0% found this document useful (0 votes)
117 views42 pages

21-355 Notes

The document is a set of lecture notes on real analysis. It begins by defining the natural numbers using the Peano axioms and proving that the natural numbers are the set of non-negative integers {0, 1, 2, ...}. It then defines addition on the natural numbers and proves several properties of addition, including commutativity, associativity, and cancellation.

Uploaded by

acganesh
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
117 views42 pages

21-355 Notes

The document is a set of lecture notes on real analysis. It begins by defining the natural numbers using the Peano axioms and proving that the natural numbers are the set of non-negative integers {0, 1, 2, ...}. It then defines addition on the natural numbers and proves several properties of addition, including commutativity, associativity, and cancellation.

Uploaded by

acganesh
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 42

21-355: Real Analysis 1

Carnegie Mellon University


Professor Ian Tice - Fall 2013

Project LATEXd by Ivan Wang


Last Updated: November 15, 2013

CONTENTS

21-355 Notes

Contents
1 The Number Systems
1.1

1.2

1.3

1.4

1.5

1.6

The Natural Numbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.1.1

Positivity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.1.2

Order . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.1.3

Multiplication . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

The Integers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.2.1

Properties of Integers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.2.2

Algebraic Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

The Rationals and Ordered Fields . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.3.1

Fields and Orders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

Problems with Q . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.4.1

Bounds (Infimum and Supremum) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

The Real Numbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.5.1

Defining the Real Numbers: Dedekind Cuts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

1.5.2

Defining the Real Numbers: The Least Upper Bound Property . . . . . . . . 10

1.5.3

Defining the Real Numbers: Addition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10

1.5.4

Defining the Real Numbers: Multiplication . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11

1.5.5

Defining the Real Numbers: Distributivity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11

1.5.6

Defining the Real Numbers: Archimedean . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12

Properties of R . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12
1.6.1

Absolute Value . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13

2 Sequences
2.1

13

Convergence and Bounds . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13


2.1.1

Squeeze Lemma . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14

2.2

Monotonicity and limsup, liminf

2.3

Subsequences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
2.3.1

2.4

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15

Limsup Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16

Special Sequences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17

3 Series
3.1

3.2

17

Convergence Results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18
3.1.1

Cauchy Criterion Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18

3.1.2

Logarithm . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19

The number e . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20

CONTENTS

21-355 Notes

3.3

More Convergence Results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21

3.4

Algebra of Series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21

3.5

Absolute Convergence and Rearrangements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22

4 Topology of R
4.1

4.2

Open and Closed Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24


4.1.1

Open Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

4.1.2

Closed Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

4.1.3

Limit Points . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25

4.1.4

Closure, Interior, and Boundary Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26

Compact Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
4.2.1

4.3

24

Heine-Borel Theorem

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28

Connected Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29

5 Continuity
5.1

30

Limits of Functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30
5.1.1

Divergence Criteria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30

5.2

Continuous Functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31

5.3

Compactness and Continuity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33

5.4

Continuity and Connectedness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34

5.5

Discontinuities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34

5.6

Monotone Functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35

6 Differentiation

35

6.1

The Derivative . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35

6.2

Mean Value Theorems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36

6.3

Darbouxs Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37

6.4

LH
opitals Rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38

6.5

Higher Derivatives and Taylors Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38

7 Riemann-Stieltjes Integration

39

7.1

The R-S Integral . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39

7.2

Integrability Criteria . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40

21-355 Notes

1
1.1

The Number Systems


The Natural Numbers

Theorem (existence of N): There exists a set N satisfying the following properties, known as the
Peano Axioms:
PA1 0 N
PA2 There exists a function S : N N called the successor function. In particular,
S(n) N.
PA3 n N. S(n) 6= 0
PA4 S(n) = S(m) = n = m (S is injective, one-to-one)
PA5 [Axiom of Induction] Let P (n) be a property associated to each n N.
If P (0) is true, and P (n) = P (S(n)), then P (n) is true n N.
Definition: PA1 = 0 N. PA2 = S(0) N.
Define 1 = S(0), 2 = S(1), 3 = S(2), etc.
PA2 guarantees that {0, 1, 2, } N.
PA3 prevents wraparound: no successor can map to a negative number.
PA4 prevents stagnation: the cycle does not terminate.
Theorem: N = {0, 1, 2, }
Proof : We know that {0, 1, 2, } N, so it suffices to prove that N {0, 1, 2, }.
Let P (n) denote the proposition that n {0, 1, 2, }. Clearly P (0) is true.
Suppose P (n) is true; then n {0, 1, 2, } = S(n) {0, 1, 2, } by construction.
Hence, P (S(n)) is true. By induction, PA5 guarantees that P (n) is true n N.
It follows that N {0, 1, 2, }.
Definition: For any m N, we define 0 + m = m.
Then if n + m is defined for n N, we set S(n) + m = S(n + m).
Proposition (Properties of Addition):
1. n N. n + 0 = n

(0 is the additive identity)

2. m, n N. n + S(m) = S(n + m)
3. m, n N. m + n = n + m

(commutativity)

4. k, m, n N. k + (m + n) = (k + m) + n

(associativity)

5. k, m, n N. n + k = n + m = k = m

(cancelation)

Proof :
1. Let P (n) be n + 0 = n.
P (0) is true because 0 + 0 = 0 by definition.
Note P (n) = S(n) + 0 = S(n + 0) = S(n), so P (S(n)) is true. By induction,
(1) is true.
3

1.1

The Natural Numbers

21-355 Notes

2. Fix m N. Let P (n) denote n + S(m) = S(n + m).


P (0) is true because 0 + S(m) = S(m) = S(0 + m).
P (n) = S(n) + S(m) = S(n + S(m)) = S(S(n + m)) = S(S(n) + m), so P (S(n))
is true. By induction, since m N was arbitrary, (2) is true.
3. Let m be fixed and P (n) denote n + m = m + n.
P (0) is true since 0 + m = m by definition, and m + 0 = m by 1, so 0 + m = m =
m + 0.
Suppose P (n); then S(n) + m = S(n + m) = S(m + n) = m + S(n), so P (S(n)) is
true. By induction and arbitrary choice of m, (3) is true.
4. Fix k, m N and let P (n) denote k + (m + n) = (k + m) + n.
P (0) is true as k + (m + 0) = k + m = (k + m) + 0.
Suppose P (n); then k+(m+S(n)) = k+S(m+n) = S(k+(m+n)) = S(k+m)+n =
(k + m) + S(n) by (2). By induction and arbitrary choice, (4) is true.
5. Fix m, n N and let P (k) denote proposition 5.
P (0) is true because n + 0 = n = n + m = m = 0 = k = m.
Suppose P (k); also, suppose m + S(k) = n + S(k). Then S(m + k) = m + S(k) =
n + S(k) = S(n + k) = m + k = n + k = m = n (by 4). By the axiom of
induction, (5) is true.
1.1.1

Positivity

Definition: We say that n N is positive if n 6= 0.


Proposition (Properties of Positivity):
1. n, m N, if m is positive, then m + n is positive.
2. n, m N, if m + n = 0, then m = n = 0.
3. n N, if n is positive, then there exists a unique m N such that n = S(m).
1.1.2

Order

Definition: For all m, n N, m n or n m iff n = m + p for some p N.


m < n or n > m iff m n m 6= n. The relation provides what is called an order on N.
Proposition (Properties of Order):
Let j, k, m, n N. Then:
1. n n (reflexitivity)
2. m n k m = k n (transitivity)
3. m n m n = m = n (anti-symmetry)
4. j k m n = j + m k + n (order preservation)
5. m < n S(m) n
6. m < n n = m + p for some positive p N.
7. n m S(n) > m
8. n = 0 0 < n

1.2

The Integers

21-355 Notes

Theorem (Trichotomy of Order): Let m, n N. Then exactly one of the following is true:
m<n

m=n

m>n

Proof : Show that no two can be true simultaneously (by definition of < and >), and then at least
one must be true (by induction on n).
1.1.3

Multiplication

Definition: Fix m N. Define 0 m = 0. Now, if n m is defined for some n N, we define


S(n) m = n m + m.
Proposition (Properties of Multiplication):
Fix k, m, n N. Then:
1. m n = n m (commutativity)
2. m, n are positive = mn is positive
3. m n = 0 m = 0 n = 0 (no zero divisors)
4. k (m n) = (k m) n (associativity)
5. k m = k n k is positive = m = n (cancelation)
6. k (m + n) = (m + n) k = k m + k n (distributivity)
7. m < n k l k, l are positive = m k < n l

1.2

The Integers

Consider the following relation on the set N N:


(m, n) ' (m0 , n0 ) m + n0 = m0 + n
Lemma: ' is an equivalence relation.
Proof :
Reflexivity: m + n = m + n = (m, n) ' (m, n)
Symmetry: (m, n) ' (m0 , n0 ) = m + n0 = m0 + n = m0 + n = m + n0 =
(m0 , n0 ) ' (m, n)
Transitivity: Suppose (m, n) ' (m0 , n0 ) (m0 , n0 ) ' (m00 , n00 ). Then:
m + n0 = m0 + n m0 + n00 = m00 + n0
= m + n00 = m00 + n
= (m, n) ' (m00 , n00 )
Definition: Write the equivalence class of (m, n) as [(m, n)] = {(p, q) | (p, q) ' (m, n)}.
Define the integers Z = {[(m, n)]}.
Lemma: Suppose (m, n) ' (m0 , n0 ), (p, q) ' (p0 , q 0 ). Then:
1. (m + p, n + q) ' (m0 + p0 , n0 + q 0 )
5

1.2

The Integers

21-355 Notes

2. (mp + nq, mq + np) ' (m0 p0 + n0 q 0 , m0 q 0 + n0 p0 )


Proof : Consider equalities (a) : m + n0 = m0 + n and (b) : p + q 0 = p0 + q (by definition of ').
Using linear combinations of (a) and (b), we derive the two rules of the lemma:
1. (a) + (b)
2. (a)(p0 + q 0 ) + (b)(m + n)
Definition: Let [(m, n)], [(p, q)] Z. Then:
1. [(m, n)] + [(p, q)] = [(m + p, n + q)] (addition of integers)
2. [(m, n)] [(p, q)] = [(mp + nq, mq + np)] (multiplication of integers)
By the lemma, these are well-defined operations.
Note that for all m, n N:
[(m, 0)] = [(n, 0)] m + 0 = n + 0 m = n
[(m, 0)] + [(n, 0)] = [(m + n, 0)]
[(m, 0)] [(n, 0)] = [(mn, 0)]
As such, the set {[(n, 0)] | n N} Z behaves exactly like a copy of N.
Definition: For n N we set n Z to be n := [(n, 0)].
For x = [(m, n)] Z we define x = [(n, m)].
1.2.1

Properties of Integers

(We can see that every integer x Z can be represented as x := m n where x = [(m, n)].)
Theorem: Every x Z satisfies exactly one of the following:
1. x = n for some n N\{0}
2. x = 0
3. x = n for some n N\{0}
Proof : Write x = [(p, q)] for some p, q N. By trichotomy of order on N we know that p < q or
p = q or p > q. Each of these correlates to one of the three properties.
Corollary: Z = {0, 1, 2, . . .} {1, 2, 3, . . .}
1.2.2

Algebraic Properties

Proposition: Let x, y, z Z. Then the following hold:


1. x + y = y + x
2. x + (y + z) = (x + y) + z
3. x + 0 = 0 + x = x
4. x + (x) = (x) + x = 0
5. xy = yx
6

1.3

The Rationals and Ordered Fields

21-355 Notes

6. (xy)z = x(yz)
7. x 1 = 1 x = x
8. x(y + z) = xy + xz
Definition: Define x y = x + (y). The usual properties hold.
Definition: For x, y Z, we say x y or y x if y x = n for some n N.
We say x < y if x y x 6= y.

1.3

The Rationals and Ordered Fields

Let a relation on Z (Z\{0}) be given by (m, n) ' (m0 , n0 ) mn0 = m0 n.


Lemma: ' is an equivalence relation. Proof follows from properties of Z.
Definition: Q = {[(m, n)]}
1. [(m, n)] + [(p, q)] = [(mq + np, nq)] (addition)
2. [(m, n)] [(p, q)] = [(mp, nq)] (multiplication)
3. [(m, n)] = [(m, n)] (negation)
4. If m 6= 0 we set [(m, n)]1 = [(n, m)]
Remark: the heuristic here is that

m
n

= [(m, n)].

