José Diez - Falsificationism and The Structure of Theories: The Popper - Kuhn Controversy About The Rationality of Normal Science (2007)
José Diez - Falsificationism and The Structure of Theories: The Popper - Kuhn Controversy About The Rationality of Normal Science (2007)
José Diez - Falsificationism and The Structure of Theories: The Popper - Kuhn Controversy About The Rationality of Normal Science (2007)
Studies in History
and Philosophy
of Science
Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 38 (2007) 543554
www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa
Abstract
Many controversies within philosophy of science have been attempted to be explained in terms of the metaphilosophical prescription/
description distinction over the goal of philosophy of science. The aim of this paper is to show that the controversy between Popper and
Kuhn about the ir/rationality of Normal Science cannot be fully explained in these terms, not even if we also take the truth/problemsolving distinction over the goal of science into account. It is argued that, to gain full understanding of this controversy, it is necessary to
take into account their dierences regarding a topic apparently not involved in it, namely the structure of scientic theories. The conclusion is that both Popper and Kuhn were descriptive/prescriptive at the same time in their attempt to make the rules of (a specic part
of) scientic practice explicit, yet Kuhn did it better because he had a richer and more accurate idea of what scientic theories are.
Although this work is mainly a piece of history of philosophy of science, it also aims at shedding some light on epistemological issues.
If the conclusion is sound, it also shows how structural aspects of scientic theories may be relevant to the epistemology of science.
2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
Keywords: Falsicationism; Normal science; Rationality; Theories; Thomas Kuhn; Karl Popper
When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
and Kuhn about the ir/rationality of Normal Science cannot be fully explained in terms of the metaphilosophical
prescription/description distinction, not even if we also
take the truth/problem-solving distinction over the goal
of science into account. To gain full understanding of this
controversy, it is necessary to take into account their dierences regarding a topic apparently not involved in it,
namely the structure of scientic theories. I begin with
some introductory remarks about the task of philosophy
of science showing that, in the specic eld relevant to
the controversy, description and prescription are not in
opposition, and that, a fortiori, their alleged opposition
cannot explain crucial episodes of such controversy.
Secondly, I introduce the main textual references of the
544
rule-following and allows others. The rules of many practices do not determine a unique course of action, but this
does not mean that they are not normative/prescriptive.
All this applies to scientic practices as well. Scientists
perform certain practices like testing, explaining, experimenting, working within a theory, and so on. These practices are constituted by their own rules, and philosophers of
science try to make these rules explicit by analysing the corresponding scientic practices. The analysis must be evaluated in the light of historical/empirical data about scientic
practice, taking paradigmatic examples specially into
account. For instance, if certain analysis of working within
a theory implies that the rst predictive failure amounts to
(epistemically) throwing the whole theory away, then it
enters into conict with paradigmatic examples of good scientic practice like working within Newtonian theory
when, before the discovery of Neptune, predictions about
Uranus trajectory didnt t the data.
As in the other cases, this endeavour of describing the
rules governing scientic practices has normative import
and allows for evaluating some performances as good, that
is, rule-following (e.g. Lavoisiers mercury experiment),
and some others as bad, that is, non-rule-following (e.g.
phlogiston theorists attempt to face Lavoisier experiment
postulating negative mass). This normativity, which
excludes certain courses of action, is, again, compatible
with leaving some others open, that is, it may not uniquely
determine what to do in a specic situation.
Scientic practices, though, have a peculiar character.
They are the paradigm (or at least, one prominent paradigm) of epistemic rationality, of coming to believe in a
rational way. And this does not simply follow from its
being constituted by rules, since there are many other practices that are constituted by rules which are not rational in
the relevant sense, such as exorcism, tarot, chiromancy,
astrology, and the like. Of course one can stipulate a sense
of rational equating it with performing a practice according to its constitutive rules, and maybe it could even be
useful for distinguishing, say, rational astrology practitioners from irrational ones. But this is not the relevant sense
at stake. Scientic practice is paradigmatically rational in a
sense in which other, also regulated, practices are not. And
this specic rationality must rest in the specicity of the
constitutive rules of scientic practice. It is then an additional task for philosophy of science to elucidate the sense
in which the constitutive rules of scientic practice make
such a peculiar practice a paradigm of rationality (although
545
Scientists work from models acquired through education and through subsequent exposure to the literature
often without quite knowing or needing to know what
the characteristics have given these models the status
of community paradigms. And because they do so, they
need no full set of rules. Paradigms may be prior to,
more binding, and more complete than any set of rules
for research that could be unequivocally abstracted
from them. (Ibid., p. 46)
Contrary to appearances, I dont think these passages are
in tension with the above characterisation of the analysis of
scientic practice as making the rules of such practice explicit. There are two readings of the word rule involved here.
