Social Sin and Fundamental Option

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10
At a glance
Powered by AI
The text discusses the relationship between personal sin, understood as fundamental option, and social sin. It argues that personal and social sin are interrelated as cultural influences shape individual choices and values.

The text argues that personal and social sin are interrelated, as cultural influences shape individual choices and values. It discusses Leonardo Boff's view that a strong relationship exists between individual and cultural 'projects'.

The author defines fundamental option as the deepest core of a person where they fundamentally choose to say 'yes' or 'no' to God. This orientation then shapes their daily choices and habits.

Social Sin and Fundamental

Option
Mark
OKeefe,
O. S. B.
The renewal of the Catholic
theology
of sin has
progressed
significantly
since the
period immediately prior
to the Second Vatican
Council. Personal sin is understood in more
personalist
and relational
terms rather than
exclusively
in terms of individual acts and laws. Fur-
thermore,
many
have come to view
sin,
not
primarily
in terms of discrete
actions,
but in terms of a fundamental
option
at the core of the
person.
At the same
time,
it has come to be more
clearly recognised
that sin is
a
social,
as well as a
personal, reality.
This has resulted in a distinct
theology
of social sin.
Despite
the renewal of the
theologies
of
personal
sin and social
sin, however,
it must be noted that these
developments
have occurred
largely
in isolation from one another. This
separation,
while understandable in
light
of the tasks involved in the renewal of
each,
has resulted in
relatively
little attention focused on the
interrelationship
of
personal
sin
(as
fundamental
option)
and social sin.
How is the fundamental
disposition
of the human
person
to be under-
stood in relation to the social world in which s/he lives? In his 1976 book
Liberating Grace,
Leonardo Boff
proposes
that a
strong
interrelation
exists between the &dquo;fundamental
project&dquo;
of
persons
and the cultural
projects
of the societies to which
they belong.
Because humans are
socially constituted,
in
part by
their
multiple relationships
with the
culture in which
they
find
themselves,
cultural directions and relation-
ships
will exercise a
strong
influence on the most basic
project
of each
individual.
Although
each
person possesses
an irreducible core which can resist or
rise above the cultural
norms,
such resistance will
always
be difficult
because of the enormous
pressure
of the cultural
project.
In
proposing
a
relationship
between cultural and individual
projects,
Boffs work
sug-
gests
that the
relationship
between social sin and
personal
sin be under-
stood as fundamental
option.
It will be the
purpose
of the
present
article
to further the examination of the interrelation between social sin and fun-
damental
option, focusing particularly
on the social nature of
freedom,
knowledge
and value.
Fundamental
option _
The most basic tenet of a
theology
of
personal
sin as fundamental
option
is that sin cannot be understood
primarily
in terms of individual
acts but
only
in terms of the
persons
basic life direction or orientation.
The fundamental
option, positive
or
negative, represents
the
persons
86
response
to the innate human
longing
for God and to Gods
gracious
self-
offering
in Christ. At his or her
deepest core,
the
person
either
says
a fun-
damental
&dquo;yes&dquo;
or &dquo;no&dquo; to
God;
and this orientation is lived out in the
dynamism
of
daily
choices and in
developed
habits
(virtues
and
vices).
Beyond
its most basic
lines,
fundamental
option theory
has been
developed
in a number of different
ways -
none of them
mutually
exclusive. Berhard
Haring,
for
example, drawing especially
from
scrip-
ture and from
contemporary psychology,
identifies the fundamental
option
with the biblical
image
of the &dquo;heart&dquo; as the
deepest
core of the
person
where conversion and authentic
relationship
with God
develop.2
2
Joseph
Fuchs focuses on the Thomistic
understanding
that the human
person
is ordered to God as the ultimate end as the foundation for a fun-
damental
option theory.3 Perhaps
the most influential
starting point,
however,
has been the distinction which Karl Rahner has made between
the transcendental and
categorical
levels of freedom.4
4
For
Rahner,
human freedom is
not,
in the first
instance,
the
ability
to
choose between two
objects.