Definition: If m Z, we write m = [(m, 1)] Q; and thus N Z Q.


1. For x, y Q, we define x y = x + (y) Q
2. For x, y Q, y 6= 0 we define
y = [(0, n)].

x
y

= x(y)1 . This is well defined because y = 0

Proposition: Q = { m
n | m, n Z, n 6= 0}.
We define and propose the trichotomy of order on Q, as per the integers.
1.3.1

Fields and Orders

Definition: A field is a set F endowed with two binary operations, +, , satisfying the following
axioms:
(A1, M1) x, y F. x + y F, xy F (closure)
(A2, M2) x, y F. x + y = y + x, xy = yx (commutativity)
(A3, M3) x, y, z F. x + (y + z) = (x + y) + z, x(yz) = (xy)z (associativity)
(A4, M4) (0, 1) F. x F. 0 + x = x + 0 = x, 1 x = x 1 = x (identity)
(A5, M5) x F. (x). x + (x) = 0; x1 F. xx1 = x1 x = 1 (inverse)
(D1) x, y, z F. x(y + z) = xy + xz (distributivity)
Remark : Field must have at least 2 elements (0, 1) by (A/M4). To prove field, must prove 5
properties of addition and multiplication (closure, commutativity, associativity, identity, inverse)
as well as distributivity.
Definition: Let E be a set; an order on E is a relation < satisfying the following:
7

1.4

Problems with Q

21-355 Notes

1. x, y E exactly one of the following is true: x < y or x = y or y < x (trichotomy)


2. x, y, z E, x < y y < z = x < z (transitivity)
Definition: Let F be a field. Then we define x y = x + (y) and

x
y

= xy 1 (for y 6= 0).

Theorem: Q is an ordered field with order <.


Proof : Follows from definitions and properties of Z.

1.4

Problems with Q

Theorem: There does not exist a q Q such that q 2 = 2.


Proof : Suppose not; i.e. there does exist such a q Q.
Consider the set S(q) = {n N+ | q = m
n for some m Z}. Cleary |S(q)| > 0. Then
the well-ordering principle implies that !n S(q). n = min S(q).
2

m 2
m
2
Since n S(q), we know that q = m
n for some m Z. Then q = ( n ) = n2 =
2
2
2
m = 2n = m is even. We claim that m is also even (proof is exercise to reader).

Then l Z. m = 2l. Then 4l2 = (2l)2 = m2 = 2n2 = n2 = 2l2 = n2 is even


= n is even = n = 2p for some p N+ .
2l
l
Hence q = m
n = 2p = p = p S(q). But clearly p < n, which contradicts the fact
that n is the minimal element. By contradiction, the theorem must be true.

1.4.1

Bounds (Infimum and Supremum)

Informally, Q has holes:


Definition: Let E be an ordered set with order <.
1. We say A E is bounded above iff x E. a A. a x. We say x is an upper
bound of A.
2. We say A E is bounded below iff x E. a A. x a. We say x is a lower
bound of A.
3. We say A E is bounded iff its bounded above and below.
4. We say x is a minimum of A iff x A and x is a lower bound of A.
5. We say x is a maximum of A iff x A and x is an upper bound of A.
Remark : If a min or max exists, then it is unique.
Definition: Let E be an ordered set and A E.
1. We say x E is the least upper bound (supremum) of A, written x = sup A, iff x
is an upper bound of A and y E is an upper bound of A = x y.
2. We say x E is the greatest lower bound (infimum) of A, written x = inf A, iff x
is a lower bound of A and y E is a lower bound of A = y x.
Remark : If x = min(A), then x = inf(A). If x = max(A), then x = sup(A). But the converse is
false; some sets have a supremum but no maximum, others a infimum but no minimum.
Definition: Let F be an ordered field. We say that F has the least upper bound property iff every
6= A F that is bounded above has a least upper bound.
8

1.5

The Real Numbers

21-355 Notes

Theorem: Q does not satisfy the least upper bound property.


Proof : Consider the set A = {x Q | x > 0, x2 2}.
Note that 0 < 1 = 12 2 = 1 A, so A is non-empty. Also, 2 4 = 22 implies
(x A = 0 < x2 < 2 < 22 ) = x < 2. Then 2 is an upper bound of A.
Assume for sake of contradiction that Q has the least upper bound property. Then A
has a supremum. Let x = sup A Q and write x = pq for p, q Z.
By trichotomy, x2 < 2 or x2 = 2 or x2 > 2. We know x2 6= 2.
Case 1: Suppose x2 < 2. Then for any n N+ we have ( pq + n1 )2 =
p2
q2

1 2p+q
n ( q ).

From algebra, we derive

( pq

1 2
n)

< 2 for some n

Cleary x > 0 since otherwise x 0 < 1 A. Hence 0 < x =


x is not an upper bound = contradiction.

p
q

<

p2
q2

2p
qn

1
n2

N+ .
p
q

1
n

A. But then

Case 2: Suppose x2 > 2. Considering ( pq n1 )2 > 2 and using the same logic as
before, we can choose n large enough such that pq n1 is an upper bound of A. But
p
p
1
q n < q = x, which contradicts the fact that x = sup A.
As all cases are false, we contradict trichotomy, and hence Q cannot have the least
upper bound property.

1.5

The Real Numbers

We now construct an ordered field satisfying the least upper bound property using Q.
Definition: We say Q is Archimedean iff (x Q). x > 0 = (n N). x < n.
Lemma: If Q is Archimedean, then (p < q Q). (r Q). p < r < q.
(Proofs in HW 2.)
1.5.1

Defining the Real Numbers: Dedekind Cuts

Definition: We say that C P(Q) is a cut (Dedekind cut) iff the following hold:
(C1) 6= C, C 6= Q
(C2) If p C and q Q with q < p, then q C.
(C3) If p C, (r Q). p < r r C.
Lemma: Suppose C is a cut. Then:
1. p C, q
/ C = p < q
2. r
/ C, r < s = s
/C
3. C is bounded above
Lemma: Let q Q. Then {p Q | p < q} is a cut.
Proof : Call the set C. We prove the 3 properties of a cut:
(C1) q 1 C = C =
6 ; q + 1
/ C = C =
6 Q.
(C2) If p C and r Q such that r < p, then r < p < q = r < q = r C.
(C3) Let p C where p < q. Since Q is Archimedean, (r Q). p < r < q = r C.
9

1.5

The Real Numbers

21-355 Notes

Definition: Given q Q we write Cq = {p Q | p < q}. By the above lemma, Cq is a cut.


Definition: We write R = {C P(Q) | C is a cut} =
6 .
Lemma: The following hold:
1. A, B R, exactly one of the following holds: A B, A = B, B A.
2. A, B, C R, A B B C = A C.
Definition: If A, B R we say that A < B A B, and A B A B. This defines
an order on R by the above lemma.
1.5.2

Defining the Real Numbers: The Least Upper Bound Property

Lemma: Suppose 6= E R is bounded above. Then B :=

AE

A R.

Theorem: R satisfies the least upper bound property.


Proof : Let 6= E R be bounded above and set B =

AE

A R. We claim B = sup E.

First, we show that B is an upper bound of E. Let A E. Then A B = A B


(by definition). This is true for all A E, so B is an upper bound.
We claim that for C R. C < B = C is not an upper bound of E. If C < B, then
C B. This implies b B. b
/ C = (A E). b A b
/ C. Then A > C since
otherwise A C = b C, b
/ C. Hence C < A and C is not an upper bound of E.
By the contrapositive: if C is an upper bound, C B. Thus, B is the least upper bound,
and the theorem holds.
1.5.3

Defining the Real Numbers: Addition

Definition: Given A, B R, set A + B = {a + b | a A, b B}.


Lemma: If A, B R, then A + B R.
Theorem: Define A = {q Q | (p > q). p
/ A}. Then R, +, 0R = C0 = {p Q | p < 0}
satisfy the field axioms.
Proof :
(A1) A + B R by previous lemma.
(A2) A + B = {a + b} = {b + a} = B + A.
(A3) A + (B + C) = {a + (b + c)} = {(a + b) + c} = (A + B) + C.
(A4) Show A R. 0R + A = A.
(A5) Show that A R, then A + (A) = 0R using Archimedean property.
Theorem (Ordered Field): Let A, B, C R. If A < B then A + C < B + C.
Proof : Its trivial to see that A B = A + C B + C = A + C B + C.
If A + C = B + C, we can add C to both sides and use the last theorem to see that
A = B, a contradiction. Hence, A + C < B + C.

10

1.5

The Real Numbers

1.5.4

21-355 Notes

Defining the Real Numbers: Multiplication

Lemma: Let A, B R, A, B > 0R . Then C = {q Q | q 0} {a b | a A, b B, a, b > 0} R.


Proof :
(C1) 0 C = C 6= . A, B are bounded above by, say M1 , M2 , so M1 M2 + 1
/C
and C 6= Q.
(C2) Let p C and q < p. If q 0 then q C by definition. If q > 0 then 0 < q < p,
but then 0 < p = p = a b for a A, b B, a, b > 0. Then 0 < q < a b =
q
q
q
a < b = 0 < a B. Then q = a( a ) C.
(C3) Let p C. If p 0 then any a b with a A, b B, a, b > 0 satisfies p < a b C,
so r = a b is the desired element of C. However, if p > 0, then p = a b for
a A, b B, a, b > 0. Choose s A such that a < s, t B such that t > b. Then
p = a b < s t S, so r = s t proves the claim.
Definition of Multiplication: Let A, B R.
1. If A > 0, B > 0 we set A B = {q Q | q 0} {a b | a A, b B, a, b > 0} R.
2. If A = 0 or B = 0, we set A B = 0R .
3. If A > 0 and B < 0, let A B = (A (B)).
4. If A < 0 and B > 0, let A B = ((A) B).
5. If A < 0 and B < 0, let A B = (A) (B).
Theorem: R, satisfies (M1-M5) with 1R = C1 , and
A > 0 = A1 = {q Q | q 0} {q Q | q > 0, p > q. p1
/ A} R;
A < 0 = A1 = (A)1 .
Proof : HW3 (similar to addition).
Theorem: If A, B > 0, then A B > 0.
Proof : By definition C0 A B = 0 A B. Equality is impossible since A, B > 0.
1.5.5

Defining the Real Numbers: Distributivity

Theorem: Let A, B, C R. Then A (B + C) = A B + A C.


Proof : We prove the case where all are positive. The other cases are in HW.
Let p A(B + C). If p 0 then p A B + A B is trivial (both products contain the
interval less than 0).
If p > 0, p = a(b + c) for a A, b B, c C for a > 0, b + c > 0.
Regardless of sign of b or c, a b A B, a c A C. Hence p = a(b + c) = a b + a c
A B + A C. So A(B + C) A B + A C.
Finally, we show the converse is true; let p A B + A C = p = r + s for
r A B, s A C. Case on positivity of p, r, s to show p A(B + C).

11

1.6

Properties of R

1.5.6

21-355 Notes

Defining the Real Numbers: Archimedean

Theorem: For p, q Q, the following are true:


1. Cp+q = Cp + Cq
2. Cp = Cp
3. Cpq = Cp Cq
4. If p 6= 0 then Cp1 = (Cp )1
5. p < q Q Cp < Cq R
Proof : HW.
Definition: For q Q we say Cq R. Then Q R.
Theorem: There exists an ordered field satisfying the least upper bound property; R is unique (for
any ordered field F satisfying these properties, F = R up to isomorphism; and R is Archimedean.
Proof : The basic assertion is Steps (0)-(4). Step (5) proves 1, Step (6) proves 3.

1.6

Properties of R

Notation: think of R as numbers, not cut notation.


