Philosophy of Science
Philosophy of Science
Philosophy of Science
Philosophy of science
Part of a series on
Science
Outline
Portal
Category
The philosophy of science is concerned with all the assumptions, foundations, methods, implications of science, and
with the use and merit of science. This discipline sometimes overlaps metaphysics, ontology and epistemology, viz.,
when it explores whether scientific results comprise a study of truth. In addition to these central problems of science
as a whole, many philosophers of science consider problems that apply to particular sciences (e.g. philosophy of
biology or philosophy of physics). Some philosophers of science also use contemporary results in science to reach
conclusions about philosophy.
Philosophy of science has historically been met with mixed response from the scientific community. Though
scientists often contribute to the field, many prominent scientists have felt that the practical effect on their work is
limited; a popular quote attributed to physicist Richard Feynman goes, "Philosophy of science is about as useful to
scientists as ornithology is to birds." In response, some philosophers (e.g. Craig Callender[1]) have suggested that
ornithological knowledge would be of great benefit to birds, were it possible for them to possess it.
Demarcation
The demarcation problem refers to the distinction between science and nonscience (including pseudoscience); Karl
Popper called this the central question in the philosophy of science.[] However, no unified account of the problem
has won acceptance among philosophers, and some regard the problem as unsolvable or uninteresting.[]
Early attempts by the logical positivists grounded science in observation while non-science was non-observational
and hence meaningless.[] Popper argued that the central property of science is falsifiability (i.e., all scientific claims
can be proven false, at least in principle, and if no such proof can be found despite sufficient effort then the claim is
likely true).[]
Philosophy of science
Scientific explanation
In addition to providing predictions about future events, society often takes scientific theories to offer explanations
for those that occur regularly or have already occurred. Philosophers have investigated the criteria by which a
scientific theory can be said to have successfully explained a phenomenon, as well as what gives a scientific theory
explanatory power. One early and influential theory of scientific explanation was put forward by Carl G. Hempel and
Paul Oppenheim in 1948. Their Deductive-Nomological (D-N) model of explanation says that a scientific
explanation succeeds by subsuming a phenomenon under a general law. An explanation, then, is a valid deductive
argument. For empiricists like Hempel and other logical positivists, this provided a way of understanding
explanation without appeal to causation.[] Although ignored for a decade, this view was subjected to substantial
criticism, resulting in several widely believed counter examples to the theory.[]
In addition to their D-N model, Hempel and Oppenheim offered other statistical models of explanation which would
account for statistical sciences.[] These theories have received criticism as well.[] Salmon attempted to provide an
alternative account for some of the problems with Hempel and Oppenheim's model by developing his statistical
relevance model.[][] In addition to Salmon's model, others have suggested that explanation is primarily motivated by
unifying disparate phenomena or primarily motivated by providing the causal or mechanical histories leading up to
the phenomenon (or phenomena of that type).[]
Philosophy of science
Induction
How is it that scientists can state, for example, that Newton's Third Law is universally true? After all, it is not
possible to have tested every incidence of an action, and found a reaction. There have, of course, been many, many
tests, and in each one a corresponding reaction has been found. But can one ever be sure that future tests will
continue to support this conclusion?
One solution to this problem is to rely on the notion of induction. Inductive reasoning maintains that if a situation
holds in all observed cases, then the situation holds in all cases. So, after completing a series of experiments that
support the Third Law, and in the absence of any evidence to the contrary, one is justified in maintaining that the
Law holds in all cases.
Although induction commonly works (e.g. almost no technology would be possible if induction were not regularly
correct), explaining why this is so has been somewhat problematic. One cannot use deduction, the usual process of
moving logically from premise to conclusion, because there is no syllogism that allows this. Indeed, induction is
sometimes mistaken; 17th century biologists observed many white swans and none of other colours, but not all
swans are white. Similarly, it is at least conceivable that an observation will be made tomorrow that shows an
occasion in which an action is not accompanied by a reaction; the same is true of any scientific statement.
One answer has been to conceive of a different form of rational argument, one that does not rely on deduction.
Deduction allows one to formulate a specific truth from a general truth: all crows are black; this is a crow; therefore
this is black. Induction somehow allows one to formulate a general truth from some series of specific observations:
this is a crow and it is black; that is a crow and it is black; no crow has been seen that is not black; therefore all
crows are black.