In the strong reading, it refers to a set of quasi-mechanised
procedures that one can explicitly be taught in practicelearning.7 This is the sense in which the late Wittgenstein
famously denied that to learn a language is to learn a set
of such rules and claimed, instead, that to learn a language
consist better in capturing similarities among groups of paradigmatic examples. This is the sense used by Kuhn in these
passages, who explicitly mentions Wittgensteins move at
the beginning of the chapter. In this sense, according to
Kuhn (and to me) normal science does not reduce to a set
of rules; in normal science the ability to capture similarities
among paradigms/exemplars plays a more important and
essential role. It is in this sense that normal science is not
guided by rules but by paradigms. But this is not the sense
in which I stated above that scientic practice, like any other
practice, is constituted by rules. In this weaker sense, for
instance, trying to apply the same symbolic generalisations
to cases which one nds similar to paradigms, is one of the
rules that constitute normal science, and not reducible to
any set of rules in the rst, stronger sense.8
2. Popper and Kuhn on the ir/rationality of normal science
Which are the aspects of the controversy that are better
understood as caused by their implicit disagreements on
the structure of theories? What might be called the possibility conditions for the rationality of NS. If Popper were
right, NS could not be rational, NS would be irrational in
principle. If Kuhn (and Lakatos) is (are) right, NS may
be perfectly rational (and as a matter of fact,9 it is almost
always rational). The parts of the controversy I deal with
are then conned to these, so to speak, transcendental
Of course one could always try to impose dierent rules, yet this is not to analyse a practice but to change it.
Of course this does not need to coincide with either Popper or Kuhn self-description of their task in general, and of their controversy in particular, since
they may be metaphilosophically misguided (as, if I am right, they partially are).
6
I owe this criticism to an anonymous referee.
7
For instance, to learn the syntax of a formal language, for example the rules of well formed formulae in, say, propositional logic. But there are very few
interesting real life examples, if any, of such rules and practices; maybe chess-moving or following driving regulations, which of course are only part of
the more complex practices playing chess and driving, really real life and not rule-guided in this rst sense.
8
Just as playing chess or driving are constituted by rules in this weak sense which are not reducible to sets of rules in the stronger sense. One might
now object that then the thesis that scientic practice is constituted buy rules is very weak. And it actually is, but not totally empty; it simply emphasises
that scientic practice is a practice and, like any other practice, analysing it consists in making explicit what the practice consists in. If someone objects that
in this weak sense it is better not to use the word rule, I would be happy with some other more adequate term.
9
But, importantly, not in virtue of the denition of NS (see the last section).
5
546
aspects of the rationality in NS. I wont deal with the conditions for NS to be actually rational, nor with any aspect
of inter-paradigmatic or trans-revolutionary rationality.10
Since this controversy is well known, I shall emphasise
only the most striking passages, beginning with the astonishing two which head this paper:
Though he is not a nave falsicationist, Sir Karl may, I
suggest, legitimately be treated as one. (Kuhn, 1970a, p.
14)
This passage is really astonishing. It is exactly like saying: Although he is not a murderer, Sir Karl may, I suggest, legitimately be treated as one. (Popper, 1983
[1956], p. xxxiv)
and continuing with Poppers complaints about Kuhns
(and Lakatos) incapacity for understanding his ideas:
[Kuhn] attended my William James Lectures at Harvard
in 1950 . . . But it seems clear that he does not fully
remember what happened during these lessons. (Ibid.,
p. xxxii)
Kuhn, early in his career, formed a theory of my views
which became his paradigm of Popper . . . Kuhn formed
this paradigm before he ever read any of my writings . . .
