and it facilitates comparisons, more
broadly, with other theories of similar outlook. Jenkinsons comment,
quoted initially, picks out the two defining themes of the tradition:
a concern with state sovereignty and a fear of religious civil war. To
these I will add below: secularism; quasi-normativity, meaning a
habit of blending descriptive and prescriptive statements; and, lastly,
a sensibility best described as the absolutism of fear.
Bodins Rpublique earned a place in the canonical history of ideas
for the single idea that an ultimate authority, accountable only to God,
is a necessary feature of the state as a political unit. Soueraigntie, he
wrote, is the most high, absolute, and perpetuall power ouer the citisens and subiects in a Commonweale; the prince or people themselues, in whome the Soueraigntie resteth, are to giue account vnto none,
but to the immortall God alone.7 Just so, Grotius echoed, sovereign
power is That power . . . whose actions are not subject to the legal control of another, so that they cannot be rendered void by the operation
of another human will.8 And Hobbes in turn declared that In every
perfect City . . . there is a Supreme power in some one, greater then
which cannot by Right be conferrd by men . . . that power . . . we call
of Grotius and Pufendorf. John Locke in the Two Treatises of Government may be
said to have mounted the definitive attack on both these traditions (Foundations of
Modern Political Thought, Vol. II, The Age of Reformation [Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1978], 347).
6
In the Conclusion of Foundations, vol. II, Skinner discusses the emergence, by the
early seventeenth century, of a focus on a concept of the State (34958).
7
Bodin, SB, I.viii, pp. 84, 86. See the discussion of Bodinian Absolutism in chapter 4.
8
Grotius, DJB, I.iii.7, p. 102. See chapter 4, above, on Grotian Contractarianism.
172
chapter seven
Hobbes, DC, VI.xiii, p. 97. See the section Hobbesian Contractarian Absolutism in chapter 4.
10
Gianfranco Poggi, The Development of the Modern State: A Sociological Introduction (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1978), 74.
11
Regarding Bodin, see Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 28486. Grotius was initially
sentenced to death but this was later reduced to life imprisonment, partly, it must be
said, because he testified against his patron, who was executed (Tuck, Philosophy and
Government, 18184).
12
Considerations upon the Reputation, Loyalty, Manners, and Religion, of Thomas
Hobbes of Malmesbury, English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, ed. Sir William Molesworth, vol. IV [London: J. Bohn, 1840], 414; Thomas Hobbes, Behemoth or
the Long Parliament, ed. F. Tnnies, 2nd ed. (London: Frank Cass, 1969), 23.
afterword
173
13
Hobbes, EL(G), Chapters and Table of Contents, pp. 1415. The work contains
only one other chapter on religion, which contrasts with the lengthy treatment of the
subject in Parts III and IV of Leviathan. That third chapter (18) supplies Scriptural
confirmation for the laws of nature that were laid out in the previous two chapters
(p. 10).
14
Julian H. Franklin, Jean Bodin and the Rise of Absolutist Theory (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1973), 41, 5051; Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 285:
Given this vision of the frailty of order and the paramount need to maintain it,
Bodin clearly saw his major ideological task . . . as that of attacking and repudiating
the Huguenot theory of resistance, which he had come to regard as the greatest single
threat to the possibility of re-establishing a well-ordered monarchy in France.
15
Bodin, SB, I.9, p. 146; III.2, p. 290; III.3, p. 300.
16
Bodin, SB, IV.7, pp. 53539. See Skinner, Foundations, vol. II, 352.
17
Hugo Grotius, Ordinum Hollandiae ac Westfrisiae Pietas, ed. and trans. Edwin
Rabbie (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1995), 118, p. 189. See Henk J. M. Nellen, Hugo Grotiuss Political and Scholarly Activities in the Light of his Correspondence, in Property, Piracy and Punishment, ed. Hans W. Blom (Leiden: Brill, 2009): 2526; and Jan
Rohls, Calvinism, Arminianism and Socinianism in the Netherlands until the Synod
of Dort, in Socinianism and Arminianism: Antitrinitarians, Calvinists and Cultural
Exchange in Seventeenth-Century Europe, ed. Martin Mulsow and Jan Rohls (Leiden:
Brill, 2005), 348.