The problem of induction is one of considerable debate and importance in the philosophy of science: is induction
indeed justified, and if so, how?
Duhem-Quine thesis
According to the Duhem-Quine thesis, after Pierre Duhem and W.V. Quine, it is impossible to test a theory in
isolation. One must always add auxiliary hypotheses in order to make testable predictions. For example, to test
Newton's Law of Gravitation in our solar system, one needs information about the masses and positions of the Sun
and all the planets. Famously, the failure to predict the orbit of Uranus in the 19th century led not to the rejection of
Newton's Law but rather to the rejection of the hypothesis that there are only seven planets in our solar system. The
investigations that followed led to the discovery of an eighth planet, Neptune. If a test fails, something is wrong. But
there is a problem in figuring out what that something is: a missing planet, badly calibrated test equipment, an
unsuspected curvature of space, etc.
One consequence of the Duhem-Quine thesis is that any theory can be made compatible with any empirical
observation by the addition of a sufficient number of suitable ad hoc hypotheses. This is why science uses Occam's
Razor; hypotheses without sufficient justification are eliminated.
This thesis was accepted by Karl Popper, leading him to reject nave falsification in favor of 'survival of the fittest',
or most falsifiable, of scientific theories. In Popper's view, any hypothesis that does not make testable predictions is
simply not science. Such a hypothesis may be useful or valuable, but it cannot be said to be science. Confirmation
holism, developed by W.V. Quine, states that empirical data are not sufficient to make a judgment between theories.
In this view, a theory can always be made to fit with the available empirical data. However, the fact that empirical
evidence does not serve to determine between alternative theories does not necessarily imply that all theories are of
equal value, as scientists often use guiding principles such as Occam's Razor.
One result of this view is that specialists in the philosophy of science stress the requirement that observations made
for the purposes of science be restricted to intersubjective objects. That is, science is restricted to those areas where
there is general agreement on the nature of the observations involved. It is comparatively easy to agree on
Philosophy of science
observations of physical phenomena, harder to agree on observations of social or mental phenomena, and difficult in
the extreme to reach agreement on matters of theology or ethics (and thus the latter remain outside the normal
purview of science).
Theory-dependence of observations
When making observations, scientists look through telescopes, study images on electronic screens, record meter
readings, and so on. Generally, on a basic level, they can agree on what they see, e.g., the thermometer shows 37.9
C. But, if these scientists have different ideas about the theories that have been developed to explain these basic
observations, they can interpret them in different ways. Ancient scientists interpreted the rising of the Sun in the
morning as evidence that the Sun moved. Later scientists deduce that the Earth is rotating. For example, if some
scientists may conclude that certain observations confirm a specific hypothesis, skeptical colleagues may suspect that
something is wrong with the test equipment. Observations when interpreted by a scientist's theories are said to be
theory-laden.
Whitehead wrote, "All science must start with some assumptions as to the ultimate analysis of the facts with which it
deals. These assumptions are justified partly by their adherence to the types of occurrence of which we are directly
conscious, and partly by their success in representing the observed facts with a certain generality, devoid of ad hoc
suppositions."[]
Observation involves both perception as well as cognition. That is, one does not make an observation passively, but
is also actively engaged in distinguishing the phenomenon being observed from surrounding sensory data. Therefore,
observations are affected by our underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions, and that
understanding may influence what is perceived, noticed, or deemed worthy of consideration. More importantly, most
scientific observation must be done within a theoretical context in order to be useful. For example, when one
observes a measured increase in temperature with a thermometer, that observation is based on assumptions about the
nature of temperature and its measurement, as well as assumptions about how the thermometer functions. Such
assumptions are necessary in order to obtain scientifically useful observations (such as, "the temperature increased
by two degrees").
Empirical observation is used to determine the acceptability of hypotheses within a theory. Justification of a
hypothesis often includes reference to a theory operational definitions and hypotheses in which the observation
is embedded. That is, the observation is framed in terms of the theory that also contains the hypothesis it is meant to
verify or falsify (though of course the observation should not be based on an assumption of the truth or falsity of the
hypothesis being tested). This means that the observation cannot serve as an entirely neutral arbiter between
competing hypotheses, but can only arbitrate between hypotheses within the context of the underlying theory that
explains the observation.