Proposition: R satisfies the following:
Theorem: For p, q Q, the following are true:
1. R is Archimedean: x R, x > 0. n N. x < n
2. N R is not bounded above
3. inf{ n1 | n N, n 1} = 0
4. x R the set B(x) = {m Z | x < m} has a minimum in Z.
5. x, y R, x < y. q Q. x < q < y
Remarks:
1. (5) is interpreted as the density of Q R. Any element x R can be approximated to arbitrary accuracy by elements of Q.
2. (4) allows us to define the integer part of any x R. We can set bxc = min B(x)
1 Z. Then bxc x < bxc + 1.
Next we show that R does not have the holes we saw in Q.
Theorem: Let x R satisfy x > 0 and n N, n 1. Then !y R. y > 0 y n = x.
Proof : The case n = 1 is trivial so assume n 2.
Set E = {z R | z > 0 z n < x}. We want to show E 6= and is bounded above. Set
x
t = 1+x
; then 0 < t < 1 and t < x. Hence 0 < tn < t < x, and so t E and E 6= .
Set s = 1 + x. Then 1 < s x < s = x < s < sn ; so if z E then z n < x < sn =
z < s. Then s is an upper bound of E.
By least upper bound property, y R. y = sup E. Since t E, 0 < t < y, so y > 0.
We claim that y n < x and y n > x are both impossible (proof is exercise), so y n = x.
1

Definition: Let n 1; for x R, x > 0, we write x n = y where y n = x. We set 0 n = 0.


12

21-355 Notes

1.6.1

Absolute Value

For x R, we define the function | | : R {r R | r 0}:

if x > 0
x
|x| = 0
if x = 0

x if x < 0
Proposition (Properties of | |):
1. x R. |x| 0 and |x| = 0 x = 0
2. x, y R. |x| < y y < x < y
3. x, y R. |xy| = |x||y|
4. x, y R. |x + y| |x| + |y| (Triangle Inequality)
5. x, y R. ||x| |y|| |x y|

Sequences

Let E be a set. Then we may define a sequence {an }


n=l E as the set of values an a(n) for
some l Z and some function a : {n Z | n l} E.

2.1

Convergence and Bounds

Definition: We say a sequence {an }


n=l R converges to a R, i.e. an a as n
or limn an = a, if for every 0 <  R, there exists N {m Z | m l} such that
n N = |an a| < .
Definition: We say a sequence {an }
n=l R is bounded iff. M R, M > 0. |an | < M (n l).
Lemma: If a sequence converges, then it is bounded.
Definition: Given {an }, {bn } R we define {an + bn } R to be the sequence whose elements are
an + bn . We similary define {can } for a fixed c R, {an bn }, and {an /bn } where bn 6= 0, n l.
Theorem (algebra of convergence): Let {an }, {bn } R, c R, and assume that an a, bn b
as n . Then the following hold:
1. an + bn a + b as n
2. can ca as n
3. an bn ab as n
4. If bn 6= 0 and b 6= 0, then an /bn a/b as n .
Proof : (1), (2) are in next weeks HW.
(3): Note that |an bn ab| = |an bn abn + abn ab| |an bn abn | + |abn ab| =
|bn ||an a| + |a||bn b|. Since bn b we know that M > 0. |bn | < M (n l).
Let  > 0. Since an a and bn b we may choose N1 such that n N1


; and N2 where n N2 = |bn b| < 2(1+|a|)
.
|an a| < 2M
13

2.1

Convergence and Bounds

21-355 Notes

Then set N = max(N1 , N2 ). So if n N we know that |an bn ab| |bn ||an a| +




|a||bn b| < M |an a| + |a||bn b| < M 2M
< 2 + 2 = .
+ |a| 2(1+|a|)
Since  was arbitrary, we deduce that an bn ab.
an bab+ababn
n
|
(4): We know | abnn ab | = | an bab
bn b | = |
bn b
|a|
|b||bn | |bn

|an bab|
|bn ||b|

|ababn |
|b||bn |

|an a|
|bn |

b|.

Let  > 0. Since bn b 6= 0 we know that N1 such that n N1 = |bn b| < |b|
2 .
|b|
|b|
Then n N = 0 < |b| = |b bn + bn | |b bn | + |bn | < 2 + |bn | = 0 < 2
2
|bn | = 0 < |b1n | < |b|
.
Similarly, an a = N2 . (n N2 = |an a| < 4 |b|; and
bn b = N3 . (n N3 = |bn b| <

|b|2
4(1+|a|) .

Set N = max(N1 , N2 , N3 ). Then n N = | abnn ab |


2
|b||an a|

2|a|
|b
|b|2 n

b| <


2

 |a|
2 1+|a|

|an a|
|bn |

|a|
|bn ||b| |bn

b| <

< .

Since  > 0 was arbitrary, we deduce

an
bn

a
b

as n .

Lemma: Let {an }


n=l converge to a R. Then  > 0. N. m, n N = |an am | < .
Definition: We say {an }
n=l R is Cauchy iff  > 0. N. m, n N = |an am | < .
Lemma: If {an } is Cauchy, then its bounded.
Proof : Let  = 1. Then N. m, n N = |am an | < 1. Then n N = |an aN | < 1 =
|an | < |an aN | + |aN | < 1 + |aN |. Set M = max(1 + |aN |, k), where k = max{|al |, . . . , |aN 1 |}.
Then |an | < M (n l), and {an } is bounded.
Theorem: Let {an } R. Then {an } converges {an } is Cauchy.
Proof : = is covered by 2nd-previous lemma. We show the converse:
Suppose {an } is Cauchy. Then |an | < M (n l) by the last lemma.
Set E = {x R | N. n N = x < an }. Note that M < an (n l), and so
M E and E 6= .
Also, x E = Nx . n Nx = x < an < M , and so M is an upper bound of E.
By the least upper bound property of R, a = sup E R. We claim that an a as
n .
Let  > 0. Then since {an } is Cauchy, N. m, n N = |an am | < 2 . In particular,
|an aN | < 2 when n N . Then n N = aN 2 < an = aN 2 E =
aN 2 a.
If x E, then Ex . (n Nx = x < an < aN + 2 ). Hence aN +
of E = a aN + 2 . Then |a aN | < 2 .
But if n N , then |an a| |an aN | + |aN a| <
2.1.1


2


2


2

is an upper bound

= . Hence an a.

Squeeze Lemma

Lemma: Let {an }


n=l , {bn }, {cn } R and suppose that an a, cn a as n . If k l such
that an bn cn (n k), then bn a as n .
Examples:
14

2.2

Monotonicity and limsup, liminf

21-355 Notes

1. Suppose an 0 and {bn } is bounded, i.e. |bn | M (n l). Then |an bn | = |an ||bn | |an |M .
But cn 0 |cn | 0. Then 0 |an bn | |an |M , both sides of which go to 0; and by
the squeeze lemma, |an bn | 0 = an bn 0.
2. Fix k N with k 1. Set an =

1
,n
nk

1. Then 0

1
nk

n1 , and by squeeze lemma

1
nk

0.

3. Fix k N with k 2. Let an = k1n , n 0. We know n N. n k n (proof by induction).


Then 0 k1n n1 , and by squeeze k1n 0.

2.2

Monotonicity and limsup, liminf

Definition: Let {an }


n=l R. We say {an } is:
1. increasing iff. an < an+1 (n l),
2. non-decreasing iff. an an+1 (n l),
3. decreasing iff. an+1 < an (n l),
4. non-increasing iff. an+1 an (n l).
We say {an } is monotone iff. it is either non-increasing or non-decreasing.
Remark : increasing = non-decreasing, decreasing = non-increasing.
Theorem: Suppose that {an }
n=l R is monotone. Then {an } is bounded iff {an } is convergent.
Proof : = is done in a previous lemma.
= : Well prove when the sequence is non-decreasing (other case handled by similar
argument).
Set E = {an | n l} R. Clearly E 6= . Also, since {an } is bounded, E is as well (in
particular above). By least upper bound property of R, a = sup(E) R. We claim
that a = limn an .
Let  > 0. Since a = sup(E) we know that a  is not an upper bound of E; hence
(N l). a  < aN . Also, since the sequence is non-decreasing, an an+1 (n l),
and so n N = aN an . Then n N = a  < aN an a because a is an
upper bound of E.
So n N =  < an a 0 = |an a| < . Since  > 0 was arbitrary, we
deduce that an a as n .
Lemma: Suppose that {an } is bounded. Set Sm = sup{an | n m} and Im = inf{an | n m}.
Then Sm , Im R are well-defined m l; {Sm } is non-increasing; and {Im } is non-decreasing.
Both sequences are bounded.
Definition: Suppose {an } R is bounded. We set lim supn an = limm Sm R and
lim inf n an = limm Im R. Both limits exist by the lemma and previous theorem. We know
that lim inf n an lim supn an from HW.

2.3

Subsequences

Definition: Let : {n Z | n l} {n Z | n l} be order preserving (increasing), i.e. m < n

then (m) < (n). Let {an }


l=k R be a sequence. We say {a(k) }k=l is a subsequence of {an }.
Remarks:
15

2.3

Subsequences

21-355 Notes

1. (k) = k is order preserving, so every sequence is a subsequence of itself.


2. Not every an has to be in the subsequence {a(k) }.
For example, if l = 0 then (k) = 2k is order preserving. In this case an , n odd
does not appear in the subsequence {a(k) }.
3. We will often write nk = (k) to simplify notation, so {ank } denotes a subsequence.
4. From HW1, we know k (k) (k l).
Proposition: Suppose {an } satisfies an a R as n . Then any subsequence of {an } also
converges to a.
Proof :
Let {a(k) } be a subsequence of {an }. Let  > 0. Since an a as n , we know
N l. n N = |an a| < . We claim K l. k K = (k) N .
If not, then (k) < N (k l); but k (k) < N (k l) is a contradiction. Then
the claim is true, and k K = (k) N = |a(k) a| < . Since  > 0 was
arbitrary, we deduce {a(k) } a as k .
Remark : Converse fails. Example: an = (1)n ; a2n = +1 +1, but a2n+1 = 1 1.
2.3.1

Limsup Theorem

Theorem: Let {an } R be bounded. The following hold:


1. Every subsequence of {an } is bounded.
2. If {ank } is a subsequence, then lim supk ank lim supn an .
3. If {ank } is a subsequence, then lim inf n an lim inf k ank .
4. There exists a subsequence {ank } such that limk ank = lim supn an .
5. There exists a subsequence {ank } such that limk ank = lim inf n an (6= (4)).
Proof :
1. Trivial.
2. Since k (k), {a(n) | n k} {an | n k} for every order-preserving . Hence
Sk = sup{a(n) } | n k} sup{an | n k} = Tk . But:
lim supn a(n) = lim supk {a(n) | n k} lim supk {an | n k} =
lim supn an .
3. Similar to (2); exercise to reader.
4. Too lazy to LATEX; exercise to reader.
5. Exercise to reader.
Theorem: Suppose {an } R; the following are equivalent:
1. an a as n
2. {an } is bounded, and every convergent subsequence converges to a.
3. {an } is bounded, and lim supn an = lim inf n an .
Proof : (1) = (2) proven already.
16

2.4

Special Sequences

21-355 Notes

(2) = (3)
Limsup theorem (4,5) = {a(k) }, {a(k) } subsequences such that a(k) lim supn an , a(k)
lim inf n an as k . By (2) the limits must agree.
(3) = (1)
Limsup theorem (1-3) = {a(k) }. lim inf n an lim inf k a(k) lim supk a(k)
lim supn an . As the first and last are equal, by transitivity it follows all subsequences
satisfy lim inf k a(k) = lim supk a(k) . As an is a subsequence of itself, it therefore
converges to some a as n .
Theorem (Bolzano-Weierstrass): If {an } R is bounded then there exists a convergent subsequence. Proof from (4) or (5) of Limsup Theorem.

2.4

Special Sequences

Definition: Given an R for 0 k n, n N we define

Pn

= a0 + a1 + + an .
n

P
n k nk
Lemma (Binomial Theorem): Let x, y R and n N. Then (x + y)n =
, where
k x y
k=0

n
n!
k := k!(nk)! N.
k=0 an

Theorem: In the following assuming that n 1:


1. Let x R, x > 0. Then an =
2. Let x R, x > 0. Then an =

1
nx 0
x1/n

as n .
1 as n .

3. Let an = n1/n ; then an 1 as n .


4. Let a, x R, x > 0. Then

na
(1+x)a

0 as n .

5. Let x R, |x| < 1. Then an = xn 0 as n .

Series

Definition: Let {an }


n=l R; for p < q we write
1. We define, for each n l, Sn =

n
P
k=l

Pq

n=p an

= (ap + + aq ).

ak R to be the nth partial sum of {an }


n=l .