But, as we have learnt from Kuhn, paradigms are not
given up so easily. (Ibid., p. xxxiv)
Lakatos has read almost everything I have written. After
being my pupil, he was my colleague and after my successor at LSE. Yet I have to warn the reader that he
has not understood my theory of science. (Popper,
1974, p. 999)
There must be some noise in the controversy that
explains the diculties for understanding one another. It
is true that Popper said from the very beginning (together
with, and besides, his conventionalism on observational
statements) that theories cannot conclusively be proved
false, that there always are possible strategies for eluding
the refutation, etc. But at the same time he says things like:
scientic theories are inventions to be eliminated if they
clashed with observations. (Popper, 1963, p. 61)
the falsity of a theory can be inferred from empirical evidence, and this inference is a purely deductive one.
(Ibid., p. 72)
it must be possible for an empirical scientic system to
be refuted by experience. (Popper, 1958 [1934], p. 18)
I am going to propose that the empirical method shall be
characterized as a method that excludes precisely those
ways of evading falsication which, as my imaginary
critic rightly insists, are logically possible. (Ibid., p. 20)
10
Regarding the former, cf. the last paragraph of the last section; about the latter, although I think Kuhn has many insights (cf. Kuhn, 1977), their
elaboration is, to me, totally led astray by his ideas on incommensurability.
547
same weight; this is a rocky view of theories with no dierence between more essential/central and less essential/central
constituents. Then, upon this view, every change is alike.
Kuhns (and Lakatoss) interest in the history of science
allows him (them) to emphasise a fact that, yet almost obvious once one pays attention to it, is extremely important for
a correct analysis of scientic practice, namely that scientic
theories are enduring entities: they change preserving their
identity for a while, passing through dierent stages/versions, until they die, that is, until they are replaced by a
new one. If theories, diachronically considered, are enduring entities then, synchronically considered, they must be
non-compact entities: they must have parts which are not
essential in the sense that their change is compatible with
the survival of the theory; and other parts which are essential, whose change amounts to the death of the theory.
When, after several (and sound) charges of imprecision,
Kuhn makes his original notion of paradigm more precise
by the new concept of disciplinary matrix, he says of the
rst component, the laws:
Actually, from a problem-solving perspective, if the failure is not massive and the paradigm continues to work quite well in a vast number of other
cases, it might be more rational to try to solve the anomaly while preserving the (nucleus of) the paradigm than to abandon it building a new one, since the
later may imply a (perhaps temporal) lost of problem-solving capacity.
12
To be fair, Kuhn didnt help very much, perhaps because he was not conscious yet that part of the controversy was driven by their dierences about the
structure of scientic theories.
548
S-T11
f=m(s/t)"
s-dep. forces
dir. dep.
m(s/t)"=-kx
m(s/t)"=
-mgsin
(s/t)'-dep. forces
inv. dep.
sq. inv.
S-T1n
S-T21
S-T22
..
..
..
frict. forc.
m(s/t)"=
-(s/t)'mgsin
m(s/t)"=
G(mm'/s2)
Fig. 1.
S-T12 ..
D-T1
D-T2
Normal science
Revolution
Normal science
Fig. 2.
What follows is a Sneedianstructuralist presentation of these Kuhnian ideas, which Kuhn himself recognised as an accurate precisication of (this part
of) his thinking (cf. Kuhn, 1976, 2000). This graph shows only the net of laws, it should be completed with the associated applications, models, values, etc.
This is an informal presentation, but it can be made fully precise using the structuralist tools; for an early structuralist precisication of Kuhns ideas (cf.
Stegmuller, 1973, Ch. XIX, and 1979); for a later one with more standard structuralist apparatus (cf. Balzer, Moulines, & Sneed, 1987, Ch. 5, and Balzer &
Moulines, 1998).
14
For instance in the Classical to Relativistic revolution, the idea that for bodies to change their state of motion energy is needed.
15
Epistemically, since this is compatible with continuing to use the refuted theory for practical reasons as long as we dont have better alternatives, or
when we have an epistemically better one but the former is simpler and works quite well in certain domains (e.g. geocentrism for navigation, Classical
Mechanics in vast number of cases, etc.).
(D-FALS) D-theories must be (epistemically) abandoned when (their last stage is) refuted.
(S- FALS) S-theories must be (epistemically) abandoned
when refuted.