Thomas Kuhn denied that it is ever possible to isolate the hypothesis being tested from the influence of the theory in
which the observations are grounded. He argued that observations always rely on a specific paradigm, and that it is
not possible to evaluate competing paradigms independently. By "paradigm" he meant, essentially, a logically
consistent "portrait" of the world, one that involves no logical contradictions and that is consistent with observations
that are made from the point of view of this paradigm. More than one such logically consistent construct can paint a
usable likeness of the world, but there is no common ground from which to pit two against each other, theory against
theory. Neither is a standard by which the other can be judged. Instead, the question is which "portrait" is judged by
some set of people to promise the most useful in terms of scientific "puzzle solving".
For Kuhn, the choice of paradigm was sustained by, but not ultimately determined by, logical processes. The
individual's choice between paradigms involves setting two or more "portraits" against the world and deciding which
likeness is most promising. In the case of a general acceptance of one paradigm or another, Kuhn believed that it
represented the consensus of the community of scientists. Acceptance or rejection of some paradigm is, he argued, a
social process as much as a logical process. Kuhn's position, however, is not one of relativism.[3] According to Kuhn,
Philosophy of science
a paradigm shift will occur when a significant number of observational anomalies in the old paradigm have made the
new paradigm more useful. That is, the choice of a new paradigm is based on observations, even though those
observations are made against the background of the old paradigm. A new paradigm is chosen because it does a
better job of solving scientific problems than the old one.
The fact that observation is embedded in theory does not mean observations are irrelevant to science. Scientific
understanding derives from observation, but the acceptance of scientific statements is dependent on the related
theoretical background or paradigm as well as on observation. Coherentism, skepticism, and foundationalism are
alternatives for dealing with the difficulty of grounding scientific theories in something more than observations. And,
of course, further, redesigned testing may resolve differences of opinion.
Coherentism
Induction must avoid the problem of the criterion, in which any justification must in turn be justified, resulting in an
infinite regress. The regress argument has been used to justify one way out of the infinite regress, foundationalism.
Foundationalism claims that there are some basic statements that do not require justification. Both induction and
falsification are forms of foundationalism in that they rely on basic statements that derive directly from immediate
sensory experience.
The way in which basic statements are derived from observation complicates the problem. Observation is a cognitive
act; that is, it relies on our existing understanding, our set of beliefs. An observation of a transit of Venus requires a
huge range of auxiliary beliefs, such as those that describe the optics of telescopes, the mechanics of the telescope
mount, and an understanding of celestial mechanics, all of which must be justified separately. At first sight, the
observation does not appear to be 'basic'.
Coherentism offers an alternative by claiming that statements can be justified by their being a part of a coherent
system. In the case of science, the system is usually taken to be the complete set of beliefs of an individual scientist
or, more broadly, of the community of scientists. W. V. Quine argued for a Coherentist approach to science, as do E
O Wilson and Kenneth Craik, though neither use the term "Coherentism" to describe their views. An observation of a
transit of Venus is justified by its being coherent with our beliefs about celestial mechanics and earlier observations.
Where this observation is at odds with any auxiliary belief, an adjustment in the system will be required to remove
the contradiction.
Ockham's razor
The practice of scientific inquiry typically involves a number of heuristic principles, such as the principles of
conceptual economy or theoretical parsimony. These are customarily placed under the rubric of Ockham's razor,
named after the 14th century Franciscan friar William of Ockham, who is credited with many different expressions
of the maxim, not all of which have yet been found among his extant works.[4]
William of Ockham (c. 12951349)... is remembered as an influential nominalist, but his popular fame as a great logician rests chiefly on the
maxim known as Ockham's razor: Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem ["entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity]. No
doubt this represents correctly the general tendency of his philosophy, but it has not so far been found in any of his writings. His nearest
pronouncement seems to be Numquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necessitate [Plurality must never be posited without necessity], which
occurs in his theological work on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (Super Quattuor Libros Sententiarum (ed. Lugd., 1495), i, dist. 27, qu. 2, K).