2. P
If s R. Sn s as n , then

n=l an converges.

n=l

an = s. We say the infinite series

3. If the series does not converge, it diverges.


Examples
P
P
1. P
Let an = xn for
n 0, xP R. Then Sn = nk=0 xk . Notice that (1 x)Sn = nk=0 xk
P
n
n
n+1 k
k+1 =
k
n+1 .
k=0 x
k=0 x
k=1 x = 1 x
P
n+1
1
So Sn = nk=0 xk = ( 1x
1x ). If |x| < 1 then Sn 1x by special seq (5).
2. Suppose
{bn }
b as n . Set an = bn+1 bn for n 0. Then the series
n=0 R where bn P
P

a
converges
and
in
fact
n=0 n
n=0 = b b0 .

17

3.1

Convergence Results

3.1

21-355 Notes

Convergence Results

We develop tools that will let us deduce the convergence of a series without knowing its value.
P
Theorem: Suppose
n=l an converges. Then an 0 as n .
Proof : Notice that an = Sn Sn1 and so limn an = limn (Sn Sn1 ) = S S = 0.
P
P
n
Corollary:
n=0 (1) and
n=0 n diverge, as neither sequences converge to 0.
P n
Corollary: The series n=0 x converges |x| < 1.
Proof : |x| 1 = |xn | = |x|n 1(n N). The converse was proved last time.
Next, we provide a characterization of convergence in terms of the size of the tails of the series.
P
Pm
Theorem:
n=l an converges  > 0. N l. m k N = |
n=k an | < .
P
Pk
Proof : n=l an converges Sk = n=l an converges {Sk } is Cauchy.
This is useful in practice because we can guarantee a series converges without knowing its value.
Theorem:
1. If n k. |an | bn for some k l, and

bn converges, then

n=l

2. If n k. 0 an bn for some k l, and

an converges.

n=l

an diverges, then

n=l

bn diverges.

n=l

Proof : (1) Let  > 0 and prove with previous theorem and induction on triangle inequality. (2)
follows from contrapositive.
Examples:
P
1.
n=0

(1)n
2n

converges because | (1)


2n | =

1
2n

and

1
n=0 2n

converges ( 12 < 1).

2. Suppose
n=0 an converges and an 0 n 0. Let {bn } R be
Pbounded,
i.e.
= |an ||bn | M an . Then M Sn = M nk=0 an =
Pn |bn | M n. Then |an bn | P

n=0 an bn converges.
k=0 M an , so by the theorem,
P (1)n n!
2
3n
3.
n=0 2n nn 4n2 +2 converges because the product is bounded.
P

Theorem: Suppose n l. an 0. Then


n=l an converges {Sn }n=l is bounded.
Pn
Proof : Since an 0, the sequence Sn = k=l ak is non-decreasing: Sn+1 = an+1 + Sn Sn . Since
Sn is monotone and converges, it is bounded.
3.1.1

Cauchy Criterion Theorem

Theorem: Suppose that {an }


n=1 R satisfies n l. an 0 and n 1. an+1 an . Then

P
P
n
an converges
2 a2n converges.
n=1

n=0

Proof :
P
P
n
k
Let Sn = nk=1 ak and Tn = m
n=0 2 a2n . Notice that if m 2 then Sm = a1 + a2 +
+ a2k a1 + (a2 + a3 ) + + (a2k + + a2k+1 1 ) a1 + 2a2 + + 2k a2k = Tk .

18

3.1

Convergence Results

21-355 Notes

On the other hand, if m 2k , Sm a1 + + a2k = a1 + a2 + (a3 + a4 ) + + (a2k1 1 +


+ a2k ) 21 a1 + a2 + + 2k1 a2k = 12 Tk .
P
n
Now, if
Tn T as n and so Sm limn Tm = T ,
n=0 2 a2n converges, thenP
which means {Sm } is bounded and
n=1 an converges.
P
Similarly,
P n if n=1 an converges, then Tk 2 limn Sn = {Tk } is bounded =
n=0 2 a2n converges.
Theorem: Let p R. Then

1
n=1 np

converges p > 1.

Proof :
If p 0 the result is trivial since n1p 1 (the sequences converges to 0). Assume that
1
1
p > 0. Then (n+1)
p np , so we can apply the Cauchy criterion:

X
X
1
2n
converges

converges.
np
(2n )p

n=1

But

2n
n=0 (2n )p

n=0

1
n=0 (2p1 )n ,

and this series converges

P
P
1
Notice
n=1 n is divergent, but
n=1
we need the logarithm.
3.1.2

1
n1+r

1
2p1

< 1 p > 1.

converges r > 0. To try to find intermediate series,

Logarithm

Definition: From Supplemental Reading 3, for every 1 < b R, we define a function


logb : {x R | x > 0} R such that
1. blogb x = x (x > 0)
2. logb (1) = 0, logb b = 1
3. 0 < x < y logb x < logb y
4. logb (xz ) = z logb (x) (x > 0, z R)
5. logb is a bijection
6. lim

logb n
nr

= 0 (r R, r > 0)

Then from (6), for large n and p > 0 we know:


1
n(log1
n n(logb n)p n np = n1+p = n1+p

So

1
n(logb n)p

P
n=2

n=2

P
n=1

n1 .

is such an intermediate series.

Theorem: Let b > 1.


Proof :

n)p

1
n(logb n)p

converges

1
(logb 2)p np

In particular,

P
n=2

1
n(logb n)p

1
(logb 2)p

1
n logb n

P
n=1

converges p > 1. (n 2 = logb n > 0)

P
n=1

1
np

2n
2n (logb 2n )p

converges by Cauchy criterion, but

converges p > 1.

is divergent.
19

3.2

3.2

The number e

21-355 Notes

The number e

Lemma:

1
n=0 n!

converges.

Proof : If n 2 then:
n
X
1
1
1
=1+1+
+ +
Sn =
k!
21
n(n 1) 2 1
k=0

1
1
1
+
+ + n1
2 22
2

X
1
=1+2=3
1+
2k

1+1+

k=0

Since Sn is increasing and bounded, we know that


Definition: We set e =

P
n=0

1
n! .

1
n=0 n!

converges.

Note that e > 1.

Theorem: e = limn (1 + n1 )n .
P
1
Proof : Let Sn = nk=0 k!
, Tn = (1 + n1 )n . Then by the Binomial Theorem:
n

X
n!
1
1
Tn = (1 + )n =
n
k!(n k)! nk
k=0

1 n(n 1) 1
1 n(n 1)
=1+1+
+ +
2
2!
n
n!
nn
1
1
1
2
1
1
n1
1
)
= 1 + 1 + (1 ) + (1 )(1 ) + + (1 ) (1
2!
n
3!
n
n
n!
n
n
1
1
= Sn
1 + 1 + + +
2!
n!
Hence, lim supn Tn lim supn Sn = limn Sn = e.
OTOH, fix m N. Then for n m:

1
1
1
1
m1
(1 ) + +
(1 ) (1
)
2!
n
m!
n
n
1
1
1
1
m1
= lim inf Tn lim inf RHS 1 + 1 + lim inf (1 ) + +
lim inf (1 (1
) =1+1+
n
n
2! n
n
m! n
n
n
Tn 1 + 1 +

Then, letting m , e = limm Sm lim inf n Tn .


Thus, e lim inf n Tn lim supn Tn e = limn Tn = e.
Theorem: n 1. 0 < e Sn <

1
nn! .

Also, e R\Q is irrational.

Proof : Since Sn is increasing, 0 < e Sn is clear. The other side can be seen from algebra.
Now, suppose e Q; then e =

p
q

for p, q N, p, q 1.

Then 0 < q!(e Sq ) < 1q (q 1). Notice that q!e = q! pq = (q 1)!p N and
q!(1 + 2!1 + + q!1 ) N.
Hence q!(e Sq ) Z; but this yields an integer between 0 and 1, a contradiction. So e
is irrational.
Remark : In fact, e is transcendental.
20

3.3

More Convergence Results

3.3

21-355 Notes

More Convergence Results

1/n } is bounded. Let 0 = lim sup


1/n .
Theorem (Root Test): Suppose {an }
n |an |
n=l R and {|an |
Then the following holds:
P
1. If < 1, then
n=l an converges.
P
2. If > 1, then n=l an diverges.

3. if = 1, both convergence and divergence are possible.


Theorem (Ratio Test): Let {an }
n=l R. Then

n=l

an :

1. converges if {| an+1
an |}n=l is bounded and lim supn

|an+1 |
|an |

< 1.

2. diverges if k l. |ak | =
6 0 and |an+1 | |an |(n k).
Lemma (Summation of Parts): Let {an }
n=0 R and define:
(P
n
k=0 ak if n 0
An =
0
if n = 1
Then if 0 p < q:
q
X

an bn =

n=p

q1
X

An (bn bn+1 ) + Aq bq Ap1 bp

n=p

Theorem (Dirichlet Test): Suppose {an }


n=0 , {bn }n=0 R satisfy:
P
1. The sequence An = nk=0 ak is bounded.

2. 0 bn+1 bn (n N)
3. limn bn = 0
Then

n=0 an bn

converges.

P
n
Corollary (Alternating Series): Suppose 0 an+1 an , an 0 as n . Then
n=l (1) an
converges. Proof follows from Dirichlet Test.
P
Corollary
(Abels
Test):
Suppose
n=l an converges, bn+1 bn (n l) and bn b as n .
P
Then n=l an bn converges.

3.4

Algebra of Series

Theorem: If A =

n=l

an , B =

(1)A + B =

n=l

B N , then

(an + bn )

(2)cA =

n=l

can (c R)

n=l

Theorem: Suppose {an }


n=0 , {bn }n=0 R satisfy:

(1)

|an | converges

n=0

Then

n=0 cn

(2)

bn = B

n=0

(3) cn =

n
X
k=0

= A B converges.
21

ak bnk for n 0

3.5

Absolute Convergence and Rearrangements

Definition: The series


of the series

an ,

n=0

n
P

cn , where cn =

n=0

21-355 Notes

ak bnk , is called the Cauchy product

k=0

bn .

n=0

P
P
P
Remark : If an , bn converge, cn does not necessarily converge if neither series has convergent
absolute values.

3.5

Absolute Convergence and Rearrangements

P
|an | converges, then
n=l an converges. Proof is trivial.
P
P
Definition:
Suppose n=l an converges. If n=l |an | converges, the series converges absolutely. If
P
|an | diverges, the series is conditionally convergent.
P
P
(1)n
(1)n
Example:
is conditionally convergent, while
n=1
n=1 n2 is absolutely convergent.
n
Proposition: If

n=l

Lets try to manipulate the series without being careful.


=

X
(1)n+1

n=1

= lim (Sk =
k

=1

1 1 1
+ +
2 3 4

k
X
(1)n+1

n=0

) = lim (S2k =
k

2k
X
(1)n+1
n=0

1
1 1
1
1
but: S2k = (1 ) + ( + + (
)>0
2
3 4
2k 1 2k
Hence, > 0. But the next step is questionable:
2 =
?

X
(2)(1)n+1
n=1

X
k=0

X
k=0

X 2
2

2k + 1
2k
k=1

X
X
2
1 X 1
1

=
2k + 1
k
2k + 1
2k
k=1

= 2 = > 0

k=0

k=1

a contradiction!

Problem: rearrangement is a delicate issue.


P
Definition: Let : {m P
Z | m l} {m Z | m l} be a bijection. The series
n=l a(n) is
called a rearrangement of
a
.
n=l n
P
P
Theorem: If n=l an is absolutely convergent, then every rearrangement converges to
n=l an .
Proof : Let  > 0.
P

Pk

an converges absolutely, N l. k m N =
n=m |an | < 2 .
P

Let k :
n=m |an | 2 < .
Now choose MP N suchPthat {l, l + 1,
. . , N } {(l), (l + 1), . . . , (M )}. Then
P.
m
m
m M = | n=l an n=l a(n) | n=N |an | < .
Pm
P
Hence lim
and from this we deduce
m ( n=l an
n=l
P
Pam(n) ) = 0P

limm m
a
=
lim
a
=
m
n=l (n)
n=l n
n=l an .
Since

n=l

22

3.5

Absolute Convergence and Rearrangements

21-355 Notes

When a series is only conditionally convergent, the situation is vastly worse.


P
Theorem: Suppose
c R.
n=0 an is conditionally convergent. Let P
There exists a rearrangement (bijection) : N N such that
n=0 a(n) = c.
P
Lemma: Suppose n=0 an is conditionally convergent and set:
(
(
an if an > 0
an if an < 0
bn =
cn =
0
if an 0
0
if an 0
Then

n=0 bn

and

n=0 cn

both diverge.