D-FALS is false, it has no rationality import (irrespective of whether sciences goal is truth or merely problemsolving). As Kuhn showed, there is no purely logical reason
for abandoning one D-theory and starting another (in
Lakatosian terms, for abandoning the core instead of keeping addressing the refutation to the protection belt). This
is not matter of logic but of condence failure; scientists
dont trust the theory any more as the frame for trying
to solve the anomalies. Just as, following Stegmullers analogy,16 there is no (formal) logic involved in the decision of
building a new house instead of continuing trying to x the
leaks. Yet according to Kuhn there is a lot of non-(formal)logic rationality: you can be rational or irrational in
doing it, but the criteria have nothing to do with (formal)
logic.17
S-FALS is true (irrespective of whether sciences goal is
problem-solving or truth), and keeps all of Poppers correct
insight. And Kuhn endorses it: in NS, when we have a problem/anomaly, we (epistemically) must do something, we
cannot be (epistemically) indierent, we must change/abandon the S-theory and build a new one. Either preserving
the core, that is, building a dierent S-theory stage of the
same D-theory (changing the protection belt, in Lakatosian
terms); or trying a dierent core, that is, building a dierent
S-theory with a new core opening thereby a new D-theory.
Nothing in logic obliges us to do the later better than the
former and this is perfectly compatible with any sensible
notion of rationality. Yet, logic does oblige us to do either
the former or the later, and Kuhn totally agrees with this
(remember that, among the former, there is room for the
redescription of facts/observations, changing some constants, changing some very specic laws, applying new
measurement methods, postulating new applications, and
so on18).
There is a curious passage that could seem a refutation
of my claim that Kuhn endorses S-FALS, a passage in
which Kuhn says that in NS it is not the theory but the scientist what is tested:19
16
549
when engaged with a normal research problem, the scientist must premise current theory as the rules of his
game. His object is to solve a puzzle . . . [If his conjecture] fails, only [his] own ability not the corpus of current science is impugned. In short, though tests occur
frequently in normal science, these tests are of a peculiar
sort, for in the nal analysis it is the individual scientist
rather than current theory which is tested. (Kuhn,
1970a, pp. 45)
This cannot mean, literally, that in NS the entity which is
the target of an empirical test is not a scientic construct
but a human being. They key is to realise that what scientists have to do in NS is to solve puzzles/anomalies. And an
anomaly is something that does not t with the current theory. Hence the current theory, the current D-theory, has a
problem; that is, its last current S-theory has a problem.
And the fact that Kuhn clearly states here (as everywhere
else) that normal scientists task is to try to x these problems shows uncontroversially that according to him the
normal scientist cannot remain (epistemically) indierent
when confronted to an anomaly. Normal scientists must
try to solve the problem. This is their task in NS, which
in our jargon is tantamount as saying that they have to
change the current S-theory by another one that solves
the anomaly.20 Thus the current S-theory must be (epistemically) abandoned, which is what S-FALS states. Since
we are in NS it must be replaced by another S-theory of
the same current D-theory; in NS the scientist must premise
the (nucleus of the) current (D-)theory. Of course in doing
so the normal scientist may fail, and in this sense it is him,
not the premised D-nucleus, that is challenged.
Hence, in both normal science and revolutionary science
(RS), when we proceed to an empirical test what is tested is
what we use to make the prediction, and this is the whole
theory. To be more precise, what is tested is at least one
branch of the theory-net including both top-nuclear and
bottom-specic parts which, remember, cannot be tested
independently of each other. What is dierent in NS and
in RS is what scientists are ready to do after a negative
outcome. As we have seen, NS is characterised by the
(implicit) rule of trying to solve negative tests addressing
the changes to the bottom-specic parts preserving the
Cf. Stegmuller (1973) (for a related, yet dierent ancestor of this analogy, see also Post, 1971).
This is not exactly inter-paradigmatic theory choice/evaluation (cf. Kuhn, 1977), since in theory choice the options already exist to be compared. The
rationality related to the choice between continuing to reforming the old paradigm or starting a new one has to do with plausibility conditions and what
Kuhn calls crisis phenomena. These plausibility conditions are vague and hard to systematise but, although Kuhn speaks often in quite psychological
terms, they provide the only possible notion of rationality applicable in this case, as we realise when we think in the building-a-new-house analogy: if
things start to go too badly, it is irrational to keep xing the house; as it would be irrational to build a new one after the rst leak (with lot of vagueness in
between, true, but vagueness is a dierent issue).
