This document discusses Maximus the Confessor's brief references to life after death, which take an ontological approach. It makes two key points:
1) Maximus viewed truth as an event embodied in the Church, not as objective facts from Scripture alone. Truth is participating in the Church's mode of existence, not just possessing texts.
2) For Maximus, after death a person exists "by Grace" not nature, hypostasizing uncreated divine energies rather than created human energies. This allows for an ontological view of hell not based on punishment but on one's ability to respond to God's love.
This document discusses Maximus the Confessor's brief references to life after death, which take an ontological approach. It makes two key points:
1) Maximus viewed truth as an event embodied in the Church, not as objective facts from Scripture alone. Truth is participating in the Church's mode of existence, not just possessing texts.
2) For Maximus, after death a person exists "by Grace" not nature, hypostasizing uncreated divine energies rather than created human energies. This allows for an ontological view of hell not based on punishment but on one's ability to respond to God's love.
This document discusses Maximus the Confessor's brief references to life after death, which take an ontological approach. It makes two key points:
1) Maximus viewed truth as an event embodied in the Church, not as objective facts from Scripture alone. Truth is participating in the Church's mode of existence, not just possessing texts.
2) For Maximus, after death a person exists "by Grace" not nature, hypostasizing uncreated divine energies rather than created human energies. This allows for an ontological view of hell not based on punishment but on one's ability to respond to God's love.
This document discusses Maximus the Confessor's brief references to life after death, which take an ontological approach. It makes two key points:
1) Maximus viewed truth as an event embodied in the Church, not as objective facts from Scripture alone. Truth is participating in the Church's mode of existence, not just possessing texts.
2) For Maximus, after death a person exists "by Grace" not nature, hypostasizing uncreated divine energies rather than created human energies. This allows for an ontological view of hell not based on punishment but on one's ability to respond to God's love.
Download as DOC, PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 6
At a glance
Powered by AI
The text discusses Maximus the Confessor's brief references to life after death and how he viewed it from an ontological perspective rather than proposing definitive theses.
The two clarifications are: 1) The role and authority of Scripture and Tradition in the Church. 2) Understanding that the truth of the Church is an event/mode of existence rather than objective facts or propositions.
Maximus viewed that the Church experiences and records truth in Scripture and Tradition, rather than them being the sources of truth. The truth is participating in the mode of existence that constitutes the Church.
The Ontological Realism of our Hopes Hereafter: Conclusions from St Maximus the
Confessors Brief References
Christos Yannaras Maximus the Confessor did not write a dedicated treatise or homily or epistle or any other systematic reference on the subject of the continuation of mans existence after death. However, there are, scattered through his works, hints on the subject, which could perhaps form a sufficient basis for us to understand his perspective. His brief references usually convey an ontological approach that is valuable for the empirical character which is required for the realism of the ecclesial testimony. Two clarifications would be useful to correctly understand Maximus approach on the afterlife: First of all, we should clarify, what is the role and the authority of the patristic texts and of Scripture itself in the life of the Church. And to be more specific: is it the Church that gives birth to Scripture and Tradition; do Scripture and Tradition record the testimony of the ecclesial experience? Or is it Tradition and Scripture that give birth to the Church, that act as the sources of the ecclesial truth (just as Marxs texts gave birth to Marxism or Freuds texts to Freudianism)? In the first case, the Churchs truth is an event, a mode of existence incarnate in a specific body of human coexistence. This mode, this way of existence iconizes (that is, pursues and potentially realizes freedom from all necessity and from all restrictions of time, space, deterioration, and death): the mode of existence of the uncreated triune Causal Principle of existence. The experience of the ecclesial body is recorded and testified in the texts of the Scripture, in the liturgical texts, in the texts of the Fathers. The texts themselves are a record of this experience; they do not substitute the experience; the experience itself (the mode of existence) is the truth; texts can only show us its limits at best. We will not come to know the triunity of God by reading the Scripture or synodal decrees, but we will come to know it by participating (perhaps over a long time) in the mode of existence that constitutes the Church. In the second case, if