174
chapter seven
there being more than one) and that he has a care for the affairs of
men.18 Hobbes defended another version of religious minimalism as
well as the authority of the state over religion. He told fellow subjects,
All that is necessary to Salvation, is contained in two Vertues, Faith
in Christ, and Obedience to Laws; moreover, all that God requires
is a serious Endeavour of obedience.19 By combining this doctrine
with the institution of a state-controlled national church, he further
explained, it is not hard to reconcile our Obedience to God, with our
Obedience to the Civill Soveraign.20
Part and parcel of their preoccupation with religious conflict was
the secularism of their theories. All three were notorious for advancing secular arguments, which opened them to the dangerous charge of
atheism. Grotius was the boldest, proclaiming in the opening pages of
De Jure Belli ac Pacis: What we have been saying would have a degree
of validity even if we should concede that which cannot be conceded
without the utmost wickedness, that there is no God, or that the affairs
of men are of no concern to Him.21 Hobbes burned correspondence,
late in life, from fear of prosecution for heresy, and indeed in 1666 a
parliamentary committee cited Leviathan as exemplary of books as
tend to Atheisme Blasphemy or Prophanenesse or against the Essence
or Attributes of God.22 The political foundation of their secularism
is obscured if we regard their political theories as derivations from
assumptions about individual psychology and morality, as the socialcontract metaphor dictates. Regarding these thinkers as theorists of a
18
Grotius, DJB, II.20.46, p. 513. This was elaborated (though with the exclusion of
polytheism) in terms of four principles that are common to true religion in all ages:
there is one God; who is more exalted than anything we see; who cares for and judges
human affairs, and is the creator of all things (II.20.45, pp. 51011). This material is
discussed in Richard Tucks, Philosophy and Government, 18495.
19
Hobbes, LV, 43, pp. 61011. He summarizes: Whosoever therefore unfeignedly
desireth to fulfill the Commandements of God, or repenteth him truely of his transgressions, or that loveth God with all his heart, and his neighbor as himself, hath all
the Obedience Necessary to his Reception into the Kingdome of God: For if God
should require perfect Innocence, there could no flesh be saved (611).
20
LV, 42, p. 575, and 43, p. 624.
21
DJB, Prolegomena, p. 13.
22
BL MS Harl. 7257 (journal of the House of Commons, 16656), p. 220 (17/[27] Oct.
1666), quoted in Noel Malcolm, General Introduction to Thomas Hobbes, The Correspondence, vol. I (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), xxv. Regarding Bodin, see J. H. M.
Salmon, The French Religious Wars in English Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1959), 23: he was notorious as a rationalist in his religious opinions and
was represented by Ben Jonson . . . as an atheist fit for the company of Machiavelli.
afterword
175
176
chapter seven
afterword
177
suggest that interest constituted some kind of justification for acting.27 Perhaps Bodin learned the style from Machiavelli or others of
the reason of state school; however, where those thinkers used it in
connection with rulers actions, he applied it to constitutional issues.
Once one notices quasi-normativity, it becomes apparent that it
littered the landscape of early-modern political and social philosophizing. In chapter four, I discussed contract theorys peculiar blend
of voluntarist and nonvoluntarist claims, in the form of the typical
assertion that a contract of a particular sort both would and should
be chosen. This, clearly, is a variant of prescription by definition
and, I argued in that chapter, was something Hobbes appears to have
learned from Bodin and which subsequently was passed down to
Rawlsian theory. In this regard, therefore, it may be apt to conclude
that modern contract theory owes one of its most fundamentaland
problematicfeatures to early-modern absolutist and reason-of-state
argumentation. Moreover, the natural jurisprudence of Grotius and
Hobbes had a similar character inasmuch as they derived prescriptive natural law from propositions about human nature universally.28
This is among the points at which there is an affinity between absolutist theory and Humean philosophy, albeit one that Hume missed
(or ignored) by making Lockean contract thinking his foil. Where he
might have noted a parallel between the naturalism of his thinking
and their natural jurisprudence, both being efforts to root philosophical principles in ordinary impulses and experience, he instead concentrated on how alien the contract story was to everyday political
experience.
Many years ago, I framed the idea of viewing early-modern thinkers
as observers on the ground of the development of the state in Western
Europe. It was, I have come to realize, an anachronistic idea insofar
as it presupposed a distinction between observation and prescription.
Clearly these thinkers were innocent of the (Humean) knowledge
that ought cannot be derived from is29 and developed a hybrid in
a number of different forms. It may not be speculating too wildly to
27
Malcolm, Reason of State, 95. I take the term quasi-normativity from this discussion (94).
28
Tuck, Philosophy and Government, esp. 190.