It
is, rather,
the
capacity
to decide about
oneself,
to
dispose
oneself and
ultimately
to
say &dquo;yes&dquo;
or &dquo;no&dquo; to God.
This
capacity
or freedom to
accept
the divine self-offer is the constitutive
core of the human
person.
It is the most fundamental
purpose
of freedom
at this transcendental level to &dquo;choose&dquo; God - that
is,
to make a funda-
mental
option
for God. The transcendental exercise of freedom becomes
the
ground
for all
conscious, categorical
choices. The fundamental
option
itself
cannot, however,
be
fully
available to our consciousness
because we can never
grasp
ourselves
totally
as an
object
of
knowledge.
Sin,
most
basically,
is the
negative
fundamental
option,
a life turned
away
from
God,
a basic &dquo;no&dquo; to Gods
self-offering.
What we
usually
call &dquo;freedom of
choice&dquo;,
or what Rahner calls
&dquo;categorical freedom&dquo;,
is the freedom to choose between different
objects.
The
person consciously
deliberates between and
among
various
objects
of
possible
choice. It is at this level of free choice that the
transcendental orientation of the
person
is actualised. Because the
transcendent God is
experienced
in mediated
ways,
our transcendental
orientation to God is realised in and
through
our individual choices.
Although
the fundamental
option
is incarnated in such choices and is
unavoidably
affected
by them,
it can never be reduced to these choices.
Thus,
true
personal
sin is
always
mediated in discrete actions but cannot
be
irreducibly
identified with such actions.
The distinction between levels of freedom can be further clarified
by
noting
the distinction between the
value(s)
toward which each
type
of
freedom is directed.
Categorical
freedom is directed at
individual,
discrete values which are
present
in
particular
situations and which serve
human
flourishing.
Transcendental
freedom,
on the other
hand,
is
directed at the transcendent
ground
of value
itself,
which is God and in
which all other values
participate
and have their end. In
choosing
87
particular
values in
particular situations,
the
person implicitly
chooses
God in whom these values
participate. Thus,
the authentic exercise of
categorical
freedom is aimed
implicitly
at God. On the other
hand,
the
fundamental orientation of ones life toward God includes an
implicit
orientation to
particular
values.
Thus,
transcendental freedom seeks to
be
realised, actualised,
in individual choices. In
fact,
the
dynamism
of the
transcendental &dquo;choice&dquo; for God seeks to
integrate
all of ones individual
categorical
choices into this most basic orientation.
Again
we see that the
transcendental and
categorical
levels of freedom are distinct but
intimately
interrelated.
Sin,
understood as the
negative
fundamental
option,
is the most basic
orientation of ones life
away from
God. The transcendental &dquo;no&dquo; to God
will be realised and actualised in individual choices. The
person
directed
away
from the source of value cannot
hope reliably
to choose discrete
values in
particular
situations. Sin will become realised in sins - in sinful
actions. On the other
hand,
the
positive
fundamental
option
for God can-
not be sustained in the face of
persistent
individual choices that are con-
trary
to the authentic values
present
in a situation. To act
consistently
and
seriously against
discrete values is to undermine ones most basic
commitment to the
ground
of all value.
While the
understanding
of sin as fundamental
option
does overcome
an older
overemphasis
on
acts,
it continues to focus on the inner orienta-
tion and freedom of the individual. In
fact,
taken
alone,
a fundamental
option theory
of sin
might
seem as
susceptible
to claims of individualism
as earlier
understandings
of sin. This is not the
case, however,
where
freedom,
knowledge
and value are understood in their
appropriate
social
context.
Knowing
and
choosing
value in a social context
The freedom of the individual
person
never exists in a vacuum. While
utterly personal,
it is not isolated nor
completely private.
Rather,
freedom is
always
exercised and indeed formed within the limits of
physical
and
biological
boundaries but also within the
cultural, social,
economic,
religious
environment in which the
person develops.