In his Summa Totius Logicae, i. 12, Ockham cites the principle of economy, Frustra fit per plura quod potest fieri per pauciora [It is futile to
do with more things that which can be done with fewer]. (Kneale and Kneale, 1962, p. 243)
As interpreted in contemporary scientific practice, "entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity" advises
opting for the simplest theory among a set of competing theories that have a comparable explanatory power,
discarding assumptions that do not improve the explanation. Among the many difficulties that arise in trying to apply
Ockham's razor is the problem of formalizing and quantifying the "measure of simplicity" that is implied by the task
of deciding which of several theories is the simplest. Although various measures of simplicity have been brought
Philosophy of science
forward as potential candidates, it is generally recognized that there is no such thing as a theory-independent
measure of simplicity. In other words, there appear to be as many different measures of simplicity as there are
theories themselves, and the task of choosing between measures of simplicity appears to be every bit as problematic
as the job of choosing between theories. Moreover, it is extremely difficult to identify the hypotheses or theories that
have "comparable explanatory power", though it may be readily possible to rule out some of the extremes. Ockham's
razor also does not say that the simplest account is to be preferred regardless of its capacity to explain outliers,
exceptions, or other phenomena in question. The principle of falsifiability requires that any exception that can be
reliably reproduced should invalidate the simplest theory, and that the next-simplest account which can actually
incorporate the exception as part of the theory should then be preferred to the first. As Albert Einstein puts it, "The
supreme goal of all theory is to make the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having
to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience".
Philosophy of science
Philosophy of biology
Philosophy of biology deals with epistemological, metaphysical, and ethical issues in the biological and biomedical
sciences. Although philosophers of science and philosophers generally have long been interested in biology (e.g.,
Aristotle, Descartes, Leibniz and even Kant), philosophy of biology only emerged as an independent field of
philosophy in the 1960s and 1970s.[6] Philosophers of science began to pay increasing attention to developments in
biology, from the rise of the Modern synthesis in the 1930s and 1940s to the discovery of the structure of
Deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) in 1953 to more recent advances in genetic engineering. Other key ideas such as the
reduction of all life processes to biochemical reactions as well as the incorporation of psychology into a broader
neuroscience are also addressed. Research in current philosophy of biology is dominatedWikipedia:No original
researchWikipedia:Avoid peacock terms by investigations about the foundations of evolutionary theory.[7]
Philosophy of chemistry
Philosophy of chemistry considers the methodology and underlying assumptions of the science of chemistry. It is
explored by philosophers, chemists, and philosopher-chemist teams.
Topics of interest include:
1. The relationship between chemical concepts and reality. Resonance structures are often used in chemical
explanations despite their decided non-reality. In a similar sense, the reality of concepts such as nucleophiles and
electrophiles has been questioned.
2. Questions regarding whether chemistry studies atoms (substances) or reactions (processes).
3. Symmetry in chemistry, specifically the origin of homochirality in biological molecules
4. Reductionism with respect to physics and questions regarding whether quantum mechanics can fully explain all
chemical phenomena.
Philosophy of physics
Philosophy of physics is the study of the fundamental, philosophical questions underlying modern physics, the study
of matter and energy and how they interact. The main questions concern the nature of space and time, atoms and
atomism. Also included are the predictions of cosmology, the results of the interpretation of quantum mechanics, the
foundations of statistical mechanics, causality, determinism, and the nature of physical laws. Classically, several of
these questions were studied as part of metaphysics (for example, those about causality, determinism, and space and
time).
Philosophy of science
Philosophy of psychology
Philosophy of psychology refers to issues at the theoretical foundations of modern psychology. Some of these issues
are epistemological concerns about the methodology of psychological investigation. For example:
What is the most appropriate methodology for psychology: mentalism, behaviorism, or a compromise?
Are self-reports a reliable data gathering method?
What conclusions can be drawn from null hypothesis tests?
Can first-person experiences (emotions, desires, beliefs, etc.) be measured objectively?
Other issues in philosophy of psychology are philosophical questions about the nature of mind, brain, and cognition,
and are perhaps more commonly thought of as part of cognitive science, or philosophy of mind, such as:
Philosophy of psychology also closely monitors contemporary work conducted in cognitive neuroscience,
evolutionary psychology, and artificial intelligence, questioning what they can and cannot explain in psychology.