Scripture and Tradition give birth to the Church and are the sources of her truth, then the truth of the Church is percieved as an objective fact each person can individually possess it (with the help of his intellect, his emotions, or any other individual quality). The truth can be his individual possession, privilege, and armor of his ego. The objectified sources of truth, the texts, are recognized and sanctified in themselves, like idols, and the individual fidelity to the letter of biblical, patristic or of liturgical texts alienates the faith: from an event and athlema of confidence and self-givingness it is turned into individual beliefs. And the idolized correctness of these individual beliefs is turned into measurable earned merit and egocentric self-hedonism. Here is the second clarification, so that we can understand Maximus the Confessors hints on the continuation of mans life after death: It is exactly because the truth of the Church is a how and not a what (it is the mode of the formation and function of her eucharistic body, a mode that is the athlema of iconizing the trinitarian fullness of being) that the apposition of theses that claim to answer any human question on meta-physics does not precede the Church. As a rule, the Church expressed the testimony of her experience using the language of the time of her historical birth, the religious language that was then understood by everyone for every subject pertaining to meta-physics (the language that was also used by the Hebrews to express the unveiling of God in their history). That is why, in the texts of the New Testament, the division of the transcendental existence in numbered heavens is treated as a self-evident fact; or the presence of God is stated as fire, earthquake, and a flying bird; or the angelology and daemonology common in almost all pagan religions of the Middle East prevails, etc. The Church intervened only in cases where her empirical truth was falsified or formulated in a language too susceptible to significant deviations from the ecclesial mode of existence. She intervened in councils, in synods, to express and formulate in words through the testimony of her bishops the experience of the whole catholic Church. And in these instances the language used by the Church to express herself was the universal language formed by the Greeks to express the ontological problem with claims of consistent (that is, wholly communicable) empiricism, for the first time in human history: the problem of the distinction of the real and the imaginary or the conceived, of the actually existing and of the transient and ephemeral, the problem of the meaning (of the cause and the purpose) of existence. The Church, thus, defined her faith in and experience of the triunity of God and of the Incarnation of the Son and Logos with the language of the ontological concern of the Greeks, along with the realism and catholicity of this language. The Church also defined the distinction between the icon and the idol, the distinction between the icon and the decorative painting and pleasing to the individuals senses. There was no ecumenical and synodal decree concerning our hopes hereafter, an illumination of the ecclesial hopes ontological content. Maximus the Confessor imports some ontological clarifications in the brief hints on the subject scattered through his works. However, he avoids completing a systematic ontological approach which could be understood as a hermeneutic thesis. Let us not forget that is seems impossible to express, to signify a reality to which we dont have sensory access through our language. Apostle Paul describes the experience of existence beyond the senses as something literally indescribable: [ He] heard things so astounding that they cannot be expressed in words, things no human is allowed to utter. (2 Cor 12: 4) no eye has seen, no ear has heard, no mind has conceived what God has prepared for those who love him (1 Cor 2: 9). However, the ecclesial testimony has achieved to express the experience of the reality of the created world as well as that of the uncreated with the help of the Greek philosophical language of ontology (with the categories: essence-nature [ - ], person-hypostasis [ - ], energies of nature [ ], hypostatic properties [ ], otherness [ ], freedom [ ], relation [ ], etc.). This is done while being always conscious of the apophatic character of the formulations in language, of the fact that the understanding of the signifiers is not identical with the knowledge of the signified, of the fact that truth is not limited to its formulations in language. Such an effort to express and signify the reality of our hopes hereafter with the language of consistent ontological questioning has not taken place in the Churchs history. Didnt the request for such an effort appear? Has the need for it not manifested? Was it impossible to convene an Ecumenical Council from some point in history onwards? The fact remains that the Church prays and speaks about the hereafter, until today, with the juridical and psychological language of the ancient Middle Eastern religions, interspersed with fragments of revealing ontological expressions that remain unconnected, if not inconsistent, with the rest of the religious teaching. Saint Maximus introduces ontological designations that could become a starting point for a search for a more consistently ecclesial (as opposed to religious) expression of our hope hereafter. The first valuable interpretative clarification that we owe to him is his position that after death the existence of the human person is realized not by nature, but by Grace. 