29
Hume, Treatise, 52021. Regarding the contrast between Hobbes and Hume
on the issue, see C. B. Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism:
Hobbes to Locke (London: Oxford University Press, 1962), 8187.
178
chapter seven
30
Judith N. Shklar, Ordinary Vices (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press/
Belknap, 1984), 237.
31
Thomas Hobbes, A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common
Laws of England, English Works, vol. VI (1840), 13. I discussed Hobbess version of
this sensibility in Hobbess Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1988), ch. 7.
32
Bodin, SB, IV.5, p. 494. A margin note summarized: Contention betwixt great
magistrats or courts, about their power and jurisdicton, alwais vnto the poore subject
hurtfull (III.6, p. 356). See, too, IV.4, p. 476: cities, citisens, and Commonweales, vse
commonly to be for nothing more turmoiled and troubled than by men for the obtaining of offices and honours. Also, SB, IV.7, p. 519: if one shall say, That seditions, and
ciuill warres, are good, hee might also say, that murders, parricides, adulteries, theft,
and the subuersion of estates & Commonweales are also good.
33
Bodin, SB, III.7, pp. 37071. See Franklin, Jean Bodin, 9091.
afterword
179
34
To the contrary, writing De Jure Belli ac Pacis in exile, he describes himself as
undeservedly forced out from my native land and now consigned to study in private
and deprived of the opportunity for public service, which I practised with the utmost
degree of probity of which I was capable (Prolegomena, pp. 2021).
35
This contrast is drawn by Hont, Jealousy of Trade, 1617.
36
Sally Jenkinson, Bayle and Hume on Monarchy, Scepticism, and Forms of Government, in Monarchisms, ed. Blom et al., 69, 71.
37
Nicholas Phillipson discusses Humes awareness of this transformation in Hume
(London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1989), ch. 2.
38
Cf. David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Humes Philosophical Thought
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), who argues in the concluding chapter that Humes
thought had both liberal and conservative features and is better labeled an establishment ideology; and Anthony Quinton, The Politics of Imperfection: The religious
and secular traditions of conservative thought in England from Hooker to Oakeshott
(London: Faber and Faber, 1978), who labels Humes philosophy conservative rationalism (45).
180
chapter seven
39
40
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Alexander, Sidney S. Social Evaluation Through Notional Choice. The Quarterly
Journal of Economics 88 (1974): 597624.
Allen, J. W. A History of Political Thought in the Sixteenth Century. London: Methuen,
1960.
Allen, William [Edward Sexby]. Killing Noe Murder: Briefly Discourst in Three Quaestions, 1657. In Divine Right and Democracy, edited by D. Wootton. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1986.
Ashcraft, Richard. Revolutionary Politics and Lockes Two Treatises of Government.
Political Theory 8 (1980): 42986.
. Revolutionary Politics & Lockes Two Treatises of Government. Princeton, N. J.:
Princeton University Press, 1986.
Aubrey, John. Thomas Hobbes. In Aubreys Brief Lives, edited by O. L. Dick. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962.
Baumgold, Deborah. Hobbess Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1988.
Baynes, Kenneth. The Normative Grounds of Social Criticism: Kant, Rawls, and Habermas. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992.
Benhabib, Seyla. The Methodological Illusions of Modern Political Theory. Neue
Hefte fr Philosophie 21 (1982): 4774.
Blom, Hans, John Christian Laursen, and Luisa Simonutti, eds. Monarchisms in the
Age of Enlightenment: Liberty, Patriotism, and the Common Good. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2007.
Brett, Annabel. Natural Right and Civil Community: The Civil Philosophy of Hugo
Grotius. The Historical Journal 45 (2002): 3151.
Burgess, Glenn. Usurpation, Obligation and Obedience in the Thought of the Engagement Controversy. The Historical Journal 29 (1986): 51536.
. Contexts for the Writing and Publication of Hobbess Leviathan. History of
Political Thought 11 (1990): 675702.
. On Hobbesian Resistance Theory. Political Studies 42 (1994): 6283.
Burke, Edmund. Reflections on the Revolution in France. Garden City, N. Y.: Doubleday/Anchor, 1973.
Collingwood, R. G. An Autobiography. London: Oxford University Press, 1970.
Collins, Jeffrey R. The Allegiance of Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2005.
DAddario, Christopher. Exile and Journey in Seventeenth-Century Literature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Darnton, Robert. What is the History of Books?. In Books and Society in History,
edited by K. E. Carpenter. New York: R. R. Bowker, 1983.