P
Proof
IfP bn converges,
then cn = bn an =
P : Suppose
P
Pnot; one of the series is convergent.
P
P
cn = bn an ; but |anP
| = bn +cn and so |an | = bn + cn is convergent, a contradiction.
A similar argument holds if
cn converges.
Rearrangement Theorem Proof :


Let {a+
n }n=0 denote the subsequence of {bn | bn > 0 or bn = 0 an = 0}. Let {an }n=0
denote the subsequence of {cn | cn > 0} (from last lemma). Note:

1. a+
n 0, an 0 since an 0 = bn 0, cn 0.
P +
P
P
P
2.
an and a
bn , cn respectively.
n both diverge because they differ by 0 from

P +
m1 =
Set m0 = n0 =
Since
an diverges we may use the well-ordering
Pk
Pm1 + principle:
P1.
< c}.
a
a

>
c}.
Similarly,
n
=
min{k

N
|
min{k N | kn=0 a+
1
n
n=0 n
n=0 n
Next, if mp and np are known, we set:

p1 X
p1 X
nl
ml
k

X
X
X
+

a
>
c
a
+
mp+1 = min k N |
a+

j
j
j

j=1+mp
l=0 j=1+nl
l=0 j=1+ml

mp+1
p1 X
p1 X
nl
ml
k

X
X
X
X

+
a
<
c
np+1 = min k N |
a+

a
+
a

j
j
j
j

l=0 j=1+ml

l=0 j=1+nl

j=1+mp

j=1+np

+
) + (a+
Consider the series (a+
1+m1 + + am+2 ) (a1+n1 +
1 + + am1 ) (a1 + + an+1P

+ a
n2 ) + . This is clearly a rearrangement of
n=0 an .
Pmp+1
P
np+1
+

Write Ap = l=1+mp al , Ap = l=1+np al , and let Sj denote the j th partial sum of


the rearrangement.
P
P
By construction, lim supj Sj = lim supp ( p+1
A+
pl=0 A
l=0
l
l ) and
Pp
Pp
+

lim inf j Sj = lim inf p ( l=0 Al + l=0 Al ).


P
Pp
Pp+1 + Pp+1
+

Also, c < p+1


l=0 Al
l=0 Al < c + amp+1 and c anp+1 <
l=0 Al
l=0 Al < c.
Pp+1 + Pp
Pp
+
Thus,
by the squeeze lemma, limp ( l=0
Al l=0 A
l ) = limp ( l=0 Al
Pp
P

n=0 a(n) = c.
l=0 Al ) = c, and so limj Sj = c =

Remark : One can also rearrange such that

a(n) = .

23

21-355 Notes

Topology of R

Our goal in Section 4 is to develop some tools for understanding the topology of R, which is a
sort of generalized qualitative geometry.

4.1
4.1.1

Open and Closed Sets


Open Sets

Definition:
1. For a, b R with a b, we define:
(a, b) = {x R | a < x < b}

[a, b) = {x R | a x < b}

(a, b] = {x R | a < x b}

[a, b] = {x R | a x b}

2. For x R and  > 0, we set B(x, ) = (x , x + ) and B[x, ] = [x , x + ].


We call the set B(x, ) a neighborhood of x or a ball of radius  centered at x.
3. A set E R is open if x E.  > 0. B(x, ) E.
In other words, every point in E has a neighborhood contained in E.
Examples:
1. is vacuously open.
2. R is open because x R. B(x, 1) R.
3. If a < b then (a, b) is open.
Proof : Fix x (a, b) and let  = min{x a, b x} > 0. Then a x  < x <
x +  b by construction, and B(x, ) (a, b).
4. If a < b then [a, b) is not open.
Proof : For x = a we know that  > 0. a 
/ [a, b) and hence B(a, ) 6 [a, b).
5. [a, b] is not open, nor is (a, b] by previous argument.
6. E = {a} is not open.
7. E = { n1 | n N, n 1} is not open:  > 0. B(1, ) 6 E.
S
Lemma: If E R is open A (some index set), then A E is open.
S
Proof : SLet x A E . Then x E0 for some 0 A. Since E0 is open,  > 0. B(x, )
E0 A E .
T
Lemma: If Ei R is open for i [n], n N, then ni=1 Ei is open.
1
Remark
: Infinite intersections of open sets need not be open. Let En = ( 1
n , n ), n 1.
T
Then n=1 En = {0} which is closed.

4.1.2

Closed Sets

Definition: We say E R is closed iff E c = R\E is open.


Lemma: E is open E c is closed (by definition).
Examples:
24

4.1

Open and Closed Sets

21-355 Notes

1. is closed because c = R is open.


2. R is closed because Rc = is open.
3. [a, b] is closed because [a, b]c = (, a) (b, ) is the union of open sets, and thus
open.
4. [a, b) and (a, b] are not closed because [a, b)c = (, a) [b, ) and B(b, ) 6
[a, b)c ( > 0).
5. {a} is closed since {a}c = (, a) (a, ), both open sets.
6. Suppose E R is finite. Write E = {ai | i [n]} where a1 < a2 < . . . < an . Then
E c = (, a1 ) (a1 , a2 ) (an1 , an ) (an , ), all of which are open.
S
1
1
7. E = { n1 | n N, n 1} is not closed. E c = (, 0]
n=1 ( n+1 , n ) (1, ) is not
open because B(0, ) E = { n1 | 1 < n} =
6 = B(0, )
/ Ec.
S
1
1
8. E = {0} { n1 | n 1} is closed, as E c = (, 0)
n=1 ( n+1 , n ) (1, ) is open.
Lemma:
T
1. If E R is closed A, then A E is closed.
S
2. If Ei R is closed i [n] then ni=1 Ei is closed.
Proof : The complement is the union of Ec (open by claim), which is open by previous lemma.
Remark : Example (7) shows that infinite unions of closed sets need not be closed.
4.1.3

Limit Points

Definition: Let E R.
1. A point x R is a limit point of E iff.  > 0. (B(x, ) E)\{x} =
6 .
2. A point x E is called isolated if it is not a limit point.
Example: E = { n1 | n 1}. 0 is a limit point, but

1
n

1
E is isolated, since B( n1 , n(n+1)
) E = { n1 }.

Theorem: Let E R. E is closed every limit point of E is contained in E.


Proof :
= :
Assume E is closed and x R is a limit point of E. If x E c then, since E c is open,
 > 0. B(x, ) E c = B(x, ) E = . But this contradicts the fact that x is a
limit point of E; thus x E.
=:
Suppose E is not closed; then E c is not open and so  > 0. x E c . B(x, ) E 6= .
Since x E c , (B(x, ) E)\{x} = B(x, ) E 6= and hence x is a limit point of E.
Then x E E c , a contradiction; and E is closed.
Definition: Let {xn }
n=l S for some set S. We say {xn } is eventually constant if
N l. xn = xN (n N ).
Proposition: Let E R. Then x is a limit point of E {xn }
n=1 E such that the sequence
is not eventually constant and xn x as n .
Proof :
25

4.1

Open and Closed Sets

21-355 Notes

= :
Suppose x is a limit point of E, i.e.  > 0. (B(x, ) E)\{x} 6= . Set r1 = 1 and
choose x1 E such that x1 (B(x, r) E)\{x}.
Set rn = min( n1 , |x xn1 |) and choose xn (B(x1 , rn ) E)\{x}.
1
Then n 1. {xn }
n=1 E and |x xn1 | < |x xn | and |x xn | < n . It follows {xn }
is not eventually constant, and xn x as n .

=:
Let  > 0. N 1. n N = |x xn | < . Then {xn | n N } B(x, ) E.
If {xn | n N } = {x} then {xn } is eventually constant, a contradiction. Hence
6= {xn | n N }\{x} (B(x, ) E)\{x} = (B(x, ) E)\{x} 6= , and hence x
is a limit point.
Corollary: Let E R. The following are equivalent (proof follows from last theorem):
1. E is closed.
2. If x R is a limit point of E, x E.
3. If {xn }
n=l E is such that xn x as n , then x E.
Corollary: Let E R and E 6= . Suppose E is closed.
1. If E is bounded above, then sup E E, i.e. sup E = max E.
2. If E is bounded below, then inf E E, i.e. inf E = min E.
4.1.4

Closure, Interior, and Boundary Sets

Definition: Let E R.
1. Let O(E) = {V R | V E and V is open} P(R)
C(E) = {C R | E C and C is closed} P(R).
Note that O(E) and R C(E).
S
2. We define E 0 = V O(E) V , and call this set the interior of E.
=T
We define E
CC(E) C, and call this set the closure of E.
3. We define E = E\E 0 to be the boundary of E.
Theorem: Let E R. The following hold:

1. E 0 E E
E are closed.
2. E 0 is open and E,
3. For every x E, x E 0 x E.
4. E = {x R |  > 0. B(x, ) E 6= and B(x, ) E c 6= }.

5. E is open E = E 0 , E is closed E = E.
Proof :
1. Trivial.
is an arbitrary intersection
2. E 0 is an arbitrary union of open sets and thus open; E
0

of closed sets, so its closed. E = E\E = E (R\E 0 ) is the intersection of two


closed sets, so its closed.
26

4.2

Compact Sets

21-355 Notes

3. Trivial.
4. Suppose x E. Show the two properties of the set are satisfied via contradiction.
Next, assume x in the set, and show that x E.
5. Trivial.
Corollary: Let E R. Then E is closed E E.
= E E
E. On the other hand, if E E then
Proof : E is closed = E = E
0

E E = E E E, so E = E.
Theorem (Bolzano-Weierstass, Part 2): Let E R be infinite and bounded. Then E has a
limit point.
Proof : Since E is infinite we may construct a non-eventually-constant sequence {xn }
n=0 E. We
+
do so by choosing x0 E arbitrarily, and xn E\{x0 , . . . , xn1 } for any n N . Since E is
bounded, the sequence is too, so B-W implies there exists a convergent subsequence {xnk }
k=0 E.
This subsequence is not eventually constant by construction, so its limit is a limit point.

4.2

Compact Sets

Definition:
1. Let A be some index set and assume A. V R. We write V = {V }A for
the collection of all of these subsets.
S
2. If E R and E A V , then we say V is a cover of E.
3. If V R is open A and V is a cover of E, we say V is an open cover.
4. Let V be a cover of E. We say W = {V }A0 is a subcover of E if A0 A and W
is a cover of E.
5. Let V be a cover of E. If A is finite, then W = {V }A0 is a finite subcover of E,
if W is a subcover of E.
Examples:
1. Every E R admits a cover: E =

xE {x}.

2. Every E R admits an open cover: E

xE

B(x, ) for  > 0.

3. If E is finite and V is an open cover, we claim there is a finite open subcover.


Indeed,
S write E = {ai | 1 i n} and choose Vi such that ai Vi . Then
E ni=1 Vi and {Vi }ni=1 {V }A . Hence every open cover of a finite set
admits a finite open subcover.
1
4. E = { n1 | n 1}. V = {B( n1 , n(n+1)
}
n=1 is an open cover of E. Note that
1
1
1
B( n , n(n+1) ) E = n , so there does not exist a finite subcover.

5. E = {0}{ n1 | n 1}. Suppose V is an open cover of E. Since 0 E, 0 A. 0


V0 . Since V0 is open,  > 0. B(0, ) V0 . Then B(0, ) E = { n1 ||; n N }
where N = min{n N | n 1 }. Hence E\B(0, ) = { n1 | 1 n N }. There
S
exist Vn for n [N ] such that n1 Vn . Then E N
n=0 Vn and E has a finite
subcover.
1
1
6. Let a < b and E = (a, b). Then V = {(a + n+1
, b n+1
)}nN is an open cover of
E. Since these intervals are nested, there cannot be a finite subcover.

27

4.2

Compact Sets

21-355 Notes

Definition: Let E R. We say that E is compact if every open cover of E admits a finite
subcover.
Examples:
1. is trivially compact.
2. R is not compact because V = {B(0, n)}nN is an open cover that clearly does not
admit a finite subcover of R.
3. Any finite set E R is compact.
4. (a, b) for a < b is not compact.
5. { n1 | n 1} is not compact.
6. {0} { n1 | n 1} is compact.
Notice in each of our examples of compact sets that the set is closed and bounded.
4.2.1

Heine-Borel Theorem

Theorem: Let K R. Then K is compact K is closed and bounded.