18
An aside: facts/observations may very well be theory-laden, but not by the same theory-laws that try to explain/predict them. Sometimes they are laden
through non-nuclear connections with other theories (e.g. optics in the case of the telescope and Venus phases), sometimes by a presupposed theory in
the nucleus (e.g. kinematics in mechanics) (cf. Lewis, 1970; Hempel, 1970 and 1973; Sneed, 1979 [1971]; Lakatos, 1970 and Dez, 2002) for the origin of the
distinction between the conceptual part of the theory that describes the facts (concepts whose determination does not presuppose the laws of the theory)
and the conceptual part that explains data so described as a dierent distinction from the traditional observable/theoretical one.
19
I thank Stephan Hartmann for pointing this out to me.
20
Of course this is an idealisation, since as Kuhn insists many times we can never x all the anomalies, paradigms/disciplinary matrices do have always
anomalies.
17
550
top-nuclear unchanged (the Lakatosian negative and positive heuristics), whereas RS consists in addressing changes
to the nucleus. The kind of activity scientists are ready to
do after a failure test is quite dierent. Normal scientists
have to nd out a way of xing the anomaly without
changing the nucleus, which amounts to dierent aims
and needs dierent abilities to the ones needed in RS. I take
Kuhns statement to be a peculiar way of emphasising this
dierence in attitudes and abilities, connoting that in NS
the (nucleus of the) D-theory is not put into question,
but premised. Yet of course there is one S-theory literally
tested in NS and, if unsuccessfully, scientists are (epistemically) obliged to change it. This is the only interpretation of
the passage compatible with other parts of Kuhns work.
Therefore, Kuhn is not denying S-FALS, quite the
contrary.
Another challenge to my interpretation21 comes from
the many places in which Kuhn says that theory replacement is exclusive of revolutionary science, or even that
[p]aradigms are not corrigible by normal science (Kuhn,
1970d [1962], p. 122). Moreover, Kuhn insists many times
that normal science, unlike revolutionary science, is cumulative, but how could it be so if, as I maintain, theories are
substituted during normal science? The key is to insist that
theory is ambiguous, it can refer to either S-theories or Dtheories. My whole point is just that when Kuhn says such
things, as when he explicitly argues against falsicationism,
he is referring to D-theories. Paradigms are not corrigible
by normal science in the sense that what constitutes the
paradigm/disciplinary matrix is the nucleus, and the
nucleus, as we have seen, is preserved during normal science; actually, the preservation of the nucleus is what
denes normal science. But if we take at a certain moment
the nucleus together with the whole set of complementary
assumptions, laws, and soon, what we obtain is (in our
terms) a complete S-theory, that is, a specic version of
the paradigm/disciplinary matrix in a specic moment.
And these things are replaced during normal science. Not
in their nuclear part, of course, but in their non-nuclear
components. Kuhn devotes the full Chapter III of The
structure to the dierent kinds of activities developed during normal science. The main ones are: improving the
experiments/measurements and the experimental/measurement apparatus; determining or making more precise some
physical constants; identifying new phenomena as similar
to familiar ones; improving the form of existing laws;
applying existing laws to new phenomena (for example
tides); developing new laws relating new phenomena to
old ones (for example hydrodynamics); and, we can add,
even sometimes throwing away some phenomena (for
21
example light). In our terminology, all this consists in modifying the non-nuclear parts of the S-theories, that is, in
substituting a specic S-theory by another which shares
the nucleus with the former. Of course Kuhn does not
express this in these terms;22 the whole point of this paper
is that reconstructing him in this way we understand him
and this part of his controversy with Popper better. This
is the sense in which Kuhn (rightly) endorses S-FALS,
yet (rightly too) not D-FALS. Intra-paradigmatic change
is S-theory replacement, which is compatible with leaving
the (essential part of the) paradigm unchanged. And this
is how normal science may be cumulative (and as a matter
of fact it isoftencumulative), because the common
nucleus is what theoretical content depends on. Since this
common core is what is not preserved in revolutionary/
inter-paradigmatic change, such change, according to
him, does not allow comparison by content and, as a consequence, revolutionary science is not cumulative (all this
depends on additional, and highly controversial theses on
content and meaning that I will not discuss here).