Thus,
while freedom is not
completely
determined
by
social factors
(and
thus
ultimately denied),
it is
necessarily
limited, structured,
and even to a
degree
constituted
by
the social world in which the
person
lives. In his
early
work on &dquo;the sin of the
world&dquo;,
Piet
Schoonenberg
referred to
freedom as &dquo;situated&dquo;.5
Freedom, then,
is never
totally personal
or
totally sovereign.
Freedom is itself
social,6
and this is
particularly
true at
the
categorical
level in which the
person
chooses between discrete values.
The social nature of freedom is
intimately
interrelated with the fact
that the values which are the
objects
of free choice exist
only
within a
social matrix. Values are learned
precisely
from the social
world,
88
beginning
with the
family
and
extending throughout
ones life. In the
process
of
entering
into social interaction - socialisation - the
young
person
learns what is
important
and what is not. As the
person
takes on
a role in
society (e.g.,
as a
parent,
as a
working person,
or within a
profes-
sion),
s/he learns the
implicit priorities
and values of that role. Know-
ledge
of
values, then,
like
freedom,
is a social
reality.
Constituted in
part by
his or her social
relationships,
the
person
will
generally appropriate uncritically
the
prevailing
values of a culture -
even
though
from an
objective standpoint
an outsider
may
see
quite
readily
that the
prevailing hierarchy
of values is
seriously
disordered.
Pope
John Paul II has criticised Western
culture,
for
example,
for the
overemphasis
it
places
on material
goods
and success -
implicitly arguing
that the
prevailing
cultural
hierarchy
of values is disordered.
Similarly,
the
person
will be
largely
blind to those values which are not embodied
in ones culture and its institutions. This is
clearly exemplified
in situa-
tions of sexism and
racism,
where the value of women and
persons
of col-
our as well as the distinct values held
by marginalised groups
are either
ignored
or
relegated
to a
secondary place.
We see that
knowledge
and freedom are
intimately
interrelated - to
serve or to
hamper
the
development
of one is to serve or to
hamper
the
development
of the other. Freedom is
inherently
directed to value and
ultimately
to God in which all values
participate.
If freedom were unen-
cumbered
by sin,
a clear
perception
of value would lead
naturally
to
choice of the value.
Knowledge
and freedom would work
harmoniously.
The
presence
of
personal
and social
sin, however,
makes both the
percep-
tion of value and the free
response
to it more difficult. Where
knowledge
of value is
obscured,
the
development
and action of freedom is
hindered;
and,
on the other
hand,
where freedom is
encumbered, knowledge
of
value cannot be
pursued.
The social embodiment of value and the social nature of freedom does
not
deny
the
ability
of
persons
to
transcend,
criticise and even
reject
the
prevailing
values of their own culture. To claim that freedom and know-
ledge
are &dquo;situated&dquo; is not to claim a form of determinism. At the same
time, however,
the embodiment of authentic value in
society
becomes
crucial for the authentic
development
of
persons.
Where
society
and its
institutions manifest values and an authentic
hierarchy
of
values,
authen-
tic human
development
is served. On the other
hand,
where authentic
values are not manifest or their
priority
is
skewed,
the authentic
develop-
ment of
persons
will be more
difficult;
and this social situation will be
difficult to overcome.
The social nature of
knowledge
and of freedom is
clearly operative
at
the
categorical level,
where the
person recognises
value and chooses to
act for values. This has obvious
implications
for fundamental
option
itself,
for the exercise of transcendental freedom cannot be isolated from
the social
interrelationships
in which the
person
finds himself or herself.
89
Where the
person
is blind to or acts
against
values at the
categorical level,
his or her fundamental
option
will be
inevitably
affected. The
ability
of
the
person
to
make,
maintain and
integrate
a fundamental
option
for
God will be influenced
by
the
persons ability
to
recognise
and to act on
authentic values in the social world. To understand how this is
so,
we
must now turn to an examination of social sin itself.
Social sin
.