Philosophy of psychology is a relatively young field, because psychology only became a discipline of its own in the
late 1800s. Philosophy of mind, by contrast, has been a well-established discipline since before psychology was a
field of study at all. It is concerned with questions about the very nature of mind, the qualities of experience, and
particular issues like the debate between dualism and monism.
Also, neurophilosophy has become its own field with the works of Paul Churchland and Patricia Churchland.
Philosophy of economics
Philosophy of economics is the branch of philosophy which studies philosophical issues relating to economics. It can
also be defined as the branch of economics which studies its own foundations and morality.
Philosophy of mathematics
Philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the philosophical assumptions, foundations, and
implications of mathematics.
Recurrent themes include:
What is a number?
Are mathematical proofs exercises in tautology?
Why does it make sense to ask whether "1+1=2" is true?
Philosophy of science
How do we know whether a mathematical proof is correct?
Social accountability
Scientific openness
A very broad issue affecting the neutrality of science concerns the areas over which science chooses to explore, so
what part of the world and man is studied by science. Since the areas for science to investigate are theoretically
infinite, the issue then arises as to what science should attempt to question or find out.
Philip Kitcher in his "Science, Truth, and Democracy"[12] argues that scientific studies that attempt to show one
segment of the population as being less intelligent, successful or emotionally backward compared to others have a
political feedback effect which further excludes such groups from access to science. Thus such studies undermine the
broad consensus required for good science by excluding certain people, and so proving themselves in the end to be
unscientific.
Philosophy of science
10
Philosophy of science
The largest effect on the continental tradition with respect to science was Martin Heidegger's critique of the
theoretical attitude in general which of course includes the scientific attitude. For this reason the Continental
tradition has remained much more skeptical of the importance of science in human life and philosophical inquiry.
Notwithstanding, there have been a number of important works: especially a Kuhnian precursor, Alexandre Koyr.
Another important development was that of Foucault's analysis of the historical and scientific thought in The Order
of Things and his study of power and corruption within the "science" of madness.
Several post-Heideggerian authors contributing to the Continental philosophy of science in the second half of the
20th century include Jrgen Habermas (e.g., "Truth and Justification", 1998), Carl Friedrich von Weizscker ("The
Unity of Nature", 1980), and Wolfgang Stegmller ("Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschafttheorie und
Analytischen Philosophie", 19731986).
Notes
[1] http:/ / www. philostv. com/ craig-callender-and-jonathan-schaffer/
[3] T. S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed., Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Pr., 1970, p. 206. ISBN 0-226-45804-0
[4] Ockham's razor, however, was not originally a principle of science but of theology and the issue of parsimony comes, not from science, but
from the vow of poverty that was modeled on the life of Christ. However, the origins of the idea do not necessarily take away from its overall
usefulness.
[5] http:/ / www. uned. es/ dpto_log/ jpzb/ abstracts. html#Rhetoric,_induction,_and_the_free_speech_dilemma. _
[6] Hull D. (1969), What philosophy of biology is not, Journal of the History of Biology, 2, p.241268.
[7] Recent examples include Okasha S. (2006), Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press, and Godfrey-Smith P.
(2009), Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[8] Stanford Encyclopaedia: Auguste Comte (http:/ / plato. stanford. edu/ entries/ comte/ )
[9] Giddens, Positivism and Sociology, 1
[10] Schunk, Learning Theories: An Educational Perspective, 5th, 315
[11] Outhwaite, William, 1988 Habermas: Key Contemporary Thinkers, Polity Press (Second Edition 2009), ISBN 978-0-7456-4328-1 p.68
[12] Kitcher, P. Science, Truth, and Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001
[13] Paul Feyerabend, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge (1975), ISBN 0-391-00381-X, ISBN 0-86091-222-1,
ISBN 0-86091-481-X, ISBN 0-86091-646-4, ISBN 0-86091-934-X, ISBN 0-902308-91-2
Further reading
Agassi, J., (1975), Science in Flux, Reidel, Dordrecht.
Agassi, J. and Jarvie, I. C. (1987), Rationality: The Critical View, Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Augros, Robert M., Stanciu, George N., The New Story of Science: mind and the universe, Lake Bluff, Ill.:
Regnery Gateway, c1984. ISBN 0-89526-833-7
Babich, Babette E. (1994) Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Baudet, Jean C. (2005), Mathmatique et vrit, L'Harmattan, Paris.