1 We term person ( ) the logical (i.e., pertaining to Logos) hypostasis of each man in the image of God, each hypostatic realization of human nature. The human person exists by hypostasizing (constituting as hypostasis) the created energies of the created human nature; it hypostasizes them with individual properties, that is both with morphic (distinctive) otherness and with active (free from predeterminations) otherness. And the question arises: after the physical death, after the complete shutting down of the created human natures created energies, which energies does the human hypostasis hypostasize so that it can constitute an existing person, an actually existing being? Saint Maximus answers: after our death, the hypostasis hypostasizes not the created nature any more, but the uncreated Grace. Man exists not by nature but by Grace; his existence is realized not through the created energies of a created nature, but with the energies of an existence given as a present by God, with the uncreated energies of divine Grace. Maximus creates with his ontological interpretative proposal the possibility for an ontological interpretation of hell as well, which is usually understood by religious standards, that is with juridical and psychological ones. In Maximus perspective, God does neither create or impose hell as a punishment. God is only love, and He gives himself to every human being getting united with him towards the eternity, towards immortality. If mans freedom has developed in him a quality of disposition ( ) capable of responding to the Grace of his union with God, then the union will be for the one uniting with God an inconceivable pleasure ( ). If man receives this life-giving Grace but cannot respond to it, hasnt acquired the preparedness and responsiveness for it, then his union with God will be unspeakable suffering ( ), hell. Everyones quality of disposition ( ), which will judge the union of man with God after death as an inconceivable pleasure or as an unspeakable suffering, is a second ontological perspective by Saint Maximus that is crucial for our hopes. He does not analyze the content of this quality that will determine the disposition and by disposition he means here our willingness to devote and give ourselves, the freedom we have to give positive or negative response and self-offering to the union with God that is offered by Him. However, this quality may not be translated into a logistical numbering and contradistinction of good deeds and sins; this juridical understanding screams of its religious (and not ecclesial) roots. An ecclesial approach would perhaps be to see in this quality of disposition a preparedness that does not come through observation (Luke 17: 20) and probably finds its most characteristic illustration in the thiefs remember me shortly before his last breath. The thiefs quality of disposition turns him into a partaker of paradise on the same day, without requiring the slightest merits. A third ontological clarification by Maximus concerns the existential fullness we expect after death, when [man] joins the Providence in all immediacy, without mediation. 2 How could we come to understand this direct joining, this participation in the fullness of being by Grace, in terms of a mode of existence? In the funeral service of todays Orthodox Churches, which is formulated in a purely religious language, supplications for the eternal rest of the deceased and for the forgiveness (of sins, of faults, of crimes) that this rest presupposes are continuously repeated. However, for the man who has tasted in his earthly life the joyous adventure of research, of creating, of a knowledge that remains always unlimited, of the vast diversity of beauty, of the astonishment of love and of child-bearing, of the expressive abilities of Art, for this person an eternal rest (that is, a perhaps voluptuous but surely stagnant inactivity, some kind of retirement without an end through death) would be a complete nightmare. Saint Maximus sees that the becoming of existence presupposes movement as a necessity: the perpetual motion of the created world until the end of the Aeons is realized in its returning movement towards its existential Cause, a Cause that is essentially inaccessible. 3 Therefore, when the human hypostasis will hypostasize the uncreated Grace and not the created nature, there will be no movement and motion just as there will be no dimension (space and time). Maximus, in his attempt to signify this reality of participating in the ineffable mode of the Uncreated with the language of the created, joins contradictory concepts together: he says that the human existence will acquire an ever-moving repose and a stationary movement. 