While the social world in which we find ourselves is
value-laden,
it
may
also hide
values,
fail to
embody
certain
important
values or skew an
authentic
prioritising
of values. In this
sense,
social sin creates what Ber-
nard
Haring
refers to as
&dquo;value-blindness&dquo;,7
an
inability
to
recognize
and
act for certain
types
of values or for
particular
values
precisely
because
these values are absent in the social world. The
blinding
of
persons
to
authentic values
through
their absence within the structural
relationships
is an
important aspect
of social sin.
Gregory
Baums identification of four levels of social sin can serve to
demonstrate how social sin blinds
persons
to value.8 The first level of
social sin involves the
injustices
and
dehumanising
trends that are built
into the various societal institutions which
embody peoples
collective
life. The
injustices
and
dehumanising
trends in these structural relation-
ships
indicate that the inherent value of certain
persons
and some of the
values that are essential to authentic human
development
have been hid-
den,
masked or skewed in
society.
The second level of social sin involves
the cultural and
religious symbols,
which are
operative
in the
imagination
and fostered
by society,
that
legitimate,
reinforce and
intensify
the
injustice
and
dehumanising
trends within the
society. Symbols
are the
vessels in which values are enshrined and the avenue
by
which values
enter the human
imagination, self-understanding
and worldview. Where
cultural and
religious symbols
mask or hide
values,
they support
the
structural
relationships
that
perpetuate injustice
and that hinder authen-
tic human
development.
The third level of social
sin, according
to
Baum,
involves the &dquo;false consciousness&dquo; that convinces
persons
that the actions
based on the
ordinary
structures of
society
and its
prevailing symbols
are
right.
At this level we see that an entire worldview has been created in
which even
people
of
good
conscience base their decisions on an
inauthentic
ordering
of values. The fourth level of social sin is the level
of collective
decisions,
generated by
this false
consciousness,
which fur-
ther increase the
injustices
and
dehumanising
trends
already present.
The
blindness to value and the
hierarchy
of values is
perpetuated by
the
ongo-
ing
interactions of
persons making
decisions based on their false
consciousness.
Bernard
Lonergans
notion of &dquo;bias&dquo; further
highlights
the
power
of
social sin to blind the
person
to value.9 &dquo;Bias&dquo; can be understood as the
90
tendency
to eliminate from consideration data
upon
which to base under-
standing, judgment
and decision because such data is
perceived
as a
threat to the
persons well-being.
Bias is thus a threat to the authentic
development
of
persons
which
requires
the
ability
to
challenge
and trans-
cend accustomed modes
by
which the self and the world are viewed. The
harm to authentic
personal development
cannot but harm the authentic
development
of
society. 10
According
to
Lonergan,
bias functions at both the individual level and
the social level.
Particularly
relevant to the
concept
of social sin is what
Lonergan
calls
&dquo;group bias&dquo;,
the
tendency
of a
group
to eliminate from
all consideration all data which threatens the
self-understanding,
status
and
power
of the dominant
group.
Bias therefore serves to eliminate cer-
tain
particular
values or
types
of value from consideration because to
accept
the value would threaten the
group.
We can see here the &dquo;false
consciousness&dquo; that is
grounded
in the
groups symbols,
which
prevents
its members from
recognizing
and
acting
on authentic values.
The
interrelationship, then,
of the
categorical
exercise of freedom and
social sin can be
readily
seen. Human
choice,
the exercise of
categorical
freedom,
exists within the context of the
persons
social
interrelationships
-
including structural,
institutional
relationships.
The individual choices
of each
person
thus exist within the context of the values embodied or
hidden in each
society
and within the context of the social
development
of
personal
freedom. Where values are hidden
by
bias or their
priority
is
skewed,
the
person
will have
greater difficulty
in the choice of authentic
values in resistance to those which
prevail
in
society. Likewise,
where the
person
has not
developed
or witnessed a consistent
ability
to choose
values in
preference
to mere satisfactions or in the face of obstacles and
societal
pressure,
it will be more difficult to choose in a
way
that is con-
trary
to this
ordering -
either in individual situations or in the sustained
and habitual
development
of virtue.