It is worth stressing that, as I have already said, nothing
in this interpretation depends on whether we believe that
the goal of science is truth instead of merely problem solving. Maybe one could say, along the lines of Feyerabends
proliferationism, that logic alone doesnt entitle us to
change the D-theory, but that logic plus the thesis that science aims at truth (not only at problem-solving) does, since
the more the proliferation of theories the higher the
chances for truth; hence this issue would not be independent of theses about sciences goal. But things are not so.
It is true that the greater the proliferation the higher the
chances for truth, but the key question is: the greater the
proliferation of what? Of D-theories or of S-theories? If science aims at truth, after a refutation the truth may lie in
principle in a dierent D-theory as well as in a dierent
S-theory of the same D-theory. That is, the falsehood of
an S-theory may lie in the top, core, D-essential, general
laws/principles, but it may lie in the bottom, more specic,
D-non essential ones as well, and since neither top nor bottom laws/principles can be tested in isolation, refutation does
not entitle us to modify the former rather than the latter,
even if the goal of science is truth. Maybe science aiming
at truth makes a case for proliferation, but the whole point
is that even regarding truth, proliferation of dierent S-versions of the current D-theory is as rational as proliferation
of (incipient) new D-theories.23
To summarise: Popper attributes to Kuhn the theses
that science often behaves non-FALS and that this is good
for science, whereas for him it is a danger for science and
even to our civilisation. Yet, because of the ambiguity of
FALS, this charge is misguiding. I am not saying that Popper attributes to Kuhn the negation of both D-FALS and
S-FALS, since he didnt distinguish between them. But
the eect was the same, he attributed to Kuhn a general,
or global, anti-FALS thesis. If we distinguish them, I
think it is clear that Kuhn never defended an anti-S-FALS
thesis (a real danger for science, true, if not to our civilisation), though he did defend an anti-D-FALS thesis, which
is perfectly correct, completely coherent with any sensible
notion of rationality and not dangerous for science at all.
In brief: since Popper didnt have in mind the distinction
between S-theories and D-theories, he (i) could not articulate his non-nave falsicationism, and (ii) could not see
that NS persistence is compatible with FALS-rationality
properly understood. Since Kuhn did have this distinction
implicitly in mind, he could articulate better the same
facts and see that the persistence of NS is perfectly coherent with FALS-rationality properly understood. In our
terms, coherent not with D-FALS, which is false, but with
S-FALS, true and never questioned (at the epistemic level)
by Kuhn. If I am right, then, this implicit equivocation on
the notion of theory causes the puzzling aspects of the
controversy and looking at it we can remove the perplexity
Kuhn himself confesses to feeling:
our intentions are often quite dierent when we say the
same things. Though the lines are the same, the gures
which emerge from them are not. That is why I call what
separates us a gestalt switch rather than a disagreement
and also why I am at once perplexed and intrigued about
how to explore the separation. (Kuhn, 1970a, p. 3, my
emphasis)
All this has to do with possible NS-rationality, that is, it
shows just that, contrary to Popper, NS may be rational.
Which are the criteria for NS actually being rational is
another, related but dierent issue, an issue that has to
do with the connections (both lawful/formal and empirical/applicative) between successive S-theories stronger than
merely preserving the theory-core. It is worth emphasising
that NS is not actually rational merely by denition of
NS.24 What denes NS is, basically, the persistence of certain formal-and-applicative nucleus, plus certain models,
values and practices associated with it. But, although as a
matter of fact scientists do this kind of activity almost
always (and as a group, probably always) rationally, the
notion of NS does not exclude the possibility of an irrational normal scientist, nor even of an irrational normal scientic community. For instance, if they continue working
within what has become, in Lakatosian terms, a clearly
degenerate research programme (that is, post-Lavoisier
phlogiston chemistry, post-Keplerian geocentric astronomy, and the like). It is true that this irrationality is hard
to evaluate at present, since the conceptual possibility that
24
551
Of course the rationality of NS does follow from the denition of good NS, but this is of course an additional denition (see below).