4 He wishes to signify the existential freedom from every necessity of motion or repose, the realization of existence as relation, the freedom of love as the mode of the fullness of existence. Only relation can include the rapture of motion-quest-pursuance and the fullness of repose as an existential event perhaps this is what Paul indicates with his words: We all, who with unveiled faces contemplate the Lords glory, are being transformed into his image with ever-increasing glory, which comes from the Lord, who is the Spirit (2 Cor 3: 18), For now we see only a reflection as in a mirror; then we shall see face to face (1 Cor 13: 12). Even while existing within the confines of createdness, the human person is experiencing a part of the fascinating experience of relation and relationship, of the unlimited cognitive dynamics of relation, of its always incomplete fullness the human person is experiencing in its interpersonal relationships some, perhaps only a few but nonetheless revealing, instances of a freedom from time, space, deterioration. There are also other ontological approaches about our hopes hereafter that can be found in the texts of St Maximus, both direct and indirect approaches. For example, the possibility that what we term in our language as hell could refer to mans free choice not to exist. If the foundation of existing is the relationship with God, and the logical relationship (which, to be logical-personal, must be free) constitutes the logical-personal existence, then this relationship-existence can be either accepted or even rejected, leading to nonexistence. Hell, says Maximus, is the negation to participate in the and in the and the 5: the free self-exclusion from existence, from relation- participation in being, the negation of the relationship and as such the negation of existing, of existence. And this voluntary nonexistence as a deprivation and loss of the gift of deification can perhaps only be signified symbolically in language with the image of endless torture, of suffering and weeping. Thereby is the unbearable scandal dispelled, that a God who is love preserves His deniers eternally in existence only to see them suffer hopelessly. More generally, Maximus ontological perspective on the restoration ( ) of the whole of nature in the freedom of the glory of Gods children, the difference between his perspective and one of Origen or of Gregory or Nyssa, is one of the most exciting challenges for an ontological clarification of the ecclesial testimony. A brief conference paper does not suffice but merely remind us of pendencies that might be worth the attention of systematic research. St Maximus example allows us to conclude that the ecclesial experiences testimony was not finitely completed in a glorious past, but is perpetually realized with the dynamics of gradually fuller expressive capabilities, especially in the field of ontological hermeneutics language. It is very likely that criteria and prerequisites for an illumination of crucial hermeneutic pendencies concerning our hopes hereafter can be drawn from St Maximus work. Completing this presentation, I would like to indicatively cite some of these pendencies: 1. If by the term person ( ) we define existence as an at least relative freedom of self-determination, then how can we accept that there is no repentance after death? Can there be a personal being without the capability of constituting relation or of negating relation? Does man cease to be a person after death, is he turned into an impersonal, brutish being of monomodal predetermination? 1. Should we perhaps understand our condition after death as a freedom from the existential preconditions of createdness, a freedom from the existential dilemmas of the necessities that govern created nature? That is, a freedom from repentance or non-repentance, non-repentance, a freedom of transition from glory to glory? 3. If we answer affirmatively to the previous question, how can we interpret ontologically the ecclesial angelology and daemonology? Are angels and demons personal beings? If so, how can the unchangeable character of their nature be interpreted? Are they of a created or an uncreated nature? If they are created, which existential restrictions of createdness govern their nature and how can these restrictions be withdrawn in the case of angels, without the angelic nature ever having been assimilated by God? 4. If motion and time are withdrawn after death, why does judgement reside in the future, and why is the resurrection of the dead expected? Why should the semantics of our hopes be limited to the logic of the constrains of the created world? What indications does the ecclesial testimony allow for an ontological interpretation of the hope within us, judging from the behavior of Christs physical body after his Resurrection and on the event of his Ascension? These are articulated with a brevity that does not exclude risk. Footnotes: 1 See Myst. PG 91, 696. Cap. theol. PG 90 1312 C. Christos Yannaras, The Effable and the Ineffable (T ), Chapter 19, . 17, 2-2.5.1. 2 QThal. PG 90, 760. 3 Amb. PG 91, 1304D. -1308 . Lars Thunberg, Microcosm and Mediator, Lund 1965 p. 147ff. 4 See footnote 2 and Christos Yannaras, Person and Eros 33. Relational Ontology 20.3.4. 5 Amb. PG 91, 1325 . Also see: John Zizioulas, Eschatology and Existence ( ), Synaxis n. 121/ 2012, p. 48.