Social
sin, therefore,
sets
up
a
strong tendency
to choose lesser values
or to act
against
authentic values - a
tendency already present
within the
person
due to
original
sin. The disordered sense of value from outside
meets the internal
tendency
to choose the lesser value in situations of
choice or to act for mere satisfaction rather than for value. Social
sin,
like
concupiscence, then,
is an inducement to
personal
sin.
But,
since sin
resides
primarily
at the transcendental
level,
according
to fundamental
option theory,
such
categorical
acts
against
authentic value cannot
immediately
be identified as
sin,
properly speaking.
Such disordered
actions are sinful actions to the
degree
in which
they
manifest a
negative
fundamental
option, signal
its reversal or weaken the
vitality
of the
positive
fundamental
option.
Although
social sin
represents
a
powerful tendency
toward disordered
actions,
social sin and
personal
sin - even at the
categorical
level - can-
not be
simply
identified.
Someone,
for
example,
who
uncritically accepts
91
the materialistic bias of his or her culture cannot be said
immediately
to
be
guilty
of
personal
sin.
According
to the traditional criteria for deter-
mining
the true sinfulness of an
act,
mortal sin
requires
full
knowledge,
full freedom and
grave
matter. But social sin
operates precisely
to create
a form of
ignorance
about value and a weakened
ability
to choose values
freely.
Where
people
are
truly ignorant
of
value, they
cannot be
guilty
of
true
personal
sin. In the same
way,
where the
development
of their
freedom has been
seriously
hindered
by
societal
pressures, people
cannot
be
guilty
of
personal
sin. Such
pressures operate very subtly.
We
may
think,
for
example,
of the manner in which
prevailing
materialism affects
the
persons ability
to
grasp
authentic values such as
simplicity (and
thus
to choose these
values)
and their
ability
to choose
contrary
to
prevailing
patterns.
Further,
the
type
of
knowledge
at stake in
questions
of sin is not an
abstract,
theoretical
acceptance
of values
(conceptual
or
speculative
knowledge)
but a true
experiential
and
personal grasping
of values
(evaluative knowledge).
It is an evaluative
recognition
of
value, grounded
in
personal
and communal
experience,
which moves one to action - not
an intellectual
acceptance
of value. Social
sin, therefore,
can influence
persons very deeply
even where
they
are
taught quite clearly by
moral
authorities about the nature of authentic values. At
times,
wider
society
can exercise such a
powerful
and even dominant influence that
people
find it
extremely
difficult to attain a true evaluative
knowledge
of authen-
tic value.
They
are unable
truly
to
grasp
the value as
worthy
of choice
or are unable to muster sufficient moral effort to attain it in the face of
obstacles.
Just as social sin and
personal
sin at the
categorical
level cannot be
simply identified,
neither can it be
argued
that social sin causes
personal
sin.
People
have the
power
to rise above
prevailing
societal values and
disvalues -
although
it must be added
immediately
that such resistance
may
be
extremely
difficult to initiate or sustain in the face of societal
pressures. Thus,
while we
deny
a strict
determinism,
human
experience
requires
us to
deny
as well
any understanding
of freedom as unaffected
by
the environment.
People
have the
(situated)
freedom to act
contrary
to the influence of social sin. In
fact, they
have a
responsibility
to do so.
The fact of
powerful
societal influences on human freedom and know-
ledge
cannot be used to exonerate a
person
of the
responsibility
for over-
turning
social sin. We
may
recall here the traditional notion of
&dquo;culpable
ignorance&dquo; -
a blindness to value for which a
person
is
responsible.
Bernard
Haring
talks as well about a
&dquo;culpable
loss of freedom&dquo;.&dquo;
Ignorance
or
impotence against
the force of social sin should not be an
easy
excuse to
perpetuate injustices
and
dehumanising
trends in
society.
This is
especially
true for Christians who
belong
to a
community
where
an authentic
knowledge
of values is
taught (though
not
always experien-
tially grasped)
and models of authentic exercises of freedom are
92
enshrined
(e.g., saints).
