The document discusses the criminal law in 18th century England and how it functioned as an ideological system to maintain social control and the status quo. It analyzes how the criminal law manifested concepts of majesty, justice, and mercy through elaborate court rituals, procedures that guaranteed rights for the accused but were still divided by class, and the wide discretion exercised by judges and magistrates in pardoning criminals. These aspects combined force and imagery with ideals in a way that helped persuade the lower classes to accept the authority of the ruling elites, despite inconsistencies and the law's use mainly to protect property rights.
The document discusses the criminal law in 18th century England and how it functioned as an ideological system to maintain social control and the status quo. It analyzes how the criminal law manifested concepts of majesty, justice, and mercy through elaborate court rituals, procedures that guaranteed rights for the accused but were still divided by class, and the wide discretion exercised by judges and magistrates in pardoning criminals. These aspects combined force and imagery with ideals in a way that helped persuade the lower classes to accept the authority of the ruling elites, despite inconsistencies and the law's use mainly to protect property rights.
The document discusses the criminal law in 18th century England and how it functioned as an ideological system to maintain social control and the status quo. It analyzes how the criminal law manifested concepts of majesty, justice, and mercy through elaborate court rituals, procedures that guaranteed rights for the accused but were still divided by class, and the wide discretion exercised by judges and magistrates in pardoning criminals. These aspects combined force and imagery with ideals in a way that helped persuade the lower classes to accept the authority of the ruling elites, despite inconsistencies and the law's use mainly to protect property rights.
The document discusses the criminal law in 18th century England and how it functioned as an ideological system to maintain social control and the status quo. It analyzes how the criminal law manifested concepts of majesty, justice, and mercy through elaborate court rituals, procedures that guaranteed rights for the accused but were still divided by class, and the wide discretion exercised by judges and magistrates in pardoning criminals. These aspects combined force and imagery with ideals in a way that helped persuade the lower classes to accept the authority of the ruling elites, despite inconsistencies and the law's use mainly to protect property rights.
78 Part II : The Search for Law Section III: Three Dilemmas of Social Organization
ion' prevailed over 'physical strength.' The
opinion was that of the ruling class; the law was one of their chief ideological instru- ments. 8 It combined the terror worshipped by Nourse with the discretion stressed by Paley, and used both to mould the consciousness by which the many submitted to the few. More- over, its effectiveness in doing so depended in large part on the very weaknesses and incon- sistencies condemned by reformers and lib- eral historians. In considering the criminal law as an ideological system, we must look at how it combined imagery and force, ideals and practice, and try to see how it manifested itself to the mass of unpropertied English- men. We can distinguish three aspects of the law as ideology: majesty, justice and mercy. Understanding them will help us to explain the divergence between bloody legislation and declining executions, and the resistance to reform of any kind. II MAJESTY . . .In the court room the judges' every ac- tion was governed by the importance of spec- tacle. Blackstone asserted that 'the novelty and very parade o f . . . [their] appearance have no small influence upon the multitude': 9 scar- let robes lined with ermine and full-bottomed wigs in the seventeenth-century style, which evoked scorn from Hogarth but awe from or- dinary men. The powers of light and darkness were summoned into the court with the black cap which was donned to pronounce sentence of death, and the spotless white gloves worn at the end of a 'maiden assize'when no prisoners were to be left for execution. Within this elaborate ritual of the irratio- nal, judge and counsel displayed their learn- ing with an eloquence that often rivalled that of leading statesmen. There was an acute con- sciousness that the courts were platforms for addressing 'the mul t i t ude' . . . . In its ritual, its judgements and its channel- ling of emotion the criminal law echoed many of the most powerful psychic components! religion. The judge might, as at Chelmsfori emulate the priest in his role of human ager helpless but submissive before the demain of his deity. But the judge could play the rol of deity as well, both the god of wrath andtl merciful arbiter of men's fates. For the righ teous accents of the death sentence were niai even more impressive by the contrast with til treatment of the accused up to the moment (1 conviction. The judges' paternal concern fj their prisoners was remarked upon by foreig visitors and deepened the analogy with tl Christian God of justice and mer cy. . . . JUSTICE 'Justice' was an evocative word in the eigh teenth century, and with good reason. Th( constitutional struggles of the seventeentl had helped to establish the principles of th rule of law: that