Dunn, John. The Political Thought of John Locke. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1969.
. The Politics of Locke in England and America in the Eighteenth Century.
In Political Obligation in its Historical Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1980.
Dzelzainis, Martin. Edward Hyde and Thomas Hobbess Elements of Law, Natural
and Politic. The Historical Journal 32 (1989): 30317.
Faulkner, Thomas C. Robert Burtons Sources and Late Topical Revision in The Anatomy of Melancholy. Medieval & Renaissance Texts & Studies. Vol. 188, New Ways
of Looking at Old Texts, II, edited by W. S. Hill, 1998.
182
bibliography
bibliography
183
. The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity, and Chance. The English Works of
Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, edited by W. Molesworth. Vol. V. London: J. Bohn,
1841.
. To the Right Honourable the Marquis of Newcastle [dedication to A minute
or first draught of the Optiques]. The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, edited by W. Molesworth. Vol. VII. London: J. Bohn, 1845.
. Six Lessons to the Professors of the Mathematics. The English Works of Thomas
Hobbes of Malmesbury, edited by W. Molesworth. Vol. VII. London: J. Bohn,
1845.
. The Autobiography of Thomas Hobbes, translated by B. Farrington. In The
Rationalist Annual 1958, edited by H. Hawton. London: Watts & Co, 1957.
. Behemoth or the Long Parliament. 2d ed., edited by F. Tnnies. London: Frank
Cass, 1969.
. Lviathan: trait de la matire, de la forme et du pouvoir de la rpublique ecclsiastique et civile, translated by F. Tricaud. Paris: ditions Sirey, 1971.
. Critique du De Mundo de Thomas White, edited by J. Jacquot and H. W. Jones.
Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1973.
. The Correspondence of Thomas Hobbes, edited by N. Malcolm. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.
. The Prose Life. In The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, by T. Hobbes,
edited by J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994.
. The Verse Life. In The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, by T. Hobbes,
edited by J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994.
. Three Discourses: A Critical Modern Edition of Newly Identified Work of the
Young Hobbes, edited by N. B. Reynolds and A. W. Saxonhouse. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995.
Hoekstra, Kinch. Hobbes on Law, Nature, and Reason. Journal of the History of
Philosophy 41 (2003): 11120.
. The de facto Turn in Hobbess Political Philosophy. In Leviathan After 350
Years, edited by T. Sorrell and L. Foisneau. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004.
. IIThe End of Philosophy (The Case of Hobbes). Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (2006): 2360.
Holzgrefe, J. L. The Origins of Modem International Relations Theory. Review of
International Studies 15 1989: 1126.
Honig, B. Rawls on Politics and Punishment. Political Research Quarterly 46 (1993):
99125.
Hont, Istvan. Jealousy of Trade: International Competition and the Nation-State in
Historical Perspective. Cambridge. Mass.: Harvard University Press/Belknap, 2005.
Hpfl, Harro and Martyn P. Thompson. The History of Contract as a Motif in Political Thought. American Historical Review 84 (1979): 91244.
Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by E. C. Mossner. Harmondsworth,
Middlesex: Penguin/Pelican, 1969.
. Of the Original Contract In Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, edited by
E. F. Miller. Indianapolis. Indiana: Liberty Fund, 1987.
. Of Passive Obedience. In Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, edited by E. F.
Miller. Indianapolis. Indiana: Liberty Fund, 1987.
Jacoby, E. G. Thomas Hobbes in Europe. Journal of European Studies 4 (1974):
5765.
Jacquot, Jean and Harold Whitmore Jones. Introduction to Critique du De Mundo
de Thomas White, by T. Hobbes. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1973.
James I. The Trew Law of Free Monarchies, 1598.
Jefferson, Thomas. The Political Writings of Thomas Jefferson: Representative Selections,
edited by E. Dumbauld. Indianapolis, Indiana: Bobbs-Merrill, 1955.
. A Declaration by the Representatives of the United States of America, in
184
bibliography
bibliography
185
McClure, Kirstie. Judging Rights: Lockean Politics and the Limits of Consent. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1996.
McKenzie, D. F. Bibliography and the Sociology of Texts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Miller, David. Philosophy and Ideology in Humes Philosophical Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981.
Mosse, George L. The Struggle for Sovereignty in England. New York: Octagon Press,
1968.
Nauta, Lodi. Hobbes the Pessimist?. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 10
(2002): 3154.