Proof :
= Suppose K is compact.
S
S
Notice that
n=1 B(0, n).
n=1 B(0, n) = R (since R is Archimedean) and so K R =
ThenS{B(0, n)}
is
an
open
cover
of
K.
Since
K
is
compact,

a
finite
subcover :
n=1
B(0,
n
)
for
some
m

N.
K m
i
i=1
S
Set r = maxi[m] ni . Then K m
i=1 B(0, ni ) B(0, r) = K is bounded.
Now we show K is closed. Let x K C . For each y K we set ry = 21 |x y| > 0. Then
B(y, ry ) B(x, ry ) = (y K). Also, {B(y, ry )}yK is an open cover.
S
B(yi , ryi ). Set r = mini[n] ri > 0
K compact = a finite subcover: K ni=1S
and notice that B(yi , ryi ) B(y, r) = . Hence ni=1 B(yi , ryi ) B(x, r) = =
K B(x, r) = = B(x, r) K C . This means that K C is open and so K is closed.
= (Heine-Borel) Suppose K is closed and bounded. If K = were done, so suppose K 6= .
Notice that K bounded = inf K, sup K R, and K closed = inf K, sup K K.
In particular, sup K = max K, inf = min K. Let V be an open cover of K.
Let E = {x K | V admits a finite subcover of K [inf K, x]} K. Notice that
K [inf K, inf K] = {inf K} is a finite set and hence compact; thus V admits a finite
subcover of K [inf K, inf K]. Hence inf K E, and so E 6= . Clearly E is bounded
above by sup K. By LUB property, sup E R and sup E sup K.
We want to show sup E = sup K = max E. Notice that n 1. xn E K such
that sup E n1 < xn sup E. Then xn sup E as n , and so sup E K (since
K is closed).
Write V = {V }A . Since sup E K, 0 A such that sup E V0 . But V0 is
open so  > 0. B(sup E, ) V0 . By definition, x E. sup E S< x sup E.
n
Hence V admits a finite
Sn subcoverof K [inf K, x], i.e. K [inf K, x] i=1 Vi . Then
K [inf K, sup E] i=0 Vi = sup E E = sup E = max E.
28

4.3

Connected Sets

21-355 Notes

S
Assume for sake of contradiction that max E < max K. Let K 0 = K\ ni=0 Vi . K 0
0
is
Snclosed since its the intersection of closed sets. K 6= since otherwise K
i=0 Vi = max E = max K.
Let y = inf K 0 = min K 0 (since S
K 0 is closed) and note that y > max E. Then K
0
[inf K, y] = K[inf K, min K ] ni=0 Vi {y}. But since y K 0 K, Vn+1 V such
S
that y Vn+1 . Hence K [inf K, y] n+1
i=0 Vi = y E = max E < y max E,
a contradiction. We then deduce that max E = max K = K = K [min K, max K]
is covered by a finite subcover of V; thus, K is compact.
Corollary:
1. If K R is compact and E R is closed, then E K is compact.
2. If K R is compact and E K is closed, then E is compact.
S
3. If Ki R is compact for i [n], then ni=1 Ki is compact.
T
4. If K R is compact A, then A K is compact.

4.3

Connected Sets

= A B = .
Definition: We say two sets A, B R are separated if A B
A set E R is disconnected if E = A B such that a 6= , B 6= and A, B are separated.
If a set is E R is not disconnected, we say its connected.
Examples:
1. (0, 1) and [1, 2) are not separated, though they are disjoint, since (0, 1) [1, 2) =
[0, 1] [1, 2) = {1} =
6 .
2. (a, b) and (b, c) for a < b < c are separated, since (a, b) (b, c) = = (a, b) (b, c).
Then (a, c)\{b} is disconnected, since (a, c)\{b} = (a, b) (b, c).
3. Similarly, a R. (, a) an (a, ) are separated.
Then R\{a} = (, a) (a, ) is disconnected.
Theorem: Let E R. Then E is connected (x, y E and x < z < y = z E).
Proof :
2 = 1:
If (2) is false then x, y E and z (x, y) such that z
/ E. Then E = Lz Rz for
Lz = E (, z) and Rz = E (z, ). Since x Lz , y Rz , and Lz (, z) and
Rz (z, ), it follows that Lz and Rz are separated. Hence E is disconnected.
1 = 2
= .
Suppose E is disconnected. Write E = A B with A, B 6= and A B = A B
Let x A and y B. Without loss of generality, we assume x < y.
Let z = sup(A [x, y]). Clearly z A and so z
/ B = z 6= y = x z y. If

z
/ A then z 6= x = x < z < y and z
/ A B = E. Otherwise, if z A, then z
/ B.
C
is closed, so B
is open; and hence we can find w such that z < w < y, w
B
/ B, and
w
/ A. Then x < w < y and w
/ A B = E. In all cases, then, 2 is true.
Corollary: R, (, a), (, a], (a, ), [a, ), (a, b), (a, b], [a, b), and[a, b] are all connected.
29

21-355 Notes

Continuity

5.1

Limits of Functions

Definition: Let E R, f : E R, and p R be a limit point. Let q R.


We say limxp f (x) = q or f (x) q as x p iff  > 0. > 0. x E 0 < |x p| < =
|f (x) q| < .
Examples:
1. E = [0, 1], f (x) = x. Let p = 12 . limx 1 f (x) = 12 .
2

Proof : Let  > 0; choose =  > 0. Then x [0, 1] and 0 < |x 21 | < S =
|f (x) 12 | < .
2. E = [0, 1], f (x) = x (for x 6= 21 ), f (x) = 37 (for x = 12 ).
By the proof of (1), the claim still holds.
3. f (x) = xn on E = (0, 1) for 2 n N. 0 is a limit point of E; we claim
limx0 xn = 0.
Proof : Let  > 0; choose = 1/n > 0. Then x (0, 1) and 0 < |x 0| < =
0 < x < = 0 < xn < n =  = |f (x) 0| = xn < .
4. limxp x = p whenever p is a limit point of E.
5. If x E. f (x) = 1 then limxp f (x) = 1 whenever p is a limit point of E.
2

6. Let E = R and f (x) = cos(x). From HW6, | cos(x) 1| x2 ex . We claim


limx0 cos(x) = 1.
p
Proof : Let  > 0. Choose

=
min(1,
/e) > 0. Then for x R, 0 < |x 0| <
p
= |x| < min(1, /e) = | cos(x) 1| x2 e1 (since |x|2 < 1 =
p
2
e|x| e1 ) = | cos(x) 1| < 2 e ( /e)2 e = .
7. E = { n1 | n 1}, p = 0. Let f (x) = x1 for x E. We claim limx0 f (x) does not
exist.
Proof : Suppose not. Then for  = 1. > 0. x E, 0 < |x 0| < =
1
|f (x) q| < 1. But x E, |x| < = x = n1 , 1 < n, and |f (x) q| = | 1/n
q| =
|n q| < 1, which is a contradiction.
Definition: Let f : E R for some E R. If A E we define f (A) = {f (x) | x A} R as
the image of A under f . If B R we define f 1 (B) = {x E | f (x) B} as the pre-image of B
under f .
Lemma: Suppose f : E R. Then A B E = f (A) f (B), and
A B R = f 1 (A) f 1 (B) E.
5.1.1

Divergence Criteria

Theorem (Divergence Criteria): Let E R, f : E R, p be a limit point of E, q R. The


following are equivalent:
1. limxp f (x) = q
2. For every open set V R such that q V , an open set U R with p U such
that f (U E\{p}) V . (Topological characterization)

30

5.2

Continuous Functions

21-355 Notes

3. If {xn }
n=l E satisfies xn 6= p (n l) and xn p as n , the sequence
{f (xn )}
n=l R converges and f (xn ) q as n . (Sequential characterization)
Proof :
(1) = (2) :
Assume (1) and let V R be open with q V . Since V is open,  > 0. B(q, ) V .
Since limxp f (x) = q, > 0. x E 0 < |x p| < = |f (x) q| < . Let
U = B(p, ) (an open set). Then x U E\{p} = x E |x p| < =
|f (x) q| <  = f (x) B(q, ) V . So f (U E\{p}) V as desired.
(2) = (3):
Assume (2) and let {xn }
n=l E satisfy xn 6= p, xn p. Let  > 0 and set V = B(q, )
(open). From (2), open U such that f (U E\{p}) V and p U . Since U is open,
> 0. B(p, ) U . Since xn p as n , N l. n N = ) < |xn p| <
= xn U E\{p} = f (xn ) V = B(q, ). Hence n N = |f (xn ) q| < ,
and f (x) q as n .
(1) = (3):
Suppose (1) is false; then  > 0. > 0. x E with 0 < |x p| < such that
|f (x) q| . For n N, n 1, set = n1 to find xn E such that 0 < |xn p| < n1
and |f (xn ) q| . Clearly, {xn }
n=1 E satisfies xn 6= p, xn p. But f (xn ) does
not converge to q. Hence (3) fails.
Corollary: If E R, f : E R, p is a limit point of E, and limxp f (x) = q, then q is unique.
Proof : Limits of sequences are unique, so this follows from (3) in Divergent Criteria theorem.
Corollary (Algebra of limits): Let E R, f, g : E R, p be a limit point of E. Assume
limxp f (x) = q1 , limxp g(x) = q2 . The following hold:
1. If , R then limxp (f (x) + g(x)) = q1 + q2
2. limxp f (x)g(x) = q1 q2
3. If q2 = limxp g(x) 6= 0, then

f
g

point of E\g 1 ({0}), and limxp

: E\g 1 ({0}) R is well-defined, p is a limit


f (x)
g(x)

q1
q2

Proof : All follow from the algebra of sequential limits and (3) in the Theorem.
As an application of this, we get a large class of limit examples.
Corollary: Let P : E R be a polynomial, i.e. P (x) = a0 +a1 x+ +an xn for some n N, ai R
for i [n]. If p is a limit point of E, then limxp P (x) = P (p).
Proof : We know limxp 1 = 1, limxp x = p. Algebra of limits (2) and simple induction show
limxp xk = pk (k N+ ). Then algebra of limits (1) and another induction argument prove
limxp P (x) = limxp (a0 + a1 x + + an xn ) = limxp (a0 + a1 p + + an pn ) = P (p).

5.2

Continuous Functions

Definition: Let E R, f : E R, p E. We say f is continuous at p iff:


 > 0. > 0. x E |x p| < = |f (x) f (p)| < 
31

5.2

Continuous Functions

21-355 Notes

If f : E R is continuous at each p E we say f is continuous on E.


Remarks:
1. In order to be continuous at p E, f must be defined at p. Contrast this to
limxp f (x), in which case p need only be a limit point of E.
2. Informally one can think of continuous functions as those approximated well near
p by f (p), i.e. f (x) f (p) when x p.
3. In the definition, the value of may depend on the point p. If a function is
continuous on E then for a given  > 0 the = (p) may vary greatly as p varies.
4. If p E is isolated (not a limit point of E), then f is vacuously continuous at p:
x E, |x p| < for small enough = x = p.
Example:
We saw last time that limxp P (x) = P (p) for all polynomials P : R R. Hence
 > 0. > 0. x R, 0 < |x p| < = |P (x) P (p)| < . Hence P is continuous
at p.
Theorem: Let E R, f : E R, p E be a limit point of E. Then:
f is continuous at p lim f (x) = f (p)
xp

Corollary (Algebra of Continuity): Let E R, f, g : E R, and p E. Assume that f, g are


continuous at p. Then the following hold:
1. If , R then f + g is continuous at p.
2. f g is continuous at p.
3. If g(p) 6= 0 then

f
g

: E\g 1 ({0}) R is well-defined and continuous at p.

Proof : If p is isolated, the claim is vacuously true. Assume p is not isolated, i.e. p is a limit point
of E. Then the last theorem and algebra of limits gives the result.
Corollary: Let E R, f, g : E R. If f, g are continuous on E, then:
1. If , R then f + g is continuous on E.
2. f g is continuous on E.
3. If g(x) 6= 0 (x E), then

f
g

is continuous on E.