offences should be fixed, no indeterminate; that rules of evidence shouli be carefully observed; that the law should b admi ni st ered by a bench that was boti learned and honest. These achievements wert essential for the protection of the gentry from royal greed and royal tyranny, and for the reg- ulation, in the civil side of the courts, of the, details of conveyancing, entailing, contract- ing, devising, suing and releasing. Since the same judges administered the criminal law at its highest levels, on the same principles, even the poorest man was guaranteed justice in the high courts. Visitors remarked on the extreme solicitude of judges for the rights of the ac- cused, a sharp distinction from the usual practice of continental benches. . . . Equally important were the strict proce- dural rules which were enforced in the high courts and at assizes, especially in capital cases. Moreover, most penal statutes were in- terpreted by the judges in an extremely nar- row and formalistic fashion. In part this was based on seventeenth -century practice, but as more capital statutes were passed in the eigh- teenth century the bench reacted with an in- creasingly narrow interpretation. Many pros- ecutions founded on excellent evidence and 80 Part II: The Search for Law Section III: Three Dilemmas of Social Organization Eighteenth-century 'justice' was not, how- ever, a nonsense. It remained a powerful and evocative word, even if it bore a much more limited meaning than a twentieth-century (or seventeenth-century) egalitarian would give it. In a society radically divided between rich and poor, the powerful and the powerless, the occasional victory of a cottager in the courts or the rare spectacle of a titled villain on the gallows made a sharp impression. Moreover, it would be wrong to suggest that the law had to be wholly consistent to persuade men of its legitimacy. 'Justice,' in the sense of rational, bureaucratic decisions made in the common interest, is a peculiarly modern conception. It was gaining ground in the eighteenth century. Most reformers worked to bring about such law, and of all schemes Jeremy Bentham's was the logical conclusion. Yet his plan for a crimi- nal code that was precise, consistent and wholly enforced was alien to the thought of most eighteenth-century Englishmen. They tended to think of Justice in personal terms, and were more struck by understanding of in- dividual cases than by the delights of abstract schemes, where authority is embodied in di- rect personal relationships, men will often ac- cept power even enormous, despotic power, when it comes from the 'good King,' the-fa- ther of his people, who tempers justice with mercy. A form of this powerful psychic con- figuration was one of the most distinctive as- pects of the unref ormed cri mi nal law. Bentham could not understand it, but it was the law's greatest strength as an ideological system, especially among the poor, and in the countryside. MERCY The prerogative of mercy ran throughout the administration of the criminal law, from the lowest to the highest level. At the top sat the high court judges, and their free use of the royal pardon became a crucial argument in the arsenal of conservatives opposing reform. At the lowest Jurisdiction, that of the Justice of the Peace, the same discretion allowed the magistrate to make decisions that sometimes escaped legal categories altogether. Althougl he frequently made obeisance to the rule when convicting, as we have seen, he couli dispense with them when pardoning, and til absence of a jury made it even easier for him to do so. Latitude in the direction of mere caused some critics to complain that man; justices, partly from laziness or carelessnes but frequently from benevolent views im- properly indulged,' judged cases 'partly or en tirely by their own unauthorized ideas of eq- uity. This element of discretion impressed Weber when he examined the office of JP. Ht compared it to Arabic ' khadi justice'1 formalistic administration of law that was nevertheless based on ethical or practical judgements rather than on a fixed, rational set of rules. It could combine rigid tradition with 'a sphere of free discretion and grace ol the ruler.' 11 Thus it allowed the paternalist]! to compose quarrels, intervene with prosecu- tors on behalf of culprits, and in the final in- stance to dismiss a case entirely. The right ol the pardon was not limited, however, to high court judges and Justices of the Peace. The mode of prosecution, the manner of trial and the treatment of condemned convicts gave some of the same power to all men of prop- erty. 'Irrationality, in the sense used by Weber, and the 'grace of the ruler' which grew from it pervaded the entire administration of the l aw. . . . .. .There is a danger, which perhaps this es- say has not avoided, of giving the impression that a system of authority is something rather than the actions of living men. The invisible hand of Adam Smith's political economy was metaphor, shorthand for an effect rather than a cause; it was a description of recurrent pat- terns of useful behaviour forged out of the en- ergy, conflicts and greed of thousands of indi- viduals in a capitalist market. In a somewhat similar way, much of the ideological structure surrounding the criminal law was the product of countless short-term decisions. It was often a question of intuition, and of trial and error. In handling a mob it was useful to appeal to