The
teaching
and witness of
Jesus,
the
perfect
human,
is
certainly
the most authentic teacher of value and of freedom.
Social sin and fundamental
option
As a
powerful
influence on the
categorical
level of
freedom,
social sin
exercises a subtle and indirect but nonetheless
strong
influence on the
fundamental
option,
the level at which
sin, properly speaking,
resides. As
an exercise of transcendental
freedom,
fundamental
option
cannot be
simply
identified with choices
concerning
the individual values which are
embodied or hidden
by
a
particular society.
At the same
time, however,
transcendental freedom is the
ground
of
categorical
choices and
inevitably
is affected
by
them. The
relationship,
then,
between funda-
mental
option
and social sin is rooted in the
relationship
between the
transcendental and
categorical
levels of freedom. Just as
categorical
choices influence and affect the fundamental
option
without
being
iden-
tified with
it,
so too social sin influences and affects the fundamental
option
without
determining
it.
All authentic human values mediate and
participate
in God as the
creator and
ground
of value. To choose values and to act on their behalf
is an
implicit, though
not
direct,
choice for God as their transcendent
ground.
This is
clearly
true where
persons
have a
positive
fundamental
option,
a life that is directed toward God. When such
persons
choose to
act on behalf of a
value,
they
are
implicitly choosing God,
and their
categorical
choice is a mediation of their transcendent
orientation
toward
God.
Right
action then reinforces and
strengthens
the commitment of the
person
to the
ground
of value. To act
against
a
value,
on the other
hand,
contradicts the
positive
fundamental
option - influencing
it,
weakening
its
commitment, though
not
necessarily reversing
it
entirely.
When the social world hides or skews values and fails to aid the
development
of authentic freedom
(at
the
categorical level),
the funda-
mental
option
is
necessarily
affected. Social sin affects the
ability
of the
person
to know and choose
value,
thus
hindering
the
persons ability
to
know and choose the creator and transcendent
ground
of value. The face
of God is further obscured
by
blindness to values which are a manifesta-
tion of the divine
goodness. When,
for
example, people
are born into a
world with subtle but
powerful
forces of
racism,
sexism and
materialism,
they
will be
largely
blind to a whole realm of
important
values which can
point
them to the creator and sustainer of these values. This is most
especially
true when
people
do not
fully grasp
the value of other
persons
who are the
very image
of God.
Social sin
cannot, therefore,
&dquo;cause&dquo; a reversal of a
positive
funda-
mental
option - anymore
than it can determine freedom of choice. And
yet,
in the context of social sin in its various
manifestations,
the
persons
ability
to
strengthen
his or her
positive
fundamental
option through right
93
choices will be lessened. The fundamental
disposition
of oneself at the
transcendental level seeks not
only
to manifest itself in
categorical
choices but to
integrate
further all such choices into ones transcendental
orientation. Where social sin
urges categorical
choices which are
contrary
to this
orientation,
the
ability
to
strengthen
the fundamental
option
is
made more difficult. Social sin hinders the
integration
which
strengthens
the fundamental
option, making
a
tragic
reversal more
possible.
Social
sin, therefore,
does not &dquo;cause&dquo; either
wrong
choices or the
reversal of a
positive
fundamental
option,
but it does exercise an
influence on both levels of freedom. Social sin creates an environment in
which it becomes more difficult to make
good
choices and in which the
positive
fundamental
option
becomes more difficult to
integrate
and
strengthen.
In
fact,
social sin
heightens
the
tendency
that is
present
because of
original
sin to turn
away
from God - that
is,
to sin
personally
and
mortally.
Conclusion
The fundamental
option
is the fundamental
disposition
of the self to
God at the
deepest
core of the human. It is therefore
utterly personal
and
irreducible. And
yet,
the transcendental
&dquo;yes&dquo;
of the
person
to God exists
in the context of the
&dquo;yes&dquo;
of the entire
Body
of
Christ,
extended in
space
and time and united to the
&dquo;yes&dquo;
of the head of the
Body,
Christ himself.