Theorem: Let E, F R, f : E R, g : F R. Assume f (E) F , f is continuous at p E,


and g is continuous at f (p) F . Then g f : E R (where (g f )(x) = g(f (x))) is continuous at
p. Moreover, if f is continuous on E and g is continuous on F , then g f is continuous on E.
Proof : Let  > 0.
Since g is continuous at f (p), > 0. y F and |y f (p)| < = |g(y)g(f (p))| < .
Since f is continuous at p, > 0. x E, |x p| < = |f (x) f (p)| < .
Since f (E) F we know that x E, |x p| < = f (x) F, |f (x) f (p)| < =
|g(f (x)) g(f (p))| < . Hence, g f is continuous by definition.
Examples:
32

5.3

Compactness and Continuity

21-355 Notes

1. exp, cos, sin : R R are continuous on R (proof in HW). YAlso, log : (0, ) R
is continuous on (0, ).
2. Let R and set f : (0, ) R via f (x) = x . Notice that f (x) = exp( log x).
Since log and exp are continuous, f (x) = x is continuous.
Definition: Let E R and A E. We say A is relatively open in E iff A = U E for some open
set U R. Similarly, we say A is relatively closed in E iff A = C E for some closed C R.
Proposition: Let A E R. The following hold:
1. A is relatively open in E x A.  > 0. B(x, ) A E.
2. A is relatively closed in E A = B C E for some relatively open B E.
Theorem (Continuity Criteria): Let E R, f : E R. The following are equivalent:
1. f is continuous on E.
2. If p E is a limit point of E, then limxp f (x) = f (p).
3. If p E is a limit point of E and {xn }
n=l E satisfies xn p as n , then
f (xn ) f (p) as n .
4. If V R is open, then f 1 (V ) E is relatively open in E.
5. If C R is closed, then f 1 (C) E is relatively closed in E.
Proof :
(1) (2) (3) follows from the sequential criterion of limits, previous theorem.
(4) (5) follows since f 1 (V C ) = (f 1 (V ))C E.
(1) = (4):
Let V R be open and choose p f 1 (V ). Since V is open,  > 0. B(f (p), ) V .
It suffices to show, via previous proposition, that > 0. B(p, ) E f 1 (V ). Since
f is continuous on E, > 0. x E, |x p| < = |f (x) f (p)| < . That
is, x B(p, ) E = |f (x) f (p)| <  = f (x) B(f (p), ) V . Hence
B(p, ) E f 1 (V ).
(4) = (1):
Let p E,  > 0, and V = B(f (p), ). Then f 1 (B(f (p), )) E is relatively open in
E = (by previous proposition) > 0. B(p, ) E f 1 (B(f (p), )). Then x E
and |x p| < = f (x) B(f (p), ) = |f (x) f (p)| < . Since , p were arbitrary,
we deduce f is continuous on E.

5.3

Compactness and Continuity

Theorem: Suppose K R is compact and f : K R is continuous on K. Then f (K) is compact.


Proof :
Note that for E R, f (f 1 (E)) E and E f 1 (f (E)). Let {V }A be an open
cover of f (K). Since f is continuous and V is open, f 1 (V ) is relatively open in
K = f 1 (V ) = U K for some open U R.
Since {V }A cover f (K), we see that {f 1 (V )}A is a cover of K. Then {UT }A is
an open cover
compact, there exists a finite
subcover: K Sni=1 Ui .
Sn of K. Since KSis
S
Then K i=1 Ui K = ni=1 f 1 (Vi ) = f (K) ni=1 f (f 1 (Vi )) ni=1 Vi .
As we have extracted a finite open subcover of f (K), f (K) is compact.
33

5.4

Continuity and Connectedness

21-355 Notes

Extreme Value Theorem: Let K R be compact and f : K R be continuous. Then


x0 , x1 K such that f (x0 ) f (x) f (x1 ) (x K). That is, f (x0 ) = minxK f (x) = min f (K)
and f (x1 ) = maxxK f (x) = max f (K).
Proof : From last theorem, we know f (K) is compact, so its closed and bounded. From a previous theorem, closed and bounded sets contain their infimum and supremum (and thus min, max).
Definition: Let E R and f : E R. We say f is uniformly continuous on E iff:
 > 0. > 0. x, y E |x y| < = |f (x) f (y)| < 
Remarks:
1. f is uniformly continuous on E = f is continuous on E.
2. The key difference is that for uniform continuity, > 0 works for all points in E.
Examples:
1. Let E = (0, 1) and f (x) = x1 . Its trivial that f is continuous on E, but it is not
uniformly continuous.
Proof : Suppose it is; then for  = 12 , > 0. x, y (0, 1) |x y| < =
1
|f (x) f (y)| < 21 . Choose N N such that 1 < N . Then x = n1 , y = n+1
satisfy
1
|x y| = n(n+1)

contradiction.

1
n2

< if n N . Then

1
2

> |f (x) f (y)| = |n (n + 1)| = 1, a

Definition: A function f : E R is Lipschitz if x, y E. k > 0. |f (x) f (y)| k|x y|.


Claim: If f is Lipschitz, it is uniformly continuous. Proof: let = k .
Theorem: Let K R be compact and f : K R be continuous. Then f is uniformly continuous
on K.

5.4

Continuity and Connectedness

Theorem: Let E R be connected and f : E R be continuous on E. If X E is connected,


then f (X) is connected.
Intermediate Value Theorem: Let a < b R. Suppose f : [a, b] R is continuous. If
f (a) < c < f (b) or f (b) > c > f (a) for some c R, then x (a, b). f (x) = c.

5.5

Discontinuities

Lemma: If p is a limit point of E R then p is a limit point of Ep+ = E (p, ) or Ep =


E (, p).
Definition: Let E R, f : E R, p be a limit point of E, q R.
1. If p is a limit point of Ep , we say limxp f (x) = q  > 0. > 0. x Ep ,
0 < p = |f (x) q| < .
2. If p is a limit point of Ep+ , then limxp+ f (x) = q  > 0. > 0. x Ep+ ,
0 < x p < = |f (x) q| < .

34

5.6

Monotone Functions

21-355 Notes

Proposition: If p is not a limit point of Ep+ then limxp f (x) = limxp f (x). If p is not a limit
point of Ep then limxp f (x) = limxp+ f (x).
Proposition: If p is both a limit point of either Ep+ or Ep , then
lim f (x) = q lim f (x) = lim f (x) = q

xp

xp

xp+

Definition: Suppose E R, f : E R, p E is a limit point of E. Suppose further that p is not


a point of continuity of f .
1. We say f has a simple discontinuity of p if
p is not a limit point of Ep+ and limxp f (x) exists,
p is not a limit point of Ep and limxp+ f (x) exists, or
p is a limit point of Ep+ and Ep and limxp+ f (x), limxp f (x) both exist.
2. Otherwise, we say f has an essential discontinuity of p.

5.6

Monotone Functions

Definition: Let E R and f : E R. We say:


f is non-decreasing (increasing) if x, y E and x < y = f (x) f (y) (f (x) < f (y)), and
f is non-increasing (decreasing) if x, y E and x < y = f (y) f (x) (f (y) < f (x)).
If f is non-increasing or non-decreasing, f is monotone.
Theorem: Suppose f : (a, b) R is monotone, and let p (a, b). Then limxp f (x) and
limxp+ f (x) both exist. Moreover, if f is non-decreasing, then
lim f (x) = sup f ((a, p)) f (p) inf f ((p, b)) = lim f (x)

xp

xp+

Corollary: If f : (a, b) R is monotone, then f has no essential discontinuities.


Example: f (x) = bxc is non-decreasing and f has countably many simple discontinuities.
Theorem: If f : (a, b) R is monotone, then f has at most countably many simple discontinuities.

6
6.1

Differentiation
The Derivative

Definition: Assume f : [a, b] R for a < b R. For all x [a, b], the function : (a, b)\{x} R
(x)
via (t) = f (t)f
is well-defined, and x is a limit point of (a, b)\{x}. If limtx (t) exists we
tx
0
write f (x) = limtx (t) and say that f is differentiable at x.
We define f 0 : {x [a, b] | x is differentiable at x} R to be the derivative of f . If f is differentiable x E [a, b], we say f is differentiable on E.
Definition (General): Let E R, f : E R, and x E be a limit point of E. Define
(x)
: E\{x} R by (t) = f (t)f
. If limtx (t) exists we say f is differentiable at x, and write
tx
0
f (x) = limtx (t).
Proposition (locality of derivative): Suppose f : E R, g : F R, x E F is a limiit
point of E F , and that f and g are differentiable at x. If f = g on E F then f 0 (x) = g 0 (x).
This shows that f 0 (x) only depends on the value of f near x.
35

6.2

Mean Value Theorems

21-355 Notes

Proposition (Newtonian approximation): Let f : E R, x E be a limit point of E, and


L R. Then the following are equivalent:
1. f is differentiable at x and f 0 (x) = L
2.  > 0. > 0. t E |x t| < = |f (t) (f (x) + L(t x))| < |t x|
Proof follows from definition of limtx (t). Newtons approximation says differentiable
functions are those that can be well-approximated by affine functions +x. Continuous functions are those well-approximated by constants, while differentiable functions
are well-approximated by the next simplest function.
Theorem: Suppose f : E R, x E is a limit point of E, and f is differentiable at x. Then f is
continuous at x.
Proof : By definition, if t E\{x} then f (t)f (x) = (t)(tx). Then f (t) = f (x)+(t)(tx) and
hence limtx f (t) = f (x) + limtx (t)(t x) = f (x) + f 0 (x)0 = f (x). By the limit chracterization
of continuity, we deduce that f is continuous at x.
Remark : The converse fails. Let f (x) = |x| on R. Since ||x| |y|| |x y|, f is Lipschitz
and hence uniformly continuous. However, for x = 0, t > 0 = (t) = |t|0
t0 = 1 and
t0
t < 0 = (t) = t0 = 1. Then limt0 (t) = 1 6= limt0+ (t) = 1, so f 0 (0) does
not exist.
Theorem (Algebra of Derivatives): Let f, g : E R be differentiable at x E. Then:
1. f + g : E R is differentiable at x and (f + g)0 (x) = f 0 (x) + g 0 (x)
2. f g : E R is differentiable at x and (f g)0 (x) = f (x)g 0 (x) + f 0 (x)g(x)
3. If g(x) 6= 0 then
g(x)f 0 (x)f (x)g 0 (x)
g(x)2

f
g

: E\g 1 ({0}) R is differentiable at x and ( fg )0 (x) =

Examples:
1. f (x) = + x on R = f 0 (x) = limtx

f (t)f (x)
tx

= (x R).

2. f (x) = xn for n N = f 0 (x) = nxn1 . Proof by induction.


PN
P
n1 .
n
0
3. Every polynomial P (x) = N
n=0 nan x
n=0 an x is differentiable, and P (x) =
P (x)
4. R(x) = Q(x)
is dfiferentiable when P, Q are polynomials at points p R where
Q(p) 6= 0.

Theorem (Chain Rule): Suppose f : E R is differentiable at x E, f (E) F , and g : F R


is differentiable at f (x) F . Then gf : E R is differentiable at x and (gf )0 (x) = g 0 (f (x))f 0 (x).

6.2

Mean Value Theorems

Definition: Let f : E R. We say that f has a local maximum at x E if > 0. t E and


|x t| < = f (t) f (x). We say f has a local minimum at x E if f has a local maximum.
If f has either a local max or min at x E, we say f has a local extremum at x.
Theorem: Suppose f : E R is differentiable at x E and x is a limit point of both Ex+ and
Ex . If f has a local extremum at x, then f 0 (x) = 0.

36

6.3

Darbouxs Theorem

21-355 Notes

Proof : It suffices to assume that f has a local max at x. Let > 0 such that t E and
(x)
|x t| < = f (t) f (x). Then t E, 0 < x t < = f (t)f
0 and 0 < t x < =
tx
f (t)f (x)
tx

0. So limtx

f (t)f (x)
tx

= f 0 (x) 0, limtx

f (t)f (x)
tx

= f 0 (x) 0, and thus f 0 (x) = 0.