Maybe this sense is weaker than Poppers rationality, but as I said at the beginning, philosophy of science has to elucidate the kind of rationality
characteristic of the rules that actually constitute scientic practices, not to misinterpret the rules guided by a preconceived notion of rationality.
25
552
classes of statements . . . The notion of theory [presupposed by] Kuhn in his description of normal science
can be adequately precisied only within the framework
of the non-statement view of theories. Kuhn himself has
contributed to the confusion conceding too much to his
popperian opponents, admitting for instance, that a theory must be testable in principle. (Stegmuller, 1973, Ch.
IX, 2d)
According to our interpretation, this explanation is
totally misguiding. The statement/non-statement dierence
on the nature of theories has nothing to do with this controversy about falsicationism. One could present both the
Popper and Kuhn accounts in either way. Though Kuhns
ideas are better presented in a non-statement manner, we
can perfectly make sense of the distinction between S-theories and D-theories within the statement view. The reason
why the statement/non-statement dierence does not
account for the PopperKuhn controversy over falsicationism is that, though literally speaking theories reconstructed in a non-statement manner, that is, as sets of
models, are not the kind of entity of which truth and falsehood are predicable, nevertheless they carry a statement
associated with them, the so-called theorys empirical claim,
which asserts that certain empirical systems are embeddable into the models. And this statement is of course suitable
of truth/falsehood. This suces for referring to the refutation of the theory in the sense relevant to the controversy
analysed here.
What I propose is then, in Kuhns terms, like a gestalt
change: if you read things in the proposed way, paying
attention to their implicit disagreement on the nature and
structure of scientic theories, then you see what happened and you understand certain passages that, otherwise, are hardly understandable.26 The only author I
have found that, if I understand him well, is relatively close
to this interpretation is Worrall (2003). He correctly
emphasises the presence of a Duhemian ancestor in Kuhns
theses, namely the idea that the minimum testable unit in
science consists always of a central theory together with a
set of auxiliary assumptions, and that in some cases the
central theory breaks down into a core component together
with a series of more specic assumptions. This fact has the
consequence that [t]he falsity of the central theory does not
26
One can then raise the following question: had Popper entertained and accepted the distinction between S-theories and D-theories, would he have
accepted that (*) the step from one S-theory to another S-theory of the same D-theory preserving the nucleus is compatible with his (non-nave)
falsicationism? Answer: if he accepted that the nuclear laws/principles cannot be tested in isolation (as he probably did), then he should have accepted (*)
(but, who can tell what Popper would actually had done?).
27
This diagnosis, Worrall says, is reinforced if we take into account two new features that Kuhn added to Duhem which are connected with Kuhns
insistence on the importance in science of commitment to tradition (p. 78): (i) often it is not clear for scientists which specic auxiliary assumptions are
the best for completing the central theory; (ii) the central theory is often associated with a heuristics. I think Worrall is right in emphasising these facts, to
which I have not paid enough attention; yet I also think that this does not undermine the core of the interpretation defended here.
28
The same could be said about Lakatos, upon a certain reading of him, since it is not clear to me that his research programmes always t the prole of
our D-theories (cf. 1977). Sometimes they do, but sometimes he seems to refer to more coarse grained entities, including more than one D-theory,
something in between Kuhns D-theories and Laudans research traditions (cf. 1977). But, as the many references to him in the text show, I think that his
essential point against Poppers nave falsicationism and his sophisticated alternative is along the same lines we have outlined here for Kuhn.
553
29
Of course this presupposes that it is possible to treat the dierent parts of the PopperKuhn controversy independently of one another, and at least to
treat this part centred on falsicationism independently of other parts related to comparison through revolutions, scientic progress, incommensurability,
etc. The strategy here is then opposite to those who treat the overall controversy holistically (for a moderate cases see Bird, 2000 and Perez Ransanz,
1999; for a radical case, cf. Fuller, 2003). My strategy does not deny that there may be certain aspects of the controversy that deserve a more holistic
approach, it simply states that the aspects presented in the second section can be elucidated prior to, and independently of, the rest in terms of the
distinction between D-theories and S-theories and the corresponding D- and S- falsicationism theses.
554