. Hobbes on Religion and the Church between The Elements of Law and Leviathan: A Dramatic Change of Direction?. Journal of the History of Ideas 63 (2002):
57798.
Nellen, Henk J. M. Hugo Grotiuss Political and Scholarly Activities in the Light of
his Correspondence. In Property, Piracy and Punishment, edited by H. W. Blom.
Leiden: Brill, 2009.
Nenner, Howard. The Later Stuart Age. In The Varieties of British Political Thought,
15001800, edited by J. G. A. Pocock. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1993.
. The Right to be King. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1995.
Parker, David. Law, Society and the State in the Thought of Jean Bodin. History of
Political Thought 2 (1981): 25385.
Parker, Henry. Observations upon some of his Majesties late Answers and Expresses,
1642.
Phillipson, Nicholas. Hume. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1989.
Pitkin, Hanna. Hobbess Concept of RepresentationII. American Political Science
Review 58 (1964): 90218.
Plamenatz, John. Man and Society. Vol. 1. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1963.
Plumb, J. H. The Origins of Political Stability: England 16751725. Boston: Houghton
Mifflin, 1967.
Pocock, J. G. A. The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law. New York: Norton, 1967.
. The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law: A Reissue with a Retrospect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.
Poggi, Gianfranco. The Development of the Modern State: A Sociological Introduction.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1978.
Polin, Raymond. Politique et Philosophie chez Thomas Hobbes. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1953.
Pufendorf, Samuel. De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo, translated by C. H. Oldfather and W. A. Oldfather. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1934.
Quinton, Anthony. The Politics of Imperfection: The religious and secular traditions
of conservative thought in England from Hooker to Oakeshott. London: Faber and
Faber, 1978.
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press/Belknap,
1971.
. Reply to Alexander and Musgrave. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 88
(1974): 63355.
. Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs
14 (1985): 22351.
. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.
. Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy, edited by S. Freeman. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press/Belknap, 2007.
Rhodes, Rosamond. Obligation and Assent in Hobbess Moral Philosophy. Hobbes
Studies 15 (2000): 4567.
186
bibliography
bibliography
187
188
bibliography
Wootton, David, ed. Divine Right and Democracy. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1986.
Wootton, David. John Locke and Richard Ashcrafts Revolutionary Politics. Political
Studies 40 (1992): 7998.
Zagorin, Perez. Hobbes on Our Mind. Journal of the History of Ideas 51 (1990):
31735.
. Hobbes Without Grotius. History of Political Thought 21 (2000): 1640.
INDEX
absolutism, 9, 34, 41, 43, 47 n, 76,
8889, 169 n, 170 n, 171172, 17577;
Bodins account of, 55, 76 n, 8487,
88 n, 89, 171, 176; of fear, 171, 176,
17880; Grotiuss account of, 3335,
53, 5758, 8084, 179; Hobbess
discussion of, 810, 13, 23, 37, 40,
54, 56 n, 59, 6366, 7173, 75, 8990,
93, 96, 11921, 12324, 144, 15556;
Hobbess use of Bodin and Grotius,
5556, 58, 7778, 9091, 94, 12122,
124; Lockes critique of, 7, 14, 43, 46,
47 n
accountability of government, 6, 27, 89;
Bodins view of, 60, 171; Grotiuss
treatment of, 30, 3335, 57, 83;
Hobbess discussion of, 813, 37,
58, 6061, 65, 73, 92, 119; Lockes
account of, 19, 4142, 47; and
violence, 2829, 45, 49
Alexander, Sidney, 99 n
Ashcraft, Richard, 14, 39 nn, 43 n, 44
n, 47
Aubrey, John, 116, 126, 136, 14950,
154
Barclay, William, 15
Behemoth, 5, 53 n, 6768, 71 n, 138, 172
Blom, Hans, 170 n
Brett, Annabel, 82
Buchanan, George, 15
Burgess, Glen, 12627, 137 n, 15758
Burke, Edmund, 24
Charles I, 4, 11, 63, 67, 71, 111, 145, 148
Charles II, 14, 148
Civil War, English, 5, 10, 12, 48, 71, 114,
172
Clarendon, Earl of. See Hyde, Edward
Collingwood, R. G., 27 n
Collins, Jeffrey, 15657
constitutional (historical)
contractarianism, 3, 13, 19, 58, 64,
7173, 8083
contractarianism. See constitutional
(historical) contractarianism;
philosophical contractarianism
Cromwell, Oliver, 5, 44, 68
190
index