Remark : The result is false if x is not a limit point of either Ex+ or Ex . Consider f (x) = x on
E = [0, 1]; f has a local min at x = 0, local max at x = 1, but f 0 (x) = 1x [0, 1].
Theorem (Monotonicity part 1): Let f : E R be differentiable at x E.
1. If f is non-decreasing on E, then f 0 (x) 0.
2. If f is non-increasing on E, then f 0 (x) 0.
Cauchys Mean Value Theorem: Suppose that f, g : [a, b] R are continuous on [a, b], differentiable on (a, b). Then x (a, b). (g(b) g(a))f 0 (x) = (f (b) f (a))g 0 (x).
Proof :
Consider h : [a, b] R via h(x) = (g(b) g(a))f (x) (f (b) f (a))g(x). To prove the
result, it suffices to find x (a, b) such that h0 (x) = 0 (since h is cont, diff on [a, b] and
(a, b)).
Notice that h(a) = g(b)f (a) g(a)f (b) = h(b).
If h is constant, then h0 (x) = 0 trivially and were done. Assume h is not constant; then
t (a, b). h(t) > h(a) or h(t) < h(a).
If h(t) h(a), then Extreme Value Theorem guarantees that x (a, b). h(x) =
max h([a, b]) and Local Extremum Theorem = h0 (x) = 0.
If h(t) < h(a) then EVT guarantees x (a, b). h(x) = min h([a, b]) and LET =
h0 (x) = 0.
Corollary (Mean Value Theorem): If f : [a, b] R is cont and diff on [a, b], (a, b) then
x (a, b). f (b) f (a) = f 0 (x)(b a). Proof : Set g(x) = x.
Corollary (Monotonicity part 2): Suppose f : (a, b) R is differentiable on (a, b). The
following hold:
1. x (a, b). f 0 (x) > 0 = f is increasing.
2. x (a, b). f 0 (x) 0 = f is non-decreasing.
3. x (a, b). f 0 (x) = 0 = f is constant.
4. x (a, b). f 0 (x) 0 = f is non-increasing.
5. x (a, b). f 0 (x) < 0 = f is decreasing.
Proof : by MVT, if a < x1 < x2 < b, then f (x2 ) f (x1 ) = f 0 (x)(x2 x1 ).

6.3

Darbouxs Theorem

Definition: We say a function g : R R is periodic with period p > 0 if g(x + p) = g(x) (x R).
Theorem (Darboux): Suppose f : [a, b] R is differentiable on [a, b] and f 0 (a) < < f 0 (b).
Then x (a, b). f 0 (x) = .
Corollary: If f : [a, b] R is differentiable on [a, b], then f 0 has no simple discontinuities.
37

6.4

6.4

LHopitals Rule

21-355 Notes

LH
opitals Rule

Theorem: Suppose f, g : [a, b] R are continuous on [a, b], differentiable on (a, b), and g 0 (x) 6= 0
0 (x)
(x)
(x (a, b)). Assume that limxa fg0 (x)
= L. If f (a) = g(a) = 0, then limxa fg(x)
= L.
Proof :
We claim first that g(x) 6= 0 for x (a, b]. Otherwise, g(x) = 0 for some x (a, b] =
0 = g(x)g(a)
= g 0 (z) for some z (a, x), a contradiction. So fg : (a, b] R is wellxa
defined.
f (xn )
Let {xn }
n=l (a, b] satisfy xn a as n . We claim that limn g(xn ) = L. Once
this is established, the sequential characterization of limits yields the desired result.

To prove the claim, we apply Cauchys Mean Value Theorem on [a, xn ]: yn (a, xn )
such that f 0 (yn )g(xn ) = f 0 (yn )(g(xn ) g(a)) = g 0 (xn )(f (xn ) f (a)) = g 0 (xn )f (xn ).
0 (x )
(xn )
n
Then n l. fg(x
= fg0 (x
. Since a < yn < xn , the squeeze lemma implies yn a.
n)
n)
Hence limn

f (xn )
g(xn )

= limn

f 0 (xn )
g 0 (xn )

= limxa

f 0 (x)
g 0 (x)

= L.

Remarks:
1. The theorem is also true if we take limits at t.
2. If f, g : (a, b] R and limxa f (x) = limxa g(x) = 0, then the theorem still
works.

6.5

Higher Derivatives and Taylors Theorem

Definition: Suppose f : E R is differentiable at x E, and x is a limit point of {y


E | f 0 (x) exists}. We say f is twice differentiable at x if f 0 : {y E | f 0 (y) exists} R is
differentiable at x; and f 00 (x) = f (2) (x) = (f 0 )0 (x). Similarly, for n N with n > 2, we say f is ntimes differentiable at x if x is a limit point of {y E | f (n1) (y) exists} and f (n1) is differentiable
at x, in which case f (n) (x) = (f (n1) )0 (x).
If f (n) exists n N, n 1 we say f is infinitely differentiable at x.
Theorem (Taylor): Suppose f : [a, b] R. Assume f (n1) is continuous on [a, b] and f ( n) exists
on (a, b). Let x, y [a, b] with x 6= y. Then z (min{x, y}, max{x, y}) such that
f (y) =

n1
X
k=0

f (k) (x)
f (n) (z)
(y x)k +
(y x)n
k!
n!

(called the Taylor polynomial or Taylor approximation).


Proof :
Suppose x < y (y < x is handled without loss of generality). Let P (t) =
x)k , and set M =

f (y)P (y)
(yx)n .

It suffices to prove that M =

f (n) (z)
n!

Pn1
k=0

f (k) (x)
k! (t

for some z (x, y).

Define g(t) = f (t) P (t) M (t x)n , and notice that g (n) (t) = f (n) (t) n!M . As such,
it suffices to show that g (n) (z) = 0 for some z (x, y).
By construction, g (k) (x) = 0 (k = 0, . . . , n 1), and g(y) = 0 (by choice of M ).
By Mean Value Theorem, xi (x, y). g 0 (x1 ) = g(y)g(x)
= 0. Similarly, x2
yx
g 0 (x1 )g 0 (x)
= 0. Iterating,
x1x
(n1)
(xn1 )g (n1) (x)
g (n) (z) = g
xn1 x

(x, x1 ). g 00 (x2 ) =

we eventually find xn1 (x, y). g (n1) (xn1 ) =

0. Then 0 =

= 0 for some z (x, xn1 ).

38

21-355 Notes

7
7.1

Riemann-Stieltjes Integration
The R-S Integral

Definition: Let a, b R with a b. A partition of [a, b] is a finite ordered set P = {x0 , . . . , xn }


such that a = x0 x1 xn = b. Write [a, b] = {P | P is a partition of [a, b]}. For brevity
well write = [a, b].
Universal Assumptions: Throughout 7 we will always assume that:
1. f : [a, b] R is bounded: x [a, b]. m f (x) M , where m = inf f ([a, b]), M =
sup f ([a, b])
2. : [a, b] R (the integrator or weight function) is non-decreasing (in particular,
is also bounded)
Definition: For each P [a, b] we associate to f the following quantities (P = {x0 , . . . , xn }):
1. mi = inf{f (x) | x [xi1 , xi ]} for i [n]
2. Mi = sup{f (x) | x [xi1 , xi ]} for i [n]
3. i = (xi ) (xi1 ) 0 for i [n]
P
P
We write U (P, f, ) = ni=1 Mi i , L(P, f, ) = ni=1 mi i .
U is the upper Riemann-Stieltjes sum, and L is the lower R-S sum.
Pn
Pn
Pn
Remark
Pn : Clearly m((b) (a)) = i=1 m((xi ) (xi1 )) = i=1 mi i=1 Mi i
M i=1 i = M ((b) (a)). Hence P [a, b]. m((b) (a)) L(P, f, ) U (P, f, )
M ((b) (a)).
Definition of Integral: We define
Rb
Rb
a f d = sup{L(P, f, ) | P [a, b]}, and a f d = inf{U (P, f, ) | P [a, b]}.
Both are well-defined by the remark.
Rb
Rb
If a f d = a f d then we say f is R-S integrable with respect to , and write
Rb
Rb
Rb
a f d = a f d = a f d.
We write R([a, b]; ) = {f : [a, b] R | f is bounded, f is R-S integrable with respect to }.
Rb
When (x) = x, a f dx is the Riemann integral and we write R([a, b]).
Heuristics: The function assigns different weights to different points in [a, b]. The
Rb
intuition is that a f d is a weighted Riemann integral. If is continuous then we
Rb
have a geometric interpretation of a f d: consider the curve in R2 parameterized by
Rb
(x(t), y(t)) = ((t), f (t)); a f d = area under this curve.
Lemma: Let f (x) = C (x [a, b]). Then f R([a, b]; ) and

Rb

f d = C((b) (a)).
P
Proof : For any P [a, b] we have mi = Mi = C. Hence U (P, f, ) = L(P, f, ) = ni=1 Ci =
Rb
Rb
C((b) (a)). So a f d = sup{(L(P, f, )} = C((b) (a)) = inf{U (P, f, } = a f d.
a

Definition: If P, P 0 [a, b] and every point in P is in P 0 , we say P 0 is a refinement of P .


If P1 , P2 [a, b] we define the common refinement P1 #P2 [a, b] by P1 #P2 = P1 P2 , ordered
appropriately.
39

7.2

Integrability Criteria

21-355 Notes

Proposition: If P, P 0 [a, b] and P 0 is a refinement of P , then L(P, f, ) L(P 0 , f )


U (P 0 , f, ) U (P, f, ).
Theorem:

Rb

a f d

Rb

a f d.

Proof : Let P1 , P2 [a, b]. Then L(P1 , f, ) L(P1 #P2 , f, ) U (P1 #P2 , f, ) U (P 2, f, )
Rb
Rb
by last proposition. Hence a f d = sup{L(P1 , f, ) | P1 [a, b]} U (P2 , f, ). Then a f d
Rb
inf{U (P2 , f, ) | P2 [a, b]} = a f d.

7.2

Integrability Criteria

Theorem (Riemann)*: f R([a, b]; )  > 0. P [a, b]. U (P, f, ) L(P, f, ) < .
Proof :
(1) = (2):
Rb
Let  > 0. By definition, P1 , P2 [a, b]. a f d 2 < L(P1 , f, ), and U (P2 , f, )
Rb
Rb


f
d
+
.
Let
P
=
P
#P
.
Then
U
(P
,
f,
)

U
(P
,
f,
)
<
1
2
1
2
2
a
a f d + 2 . Hence
U (P, f, ) L(P, f, ) < .
(2) = (1):
Rb
Rb
For any partition P [a, b] we know a f d U (P1 , f, ) and L(P, f, ) a f d.
Rb
Rb
We also know a f d a f d. Then (2) implies that for  > 0 we have P
Rb
Rb
[a, b]. U (P1 , f, ) L(P1 , f, ) < . But then 0 a f d a f d <  ( > 0)
Rb
Rb
and so a f d = a f d = f R([a, b]; ).
Lemma: Let P [a, b]. The following are true:
1. If P 0 is a refinement of P , then U (P 0 , f, ) L(P 0 , f, ) U (P, f, ) L(P, f, ).
P
2. If si , ti [xi1 , xi ] (i [n]), then 0 ni=1 |f (si ) f (ti )|i U (P, f, )
L(P, f, ).
Rb
P
3. If f R([a, b]; ), then ti [xi1 , xi ] = | ni=1 f (ti )i a f d| U (P, f, )
L(P, f, ).
Theorem: If f is continuous on [a, b], then f R([a, b]; ).
Proof :
Note that EVT implies f is bounded. Let  > 0 and choose k > 0 so k((b) (a)) < .
Since f is cont on compact [a, b], f is uniformly continuous. Then > 0. x, y [a, b]
and |x y| < = |f (x) f (y)| < k.
Choose a partition P [a, b] such that xi xi1 < (i [n]). Then by EVT,
s
that mi = f (si ), Mi = f P
(ti ). Then U (P,P
f, ) L(P, f, ) =
Pin, ti [xi1 , xi ] suchP
n
n
n
i=1 (Mi mi )i =
i=1 (f (ti ) f (si ))i
i=1 ki = k
k=1 i =
k((b) (a)) < . Since  > 0 was arbitrary, we deduce Riemanns Theorem that
f R([a, b]; ).
Theorem: Suppose that f is monotone and is continuous on [a, b]; then f R([a, b]; ).
Remarks:
40

7.2

Integrability Criteria

21-355 Notes

1. If = x, then all monotone functions f are in R([a, b]), i.e. all monotone functions
are Riemann integrable.
2. Monotone functions dont have to be continuous, so f with simple discontinuities
in R([a, b]; ) when is continuous.
3. Monotone functions can have countably infinite sets of discontinuity; R-S integrals
can handle infinite discontinuities.

41

You might also like