The
positive
fundamental
option
is incarnated in a world that is shot
through
with
grace,
mediated
through persons
and
events, challenging
the
person
to an
ever-deeper response
to God. But it is incarnate too in
a world that is burdened
by
sin which threatens the
dynamic growth
of
the
persons self-disposition
to God. In the same
way,
the transcendental
&dquo;no&dquo; of sin exists in the context of the
history
of human
sin,
the &dquo;sin of
the
world&dquo;,
dragging
the sinner down
deeper
into the mire of sin. Even
more, however,
does the
negative
fundamental
option
find itself in a
world of
grace calling
the sinner to conversion.
The
proper response
to sin - in oneself and in the world - is conver-
sion. For the
person
with a
negative
fundamental
option,
conversion is
the
turning
back at his or her
deepest
core to God. For the
person
with
a
positive
fundamental
option,
conversion is the
daily,
continual effort
to
integrate
all of ones choices into this fundamental
option
for God.
The
response
to social sin involves this individual
conversion,
but it
demands no less the conversion of the societal structures which mask
values and hinder the authentic
development
of human freedom.
The two conversions -
personal
and social - are
inseparable.
It is
precisely
those
persons
who have embraced values and their transcendent
ground through
the
positive
fundamental
option
who will work to
embody
such values in social
relationships.
On the other
hand,
the ulti-
mate
durability
of
any personal
conversion and the
ability
of others to
94
convert will
require
that authentic values can be
recognised
and chosen
in their social context. The
positive
fundamental
option
thus aims to
overcome the blindness and constraints that are caused
by
social sin -
even as the
strengthening
of the
positive
fundamental
option
is aided
by
the transformation of
society
so that authentic values are more
perfectly
enshrined in societal
relationships
and structures.
1. Leonardo
Boff,
Liberating
Grace
(tr.
J.
Drury; Maryknoll,
NY:
Orbis, 1979)
141-7.
2. Bernard
Häring,
Free and
Faithful
in Christ
(New
York:
Seabury, 1978) 1,
164-222.
3.
Joseph Fuchs,
Human Values and Christian
Morality (Dublin:
Gill and
Macmillan, 1970)
92-111.
4. Karl
Rahner,
Theological Investigations (New
York:
Crossroad, 1982) 6, 178-96;
Founda-
tions
of
Christian Faith
(New
York:
Crossroad, 1982)
90-115.
5. Piet
Schoonenberg,
The Sin
of
the World: A
Theological
View
(tr.
J.
Donceel;
Notre
Dame,
In.:
University
of Notre Dame
Press, 1965), 104-6,
111-18.
6. Peter
Hodgson, A
New Birth
of
Freedom: A
Theology of Bondage
and Liberation
(Philadelphia:
Fortress, 1976).
7. Bernard
Häring,
Free and
Faithful, 1,
183-4.
8.
Gregory Baum,
Religion
and Alienation: A
Theological Reading of Sociology (New
York:
Paulist,
1975)
200-3.
9. Bernard
Lonergan, Insight:
A
Study of
Human
Understanding (reprint ed.;
New York:
Harper
and
Row, 1978)
218-42. The
relationship
of bias and social sin is discussed more
explicitly
and furthered
by
Patrick
Kerans, Sinful
Social Structures
(New
York:
Paulist,
1974) 77-8;
Matthew
Lamb,
Solidarity
with Victims: Toward a
Theology of
Social
Transfor-
mation
(New
York:
Crossroad, 1985) 2-12; Nancy Ring,
"Sin and Transformation from a
Systematic Perspective", Chicago
Studies 23
(November 1984)
303-19.
10.
Lonergan
refers to "societal decline" as the
long-term
social effect of bias
(Insight,
218-42.
11. Bernard
Häring,
Sin in the Secular
Age (Garden City,
NY:
Doubleday, 1974) 135-6,
165-8;
and Free and
Faithful 1,
262-3.

You might also like