Baudet, Jean C. (2010), Curieuses histoires de la science. Quand les chercheurs se trompent, Jourdan, Bruxelles.
Ben-Ari, M. (2005) Just a theory: exploring the nature of science, Prometheus Books, Amherst, N.Y.
Bird, Alexander (1998) Philosophy of Science, Routledge, London.
Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S. (2003), Bayesian Epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Boyd, R., Gasper, P., and Trout, J.D. (eds., 1991), The Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge,
MA.
Chalmers, Alan (2007) What Is This Thing Called Science? (http://books.google.com/
books?id=WQh5wDlE8cwC&printsec=frontcover&dq="called+science"&hl=en&
ei=N5_JTsOAMKSViQeR9bD1Dw&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=1&
ved=0CDIQ6AEwAA#v=onepage&q="called science"&f=false), University of Queensland Press, Open
University press, (reprint of 1999 3rd revised edition).
Feyerabend, Paul K. 2005. Science, history of the philosophy of. Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford.
Glazebrook, Trish (2000), Heidegger's Philosophy of Science, Fordham University Press.
11
Philosophy of science
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003) Theory and reality: an introduction to the philosophy of science, The University of
Chicago Press, Chicago and London
Gutting, Gary (2004), Continental Philosophy of Science, Blackwell Publishers, Cambridge, MA.
Harris, Errol E. (1965), The Foundations of Metaphysics in Science , George Allen and Unwin, London,
Reprinted by Routledge, London (2002).
Harris, Errol E. (1991), Cosmos and Anthropos, Humanities Press, New Jersey.
Hawking, Stephen. (2001), The Universe in a Nutshell, Bantam Press. ISBN 0-553-80202-X
Harr, R. (1972), The Philosophies of Science: An Introductory Survey, Oxford University Press, London, UK.
Heelan, Patrick A. (1983), Space-Perception and the Philosophy of Science, University of California Press,
Berkeley, CA.
Honderich, Ted (Ed.) (2005) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. New York, NY.
Kearney, R. (1994), Routledge History of Philosophy, Routledge Press. See Vol. 8.
Klemke, E., et al. (eds., 1998), Introductory Readings in The Philosophy of Science, Prometheus Books, Amherst,
New York, NY.
Kneale, William, and Kneale, Martha (1962), The Development of Logic, Oxford University Press, London, UK.
Kuipers, T.A.F. (2001), Structures in Science, An Advanced Textbook in Neo-Classical Philosophy of Science,
Synthese Library, Springer-Verlag.
Walker, Benjamin, Caesar's Church: The Irrational in Science & Philosophy, Book Guild, Lewes, Sussex, 2001,
ISBN 1-85776-625-3
Ziman, John (2000). Real Science: what it is, and what it means. Cambridge, Uk: Cambridge University Press.
12
Philosophy of science
External links
Philosophy of science (http://philpapers.org/browse/general-philosophy-of-science) at PhilPapers
Philosophy of science (https://inpho.cogs.indiana.edu/taxonomy/2218) at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology
Project
Philosophy of science (http://www.iep.utm.edu/category/s-l-m/science/) entry in the Internet Encyclopedia
of Philosophy
An introduction to the Philosophy of Science, aimed at beginners - Paul Newall. (http://www.galilean-library.
org/manuscript.php?postid=43784)
Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science at the London School of Economics (http://www2.lse.ac.
uk/CPNSS/Home.aspx)
Interdisciplinary Centre for Science and Technology Studies (http://www.izwt.uni-wuppertal.de)
Essays on concepts in the Philosophy of Science (http://www.galilean-library.org/hps.php) at The Galilean
Library.
Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh (http://www.pitt.edu/~pittcntr/)
Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science (http://www.mcps.umn.edu/)
Boston Center for Philosophy and History of Science (http://www.bu.edu/philo/centers/cphs/)
Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS) (http://www.tilburguniversity.nl/faculties/
humanities/tilps/)
Journal for General Philosophy of Science (http://www.springer.com/philosophy/philosophy+of+sciences/
journal/10838)
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
Synthese, An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science
13
License
Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0 Unported
//creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/
14